for ttefamA^df^folUepmt^CoUif^l BOUGHT WITH THE INCOME John Elliott Fund IS THE NEW THEOLOGY CHRISTIAN 156 CfLHRinGCROSS' ROAB /( ^ # V. 7> 0 C ffi u 0 7. /S [ffif A^^I^^^^'Cr^^fp^Tafc^yft rEEfis o P kW /^»^/^^*!L^B!^]i^\M m <* KJ^l^^^^wli *>'a P1 fflfii^ M^^nTPs^M lilllj r 0 r c ro t« ? Fl ¦ xJ1" \g jj'it&vCF^PiAt^K^FTtggh. 1 IB 1 r* fe uoano n^tss^yaaniand- IS THE NEW THEOLOGY CHRISTIAN BV HAKLUYT -EGERTON AUTHOR OF "PATRIOTISM," "a PLEA FOR CHURCH SCHOOLS," ETC., ETC. LONDON: GEORGE ALLEN & SONS 156, CHARING CROSS ROAD 1907 [All rights reserved] M tt t-0 t%t Printed by Ballantvnh, Hanson &* Co. At the Ballantyne Press, Edinburgh CONTENTS CHAP. PAGE Introduction i I. The Re-statement of the Christian Message 19 II. The Nature of Religion 29 III. Mr. Campbell's Doctrine of God and the World 37 The Existence of God .... 39 God and the Universe . . . . 81 Note. — Creation and Love . . .100 God and Man 103 Note. — The New Theology as the Re ligion of Science . . .108 „ The Self-Limitation of God . 108 Conclusion 109 Pantheism 115 The Immanence of God . . . .118 Individual Immortality .... 121 The Practical Value of the New The ology 127 IV. The Person and Work of our Lord . . 133 The Person of our Lord .... 135 Is the New Theology Unitarian? . . 139 The Doctrine of the Trinity ... 142 Sin 146 Atonement 149 The Uniqueness of our Lord . . . 155 The Adequacy of Mr. Campbell's Christ ology 160 Is the New Theology Christian? . . 166 V. The Church 171 INTRODUCTION The following are the Author's principal conclusions : — (i) Mr. Campbell's New Theology is a non- Christian system of doctrine, which borrows from Christian thought only certain illustrations (pp. i6'6— 168). (2) The central conception ofthe New Theology can be held reasonably — up to a certain point — only if developed into a non- Theistic philosophy (pp. 1 11— 115). Note. — The passages quoted are taken from Mr. Campbell's book, " The New Theology." IS THE NEW THEOLOGY CHRISTIAN * INTRODUCTION I This little book is not an answer to the New Theology, but a comment upon it. Adequately to answer that adventurous thought would involve counter-construction — the exposition of an alter native system — and in the following pages my primary purpose is not expository but critical. Mr. Campbell has said many things that those who have not left the older ways of thought find repellent, and some that others — not less familiar than he with the world's new fashions — think mischievously mistaken. The book in which these things have been said one cannot praise, but the significant event is — not that these things have been unworthily said, but that they have been said and welcomed. Mr. Campbell speaks primarily for himself, and for himself alone ; but he is a promi nent preacher ; he utters boldly what many have been less extravagantly thinking ; and among his readers are many whose incipient humanism has already predisposed them to neology. 2 INTRODUCTION Moreover, some of us, who are not in the least attracted by Mr. Campbell's reconstruction, believe that, in one important particular of his message, he has told the Christian world a truth which it needed to be told. We are persuaded that a great deal of ordinary Christian teaching is deplorably out of touch with the world's actual life. Not only is its ethical witness feeble and obscure, but it does not ade quately take account of those increasing proba bilities which are the characteristic contribution of modern times to the general body of the world's knowledge. Its apologetic lags behind the doubt it is supposed to refute : its presentation of the Christian essentials is disfigured by crudities that provoke to unbelief, and is encumbered by acces sories that increasing numbers reasonably reject. There is therefore, we think, urgent need for a readjustment of the Christian message, for a re-statement of Christian truth. The old theology must renew its life by contact with the present needs of men and their actual knowledge. It need not forget its past, it may not forget the unchang ing revelation it safeguards and sets forth, but it dare no longer stand aloof from the intellectual progress of men. The world has changed much in nineteen hundred years. Its needs, indeed, remain essentially the same, and to those un changed needs the unchanged Christ is adequate — not less so' to-day than when the earliest evangel proclaimed Him to be the effectual power of God. But, since the preaching of that first evangel, man has more widely explored his physical environment and more critically examined his own past, and INTRODUCTION 3 has thereby grown into a new way of looking at things. His thought is to-day governed by new probabilities, which constitute a new criterion of reasonableness, and have made incredible (or hardly credible) many things that were aforetime generally received. An increasing number of earnest men can no longer use the Old Testament as our fathers used it, or even as St. Paul used it, and find not unreasonable difficulty in accepting a theology moulded to beliefs that no longer seem to them true. It were easy to assert that these new proba bilities are merely probabilities, and to contrast the impregnable rock of Christian revelation with the ever-changing tides and currents of human opinion. But this would involve a sceptical view of history for which few are prepared. The progress of the world has not been, wholly material. We know more than the men of old knew. It may be that we are as far as they from a complete philosophy ; but, at least, the atmosphere of thought has become clearer. Schools of thought have arisen and declined, opinions have swayed backwards and forwards between widely separate extremes, well- accredited solutions have become discredited, and old problems have revived — nothing seems final, nothing seems secure, and yet, through all the seeming confusion, there has been a real advance, for a new and more reasonable conception of the world and of life has been gradually wrought out. But this conception, it may be said, is merely probable. No, it is more probable — probabilior — and, because more probable, it is normal for our thinking. 4 INTRODUCTION I am not advocating a new idolatry of the Zeit-Geist. Not everything put forth in the name of modern knowledge is true. Sometimes the new conception shaped for us by the progress of thought and inquiry is developed into dogmatic constructions — such, for instance, as Professor Haeckel's — which no Christian thinker can accept, but these illegitimate developments do not invali date the conception they misrepresent. That conception — that Welt-Anschauung — remains, I think, more probable, and, if we desire to com mend the Christian message to the mind of the modern world, we must readjust it to the new criterion of reasonableness which that conception establishes. The Christian revelation is, indeed, unchanging, but Christian teaching is not unchanging. It has been shaped by various interests, adapted to various modes of thought, and, in its effort to set forth the Christian message reasonably, has lawfully made use of many conceptions that are not part of that message. These interpretative accessories have served their purpose well, but some have become obsolete. They no longer help us to apprehend for ourselves the revelation of God. Rather do they interpose difficulties, and throw a shadow of unreasonableness over the Faith they once sufficingly explained. The time, then, has come for a new criticism of accessories — of the instrumental conceptions whereby we seek to commend the Gospel to the minds of men ; and Mr. Campbell's insistence upon this — although not always the manner thereof — should be counted to him for righteousness. INTRODUCTION 5 There can, I think, be no doubt that many are thus far in agreement with Mr. Campbell, but this agreement does not infer acceptance of the New Theology. To me, indeed, that particular re-state ment of the Christian message seems radically false. The judgment is severe, but (I hope) not uncharitable, and in the following pages I submit, for the consideration of those interested in Christian thought, the reasons that have led me to it. II (a) The notes to which these lines are intro ductory are primarily critical, and, in so far as they are critical, they are dialectical. I am not unmindful of the text, Non in dialectica complacuit Deo salvum facere populum suum, and I do not suggest that logic can furnish the content of religious faith. To suppose that it can do this were wholly to mistake the function of logic, and would lead us towards the characteristic error of rationalism. Reality, whether spiritual or natural, is always a datum — a thing given — and our appre hension of it in experience is independent of logic, and antecedes inference. But over all explana tory thought logic is supreme. In explanation we attempt to make something — the explicandum — intelligible. All explanation is an appeal to reason, and must be judged by the canons of reason — that is, by logic. Indeed, the characteristic function of logic, when in the presence of a proffered ex planation, is to judge of its reasonableness. An unreasonable explanation — one that involves invalid conceptions, or unsound processes of 6 INTRODUCTION thought — is not an explanation, but only a pre tended explanation. Now, Mr. Campbell's New Theology — be it true or false— is distinctively an explanatory system. He attempts to re-state the Christian message in terms of " monistic idealism," and this attempt naturally suggests three inevitable questions : — (i) Is the Christian message faithfully re-pre sented in Mr. Campbell's re-statement ? (2) Is monistic idealism true ? (3) Are the articles of the New Theology severally consistent with monistic idealism ? I have designated these questions inevitable, and, sooner or later, if discussion continue, they will be found to Tbe so. They can be answered only by logical criticism. (b) But, although the following notes be primarily critical, they include certain positive conceptions which seem to me important, not only for Christian apologetic, but also for the right understanding of the Christian religion and of Christian history. I do not now propose to discuss those conceptions — to do so adequately would change the character of this book — but it may be convenient if I here resume them.1 (1) Religion exists because of human need. In every place, and at every stage of human develop ment, men have felt the need of helpful relations with Nature, or with some supposed or actual powers or Power in or beyond Nature. These relations have been desired and sought because 1 They are more fully set out in my New Way in Apologetic. INTRODUCTION 7 man has discovered in his environment some real or apparent "unfriendliness" which menaces his life, or his purposeful endeavour, or both. Some times the menace, be it then real or supposed, threatens only the savage industry of savage life ; sometimes it does but reflect the fears awakened by the mysteries of an unexplored world wherein man had not yet found himself at home. At other times it arises out of the contradiction between man's sovereign vocation to righteous ness and the seemingly non-moral world wherein that vocation — if it be not ignored — must be followed. Religion exists to overcome this real or apparent unfriendliness, and, in all its forms — alike in savage wizardry and' in the Christian Eucharist — it discloses or establishes (or purports to disclose or establish) relations between man and his environment which overcome that un friendliness. The "objective aspect" of religion is constituted by the practices (ethical or ritual) and beliefs which establish or disclose (or purport to establish or disclose) those helpful relations. The "subjective aspect" is constituted by the inner disposition which accepts and uses the mediating apparatus of the objective aspect. It follows from this that religion is not co terminous with "theolatry" — the worship of God. Art, philosophy, and science may severally dis charge religious functions, and may severally constitute the " objective aspect " of genuine re ligions. Even Professor Haeckel's Monism may be a genuine religion. But no merely " natural " religion can be com pletely adequate to man's higher religious needs, 8 INTRODUCTION because none of the "natural" means whereby man explores his environment — neither philo sophy, nor science, nor art — can adequately overcome the contradiction between man's moral vocation and the seemingly non-moral katabolism of his world. That contradiction can be ade quately overcome only by revelation. A "natural " religion may, indeed, reach the truth, but cannot, by itself, finally establish its own truthfulness. An adequate revelation will not only disclose the truth, but will enable man sufficingly to trust it. This is precisely what the Christian religion does. (2) The Christian religion has its ground in the revelation given once for all in and through the Incarnate Life, wherein and whereby God made known to men that He is Love. By this revela tion the contradiction apparent between man's moral vocation and his natural environment is conclusively overcome, for, if God (Who created both man and the world) be indeed Love, we may be certain that He will not frustrate the hope that He has Himself quickened, and that He has not foredoomed us — who are the work of His hand, and, therefore, of His Love — to final disappointment. The ultimate ground of the Christian religion is not in the teaching of Christ but in His Person, and the faith which apprehends that Person is the subjective aspect of that religion. The ultimate ground of our confidence that God is Love, that Reality is neither neutral nor unfriendly, is not in the words and example of our Lord, but in the fact that He Who is eternally God became INTRODUCTION 9 Incarnate, and not only gave us the witness of words and deeds, but also suffered ignominious death — all to make us know that God is Love. (3) The Divine co-efficient in Christ, which makes His Person a conclusive revelation, is not patent to ordinary observation, but, as in the beginning, is only to be apprehended by an act of faith — an act which is also an act of inter pretation. In the first believers this interpreting and accepting faith was awakened by personal intercourse with our Lord : in later generations it has been awakened by an equivalent experience, which — at least, after its first beginnings — is nor mally an experience within the Christian society. That experience is characteristically an experience of grace — of grace which is operative unto the renewing of our lives and unto an apprehension of Christ therewith concomitant. Did that renewal stand .alone, as an ethical process within our selves, it might but accentuate the contradiction of Nature against our moral vocation, but our con comitant apprehension of the Christian revelation overcomes the contradiction, and quickens us into " sure and certain hope." (4) The characteristic note of the Christian religion is " acceptance of Christ," by faith. Now, faith — which comes to its completeness in love — is the soul's natural response to gifts that make for life. Our Christian faith is our natural response to that renewal of life which comes to us from our experience of grace within the Christian society — the Spirit-bearing body. 10 INTRODUCTION The Christian Church has a twofold vocation : — (i) To set forth the Christian revelation. (2) To edify the hearts of men into an effectual apprehension of that revelation. The revelation itself has been given once for all, but we do not apprehend it once for all. The experience wherein we apprehend our Lord is normally a progressive and continuous experience, and, to those whose experience is what it ought to be, the revelation of God is daily renewed, in hearts that are themselves daily renewed. (5) The Christian life — the life into which we are edified by our experience within the Christian society — is characteristically a life of love. Now, that life is our normal life — the life wherein our nature comes to its completeness. The Christian Church, then, edifies man into the likeness of his own ideal, and, concomitantly therewith, gives him sufficing assurance, through his apprehension of Christ, that that ideal is not misleading. (c) Because God is the Supreme Reality, a full revelation of His character must of necessity have a wide-reaching significance. All our ultimate problems are ontological, and could be sufficiently answered did we adequately apprehend the nature of Reality. Were such an apprehension in some way to become ours, the new content thereby given to our thought would be a treasure that we could only gradually explore and never ex haust. In the first moment of apprehension we would use it for that moment's needs, but that use of it would make only a first discovery of its INTRODUCTION n value, and, as other needs gave other opportunities, other discoveries would disclose more and yet more of its anticipatory helpfulness. Now, in the Christian revelation we have such a treasure as this — the " pearl of great price," to which nothing is equal. And, all through the Christian centuries, the followers of Christ have diversely proven its value. Amid the corruption of moribund Rome, in the arena and at the stake, in the darkest of the Dark Ages (when the order of the world seemed breaking up, and wonders in the sky and on the earth seemed heralds of the Final Judgment), amid the new perils and new temptations evoked by new truth, along strange and unlighted ways of duty, and when the Church itself seemed wounded unto death by sins it could not expel, or fatally benumbed by worldliness it could not conquer — in all these times and in all these circumstances, in every variety and extremity of human need, faithful hearts have found their sufficiency in Christ. And we to-day — plain thinkers of a quiet time, burdened with the new problems of the world's new knowledge, and beset by doubt — we, in our need, find help where they found it. Once for all was the Christian revelation given, " full, perfect, and sufficient," but not once for all was its power made known. Rather have the changing needs of men always found in it a new helpfulness. It may be that we, who find in Christ the truth that makes goodness a reasonable aim, speak in words that were not familiar to the piety of simpler times, and seem metaphysicians rather 12 INTRODUCTION than Christians. But our need is real, and our discovery of helpfulness in Christ is also real. In Him there is indeed the truth which alone can answer that need, and we receive that truth only in apprehending Him evangelically, as the faithful have always apprehended Him. We do not declare a new Gospel ; we tell of a new help fulness in the old Gospel — in the truth whereby the Church has ever lived. " A new helpfulness," newly found, not newly given, for the grace of God does not wait for man's importunity ; but, even along paths that he has not yet trodden, makes anticipatory provision for his need. Moreover, this conception of the Christian re ligion — which attributes religious value to Christ primarily because of the cosmological significance of His Person — is not, in any way or degree, inconsistent with the more widely held conception which sets forth Christ primarily as the Saviour, and derives the Christian revelation and religion from the good purpose of God to save men from their sins. Our experience of sin is one form of the contradiction of Nature against our moral vocation, for therein we find our lower selves in contradiction to our higher, therein the lower values that Nature does in fact make accessible are in contradiction — in successful contradiction — to the higher values that Nature seems to ignore. And, whatever be our conception of the atoning work of our Lord, through His Atonement we rise above those contradictions. (d) Because our Christian faith has its proxi mate ground in our experience within the living INTRODUCTION 13 Christian society, and its more remote ground in a historical revelation, the Christian religion has a certain positive character comparable with that of the natural sciences. It is not merely a speculation, nor merely a private illumination ; it is a practical trust in the Christian line of history, in a certain succession of actual events, to which — reasonably, as we think — we attribute a certain significance. That succession com menced in Palestine, when the Son of Man went about doing good, and our present experience of grace is part of it. In the world which seems to contradict our vocation we discover that which overcomes the apparent contradiction. And what is it that we discover ? Jesus, who is called Christ, and the Christian society, and the perduring grace that renews our lives. These are facts in the world's history, and in these do we trust. (e) If the foregoing account of Christian faith be true, the Christian society — witnessing and grace-bearing, missionary and edifying — is the proximate ground of that faith. We may not conceive of that society in any mechanical way. It is an organism, not a mechanism, and it subsists in and through the faith which joins its members severally unto Christ their Head, the charity wherewith they edify each other, and the grace wherewith they are all edified by Christ. In other words, the Chris tian society is a society only through " personal religion " and charity, — the mutual charity of its members, and the grace -giving \ charity of Christ. 14 INTRODUCTION Where is that society to be found ? The question has often been asked, and it has been variously answered. Some have found it in com munities formed by individual preferences in doctrine or practice. Others have found it in some community claiming organic continuity with the Pentecostal Church, and have thought separa tion from that fellowship to be sin. It were beyond my present purpose to discuss these answers. Indeed, from the general con ception I have endeavoured to set forth, we cannot immediately infer an answer. Two things, however, seem clear : — (i) The society integral in the grounds of Christian belief must be an actual society, and not merely an ideal society. (2) Neither the edifying grace of God nor the evangelical witness to the Christian revelation is confined to any one line of Christian succes sion. Where is the Christian society ? The question is important — of the first importance — but, here and now, I intentionally leave it unanswered, for my present purpose does not lead me to do more than indicate a certain conception of the work of that society, a conception which will, I think, one day prove to be the distinctive contribution of modern apologetic to Christian thought. Against two possible misconceptions, however, it may be well at once to guard. (1) The doctrine here briefly set forth is not Ritschlian, for it derives the religious value of Christ, not from His " value " in our experience, but from His metaphysical nature. INTRODUCTION 15 (2) That doctrine does not permit an immediate inference to the witnessing and edifying Church of the authority sometimes distinctively attributed to the Ecclesia docens.1 1 I do not say that the Catholic Church does not possess that authority, but only that the existence of that authority cannot be demonstrated from the conception here put forth. , I THE RE-STATEMENT OF THE CHRISTIAN MESSAGE THE RE-STATEMENT OF THE CHRISTIAN MESSAGE (a) Mr. Campbell suggests that the message of the Christian Church to the world that it is not yet Christian should be re-stated. To the great majority of Christians this suggestion would be novel and unwelcome. Rome does not always refuse to change, but is always at first intolerant of change, and in Eastern Christendom large communities stand, not unproudly, in the ancient ways. Even in England numbers think of the Christian message as unalterable — given once for all to the Missionary Church, and now only to be set forth. Yet, for centuries, the religious history of Eng land has been a history of re-statement. The Church of England itself — because a reformed Church — is a re-stating Church, and each of the multitudinous societies around her — that severally bear witness to her failure or her fidelity — had its origin, or soon made for itself a doctrinal foundation, in some kind of re-statement. In certain cases the original re-statement is no longer greatly regarded. No competent thinker in the Church of England now holds, without qualification or reservation, the Tudor conception 20 THE RE-STATEMENT OF of the "Christian Prince," nor is the appeal to Catholic antiquity now generally thought to exclude appeal to the present voice of the Living Church. And in at least the principal "Free Churches" there has been a similar movement away from conceptions once thought to be important. Unita rianism is not what once it was ; Calvinism is not what once it was ; and in our modern Congre- gationalists it is hard to recognise the descendants of the first Brownists. In each case the advance into new ways of thought has involved more or less of re-statement. In our more recent history, then, re-statement of the Christian message has been prominent, and to-day the suggestion of re-statement should not be strange to English ears. Moreover, we urgently need re-statement, for, in every Christian com munity, the Gospel of the Grace of God is hindered and thwarted by incomplete and outworn conceptions. (b) If, then, re-statement be necessary, what are the limits of re-statement ? The very endeavour to re-state the Christian message pre-supposes the distinction between things essential and things non-essential, things true and things false, things helpful and things unhelpful. It is clear, more over, that re-statement may not change essentials. Did it do so it would be, not a re-statement of the old Gospel, but a presentation of a new one. The ultimate limits of re-statement, then, are defined by the Christian essentials. If it be true that our Lord was only the teacher and exemplar THE CHRISTIAN MESSAGE 21 of human love, re-statement has only ethical limits, and may proceed to formal atheism.1 On the other hand, let us suppose the Christian religion to have its ground in a revelation mediated by certain historical events — by events of such a nature that they themselves are the revelation. It is then clear that re-statement may not ignore those events, or so re-present them that they cease to be a revelation. If this conception of the Christian religion be true, the primary duty of the Christian society is to preserve the memory of the events wherein the Christian revelation subsists, and this duty the Church has at least attempted to discharge by putting forth the Catholic creeds. It may be, however, that some, who accept this general conception of the Christian religion, would contend that not all the evangelical facts are of equal importance — that the Virgin-Birth is of less importance than the Incarnation, the Resurrection than the Risen Life. Were this contention put forth, what should we say ? I think we should accept it, but acceptance would not entail the consequences which some think it would entail. Primarily', the Christian revelation is a revela tion of God. By it we are assured that God is, and that He is Love. The particular fact or facts in the Divine revelation which are directly the ground of this assurance may not unreasonably 1 Mr. Campbell's own thought makes interesting approximations to atheism, and one form of it can, I think, be made reasonable up to a certain point only by conversion into atheism. In the Ritschlian school it has been seriously contended that Christianity is not inconsistent with speculative atheism. 22 THE RE-STATEMENT OF be thought the most important. But other parts of that revelation have their own importance, and one that we cannot without loss ignore. The Christian revelation is not only a revelation of God, it is also a revelation of the world and of man. In our Lord's miracles, for instance, we see (as in the sacraments) physical things — which ordinarily seem barriers to spirit — become, through Love, the instruments of spirit, and mani fest, in their higher and unwonted serviceableness, an aspect of the Divine character which ordinarily they did not indicate.1 Again, because the Incar nation came not through a mere Theophany, but through a true assumption of human nature, we learn from it that our nature, with its characteristic potencies and implicit ideals, is a thing not wholly alien from the nature of God, but so far accordant therewith that through it God could give us the fullest revelation of Himself. The Incarnation reveals to man, not only the character of God, but also His own nature, and each element in that revelation is part of the Divine response to our ultimate religious need.2 (c) One thing that Mr. Campbell urgently de mands is a re-statement of the relations between the Christian religion and the Old Testament. I will not now ask whether such a re-statement is necessary or desirable : I will only submit certain considerations preliminary to that question. (i) We all know what our fathers thought of 1 Cp. my articles on Liberal Theology published in The Church Quarterly Review during 1905 and 1906. 2 See Chapter II,, "The Nature of Religion." THE CHRISTIAN MESSAGE 23 the Old Testament — what the majority of Chris tians still think of it. Now, whether that view of the Old Testament be right or wrong, it has religious value for Christian thought primarily because it sets forth the providential preparation for Christ — because it exhibits the Christian re ligion as the designed fulfilment of a long pre paratory history. But it seems clear that we can retain these thoughts of preparation and fulfilment even though we cease to think as our fathers thought concerning the first chapters of Genesis, the nature of prophecy, and the general course of Israel's religious life. We know, I have said, our fathers' view of the Old Testament. Let me suggest another view, not as certainly true, but as alternative — as an alternative which we may reasonably hold even though we accept the conclusions of modern Old Testament criticism.1 In the opening chapters of Genesis we have'7% not a revelation of the first beginnings of the world and of human history, but the result of a spiritual development — of a development whereby conceptions, not original among the Jews, were made organic to a new thought of God, and human- history as a whole was brought within the range of ethical thinking. And through all the later history of Israel that development continued. Slowly arose the thought of One Only God whose life is Holiness. Slowly, and through great vicis situdes of history, this thought became the centre of a people's life, and, out of the wreck of national prosperity, there aros.e a great hope — a hope that 1 Cp. Liberal Theology. 24 THE RE-STATEMENT OF one day, the God thus thought of would be effectually sovereign in and through the people He had gathered unto His name. At first, this hope was a narrow patriotism, reminiscent of the real or supposed glories of the ruined kingdom. Slowly, however, a wider outlook opened out. The Coming King would be the Suffering Servant, and, although Israel would remain His chosen, all peoples would be blessed in His rule. And, then, in the fulness of time, " God sent His Son " to fulfil Israel's anticipations, to be completely what Israel had hoped for with a hope that was incomplete.1 Does the reasonableness of Christian thought require more than such a retrospect as this ? I think not. (2) It should not be forgotten that the tradi tional view of the Old Testament is neither part of the Christian revelation nor the ground of our faith therein.2 The Christian revelation comes to man in and through the Person of Christ, and we re ceive it as we apprehend that Person in and 1 According to this view, we should find the "fulfilment of prophecy " in the Divine completion of a divinely-guided process, not (or not merely) in the happening ofa predicted event. 2 A different view seems indicated by Sir Robert Anderson : — " The Christ of Christendom was a crucified Jew — crucified because He declared Himself to be the Jew's Messiah ; and His claims upon our homage and our faith are inseparably connected with that Messiah- ship. "And what were the credentials of His Messiahship ? To some extent the miracles which He wrought, but mainly the Hebrew Scriptures. And in His appeal to those Scriptures He implicitly asserted that they were in the strictest sense inspired." — In Defence, p. 63. Do we to-day give Christ homage and faith because we believe Him THE CHRISTIAN MESSAGE 25 through present Christian experience. And the revelation was given primarily, not to teach a doctrine concerning God's past relations with the world, but to set forth a new conception of God, and to bring men into new relations with Him. (3) It may, however, be asked — Does not the Christian revelation confirm a doctrine concerning God's past dealings with His people ? Is not Christ Christus Comprobator? Does He not, by His own words, confirm the traditional view of the Old Testament ? (a) It seems very difficult to show that our Lord's words will bear the weight of this suggested proof. On either view of the Old Testament, the pro phets spake of Him, and He fulfilled their words. On either view of the Old Testament, He perfectly accomplished what the institutions of Israel's re ligion indicated. (b) Moreover, we know so little, and can reason ably surmise so little, concerning the process of the Incarnation, that it seems yet more difficult to to be the Messiah ? Does not our recognition of Him as the Messiah follow upon our entirely independent apprehension of Him — in and . through personal experience — as " the Son of the Living God " ? It may be said, however, that Sir Robert means only this — we could not give Christ homage and faith if we believe that He falsely claimed Messiahship. Perhaps not, but we believe that He truly claimed it. This belief, however, does not constrain us to the traditional view of the Old Testament. According to the alternative view suggested in the text, Israel's history was a divinely-ordered preparation for the Messiah, and Christ, we believe, was the promised completion of that history. Genuine belief in our Lord's true Messiahship is quite consistent with a "modern" view ofthe Old Testament. 26 THE CHRISTIAN MESSAGE demonstrate a priori that even real acceptance by our Lord of traditional opinions would give those opinions Divine sanction.1 1 Sir Robert Anderson tells us that "every free and fearless thinker will recognise " that, if " the Kenosis theory " be valid, " it destroys the Christian revelation." " If Christ was Divine, the truth of everything adopted and accredited by His teaching is placed beyond question. To plead that, with a. view to advance His Messianic claims, He pandered to Jewish ignorance and prejudice, is not only to admit that He was merely human, but to endanger our respect for Him even as a Rabbi. And yet Christian teachers have the temerity to suggest such an explanation of His words. Such a position is utterly untenable. The Christian is, to borrow a legal term, stopped from questioning the inspiration of the Old Testa ment, or the reality of the miracles recorded in it ; and when teachers who profess to be Christians question both, they should not be surprised if they are charged with being either dishonest or credulous." — In Defence, p. 67. I find myself quite unable to agree with Sir Robert Anderson. I affirm a real providence in Israel's history, and am quite willing to believe that providence marked by miracle, but this does not carry me to Sir Robert's conclusions. Does any Christian thinker suggest that our Lord " pandered " ? Pandering is one thing : self-limitation within a certain intellectual life quite another. Moreover, even according to the alternative view suggested in the text, our Lord is the completion of Israel's history. Therefore, He rightly claimed to be that completion, and He supported His claim by an appeal to His hearers' interpretation of that history — an interpretation which, even if in some particulars mistaken, did at least affirm the essential truth that Israel's history was a providential preparation for the Christ. This affirmation was all that was necessary to make our Lord's argu ment substantially valid. II THE NATURE OF RELIGION THE NATURE OF RELIGION Religion, says Mr. Campbell, is " man's response to the call of the universe" (p. 12), is "the re sponse of human nature to the whole of things considered as an order " (p. 65). It is " the soul turning towards its source and goal " (p. 1 2). " All religion begins in cosmic emotion. It is the recognition of an essential relationship be tween the human soul and the great whole of things of which it is the outcome and expres sion. The mysterious universe is always calling, and, in some form or other, we are always an swering. The artist answers by trying to express his feeling of its beauty ; the scientist answers it by recognising its laws and unfolding its wonders ; the social reformer answers it by his self-denying labours for the common good. In each and every case there is in the background of experience a conviction of the unit as the in strument of the All ; religion is implied in these and in all other activities in which man aims at the higher-than-sel-f. But religion, properly so-called, begins when the soul consciously enters upon communion with this higher-than- self as with an all-comprehending intelligence ; it is the soul instinctively turning towards that from whence it came. Religion may assume a great many different and even repellent forms, 30 THE NATURE OF RELIGION but at bottom this is always what it is ; it is the soul reaching forth to the great mysterious whole of things, the higher-than-self, and seeking for closer and ever closer communion therewith. The savage with his totem and the Christian saint before the altar have this in common ; they are reaching through the things that are seen to the reality beyond " (pp. 16, 17). (a) It is undoubtedly true that, in religion, man endeavours to pass beyond the nearer realities of his environment and condition to some more valuable Reality beyond. The savage, whose religion — in its outward manifestation — does not rise above wizardry, and the Christian saint, who (before the altar of unceasing commemoration) presents himself, his soul and body, to be "a reasonable, holy, and lively sacrifice," are united by a common need and a common aspiration. But what is that need, and what that aspiration ? They are both, says Mr. Campbell, "reaching through the things that are seen to the reality beyond." So in fact they are, but for what reason ? According to Mr. Campbell, they are seeking communion with that unseen Reality. Now, no one will deny that, at least in the higher forms of religious life, this is what men do seek, and certainly no Christian believer whose own life has been renewed by what is ordinarily called communion with God, will deny the reality and blessedness of that renewing experience. It is not an imagination, but a thing most inti mately known, and known to be beyond price. God, we think, cannot be the immediate object THE NATURE OF RELIGION 31 in any human experience, and yet, now and again, an awe as of a holier Presence has possessed us, a wordless voice has spoken, and the silence has seemed tremulous with a besetting life. Others have told of more than this — of moments when faith has become vision, and vision has passed into a mystic union of life with life which no human words can describe.1 Let those who have had such moments tell of them ; we who live along other levels of Christian experience can bear our own testimony — not indeed to such things, but to others that seem not less truly Divine. We have heard a clear vocation that came not from our own purposes. We have felt the familiar words of absolving benediction breathe an un familiar peace, life's chaos has grown orderly with opportunities that bespoke an undeserved providence, in lonely trouble we have found an unseen companionship, in the darkness of doubt an enlightening strength. Why do we value such experience ? We value it because of its intrinsic worth — because it is valuable as honour is valuable, or patriotism, or the artist's gladness in successful work. But we value it more because we think it trustworthy, because through it we reach (or believe that we reach) ultimate reality — the sovereign truth of things. We value it because it gives us aesthetic delight : we value it more because it gives us saving help. This universe is not an obvious Theodicy. The physical world seems quite unmoral : its processes cut heedlessly across the path of our 1 Cp. my New Way in Apologetic, pp. 14-15- 32 THE NATURE OF RELIGION moral aspiration, and bring impartial destruction upon every human, achievement. Is, then, the good life a reasonable life, and our vocation to it a reasonable vocation ? Were it not wiser to accept the passing values of the passing moment, instead of essaying a doubtful and laborious quest for the highest values — for the things that are lovely and of good report ? We can reasonably answer this question in the negative only if, in some way or other, we reach a sufficing appre hension of the world's controlling reality and discover it to be good. Such a discovery the Christian religion enables us to make in and through Christian apprehension of the Person of Christ. In Him, God assumed human nature, and became subject to the con ditions of human life, and obedient even unto death. This self-limitation of the Most Perfect was " for us men and our salvation," and thereby we know that God is indeed Love, for we cannot imagine His condescension to be ironical ; thereby we know that Ultimate and Sovereign Reality is not unkindly, that it will not finally thwart the lives it has itself called into goodness, or mock the hopes it has itself quickened. The distinctive ground of Christian faith is in the Person of Christ — not in what Christ said or did, but in what He essentially is ; and our apprehension of His Person — if not in its first beginnings, at least in its daily renewal — is part of that experience which seems to us a Divine communion. In that experience He walks with us by the way, and, when our eyes are opened and we see Him as He is, we know that experience THE NATURE OF RELIGION 33 to be trustworthy, its refreshment not misleading. Through our apprehension of Christ, those times of refreshing become to us times of Divine visita tion. Therefore do we value them, and we rightly value them, for they give to us what we most need and what nothing else can give — a trust which is a present victory over the world's ap parent contradiction of our hope. (b) It may, however, be said that this account is an account of only one form of religion, and refers to a doubt which is not and never has been general. This comment, were it made, would be just. The doubt arising out of the real or appa rent contradiction between man's moral vocation and the natural environment of his life, although it has a long history, became prominent in European philosophy only at a time not yet re mote. But from the earliest times men have felt the need of assistance in their practical endeavour to live out their lives, and have sought to obtain it. At first, when feeble groups of hunters and fishers arduously won precarious subsistence from the fringe (as it were) of the yet unexplored world, and later on, when the first beginnings of husbandry laid the foundations of man's present mastery in the world, Nature was an environing menace. Fear made its darkness terrible, and peopled its untrodden recesses with invisible foes. Men, it may be, then knew no other vocation than to live — to sustain the life we call animal. Their needs were little more than biological, and to their needs their purposes were correspondent. But, simple though their purposes were, they could c 34 THE NATURE OF RELIGION not easily fulfil them, for the world was unkindly. Had men then heard of the contrast — the con tradiction — which now perplexes us, they had not understood it. But a certain contrast they also knew, for their lives too were purposeful along their own levels, and constantly they found them selves menaced, hindered', thwarted — constantly forces they could not comprehend swept de structively across their path. Out of this contrast arose their religion — crude, it may be, and barbarous, but like unto our own in. one essential particular, for it brought men (or was believed to bring men) into relation with some helpful Reality. And what religion was in its first beginnings, it has ever since ""remained. Wherever it has been more than a nam&jt has been (or has purported to be) a means of paving man from the apparent unkindliness of the/ world, of lifting man above nature's! realr- trr\ seeming contradiction of his characteristic! purpose. That contradiction has not always had the same form. To-day it appears to us as a contradiction of our moral vocation : at other times it has been other wise construed. Always, however, it has been a contradiction of some valued human purpose, and against it men have ever sought help. The story of their quest may be read in the history of the world's religions : the completed response to that quest we see on Calvary. This aspect of religion Mr. Campbell seems to ignore. Yet, more than any other aspect, it dis closes, I think, the essentials of religion.1 1 Op. A New Way in Apologetic and Liberal Theology. Ill MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF GOD AND THE WORLD MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF GOD AND THE WORLD One of the primary duties of the Christian teacher is to commend to the world the Christian tradition of Truth. To-day, large numbers — very large numbers — are without any quickening belief in God. Many do not believe that God exists. Others practically identify Him, in their thoughts, with Nature. Others picture Him as an undiscriminating Bene volence that will not ultimately be hard on any one. We lament the indifference of men — their indifference not only to religion, but to other high aspects of individual and national life. We lament the selfishness of men, their lack of intellectual and moral earnestness, their devotion to vulgar pleasures, their unscrupulous haste to be rich. We lament these things, and we have occasion for our lament ; but the things we lament are only symptoms — symptoms of a life de-vitalised by the loss of faith. Men are what we lament they are because they have no sense of a Divine vocation, no health-giving belief in a besetting Holiness that calls men severally to the highest service they can render. Those who are thus variously living "without God in the world" need to be brought to God, 38 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF and others, who are not so widely separate from Him, need their faith in Him confirmed; Because of all this, the Christian teacher must to-day be more than a theologian : he must be an apologist. And with certain apologetic thoughts. Mr. Camp bell begins his exposition of the New Theology. Before he speaks of the relation of Gobi to the world and to human life, he attempts to show upon what foundation he builds. But when we examine his foundation, what do we find ? Rubble ! — fragments of different kinds of thought, unrea soned, uncoordinated, undeveloped; and just where the foundation should be strongest, we find gaps — gaps filled only by an alleged necessity of belief, or bridged by an avowed leap ! As a con tribution to Theistic Apologetic the New Theology is valueless. Not even the reference to "mon istic idealism " makes it important. Moreover, it is part of the Christian teacher's duty to set forth a Welt-Anschauung — a conception of God and His relation to the world — that men can hold reasonably. This, however, Mr. Camp bell entirely fails to do. His cosmology is riddled with contradictions. Its central thought is the thought that the universe is the self-expression (self-realisation) of God, and when this thought is freed from contradictions, it leads, I think, to one or other of two alternative and equally un acceptable conclusions : (i) to the conclusion that the process of creation is an unmoral process, because merely and ignobly aesthetic ; or (2) to the conclusion that Ultimate Reality is not Divine. GOD AND THE WORLD 39 The Existence of God I According to Mr. Campbell, religion is " the soul reaching forth to the great mysterious whole of things, the higher -than-self, and seeking for closer and ever closer communion therewith" (pp. 16—17). " But what name are we to give to this higher- than-self whose presence is so unspeakable ? The name matters comparatively little, but it in cludes all the ordinary Christian means by God. The word ' God ' stands for many things, but to present-day thought it must stand for the un caused Cause of all existence, the unitary prin ciple implied in all multiplicity. Every one of necessity believes in this" (p. 17). (a) " All religion," says Mr. Campbell, " begins in cosmic emotion." Now, cosmic emotion is not merely emotion awakened by the cosmos, by the whole of things. It is indeed that, but it is more than that. Not only is it awakened by the cosmos, but it goes out towards the cosmos — it is a response to the cosmos. "The mysterious universe is always calling," says Mr. Campbell, " and in some form or other we are always answering." An emotion that went out beyond the cosmos towards, let us say, the transcendent wisdom or holiness of God or His perfect love, however that emotion were awakened, would not be a cosmic emotion. The wonderful beauty of a tropical honey- sucker, " which hung, loud humming, over some 40 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF fantastic bloom, and then danced away, seem ingly to call its mate, and whirred and danced with it round and round the flower-starred bushes, flashing fresh rainbows at every shifting of the lights," moved Frank Leigh — Franciscus Leighius Anglus — to the reverent exclamation, " Qualis Natura formatrix, si talis formata ? Oh, my God, how fair must be Thy real world if even Thy phantoms are so fair ! " It is not impossible, although hardly probable, that these words arose out of cosmic emotion ; it is, I think, certain that the emotion they immediately expressed was not a cosmic emotion. Religion begins, we are told, in cosmic emotion, and cosmic emotion is (we have seen) a response to "the whole of things" — not an aspiration to wards something transcendent. Quite accordantly with this conception of religion, Mr. Campbell tells us — at least, so I understand his words — that " the whole of things " is God. If this be not Pantheism — and Pantheism of quite an ordinary and well- known kind — what is it ? (b) But Mr. Campbell's words suggest the possi bility of an alternative explanation. He tells us, not that religion is, or necessarily subsists in, cosmic emotion, but that it begins in cosmic emotion. But does it end there ? Is it always — in its later history, as, ex hypothesi, in its earlier — an emotional response to " the whole of things," or does it, in the course of its age-long develop ment, leave its first beginnings behind, and estab lish itself upon a new foundation ? Such a transition were not without precedent. Our human GOD AND THE WORLD 41 love begins at or near " the dark edges of the sen sual ground," but rises into a spiritual consecration that is independent of "sense." Does not something similar occur in the development of religion ? Even if we accept Mr. Campbell's doctrine that religion " begins in cosmic emotion," may we not reasonably think that afterwards it rises above cosmic emotion — into, for instance, the discovery, by faith or thought, of a purposeful Spirit that is not "the whole of things," nor the substantial principle of their unity, but their separate and rational ground ? The transition is not unthinkable, but does Mr. Campbell leave room for it ? Not only, according to him, does religion " begin in cosmic emotion," but it is always a response to — a " reaching forth to " — the " great mysterious whole of things." We cannot rightly infer from Mr. Campbell's words that religion continues always to be, or to subsist in, cosmic emotion. His words (if not his mean ing) leave open the possibility that, in its later history, religion establishes itself upon a new ground — let us say, upon a metaphysical theory — but it seems quite clear that, even if religion reach a new foundation, its essential nature does not change. Religion, according to Mr. Campbell, is always "the soul reaching forth to the great mysterious whole of things." And "the whole of things," we are told, is what Christians designate " God." Once more, if this be not Pantheism — and Pantheism of quite an ordinary and well- known kind — what is it ? We may not forget that Mr. Campbell is an idealist of the monistic sort. It is not easy to 42 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF discover what form of monistic idealism Mr. Camp bell holds, but it seems clear that he believes the particulars of existence to be modes or expressions of an Absolute Existence. Now, one kind (if not more than one kind) of monistic idealism identifies the Absolute with the " whole of things," and does not attribute to it any existence transcendent there to or separate therefrom : the Absolute is the whole of things — that, and nothing more. Quite accordantly with this doctrine — although, it may be, accidentally so — Mr. Campbell tells us that the " whole of things " is God, or what Christians designate God. Nor may we forget the strange dualism in Mr. Campbell's conception of God. There are, we read, two modes of God. In one He is "the infinite, perfect, unconditioned, primordial being." In the other He is " the finite, imperfect, condi tioned, and limited being of which we are ourselves expressions " (p. 23). In the latter mode, God is immanent in the world of particulars — for in that mode He is, or is expressed by, that world — and it is, Mr. Campbell tells us, with "the immanent God " that "we have to do " (p. 5). Apparently, God is said to be immanent because, in His second mode, He is believed to be the substantial reality of all particular things, or because all particular things are believed to be the expression of that mode of His being. The "immanent God," then, is (or is expressed by) the " whole of things," and it is with this that we have to do. (c) We have seen that cosmic emotion pre supposes • at least a vague feeling, or obscure GOD AND THE WORLD 43 perception, that the world of particulars is a cosmos, an unity — that things constitute a whole. And Mr. Campbell tells us, in so many words, that religion " is the recognition of an essential relationship be tween the human soul and the greatwhole of things." But do things, in fact, constitute a " whole " ? Early man did not think so, and many to-day could answer the question affirmatively only with the reservation that the unity they think of is an unity of purpose, not of substance. Mr. Campbell, it is clear, believes that things do constitute a whole, and it is probable that the ultimate ground of his belief is in monistic idealism. But religion — which, according to Mr. Campbell, presupposes the unity of the world, and begins in an emotion which is a response to the " whole of things " — exists where monistic idealism is unknown, and even where it is disbelieved. Therefore cosmological unity, which, according to Mr. Campbell's account, is essential to the existence of religion, must have its ratio credendi elsewhere than in monistic idealism. Men do not ordinarily believe without reasons that seem to them sufficient, and, if they believe that things constitute a whole, they must (in most cases) believe this for reasons that are not derived from monistic idealism. What are those reasons ? Mr. Campbell does not indicate them. In the para graph which sets forth his conception of religion, the " whole of things " appears as an unverified assumption or unreasoned postulate. Indeed — unless the passing references to monistic idealism indicate a demonstration — the bases of Mr. Campbell's Theism are throughout undemon- strated. Apparently, he is a Theist because he 44 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF cannot help being one. This may sufficiently explain his own belief, but it is not an important contribution to apologetic, and seems an insecure foundation for the New Theology. (d) " Religion," says Mr. Campbell, is " implied in . . . all . . . activities in which man aims at a higher- than-self." He tells us also, as we have seen, that religion is " the soul reaching forth to the great mysterious whole of things, the higher- than-self." "The higher-than-self," then, is another name for the " whole of things." But is this alternative name appropriate ? More than self, stronger than self, the "whole of things" undoubtedly is, but is it higher ? Is it higher than man's rational will and moral personality ? Mr. Campbell does not help us. There is the mere implication that the " whole of things '' is " the higher-than-self," but this attribution of a greater worth, which makes the " whole of things " look most like the God of Christian faith, remains unsupported by argu ment or evidence. (e) What, then, leads Mr. Campbell to think that the " whole of things " is God ? He does not directly tell us. It seems that "the higher- than-self" is God because it is "the un-caused Cause of all existence, the unitary principle implied in all multiplicity," and, in a passage already quoted, "the higher-than-self" is another name for " the great mysterious whole of things." May we thence infer that the " whole of things " is God because it is " the un-caused Cause of all existence, GOD AND THE WORLD 45 the unitary principle implied in all multiplicity " ? The inference were easy, but the conclusion doubt ful. The " whole of things " is not " the un-caused Cause of all existence," it is existence itself, exist ence as a whole : it is not merely the " unitary principle implied in all multiplicity," it is the multiplicity as well. (/) It seems not improbable, however, that in " the higher-than-self " we have an indication of another conception of religion — a conception other than the " cosmic " conception — and of another and correspondingly different ground of Theism. " The mysterious universe," says Mr. Campbell, " is always calling, and, in some form or other, we are always answering." He mentions three answers — the artist's, the scientist's, the social reformer's. Now, beauty is always a " diversity in unity," and we not infrequently find an artist's work in formed by a feeling that may properly be named cosmic ; indeed, the artistic temperament seems more open than others to the " call " of things. But the unity perceived in beauty, or reproduced in art, is not always or ordinarily the unity of the "whole of things." The artist does not always make his work significant with some significance borrowed from the " whole of things " ; he does not always see the " whole " in the part. Take, for instance, a Japanese ivory statuette, say, of a fisherman or swordsman. It is difficult to believe that this expresses cosmic feeling — a feeling towards the " whole of things " — and, certainly, it does not ordinarily awaken such a feeling. 46 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF In the bolder ventures of natural science, thought does, indeed, attempt to embrace the " whole of things," and even its particular investi gations are governed by conceptions that develop into general theory. But the philanthropy of the social reformer — is this ordinarily a form of cosmic feeling, a response to the whole of things ? Do " his self-denying labours for the common good," in fact, presuppose the recognition of " an essen tial relationship " between himself and " the great whole of things " ? I think not. Cosmic emotion is a response to the cosmos — to the "whole of things." Although always imme diately awakened by some " part " — by something less than the whole — that part is always felt to be, not a quite separate existent, but part of the whole, a " part " through which the " whole " calls. We know little of it in these restless and unthoughtful days — when most men live in towns where the stars are never seen — but Wordsworth knew it well by the northern lakes, and Mr. Campbell knew it, I think, by the Cornish sea. He who wrote the following lines also knew it : — " Within the hollow silence of the night I lay awake and listened. I could hear Planet with punctual planet chiming clear, And unto star star echoing aright. Nor these alone : cloistered from deafening sight, All things that are made music to my ear : Hushed woods, dumb caves, and many a soundless mere, With Arctic mains in rigid sleep locked tight. But ever with this chant from shore and sea, From singing constellation, humming thought, And Life through Time's stops blowing variously, A melancholy undertone was wrought ; And from its boundless prison-house I caught The awful wail of lone Eternity." GOD AND THE WORLD 47 The thought expressed in these lines is an in terpretation — true or false — of the " world as a whole," and the ground of that thought is in an impression produced, a mood or an emotion awakened by, the " world as a whole " — not by this or that particular thing, but by the whole of things. An emotion must have some such reference as this — some reference to the cosmos as a whole, to the " whole of things " — before it can properly be called a cosmic emotion. Therefore, when we find Mr. Campbell attributing religious character to the social reformer's philanthropy — which, I think, has not ordinarily such a reference — it seems clear that his thought is no longer fettered by his initial account of religion. That account left us with the thought that the " whole of things " is God. But this thought appeared as a correlate (or consequence) of the doctrine that religion is a response to the " whole of things " — to the call of the universe. If, then, this latter doctrine be left behind — and, as we have seen, Mr. Campbell appears to leave it behind — we shall expect to find some correspondent change in the conception of God. Is not that change in dicated by the name " higher-than-self " ? Mr. Campbell, it is true, applies that name to the " whole of things." But he tells us also that " religion, properly so called, begins when the soul consciously enters upon communion with this higher-than-self as with an all-comprehending intelligence." It seems clear from this that, if the " higher-than-self " be the " whole of things," it is also more than the " whole of things," for — so, at least, I gather — it is the principle that makes things 48 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF a whole, and — so it seems reasonable to think — is something other than the things it unites. More over, unless the "higher-than-self" be more than the " whole of things," it is difficult to understand in what way we commune with it. Men speak, it is true, of communing with the " whole of things," but in most cases they are admittedly using imagery, and, when they are not, they conceive things to be made a whole by some other and higher Existent which speaks through them. Again, Mr. Campbell tells us that behind man's response to the " call " of the universe is " a con viction that the unit is the instrument of the All." This conviction could hardly exist were the "whole of things " thought of as merely the " whole of things." In a whole that is merely a whole the ultimate differences are only numerical ; the several parts are all equivalent. Hence it is that, when the " whole of things " is believed to be the only existent, we not infrequently find a marked de valuation of moral quantities. Instrumentality, however, implies the subordination of means to purpose, and the purpose pre-supposed by the conviction Mr. Campbell mentions is a general purpose — a purpose of the "All." Now, the All — the "whole of things" — cannot be purposeful unless it be subsistent rather than existent, unless it subsist in some "all-comprehending intelligence" that makes it a whole and informs it with purpose. Again : " The savage . . . and the Christian saint . . . have|this in common: they arej reach ing through the things that are seen to the reality beyond." It is not unreasonable to suggest that " the things that are seen " are the " whole of GOD AND THE WORLD 49 things," the " mysterious universe." But, if this interpretation be correct, God is not the " whole of things," but Reality transcendent thereto, and this " reality beyond," and not the " whole of things," is that " higher-than-self " at which (according to Mr. Campbell) man aims. Mr. Campbell does not systematise these thoughts, nor support them by any argument. They occur as incidental inconsistencies in his general account of religion, but they clearly in dicate a doctrine different from the simple Pan theism we first inferred from that account. It will be remembered that Mr. Campbell desig nates the " higher-than-self " God, because God is " the un-caused Cause of all existence, the unitary principle implied in all multiplicity." It seems, therefore, that the "higher-than-self" must be that Cause and that principle. We saw, however, that if the "higher-than-self" be merely the " whole of things," it can be neither the one nor the other. A " higher-than-self " transcendent to the " whole of things " — truly transcendent there to, even if the ground of its subsistence — could, however, undoubtedly be the un-caused Cause of all existence, and (were words made a little plastic) might well be described as the unity in multiplicity. II Let us now turn to other apologetic suggestions. " The word ' God ' stands for many things, but to present-day thought it must stand for the uncaused Cause of all existence, the unitary D So MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF principle implied in all multiplicity. Every one of necessity believes in this " (p. 1 7). (a) "The un-caused Cause of all existence." The argument to a First Cause is one of the simplest " proofs " and, to many minds, the most conclusive "proof" of the existence of God. As ordinarily stated it runs as follows : — Every event must have a cause. A beginningless series of causes is unthinkable. Therefore, there must be a First Cause. In answer to this it is often said that the alleged First Cause, if actually existent, would itself be caused — that the law of thought which impels us to seek for causes, if valid at all, is universally valid, and may not be arbitrarily suspended at this point or that. But this criticism ignores the distinctive char acter of the argument to a First Cause. According to that argument not every existent thing must have a cause but only every event. If every existent thing were caused, then, undoubtedly, " the alleged First Cause, if actually existent, would itself be caused," and, therefore, would not be a First Cause. But if the Law of Causality apply only to events, our quest for causes legitimately comes to an end when we reach a cause that is not an event. That the Law of Causality has only this limited application is, I think, clear. No constraint by reason compels us to think that everything has a cause, for we have the conception of necessary being — of something that necessarily exists, some thing that is (as we paradoxically say) causa sui, something that has the ground of its existence GOD AND THE WORLD 51 wholly within itself. But every event has a be ginning ; at one time it was not, at another time it is. Now, we cannot suppose that a thing which begins to be has necessary being, and, concerning every such thing, reflective' thought compels us to ask : Whence ? What made it happen ? The Law of Causality, then, applies only to events, and the quest for causes to which it impels us naturally terminates if and when we discover a cause that is not an event. But can we dis cover such a cause, or have we sufficient reason to suppose that such a cause exists ? From the Law of Causality, by itself, we cannot infer the existence of a First Cause. " Every event must have a cause." True, but this does not exclude the possibility that every event is caused by an antecedent event, in infinite regress. An infinite series of events, each caused by its antecedent and causing its consequent, would fully satisfy the Law of Causality. Only if we exclude the possibility of there being such a series can we infer from the Law of Causality that a cause exists which is not an event, and is, there fore, outside the Law of Causality, and properly thought of as a First Cause. This brings us to the second step in the argu ment : " A beginningless series of causes is un thinkable." " Unthinkable " ? Unimaginable it no doubt Is, but is it unthinkable ? And, if it be unthinkable, is not the infinite existence of God equally un thinkable ? Moreover, may it not be that " un- thinkableness " would illustrate only the incapacity of our own minds ? Can we be quite certain 52 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF that unthinkable things do not exist ? A better intelligence than ours might be able tp think them ! " An unbeginning series of events is unthink able." Why ? Not because it is a series, for we can think of a series. Not because it is a series of events, for we can think of a series of events. Is it, then, unthinkable because infinite ? But if an infinite series of events be unthinkable, because infinite, the infinite existence of God must also be unthinkable. And if we do in fact believe that God exists, the unthinkableness of His infinite existence notwithstanding, we must, it would seem, admit the possibility that an in finite series of causes exists. But, if we admit this possibility, the proffered argument to a First Cause inevitably fails, for only by excluding that possibility can we infer from the Law of Causality the existence of such a cause. Moreover, the infinite is not unthinkable. Unimaginable it is, but we can define it, and form a clear conception of it, and this makes it thinkable. So again, it would seem, the proffered argument fails. But the thinkableness of the infinite will nega tive that argument only if " First " mean " prior in time " — that, and nothing else. Now, undoubtedly, " first " does denote priority. But there is more than one kind of priority. Not only is there temporal priority, the priority of the antecedent to its • consequent, but there is also logical priority — the priority of premiss to con clusion, of ground to that which it supports, of noumenon to phenomenon, of substance to quality. GOD AND THE WORLD 53 This latter priority does not involve temporal sequence. If then our earlier arguments be valid, if we cannot reasonably exclude the possibility that an infinite series of causes exists, we are brought face to face with this alternative : either we must (a) abandon the argument to a First Cause ; or we must (b) re-state it as an inference to a First Cause that is logically and not temporally, or not merely temporally, prior to its " effects " — in other words, to a First Cause that is the perduring ground of events and not, or not merely, their antecedent. (b) Now, events, it may be said, are changes, and change necessarily implies permanence, the changing world an unchanging ground of its changing forms. But is the succession of events a change ? Suppose one thing to take the place of another — suppose A to take the place of B — does that succession constitute a change ? If A and B fall within our experience, then, undoubtedly, a change takes place in our experience, and, undoubtedly also, that change does imply per manence. But the permanence it implies is a permanence in ourselves, in the subject of ex perience. Unless B and A were successively present to one perduring subject, there would be no consciousness of change. But this sub jective permanence conditions only subjective change, change in our experience ; it does not condition, and is not inferred from, objective suc cession — from the actual succession of events in 54 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF the world that is the object in experience. When A succeeds B, and we are aware of the succes sion, there is a change in the content of con sciousness, and this change implies the permanence of consciousness, or, more accurately, of the sub ject in consciousness. But A and B, as existent things, as facts in the objective world, are inde pendent of our awareness of them, and the succession of A to B is independent of our aware ness of it. The permanence implied in the change in our awareness does not condition and cannot be inferred from the objective succession of which we are aware — the actual succession of A to B. Let us, then, return to our question : Suppose A to take the place of B, does that succession constitute a change ? It seems clear that, if the successive things be entirely independent existences, their succession, the succession of A to B, is not a change. B will then give place to A, but it will not change into A. Only if the successive things, A and B, be forms of one perduring existence can we rightly say that the succession of the later, A, to the earlier, B, constitutes a change. Were we to see a dog where previously we had seen a horse, it would not occur to us to say that the horse had changed into a dog, because the horse and the dog would be independent existences. But, if we saw Proteus first in his proper shape and then as a dog, we could properly speak of a change, for the two objects would be forms of one existence. Similarly, we rightly speak of water changing into ice, because ice is only frozen water ; the GOD AND THE WORLD 55 molecules that at one time exist in the form of water afterwards exist in the form of ice. We infer, then, that the succession of events does not constitute change unless the succession be a succession within an existential unity — unless the successive events be successive forms of one substance. Only if events possess this character can we rightly speak of their succession as a change. We infer change from permanence, not permanence from change. Not in this way, then, by inference from the succession of events, can we reach the conception of a perduring ground of events. There remains, however, another way. (c) We have, I have said, the conception of necessary being, and we are persuaded that every event has its ground in something that is its own ground, in something that has necessary exis tence. We can neither imagine nor think that Reality is entirely contingent — consists through out of particulars whose existence, no less than their apparent qualities, is wholly derivative and conditioned. An infinite regress of causes is thinkable, but an infinite regress of entirely de rivative existences is unthinkable. We are com pelled to think that something necessarily exists, or that some things necessarily exist. Now, the necessarily existent is a perduring ground, and not, or not merely, a temporal antecedent ; its characteristic priority is a logical priority. I do not say that this is involved in the conception of necessary being, but, certainly, it is entailed by or implied in the argument which infers that events are grounded in necessary being. 56 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF We are constrained to think that Ultimate Reality — whatever be our conception of it — has necessary being, has the ground of its existence in itself, is causa sui.1 But particular things — the spring frost, the winter's hail — come and go. We cannot think that these, in their particularity, have necessary being ; for necessary being can not have beginning — it is eternal, at least a parte ante. Yet these transient things undoubtedly exist, and, since their individual particularity has not necessary being — it must be derivative from necessary being and have its ground therein. But this necessarily existent ground must be intimately present in all transient particularity. Prior thereto it undoubtedly is, but its priority is characteristically a logical priority. We cannot believe the necessarily existent ground of things to be merely an antecedent, merely a temporal prius, for, were it only this, dependent particu larity would be without a present ground. But such an unsupported existence of things that had not in themselves necessary being were incredible. Therefore, we are constrained to think that the necessary being which is the ground of particu larity is a present ground, and not a more or less remote cause. Its characteristic priority is logical, not temporal. (d) We may reach a similar conclusion by yet another way. In the last paragraph we considered particular things in their separate individuality. 1 This seems to be the- conviction underlying the modern doctrine that the causal question may hot be asked concerning "existence as a whole." GOD AND THE WORLD 57 But our observation of the world has discovered many substantial unities — for instance, the unity constituted by the molecular identity of a sub stance which exists in several successive forms. Ice changes into water, and that into steam, but in all three modes of being the same molecules are existent. This leads us to distinguish between the ultimate reality of things and their apparent forms and qualities. But that ultimate reality is not, or not merely, a temporal prius, for it is the present ground of those apparent forms and qualities. Priority it indeed has, but, char acteristically, a logical priority. (e) From all this we must, I think, infer that if the argument to a First Cause be an argument to an antecedent cause of the world's particular existences, it is superseded by the demonstration that those particulars subsist — have their ground — in necessary being. The demonstration that necessary being exists, infinite in at least its past duration and intimately present in all par ticularity as the ground thereof, excludes the causal question — Whence are the world's par ticulars derived ? The argument to an ante cedent cause — to a First Cause whose priority is temporal — can be revived only if we discover in the world's particulars sufficing indication of a general purpose, of a purpose governing those particulars as a whole. Such a purpose could originate only in the necessarily existent ground of things, and, because purpose must always be antecedent to its results, we could thence rightly infer that the necessary ground of things has, 58 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF not only logical, but, also, temporal priority — is not only a present ground, but also an antecedent cause. (/) Two questions remain to be considered : — (i) Is necessary existence God ? (2) Is it plural or unitary ? (1) " Is necessary existence God ? " Mr. Camp bell appears to think that names are unimportant — " the name matters comparatively little" — but they have meaning, and should not be used hap-hazard. Now, it seems clear that the argument to a neces sarily existent ground of things does not enable us to attribute to that ground the personal nature and moral character which are essential in the Christian conception of God. Whether we can make that attribution otherwise is another question. (2) Is necessary existence plural or unitary ? We cannot think of necessary being as beginning to be. Therefore, we are compelled to attribute to it an infinite past duration. But from the necessity of its existence we cannot infer to it any other infinity than a temporal infinity — we cannot infer to it the infinity ordinarily attributed to God. Now, it is not impossible for several things of infinite duration to co-exist. Therefore, it is not a priori impossible that necessary existence is plural —that there are several " necessary existents." The argument which demonstrates a necessary ground of things — which demonstrates that the particularity of things subsists in necessary being — will enable us to demonstrate that necessary being is unitary only if we have independent GOD AND THE WORLD 59 reason to believe that all particular things are modes of one substance. Now, as we have seen, observation does in fact discover certain sub stantial unities or identities. When ice melts there is a perduring identity of substance : the real thing (whatever be the conception we form of it) which first exists as ice afterwards exists as water. Moreover, the advance of Natural Science discloses an increasing probability that all physical things are modes of one primary substance. Now, if the demonstration of unity could be made uni versal — if we could show that all particular things (ourselves included) are modes of one existence — that demonstration would warrant the inference that necessary being is unitary. But until this be done, and the apparent difference between the " spiritual " and the " natural " — between persons and "things" — be thereby overcome, the demon stration that particularity subsists in necessary being will not enable us to affirm that necessary being is unitary — that only one Necessary Being exists. From sufficient indications of a general purpose we would, indeed, infer that necessary being is unitary, but that would be another argument. (g) Mr. Campbell tells us — unless I misunder stand his words — that " every one of necessity believes " in " the un-caused Cause of all existence," and that this Cause is God. We have seen — (1) That the argument to a First Cause of existent particulars is valid only in the form of the demonstration that those particulars have their ground in necessary being ; and 60 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF (2) That this demonstration does not enable us to attribute to necessary being the characteristics which — according to the Christian conception — are distinctive of God, or even to affirm that necessary being is unitary, and not plural. We have not, indeed, considered the argument from general purpose, but this argument is not mentioned in the passage we are now considering — the Cause Mr. Campbell therein speaks of is the Cause of " existence," not of design. More over, to this argument we shall soon have occasion to return. (h) Mr. Campbell tells us also — unless I mis understand him — (1) That an "unitary principle" is implied in all multiplicity ; (2) That " every one of necessity believes " in this principle ; (3) That this principle is God. Now, it is true that the perception of multiplicity — or, more accurately, the recognition of multiplicity — implies the unity of the perceiving subject. Let us assume the co-existence of several particulars — A, B, C, D. If each of these particulars be perceived by a separate subject which does not perceive the others, there will be no consciousness of plurality — each percipient will perceive only one thing. Only if two or more of them be per ceived by one percipient will there be awareness of plurality. But this unity of the" perceiving subject is implied, not by the existence of plurality, but by the recognition of plurality. Can we say that the existence of plurality implies the " objective " GOD AND THE WORLD 61 unity of the several existent particulars ? — that several things cannot exist, either simultaneously or successively, unless they have their ground in, or be held together by — unless they subsist or consist in — some other thing ? An affirmative answer to this question would, I think, be quite without warrant. We may be told that Mr. Campbell speaks, not of plurality but of multiplicity. He does, and it is true, also, that multiplicity is not identical with plurality. We find plurality only where there is more than one existent, and the mere existence of more than one thing in any given field of obser vation — in any given tract of space or time — is sufficient to constitute plurality. Similarly, multi plicity implies the presence of more than one existent, but its characteristic denotation is this — that the several existents are forms of one reality. Undoubtedly, multiplicity does imply an " unitary principle." But is the world in fact a multiplicity? Are its innumerable particulars in fact forms of one existence ? To this we shall soon return. Now we need only notice that, by his use of the words " all multiplicity," Mr. Campbell either begs or hides the question. He begs it if by " all multiplicity " he mean the multiplicity of the world. He hides it, if this be not his meaning. Ill Mr. Campbell bids us remember that "the real God is the God expressed in the universe and in " ourselves. 62 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF " The question is not whether you shall believe in God, but how much you can believe about Him. You may think with Haeckel that the universe is the outcome of the fortuitous inter action of physical forces, without consciousness or definite purpose behind them ; . . . but you cannot help believing in God — the Power revealed in it" (pp. 20-2 1).1 "When I say God, I mean the mysterious Power which is finding expression in the uni verse, and which is present in the very tiniest atom of the wondrous whole. I find that this Power is the one reality I cannot get away from, for, whatever else it may be, it is myself. Theo logians will tell me that I have taken a pro digious leap in saying this ; but I cannot help it." " I cannot help it." This note of necessity we have heard before, and indeed it is (p. 1 8) charac teristic of Mr. Campbell's Theism. We ought, he tells us, "to understand clearly that to disbelieve in God is an impossibility" (p. 17). Now, this may be at once granted to Mr. Campbell — if we know the universe to be the expression of one Power " which is present in the very tiniest atom of the wondrous whole " and is, " whatever else it may be," ourselves, that Power is an omnipresent reality from which we "cannot get away." But is the universe the expression of such a Power ? And, if it be, is that Power God ? 1 Cp. the following passage : — " Professor Haeckel declares his belief in God on every page of his * Riddle of the Universe,' the famous book in which he says that God, Freedom, and Immortality are the three great buttresses of super stition, which science must make it her business to destroy " (p. 17). GOD AND THE WORLD 63 (a) Mr. Campbell uses the word " expression " — " the mysterious Power which is finding ex pression in the universe." Now, we ordinarily say that an artist finds expression in his work. In that case the expression — the work — is quite distinct and separate from that which is expressed — the artist. On the other hand, we say also that the human spirit in the course of its develop ment finds " expression " in the ethical forms of self-realisation — in justice, temperance, charity. Now, these expressions are the human spirit itself — the human spirit as just, temperate, charitable. In this case there is no existential difference between the expressions and that which they express ; the human spirit is its expressions. In which of these two ways is the universe the "expression" of one "mysterious Power"? Mr. Campbell's meaning seems clear : it is in the latter way that the universe is the expression of that Power. In one passage, indeed, Mr. Campbell describes the expression as a presence: "the mysterious Power which is finding expression in the universe, and which is present in the very tiniest atom of the wondrous whole." Now, presence may imply only a pervading, only a presence in the mode of indwelling — the mode properly named " immanence." A Power thus present is distinct and separate from the things it pervades, from the things wherein it is immanent. But presence may also imply substantial (existential) identity. The " mysterious Power '' expressed in the uni verse is " present in the very tiniest atom " if it be that atom. Now, Mr. Campbell tells us that 64 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF this Power, "whatever else it may be," is Mr. Campbell himself. These words denote sub stantial identity, and point unmistakably to the second mode of presence.1 We infer, therefore, that Mr. Campbell believes " the mysterious Power" expressed in the universe to be the Universe. (b) But is the universe thus the expression of one Power ? Are all the particulars of the uni verse (ourselves included) modes of one Power ? Observe, the question is not — Has the universe one cause or one ground ? Nor is it — Is there more than one ultimate reality ? The question we have now to answer is this — Are all the par ticulars of the universe modes of one Power ?. Is ultimate reality, not the ground of each par ticular thing, for that it must be, but is it the constituent being of such particular thing ? According to ordinary Christian thought, there is only one Ultimate Reality, but the particulars of the universe — although created by It, and con tinuously sustained by Its concurrent will — do not share Its essential being, are not modes of 1 That God is thus present in persons seems to be the unexpressed postulate of Mr. Campbell's venturous assertion that " every one believes in God if he believes in his own existence " (p. 17). That conception may be also the unexpressed postulate of the following passage : — "The blankest materialist that ever lived . . . must have affirmed God even in the act of denying Him. Professor Haeckel declares his belief in God on every page of his ' Riddle of the Universe,' the famous book in which he says that God, Freedom, and Immortality are the three great buttresses of superstition, which science must make it her business to destroy" (p. 17). But it may be that we have here, alternatively or in addition to the conception mentioned, a reference to Professor Haeckel's well-known doctrine of Substance, which Mr. Campbell seems willing to accept as a form of Theism. GOD AND THE WORLD 65 It, are not consubstantial with It. But what (according to ordinary Christian thought) those particulars are not, that, according to Mr. Campbell's thought, they are. Certainly, the theologians would be right ! Mr. Campbell has reached his cosmology by "a prodigious leap," and leaves it without support from evidence, and almost without support from argument. Mr. Campbell " cannot help it " ? It may be that he cannot, but others do not share his incapacity. (c) According to Mr. Campbell the universe is the actuality of one " mysterious Power." That Power is the universe ; that Power, Mr. Campbell tells us, is God. Why does Mr. Campbell believe that Power to be God ? Apparently, that belief is one of the things Mr. Campbell "cannot help," but, once more, others do not share his incapacity. The word " God " has beeh variously defined. As Mr. Campbell tells us, it "stands for many things," but in Christian thought it stands for One who, whatever else He be, is absolute, personal, loving. Does Mr. Campbell accept this denotation ? If he accept it, can he show reason for thinking that the Power which is the universe fulfils the conception of God thus con stituted ? Is that Power what "God" denotes in its Christian use ? For instance — Is that Power absolute ? Has it self-existence or necessary being ? From the mere fact that, according to Mr. Campbell, it is the universe, we cannot infer either an affirmative or a negative answer. We cannot think that Ultimate Reality ever began to E 66 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF be, for Ultimate Reality must have necessary being. But we can think that the universe of particulars began to be, and we can think also that the Power which is the universe then simultaneously began to be — called into existence by some higher Power. Nothing observable in Nature, and nothing properly inferred by Science, warrants the belief that the universe had not a beginning. Why, then, should we believe that the Power which is the universe had not a beginning ? But, if it had a beginning, it is not self-existent,, and, if it be not self-existent, it is not God. (d) Let us, however, concede that the Power which is the universe is a self-existent Power. This will give us a cosmology closely similar to Professor Haeckel's. The self-existent Power which is the universe differs in little but name from Professor Haeckel's Eternal Substance, which also is the universe.1 Now, Professor Haeckel's cosmology is ordinarily and, I think, rightly described as atheistic. Mr. Campbell is not an atheist, but does his conception of a Power which is the universe — if it be a conception of a self-existent Power — rise above atheism ? It may be that Mr. Campbell would admit that it does not, for to reach Theism he takes, and seems aware that he takes, " a prodigious leap." (e) Mr. Campbell, however, does not leave that " leap " wholly without explanation. At least, the 1 Cp. p. 64 (footnote). GOD AND THE WORLD 67 following passage seems to convey not only an explanation, but also a justification : — " Materialists may tell me that the universe does not know what it is doing, that it goes on clanking and banging, age after age, without end or aim ; but I shall continue to feel compelled to believe that the Power which produced Jesus must at least be equal to Jesus " (p. 21). Now, we may reasonably infer that Jesus was " produced," and we may quite as reasonably believe that the Power which produced Him was equal to producing Him. Mr. Campbell, how ever, says — not "equal to producing Jesus," but " equal to Jesus." Behind this phrase there seems to be a scale of worth. And, undoubtedly, in our own minds most of us have a scale of worth. We rank the personal above the impersonal, the rational above the irrational, the moral above the immoral. But have we sufficient reason, apart from Theism, for believing that our scale of worth has cosmic validity ; for believing that, according to the constitution of the universe and in virtue thereof, the things we deem higher are higher ? If, however, we set aside this conception of graduated worth, " equal to Jesus " can mean only " similar to Jesus." Were we to adopt this mean ing, and also Mr. Campbell's argument, we might infer that because Jesus is personal, the Power that produced Him must be personal — because Jesus loved greatly, the Power that produced Him must love greatly. These inferences would presuppose that a cause must be like its effects. This presupposition, how ever, would exclude the idea of development. If 68 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF an effect be produced by an act of production which is also an act of development, its cause is not like unto it, but unlike it. And we know that, from the age of the Vedantists unto our own day, many thinkers, some of them prominent idealists, have accepted the idea of development ; at least to the extent of believing that the personal has, in fact, arisen from the impersonal. Moreover, the argument that Mr. Campbell starts from Jesus could, with equal propriety and cogency, be started from any particular existent — from a stone or from Nero. Indeed, the first general conclusion to which this argument, if made universal, would lead is merely this — all the qualities that temporarily appear in the tran sient particulars of the universe must exist in the Power which is the universe, and produces all particulars out of itself. Observe ! All qualities, the qualities of Jesus, the qualities of a stone, the qualities of Nero ! Now, that conclusion is inter esting — if not otherwise, at least for the specula tive problems it suggests, — but it would not greatly help us towards Theism. (/) I have said that Mr. Campbell has left his attribution of Deity to the Power which is the universe almost unsupported by argument. One could say " quite unsupported " were it not for the following passage, which, it may be, Mr. Campbell intends for an argument : — " How can there be anything in the uni verse outside of God ? Whatever distinctions of being there may be within the universe, it is surely clear that they must all be transcended GOD AND THE WORLD 69 and comprehended within infinity. There can not be two infinities, nor can there be an infinite and also a finite beyond it " (p. 1 8). This passage, I think, clearly presupposes the existence of God, and proffers reasons for think ing that, whatever else He be, He is the Power existent in the world's particulars. Now, the question to which Mr. Campbell's rhe toric has led us is this — Can we infer Theism from a Power which is the universe ? Mr. Campbell's argument may be fairly re-stated in this form : — God exists, and has such and such a nature. His nature is such that there cannot be any existence other than He — " outside of God." Therefore, the Power which is the universe is God. This argument infers Deity — Mr. Campbell would, I think, say "divinity" — to the Power which is the universe from the nature of the existent God. It does not enable us to reach belief in God from the discovery of that Power, and its force would be completely broken by the not impossible rejoinder, " I do not believe that God exists ! " It may, perhaps, be said that Mr. Campbell here presupposes not the existence of God, but the conception of God, and that his argument, if re stated, should be re-stated thus: — The word "God" denotes a certain specified kind of existent. The Power which is the universe is an existent of that kind. Therefore that Power is God. The evidence is, I think, against this suggestion, but let us accept it for what it is worth. 70 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF Two questions immediately suggest them selves : — (i) Has Mr. Campbell shown that the Power which is the universe does, in fact, possess the nature and character denoted by " God " ? (2) Does Mr. Campbell give an adequate account of the conception of God ? (1) The one note of Deity mentioned by Mr. Campbell is infinity. Has Mr. Campbell shown that the Power which is the universe is infinite ? He has not. (2) Does Mr. Campbell's argument start with an adequate conception of God ? Now, as Mr. Campbell tells us, " the word ' God ' stands for many things," but, as I have already said, in its Christian use it stands for One Who, whatever else He be, is absolute, personal, loving. No existent that is not this can be the God of Chris tian Faith. The only attribute of God mentioned by Mr. Campbell is infinity. Now, we may reasonably think that an infinite existent is necessarily self- existent — that is, absolute. But would Infinite Self- Existence necessarily be personal or loving ? Mr. Campbell should, in the first place, have shown that infinity ' infers the other attributes- essential in the Christian conception of God, or should have otherwise sufficiently indicated them. But he mentions only the infinity of God, and gives no indication that infinity implies anything else. His argument, as re-stated, starts from a fatally inadequate conception of God, and not the clearest fulfilment of that conception would prove the fulfilling Power to be God. GOD AND THE WORLD 71 (g) The " real God," says Mr. Campbell, is " the God expressed in the universe " and in ourselves. According to Mr. Campbell, the impossibility of disbelieving in the existence of God excludes the question — Does God exist ? and leaves primary the quite different question — What ought we to believe concerning Him ? Even though men be materialists, like Professor Haeckel, they " cannot help believing in God " — in the Power revealed in the universe. Immediately upon these explana tions follows this passage : — " As I write these words I am seated before a window overlooking the heaving waste of waters on a rock-bound Cornish coast. ... I have never seen anything quite like it before. It tells me of a beneficent stillness, an eternal strength. ... It whispers the word impossible to utter, the word that explains everything, the deep that calleth unto deep. So my God calls always to my deeper soul, and tells me I must read Him by mine own highest and best, and by the highest and best that the universe has yet produced" (p. 21). This passage tells us how to interpret the character of God, and, at least, it gives us a useful canon whereby to judge — not the ways of God, but men's representations of His ways. If, how ever, it do nothing more than this — nothing more than indicate a way of interpreting the character of God — it will not help us to interpret the Power that is the universe, unless we first believe that Power to be, or to express, God. Yet I think Mr. Campbell intends it to give us that help. He has told us that the "real God," in whom one 72 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF "cannot help believing," is the Power revealed in the universe, and that the important question for each one of us is — What ought I to believe concerning this real God ? When, after a delay that seems primarily rhetorical, he goes on to tell us how we should " read " God, it seems reason able to think that he intends us to " read " the universe — which, according to him, expresses God — in the same way.1 If this be Mr. Campbell's intention, he would have us interpret the universe by " the highest and best " it has yet produced. Can we, in this way, reasonably assure ourselves that the Power which is the universe is God ? The " highest and best that the universe has yet produced " is, I think, the ideal of Christian humanism — the ideal of a fully-developed life made complete in love. If we use this ideal to interpret the universe, what should be our method ? We should, I think, begin by asking — What kind of Ultimate Reality does this ideal presuppose ? But the moment this question is asked an im portant distinction comes into sight. An ideal is not only existent : it is either valid or invalid. From the mere existence of an ideal — from its mere existence in the minds of men, as a fact in human history — certain cosmological inferences may be drawn, but the conclusions thus made immediately accessible are not very important. If, however, an ideal be valid — at least, if the ideal of Christian humanism be valid — its validity has much more 1 Cp. the following sentence : — " It is a Divine experiment without risk of failure, and we must interpret it in terms of our own highest." In this passage "it" unmistakably denotes the universe. GOD AND THE WORLD 73 significance than its mere existence. An invalid ideal has, I think, no other significance than the significance of its existence. (h) It is in the argument from man's moral ideals that the argument to a general purpose in things becomes most persuasive. Men do not willingly accept the conclusion that the universe is mindless, and, because purpose is the most certain indication of mind, they have everywhere sought for marks of purpose. The speculative interest of their search is clear : if there be a general purpose in the universe, we may reasonably infer that Ultimate Reality is unitary and personal. No form of the inference to purpose has been more widely popular than what is ordinarily called " the Design-argument." This argument has sometimes been merely an argument from design. Certain things having been assumed to show marks of design, there followed an easy inference to the existence of mind. But every argument of this kind has been open to this initial criticism — Are the marks here taken to be marks of design really marks of design ? We cannot infer from design unless we first have design. Now, design is not obvious in Nature. Therefore, the argument from design has developed into a more complex argu ment, of which the earlier part is an argument to design. Now, this latter argument — the argument to design — has always been more effective in its rhetorical than in its logical appeal, and recent well-accredited conceptions of adaptive develop ment have interposed difficulties that many find insuperable. 74 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF Moreover, the Design-argument is an argument, through a particular design, to a particular purpose and a mind which originated that purpose. But is the mind it reaches an universal mind ? It seems clear that not every alleged instance of design implies an universal purpose, nor every alleged purpose an universal mind. Some have attempted to infer cosmic purpose from the general process of change — called a process of evolution — whereby the particulars of the universe are (as many believe) produced. Evolution, it is said, presupposes an end, and an end implies purpose, and, since the process of evolution is universal, the purpose that guides it must also be universal. But this argument con fuses evolution with progress. Change (we know) is not always purposeful, and even evolutionary change — the change marked by the appearance of new forms — may not be thought purposeful unless its products bear the marks of purpose. It is, however, sometimes said that the cosmic process is, in fact, progressive — that in human history, for example, we have unmistakable pro gress. Now, it may be admitted, at once, that evolutionary changes constitute what we ordinarily call an ascending series : the later biological forms, for instance, are " what we call higher than the earlier, and in human history there has been a similar advance. We may also admit that, at least in human affairs, the ascent is still continuing, but for how long will it continue ? Biological de velopment and human advance presuppose certain favourable conditions — if for no other reason, then at least because animal and human life can exist, GOD AND THE WORLD 75 not in every kind of world, but only in a certain kind of world. Now, at one time this earth was lifeless, and we have strong reasons for believing that one day it will again be lifeless. If, then, the seemingly progressive history of man be part of the life-history of our planet, it is only an incident therein, and one of comparatively short duration. Moreover, the change that will make our earth intolerant of life will be brought about by pro cesses that are universal. Every part of the physical universe will, sooner or later, "run down." But, if this be true, the evolutionary ascent is but an episode, and the subsequent descent will destroy all that we now think higher. Even if the past ascent seem purposeful, what shall we say of the future descent ? To many, however, this cosmology does not seem final. They believe that man has a spiritual nature which is not essentially involved in the flux of things material, and in man's vocation to the good life they find — or think that they find — marks of a purpose which, if it be actual, must be general. Is this alleged discovery a real discovery ? In these pages, at least, it may be admitted, without discussion, that man has a moral vocation to the good life. But what is meant by a vocation ? The word " vocation " means either " a call " or " that to which one is called," and, when we speak of a vocation to the good life, we mean a call to the good life. Now, a call is something that comes to one, and those who hold the Christian faith think of man's moral vocation as the call of God. But this presupposes Theism, and, in oftr present argument, we may not presuppose Theism, 76 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF for we are endeavouring to reach Theism. Ordi narily, however, when we speak of this or that man's vocation, we do not — unless we are religi ously interpreting a religious vocation — suppose the vocation to come to him from without. A boy, we say, has a clear vocation to the Bar. We do not ordinarily mean that God has called him to the Bar — such a meaning might overtax the most robust faith — but only that he has a certain kind of aptitude for the Bar, His vocation is given by his own nature, and, if we are to use man's moral vocation in the argument to general purpose and thence to Theism, we must at first regard it as a vocation of that character. When, then, at the commencement of our Theistic argument, we postulate that man has a moral vocation to the good life, what does our postulate mean ? It means not merely that man has an aptitude for the good life, that he is capable of achieving and living the good life, but that he has a certain kind of aptitude for it. We mean that human nature is so constructed that only in and through the good life can it become complete and satisfied. Man's vocation to that life comes from the intrinsic determination J of his nature thereto. The human spirit is characteristically a potency, and the good life is the natural end or term of that potency, the end in which alone it can become completely actual.2 In other words, human nature is not fixed and unchanging, but develop ing, and its development can become complete 1 When using the word " determination " at this early stage of our argument, we should be careful to exclude all thought of "purpose," and to think only of " potency " and " end." 2 Cp. my Patriotism, pp. 33-40. GOD AND THE WORLD 77 only in and through the particular kind of life we call the good life. Now, the good life is nowhere completely actual, — at least, nowhere within human experience, and our argument does not yet permit us to speak of the perfect life of God. Within our experience it exists — in its perfect form — only as an ideal. Consequently, the question immediately arises : Is that ideal a practicable and reasonable ideal ? Can we reasonably and hopefully make it the guide of life ? A guide it unmistakably claims to be, and it sets forth values which we ourselves believe to be highest. But is that claim valid ? Are those values really highest ? We have a sense of obligation towards it — we ought to be what it invites us to be — but is that obligation trustworthy or misleading ? The good life is undoubtedly an attractive life — the best judgment of the race deems it the highest life, — but it is not easily attainable, and even growth towards it entails or involves no little sacrifice. Man has more than one kind of aptitude, more than one kind of thing is valuable to him — really valuable — and some values are near at hand and easily accessible. Is it wise to forego these, and to become ascetic for righteousness' sake ? If the highest values be unattainable, it is madness to pursue them. If, although attainable, they be transient, finally extinguished by death, are they worth the effort of attainment ? Moreover, the good life can become completely actual only as the result of a spiritual develop ment which none of us can hope to see completed within ourselves during our earthly existence. Is there a life for man beyond the grave, and, if there 78 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF be, what is its character ? Will that after-life fulfil or contradict this earthly life, and, in that after-life, will the good life still be reasonable ? These questions cannot be adequately answered in the affirmative by an unassisted theory of human nature. Suppose it true that man will live here after, and that, in his future life, the values which now seem highest will still seem highest. The question would still remain unanswered — Is man's vocation to those values a reasonable vocation ? There are those who would tell us that, if the after-life proved to be like this life, the demonstra tion of reasonableness would (to say the least) be difficult,, because, in and for earthly experience, the good life is only doubtfully reasonable, and the mere prolongation of our existence upon a similar, although another, scene would not make that life more reasonable. Now, why is it said that, in and for this world, the good life is only doubtfully reasonable ? If, here and now — in and for present experience — it seem unreasonable, its apparent unreasonableness comes, I think, not from Nature, but from man himself, from man's inhumanity to man, from his selfishness and ignorance, from his indifference to the best things, and his heedless hurry after the lower. The selfishness of pretentious mediocrity sheltered by insolent privilege, and of those who hasten ruthlessly to be rich, or as ruthlessly to enjoy, and the ignorance which not only impoverishes the ignorant but hinders those jwho know better — these are the things that sometimes make life seem not worth the living. Nature, as we now know it, is tolerant of the good life. In some sufficing GOD AND THE WORLD 79 degree of completeness, that life could be lived here and now did men seriously and generally resolve to live it. Nature, in its relations to human life, does indeed present problems, but these are important for theology rather than for ethics — for those who allege a Theodicy, rather than for those who affirm the reasonableness of the good life. Death, it is true, would, if it were final, reduce all values to equal insignificance, and leave Epicureanism the only reasonable creed. But, if there be a future life, and if the theatre of that life be no more unkindly than the Nature which now environs us, the good life is, I think, a sufficingly reasonable life. Let it be assumed, then, that human nature is essentially a spiritual nature, and that it will eternally perdure after death — can we thence infer a general purpose ? The alternative inference would be that this nature which thus perdures has arisen, without purpose, by some necessary development from Ultimate Reality. This alternative may seem the less probable, but we may not altogether ignore it. Our argument to reasonableness involved, how ever, more than immortality. It involved also a tolerant environment. For us, here and now — in and for our present experience — our present en vironment is, I think, sufficingly tolerant, but will the environment of our future life be not less kindly, or will it make the good life impossible, e.g. by making it a perpetual and profitless martyrdom ? If the environment of that future life will be sufficiently tolerant, can we, from that fact, infer 80 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF a general purpose ? Remember, we have reached the conclusion that our present environment is sufficingly tolerant. Were it demonstrated, or otherwise known, that our future environment will be no less friendly, that discovery would enable us to frame this general proposition — The en vironment of man's immortal existence is, and always will be, tolerant of the good life. Thence we could infer that the good life is a reasonable life. Could we thence — from that eternal coin cidence of opportunity with vocation — infer also a general purpose ? Once more, the alternative inference to a necessary and unpurposed develop ment might seem the less probable, but, once more, it could not properly be altogether ignored. We set out to answer the question — Does man's moral vocation to the good life presuppose a general cosmic purpose ? We have discovered — what ? An alternative, and, it may be, a some what greater probability on the side of affirmation. To make this discovery, however, we assumed immortality, and in that assumption we virtually assumed also that man's vocation to the good life is a reasonable vocation. But is that vocation in fact reasonable ? We do not know. Experience does not and cannot demonstrate the reasonable ness of it, and the natural sciences suggest nega tion. There are, indeed, some who would seek to exhibit this reasonableness as part of a general philosophical construction. But every philoso phical construction is a construction of human thought, and who can certainly say that our thought is adequate to metaphysical exploration ? — that our undoubted metaphysical capacity is a GOD AND THE WORLD 81 thoroughly competent capacity, able to accomplish (with known and objective validity of accomplish ment) that final interpretation of Ultimate Reality which it so confidently essays ? The answer must, I think, be — No one I J This discussion arose out of Mr. Campbell's precept to interpret the universe by our own " highest and best." Mr. Campbell tells us of a Power which is the universe, and we have sought for proof that it is God. Could we prove it to be purposeful, we could reasonably believe it to be personal, and this would bring us very near to Theism. But, not even with the help of Mr. Campbell's precept, have we been able to discover purpose, and Mr. Campbell's guidance leaves us on the hither — the non-theistic — side of his " pro digious leap." God and the Universe We have endeavoured to discover in Mr. Camp bell's thought some sufficient ground for a reason able Theism. We have endeavoured, but we have failed, because Mr. Campbell reaches Theism by a " prodigious leap " for which no adequate warrant is adduced. From the other side of that leap Mr. Campbell speaks to us, no longer of a Power that is the universe, but of God, and goes on to explain the 1 It will be noticed that the argument here considered — the argument from man's moral vocation to a general cosmic purpose and thence to Theism — is not the argument from the Law of Conscience to a Law giver, nor is it precisely Kant's argument through the concomitance of pleasure with blessedness. F 82 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF method and purpose of creation. What concep tion of God does this explanation disclose ? (^4) At the very outset, Mr. Campbell points us to an easy inference that God — whatever else He be — is the universe. " How can there be anything in the universe outside of God ? Whatever distinctions of being there may be within the universe, it is surely clear that they must all be transcended and comprehended within infinity. There cannot be two infinities, nor can there be any infinite and also a finite beyond it" (p. 18). If God be infinite, it seems clear that all the particulars of the universe must subsist within His infinite being. But this does not define the mode of their subsistence. Are we compelled to believe that they subsist as modes of His essence — that God can make particulars exist only by, as it were, fashioning into particulars unseparated parts of His own substance ? If God were extended sub stance, filling infinite time and space, the belief might seem inevitable, for there would be no un filled parts of time or space wherein non-divine things could exist. All the particulars of the visible universe occupy time and space, and, if all time and space be filled with the infinite being of God, it at first sight seems clear that those particulars must be so many forms or modes or parts of God, for there is no room for anything that is not God. But this conception of God is to-day an anach ronism. God is not extended substance, nor does He fill time and space. These, indeed, are not GOD AND THE WORLD 83 real extensions. To us they seem such, but to God they are, I think, abstract conditions of presentation (yorstellung) or " position," — forms wherein He presents to Himself, or posits, the particulars of the world. Are we to assume that He can therein posit only particularised parts of Himself ? May it not be that He creates the things He posits, and gives unto them a substantial existence other than that of His own self-existent being, — not integral therein, and, although other than it, not " outside " it ? If God be not in time and space, and these be not real extensions but " forms " of Divine action, the positing of such other things therein would not derogate from the completeness of the Divine nature, nor would such things " limit " the being of God otherwise than as particulars — even if they be modes of God — must always limit it. (B) We will now turn to other passages — to passages wherein Mr. Campbell describes God, no longer as mere infinity, but as infinite conscious ness, and the universe as the self-realisation of God:— "What I have to say reads back through Hegehanism to the old Greek thinkers, and beyond them again to the wise men who lived and taught in the East ages before Jesus was born. It is that this universe of ours is one means to the self-realisation of the infinite. Supposing God to be infinite consciousness, there are still possibilities to that consciousness which it can only know as it becomes limited " (p. 22). " To all eternity God is what He is, and never 84 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF can be other ; but it would take Him to all eternity to live out what He is. In order to manifest even to Himself the possibilities of His being, God must limit that being. There is no other way in" which the fullest self-realisation can be attained" (p. 23). " I start, then, from the assumption that the universe is God's thought about Himself " (p. 26). (1) Self-realisation properly denotes the pro cess whereby potency passes into act, whereby possibilities develop into actual forms of life.1 Such a process we find in the growth of the individual from infancy to manhood. Intellectual capacities and moral qualities are present in adult life which were not present in earliest infancy. Yet in some form they must have been present from the very beginning; because they are not additions from without, but developments from within. How, then, did they at first exist ? As possibilities, or (more accurately) as potencies ? We think of the individual self as possessing from the first a certain definite constitution or nature — definite, although undeveloped. Its first outward expressions are simple, and probably its first inward experience is equally simple, or almost equally simple. But even at the very first it has within itself certain capacities — capacities of be coming this or that, of becoming able to do this or that. These capacities are potencies, real possibilities ; that which they can become is not yet actual, but only potential or possible. For example, we cannot think that a new-born infant 1 Cp. Patriotism, pp. 33-40. GOD AND THE WORLD 85 loves. Yet, unless it be radically abnormal, there must be within it the possibility of love, some undeveloped capacity that later on will develop into love. That undeveloped capacity is a potency, and love is its actuality. But when potency passes into actuality, when the possibility of love develops into love, the reality of the self becomes richer and more complex ; the self, we say, becomes more completely real, and this pro cess of becoming we call a process of self- realisation. Now, the forms of life wherein the self thus becomes realised (becomes more completely actual) are not separate from the self ; they are the self — the self acting in this way and that. The forms of self-realisation are forms of the self ; their existential reality is that of the self. Therefore, if the universe be the self-realisation of God, God is the universe ; and the particulars of the universe are forms of His being, modes of His life. (2) It may be, however, that (in Mr. Campbell's thought) " self-realisation " has another meaning. It may be that he means by it, not " development of potency into actuality," but " bringing into con sciousness, or into clearer consciousness." A man has lost his way — without knowing that he has lost it — on a mountain, and is walking in the dark along the edge of a precipice which he believes to be a mile away. He is in danger, but does not know that he is in danger. A flash of lightning, however, shows him the precipice at his very feet, and then for the first time he " realises " 86 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF his danger. If the universe be thus the self-realis ation of God, the process of creation is a process wherein God becomes more and more clearly or completely aware of Himself, of His own nature. But how does this awareness come to Him ? There are two alternative possibilities : — (i.) It comes in and through the development of His own nature into actuality, in and through self-realisation of the kind first discussed and properly so called. (ii.) It comes in and through a process which calls into being an universe of particulars that does not share His existential reality, but illus trates His powers and character. Between these alternatives the doctrine that the universe is (in the second sense) the self-realisation of God does not, in and by itself, enable us to choose. (3) God, we are told, is " infinite conscious ness." Now consciousness is a quality, and cannot exist without a subject. There can no more be consciousness without some one who is conscious than there can be whiteness without something that is white, or courage without some one who is brave. Clearly, then, Mr. Campbell's definition or description must be amended. God cannot be merely infinite consciousness — that and nothing else. If infinite consciousness be indeed His characteristic quality, He must be a Being who has infinite consciousness. But what is infinite consciousness ? Conscious ness implies not only a subject, but also an object. There cannot be a consciousness which is mere blank awareness, which is not a consciousness of GOD AND THE WORLD 87 something. Consciousness that is not a con sciousness of anything cannot exist. It seems, then, that an infinite consciousness is a conscious ness that has an infinite content, that is conscious of an infinite number of things. If God be such a consciousness, He must be aware of everything : for Him there can be no undeveloped possibilities, no potencies not yet become actual.1 Did such exist, His consciousness would not be infinite, for it would lack certain forms of actuality. If, however, the consciousness of God be thus complete, He cannot undergo either kind of self- realisation. Not the first, for, ex hypothesi, no possibilities (no potencies) remain undeveloped ; everything is completely actual, and cannot be come more real. Not the second, for if God be (in this sense) infinite consciousness, He is already completely aware of everything. Neither can He have undergone self-realisation in the past ; for if He be essentially a Being whose consciousness has an infinite content, His consciousness must ever have had that content. The content of His consciousness must be co-eternal with His con sciousness — that is, with Himself. We have already seen that the existence of an infinite con tent precludes self-realisation. If such a content has existed from all eternity, then from all eternity it has precluded self-realisation. (4) It may be, however, that (in Mr. Campbell's use) " infinite consciousness " does not denote a consciousness with an infinite content, but one Cp. p. 42 — " The being of God is a complex unity, containing within itself and harmonising every form of self-consciousness that can possibly exist." 88 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF which has an infinite capacity, and receives a content through the process of self-realisation. The conception of bare consciousness — of a consciousness that is merely consciousness, without being a consciousness of anything — is, as we have seen, an impossibility. But let us waive the impos sibility and suppose God to be an infinite con sciousness of that kind. We have still to face the difficulty that such a consciousness cannot undergo self-realisation. Such a consciousness already has the full reality of consciousness ; the advent of a content would not make it more real. The gradual appearance of an infinite content might, indeed, imply self-realisation ; but the self-realisation im plied would be a self-realisation, not of the con sciousness, but of the Reality, whatever its nature, that gradually revealed itself in consciousness. We can reasonably conceive of a self-realisa tion of consciousness only if we suppose the consciousness that is self-realised to be, not con sciousness, but only the potency or possibility of consciousness. Let us then once more amend Mr. Campbell's definition. God, we will say, is a Being who is characteristically the potency or possibility of an infinite consciousness. We could think of such a potency becoming actual, developing into actual consciousness ; but the process would presuppose an original unconsciousness, for a possibility of con sciousness — a possibility not yet developed into actuality — is not consciousness. Were we, then, to adopt this last amendment of Mr. Campbell's definition, it would be necessary to believe that God was at first unconscious, and GOD AND THE WORLD 89 gradually achieved consciousness by some process of self-realisation. Moreover, since the uncon scious cannot be purposeful, it would be necessary to think that the self-realisation of God began without purpose — by chance or necessity. Would such a conception of God be Christian ? Un equivocally, No ! (5) We will now bring together certain more or less widely separated passages which set forth primary aspects of Mr. Campbell's thought, and may collectively help us to apprehend his meaning. (a) "The limits of my subject forbid that I should enter into a discussion of philosophic idealism, but I think I ought to confess at once that I can only think of existence in terms of consciousness ; nothing exists except in and for mind" (p. 26). (b) " The true being is consciousness ; the universe, visible and invisible, is consciousness " (P- 32). (c) "God is "ceaselessly uttering Himself through higher and ever higher forms of existence" (p. 24). (d) "Thus to the question, Why a finite unit verse ? I should answer, Because God wants to express what He is" (p. 23). (e) " So far we have seen that the universe, including ourselves, is one instrument or vehicle of the self-expression pf God" (p. 25). If we take these passages in connection with those already quoted (pp. 83-4), what general conception will they help us to form ? God, we have already heard, is consciousness — 90 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF infinite consciousness. The universe also is con sciousness. It is God's thought about Himself ; in it God is "uttering Himself," living out what He is, manifesting to Himself the possibilities of His own being. And He does this — how ? By limiting His infinite being. The particulars of the universe are limited modes of God, and the limitation is for the purpose of self-expression. The conception is not unattractive, and claims careful consideration. (a) The particulars of the universe, we learn, are forms or modes of God's self-expression. If we call them forms or modes of self-realisation — and Mr. Campbell himself describes the process of creation as a process of self-realisation — the self- realisation we think of must be the self-realisation of the second type, for those forms or modes are said to be, not developments of Divine potencies, but the expression of Divine actualities. They set forth, not the potencies of God, but what God is : they re-present God to Himself. But, if God be from all eternity infinite consciousness, from all eternity He knows what He is. Why, then, this dramatic outspreading of a re-presentative universe ? Mr. Campbell suggests an answer : — " You may know yourself to be a brave man, but you will know it in a higher way if you are a soldier facing the cannon's mouth ; you will know it in a still different way if you have to face the hostility and prejudice of a whole com munity for standing by something which you believe to be right" (pp. 22, 23). But if God be infinite consciousness, He has eternally been aware of what He is, and has, from GOD AND THE WORLD 91 all eternity, known completely all that self-expres sion can make manifest. Why, then, has He sought self-expression ? (b) It may be that this question does not trouble Mr. Campbell, for he believes creation to be eternal J and is (it may be) content to think of it as the self-expression of God, without believing it to be purposeful. " Without believing it to be purposeful " ? Yes, for an eternal process cannot be a purposeful pro cess, because a purpose is antecedent to its effects, and there can be nothing antecedent to an eternal process — a process that has no beginning. We are, then, to think of the self-expression of God in particulars as eternal, and as therefore, un purposed. But, if it be unpurposed, it must be the result of some inner necessity in the Divine nature, for we cannot think that an eternal process exists by chance. Is this conception of the universe as the necessitated and eternal self-ex pression of God — a self-expression not originated by thoughtful purpose or intending love — one that Christian thought can welcome ? I think not ! (c) If the self-expression of God in particulars be an eternal and necessitated process, does it pre suppose any ground in the Divine nature other than a potency — a possibility as yet undeveloped — sufficient to account for those particulars ? Were the self-expression of God purposeful, we could suppose it to be the setting forth — the re presentation — of an infinite plenitude of being 1 " The act of creation is eternal, although the cosmos is changing every moment" (pp. 23, 24). On p. 27 the universe is described as " infinite and eternal." 92 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF already existent in the Divine nature. But, if once the thought of purpose be dropped, such a pleni tude would be otiose, functionless, and unnecessary. An eternal self-expression in particulars would not presuppose an antecedent plenitude, for there cannot be any antecedent to an eternal process. It would presuppose only a perduring ground containing the potency (possibility) of the par ticulars. (d) This brings us to yet another reduction of one conception of God. We have already taken away the thoughts of purpose and plenitude : we have now to remove, almost completely, the thought of transcendence. God can no longer be thought of as purposeful plenitude of being. He is merely the universe of particulars, and the not yet exhausted potency which has not, thus far, become expressed in that universe. His only transcendence is that of the marginal potency which has not yet developed into actuality. Were his self-expression complete, He would not be in any degree transcendent, for He would then be only the universe — the universe, and nothing else. Once more, are these concep tions that Christian thought can welcome ? (e) It may be, however, that even were these last reductions accepted, it would still remain necessary to think of God as the universal consciousness. But what function would we then assign to such a consciousness ? According to the original form of the conception we have gradually reduced, the self-expression of God takes place in order to manifest Himself to Himself — His nature to His consciousness. The purposeful self-expression of GOD AND THE WORLD 93 God has its term in the consciousness which be holds it — it takes place in order to give that consciousness a certain content. The Divine consciousness is the " objective," as it were, of the Divine process of self-expression. It is, however, the " objective " of that process only because — I am speaking according to our original and un reduced conception — that process is purposeful. If, however, the self-expression of God be, not a purposeful re-presentation, but the necessitated development of potency, need we suppose God to be conscious ? If our conception of the Divine self-expression be thus reduced, what is left for an universal consciousness to do ? Only one answer seems possible. A thinker who, like Mr. Campbell, believes that " all true being is consciousness " might say that, even if we abandon the thought of a purposeful self-expression, we must still continue to think of God as the uni versal consciousness — no longer, indeed, to origi nate His self-expression in particulars, or to give to that self-expression an " objective," but to make His very being intelligible. Be it so, but, since consciousness is always and only consciousness of a content, the Divine con sciousness will be merely a consciousness of the particulars of the universe and of whatever Divine potency has not received expression in those par ticulars — only of these, for, ex hypothesi, these are the only existents that can give a content to that consciousness. Once more, is this a conception that Christian thought can welcome ? (6) Mr. Campbell tells us that God is " infinite 94 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF consciousness." It is, however, not easy to dis cover with satisfactory precision what Mr. Camp bell means by this. The predicate "infinite consciousness " has more than one denotation, and Mr. Campbell does not clearly indicate which of these he adopts. Two of these denotations we have already con sidered : (i) An infinite consciousness is a consciousness with an infinite content. (2) An infinite consciousness is a consciousness infinitely capable of consciousness. There remains, however, a third denotation, which must be considered before we proceed further : (3) An infinite consciousness is a consciousness which transcends the distinction between subject and object. I will not say that this conception is distinctive of modern philosophy, but it is prominent in philosophical thought to-day as it has never been before, and this prominence gives a distinctive character to modern philosophical discussion. Unfortunately, it is difficult to make this con ception easily intelligible. We are familiar with the ordinary distinction between subject and object. I who know am the subject in my act of know ledge, and the thing that I therein know is the object. That kind of consciousness — the con sciousness of an object by a subject — is the kind which constitutes our everyday experience, but what is that other kind — the kind which transcends it ? Probably an illustration will be more useful than a technically-expressed answer. GOD AND THE WORLD 95 To ordinary thought nothing seems clearer or more fundamental than the consciousness each one has of himself. But this consciousness — this self-consciousness — is not an original endowment of human nature. In each of us it has a beginning within the individual life. In earliest infancy it does not exist. Consciousness, indeed, there then is, but not — so at least our psychologists say — self-consciousness. Our earliest experience is an ex perience in which the distinction between subject and object, though latent, has not emerged into consciousness. The content of that earliest ex perience is not the intellectual perception — " I perceive a tree," — characteristic of late years, but uninterpreted feeling, which is not even thought of as " my feeling." No doubt the elements which afterwards become a consciousness of subject and object are latent therein, but they are latent, not manifest. The consciousness of self, and of self in perceptual relation with an object, is a later development. In that development the unity of the first experience, so we are told, is broken. The content of that first experience was a feeling in which the distinction between subject and object had not become apparent. With the ap pearance of that distinction, experience falls apart into two sides, aspects, or factors — the subjective and the objective — which seem to be independent. This dualism is characteristic of our ordinary consciousness. Infinite consciousness is a con sciousness which transcends that dualism and re-establishes unity. That new consciousness is ordinarily said, rather in illustration than in description, to be a kind of feeling, but we must 96 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF be careful not to think of it as mere feeling. The transition to infinite consciousness is not a return to the beginnings of finite consciousness ; the unity is not the original unity ; the new feeling is not the original feeling. Wherein do they differ ? Let us return to our illustration. The conscious ness of self — of the subject in experience — arises out of primitive feeling which was not self-conscious, and out of the same feeling there arises, concur rently with consciousness of the self, consciousness of the object. Both develop out of primitive experience. But when the distinction between subject and object has thus emerged, that distinc tion, we are told, is a limitation. Reality is ex perience — this is the distinctive doctrine of the idealism most characteristic of our day — but sub ject and object are severally only parts or aspects of experience. Each is one side of a dualism that has arisen in experience ; neither is complete Reality, but only an aspect of Reality. Absolute experience — which is said to be Absolute Reality — is reached only when the dualism that has emerged in experience is overcome, and the sepa rate sides of it (subject and object) are brought together again in a new experience which does not obliterate the distinction between subject and object, but transcends it. Absolute experience does not negative finite experience, but completes it ; it does not annihilate the distinctions that have arisen in finite experience, for it is the " truth " of those distinctions. This is as far, or almost as far, as we can easily go — for our human speech is shaped by our finite human experience, and cannot describe an GOD AND THE WORLD 97 experience essentially different from ours, — and, fortunately, this is as far as we now need go. Does Mr. Campbell's " infinite consciousness " denote absolute experience ? or, more accurately, does it denote a consciousness related to ordinary consciousness as absolute experience is to ordinary experience ? I do not know, and cannot discover. Certain passages, if they stood alone, would incline us to believe that, in Mr. Campbell's opinion, the infinite consciousness of God is merely extensively infinite — is infinite either because it has a numerically infinite content, or because it is capable of receiving such a content. "The Infinite Consciousness sees itself as a whole ; the finite consciousness sees that same whole in part" (p. 33). "The larger and fuller a consciousness be comes, the more it can grasp and hold of the consciousness of God" (p. 28). " Individuality only has meaning in relation to the whole, and individual consciousness can only be fulfilled by expanding until it embraces -the whole " (p. 33). "The mind that thinks the universe must be immeasurably greater than my own, but in so far as I am able to think the universe, mine is one with it" (p. 26). On the other hand we have the following passage : — " Supposing God to be infinite consciousness, there are still possibilities to that consciousness which it can only know as it becomes limited " (p. 22). Here we have a new thought, the thought of G 98 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF a possible experience outside, as it were, of the infinite, an experience that can be gained only by a self-limitation of the infinite. This suggests that the infinity of the Divine consciousness is not thought by Mr. Campbell to be distinctively an extensive infinity. If the consciousness of God were infinite because possessed of a numerically infinite content, there would (and could) be nothing outside it. Its con tent would be an all-inclusive content. In it, as we have seen, every potency would be completely actualised, every possible development completely accomplished. There would be nothing for God to gain by assaying the Divine adventure of self- realisation, for He would already be everything. But if the infinity of the Divine consciousness were, distinctively, a qualitative infinity — of the kind indicated by our third denotation — then, un doubtedly, new experience would be gained by adventure into finite consciousness. If the Divine consciousness transcended the limitations of " sub ject-object experience " — were above the character istic dualism of our consciousness — it would not include the kind of consciousness distinctive of "subject-object experience." Were God to step out of His infinity into finitude, He would gain that latter kind of consciousness. He would come to know things, as we know them, and that kind of knowledge would be new to Him. But would it be worth gaining ? According to the philosophy that to-day gives us the conception of qualitative infinity, a con sciousness qualitatively infinite would be a com pletely perfect consciousness, and every other GOD AND THE WORLD 99 consciousness is imperfect. If, then, God be already perfect consciousness, why should He take the trouble 1 to achieve imperfect consciousness ? Only one answer seems possible. God takes that trouble in order to gain new experience — a new kind of knowledge or a new feeling. If this answer be accepted, the " Divine experiment " of self-expression must be merely Epicurean, for it must be an experiment made merely to obtain a certain aesthetic satisfaction — the satisfaction of gratifying an intellectual curiosity that is merely curious, satisfaction akin to that of the gourmet who tries a new dish. Few will think — Mr. Campbell himself will not think — that this adequately inter prets the purpose of God in creation.2 7, The self-realisation spoken of in the para graphs immediately preceding is self-realisation of the second kind — re-presentative self-realisation. Self-realisation of the first kind — developmental self-realisation, self-realisation by the development of potency (possibility) into actuality — is impos sible to a consciousness already qualitatively infinite, and, therefore, already completely and perfectly real. Is it, then, impossible to connect the thought of developmental self-realisation with the thought of Absolute Consciousness — of consciousness already qualitatively infinite ? Clearly not, for we can regard the consciousness as the term or goal of 1 "Trouble," indeed, is too mild a word, for the descent into finite experience brings into the Divine Life all the sin and misery of the world. ? gee note on pp. joo-103, roo MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF the self-realising process ; we can suppose the universe to be the expression or self-realisation of a Self-Existent whose potency is being gradually developed towards Absolute Consciousness, According, however, to this conception, the Divine consciousness would be an emergent, a result. God (Absolute Consciousness) would be, not the cause of the world-process, nor its perdur ing ground, but its last achievement, and, as yet, He would be non-existent, or, more accurately, only potentially existent, — existent only in the potency that would one day become God (Abso lute Consciousness), but would not as yet be God. The developing Self-Existent Reality would, in deed, be on its way to Godhead, but would not yet possess the distinctive consciousness of God, and, therefore, would not yet be God. It seems unnecessary to ask whether Christian thought could accept such an interpretation of the world-process. Note. — Creation and Love I. The following passage suggests that the self-limitation of God to the world of finite persons took place in order that God might express (become aware of) His love — in order that His love (the " Christ spirit ") might become self-conscious : — " Look abroad all through the world, look back upon the slow upward progress of humanity to its home in God, and you will read the story of the incarnation of the eternal Son. Never has there been an hour so dark but that some gleams of this eternal light have pierced the murky pall of human ignorance and sin ; never have bitter hate and fiendish cruelty gone altogether unrelieved by the human tenderness and self-devotion that testify of God. Indeed, without the limitation, the struggle, and the pain, GOD AND THE WORLD 101 how would this Christ spirit ever have known itself? Granted that self-surrender had never been called for by the conditions of life, granted that our resources had always known themselves infinite, and that which is worthiest and sublimest in the nature of God and man alike could never have been revealed. This is why the eternal Son has become incarnate " (pp. no, in). (a) " How would this Christ spirit ever have known itself" ? Mr. Campbell tells us that God is Infinite Con sciousness. If, then, God be love, and His consciousness be extensively infinite — without limit, and aware of every thing — God must eternally know that He is love. It could not have been necessary for Him to pass into finite existence — to become incarnate — in order to make dis covery of His love. Again, if » the consciousness of God be qualitatively infinite — if it be Absolute Consciousness — then, in that consciousness, love and knowledge must be transcendent- ally complete. God needs not to leave the perfection of His Absolute Existence in order to become aware that He is love, for in that Existence His love and His knowledge of His love are both eternally complete. Self-expression within the sphere of finite existence — necessarily an in complete self-expression, because within that sphere — could add nothing to His nature or to His knowledge of His nature. (b) Love, we know, cannot subsist except in a plur ality. Were God one Sole Person, He would not and could not be love. If He be love, His life must in some way be involved in plurality. If He be eternally love, the plurality wherein His love subsists must be an eternal plurality. According to the Catholic tradition of thought, such a plurality exists in the Divine Essence Itself, and, within that plurality — in the perfect life of the Holy Trinity — love is eternally complete. An alternative is not, however, inconceivable. Were the universe of finite persons eternal, that universe (together with God) would constitute an eternal plurality within which love could eternally subsist. But the love thus contingent upon the world of particulars could not be the cause of that world. (c) Catholic doctrine requires us to believe that God 102 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF created the world for some purpose consistent with His love, and became incarnate in the unique Person of our Lord in order to manifest His love — not to Himself, for that were unnecessary, but to us. Mr. Campbell teaches that " the eternal Son " is incarnate in every man, and not uniquely in our Lord. According to Mr. Campbell, God, by self-limitation, created a world of finite persons in order, through that self-limitation, to become aware of His own love — in order to manifest His love to Himself, in order that the "Christ spirit" might know itself. This, however, brings us face to face with alternative difficulties. If God be, as Mr. Campbell teaches, infinite Perfec tion, His love and His knowledge of His love must be eternally complete — the " Christ spirit" must eternally know itself. Because the self-knowledge of the infinitely Perfect must be complete, God had no need to create a world of finite persons in order to discover to Himself His own love. On the other hand, if the creation of, that world were really a self-discovery by God of His own nature, He could not, prior to that creation, have been infinitely Perfect. This alternative, however, brings us, as we have seen, within sight of a non-Theistic cosmology. II. " There are some things," says Mr. Campbell, " im possible even to omnipotence, and one of them is the realisation of a love that has never known pain" (p. 49). " Where no need exists, that is where life is infinite, love finds no expression. To realise itself for what it is, sacrifice, that is self-limitation, becomes necessary." These passages make it clear that, in Mr. Campbell's opinion, the love of God is contingent upon the existence of a world of finite particulars (see p. 101). It is, however, difficult to conceive of infinite life without love. One naturally inclines to think that the absence of love would be a most important moral limitation. Is it said that there would be capacity for love? A dormant capacity is a potency (a possibility), and, if we once begin to think of God as " potency," we are on the highroad to non-Theistic theory (see p. 100). These conclusions have an important bearing on Mr. GOD AND THE WORLD 103 Campbell's theory of evil. They suggest, too, this further question : If God achieve love only by passing into finite life, is it only thus that He becomes conscious ? III. In one passage, at least, Mr. Campbell seems to suggest an aesthetic end for the self-realisation of God in the world of finite persons. " If it affords an artist satisfaction to express himself in a beautiful picture, or a great thinker to express his noble thought in a book, surely the highest satisfaction that God can know must be His self-expression in the self-sacrifice of His children. ... It is the satisfaction He receives from the Atonement, and the only one " (p. 175). Mr. Campbell is able to represent this end as a worthy one because he does not recognise that, if God be Infinite Perfection, the satisfaction concomitant upon His self- expression in finite particulars must be poorer than the satisfaction He eternally enjoys. If God be eternally Infinite Perfection, He must eternally possess the infinite perfection of love, and to achieve the satisfaction concomitant upon finite experience would involve declension to a lower " value." x God and Man (a) Thus far we have not been able to discover precisely what relation Mr. Campbell conceives to subsist between the particulars of the world and God. Those particulars, we are told, are the self- realisation or self-expression of God. But what is meant by " self-realisation or self-expression " ? Self-realisation, we have seen, has two denota tions : — (1) It denotes the development of potency (possibility) into actuality ; 1 It should be noticed that, if God be Infinite Perfection or Absolute — that is, qualitatively infinite — Consciousness, self-expression in (or self-limitation to) the imperfections of finite existence would " express " what God is not. I64 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF (2) It denotes the re-presentation of things already existent, which, by the re-presentation, are brought into consciousness, or into clearer consciousness. Theprocessindicated bythefirstdenotation I have called developmental self-realisation. The second process I have called re-presentative self-realisation. If the finite particulars of the world be the developmental self-realisation of God, God is the existential reality of each particular. Each particular is God — is God developed or self- expressed in a certain way and form. If, however, they be the re-presentative self-realisa tion of God, they are not of the Divine substance — God is not their existential reality, although they re-present facts of the Divine Nature. If this be God's mode of self-expression, then is His self- expression comparable with a work of art, which represents its object in and through another medium — a sunset through the medium of painted canvas, a resting god through marble. (b) We have not, as yet, found any clear indica tion which of these possible and alternative modes Mr. Campbell conceives to be the actual mode of God's self-expression. When, however, we turn to Mr. Campbell's account of the relation sub sisting between man and God we find what is, I think, a clear suggestion that God and man are of one nature, that man is of the Divine substance. "To ordinary common-sense nothing seems more obvious than that we know most that is to be known about our friend, John Smith. . . . But, according to the newer psychology, this GOD AND THE WORLD 105 matter-of-fact Englishman is not what he seems even to himself. His true being is vastly greater than he knows. ... It belongs ... to the plane of eternal reality. This larger self is, in all probability, a perfect and eternal spiritual being integral in the being of God. His surface self ... is the incarnation of some portion of that true eternal self which is one with God" (pp. 31,32). " A third inference, already hinted at and pre sumed in all that has gone before, is that the highest of all selves, the ultimate Self of the uni verse, is God. The New Testament speaks of man as body, soul, and spirit. The body is the thought-form through which the individuality finds expression in our present limited plane ; the soul is man's consciousness of himself as apart from all the rest of existence, and even from God . . . the spirit is the true being thus limited and expressed — it is the deathless Divine within us ... it is at once our being and God's. What we are here to do is to grow the soul, that is to manifest the true nature of the spirit, to build up that self-realisation which is God's ob jective with the universe as a whole, and with every self-conscious unit in particular" (p. 34). We find the same doctrine, in other words, in the later chapter entitled, " Jesus, the Divine Man." "The terms with which we have to deal are Deity, Divinity, and Humanity. ... It follows from the first principle of the New Theology that all the three are fundamentally and essentially one, but in scope and extent they are different. By the Deity we mean . . . the all-controlling 106 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF consciousness of the universe, as well as the infinite . . . abyss of being beyond. By Divinity we mean the essence of the nature of the imma nent God. . . . Show us perfect love, and you have found us the divinest thing the universe can provide, whether it knows itself to be immedi ately directed and controlled by the infinite con sciousness of Deity, or whether it does not. . . . Humanity . . . stands for that expression of the Divine nature which we associate with our limited human consciousness. Strictly speaking the human and Divine are two categories which shade into and imply each other : humanity is Divinity viewed from below ; Divinity is humanity viewed from above. If any human being could succeed in living a life of perfect love ... he would show himself Divine, for he would have revealed the innermost of God"1 (pp. 74, 75). Man then, is essentially of the one only Divine substance ; he is, as it were, part of God. The spirit, which is man's true self, is the " deathless Divine " within each one of us — " it is at once our being and God's." (c) I have spoken of the Divine substance. Mr. Campbell described God as consciousness — infinite consciousness — not as substance. 1 Cp. the following passages from the same chapter :— " We have to get rid of the dualism which will insist on putting humanity and Deity into two separate categories " (p. 81). " Present-day Unitarianism is preaching with favour and clearness the foundation truth of the New Theology, the fundamental unity of God and man " (p. 82). Cp., also, the following passage : " Where, then, some one will say, is the dividing line between our being and God's ? There is no dividing line except from our side. The ocean of consciousness knows that the bay has never been separated from itself" (pp. 34, 35). On p. 40 we read of " the fundamental identity of God and man." GOD AND THE WORLD 107 The following passages, which have been quoted once before, show what relation Mr. Campbell conceives to subsist between infinite and finite consciousness : — "The Infinite Consciousness sees itself as a whole ; the finite consciousness sees that same whole in part" (p. 33). "The larger and fuller a consciousness be comes, the more it can grasp and hold of the consciousness of God " (p. 28). " Individuality only has meaning in relation to the whole, and individual consciousness can only be fulfilled by expanding until it embraces the whole" (p. 33). " The mind that thinks the universe must be immeasurably greater than my own, but in so far as I too am able to think the universe, mine is one with it" (p. 26). Finite consciousness, we gather, is related to Infinite Consciousness as " part " to " whole." This is the very relation that I have already described in terms of substance. It appears, then, that, according to Mr. Camp bell, man is God or part of God — is God existing as man. God's self-expression in man is a de velopmental self - expression or self - realisation, and, if it illustrate the mode of His self-expression in other finite particulars, then is God substan tially present in every finite particular. Of each one He is the existential reality.1 Each is — not 1 Cp. the following passage : " How can there be anything in the universe outside of God ? " (p. 18). Also the following: "In a sense, of course, everything that exists is Divine, because the whole universe is an expression of the being of God" (p. 75). 108 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF a re-presentation of God or of something in His nature, but is God, is God self-limited to that particular mode of being. This appears to be the doctrine implied in the following interesting and singular passage : — "Thus we get two modes of God — the in finite, perfect, unconditioned, primordial being ; and the finite, imperfect, conditioned, and limited being of which we are ourselves expressions. And yet these two are one" (p. 23). Note. — The New Theology as the Religion of Science Mr. Campbell claims for the New Theology that it is " the religion of science " (p. 1 5). "It is the denial that there is, or ever has been, or ever can be, any dissonance between science and religion ; it is the recognition that upon the foundations laid by modern science a vaster and nobler fabric of faith is rising than the world has ever known before. Science is supplying the facts which the New Theology is weaving into the texture of religious experience" (p. 15). " So far science has only succeeded in giving us a vaster, grander conception of God, by giving us a vaster, grander conception ofthe universe in which we live" (pp. 17, 18). If it be true that God is the universe — the universe and something more — it is clear that science (within its own range) is an exploration of the Divine Nature, and the theology which asserts the divinity of the world may fairly be called " the religion of science." Note. — The Self-limitation of God The thought of God's self-limitation is very prominent in Mr. Campbell's New Theology. " Supposing God to be the infinite consciousness, there are still possibilities to that consciousness which it can only know as it becomes limited" (p. 22). " We have seen, too, that it is by means of the universe and His self-limitation that He expresses Himself to Him self" (p. 25). GOD AND THE WORLD 109 " The coming of a finite creation into being is itself of the nature of a fall — a coming down from perfection to imperfection. We have seen the reason for that coming down; it was that the universal life may realise its own nature by attenuating or limiting its perfection. If I want to understand the composition of the ordinary pure-white ray, I take a prism and break it up into its constituents. This is just what God has been doing in creation " (p. 66). Self-limitation implies that the limited being which is the result of the limitation is not existentially separated from the original, non-limited being, but is that being made subject to certain self-imposed conditions. The last of the three passages quoted in this note sug gests an interesting resemblance between the New Theology and Vedantism. The "creation" of the world by the breaking up of the Divine perfection seems very like the "creation" of finite existence in the "veil of Maya." CONCLUSION (a) This, then, is the result of our inquiry : according to Mr. Campbell, God is the finite parti culars of the universe and something more. But what is that " something more " ? Infinite con sciousness, says Mr. Campbell, which is self- expressed in, or self-limited to, those particulars. But, again, what is infinite consciousness ? The adjective " infinite " may denote either ex tensive or qualitative infinity — either a consciousness that knows (or is capable of knowing) everything, or a consciousness that is what modern thinkers ordinarily call absolute. A consciousness of the former sort would be generically like our own ; a consciousness of the latter sort would be generi cally unlike, our own, for it would transcend the limitations of "subject-object" experience, within which our consciousness is characteristically no MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF confined, and this transcendence would be its dis tinctive note. When Mr. Campbell tells us that God is Infinite Consciousness, of what kind of Infinity does he think ? We have not been able to discover. Some of Mr. Campbell's words point to the one conception, and some to the other. (b) If, however, there be one thought which, more than any other, is essential in Mr. Campbell's doctrine, it is the thought of self-realisation or self-expression.1 Now, in an earlier part of our inquiry, we found that, if the Divine consciousness be extensively infinite, it cannot undergo self-realisa tion. (i) If it be a consciousness capable of an extensively infinite " awareness," it is already, as consciousness, completely real, and has no content that can become developed into actuality, or re presented (cp. p. 88).2 (2) If it be a consciousness with an extensively 1 " What I have to say leads back through Hegehanism to the old Greek thinkers, and beyond them again to the wise men who lived and taught in the East ages before Jesus was born. It is that this finite universe of ours is one means to the self-realisation ofthe infinite" (p. 22). 2 It may be said — Does not the self-realisation of God consist, ac cording to Mr. Campbell, in giving this infinite " awareness " a content ? I think not. The argument runs as follows : — God is consciousness without content, but capable of receiving an extensively infinite content. In the universe of particulars, this capacity to know is realised in actual knowledge. That realisation, however, cannot be a self-realisation of Infinite Consciousness, because consciousness, as such — consciousness that is not a consciousness of anything, mere " awareness " — cannot develop out of itself its own content. Because of this incapacity for self-development, the content wherein GOD AND THE WORLD in infinite content, it is already aware of everything — there is nothing left for either kind of self-realisa tion to bring forth (cp. p. 87). We found also that, if the Divine consciousness be qualitatively infinite (if it be Absolute Conscious ness), it is equally incapable of developmental self- realisation — for Absolute Consciousness is already perfect (completely real), and can essay re-presenta tive self-realisation only by a declension to lower forms of life. Because such a declension would be an act of aesthetic depravity, the conception that the universe is the re-presentative self-realisation of a consciousness qualitatively infinite seems to be outside the limits of reasonable theory (cp. p. 99). (c) We made more than one attempt to interpret the Divine Nature in a way that would permit us to think of the universe as being the developmental self-realisation of God, but each of these attempts — partly because of difficulties inherent in that conception of the universe, and partly because of the additional difficulty introduced by Mr. Camp bell's description of God's creative self-realisation as eternal — brought us, not to Theism, but to the Infinite Consciousness is said to be realised must come from without. But, according to Mr. Campbell, there is no " without " whence it could come. " All existence," says Mr. Campbell, " is consciousness." Now, there cannot be another consciousness outside Infinite Consciousness. If, then, all existence be consciousness, and God be Infinite Consciousness, He must be the sole existent, the One without a second ; there can be nothing beside Him that could give His consciousness content. Therefore, Mr. Campbell cannot suppose the Infinite Consciousness to be mere " awareness " that gradually receives a content, for, were it mere awareness, it could never (according to Mr. Campbell's philo sophy) receive a content, and there would not now be an existent universe of particulars. 112 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF some kind of raora-Theistic doctrine (cp. pp. 88-93 and p. 99). (d) One difficulty, however, we have been able to remove. It seems clear that the self-realisation or self-expression of God is supposed by Mr. Campbell to take place by self-limitation. God is the particulars of the universe, and they are God — God self-limited to finite existence. God is their existential reality ; they are of the Divine substance.1 Now, if the particulars of the universe be part of God — forms or modes of God — and if they come into being through the self-realisation of God, that creative self-realisation must be of the kind I have named developmental, for only in that kind of self-realisation are the results of self- realisation substantially identical with the nature self-realised or self-expressed in the results. If God be the particulars of the universe and they His self-realisation, the self-realising process must be one in which God has become those particulars ; each particular must be the result of the develop ment, within the Divine nature, of some potency (possibility) which, when developed, is that parti cular. Self-realisation of this kind — by the transi tion from potency into actuality — is what I have designated developmental self-realisation. Re-presentative self-realisation, on the other hand, does not and cannot take place in and through the substance of the thing realised, but in and through another medium (another substance). It involves the kind of re-presentation characteristic of Fine Art (cp. p. 104). 1 See the last section : " God and Man." GOD AND THE WORLD 113 Neither can this kind of self-realisation take place by self-limitation, for in self-limitation there is no transition into another medium (another substance). The result of self-limitation does not re-present the original non-limited Being, it is that Being, — that Being existent under certain self-imposed conditions. God cannot re-present Himself by limit ing Himself : if the universe be God in self-limited existence, it cannot be the re-presentation of God. The self-expression or self-realisation of God in the world's finite particulars is, then, a de velopmental self-expression or self-realisation — an evolution of and in the Divine nature. Now, the thought of self-expression is the characteristic note of the New Theology. It is essential and distinctive in Mr. Campbell's doc trine of God, in his account of the world-process, in his theory of human life, in his Christology. If, then, the New Theology be a coherent system of thought, its conception of God must be con sistent with this central and governing idea. Let us ask, then — To what conception of God does this thought of developmental self-realisation point ? The answer seems clear — it points to the conception that God is a potency gradually becoming realised (actualised) in the particulars of the world.1 As we have seen, this conception leads to Atheism. Self-limitation, indeed, is otherwise indicative, for, according to Mr. Campbell, the self-limitation which creates the universe is a self-limitation of the Perfect. 1 Only "potency" (possibility) can undergo developmental self- realisation (cp. p. 84). H 114 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF But the self-limitation of the Perfect to the imperfection of finite existence would necessarily be — as Mr. Campbell admits — "of the nature of a fall," and we have already seen that such a de clension would create the gravest moral difficulty. If God be Perfect, He cannot thus decline, for a voluntary declension to lower values for the sake of those lower values — and Mr. Campbell suggests no other motive — would be, at least, non-moral (cp. p. 99). The thought of self-limitation is, as I have said, prominent in Mr. Campbell's thought, but — because of the ethical difficulty the supposition would create — we cannot reasonably suppose that self- limitation is the actual mode of God's self- expression in finite particulars. Yet the thought of self-expression — of self- realisation — is essential in Mr. Campbell's doctrine, and must in some way be retained in our explana tion of that doctrine. In what way can it be retained ? Only, I think, by abandoning the thought of self-limitation, and regarding the self- expression of God as true self-realisation — i.e. as developmental self-realisation, self-realisation by the development of potency (possibility) into actu ality. Were we to adopt this correction, we should think of God or (as we would then prefer to say) Ultimate Reality as an undeveloped nature (a potency) gradually realising itself in the world of particulars.1 It would now be more than that world, but its transcendent being would be only 1 The resultant conception would be very similar to Schopenhauer's conception ofa purposeless Will in eternal "expression " (cp. p. ioo). GOD AND THE WORLD 115 potency (possibility) and would be inferior to the world of particulars as potency is necessarily inferior to — because less than — actuality (cp. p. 92). This conception of Ultimate Reality could, how ever, hardly be called Theistic.1 Pantheism Let us return to Mr. Campbell's own statement of his doctrine. "Where, then, ... is the dividing line be tween our being and God's ? There is no dividing line except from our side. The ocean of consciousness knows that the bay has never been separated from itself. . . . But, the reader may protest, this is Pantheism " (pp. 34, 35). Were the protest made it would not be un reasonable, for, certainly, a doctrine which asserts the essential unity of God and man, and teaches, more or less clearly, that God is the particulars of the universe, would ordinarily be designated Pantheism. Mr. Campbell, however, denies rhetorically that the New Theology is a form of Pantheism. " But, the reader may protest, this is Panthe ism. No, it is not. ' Pantheism ' is a technical 1 It should be remembered that Mr. Campbell describes creation as eternal. But, es we have seen, an eternal process cannot be purposeful. This creates another difficulty. It seems very hard to conceive of a Perfect Being who is eternally self-expressed by a necessitated (because unpurposed) process. The more clearly Theistic Mr. Campbell's thought appears — and it is never more clearly Theistic than when Mr. Campbell speaks of the self-limitation of the Perfect — the more clearly it seems to involve difficulties that can be overcome only by the thought itself being radically transformed. 116 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF term in philosophic parlance, and means quite different from this. It stands for a Fate-God, a God imprisoned in His universe, a God who cannot help Himself, and does not even know what He is about, a blind force which here breaks out into a rock and there into Ruskin, and is equally indifferent to either. But that is not my God. My God is my deeper Self, and yours too — He is the Self of the universe, and knows all about it. He is never baffled, and cannot be baffled ; the whole cosmic process is one long incarnation and uprisings of the being of God from itself to itself. With Tennyson you may call this doctrine the Higher Pantheism, if you like ; but it is the very antithesis of the Pantheism which has played such a part in the history of thought" (p. 35). Really, Mr. Campbell's points seem quite un important. Pantheism is the doctrine which asserts that God is the universe. But, as we have already seen, this is the very conclusion to which the New Theology leads — God is the particulars of the universe. It may be that certain non-philosophical forms of Pantheism have asserted also that the universe is God, but all the philosophies ordinarily called pantheistic assert, I think, or imply that God is more or less transcendent. He is not merely the particulars of the universe ; He is something- more, e.g. the ground and unity of those par ticulars. We find this in Vedantism, in Spinozism, in Neo-Platonism (if, indeed, that philosophy be a form of Pantheism). We find it also in GOD AND THE WORLD 117 Hegehanism, and we find it, not more clearly, in the New Theology. " My God is my deeper Self, and yours too ; He is the Self of the universe." This is precisely what the Vedantist says of his God. " He is never baffled, and cannot be baffled." So any Pantheist would say. Pantheos cannot be baffled, for He is the One Only Existent, and there is no one that can oppose Him. What ever happens is an incident in His life. " The whole cosmic process is one long incarnation and uprising of the being of God from itself to itself." A Pantheistic Hegelian could say this. According to Mr. Campbell, the God of Pan theism is " a Fate-God." But Mr. Campbell has himself told us that creation is an eternal process, and we have seen for ourselves that, if it be eternal, it must be necessitated (see p. 91). Now, a God who is eternally in necessitated self-expression does not seem very different from " a Fate-God." "My God," says Mr. Campbell, "is . . . the Self of the universe, and knows all about it." The God of Pantheistic Hegehanism is also "the Self of the universe," and He " knows all about it." l It may be that Mr. Campbell would deny that Hegehanism is a form of Pantheism, because, according to Hegelian thought, God is Spirit, not Substance, and, in His present relation to the world of particulars, is characteristically Subject. But, according to Hegelian thought, He is those par ticulars, and the difference between subject and object is a difference within His universal life. He is the One Only Existent, and the universe 1 Because He is the Universal Subject. n8 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF is His Self-manifestation. He is the universe, and something more. It can hardly be con tended that this doctrine does not fall within the limits of philosophical Pantheism ! It differs from the typical forms of that doctrine — Vedantism and Spinozism — chiefly in its conception that God is Spirit and Subject. The difference is, doubtless, an important one, but it does not seem to make the Hegelian doctrine non-pantheistic. Neither Vedantism nor Spinozism is pantheistic because of its characteristic conception of the essential nature of "God." Each is rightly called pan theistic because it teaches that " God " is the universe. But the Hegehanism I have called pantheistic also teaches this, and so does Mr. Campbell's New Theology. It seems clear that — if there be such a thing as philosophical Pantheism — the New Theology, as Mr. Campbell presents it, is a form of that Pantheism. What else could it be designated ? The Immanence of God The name " New Theology," Mr. Campbell tells us, " has long been in use ... to indicate those who believe that the fundamentals of the Christian faith need to be rearticulated in terms of the im manence of God " (p. 3). The New Theology, he says, is " an untrammelled return to the Christian sources1 in the light of modern thought. Its starting-point is a re-emphasis of the Christian 1 Something has been said concerning the " return to Christ " in my article on Liberal Theology. GOD AND THE WORLD 119 belief in the Divine Immanence in the universe and in mankind. The doctrine requires to be placed effectively in the foreground of Christian teaching" (p. 4). (a) What is meant by the immanence of God ? "Immanence" means "indwelling," and the doctrine of the Divine Immanence is the doctrine which asserts that God is not outside (or not only outside) the world, but present in the world — intimately present in each particular of the world. Men have sometimes thought of God as the Great First Cause who, having created the world, remains outside the world, and permits it to run a mechanical course under the direction of its own laws.1 The doctrine of the Divine Imma nence overcomes this supposed aloofness of God from the world, and has religious value because it does overcome this aloofness — because it repre sents God, not as One afar off and unconcerned, but as a closely besetting Reality and a Spirit intimately present within us. (b) It is clear that this doctrine of the Divine Immanence presupposes a distinction between God and the world in which He is said to be present.2 Now, according to the New Theology, God is the particulars of the world. But, if He be those particulars, the thought of indwelling (immanence) neither accurately nor adequately defines His relation to them. Substantial identity 1 This form of thought is ordinarily called Deism. 2 I dwell in my house, but I am not my house. 120 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF is inconsistent with immanence, and, as the New Theology is a doctrine of substantial identity, it is not a doctrine of immanence. (c) This, however, is not a demerit. The doc trine of the Divine Immanence presupposes a really extended universe which God pervades, and it presupposes also, I think, that God Himself is ex tended, for it is difficult to conceive that something which pervades extension is itself non-extended. But the critical philosophy has, I think, made at least one permanent contribution to thought. It has taught us that God must transcend space ; that, whatever space be to us, to God it can be only a form of presentation or " position," a form wherein He posits finite particulars, or presents them to Himself. He alone is self-existent ; everything else exists " in " Him. The world is in God, we are told, as thoughts in the mind. The concep tion may not be final, but it is helpful, and suggests, what I believe to be true, that God's relation to the world is closer than even the doctrine of immanence asserts. That doctrine presupposes the vulgar concep tion of space. If space had the reality which the plain man ordinarily attributes to it, it would or might separate God from the world that is in space. The doctrine of the Divine Immanence asserts that it does not, because (according to that doctrine) God pervades space. That doctrine, however, pertains exclusively to popular levels of thought, and to the philosophic theologian it can be (at the best) only an accommodation to popular thought. It is, indeed, little (if anything) more GOD AND THE WORLD 121 than a temporary shelter for comfortable emotion half-way on the road from the coldness of Deism to philosophic insight. Individual Immortality The New Theology clearly teaches that man is immortal, but does it permit us to believe that human individuality is immortal ? Is it a doctrine of " personal immortality " ? What does Mr. Campbell say ? The following passages are, I think, the most important : x — (1) "No part of the universe has value in and for itself alone ; it has value only as it expresses God. To see one form break up and another take its place is no calamity, however terrible it may seem, for it only means that the life con tained in that form has gone back to the uni versal life, and will express itself again in some higher and better form " 2 (p. 24). (2) " Our present consciousness of ourselves and of the world can reasonably be accounted a fall, for we came from the infinite and unto the infinite perfection we shall in the end return. I do not mean that our present consciousness of ourselves is eternal ; I only assert that our true being is eternally one with the being of God, and that to be separated from a full knowledge of that truth is to have undergone a fall " (p. 66). (4) " I start, then, with the assumption that 1 These passages should be read in connection with those already quoted (see p. 107) to illustrate Mr. Campbell's conception of the relation subsisting between finite and infinite consciousness. a Ordinarily, language such as this indicates or conceals disbelief in " personal immortality." 122 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF the universe is God's thought about Himself, and that in so far as I am able to think it along with Him, ' I and my Father ' (even metaphorically speaking) ' are one' " (p. 26). (4) " Ultimately your being and mine are one, and we shall come to know it. I shall not cease to be I, nor you to be you ; but there must be some region of experience where we shall find that you and I are one" (pp. 33, 34). (5) " Nothing that exists in your consciousness now and constitutes your self-knowledge will ever be obliterated or ever can be ; but in a higher state of existence you will realise it to be part of the universal stock" (pp. 33, 34). (6) " I build my belief in immortality on the conviction that the fundamental reality of the universe is consciousness, and that no conscious ness can ever be extinguished, for it belongs to the whole, and must be fulfilled in the whole. The one unthinkable supposition from this point of view is that any kind of being which has ever become aware of itself, that is, has ever contained a ray of the eternal consciousness, can perish " (pp. 230, 231). (7) "Again, some of my friends have been pointing out that, while the New Theology regards all mankind as being of one substance with the Father, our consciousness of that being is our own. I freely admit this while maintaining that there is no substance but consciousness. What other kind of substance can there be ? Therefore, I hold that when our finite con sciousness ceases to be finite, there will be no distinction whatever between ours and God's. GOD AND THE WORLD 123 The distinction between finite and infinite is not eternal " (p. 42). (8) "The being of God is a complex unity, containing within itself and harmonising every form of self-consciousness that can possibly exist. No one need be afraid that in believing this he is assenting to the final obliteration of his own personality. . . . No form of self-consciousness can ever perish. It completes itself in becoming infinite, but it cannot be destroyed " (p. 42). " We come from the infinite and unto the infinite perfection we shall in the end return." But in what manner shall we therein subsist ? Shall we be merged in the consciousness of God ? or will each one of us retain his individuality, although aware that he is part of a great whole ? In the final constitution of Reality — when the world- process (the self-realisation of God) is complete — will there be One Only Divine Consciousness, or will consciousness then (as now) be plural ? (a) We notice at once that, in certain passages,1 Mr. Campbell speaks as though the difference between each finite consciousness and the con sciousness of God were merely a difference in range. We know less of the universe than God knows. Were our consciousness to become co extensive in range (in content) with God's, the present difference between the human and the Divine (between man and God) would cease — at least, this appears to be Mr. Campbell's meaning. Even now, in so far as we think what God thinks, 1 See p. 107. 124 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF we are one with Him. These passages suggest that consciousness is something common to God and man, and that, in each of its manifestations, whether in God or in men, it has only accidental and temporary marks of individuation. They sug gest that consciousness is now, as it were, cut into pieces which differ only in size and position, and that, one day, the pieces now separated will be re-united. But if this suggestion be not mislead ing, it is clear that after re-union there will be only one consciousness — the present plurality will have entirely disappeared. This conception of consciousness, however, omits the characteristic note of consciousness — the note which makes each individual conscious ness essentially unique. Brown does not differ from Smith merely because his consciousness is not co-extensive in range with Smith's, but be cause it is his consciousness and not Smith's. Each man's consciousness has a. certain essential quality which makes it his and not another's. That essential quality is present throughout the entire range of his consciousness, and immediately pervades every extension of its range. No exten sion is without that quality ; no extension weakens or changes it. Consciousness is not passive awareness. It is characteristically an activity — an activity of self- reference — and its range is widened, not by a mechanical addition to its content, but by a living synthesis, which organises new experiences around an unique centre of attention, and so builds up an ever-widening body of knowledge. That unique centre is the individual self, and, in each one of GOD AND THE WORLD 125 us, consciousness is characteristically seen in self- reference — in the reference of experience to that unique centre. This self-reference makes each individual's experience exclusively his own. Mr. Campbell does not ignore this quality, but he sets it aside, and repeats that " when our finite consciousness ceases to be finite, there will be no distinction whatever between ours and God's '' (see quotation No. 7). But if every human consciousness now have this essential quality, and be thereby made unique, it does not seem that the mere extension of range — even an extension unto infinity — would deprive a given consciousness of that individuating quality. After the extension, it would still be A's conscious ness and not B's. Suppose every human con sciousness to become extensively infinite, each would retain the quality which now makes it unique ; there would be no merging of human individualities in each other, or of all in God. Each consciousness now individual would (although infinite) remain eternally distinct, and, since each human consciousness is, according to Mr. Camp bell, part of God, God would be a complex unity of several centres of attention, each the organising centre of a consciousness extensively infinite (cp. quotation No. 8). (b) Let us, however, now suppose the con sciousness of God to be qualitatively infinite — different from ours, not only in range, but in kind (see p. 94 et seq.). If the consciousness of God be qualitatively in finite, then, in the transition from finite to infinite 126 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF consciousness, the present difference between God's infinite consciousness and our finite consciousness would, no doubt, be transcended. But would our individuality be lost ? The question is a difficult one, but it should, I think, be answered affirma tively. It is very hard, if not impossible, to form more than a vague conception of a consciousness quali tatively infinite, but it seems clear that separate- ness of individuality — the separateness which now divides this man A from that man B — pertains only to the sphere of finite (subject-object) ex perience. After a general transition into Infinite (Absolute) Consciousness, there would be, not many individuals, but one only individual — the Absolute — in whose consummating " awareness " the dis tinction between subject and object would not exist (see p. 96). At present every individual is objective to other individuals — each man to other men, and all men to God. In a consciousness qualitatively infi nite there would be no objectivity. Again, finite experience is characteristically an experience wherein a subject is aware of an object. Each subject is an unique centre of attention, and the " awareness " of each subject has an essential quality — the quality of self-reference — which makes it also unique. The existential uniqueness of each centre is the ground of separate personality : the qualitative uniqueness of each awareness is the note or sign of separate personality. In Absolute Consciousness, however, neither ground nor note would exist. In that Consciousness there would be no recognition of objects by subjects — for the GOD AND THE WORLD 127 distinction between subject and object would have been left behind in the transition from finite ex perience — and, therefore, no centres of recognitive attention and no self-reference of recognitive experience. We cannot be certain, however, that Mr. Camp bell believes the consciousness of God to be qualitatively infinite. (c) Does the New Theology give us a sufficing assurance of " personal immortality " ? An explicit assurance it does not give, and Mr. Campbell's thought — compact of mutually incon sistent elements — is so confused that we cannot safely make any inference from it. The Practical Value of the New Theology According to Mr. Campbell, the New Theology discloses an unique dignity, actual or possible, in all human life, even the lowliest. "Thus, to the question — Why a finite uni verse ? I should answer, because God wants to express what He is. ' God. is the perfect Poet, Who in creation acts His own conceptions.' " This is an end worthy alike of God and man. The act of creation is eternal, although the cosmos is changing every moment, for God is ceaselessly uttering Himself through higher and ever higher forms of existence. We are helping Him to do it when we are true to ourselves ; or rather, which is the same thing, He is doing it 128 MR. CAMPBELL'S DOCTRINE OF in us. . . . To think of God in this way is an in spiration and a help in the doing of the humblest tasks. It redeems life from the dominion of the sordid and commonplace. It supplies an in centive to endeavour, and fills the heart with hope and confidence. To put it *in homely, everyday phraseology, God is getting at some thing, and we must help Him. We must be His eyes, and hands, and feet : we must be labourers together with Him" (pp. 23, 24). (a) It seems clear that Mr. Campbell values the fundamental conceptions of the New Theology be cause he infers from them that human life is, or should be, co-operant with the Divine life. A similar inference, however, can be made from any theology which exhibits the world-process as a purposeful development towards a Divinely- appointed goal. Certainly, we who stand in the Catholic tradition of Christian thought have no difficulty in reaching Mr. Campbell's inference. Our theology is not an " otherworldliness." We believe that human history, in its earthly process and achievement, is informed by a Divine purpose — by the purpose otherwise expressed in the world's redemption, and in the edifying ministry of the Church. We believe, also, that, when work ing along the lines of that purpose, we are truly co-operant with God. What more helpful thought does the New Theology afford ? (b) Will, however, the New Theology bear the inference that there is in human life the higher dignity which Mr. Campbell discovers ? The New GOD AND THE WORLD 129 Theology, as Mr. Campbell presents it, will, I think, sufficingly sustain that inference. But we may not forget our results. We have seen that the central thought of the New Theology — the thought of self-expression — can be held logically only if we be content to believe that the universe is either — (1) An unmoral self-limitation (declension) of God to values lower than those He eternally enjoys ; or (2) The necessitated development of some non- Divine Reality. Neither alternative seems very valuable, or sug gests any dignity that our more earnest thought would count worthy. Around this thought of self-expression Mr. Campbell has rhetorically woven web after web, glistening attractively with the dews of religious emotion ; but his webs are only gossamer. They are not "the diamond network of thought," and they vanish at the first touch of criticism. IV THE PERSON AND WORK OF OUR LORD THE PERSON AND WORK OF OUR LORD In our last chapter we examined, first of all, the passages which indicate the foundations of Mr. Campbell's Theism, and, afterwards, Mr. Camp bell's account of the nature of God and His relation to the world of finite existence. We have now to consider Mr. Campbell's Christology and his doctrine of Atonement. To consider these fairly, we must, for a time, forget' our criticisms, and we must accept the New Theology — with its characteristic account of God and the world — as it is proffered. It has, I think, an inadequate Apologetic and a Cosmology which Christian thought should reject, but it is not thereby foredoomed to failure in another field. In Apologetic we have to establish the reason ableness of Theistic belief ; in Cosmology we have to form some general conception of the world and the world-process. But Christology presumes the results of this earlier work — it com mences, for example, with the conception of God, and is not called upon to prove that conception valid. We start our new inquiry, then, with Mr. Camp bell's uncriticised results — with the thought that 134 THE PERSON AND WORK the world of finite existence is the self-realisation (or self-expression) of God — and we ask, first of all — What account does Mr. Campbell give of the central facts of the Christian religion, of our Lord's Person and work ? OF OUR LORD 135 The Person of our Lord Fortunately, Ihe outlines of Mr. Campbell's Christology are quite clear. "Briefly summed up, the position is as follows : Jesus was God, but so are we. He was God be cause His life was the expression of Divine love : we, too, are one with God in so far as our lives express the same thing. Jesus was not God in the sense that He possessed an infinite conscious ness : no more are we. Jesus expressed fully and completely, in so far as a finite consciousness ever could, that aspect of the Nature of God which we have called the eternal Son, or Christ, or ideal Man who is the Soul of the universe, and 'the light that lighteth every man that cometh into the world ' : we are expressions of the same primordial being. Fundamentally we are all one in this eternal Christ" (pp. 94, 95). In this passage Mr. Campbell does not do full justice to his own thought. According to Mr. Campbell, God is the particulars of the universe. It follows that Jesus is God not merely through similarity of character, but through identity of essence (substance). He is God self-limited to, or self-expressed in, a certain finite existence. But in precisely the same way all finite particulars — ourselves, General Booth, the crocodile, and all material things — are God.1 1 Cp. the following passage : — " In a sense, of course, everything fhat exists is Divine, because the whole universe is an expression of the being of God. But it can hardly be seriously contended that a crocodile is as much an expression oi God as General Booth. It is wise and right, therefore, to restrict the word ' Divine ' to the kind of consciousness which knows itself to be, 136 THE PERSON AND WORK The following passages call for a passing com ment : — " If by the Deity of Jesus is meant that He possessed the all-controlling consciousness of the universe, then assuredly He was not the Deity, for He did not possess that consciousness " (pp. 77, 78). "Then are we to understand that the self- limitation of Jesus means that the . . . eternal Son . . . quitted the throne of His glory . . . and lived for thirty-three years as a Jewish peasant? I think the dogmatic theologian would have some hesitation in giving an un qualified affirmative to this question, for the difficulties implied in it are practically insur mountable. Was the full consciousness of the Eternal Word present in the Babe of Bethlehem, for instance ? If not, where was it ? Questions like these cannot be answered on the lines of the conventional Christology. The plain and simple answer to all of them is to admit that the Jesus of history did not possess the consciousness of Deity during His life on earth. His conscious ness was as purely human as our own " (p. 79). " According to the received theology, Jesus and rejoices to be, the expression of a love which is a consistent self- giving to the universal life. ' God is love : and he that dwelleth in love dwelleth in God, and God in him.' General Booth is Divine in so far as this is the governing principle of his life. Jesus was Divine simply and solely because His life was never governed by any other principle. We do not need to talk of two natures in Him, or to think of a mysterious dividing line, on the one side of which He was human, and on the other Divine. In Him humanity was Divinity, and Divinity humanity " (pp. 75, 76). No one supposes the crocodile to be as much " an expression of God" as General Booth, but, if "the whole universe" be "an expres sion of the being of God," the crocodile is as truly "an expression of God" as General Booth, or Jesus, or anything else. OF OUR LORD 137 was God, and yet He did not possess the all-con trolling consciousness of the universe" (p. 39). " The very things which the critics declare to be impossible of personality in general in relation to God, they are affirming of at least one person ality — that of Jesus. If Jesus was God and yet prayed to God, if His consciousness was finite and yet one with the infinite, it is clear that in this one instance the seemingly impossible was not impossible" (pp. 40, 41). (1) By "the Deity of Jesus" orthodox theo logians do not mean that Jesus "possessed the all-controlling consciousness of the universe." According to the Catholic tradition of faith, " That which was born of the Virgin is God " because He is "of the Substance of the Father." We do not suppose that His consciousness was identical or co-extensive with the Father's : we know, in fact, that it was not. As to the relation between the consciousness of the Eternal Word and the consciousness of Christ "during His life on earth," it does not seem inconceivable that a spiritual existent (the Eternal Word) is diversely conscious in two spheres — in the Divine sphere and in the sphere of finite existence. The relation between the consciousness of the Eternal Word — " in whom all things consist" — and the consciousness of Christ during the years of His humiliation would seem to be similar to that which Mr. Campbell conceives to exist between the sub-liminal self and the supra-liminal self. There is only one entity (one self), but that "functions" — one 138 THE PERSON AND WORK hardly ventures to say "is conscious" — in two spheres, in the sub-liminal sphere and in the supra-liminal. (2) What are "the very things" that "the critics declare to be impossible " ? Chief among them, I surmise, is the conception that the infinite Divine consciousness expresses itself in the finite consciousness of man. In declaring such expres sion to be impossible " the critics " are, I thirjk, right, up to a certain point. Consciousness, whether in Gied or man, is essentially an individual thing. Every personal consciousness, wherther God's or man's, has an intrinsic and essential character which makes it the consciousness of a particular existent — of God, or of this or that man.1 Mr. Campbell's mistake — a mistake that goes down to the very roots of his philosophy — is to suppose that consciousness is independently existent. The truth seems to be that conscious ness is always a function of substance? an activity or property of something that is conscious. If, however, we once recognise that conscious ness has its ground in substance, there is no insuperable difficulty in the conception that one substance is conscious in several personalities.3 1 Cp. p. 124. 2 In this connection " substance " does not mean " extended sub stance." It certainly does not mean "matter." 3 The doctrine of the Holy Trinity seems to involve such a plural awareness in one substance. I have said that consciousness is a function of substance. If this be true, personality is a functional mode of substance. This definition would make the difference between the modern word "person" and the patristic iroixrunrov less than it is sometimes sup posed to be. OF OUR LORD 139 It follows from this that Pantheism is not finally refuted by the argument that one con sciousness cannot subsist in a plurality of Divine and human persons — cannot be at one and the same time the Infinite Consciousness of God and the finite consciousness of each individual man — for this argument does not exclude the possibility that one Divine Substance is conscious in such a plurality, and that possibility is clearly pantheistic. If my surmise concerning the objections made by Mr. Campbell's critics be correct, it is clear that those critics do not affirm of the personality of Jesus the "very things" which they "declare to be impossible of personality in general in relation to God." Orthodox Hunkers affirm that the Virgin-Born is God because they believe Him to be of the Divine Substance, not because they believe Him to possess or to share the Divine consciousness. Is the New Theology Unitarian ? Mr. Campbell anticipates the protest — This is sheer Unitarianism ! " But then, some one will protest, this is sheer Unitarianism after all ; you do not believe in the Jesus who is the object of the faith of Christen dom, but in one who was only a man among men ; you do not think of Him as very God of very God" (p. 81). What does Mr. Campbell say ? " Not so fast ; we are busy with names again. . . . This is not Unitarianism, and I do believe 140 THE PERSON AND WORK that Jesus was very God, as I have already shown. We have to get rid of the dualism which will insist on putting humanity and Deity into two separate categories. I say it is not Uni tarianism, for historic Unitarianism has been just as prone to this dualism as the extremist Trinitarianism has ever been. Like Trinitarian- ism it has often tended to regard humanity as on one side of a gulf and Deity as on the other: it has emphasised too much the tran scendence of God " (pp. 8 1, 82). (a) It is undoubtedly true that the New Theology differs widely from the older kind of Unitarianism. According to the latter, Jesus was man, and is not God : according to the former, Jesus (although man) is God. Again, the older, Unitarianism taught a purely monadistic theology. It asserted the unity of God in a way that excluded the thought of plurality. But (according to the New Theology) God — whatever else He be — is the particulars of the universe : all human life, for example, is a form of the Divine life. God is One, but within His unity there is an endless diversity, and, since (according to Mr. Campbell) the act of creation is eternal, there has never been a time when He has not been a plurality in unity. The doctrine of the New Theology, then, is widely different from the characteristic doctrine of old-fashioned Unitarianism. (b) We may not, however, ignore the fact that modern Unitarianism has been largely influenced OF OUR LORD 141 by the philosophical conceptions that have shaped the New Theology. As Mr. Campbell himself admits, "present-day Unitarianism is preaching with fervour and clearness the foundation truth of the New Theology, the fundamental unity of God and man" (p. 82). Nevertheless, Mr. Camp bell declines " to be labelled Unitarian," and he declines, apparently, because (in his opinion) the New Theology is a reformation that makes the familiar classification of religious thought obsolete. "The old issue between Unitarianism and Trinitarianism vanishes in the New Theology ; the bottom is knocked out of the controversy " (P- 83)- 142 THE PERSON AND WORK The Doctrine of the Trinity Some, it may be, will say that, whether the New Theology should or should not be called Unitarian, it shares with Unitarianism one important charac teristic — they are both anti-Trinitarian. Mr. Campbell tells us, however, that " we can not dispense with the doctrine of the Trinity, for it, or something like it, is implied in the very structure of the mind" (p. 85). Physical science, " after a fashion," implies the doctrine of the Trinity (p. 86), and even Professor Haeckel " be lieves in the doctrine " (p. 87). "All thinking," says Mr. Campbell, "starts with an assumption of some kind, and exact thought requires that that assumption shall be the simplest possible, the irreducible minimum beneath which we cannot get. Now, when we start thinking about existence as a whole, and ourselves in particular, we are compelled to assume the infinite, the finite, and the activity of the former within the latter. In other words, we have to postulate God, the universe, and God's operation within the universe. Look at these three conceptions for a moment, and it will be seen that every one of them implies the rest ; they are a Trinity in unity. The primordial being must, be infinite, for there cannot be a finite without something still beyond it. We know, too, that to our experience the universe is finite ; we can measure, weigh, and analyse it — an im possible thing to do with an infinite substance. And yet if we think of infinite and finite as two OF OUR LORD 143 entirely distinct and unrelated modes of existence, we find ourselves in an impossible position, for the infinite must be that outside of which nothing exists or can exist ; so of course we are compelled to think of the infinite as ever active within the finite, the source of change and motion, the exhaustless power which makes possible the very idea of development from simplicity to complexity"1 (pp. 86, 87). (a) According to Catholic doctrine there are, in the unity of the Divine Essence (technically designated Substance) three Divine Existents (technically designated Persons). Each Person is eternal, and each is Perfect God. This plurality within the Godhead is not contingent upon the Divine activity in creation. The distinctions asserted by Mr. Campbell are, however, entirely contingent upon that activity. If they be eternal, it is only because creation is eternal. Moreover, Mr. Campbell's distinctions are not the distinctions indicated by Catholic thought. For example, the Second Person in Mr. Camp bell's Trinity is merely the finite particulars of the world, many of which are impersonal. He is " the immanent God," and is those particulars 2 — "the finite, imperfect, conditioned, and limited being of which we are ourselves expressions " (p. 23). Not thus have we been taught to think concerning the Intelligible Word ! 1 It seems clear that the First, and Second Persons in this account of the Trinity — the one primordial and infinite, the other finite — are identical with the "two modes of God" elsewhere described (see quotation on p. 42). 2 Those particulars and nothing more, for "the immanent God"' has no transcendence. 144 THE PERSON AND WORK (b) Mr. Campbell, however, gives another de monstration of the Trinity ; incomplete, indeed, but sufficiently exhibited for us to be certain that it is quite inconsistent with the demonstration already noticed. "Thinkers have always been compelled to construe the universe in terms of the highest known to man, namely, his own moral nature. It was natural, therefore, that while they thought of the universe as an expression of God, they should think of it as the expression of that side of His being which can only be described as the ideal or archetypal manhood. The infinite being of God is utterly incomprehensible to a finite mind. . . . But we are justified in holding that, whatever else He may be, God is essentially man — that is, He is the fount of humanity. There must be one side, so to speak, of the infinitely complex being of God in which humanity is eternally contained, and which finds expression in the finite universe. ... If we think, there fore, of the archetypal eternal Divine Man, the source and sustenance of the universe, we cannot do better than think of Him in terms of Jesus ; Jesus is the fullest expression of that eternal Divine Man on the field of human history. Here, then, we have the first and second factors in the doctrine of the Trinity morally and spiritually construed" (pp. 88, 89). " Jesus expressed fully and completely, in so far as a finite consciousness ever could, that aspect of the nature of God which we have called the eternal Son, or Christ, or ideal Man who is the Soul of the universe, and 'the light that OF OUR LORD 145 lighteth every man that cometh into the world ' ; we are expressions of the same primordial being " (PP- 94, 95)- According to this account, the Second Person — " the eternal Son " — is not the world of finite par ticulars, but an "aspect" of the Divine nature. He is, indeed, expressed in the universe, but is other than the particulars in which He is ex pressed. He is not "the immanent God" — who is finite — but an aspect of the " infinite being of God " ; which is, we are told, " utterly incom prehensible to a finite mind," and " in regard " to which " the most devout saint is as much an agnostic as the most convinced materialist " (p. 89). In other words, "the eternal Son, the Christ," is entirely transcendent. The Second Person in Mr. Campbell's first demonstration is, however, precisely what the " eternal Son " of the second demonstration is not. He is "the immanent God." He is the particulars of the universe. He is not the tran scendent God. It is noteworthy that Mr. Campbell does not derive this doctrine of " the eternal Son " from Scripture.1 The ground of his doctrine is not in the Christian revelation, but in a philosophical argument — in the regressive argument from " our highest," from Jesus, to the nature and character of God. This argument we have already con sidered (p. 67 et seq.), and there is no need to 1 "The idea of a Divine Man, the emanation of the Infinite, the Soul of the universe, the source and goal of all humanity, is ages older than Christian theology" (pp. 89, 90). The Scriptures furnish Mr. Campbell, not with the ground of his doctrine, but with illustrations of it. K 146 THE PERSON AND WORK re-exhibit its limitations and deficiencies. Unless we are content to play with words, it will not sup port a Christology acceptable to orthodox thought. The " eternal Son " of Mr. Campbell's imaginative speculation is not the Personal Word of Catholic tradition. Sin I do not propose to discuss at length Mr. Campbell's theory of Sin, but a short account of it will be a helpful introduction to his doctrine of atonement. The following are the most important illustrative passages : — " There is no sin that is not selfishness ; there is no selfishness that is not sin.1 All possible activities of the soul are between selfishness on the one hand and love on the other" (p. 146). " The life of love is the life that is lived for im personal ends : the sinful life is the life lived for self alone. The life of love is the life which does the best with the self for the sake of the whole : the sinful life is the life which is lived for the self at the expense of the whole. The desire for gratification at some one else's cost, or at the cost of the common life, is the root principle of sin. Sin against God is an offence against the common life : it is attempting to draw away from instead of ministering to the common good" (p. 146). "And yet, my friends, realise this, ... sin itself is a quest for God — a blundering quest, but 1 Cp. the following : — " I have already pointed out that sin is selfishness, pure and simple, and that definition will cover all its manifestations " (pp. 145, 146). " Sin is the opposite of love " (p. 51). OF OUR LORD 147 a quest for all that. The man who got dead drunk last night did so because of the impulse within him to break through the barriers of his limitations, to express himself, and to realise more abundant life. His self-indulgence just came to that : he wanted, if only for a brief hour, to live the larger life, to expand the soul, to enter untrodden regions, and gather to himself new experience. That drunken debauch was a quest for life, a quest for God. The roue you saw in Piccadilly last night . . . was engaged in his blundering quest for God. . . . All men are seeking life — life more abundant — even in their selfishness and wrong-doing. . . . ' Whatever crazy sorrow saith, No life that breathes with human breath Has ever truly longed for death' " (p. 153). " Like love, selfishness is a quest for life ; but whereas love obtains more abundant life by freely giving itself, sin loses hold on life by trying to grab and keep it. Every man is seeking life, and seeking it in one or other of these opposite ways. . . . But life is God, and there is no life which is not God. God is the life all-abundant. . . . Every man, consciously or sub-consciously wants that life ; he is wanting it all the time " (pp. 146, 147). (a) The doctrine that sin is a mistaken quest for God has aroused against Mr. Campbell no small indignation, and, indeed, it is utterly in defensible — a thoroughly false piece of rhetoric. It is true that man's desire is always for life 148 THE PERSON AND WORK itself, or for something that would, he thinks, were it attained, make his life more valuable. And it is not mere rhetoric to say either that, in the profoundest sense, God is our life, or that, even in his sins, man is seeking something that would, he thinks, make his life at least momen tarily more valuable. But we cannot thence infer that, when seeking the " values " proffered by sin, man is seeking God. He is, indeed, moved by the thought of "value," and the highest "value" is God, but, when he prefers the " values " of sin, he does not mistake them for Divine. Ordinarily he knows that they are not Divine, and in his quest for them, he knows that he is not seeking God. The most that can be said is that, if the quest for " values " were perfectly reasonable and moral, it would be a quest for God, but this is as though we said that, were sin not sin, man would therein be seeking God. (b) It is, however, even more important to notice that, according to Mr. Campbell's teaching, the sin of man is a Divine activity,1 a self-expres sion or self-realisation of God. According to the New Theology, every human being is a self-expression of God, his life a self- limitation of the Divine life to a particular finite existence. Each human life is part of the uni versal self-expression of God. It follows, then,- that even the sins of each life are part of that 1 Mr. Campbell describes sin as "a misuse of Divine energy" (p. 161). Now, a "misuse " is a " use," and (according to Mr. Camp bell) the life that misuses is a self-limitation of the Divine life. OF OUR LORD 149 self-expression, for there is nothing in any human life that is not of God. Man has, it is true, free will, but the power within him that is said to be free is the Divine power — the Power that is God. The free spirit of man is a self-limitation of the One Divine Spirit, and all its activities are activities of God. These are the plain teachings of the New Theology, and it seems impossible to avoid the conclusion that, according to the ,New Theology, it is God Himself who is sinning in the sins of men. What agency is there that is not His ?l Atonement Mr. Campbell's doctrine of atonement — like his Christology — is quite clear. "Atonement is the assertion of the funda mental oneness of man with man, and all with God. Sin is the divisive, separating thing in our relations with one another, and with God the source of all, so the assertion of our oneness involves getting rid of sin. If we ask how this is to be done, the answer is simple enough : the only way to get rid of selfishness is by the ministry of love. What is it that is slowly winning 1 Mr. Campbell himself tells us that "the immanent God" is im perfect. It appears that His imperfection includes moral imperfection. Mr. Campbell tells us also that "the imperfection of the finite creation is not man's fault but God's will" (p. 67). Mr. Campbell is discussing "the nature of evil," and is speaking with immediate reference to the (real or apparent) physical imperfection of the finite creation. This imperfection, he says, is of God. It follows, I think, from his own first principles, that the moral imperfection of the finite creation is also of God — is a self-expression of God. 150 THE PERSON AND WORK the world from its selfishness to-day . . . ? There is but one thing that is doing it, and that is the spirit of self-sacrifice. Wherever you see that you see the true Atonement at work" (p. 165). "Go into any home where the spirit of self- sacrificing love is trying to do anything to supply a need or save a transgression, and you see the Atonement. Follow that Salvation lassie to the slums, and listen to her as she tries to persuade a drunken husband and father to give up the soul- destroying habit which is such a curse to wife and child, and you see the Atonement. Go with J. Keir Hardie to the House of Commons, and listen to his pleading for justice to his order, and you see the Atonement. See that grey-haired father patiently pleading with selfish hot-headed youth, or yielding up his own hard-won possessions to pay the gambler's debts and save the family name, and you have the Atonement" x (p. 173). " On the field of human history the death of Jesus is the focus and concentrated essence of this age-long atoning process, whereby selfishness is being overcome and the whole race lifted up to its home in God. Until Jesus came, no self-offering had been so consistent and so complete. . . . He showed men the ideal life by living it Himself. . . . In a selfish world that life was sure to end on a Calvary of some kind, but the very fact that it did so demonstrated the completeness of its victory 1 Cp. the following passage : — ' ' Let any man ask himself what it is that is saving the world to-day . . . and he cannot find a better answer than the fifty-third of Isaiah. It tells of Jesus ; but it tells also of all the sons of God who, in the spirit of Jesus, have ever given their lives in the service of love." OF OUR LORD 151 over all considerations of self-interest. Selfishness lost the battle by seeming to gain it " (p. 166). " It is easy to see how much the world owes to Jesus in this regard. I cannot tell what the world might have been had there never been a Jesus, but certain it is that the sacrificial life and death of Jesus have meant the outpouring of a spirit into human affairs such as had never been known in the same degree before. Here for the first time men saw a perfect manifestation of the life that is life indeed . . . the life that in the presence of selfishness must inevitably be come sacrifice, the life of Atonement ; in a sinful world that life had to come to a Calvary, but, in so doing, in refusing to shield and save itself, it became the greatest moral power and the greatest revelation of God that the world has ever known. What we succeed in doing some of the time Jesus did all the time ; when all men are able to do it all the time, the Atonement will have be come complete, and love Divine shall be all in all" (pp. 173, 174). In another passage, Mr. Campbell describes the patriotic self-sacrifice of Arnold von Winkelreid at the battle of Sempach. He then continues as follows : — " Such acts as these form part of the cherished lore of nations. . . . Something tells us that an act like that, the giving of a life for the sake of an ideal, a cause, a country, was a great thing. ... In that very battle, Austria was trying to grasp and hold, Switzerland was trying to get free and live her own life, and here was a man who, for the sake of his country's ideal, gave all that he 152 THE PERSON AND WORK had — his life. Will you tell me where to look for the focus and the centre of that ideal ? I know what your answer would be. It was at Calvary. The one thing which . . . men have recognised in Jesus that has given Him His supreme attrac tion for the world is this — He was absolutely dis interested. It is the disinterestedness of Jesus, His utter nobleness, His power of projecting Himself into the experience of others, and trying to lift humanity as a whole to His experience of God, that gave Him His power with mankind. Jesus not only proclaimed, but lived, the counter tendency to the law of sin and death " (pp. 159, 160). Mr. Campbell foresees an inevitable question : — " But in what sense is the death of Jesus a satisfaction to tl^e Father?" (p. 175). His reply is unambiguous — " In no sense at all." " But then, some will say, What has the death of Jesus effected in the Unseen so as to make it possible for God to forgive us ? Nothing what ever, and nothing was ever needed. God is not a fiend, but a father" (p. 175). " Jesus did nothing for us which we are not also called upon to do for ourselves and one another in our degree. Faith in his atoning work means death to self that we may live to God ; as self-hood perishes on its Calvary, the Christ, the True Man, the Divine reality in whom we are one with all men, rises in power in our hearts, and unites us to the source of all goodness and joy. Institutional, forensic, external, the Atone ment never has been arid never will be. But vicarious sacrifice, willingly accepted, is the great OF OUR LORD 153 redeeming force by which the world is gradually being won to its true life in God, for vicarious suffering is the expression of the law, that in a finite world the service of the whole involves pain. . . . The sacrifice of Jesus is the central and ideal expression of this principle on the field of time, but it only possesses meaning and value as it is repeated in our own lives ; the Christ has to be offered perpetually on the altar of human hearts" (p. 198). («) It seems clear that, if sin be selfishness, it is overcome in and through the life of love. It seems equally clear that such overcoming of sin — such atonement, as Mr. Campbell would say — is a process that takes place entirely within the in dividual heart. Each man must accomplish his own atonement, must in his own life overcome sin by love. Nothing that another can do will help him, except in so far as it moves him to love,1 Philanthropic effort — Mr. Keir Hardie's or the Salvation Army lassie's — is not, we infer, itself an atonement. If it be successful, and renew a sinful life, that renewal, that actual overcoming of sin, — not the helpful sympathy which accomplished it, — is the atonement when philanthropy succeeds in 1 Cp. the following passage : — "To sum up. Atonement is the assertion of the mndamental unity of all existence, the unity of the individual with the race and the race with God. The individual can only realise that unity by sacrificing himself lo it. To fulfil the self we must give the self to the All. This is the truth presumed in all ancient^ideas of Atonement" (pp. 139, 140). It is clear that the described unity can be achieved or realised only by each man for himself, in and through his own self-sacrifice. If Atonement be the achievement or realisation of that unity, each man must work out his own atonement. Another cannot atone for him. 154 THE PERSON AND WORK awakening love, that success, and that alone, is the real atonement. When it fails to awaken love there is no atonement. (b) It is quite true that victory over sin is always an achievement within the individual heart. How ever we interpret the " benefits " of our Lord's Passion, those "benefits" become ours only through personal acts of apprehension — through sincere repentance and lively faith. But those apprehend ing acts are not themselves the Atonement for our sins. That is objectively accomplished by Christ, and His work is a sufficing Atonement, whether we receive its benefits or ignore them. (c) Here, then, we have a most important differ ence between the New Theology and Catholic doctrine. The Atonement of the New Theology — the actual supersession of sin by love — is not the Atonement of the Catholic religion. The latter Atonement — purely objective in its essential character — is declared by the New Theology to be non-existent. (d) Our Lord has Himself told us that His blood was " shed for many unto remission of sins." According to Catholic doctrine the work which accomplished that remission, and that work alone, constitutes the Atonement. Now, the remission of sins is one thing, and the supersession of sin by love quite another. It is only of the latter that Mr. Campbell takes account. According to him, that supersession, and that alone, constitutes Atonement. OF OUR LORD 155 Have we, then, any ground for thinking remission to be necessary ? I think we have. There seems nothing un reasonable in the thought that sin has " objective " consequences — consequences other than those within the sinful heart — and that these, unless they were overcome, would be an obstacle to the com plete reconciliation of man with God. It seems clear from the New Testament that the first Christians believed that such an obstacle had existed, and that it had been overcome in and through the Passion of our Lord, and could not otherwise have been overcome. Moreover, when we read our Lord's own words concerning His work and death, it seems very difficult to reject this belief. The Uniqueness of Our Lord According to the distinctive tradition of Christendom, our Lord is unique because in His one Person there are two natures. Being God and Man, He is what we are not, and never can become. But, according to Mr. Campbell, Jesus had not this essential uniqueness. He was, indeed, essentially God, but, then, so is everything else — General Booth and a crocodile, Mr. Campbell him self, his followers, and his opponents. And, indeed, Mr. Campbell attributes to our Lord only a moral uniqueness. " Briefly summed up, the position is as follows : Jesus was God, but so are we. He was God because His life was the expression of Divine love ; we, too, are one with God in so far as our 156 THE PERSON AND WORK lives express the same thing. . . . Jesus ex pressed fully and completely, in so far as a finite consciousness ever could, that aspect of the nature of God which we have called the eternal Son . . . ; we are expressions of the same primordial being " (pp. 94, 95). " The reason why the name of Jesus has such power in the world to-day is because a perfectly noble and unselfish life was crowned by a perfectly sacrificial death " (p. 123). " Many a British soldier has died as brave a death as Jesus, but none have ever lived the life of Jesus. The life and death together were a per fect self-offering . . . and therefore the greatest manifestation of the innermost of God that has ever been made to the world" (pp. 124, 125). In " the sacrificial r life and death of Jesus," we are told, men saw for the first time " a perfect manifestation of the life that is life indeed . . . the life that in the presence of selfishness must inevitably become sacrifice." "In a sinful world," continues Mr. Campbell, " that life had to come to a Calvary, but, in so doing, . . . it became the greatest moral power and the greatest revelation of God that the world has ever known." " What we succeed in doing some of the time Jesus did all the time "(p. 174). According to the New Theology, Jesus (like every other man) was a self-expression of God. He differed from others, not in kind, or in essential 1 " Self-sacrificing " would be more accurate than " sacrificial." Ac cording to the New Theology, the sacrifice in our Lord's death was none other than the sacrifice of self, which those who love are always making. "Love is essentially self-giving" (p. 50). OF OUR LORD 157 nature, but only in character. He loved more perfectly than they, and therefore revealed the love of God more completely than they. He was truly pre-eminent, but His pre-eminence was only the pre-eminence of His love. (a) Now, a moral uniqueness the faith that is called orthodox also attributes to our Lord, for the self-limitation whereby God assumed human nature and submitted to human experience, even to the experience of a lonely death, was an act of sur passing love, which our human love can never rival. It may be said that Mr. Campbell also sets forth the self-limitation of God in Jesus. True, but not an unique self -limitation. According to Mr. Campbell, we have a self-limitation of God in every finite particular, and, if Jesus be the highest of finite particulars, in every other finite particular — in General Booth, in a crocodile — the self-limitation of God must be greater than in Him. God must have limited Himself more to become a crocodile, or General Booth, or a Piccadilly roue', than to become Jesus. Moreover, according to Mr. Campbell, the self- limitation of God in Jesus was not " for us men and for our salvation." It was part of an eternal and universal process, and that process — because it is said to be eternal — we cannot conceive to be purposeful. The distinctive kind of moral uniqueness which orthodox faith discovers in Christ, Mr. Campbell does not discover in Jesus. If, however, that uniqueness be set aside, what is left ? Only a 158 THE PERSON AND WORK possible pre-eminence in human love. " Only a possible pre-eminence " ? Yes, for were our Lord only what He seems to be in Mr. Campbell's New Theology, it would be hard to demonstrate that He loved more than others have loved. Jesus, Mr. Campbell tells us, is "on the throne." En throned He may be by Mr. Campbell's faith,1 but He is not enthroned by Mr. Campbell's thought, for that leaves Him one among many — each as truly as He an incarnation of " the eternal Son " — and uncertainly the first of many. (b) Yet we find Mr. Campbell strongly asserting the uniqueness of Jesus. " It is no use trying to place Jesus in a row along with other religious masters. He is first, and the rest nowhere ; we have no category for Him" (p. 70). " I have already devoted some little space to emphasising the obvious fact that it is impossible to deny the uniqueness of Jesus ; history has settled that question for us. If all the theologians and materialists were to set to work to-morrow to try to show that Jesus was just like other people, they would not succeed, for the civilised world has already made up its mind on that point, and by a right instinct recognises Jesus as the unique standard of human excellence. But this is not to say that we shall never reach 1 " Let us go on thinking of Jesus as Christ, the very Christ of glory, but let us realise that the same Christ is seeking expression through every human soul. He is incarnate in the race in order that by means of limitation He may manifest the innermost of God, the life and love eternal. To say this does not dethrone Jesus ; it lends significance to His life and work. He is on the throne, and the sceptre is in His hand" (pp. 108, 109). OF OUR LORD 159 that standard too ; quite the contrary. We must reach it in order to fulfil our destiny, and to crown and complete His work" (p. 76). " Lest any one should think that this position involves in the slightest degree the diminution of the religious value and the moral pre-eminence of Jesus, let me say that it does the very opposite. Nothing can be higher than the highest, and the life of Jesus was the undimmed revelation of the highest. Faith to be effective must centre on a living person, and the highest objective it has ever found is Jesus " (p. 96). If it indeed be true that history has settled the question, history has "settled" only that Jesus is morally pre-eminent.1 And a moral pre-eminence is all that Mr. Campbell directly attributes to Him. He was not " just like other people," but He differed from them only in kind. Indeed, accord ing to Mr. Campbell, what He was we have to become. It is quite true that Christ is " the highest objec tive " of human faith. But He is thus pre-eminent, not because of His pre-eminent character, but be cause His unique nature makes His Person an unique revelation. It is not clear that the New Theology provides any " objective " for human faith. The general structure of that theology requires us, I think, to believe that the ground of human faith is in a philosophical doctrine, in the conception that our human love is a trustworthy self-expression of 1 The essential uniqueness of our Lord's Person is still denied or ignored by large numbers, even in Christendom. 160 THE PERSON AND WORK God. Whatever be the religious importance attri buted by the New Theology to our Lord, that importance is inferred to Him from that philo sophical conception. This conclusion, if sound, makes it clearer than ever that, according to the New Theology, the uniqueness of our Lord is merely the unique ness which pertains to moral pre-eminence. If Mr. Campbell's doctrine be true, our Lord can no longer validly be the "objective" of Christian faith, for Christian faith has no longer a valid " objective." The Adequacy of Mr. Campbell's Christology (a) Behind Mr. Campbell's doctrine of the Person of Christ lies the philosophical conception that the universe of finite particulars is the self- expression or self-realisation of God, who is Infi nite Consciousness. This conception Mr. Campbell does not verify, and it involves difficulties which, I think, destroy it, or transform it into a non- Theistic doctrine. But let us assume it to be true ; is the Christology which Mr. Campbell deduces from it an adequate Christology ? There can be no doubt that Mr. Campbell's Christology, although not without precedent, differs widely from the ordinary Christology of Christendom, According to the latter, Christ has two natures. He is man, but He is also God — " Perfect God and perfect man ; of a reasonable soul and human flesh subsisting " — and this union of two natures in His Person makes that Person existentially unique. OF OUR LORD 161 Mr. Campbell, however, rejects the doctrine of the two natures. According to him, our Lord had only one nature. That nature, indeed, was essentially Divine, but the nature of each one of us is also essentially Divine. According to Mr. Campbell, Jesus was, in His essential nature, what we are. According to the doctrine prevalent in Christendom, Christ is what we are not and can not become. (b) It may, however, be urged that Mr. Camp bell's doctrine, although widely different from the doctrine called orthodox, nevertheless gives a re presentation of our Lord adequate to the world's religious needs. The highest form of the need that seems to me distinctively religious x is the need for some sufficing assurance that God exists and is Love. Does Mr. Campbell's Christology set forth One able to meet that need — able to meet it adequately ? Let us return to Mr. Campbell's fundamental conception. God is Infinite Consciousness, and realises or expresses Himself in the world of finite particulars. Jesus was one of those particulars, and from His love Mr. Campbell infers that God is Love. Undoubtedly, according to Mr. Campbell, God was realised or self-expressed in Jesus. But is that particular self-expression of God a sufficient indication to us of God's essential character ? A crocodile and a " Piccadilly roue," according to Mr. Campbell, are also forms of God's self-expres sion or self-realisation. Are they not, then, also 1 See Chapter II., The Nature of Religion. L 1 62 THE PERSON AND WORK indications of His character ? And, if indications, why should they be thought less importantly in dicative than Jesus ? Because Jesus transcends them ? But transcendence has not been demon strated. Jesus, indeed, stands higher in our thought, but is He actually higher in the process of Divine self-expression ? Indeed, is there any " higher " and any " lower " in that process ? May it not be merely the activity of a Nature which is content with self-expression as such, whatever be the character of the expression ? If it be, then the apparent worth — what seems to us to be the worth — of a given particular expression is either non-significant or unimportantly signifi cant. We may say, indeed, that, because it is an expression, its distinctive character must be in the original, but we may say the same concerning every other expression, however widely different therefrom. Let it be granted, however, that God's self- expression in the crocodile and Piccadilly roue is in fact transcended by His self-expression in the love of Jesus and in all other human love. Will or can that transcendent expression be similarly transcended ? Love, we reflect, subsists within " subject-object experience." It can exist only within the con ditions of that experience, and in Absolute Con sciousness, wherein that experience is completely transcended, Love also must be transcended. This, however, is not conclusive. We desire an assurance that God is Love, not to satisfy a merely speculative curiosity, but to meet a practical need — the need that is distinctively religious. That need OF OUR LORD 163 can exist only within the sphere of finite experi ence. When we return — as, according to Mr, Campbell, we shall return 1 — to the Infinite Con sciousness, it will no longer exist. Had we sufficing assurance that to us, within finite experience, God is, and ever will be, Love, that need would be adequately met. Can we, from Mr. Campbell's Christology, reach such an assurance ? This question could, I think, be reasonably answered in the affirmative only if we have some demonstration — similar, let us say, to Hegel's famous dialectical development of concepts — that love is the highest and final form of God's self- expression within the sphere of finite existence. Were such a demonstration given, we could rest assured that, so long as we continue within that sphere, God will be to us a God of love. Mr. Campbell, however, does not give such a demon stration, nor does he attempt to give one. He leaves open the possibility that God's self-expres sion in love will one day be transcended as com pletely as His self-expression in the crocodile is transcended. (e) Let us, however, suppose this difficulty to be in fact overcome by a demonstration such as Mr. Campbell has omitted to give — the love of Jesus, and our love, will then be a trustworthy revelation of a sufficing love in God. But it will be a trust worthy revelation only because Mr. Campbell's 1 " Our consciousness of ourselves and of the world can reasonably be accounted a fall, for we came from the infinite and unto the infinite perfection we shall in the end return " (p. 66). 1 64 THE PERSON AND WORK form of idealism is true, and we shall know it to be trustworthy only if we know that form of idealism to be true. But, in that case, only com petent metaphysicians could be Christians ! It may, however, be said that philosophy is not the only road to truth — that Christ is, in fact, effectually apprehended otherwise than by philo-< sophy. We need not dispute this ; let us admit that, although (ex hypothesi) the Christian revelation is true only because a certain form of idealism is true, it can be sufficiently apprehended otherwise than through that form of idealism. This, how ever, would re-introduce into Christian thought the Gnostic distinction between perfect and im perfect Christians. For the perfect there would be the insight of philosophy ; for the others — for the great majority — a certain practical assurance inferior to that insight as anything which falls short of vision must be to actual vision. Some, it may be, would reply that even to-day, within ordinary Christian society, that distinc tion already exists, for the many have a faith which only a few can prove to be reasonable. The existing distinction, however, is not the dis tinction entailed by Mr. Campbell's doctrine. That doctrine entails two modes of apprehension — one (by philosophy) for the learned, and one (other wise than by philosophy) for the unlearned. But to-day, within ordinary Christian society, all who apprehend Christ effectually do so in one way — by faith. It is unfortunately true that very few are competent apologists and can demonstrate the reasonableness of faith, but it is one thing to demonstrate the reasonableness of faith and quite OF OUR LORD 165 another to claim an independent and superior apprehension. (d) Let us, however, suppose the love of Jesus, and our love, to be a trustworthy revelation that, within the sphere of finite existence, God is and ever will be to usward a God of love — what then ? Would that revelation sufficingly meet our need ? Yes, if we could sufficiently apprehend it. A revelation that we could not apprehend, either because it was too far above us, or because we were in some other way separated from it, would be unavailing — indeed, to us it would not be a revelation. In conformity with Catholic tradition it has already been suggested that sin has " objective " consequences — consequences other than those within the sinful heart. Now, if there be such consequences, it is not unreasonable to believe that they separate men from God in such a way that, until they be overcome or set aside, men cannot effectually apprehend the love of God — that love which is the sufficing response to man's characteristic and deepest need. According to Catholic doctrine such " objective " consequences exist, and have been overcome, once for all, by the "objective" Atonement of our Lord — an Atonement which becomes effectual within us through our individual acceptance of it. The final question, then, suggested by Mr. Campbell's Christology is this : Were our Lord only what Mr. Campbell represents Him to have been — essentially such an one as ourselves — could He have wrought that " objective " Atonement, and 1 66 THE PERSON AND WORK thereby have overcome sinful man's " objective " separation from the sufficing love of God ? The question goes back to the Arian controversy. Had Christ been merely such an one as ourselves, could He be the world's Saviour, and have wrought a "full, perfect, and sufficient" Atonement for the sins of men ? Mr. Campbell says " Yes," but Mr. Campbell does not think of sin as others think of it. Is The New Theology Christian? One question yet remains to be asked and answered — Is the New Theology Christian ? As we have already seen, it is exceedingly difficult, if not impossible, to develop Mr. Camp bell's fundamental conceptions into a self-consistent doctrine acceptable to Christian thought. Let us, however, ignore this difficulty, and take the New Theology as Mr. Campbell presents it— Is that theology Christian ? The following considerations seem to me the most important, and I know of nothing sufficient to countervail against their apparently negative tendency. (i) The New Theology has its ratio credendi— the ground of its credibility — in the philosophic system,1 not in Christian experience, not in the Person, or life, or teaching of our Lord. 1 In the doctrine namely, that we are severally one with the self- realising God. The characteristic assurance given by the New Theology is, indeed, the Ved&ntist assurance — ' ' I am that one " (cp. Libera Theology). In this connection the following passage is noteworthy : " Our present consciousness of ourselves and of the world can reasonably be OF OUR LORD 167 (2) It would be unfair to say that the New Theology does not permit devotion to our Lord. The devotion it permits, however, is not the de votion that Christendom has always character istically paid, but only such devotion as we pay to human goodness. (3) The only thing that the New Theology derives from our Lord is the lesson and example of human love. The love of Jesus is, indeed, set forth as a witness to the love of God, but this evidential character is inferred to it solely from Mr. Campbell's philosophy, not from our Lord's Person or teaching. According to Mr. Campbell the love of Jesus is indicative of God's character only because it is a form of God's self-expression. And Jesus is believed to be a form of God's self- expression, not because of the evangelical declara tions, nor as the result of our present apprehension of His Person, but because (according to a certain philosophical doctrine) every finite par ticular is such a form. (4) The love of Jesus is said, also, to be pre eminent, but it has meaning — it illustrates the character of God — because it is love, not because it is pre-eminent love. The fundamental conceptions of the New Theology compel us to believe that the significance attributed to the love of Jesus is pos sessed by all other human love. accounted a fall, for we came from the infinite and unto the infinite perfection we shall in the end return. I do not mean that our present consciousness of ourselves is eternal ; I only assert that our true being is eternally one with the being of God, and that to be separated from a full knowledge of that truth is to have undergone a fall (p. 66). According to Mr. Campbell, the self-limitation of God to finite existence entailed a loss of knowledge. That loss can be repaired by gain of knowledge, and the knowledge that can repair it is the know ledge asserted in the VedSntist affirmation — " I am that one." 1 68 PERSON AND WORK OF OUR LORD (5) The New Theology stands or falls with its metaphysical foundation. It derives nothing but illustration from the life of our Lord. As a system of thought it is independent of His teach ing and example : its truth is independent of His Person. If it be true, it would be none the less true were the Gospels proved to be wholly mythical, and Jesus no more real than Jupiter. (6) Mr. Campbell finds passages in the New Testament which point — so he thinks — to certain characteristic tenets of the New Theology. But Mr. Campbell does not derive the New Theology from Scripture. The passages he quotes are not the foundations of his doctrine, but at most, from his point of view, interesting anticipations of certain^etails in his doctrine. From these considerations it seems to follow that the New Theology is not a system of Christian thought, but an independent philosophy 1 exhibited in a non-essential and illustrative relation with Christian thought. The Gospels and Christian experience contribute to it neither its truth nor its essential content, but only an illustration — an illustration that could equally well be found elsewhere. 1 It should not be forgotten that the fashion in thought called monistic idealism has already commenced to pass away. Hegehanism no longer has the supremacy it once had, either in Germany or in England. V THE CHURCH THE CHURCH (a) Mr, Campbell contrasts two conceptions of the Church of Christ, which he names respectively the "sacerdotal" and the "evangelical." He him self holds the evangelical conception, but he seems not to be of those who regard the Church as a mere accident in Christian history — an accident created by the natural drawing together of men who share a common loyalty and recognise a common vocation, and indicating or expressing nothing but the human sympathies out of which it sprang. He seems not, I say, to be of those, for (even if it be correct to surmise that he accepts their account of the natural genesis of the Church) he believes, or inclines to believe, that our Lord intended to found a Church — a distinctively Chris tian society or complexus of societies. But, if our Lord intended to found a Church to carry on His work, that Church was not, in the thought of our Lord, a mere accident in His religion, but an appointed instrument — the organism wherein His religion would subsist and through which it would work. But, if the Christian Church be such an instrument and organism, it has its ground, not in human sympathies — which, at most, could only extend it — but in our Lord's creative intention and constituting act. 172 THE CHURCH (b) Even if the Christian religion existed for no other purpose than to exhibit in word and life " the fellowship of love," it could most effectually perform its appointed work in and through a living society. The life of love is an achievement, and men cannot be completely edified into the life of love without mutual help. To the loving heart, indeed, love is always pos sible — even amid the most hostile surroundings — and many a remembered and many an unre- membered saint has proved it to be the victory that overcometh all that an adverse world can do against it. But men to whom Christian love is a new experience can be built up into a fruitful habit of love only by brotherly help. This help can reach them best or only through the en compassing and edifying love of a brotherhood wherein they are the youngest -born of many brethren. Again, although love can live, as a consecrating strength within the heart, amid any surround ings, it can effectually transform the world's prac tical activities only through social forms of life. Industry, for example, can be effectually " bap tized into Christ " only by becoming the industry of a Christian society. The world's industrial new-birth will never come through "atomistic" philanthropy — through individual reformers work ing separately. It can come only through wide co-operation, and this there cannot be with out some kind of social organisation. Even though Christianity had no other mission than to preach and live " the fellowship of love," it could not effectively discharge its mission THE CHURCH 173 otherwise than through corporate forms of Chris tian life.1 (c) This ethical mission the Church of Christ undoubtedly has, but it is not her only mission, and not her most characteristic mission. The Church exists, not merely, by human helpfulness, to edify men into love, but to bring men to Christ, and to give them an apprehension of Him that will become, through daily renewal, the constant refreshment and reinforcement of their love. Something concerning this I have elsewhere said.2 Here I will only repeat the thoughts that seem to me essential. The characteristic note of the Christian religion is the revelation of the Divine Love given in and through the Person of our Lord. We believe that God is Love because, "for us men and for our salvation," He became incarnate, and sub mitted to human experience, and was obedient unto death, even the death of the Cross. It is by setting forth this revelation, and bring ing us helpfully to apprehend it, that Christianity meets our deepest need — the need that seems to me distinctively religious. 1 Few better things could happen to the world than a widespread and intelligent revival of corporate Christian life. Our present un- brotherliness is more than a scandal — it at least partakes of the nature of sin. Christian men are grouped into separate and hostile denomina tions, and within no given denomination — not in the Church of England, not in the " Free Churches "—is there more than the poor beginnings of a genuine common life. We lament the slightness of the impression we make upon the world —the world we should save and have not saved. May it not be that we fail because Christian consciousness is so feeble and has so poor a content ? But how can it be strengthened and enriched, except through the corporate life of Christian brotherhood? 1 See Introduction. Cp. A New Way in Apologetic and Liberal Theology. 174 THE CHURCH The Christian revelation is given to us in a Person — in the Person of Christ, who is God Incarnate — and it becomes effectual in us only in proportion as we rightfully and helpfully ap prehend that Person. Such apprehension the Church exists to give. Through the witness of the Christian society we are brought to an ex perience — again and again renewed within its fellowship — equivalent to that which first evoked St. Peter's faith, and moved him to his great confession. Our Christian faith is distinctively faith in Christ : the distinctive ground of our trust is in His meta physical Person. We are brought to that faith and trust through the witness, and in and through the characteristic life, of the Christian society, wherein the revelation of God is daily renewed. That society is thus the proximate ground of our trust, and the primary problem of Christian thought to-day is to formulate a theory of right belief which shall exhibit that ground as a reason able ground. Were such a theory sufficingly formulated, it would, I think, prove to be a form of Pragmatism, although I do not feel certain that it would be Dr. Schiller's form of Pragmatism. Printed by Ballantyne, Hanson &> Co. Edinburgh df London WORKS BY THE SAME AUTHOR Published by George Allen &> Sons, 156, Charing Cross Road, London. PATRIOTISM : an essay towards a constructive theory of politics an alternative to socialism 5s. net. " Mr. Egerton's ideal and the many issues connected with it he works out in an inspiring and able manner." — The Times. " Mr. Egerton deals with the subject of patriotism in its highest and most reasonable form, and his book is a most admirable treatise." — Birmingham Post. " It goes to the very root of things, and so our interest in its solid and crystalline pages never fades. But though the work is so thorough, philosophical, and searching, it is also at once luminous and enthralling." THE MAINTENANCE OF DENOMINATIONAL TEACHING UNDER THE EDUCATION ACT, 1892 is. 6d. net. "The whole question is most critically and exhaustively discussed, and Mr. Egerton's conclusion is clear." — Daily Chronicle. " Learned, statesmanlike, and powerful." A PLEA FOR CHURCH SCHOOLS 6d. net. " One of the most powerful and impressive contributions to the literature of a great controversy." " It is a serious, calm, winsome, and persuasive statement of a difficult case." A NEW WAY IN APOLOGETIC WITH AN APPENDIX ON DR. FAIRBAIRN'S PHILOSOPHY is. net. Mowbray cV Co. NOTES ON THE EDUCATION BILL, 1906 is. net. THE WITHDRAWAL OF SCHOOLS NOTES ON THE TRUST-DEEDS OF VOLUNTARY SCHOOLS 6d. net. " Timely, judicious, and judicial." " Mr. Egerton . . . tells us just what we most require to know, and hence all his works more than deserve their present wide circulation."Mr. James Verity, Electric Press, Middleton, Manchester. INDIVIDUALISM AND THE STATE id. net. The Personal Rights Association. YALE UNIVERSITY LIBRARY 3 9002 08867 9957 ¦"m^.mM wmmm^ ¦¦:-¦¦>- '-.-v.