M MX'.;- mm MM #888 ilfllt ipl Hi fill iiifi • YALU'WMKVEI&SirirY0 • ]LIIMI&&IEir • 1916 THE SILESIAN HOBSEHERD THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD (DAS PFEBDEBURLA) QUESTIONS OF THE HOUR ANSWERED BY FEIEDEICH MAX MULLEK. TRANSLATED FROM THE GERMAN By OSCAR A. FECHTER WITH A PREFACE By J. ESTLIN CARPENTER, M.A. LONGMANS, GREEN, AND CO. 91 and 93 FIFTH AVENUE, NEW YORK LONDON AND BOMBAY 1903 CoPYRKJHT, 1903, BT LONGMANS, GKEEN, AND CO. PH-Gr Norbjcatf P«sb J. S. Cushing & Co. —Berwick & Smith Co. Norwood, Mass., U.S.A. PREFACE The story of this volume is soon told. In July, 1895, Professor Max Miiller contributed to the Deutsche Rundschau an essay on the lost treatise against Christianity by the philosopher Celsus, known to us through the reply of Origen of Alex andria. This essay, entitled " The ' True History ' J of Celsus," contained an exposition of the doctrine of the Logos and its place in Christian teaching, with reference also to its applications in our modern thought. Among the comments upon it which in diie time found their way to Oxford, was a vigorous, if familiar, letter (dated February, 1896) from a German emigrant to the United States, residing in Pennsylvania, who signed himself by the unusual name of the Pferdebiirla, or "Horseherd."2 His criticisms served as a fair sample of others ; and his letter was published with a reply from Professor 1 The Greek term " logos " was rendered Geschichte in the Ger man title. 2 The word Pferdebiirla is apparently a Silesian equivalent for Pferdebursche, and is represented in this volume by the term "horseherd," after the analogy of cowherd, swineherd, or shep herd. The termination biirla is probably a local corruption of the diminutive biirschel or burschlein. v VI PREFACE Max Miiller in the Rundschau of November, 1896. More letters poured in upon the unwearied scholar who had thus set aside precious time out of his last years to answer his unknown correspondent. One of these, from " Ignotus Agnosticus," supplied a text for further comment, and the whole grew into a little popular apologia, which was published at Berlin in 1899, and entitled Das Pferdebiirla, or " Questions of the Day answered by Friedrich Max Miiller." The veteran teacher thus enforced once more his ideas of the relation of language and thought, in which he had long since recognised the clue to man's knowledge of the relation of his spirit to God. This inner union he found realised in Christ, according to the testimony of the Fourth Gospel ; 1 and the lucid treatment of this great conception, freed from the technicalities of theology, will possibly prove to some readers the most helpful portion of this book. Ranging over many topics, once the themes of vehe ment controversy, the discussion has often an inti mate, familiar, personal air. The disputants on opposite sides had drawn nearer ; they could better understand each other's points of view.2 These pages, therefore, reveal the inmost beliefs of one who had 1 "What difference does it make," he would ask, "whether it was written by the son of Zebedee, or some other John, if only it reveals to us the Son of God ? " (letter from the Vicar of St. Giles's, Oxford, Life and Letters, II, Chap, xxxvi.). 2 See the letters between Max Muller and Dr. G. J. Romanes, Life and Letters, II, Chap. xxxi. PREFACE yii devoted more than fifty years to the study of the history of religious thought on the widest scale, and had himself passed through severe struggles and deep griefs with unshaken calm. No reader of Max Muller's writings, or of the Life and Letters, can fail to recognise in these trusts the secret unity of all his labours. The record of human experience con tained in the great sacred literatures of the world, and verified afresh in manifold forms from age to age, provided a basis for faith which no philosophy or science could disturb. This is the key to the reasonings and appeals of this little book. It was translated as a labour of love by Mr. Fechter, Mayor of North Yakima, in the United States. The translation has been revised on this side of the Atlantic, and is now offered to the public in the belief that this final testimony of a "voice that is still" to the reality of "things un seen " will be welcome to many inquiring and per haps troubled minds. J. ESTLIN CARPENTER. Oxford, April 2, 1903. CONTENTS PAGE Preface v I. The ' True History ' of Celsus ... 1 II. The Horseherd 40 III. Concerning the Horseherd .... 68 IV. Language and Mind 105 V. The Reasonableness of Religion . . . 153 VI. Conclusion 217 THE SILESIAN HOESEHEED The following essays, which were intended pri marily for the Horseherd, but which were published in the Deutsche Rundschau, demand a short explana tory introduction. This, I believe, can best be given by me, by means of a reprint of another essay which appeared in the same periodical, and was the direct cause for the letter, which the writer, under the name of " Horseherd," addressed to me. I receive many such anonymous communications, but regret that it is only rarely possible for me to answer them or to give them attention, much as I should like to do so. In this particular case, the somewhat abrupt, but pure, human tone of the letter appealed to me more than usual, and at my leisure I attempted an answer. My article, which called forth the letter of the Horseherd, was entitled " The ' True History ' of Celsus," 1 in the July number of the Deutsche Rundschau, 1895, and, with a few corrections, is as follows : — I THE 'TRUE HISTORY' OF CELSUS In an article which appeared in the March num ber of the Deutsche Rundschau, 1895, entitled " The Parliament of Religions in Chicago," I expressed my 1 XJeber die Wahre Geschichte des Celsus. b 1 2 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD surprise that this event which I had characterised as in my opinion the most important of the year 1893, had been so little known and discussed in Germany — so little, that the editors of the Wiener Fremden- blatt thought it needful to explain the nature of the Chicago Congress. Likewise, when in answer to the question as to what I should consider the most desirable discovery of the coming year in my depart ment, I answered the discovery of the Sermo Verus of Celsus ; this, too, appeared to be a work so little known, that the editors considered it necessary to add that Celsus was a renowned philosopher of the second century, who first subjected the ever spread ing system of Christianity to a thorough criticism in a work entitled Sermo Verus. The wish, yes, even the hope, that this lost book, of which we gain a fair idea from the reply of Origen, should again make its appearance, was prompted by the recent discoveries of ancient Greek papyrus manuscripts in Egypt. Where so many unexpected discoveries have been made, we may hope for yet more. For who would have believed that ancient Greek texts would be found in a mummy-case, the Greek papyrus leaves being carelessly rolled together to serve as cush ions for the head and limbs of a skeleton? It was plain that these papyrus leaves had been sold as waste paper, and that they were probably ob tained from the houses of Greek officials and mili tary officers, who had established themselves in Egypt during the Macedonian occupation, and whose furni- THE 'TRUE HISTORY' OF CELSUS 3 ture and belongings had been publicly sold and scat tered on occasion of their rapid withdrawal. There were found not only fragments of classical texts, as of Homer, Plato, and the previously unknown treatise on " The Government of the Athenians," not, per haps, composed, but utilised, by Aristotle, but also many fragments of Christian literature, which made it probable that the libraries of Christian families also had been thrown on the market, and that papyrus leaves, when they appeared useless for any other purpose, were used as waste paper, or as a kind of papier-mache. But why should the ' True History ' of Celsus, the Xo'70? a\r)6r)<;, or Sermo Verus, excite our curiosity ? The reason is quite plain. We know practically nothing of the history of the teaching of Christ in the first, second, and even third centuries, except what has been transmitted to us by Christian writers. It is an old rule, however, that it is well to learn from the enemy also, — " Fas est et ab hoste doceri." Cel sus was a resolute foe of the new Christian teaching, and we should, at all events, learn from his treatise how the Christian religion appeared in the eyes of a cultivated man of the second century, who, it seems, concurred in many important points with the philo sophical conception cherished in the Christian church, or at least was familiar with it, namely, the Logos idea ; but who could not comprehend how men, who had once understood and assimilated a view of the world founded on the Logos, could combine with 4 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD it the belief in Christ as the incarnate Logos. To Celsus the Christian religion is something objective ; in all other works of the first three centuries it is, and remains, almost entirely subjective. This could hardly be otherwise, for a religion in its first inception scarcely exists for the outer world. What at that time were Jerusalem and Palestine in the eyes of the so-called world ? A province yield ing little profit, and often in rebellion. The Jews and their religion had certainly attracted the atten tion of Rome and Athens by their peculiarities ; but the Jewish sects interested the classical world much less than the sects of the Platonic and Stoic schools. Christians were regarded as Jews, just as, not many years ago, Jains were treated by us as Buddhists, Sikhs as Brahmans, and Buddhists, Jains, Sikhs, and Brahmans were promiscuously placed in one pile as Indian idolaters. How should the dif ferences which distinguished the Christian from the Jew, and the Jewish Christian from the heathen Christian, have been understood at that time in Rome? To us, naturally, the step which Paul and his associates took appears an enormous one — one of world-wide import ; but of what interest could these things be outside of Palestine? That the Jews who looked upon themselves as a peculiar people, who would admit no strangers, and tolerate no marriages between Jew and Gentile, who, in spite of all their disappointments and defeats, energetically clung to their faith in a deliverer, in an earthly Messiah, THE 'TRUE HISTORY' OF CELSUS 5 and in the coming glory of their nation ; that they should suddenly declare clean what they had always considered unclean ; that they should transform their national spirit into a universal sympathy; yes, that they should recognise their Messiah in a crucified malefactor, indicate a complete revolution in their history ; but the race itself was and continued to be, in the eyes of the world, if not beneath notice, at least an object of contempt. It should not, therefore, surprise us that no classical writer has given us a really historical account of the Christian religion, or has even with one word referred to the wonderful events which, had they actually taken place as described in the Gospels, would have stirred the uttermost corners of the earth. Celsus is the only writer of the second century who, being neither Chris tian nor Jew, was not only acquainted with represen tatives of Christianity and Judaism, but had also, it would seem, carefully read portions of the Old and New Testaments. He even boasts of having a better knowledge of these religions than many of their ad herents (II, 12). That such a man considered this new Christian sect of sufficient importance to subject it to a searching investigation, is proof of his deep insight, and at the same time of the increasing power of Christianity as a religion independent of Judaism. Who this Celsus really was, it is not easy to discover. Even his adversary, Origen, seems to know but little of him ; at any rate he tells us nothing of him, — in deed, we are even still in doubt about his date. It has 6 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD been thought that he is the Celsus to whom Lucian (120-200 A.D.) dedicated his work on the false Alex ander. This is possible ; but Celsus is a very com mon name, and Origen speaks of two men of this name who were both Epicureans and are supposed to have lived in the times of Nero (54-68 A.D.) and Hadrian (118-138 A.D.). It has been argued that the latter could not have been the author of the Sermo Verus, because it apparently mentions the sect of the Marcellians, and this was not founded till the year 155 under Bishop Anicetus. But Origen's remark, that Celsus may have outlived the reign of Hadrian, has been overlooked. At any rate Origen speaks of the Sermo Verus as a work long known, and as he did not die until the year 253 A.D., in his time the work of Celsus would have been recognised as of considerable age, even if written after the year 155. Much learning has been ex pended on the identification of Celsus, which seems to me to have been wasted. It is remarkable that Ori gen made no effort to become personally acquainted with his adversary. He leaves the question open whether he is the same Celsus who composed two other books against the Christians (Contra Celsum, IV, 36). At the end of his book he speaks of him as if he had been a contemporar3r, and asserts that a second book by him against the Christians, which has either not yet been completed or has not yet reached him, shall be as completely refuted as the Sermo Verus. Such language is only used of a con- THE 'TRUE HISTORY' OF CELSUS 7 temporary. Could it be proved that Celsus was a friend of Lucian, then we should know that in the judgment of the latter he was a noble, truth-loving, and cultivated man. It was not Origen's interest to emphasise these aspects of his opponent's character ; but it must be said to his credit, that though he was much incensed at some of the charges of Celsus, he never attacked his personal character. Perhaps it was not fair in Origen to accuse Celsus of being ashamed of his Epicureanism, and of concealing his own philosophical and atheistic convictions, in order to obtain an easier hearing among Jews and Chris tians.1 This does not appear quite fair, for it was a very pardonable device for Celsus first to attack a part of Christian teaching under the mask of a Jew, who represents his faith as the older and more re spectable, and seeks to convince the Christians that they would have done better had they remained true to the religion of their fathers. On the contrary, as Celsus, whatever he may have been except a Jew, could not with a good conscience have under taken an actual defence of Judaism, it was quite nat ural that he should choose a Jew as an advocate of the Jewish religion, and put into his mouth, like a second Philo, ideas which at all events sound more Platonic than Epicurean. Origen was entirely justi fied in showing that in this process Celsus frequently forgot his part ; and this he did with much skill. But whatever Celsus may have been, — an Epicu- 1 Contra Celsum, I, 8. 8 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD rean, or, as has occasionally been maintained, a Neo- platonist, — he was at all events no mean adversary and certainly not unworthy of Origen's steel. If not, why should Origen have felt the need of such an earnest refutation ? He says, certainly, that he did it only at the request of his old friend and protector, Ambrosius. But that is what many writers under similar circumstances have said and still say. We have, at all events, lost much through the loss (or destruction ?) of all manuscripts of Celsus. Not only was he acquainted with the principal philosophical schools of antiquity, he appears also to have studied zealously the religions of the ancient world as they were known at that time to the learned, especially in Alexandria, of which we have but scant know ledge. Origen expressly states (I, 14) that Celsus described the various peoples who possessed religious and philosophical systems, because he supposed that all these views bore a certain relationship to one an other. Without a doubt much has been here lost to us, not only for the history of Greek philosophy, but also for the history of Oriental religions and philoso phies, whose representatives at that time sojourned in Alexandria, yet as to whose personal influence we are almost entirely in the dark. Celsus is presumed to have written of the doctrines of the Egyptians, the Assyrians, the Jews, Persians, Odrysians, Samo- thracians, Eleusinians, even of the Samaneans, i.e. the Buddhists (I, 24), and to have represented these as better accredited than those of the Jews. THE 'TRUE HISTORY' OF CELSUS 9 We see anew what treasures were stored up in Alexandria, and we feel all the more deeply their irrevocable loss. The desire and the hope of re covering the work of Celsus were therefore quite natural for an)r who wished to penetrate more deeply into the spiritual atmosphere of the second and third centuries, and especially for such as strove to understand clearly how men of this age, versed in philosophy, such as Clement and Origen himself, could confess Christianity, or become converted to it, or could defend it against other philosophers without in the least becoming untrue to their philo sophical convictions. That the lower classes among Jews and Greeks followed the new teaching, is much more intelligible, even without wishing to lay too much stress on the evidential value of the miracles at that time. The great majority were accustomed to miracles ; what was almost entirely lacking was practical religion. The Greek thinkers had created systems of philosophy and morals, but the traditional worship had degenerated into a mere spectacle. Even among the Jews the old religion had become a rigid temple ritual, which offered but little comfort and hope to the weak heart of man. In the eyes of the majority of the philosophers of the age every re ligion was only pernicious superstition, good enough for the masses, but scarcely worth consideration by the cultured. That Celsus made the Christian religion the object of serious treatment and refuta tion, not only implies a subtle and unprejudiced 10 THE SLLESIAN HORSEHERD view of his age, but shows us at the same time how the Christianity of that period, entirely independent of the Jewish religion, had gained in significance, and had even in the eyes of a heathen philosopher begun to be esteemed as something important, as something dangerous, as something that had to be combated with philosophical weapons. Christianity is especially indebted for its rapid spread to its practical side, to the energy of its love, which was bestowed on all who were weary and heavy laden. Christ and the apostles had understood how to gather around them the poor, the sinners, the most despised members of human society. They were offered forgiveness of their sins, love, and sym pathy, if they merely promised to amend and sin no more. Among these earliest followers of Christ there was scarcely a change of religion in our sense of the word. Christianity was at first much more a new life than a new religion. The first disciples were and remained Jews in the eyes of the world, and that they came from the most despised classes even Origen does not dispute. Celsus had re proached the Christians because the apostles, around whose heads even in Ms time a halo had begun to shine, had been men of bad character, criminals, fishermen, and tax-gatherers. Origen admits that Matthew was a tax-gatherer, James and John fisher men, probably Peter and Andrew as well ; but de clares that it was not known how the other apostles gained a livelihood. Even that they had been THE 'TRUE HISTORY' OF CELSUS 11 malefactors and criminals, Origen does not abso lutely deny. He refers to the letter of Barnabas, in which it is stated " that Jesus chose men as his apostles who were guilty of sin more than all other evil doers. " 1 He relies upon the words of Peter, when he says, " Depart from me ; for I am a sinful man, O Lord." 2 Paul, in like manner, says in his epistle to Timothy,3 " This is a faithful saying, and worthy of all accepta tion, that Christ Jesus came into the world to save sinners, of whom I am chief." But it is just in this that Origen recognises the divine power of the personality and the teaching of Christ, that by means of it men who had been deeply sunken in sins could be raised to a new life ; and he declares it to be unjust that those who repented of their early sins, and had entered into a pure life, well pleasing to God, should be reproached with their pre vious sinfulness. In this respect he makes, indeed, no distinction between the apostles and such men as Phsedon and Polemo, who were rescued from the mire of their sins through philosophy ; and he recognises in the teaching of Christ a still greater force, because it had proved its saving and sanctifying power with out any of the arts of learning and eloquence. What the apostles were, and what they became through the influence of the Gospel, Origen himself explains in the words of Paul, " For we also were aforetime foolish, disobedient, deceived, serving divers lusts 1 Contra Celsum, I, 63. 2 Luke v. 8. 8 1 Tim. i. 15. 12 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD and pleasures, living in malice and envy, and hating one another."1 He attributes it as an honour to the apostles that, even if their self-accusations were extravagant, they had so openly acknowledged their sins, in order to place the saving influence of the Gospel in a clearer light. But the fact itself, that the apostles had been sinful and despised men, Origen honestly ad mits. We also know with what true humanity Christ himself treated the adulteress : how he chal lenged the Pharisees, if they themselves were free from sin, to cast the first stone at her. And who does not admire the aged Pharisees who silently withdrew, one after the other, from the oldest to the youngest, without casting a stone? Have we many such Pharisees in our time? Jesus, however, dis missed the adulteress with the compassionate words, "Sin no more." That such a course toward sin- laden mankind by one who knew no sin, made a deep impression on the masses, is perfectly intelligible. We see a remarkable parallel in the first appearance of Buddha and his disciples in India. He, too, was reproached for inviting sinners and outcasts to him, and extending to them sympathy and aid. He, too, was called a physician, a healer of the sick ; and we know what countless numbers of ailing mankind found health through him. All this can be quite understood from a human standpoint. A religion is, in its nature, not a philosophy ; and no one could 1 Tit. iii. 3. THE 'TRUE HISTORY' OF CELSUS 13 find fault with Christianity if it had devoted itself only to the healing of all human infirmities, and had set aside all metaphysical questions. We know how Buddha also personally declined all philosophical discussion. When one of his disciples put questions to him about metaphysical problems, the solution of which went beyond the limits of human reason, he contended that he wished to be nothing more than a physician, to heal the infirmities of mankind. Ac cordingly, he says to Malunkyaputta : " What have I said to you before ? Did I say, ' Come to me and be my disciple, that I may teach you whether the world is eternal or not ; whether the world is finite or in finite; whether the life-principle is identical with the body or not, whether the perfect man lives after death or not ? ' " Malunkyaputta answered, " Master, you did not say that." Then Buddha continued, "Did you then say, 'I will be your disciple,' but first answer these questions ? " " No," said the disciple. Thereupon Buddha said : " A man was once wounded by a poisoned arrow, and his friends called in an experienced physician. What if the wounded man had said, I shall not permit my wound to be ex amined until I know who wounded me, whether he be a nobleman, a Brahman, a Vaisya, or a Sudra ; what his name is ; to what family he belongs ; if he be large or small, or of medium size, and how the 14 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD weapon with which he wounded me looked. How would it fare with such a man ? Would he not cer tainly succumb to his wound ? " The disciple then perceives that he came to Buddha as a sick man, desiring to be healed by him as a physi cian, not to be instructed about matters that lie far beyond the human horizon. Buddha has often been censured because he claimed for his religion such an exclusively practical charac ter, and instead of philosophy preached only moral ity. These censures began in early times ; we find them in the famous dialogues between Nagasena and Milinda, the king Menander, about 100 B.C. And yet we know how, in spite of all warnings given by the founder of Buddhism, this religion was soon en tirely overgrown with metaphysics ; and how, finally, metaphysics as Abhidharma found an acknowledged place in the Sacred Canon of the Buddhists. Christianity presents a parallel case. In the be ginning it sought only to call sinners to repentance. The strong, as Jesus himself said, do not require a physician, but the sick. He therefore looked upon himself as a physician, just as Buddha had done in an earlier day. He declared that he was not come to destroy the law, but to fulfil it. The truth of his teaching should be known by its fruits, and there is scarcely a trace in the Gospels of philosophical dis cussions, or even of attacks on the schools of Greek philosophy. But even here it was soon apparent that, for a practical reformation of conduct, a higher conse- THE 'TRUE HISTORY' OF CELSUS 15 cration is essential. It was admitted, as an Indian philosopher is reputed long since to have said to Socrates, that no one could understand the human ele ment who had not first understood the divine. Men of Greek culture who felt themselves attracted by the moral principles of the little Christian congre gations soon, however, wanted more. They had to defend the step which they had taken, and the Chris tianity which they wished to profess, or had pro fessed, against their former friends and co-believers, and this soon produced the so-called apologies for Christianity, and expositions of the philosophical and theological views which constituted the founda tion of the new teaching. A religion which was re cruited only from poor sinners and tax-gatherers could scarcely have found entry into the higher circles of society, or maintained itself in lecture- rooms and palaces against the cultivated members of refined circles, if its defenders, like Buddha, had simply ignored all philosophical, especially all meta physical, questions. How came it, then, that cultured men in high stations, entirely independent, professed Christi anity? how did they make their friends and former co-believers understand that such a step was bona fide ? In answering this question, we get help from Celsus, as well as his opponent, Origen. The bridge which led across from Greek philoso phy to Christianity was the Logos. It is remarkable how much this fundamental doctrine of Christianity 16 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD fell, later on, into the background ; how little it is understood, even by the educated of our own time, and how often, without giving it any consideration, they have cast it aside. In early Christian days this was probably a consequence of the practical and polit ical development of the new religion. But the liv ing nerve of the Christian religion, which was its closest bond to the highest spiritual acquisitions of the ancient Greek world, was thus severed. First, the Logos, the Word, the Son of God, was misunder stood, and mjrthology was employed to make the dogma, thus misconceived, intelligible. In modern times, through continued neglect of the Logos doc trine, the strongest support of Christianity has been cut from under its feet, and at the same time its his torical justification, its living connection with Greek antiquity, has almost entirely passed out of view. In Germany it almost appears as though Goethe, by his Faust, is answerable for the widespread treat ment of the Logos idea as something obscure, in comprehensible, mystical. Many, when reading the opening of the Fourth Gospel, " In the beginning was the Word," say to themselves, " No one understands that," and read on. He who does not earnestly and honestly make an effort to understand this beginning of the Gospel, shows that he is but little concerned with the innermost essence of Christianity, as clearly presented to us in the Fourth Gospel. He forgets that not only faith, but thought, pertains to a re ligion. It is no excuse to say, " Did not the learned THE 'TRUE HISTORY' OF CELSUS 17 Dr. Faust torment himself to discover what ' the word ' here meant, and did not find it out ? " He says in Goethe : — " 'Tis writ : ' In the beginning was the Word ' ! I pause perplexed 1 Who now will help afford ? I cannot the mere Word so highly prize, I must translate it otherwise." But this is just what he ought not do. It was not necessary to translate it at all ; he only needed to accept the Logos as a technical expression of Greek philosophy. He would then have seen that it is impossible to prize the Word too highly, if we first learn what the Word meant in the idiom of contemporary philosophy. Not even to a Faust should Goethe have imputed such ignorance as when he continues to speculate without any historical knowledge : — " If by the spirit guided as I read, ' In the beginning was the Sense,' Take heed. The import of this primal sentence weigh, Lest thy too hasty pen be led astray. Is force creative then of sense the dower? 1 In the beginning was the Power.' Thus should it stand; yet, while the line I trace, A something warns me once more to efface. The spirit aids, from anxious scruples freed, I write : ' In the beginning was the Deed.' " J Had Goethe wished to scourge the unhistorical exegesis of modern theologians, he could not have 1 Miss Swanwick's translation. 18 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD done so better than by this attempt of an interpre ter of the Bible, fancying himself illumined by the spirit, but utterly destitute of all knowledge of his tory. Knowledge of the history of the Greek phi losophy of the first and second centuries after Christ is indispensable to the understanding of such a word as Logos — a word that grew up on Greek soil, and whose first roots reach far into the distant past of the Greek mind ; and for that very reason not admitting of translation, either into Hebrew or into German. Like many other termini technici, it must be under stood historically ; just as logic, metaphysic, analytic, organon, etc., can only be apprehended and under stood historically. Now it is, perhaps, not to be de nied, that even now a majority of educated readers either perfunctorily repeat the first sentence of the Fourth Gospel, " In the beginning was the Word," or believe that something lies buried therein that is beyond the depth of ordinary men. This, of course, is partially true, and it cannot be otherwise in religions which are intended not only for the young, but for the wise and learned, and which should be strong meat for adults, and not merely milk for babes. The fault lies chiefly in the translation, in that it should have been thought necessary to translate a word instead of per mitting it to remain, what it was, a foreign word. This becomes still worse when, as for instance, in cer tain Oriental languages, the newly converted Chris tian has to read, " In the beginning was the Noun or the Verb." The correct translation would, of course, THE 'TRUE HISTORY' OF CELSUS 19 be, "In the beginning was the Logos." For Logos is not here the usual word Logos, but a terminus techni- eus, that can no more be translated out of the lexicon than one would think of etymologically translating Messiah or Christ as the "Anointed," or Angelos as "messenger" or "nuncio." If we read at the beginning of the Gospel, " In the beginning was the Logos," at least every one would know that he has to deal with a foreign, a Greek word, and that he must gain an understanding of it out of Greek philosophy, just as with such words as atom, idea, cosmos, etc. It is remarkable what human reason will consent to. Millions of Christians hear and read, " In the begin ning was the Word," and either give it no thought, or imagine the most inconceivable things, and then read on, after they have simply thrown away the key to the Fourth Gospel. That thought and re flection also are a divine service is only too readily forgotten. Repeated reading and reflection are necessary to make the first verse of the Fourth Gospel accessible and intelligible in a general way ; but one cannot be a true Christian without thinking and reflecting. An explanation of Logos in Greek philosophy is much simpler than is commonly supposed. It is only needful not to forget that for the Greeks thought and word were inseparable, and that the same term, namely, Logos, expressed both, though they dis tinguished the inner from the outer Logos. It is one of the most remarkable aberrations of the 20 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD human mind, to imagine that there could be a word without thought or a thought without word. The two are inseparable: one cannot exist or be even conceived without the other. I believe that I have clearly shown in my Science of Thought that thought without word and word without thought are impossible and inconceivable, and why it is so. Here is the first key to a historical solution of the riddle at the beginning of the Fourth Gospel. We know that Greek philosophy after making every possible effort to explain the world mechanically, had already in the school of Anaxagoras reached the view that the hylozoic as well as the atomic theory leaves the human mind unsatisfied ; and that it is necessary to posit as the origin of all things a thought or thinking mind that manifests itself in the universe. This was the nous, the mind, of Anaxagoras. He could just as well have called it Logos, for the word was in use even before the time of Anaxagoras, to express that reason, the rec ognition of whose all-pervading presence in the universe was the great step in advance made by the system of Anaxagoras. Even Heraclitus had divined the existence of reason in the universe, and had applied to it the name Logos. While the masses recognised in Moira or SeimarmenS only destiny, or fate, Heraclitus declared, that the essence of this Heimarmene is the Logos, the Reason that pervades the world. This is the oldest expres sion of Hegel's thought, "What is, is rational." THE 'TRUE HISTORY' OF CELSUS 21 We must not suppose, however, that Heraclitus con sidered this Logos as identical with his fire. He merely says that the fire is subordinate to the Logos, that it operates Kara rbu \6yov, according to the Logos, or (as we should say) rationally. Our knowledge of the entire system of Heraclitus is of course so fragmentary that we can only speak of this, as of many other points, with great caution. The same is true, although in a lesser degree, of the system of Anaxagoras. His nous, if we translate it by mind, is more comprehensive than Logos. We must not, however, suppose, that this nous bore a personal character, for Anaxagoras expressly states that it is a ^prifia, a thing, even though he would have said that this nous regulated all things. Whether an impersonal mind is conceivable, was still at that time a remote problem. Even in Plato we cannot clearly determine whether he represented his nous as God in our sense, or as Sophia, wisdom, a word which with him often replaces nous. It is remarkable that in his genuine works Plato does not generally use the word Logos, and in Aristotle as well nous remains the first term, what we should call the divine mind, while Logos is the reason, the causal nexus, the ov eveica, therefore decidedly some thing impersonal, if not unsubjective. Plato is the first who distinguishes between essence and being in the primeval cause, or, as we might say, between rest and activity. He speaks of an eternal plan of the world, a thought of the world, the world 22 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD as a product of thought, inseparable from the creator, but still distinguishable from him. This is the Pla tonic world of " Ideas," which lies at the foundation of the world perceivable by the senses, the phenome nal world. What is more natural or more reason able than this thought ? If the world has an author, what can we imagine as reasonable men, but that the thought, the plan of the world, belongs to the author, that it was thought, and thereby realised for the first time ? Now this plan, this idea, was the inner Logos, and as every thought finds its imme diate expression in a word, so did this one, which was then called the outer Logos. The outer was not possible without the inner, even as a word is impossible without mind and reason. But the inner Logos also first realises itself in the outer, just as the reasonable thought can only be made real in the word. This character of the Logos as thought and word, at once capable of distinction and yet undifferentiated and inseparable, is of the highest importance for Christian speculation ; without an exact comprehension of it, we shall see that the relation of the Son to the Father as we find it explained by Clemens and other fathers of the church, remains dark and misty. We have no con cept without a word, and philology has shown us how every word, even the most concrete, is based on a concept. We cannot think of " tree " without the word or a hieroglyphic of some kind We can even say that, as far as we are concerned, there is THE 'TRUE HISTORY' OF CELSUS 23 no tree, except in language, for in the nature of things there are only oaks or beeches, but not and never a tree. And what is true of tree is true of all words, or t» speak with Plato, of all ideas, or to speak with the Stoics, of all Logoi. There are no doubt conjurers who pretend to be able to think without words, and even take no little pride in be ing able to perform this trick. They forget only too often that their inexpressible thoughts are nothing but obscure feelings, in fact, they do not even dis tinguish between presentation and idea, and forget that when we speak of words, we do not understand by them mere mimicry of sound or interjections, but only and exclusively intelligible words, that is, such as are based on concepts and are derived from roots. The old Greek philosophers, probably favoured by their language, appear never to have forgotten the true relation between Logos and Logos, and their thought finally resulted in a view of the world founded upon it. Although it is now the custom to speak slightingly of the later Platonists, we should always recognise that we owe to them the preserva tion of this, the most precious jewel out of the rich storehouse of Greek philosophy, that the world is the expression and realisation of divine thought, that it is the divine word expressed. We cannot here enter into the various phases in which Plato and his followers presented these ideas. At times they are represented as independent of the Creator, as models, as golden statues, to which the 24 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD creative mind looks up. Soon, however, they are conceived as thoughts of this mind, as something secondary, created, sometimes also as something in dependent, as much so as is the Son in relation to his Father. The whole Logos, with all ideas, became in this manner the first-born Son of the Creator, yet so that the Father could not be Father without the Son, or the Son without the Father, Son. All these distinctions, insignificant as they may appear from a purely philosophical point of view, demand attention because of the influence that they afterward exerted on Christian dogma, especially on that of the Trinity — a dogma which, however spe cifically Christian it may appear to be, must still in all its essential features be traced back to Greek elements. It is certainly remarkable that Jewish philosophy also developed on very similar lines, of course not with the purity and exactness of the Greek mind, but still with the same object in view, — to bring the reason and wisdom recognised in nature into renewed connexion with their supernatural Jehovah. Through the Proverbs of Solomon and similar works the Jews were well acquainted with Wisdom, who says of herself (viii. 22 ff.) : " The Lord possessed me in the beginning of his way, before his works of old. I was set up from everlasting, from the beginning, or ever the earth was. . . . Before the mountains were settled, before the hills was I brought forth. . . . When he prepared the heavens, I was THE 'TRUE HISTORY' OF CELSUS 25 there : when he set a compass upon the face of the depth. . . . Then I was by him, as a master work man : and I was daily his delight, rejoicing always before him." These and similar thoughts were fa miliar to Jewish thinkers (see Proverbs viii. and ix. , Job xxviii. 12, Ecclesiasticus i. 4), and it was nat ural that, in coming in contact with Greek philos ophy, especially in Alexandria, they should seek to recognise again this traditional conception of divine Wisdom in the Logos of Greek philosophers. We see this most clearly in Philo, a contemporary of Christ, of whom it is often difficult to say whether he reasons more as a Greek or as a Jew. While the Greeks had almost lost sight of the bridge between the world and God by abstraction, the Jews, through mistaken reverence, had so far removed the Creator above his creation that on both sides the need of mediation or a mediator was deeply felt. The Jew ish God was little better than the Epicurean. If the Epicureans taught that there probably is a God, but that the world is of no concern to Him, so among the Jews of the first century gnostic ideas prevailed, according to which not the highest but a subordinate God created and ruled the world. The task of cre ation seemed unworthy of the supreme God. Philo therefore seized the Stoic idea of the Logos or Logoi in order to bring his transcendental God again into relation with the visible world. The most important attributes and powers of God were hypostatised as be ings who participated in the creation and government 26 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD of the world. Philo's God first of all creates or pos sesses within himself a world that is conceived, an invisible world,1 which is also called the world of ideas2 or the idea of ideas.3 These ideas are the types* of all things, and the power by which God created them is often called Sophia or Episteme, wisdom or knowledge.5 This world of ideas in its entirety corresponds, as is readily seen, to the Greek Logos, the separate types to the Platonic ideas or the Stoic Logoi. The entire Logos, or the sum of Ideas, is called by Philo, entirely independent of Christianity, the true Son of God, while the realised world of Chris tian teaching passes as the second Son. If the first Logos is occasionally called the image or shadow of God, the world of sense is the image of the image, the shadow of the shadow. More logically expressed, God would be the causa efficiens, matter the causa materialis, the Logos the causa instrumentalis, while the goodness of God is sometimes added as the causa finalis. At the same time we also see here the dif ference between the working of the Jewish and Greek minds. In the Old Testament and in Philo, the So phia or wisdom of God becomes a half mythological being, a goddess who is called the mother, and even the nurse,6 of all beings. She bore with much labour out of the seed of God,7 as Philo says, the only and 1 k6o rod yeveaOat ypovov ical top vttvov, — 'An axagoras said that two things admonished us about death: the time before birth and sleep.' " The raindrop, because it is a drop, may fear for its individuality when it falls back into the sea whence it came. We men are perhaps only passing drops formed out of the everlasting changes of the world-sea. (Of what does the world-sea consist but drops ?) " Those who think as I do constitute a silent but large congregation: silent, because the time is not yet ripe for a view that will rob thousands of their illu sions. We do not preach a new salvation, but a silent, for many, a painful, renunciation. But the profound CONCERNING THE HORSEHERD 81 peace that lies in this view is as precious to those who have acquired it as is the hope of heaven to the be liever. In honest doubt, too, lies a saving power as well as in faith ; and your Horseherd is on the path of this salvation. (I believe that too.) " With great respect, " Yours very faithfully, "Ignotus Agnosticus." Whilst I received this and many other letters from many lands, no sign of life reached me from my Horse herd. He must have received my letter, or it would have been returned to me through the post. I re gretted this, for I had formed a liking for the man as he appeared in his letter, and he no doubt would have had much to say in reply to my letter, which would have placed his views in a clearer light. He was an honest fellow, and I respect every conviction that is honest and sincere, even if it is diametrically opposite to my own. Now, my unknown friend could have had no thought of self in the matter. He knew that his name would not be mentioned by me, and it would probably have been of little concern to him if his name had become known. The worst feature of all discussions is the intrusion of the personal element. If for instance in a criticism of a new book we empha sise that which we think erroneous, for which every author should be grateful, we feel at the same time, that while desiring to render a service to the cause of 82 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD truth, we may not only have hurt the book or the writer, but may have done a positive injury. The writer then feels himself impelled to defend his view not only with all the legitimate arts of advocacy, but also with the illegitimate. This poor truth is the greatest sufferer. As long as two paths are open, there is room for quiet discussion with one's travelling companion as to which may be the right and best path by which to reach the desired point. Both parties have the same object in view, the truth. As soon however as one goes, or has gone his own way, the controversy becomes personal and violent. There is no thought of turning back. It is no longer said: " This is the wrong path," but " You are on the wrong path," and even if it were possible to turn back, the controversy generally ends with, "I told you so." Poor Truth stands by sorrowfully and rubs its eyes. Now what was the Horseherd to me, and what is he now, even if he has been brought to what he called a joyful end by his catarrh " verging upon a perfect asthma." There was nothing personal between us. He knew me only by that which I have thought and said ; I knew of him only what he had gathered in his hours of leisure, and had laid aside for life. I have never seen him face to face, do not know the colour of his eyes, hardly even whether he was old or young. He was a man, but he may be even that no longer. Everything that in our common view con stitutes a man, his body, his speech, his experience, is gone. We did not bring these things with us into CONCERNING THE HORSEHERD 83 the world and probably shall not take them away with us. What the body is, we see with our eyes, especially if we attend a cremation, or if in ancient graves we look into the urns which contain the gray ish black ashes, whilst near by there sleeps in cold marble, as in the Museo Nazionale in Rome, the lovely head of the young Roman maiden, to whom two thousand years ago belonged these ashes, as well as the beautiful mansion that has been excavated from the earth and rebuilt round about her. And the language, the language in which all our experi ence here on earth lies stored, will this be everlast ing? Shall we in another life speak English or Sanscrit? The philologist knows too well of what material speech is made, how much of the temporal and accidental it has adopted in its eternal forms, to cherish such a hope, and to think that the Logos can be eternally bound to the regular or irregular declen sions or conjugations of the Greek, the German, or even the Hottentot languages. What then remains ? Not the person, or the so-called ego — that had a be ginning, a continuation, and an end. Everything that had a beginning, once was not, and what once was not, has in itself, from its very beginning, the germ of its end. What remains is only the eternal One, the eternal Self, that lives in us all without be ginning and without end, in which each one has his true existence, in which we live, move, and have our being. Each temporal ego is only one of the million phenomena of this eternal Self, and such a phenome- 84 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD non was the Horseherd to me. It is only what we recognise in all men as the eternal, or as the divine, that we can love and retain. Everything else comes and goes, as the day comes in the morning and goes at night, but the light of the sun remains forever. Now it may be said: This Self, that is and abides, is after all next to nothing. It is, however, and that iis,7 is more than everything else. Light is not much either, probably only vibration, but what would the world be without it? Did we not begin this life simply with this Self, continue it with this Self, and bring it to an end with this Self? There is nothing that justifies us in saying that this Self had a begin ning, and will therefore have an end. The ego had a beginning, the persona, the temporal mask that unfolds itself in this life, but not the Self that wears the mask. When therefore my Horseherd says, " After death we are just as much a nullity as before our birth," I say, quoderat demonstrandum is still to be proved. What does he mean by we ? If we were nothing before birth, that is, if we never had been at all, what would that be that is born? Being born does not mean becoming something out of nothing. What is born or produced was there, before it was born or produced, before it came into the light of the world. All creation out of nothing is a pure chimera for us. Have we ever the feeling or ex perience that we had a beginning here on earth, or have we entirely forgotten the most remarkable thing in our life, viz., its beginning ? Have we ever CONCERNING THE HORSEHERD 85 seen a beginning? Can we even think of an abso lute beginning? In order to have had our begin ning on earth, there must have been something that begins, be it a cell or be it the Self. All that we call ego, personality, character, etc., has unfolded itself on earth, is earthly, but not the Self. If we now on earth were content with the pure Self, if in all those that we love, we loved the eternal Self and not only the appearance, what then is more natural than that it should be so in the next world, that the continuity of existence cannot be severed, that the Self should find itself again, even though in new and unexpected forms? When therefore my friend makes the bold assertion : " After our death we are again as much a nullity as before our birth," I say, " Yes, if we take nullity in the Hegelian sense." Otherwise I say the direct contrary to this : "After our death we are again as little a nullity as before our birth. What we shall be we cannot know ; but that we shall be, follows from this, that the Self or the divine within us can neither have a beginning nor an end." That is what the ancients meant in saying that death was to be best under stood from the time before birth. But we must not think that each single ego lays claim only to a part of the Self, for then the Self would be di vided, limited, and finite. No, the entire Self bears us, just as the entire light illumines all, every grain of sand and every star, but for that reason does not belong exclusively to any one grain of sand or star, 86 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD It is that which is eternal, or in the true sense of the word that which is divine in us, that endures in all changes, that makes all change possible, for without something that endures in change, there could be no change ; without something continuous, that per sists through transformation, nothing could be trans formed. The Self is the bond that unites all souls, the red thread which runs through all being, and the knowledge of which alone gives us knowledge of our true nature. " Know thyself " no longer means for us " Know thy ego," but " Know what lies beyond thy ego, know the Self," the Self that runs through the whole world, through all hearts, the same for all men, the same for the highest and the lowest, the same for creator and creature, the Atman of the Veda, the old est and truest word for God. For this reason the Horseherd was to me what all men have always been to me — an appearance of the Self, the same as I myself, not only a fellow- creature, but a fellow-man, a fellow-self. Had I met him in life, who knows whether his ego or his ap pearance would have attracted me as much as his letter. We all have our prejudices, and much as I honour a Silesian peasant who has spent his life faith fully and honestly in a strange land, I do not know whether I should have sat down by his iron stove and chatted with him about to, [leyicna. I also felt as I read his letter, that it was not a soli tary voice in the desert, but that he spoke in the name of many who felt as he felt, without being CONCERNING THE HORSEHERD 87 willing or able to express it. This also has proved to be entirely true. Judging by the numerous letters and manuscripts that reach me, the Horseherd was not alone in his opinions. There are countless others in the world of the same mind, and even if his voice is silenced, his ideas survive in all places and directions, and he will not lack followers and defenders. The strik ing thing in the letters that reached me was that the greater number and the most characteristic among his sympathisers did not wish their names to be known. What does this signify? Do we still live on a planet on which we dare not express what we hold to be the truth — planet Terra so huge and yet so contemptibly small ? Has mankind still only free dom of thought, but not freedom of utterance ? The powers may blockade Greece ; can they blockade thoughts on wings of words ? It has been attempted, but force is no proof, and when we have visited the prisons in which Galilei or even Giordano Bruno was immured, we learn how nothing lends greater strength to the wings of truth than the heavy chains with which men try to fetter it. It is still the general opinion that even in free England thought and speech are not free, that in the realm of thought there is even less freedom on this side of the Chan nel than on the other.1 Oxford especially, my own university, is still considered the stronghold of 1 These pronouns, referring of course to England and the Con tinent, were reversed in the original. 88 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD obscurantists, and my Horseherd even considers the fact that I have lived so long in Oxford a circon- stance attSnuante of my so-called orthodoxy. Plainly what is thouglit, said, and published in England, and especially in Oxford, is not read. In England we can say anything we please, we must only bear in mind that the same consideration is due to others that we claim from others. It is true that from time to time in England, and even in Oxford, feeble efforts have been made, if not to curtail freedom of thought, at least to punish those who laid claim to it. Where possible the salaries of professors were curtailed ; in certain elections very weak candidates were preferred because they were outwardly orthodox. I do not wish to mention any names, but I myself have re ceived in England, even if not in Oxford, a gentle aftertaste of this antiquated physic. When at the request of my friend Stanley, the Dean of Westmin ster Abbey, I delivered a discourse in his venerable church, which was crowded to the doors, petitions were sent to Parliament to condemn me to six months' imprisonment. I was accosted in the streets, and an ordinary tradesman said to me, " Sir, if you are sent to prison, you shall have at least two warm dinners each week from me." I am, to be sure, the first layman that ever spoke publicly in an English church, but I had the advice of the highest authori ties that the Dean was perfectly within his rights, and that we were guilty of no violation of law. I there fore waited in silence ; I knew that public opinion CONCERNING THE HORSEHERD 89 was on my side, and that in the end the petition to Parliament would simply be laid aside. Later on it was attempted again. At the time that I delivered my lectures on the Science of Religion at the uni versity of Glasgow, by invitation of the Senate, I was accused first before the presbytery at Glasgow, and when this attempt failed, the charge was carried before the great Synod at Edinburgh. In this case, too, I went on my way, in silence, and in the end, even in Scotland, the old saying, " Much cry and little wool," was verified. This proverb is frequently heard in England. I have often inquired into its origin. Finally I found that there is a second line, "As the deil said when he shore the sow." Of course such an operation was accompanied with much noise on the part of the sow, but little wool, nothing but bristles. I have never, however, had to turn my bris tles against the gentlemen who wished to shear me. I am of opinion, therefore, that those who wished to espouse the cause of my Horseherd should have done so publicly and with open visor. As soon as any one feels that he has found the truth, he knows also that what is real and true can never be killed or silenced ; and secondly, that truth in the world has its purpose, and this purpose must in the end be a good one. We do not complain about thunder and light ning, but accustom ourselves to them, and seek to understand them, so as to live on good terms with them ; and we finally invent lightning conductors, to protect ourselves, as far as we can, against the inevi- 90 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD table. So it is with every new truth, if it is only maintained with courage. At first we cry and clamour that it is false, that it is dangerous. In the end we shake our wise heads and say these are old matters known long since, of which only old women were afraid. In the end, after the thunder and lightning, the air is made clearer, fresher, and more wholesome. When I first read the long letter of my Horseherd, I said to myself, " He is a man who has done the best he could in his position." He has let himself be taught, but also irresistibly influenced, by certain popular books, and has come to think that the abandonment of views that have been instilled into him from his youth is so brave and meritorious, that all who disagree with him must be cowards. This inculcation of truth into childish minds is always a dangerous matter, and even if I do not use the strong expressions that are used by my friend, — for I always think, the stronger the expression the weaker the argument, — I must admit that he is right up to a certain point. It does not seem fair that in the decision of the most important questions of life the young mind should have no voice. A Jewish child becomes a Jew, a Christian child a Christian, and a Buddhist child a Buddhist. What does this prove ? Unquestionably, that in the highest concern in life the child is not allowed a voice. My friend asks indignantly : " Is there any thing in face of our knowledge, and of the realm of nature and of man's position in it, so unbearable, CONCERNING THE HORSEHERD 91 yes so odious, as the inoculation of such error in the tender consciousness of our school children ? I shudder when I think that in thousands of our churches and schools this systematic ruin of the greatest of all gifts, the consciousness, the human brain, is daily, even hourly, going on. Max, can you, too, still cling to the God-fable ? " etc. Now I have explained clearly and concisely in what sense I cling to the God-fable, and I should like to know if I have convinced my Horseherd. I belong, above all, to those who do not consider the world an irrational chaos, and also to those who can not concede that there can be reason without a reasoner. Reason is an activity, or, as others have it, an attribute, and there can neither be an activity without an agent, nor an attribute without a subject ; at least, not in the world in which we live. When ordinary persons and even professional philosophers speak of reason as if it were a jewel that can be placed in a drawer or in a human skull, they are simply myth-makers. It is precisely in this ever recurring elevation of an adjective or a verb to a noun, of a predicate to a subject, that this disease of language, as I have called mythology, has its deepest roots. Here lies the genesis of the majority of gods, not by any means, as it is generally believed I have taught, merely in later quibbles and misunderstand ings, which are interesting and popular, but have little reference to the deepest nature of the myth. We must not take these matters too lightly. 92 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD I recognise therefore a reasoner, and consequent reason in the world, or in other words, I believe in a thinker and ruler of the world, but gladly concede that this Being so infinitely transcends our faculties of comprehension, that even to wish only to give him a name borders on madness. If, in spite of all of this, we use such names as Jehovah, Allah, Deva, God, Father, Creator, this is only a result of human weak ness. I cling therefore to the God-fable in the sense which is more fully set forth in my letter, and it pleased me very much to see that at least a few of those, who as they said were formerly on the side of the Horseherd, now fully agree with me, that the world is not irrational. Here is the dividing line be tween two systems of philosophy. Whoever thinks that an irrational world becomes rational by the sur vival of the fittest, etc., stands on one side ; I stand on the other, and hold with the Greek thinkers, who accept the world as the expression of the Logos, or of a reasonable thought or thinker. But here the matter became serious. To my Horseherd I thought that I could make myself intel ligible in a humorous strain, for his letter was per meated with a quiet humour. But my known and unknown opponents take the matter much more seri ously and thoroughly, and I am consequently obliged at least to try to answer them seriously and thoroughly. What my readers will say to this I do not know. I believe that even in short words we can be serious and profound. When Schiller says that he belongs CONCERNING THE HORSEHERD 93 to no religion, and why? because of religion, the statement is short and concise, and yet easily under stood. I shall, however, at least attempt to follow my opponents step by step, even at the risk of becoming tedious. And first of all a confession. It has been pointed out to me that in one place I did my Horseherd an injustice. I wrote : " You are of opinion that to love God and your neighbour is equivalent to being good, and are evidently very proud of your discovery that there is no distinction between good and evil. Well," I then continue, "if loving God and your neighbour is equivalent to being good, then it follows that not loving God and not loving your neighbour is equivalent to not being good, or to being evil. There is, then, a very plain distinction between good and evil. And yet you say that you turned a somersault when you discovered that there was no such distinc tion." Well, that looked as though I had driven my friend into a corner from which he would find it difficult to extricate himself. But I did him an injustice and shall therefore do everything in my power to right it. My memory, as it so frequently does, played me a prank. At the same time that I answered him, I was in active correspondence with one of the dele gates to the Chicago Parliament of Religions, at which the love of God and one's neighbour had been adopted, as a sort of article of agreement which the followers of any or every faith could accept. Thus it befell 94 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD that I supposed the Horseherd in America to stand at the same point of view, and consequently to be guilty of a contradiction. Such is, however, not the case ; he made no such concession of love of God and one's neighbour in his letter. If he therefore insists that there is no distinction between good and evil, I cannot at least refute him out of his own mouth. The only place where he is inconsistent is where he concedes that he could not strike a dog, but is filled with bloodthirstiness toward the Jewish idea of God. Here he clearly holds it good that he cannot be cruel to an animal, and that he looks upon blood- thirstiness as a contrast. He also concedes that a lie can never accomplish any good, and believes that the truth is beautiful and holy. If a lie can accomplish no good, only evil, then there must be a distinction between good and evil. And what is the meaning of beautiful and holy, if there is no contrast between good and evil. But I shall argue this point no farther, but simply say peecavi, and I believe that he, and those like-minded with him, will be satisfied with that. How different it would have been, however, had I been guilty of such a mistake in a personal dis pute ! The injured party would never have believed that my oversight was accidental, and not malicious, in spite of the fact that it would have been the most stupid malevolence to say that which every one who can read would instantly recognise as untrue. But enough of this, and enough to show that my Horse herd at least remained consistent. Even when he CONCERNING THE HORSEHERD 95 so far forgets himself as to say, " God be praised," he excuses himself. Only he has unfortunately not told us what he really means when he says that good and evil are identical. Good and evil are relative ideas, just like right and left, black and white, and although he has told us that he turned somersaults with joy over the discovery that this distinction is false, he has left us in total darkness as to how we shall conceive this identity. But let us turn back to more important things. My opponents further call me sharply to account, and ask how I can imagine that the material world can be rational, or permeated with reason. I believed that it must be clear to every person with a philo sophical training, that there are things that are be yond our understanding, that man can neither sensibly apprehend nor logically conceive an actual beginning and that to inquire for the beginning of the subjective self, or of the objective world, is like inquiring for the beginning of the beginning. All that we can do is to investigate our perceptions, to see what they presup pose. A perception plainly presupposes a self that perceives, or that resists, and on the other side, some thing that forces itself upon us, or, as Kant says, some thing that is given. This " given " element might be mere confusion, but it is not ; it displays order, cause and effect, and reveals itself as rational. This reve lation of a rational world may, however, be explained in two ways. That there is reason in nature, even the majority of Darwinians admit, but they think that 96 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD it arises of itself, since in the struggle for life that which is most adapted to its conditions, fittest, best, necessarily survives. In this view of the world, however, if I see it aright, much is admitted surrep titiously. Whence comes all at once this idea of the best, of the good, the fit, the adapted, in the world? Do roasted pigeons fall from the sky? Is the pigeon itself an accidental combination, an evo lution, that might as well have been as it is, or otherwise? It is all very fine to recognise in the ascending series of protozoa, coelenterata, echino- derms, worms, mollusks, fishes, amphibia, reptiles, the stages of progress toward birds and finally to mam mals and man. But whence comes the idea of bird or pigeon ? Is it no more than an abstraction from our perceptions of thousands of birds or pigeons, or must the idea of bird, of pigeon, even of the wood pigeon, be there already, that we may detect it behind the multiplicity of our perceptions ? Is the pigeon, in whose wing each feather is counted, a mere accident, a mere survival which might have been what it is or something different, or is it some thing willed and thought, an organic whole? It is the old question whether the idea preceded or fol lowed the reality, on which the whole Middle Ages broke their teeth, the question which separated and still separates philosophers into two camps, — the Real ists and the Nominalists. I think that the latest in vestigations show us that the Greek philosophers, and especially Plato, saw more correctly when they recog- CONCERNING THE HORSEHERD 97 nised behind the multiplicity of individuals the unity of the idea, or the species, and then sought the true sequence of evolution not in this world, in a struggle for existence, but beyond the perception of the senses, in a development of the Logos or the idea. The circumstances, it appears to me, in this view remain just the same ; the sequence, and the purposiveness in this sequence, remain untouched, only that the Greeks saw in the rational and purposive in nature the realisation of rational progressive thoughts, not the bloody survivals of a monstrous gladiatorial com bat in nature. The Darwinians appear to me to re semble the Roman emperors, who waited till the combat was ended, and then applauded the survival of the fittest. The idealist philosophy, be it Plato's or Hegel's, recognises in what actually is, the rational, the realisation of eternal, rational ideas. This reali sation, or the process of what we call creation, can never be conceived by us otherwise than figuratively. But we can make this figurative presentation clearer and clearer. That the world was made by a wood cutter, as was originally implied in the Hebrew word bara, and in the German schoepfer, schaffer, in the English shaper, or in the Vedic tvashtd, and the Greek re/crcw, was quite comprehensible at a time in which man's highest product was that of the car penter and the stone mason ; and in which the name of timber (materies) could become the universal name for matter (vXr/, Avood). After this idea of the founder of the universe as a carpenter or builder was 98 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD abandoned as inadequate, the world was divided into two parties. The one adopted the theory of material primitive elements, whether they be called atoms, or monads, or cells, which by collision or struggle with each other, and by mutual affinity, became that which we now see around us. The other saw the impossi bility of the rise of something rational out of the irra tional, and conceived a rational being, in which was developed the original type of everything produced, the so-called Logos of the universe. How this Logos became objectively and materially real, is as far be yond human comprehension as is the origin of the cosmos out of countless atoms, or even out of living cells. So far, then, one hypothesis would be as com plete and as incomplete as the other. But the Logos hypothesis has the far-reaching advantage, that in stead of a long succession of wonders, — call them if you like the wonder of the monads, or the worm, or the mollusk, or the fish, or the amphibian, or the rep tile, or the bird, or, lastly, man, — it has but one won der before it, the Logos, the idea of thought, or of the eternal thinker, who thought everything that exists in natural sequence, and in this sense made all. In this view we need not even abandon the survival of the fittest, only it proceeds in the Logos, in the mind, not in the outward phenomenal world. It would then also become conceivable that the embryological development of animated nature runs parallel with the biological or historical, or as it were recapitulates it, only the continuity of the idea is far closer and more CONCERNING THE HORSEHERD 99 intimate than that of the reality. Thus, for instance, in the development of the human embryo, the transi tion from the invertebrate to the vertebrate may be represented in the reality by the isolated amphioxus, which remains stationary where vertebrate man be gins, and can make no step forward, while the human embryo advances farther and farther till it reaches its highest limit. In order now to infer from these and similar facts that man at one time really existed in this scarcely vertebrate condition of the amphioxus, — a conclu sion which, strictly understood, yields no meaning, — we can make the case much more easily conceivable if we represent the thinking, or invention of the world, as an ascending scale, in which even the least chromatic tone must have a place without a break, while the principal tones do not become clear and full until the requisite number of vibrations is at tained. These gradations of tone are the really interesting thing in nature. As the full, clear tones imply certain numerical relations among the vibra tions, so the successive stages or the true species in nature imply a will or thought in which the true Origin of Species has its foundation. That natural selection, as it is called, could suffice to explain the origin of species, was doubted even by Huxley,1 who yet described himself as Darwin's bull-dog. If we have followed the supporters of my Horse herd so far, I should like here to enter a caveat, that 1 Academy, January 2, 1897, p. 12. 100 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD is indeed of no great significance, but may turn one or another from a by-way, which the Horseherd himself has not avoided. He speaks of the place of man in nature ; he thinks (like so many others) that man is not only an animal belonging to the mam malia, which no one has ever denied, but that he is of the same nature as the animal world. He need not therefore have accepted the whole simian theory, at least he does not say so ; but that each man, and the entire human race, has descended from an un known pair of animals, he appears to receive as indu bitable. This would not, so far as I can see, make the slightest difference in the so-called dignity of mankind. If man had a prehensile tail, it would not detract from his worth. I myself have little doubt that there were men with tails in prehistoric or even in historic times. I go still farther and declare that if ever there should be an ape who can form ideas and words, he would ipso facto be a man. I have therefore no prejudices such as the advocates of the simian theory like to attribute to us. What I and those who agree with me demand of our opponents, is merely somewhat keener thought, and a certain consideration for the results of our knowledge, such as we on our side have bestowed on their researches. They have taught us that the body in which we live was at first a simple cell. The significance of this " at first " is left somewhat vague. This cell was really what the word means, the cella (room) of a dumb inhabitant, the Self. The essential thing is CONCERNING THE HORSEHERD 101 and remains what was in the cell. Through gem mation, differentiation, segmentation, evolution, or whatever other technical expressions we may use for division, multiplication, budding, increase, etc., each cell became a hundred, a thousand, a million. Within this cell is a bright spot into which not even the microscope can penetrate, although whole worlds may be contained therein. If it is now remembered that no one has ever succeeded in distinguishing the human cell from the cell of a horse, an elephant, or an ape, we shall see how much unnecessary indigna tion has been expended in recent years over the simian origin of the human race, and how much intel ligent thought has been wasted about the animal origin of man, that is of the individual. My body, your body, his body, is derived (ontogenetically) from the cell, is in fact the cell which has re mained persistently the same from beginning to end, without ever, in spite of all changes, losing its identity. This cell in its transformations has shown remarkable analogies with the transformations of other animal cells. While, however, the other ani mal cells in their transformations remain stationary here and there, either at the boundary line of worms, fishes, amphibia, reptiles, or mammals, the one cell which was destined to become man moves on to the stage of the tailed catarrhine apes, then of the tail less apes, and without staying here it irresistibly strides towards its original goal, and only stops where it is destined to stop. Speaking, however, not 102 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD phylogenetically, but ontogenetically, at what point does our own cell come in contact with the cell that was intended to become an ape, and that became and remained an ape? If we accept the cell theory in its latest form, what meaning can there be in the statement of the late Henry Drummond, that " In a very distant period the progenitors of birds and the progenitors of men were one and the same " ? 2 Would not a very small quantity of strictly logical thought have cut off a priori the bold hypothesis that directly or indirectly we descend from a menagerie ? Every man, and consequently all mankind, has accomplished his uninterrupted embryological development on his own account; no man and no human cell springs from the womb of an ape or any other animal, but only from the womb of a human mother, fertilised by a human father. Or do men owe their being to a miscarriage ? As many streams may flow alongside of each other and through the same strata, and one ends in a lake while the others flow on and grow larger and larger, till finally one river attains its highest goal, the sea, so the cells develop for a time along side of each other, then some remain stationary at their points of destination, while others move on farther ; but the cell that has moved forward is as little derived from the stationary cell as the Indus from the Sarasvati. It is at the points of destination that the true species digress, and when these points 1 Ascent of Jlfan, p. 187. CONCERNING THE HORSEHERD 103 are reached, the specific development ceases, and there remains only the possibility of the variety, the origin of which is conditioned by the multiplicity of individuals ; but which must never be confounded with a true species. Every species represents an act of the will, a thought, and this thought cannot be shaken from its course, however close temptation may often come. With this I believe I have cleared up and refuted one of the objections that my correspondents made, at any rate to the best of my ability. Whoever is convinced that each individual, be it fish or bird, springs from its own cell, knows ipso facto that a human cell, however undistinguishable it may be to the human eye from the cell of a catarrhine ape, could never have been the cell of an ape. And what is true ontogenetically, is of course true phylo genetically. For myself this inquiry into the simian origin of man never had any great interest ; I even doubt whether the Horseherd would have laid great stress upon it. His champions, however, plainly con sider it one of the principal and fundamental questions on which our whole view of the world must be erected. In my opinion so little depends on our covering of flesh, that as I have often said, I should instantly acknowledge an ape that could speak, that is, think in concepts, as a man and brother, in spite of his hide, in spite of his tail, in spite of his stunted brain. We are not that which is buried or burned. We are not even the cell, but the inhabitant of the 104 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD cell. But this leads me to new questions and objec tions, which have been made by the representatives and successors of the Horseherd, and to which I hope to reply on some other occasion, assuming that my own somewhat dilapidated cell holds out so long against wind and rain. F. Max Muller. Frascati, April, 1897. IV LANGUAGE AND MIND The number of Horseherds appears to grow each month. He would rejoice to see the letters of men and women who are all on his side, and give me clearly to understand that I should by no means imagine that I have refuted my unknown friend. The letter of Ignotus Agnosticus in the June num ber of the Deutsche Rundschau is a good example of these communications. I have read it with much interest, and have partly dealt with it in my article in the same number; but I hope at some future time to answer his objections, and those of several other correspondents, more fully. I should have been glad to publish some of these letters. But first, they are too long, and they are far inferior in power to the letter of the Horseherd. Moreover, they are usually so full of friendly recognition, even when disagreeing with me, that it would ill become me to give them publicity. That there was no lack of coarse letters as well, may be taken for granted ; these however were all anonymous, as if the writers were ashamed of their heroic style. I have never been able to understand what attraction there can 105 106 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD be in coarseness. The coarse work is generally left for the apprentice. Everything coarse, be it a block, a wedge, or a blade, passes as unfinished, as raw, jagged, and just the reverse of cutting. No one is proud of a coarse shirt, but many, even quite dis tinguished people, proudly strut about the streets in a coarse smock of abusive language, quite un concernedly, without any suspicion of their unsuit able attire. Well, I shall endeavour to be as fair as I can to my unknown opponents and friends, the coarse as well as the courteous. I cannot be coarse myself, much as it seems to be desired in some quarters that I should. Each one must determine for himself what is specially meant for him. I cannot of course enter into all the objections that have been made. Many have very little or nothing to do with what lay nearest the Horse- herd's heart. The antinomies, for example, on the infinity of space and time, have long since belonged to the history of metaphysics, and have been so thoroughly worked out by Kant and his school that there is hardly anything new to be said about them. In the question about the age of our world, we need only distinguish between world as universe and world as our world, that is, as the earth or the terrestrial world. A beginning of the world as universe is of course incomprehensible to us ; but we may speak of the beginning of the earth, especially of the earth as inhabited by man, because here, as Lord Kelvin LANGUAGE AND MIND 107 has shown, astronomical physics and geology have enabled us to fix certain chronological limits, and to say how old our earth may be, and no older or younger. When I said of the world, that though it were millions of years old, there still was a time before it was one year or 1897 years old, I referred to the world in the sense of our world, that is, the earth. Of the world as universe this would scarcely be said; on the contrary, we should here apply the axiom that every boundary implies something be yond, i.e. an unbounded, until we arrive at the region where, as people say, the world is nailed up with boards. Many years ago I tried to prove that our senses can never perceive a real boundary, be it on the largest or the smallest scale ; they present to us everywhere the infinite as their background, and every thing that has to do with religion has sprung out of this infinite background as its ultimate and deepest foundation. Instead of saying that by our senses we perceive only the finite or limited, I have sought to show ( On the Perception of the Infinite) that we everywhere perceive the unlimited, and that it is we, and not the objects about us, that draw the boundary lines in our perceptions. When I also called this unknown omnipresence of the infinite the source of all religion, this was the highest, the most abstract, and the most general expression that could be found for the wide domain of the tran scendent; it had of course nothing to do with the historical beginnings of religion. When the Aryans 108 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD felt, thought, and named their god, their Dyaus, in the blue sky, they meant the blue sky within the limits of the horizon. We know, however, that while they called the sky Dyaus, they had in mind an infinite subject, a Deva, a God. But, as stated, these things were remote from the Horseherd, and he would scarcely have had anything to object. His chief objection was of a quite different nature. He wished to show that the human mind was a mere phantom of man's making, that there are only bodies in the world, and that the mind has sprung from the body, and therefore constituted, not the prius, but the posterius of those bodies. This view is evidently widely disseminated and has found very abundant support, at least in the letters addressed to me. " The mind," so wrote the Horseherd, " is not a prius, it is a development, a self-evolving phenomenon." Every thing is now development, and there is no better salve for all ills than development. If our knowledge of development is taken in the sense of scientific his torical inquiry, then we all agree, for how can there be anything that has not developed? In order to know what a thing is, we must learn how it became what it is. A much-admired philosopher, recently deceased, Henry Drummond, who was quite intoxi cated with evolution, nevertheless admits quite plainly in his last work, The Ascent of Man, that " Order of events is history, and evolution is his tory" (p. 132). With this I am of course quite satis fied, for it is what I have been preaching in season LANGUAGE AND MIND 109 and out of season for at least thirty years. But this order, or this sequence of facts, must be proved with scientific accuracy, and not merely postulated. If then my Horseherd had been content to say, " The human mind is also a development," certainly no student of history, least of all a philologist, would have contradicted him. But he says : " Max, all German savants, or, if you please, the majority of them, still labour under the delusion that mind is a prius. But nonsense, Max, mind is a development, a self-evolving phenomenon. One would consider it impossible that a thinking man, who has ever ob served a child, could be of any other opinion; why seek ghosts behind matter? Mind is a function of living organisms, which belongs also to a goose and a chicken." In the Horseherd such language was excusable, but for philosophers to talk in the same style is strange, to say the least. How can such an asser tion be made without any proof whatever, without even a few words to explain what is meant by the term "mind"? The German like the English language swarms with words that may be used interchangeably, though each of them has its own shade of meaning. If we translate Geist (Spirit) as mind, then we must consider that " spirit," in such expressions as " He has yielded up his spirit," means the same as the principle of life or physical life. The same is true of " spirit " in such a phrase as " his spirit has departed." But easy as it is to distinguish between 110 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD spirit in the sense of the breath of life, and spirit in the sense of mind, the exact definition of such words as intellect, reason, understanding, thought, consciousness, or self-consciousness becomes very difficult, to say nothing of soul and feeling in their various activities. These words are used in both English and German so confusedly that we often hesitate merely to touch them. Now if we say that the mind is a development, and is not a prius, what idea ought it to suggest? Does this mean the principle of life, or the understanding, or the reason, or consciousness ? We suffer here from a real and very dangerous embarras de richesse. The words are often intended to signify the same things, only viewed under different aspects. But as there were various words, it was believed that they must also signify various things. Different philosophers have further advanced different definitions of these words, until it was finally supposed that each of these names must be borne by a separate subject, while some of them originally only signified activities of one and the same substance. Understanding, rea son, and thought originally expressed properties or activities, the activities of understanding, of perceiv ing, of thinking, and their elevation to nouns was simply psychological mythology, which has pre vailed, and still prevails just as extensively as the physical mythology of the ancient Aryan peoples. It would be most useful if we could lay aside all these mouldy and decayed expressions, and introduce LANGUAGE AND MIND 111 a word that simply means what is not understood by body, the subject, in opposition to the objective world. It would by no means follow that what is not body must therefore exist independent of the body. It would first of all only declare that beside the ob jective body perceived by the senses, there is also something subjective, which the five senses cannot perceive. The best name for this appears to me still to be the Vedantic term Atman, which I translate into " the Self " (neuter), because our language will scarcely allow the phrase "the Self" (masculine). " Soul " has a too tender quality to be the equivalent of Atman. This Self is something that exists for itself and not for others. While everything that is purely corporeal only exists for us men, inasmuch as it is perceived, the Self exists by reason of the fact that it perceives. While the Esse of all objects is a percipi, a some thing perceived, which has come into knowledge, the Esse of the self is a percipere, a perceiving, a know ing, that is, the Self can only be thought of as self- knowing. The Self exists even when it does not yet clearly know itself, but it is not the real Self until it knows itself ; and it requires long and earnest thought for the Self to know or recognise itself as different from the ego or the body. But if the Self has once come to itself, the darkness or the phenomenal ap pearance which the Vedanta philosophers called Avidyd (not knowing, ignorance), or also Mdyd (ap pearance, or illusion), vanishes. 112 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD The origin of this ignorance, this illusion, or the world of appearance, is a question which no human being will ever solve. There are questions which must be set aside as simply ultra vires by every rea sonable philosophy. We know that we cannot hear certain tones, cannot see certain colours ; why not then understand that we cannot comprehend certain things? The Vedanta philosophers consider the Avidyd (ignorance) as inexplicable, and this was no doubt originally implied in the name which they gave it. Their aim was, to prove the temporal exist ence of such an Avidyd, not to discover its origin ; and then in the Vidyd, the Vedanta philosophy, to set forth the means by which the Avidya, could be destroyed. How or when the Self came into this ignorance, Avidyd, or Mdyd (illusion, or the phe nomenal world), the Vedanta philosophers no more sought to explain than we seek to explain how the Self conies into the body, the bodily senses, and the phenomenal world which they perceive. We begin our philosophy with what is given us, that is, with a Self, that in its embodiment knows everything that befalls the body ; that for a time is blended with the body, till it attains a true self-knowledge, and then, even in life, or later in death, by liberation from its phenomenal existence, or from the body, again comes to itself. How this body, with its senses that convey and present to us the phenomenal world, originated or developed, is a question that belongs to biology. So LANGUAGE and mind 113 far as is possible to the human understanding, this question has been solved by the cell theory. The other question is the development of what we call mind, that is, the subjective knowledge of the phe nomenal world. To this the body, as it exists and lives, and the organs of sense, as they exist, are essen tial. We know that all sense-perceptions depend upon bodily vibrations, i.e. the nerves ; and if we wish to make plain the transition of impressions to conscious ideas, we can best do so through the assumption of the Self as a witness or accessory to the nerve-vibrations. This, however, is only an image, not an explanation, for an explanation belongs to the Utopia of philosophy. How it happens that atoms think, atomists do not know, and no one should imagine that so-called Darwinism has helped or can help us even one step farther. Whatever some Darwinians may say, nothing can be simpler than the frank admission of ignorance on this point on the part of Darwin. The frank and modest expressions of this great but sober thinker are gen erally passed over in silence, or are even controverted as signs of a temporary weakness. To me, on the contrary, they are very valuable, and very char acteristic of Darwin. In one place 1 he says, " I have nothing to do with the origin of the primary mental power any more than I have with that of life itself." In another place2 1 Origin of Species, 5th ed., 1869, p. 255. 2 Descent of Man, 1871, Vol. I, p. 36. i 114 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD he speaks still more plainly and says, " In what man ner the mental powers were first developed in the lowest organisms is as hopeless an inquiry as how life first originated." Let no one suppose, therefore, that all gates and doors can be opened with the word "evolution" or the name Darwin. It is easy to say with Drummond, " Evolution is revolutionising the world of nature and of thought, and within living memory has opened up avenues into the past and vistas into the future such as science has never wit nessed before." 1 Those are bold words, but what do they mean or prove ? DuBois-Reymond has said long before, " How consciousness can arise from the co operation of atoms is beyond our comprehension." In the Contemporary Review, November, 1871,2 Hux ley speaks just as decidedly as Darwin in the name of biology, "I really know nothing whatever, and never hope to know anything, of the steps by which the passage from molecular movement to states of consciousness is effected." Molecules and atoms are objects of knowledge. If we ascribe knowledge to them, they immediately become the monads of Leibnitz ; you may evolve out of them what you have first involved into them. Knowledge belongs to the Self alone, call it what we will. The nerve-fibres might vibrate as often as they pleased, millions and millions of times in a second ; they would never produce the sensation of red if there were no Self as the receiver and illuminator, the translator of these vibrations of 1 Ascent of Man, 1894, p. 9. 2 Vol. XVIII, p. 464. LANGUAGE AND MIND 115 ether ; this Self, that alone receives, alone illumines, alone knows, and of which we can say nothing more than what the Indian philosophers call sa&-&id-&nanda, that it exists, that it perceives, and as they add, that it is blessed, i.e. that it is complete in itself, serene and eternal. If we take a firm stand on this living and perceiv ing Self (for kid is not so much thinking as perceiv ing, or knowing), there can then be no question that it is present not only in men, but in animals as well ; only let us beware of the inference that what we mean by human mind, that is, understanding and reasoning thought, is a necessary function of all living organisms, and is possessed also by a goose or a chicken. It is just the same with the perceiving Self as it is with the cell. To the eye they are all alike. To express it figuratively, one cell has a ticket to Cologne, another to Paris, a third to London. Each reaches its destination, and then remains stationary, and no power on earth can make it advance beyond the place to which it is ticketed, that is, its original destination, its fundamental eternal idea. It is just the same with the perceiving Self. It is true that the Self sees, hears, and thinks. As there are ani mals that cannot see, that cannot hear, so there are animals — and this class includes the whole of them — that cannot speak. It is true that the speaking animals, that is men, have passed the former stations on a fast train ; but they did not leave the train, nor have they anything in common with those who re- 116 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD mained behind at previous stations, least of all can we consider them as the offspring of those that remained behind. This is only a simile, and should not provoke ridicule. Of course it will be said that those who can journey to Cologne may go on to Paris, and once in Paris may easily cross the Channel. We must not ride a comparison to death, but always adhere to the facts. Why does not grass grow as high as a poplar, why is care taken, as Goethe says, that no tree grows up to the sky? A strawberry might grow as large as a cucumber or a pumpkin, but it does not. Who draws the line? It is true, too, that along every line slight deviations take place right and left. Nearly each year we hear of an abnormally large strawberry, and no doubt abnor mally small ones could be found as well. But in spite of all, the normal remains. And whence comes it, if not from the same hand or the same source which we compared with the ticket agent at the railway station, in whom all who are familiar with the history of philosophy will again readily recognise the Greek Logos ? These comparisons should at least be so far useful as to disclose the confusion of thought, when, for in stance, Mr. Romanes holds that it is not only compre hensible, but the conclusion is unavoidable, that the human mind has sprung from the minds of the higher quadrumana on the line of natural genesis. The human mind may mean every possible thing; the question therefore arises if he refers only to con- LANGUAGE AND MIND 117 sciousness, or to understanding and reason. In the second place the human mind is not something sub sisting by itself, but can only be the mind of an in dividual man. We cannot be too careful in these discussions — otherwise we only end by substituting bare abstractions for concrete things. We do not know the human mind as anything concrete at all, only as an abstraction, and in that case only as the mind of one man, or of many men. How can it then be thought that my mind or the mind of Darwin sprang from the minds of the higher quadrumana. We may say such things, but what meaning can we attach to them ? The same misconception exists here, if I am not mistaken, as in the statement, that the human body springs from the bodies of the higher quadrupeds — a misconception to which we have al ready referred. That has absolutely no sense if we only hold firmly, that every organised body was origi nally a cell, or originates in a cell, and that each cell, even in its most complicated, manifold, and perfect form, always is, and remains, an individual. It is useless therefore to talk of a descent of the human mind from the minds of the higher quadrupeds, for no intelligible meaning can be discovered in it ; we should have to fall back on a miscarriage, and to set up this miscarriage as the mother of all men, and with out a legitimate father. Such are the wanderings of a wrong method of thought, even if it struts about in kingly robes. Above all things we must settle what we are really 118 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD to understand by the mind of the higher quadrupeds as distinguished from the human mind. What is there lacking in these animal minds to make them human? And what do they possess, or what are they, that they should claim equal birth with man? How much obscurity there is in these matters among the best animal psychologists is seen when, for instance, we compare the assertions of Romanes with those of Lloyd Morgan. While the former sets up a natural genesis of the human mind from animal mind as being indispu table and as not being thinkable in any other way, the latter, his greatest admirer, says, " Believing, as I do, that conception is beyond the power of my favourite and clever dog, I am forced to -believe that his mind differs generically from my own. " 1 Undoubtedly by " generically " is meant, according to his genus or his genesis. But in spite of this, the same savant says in another place, that he cannot allow that there is a difference in kind, that is in genere, between the hu man mind and the mind of a dog. If men would only define their words, such contradictions would in time become impossible. What men and animals have in common is the Self, and this so-called Self consists first of all in percep tion. This perception belongs, as has been said, to those things which are given us, and not to those which can be explained. It is a property of the eternal Self, as of light, to shine, to illumine itself, that is, to know. Its knowing is its being, and its 1 Lloyd Morgan, Animal Life and Intelligence, p. 350. LANGUAGE AND MIND 119 being is its knowing, or its self-consciousness. If we take the Self as we find it, not merely in itself, but embodied, we must attribute to it, besides its own self-consciousness, a consciousness of the conditions of the body ; but of course we must not imagine that we can make this embodiment in any way conceivable to us. It is so — that is all that we can say, just as in an earlier consideration of the embodiment and multipli cation of the eternal Logos we had to accept this as a datum, without being able to come any nearer to the fact by conceptions, or even by mere analogies. This is where the task of the psychologist begins. Grant the self-consciousness of the individual, although still very obscure ; grant the sentient perception ; every thing else that we call mind is the result of a develop ment, which we must follow historically in order to understand that it could not come about in any other way. But where are the facts, where the monuments, where the trustworthy documents, from which we can draw our knowledge of this wonderful development ? Four sources have been propounded for the study of psychogenesis. It has been said that to investigate the development of the human mind, the following objects must be scientifically observed : (1) The mind of a child ; (2) the mind of the lower animals ; (3) the survivals of the oldest culture, as we find it in ethnological collections ; (4) the mind of still living savages. I formerly entertained similar hopes, but in my own melancholy experience all these studies end in delusion, in so far as they are applied to explain the 120 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD genesis of the human mind. They do not reach far enough, they give us everywhere only the products of growth, the result of art, not the natural growth, or the real evolution. The observations on the development of a child's mind are very attractive, especially when they are made by thoughtful mothers. But this nursery psychology is wanting in all scien tific exactness. The object of observation, the child that cannot yet speak, can never be entirely iso lated. Its environment is of incalculable influence, and the petted child develops very differently from the neglected foundling. The early smile of the one is often as much a reflex action as the crying and blustering of the other, from hunger or inherited disease. Much as I admire the painstaking effort with which the first evidences of perception or of mental activity in a child have been recorded from day to day, from week to week, these observations prove untrustworthy when we endeavour to control them independently. It has been said that the mental activities of a child develop in the following order : — After three weeks fear is manifested ; After seven weeks social affections ; After twelve weeks jealousy and anger ; After five months sympathy ; After eight months, pride, sentiment, love of orna ment; After fifteen months, shame, remorse, a sense of the ludicrous.1 1 H. Drummond, Ascent of Man, 1894, p. 169. LANGUAGE AND MIND 121 We may generalise this scale as much as we please, and gradually permit the gradations to vanish, but I doubt if even two mothers could be found who would agree in such an interpretation of their chil dren's looks. Add to this that this whole scale has very little to do with what, in the strict sense of the word, we call mind. From fear up to shame and peni tence are all manifestations simply of the feelings, and not of the mind. We know that what we call fear is often a reflex action, as when a child closes its eyelids before a blow. What has been named jealousy in a child, is often nothing but hunger, while shame is in stilled into one child, and in others is by no means of spontaneous growth. The worst feature of such observations is that they are very quickly regarded as safe ground, and are reared higher and higher until in the end the entire scaffold collapses. In order to establish the truth of this psychologic scale in children still more firmly, and at the same time to make good its universal necessity, an effort has been made to prove that a similar scale is to be found in the animal kingdom, and of course what was sought has been found. Romanes asserts that the lowest order of animals, the annelids, only show traces of fear ; a little higher in the scale, in insects, are found social instincts such as industry, combativeness, and curiosity; another step higher, fishes exhibit jealousy, and birds, sym pathy ; then in carnivorous animals follow cruelty, hate, and grief ; and lastly, in the anthropoid apes, 122 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD remorse, shame, and a sense of the ridiculous, as well as deceit. It needs but one step more to make this scale, which belongs much more to the sphere of feel ing than the realm of thought, universally applicable to all psychology. How should we otherwise explain the parallelism between the mental development of infants and that of undeveloped animals ? One need but take a firm hold of such observations, and they are transformed into airy visions. Who, for instance, would dare to distinguish the traces of fear in an nelids from those of surprise in higher animals? Nevertheless fear occupies the first place, surprise the third. And what mark distinguished combative ness in insects from jealousy in fishes ? In the same way I doubt if any two nurses would agree in the chronology of the phenomena of the infant disposi tion, and have therefore long since given up all hope of obtaining any hints either in embryological or physiological development, about the real historical unfolding of the human consciousness, either out of a nursery or out of a zoological garden. As for ethnological museums, they certainly give us wonderful glimpses into the skilfulness of primi tive man, especially in what relates to the struggle for life ; but of the historic or prehistoric age of these wood, horn, and stone weapons, they tell us absolutely nothing. Whoever thinks that man de scended from an ape, may no doubt say that flint implements for kindling fire belonged to a higher period, post hominem natum, although it has been LANGUAGE AND MIND 123 thought that even apes could have imitated such weapons, though they could not have invented them. Romanes, in his book on Mental Evolution in Animals, has collected a large number of illustrations of animal skilfulness ; the majority of them, however, are ex plained by mere mimicry ; of a development of origi nal ideas peculiar to animals in their wild state, apart from the contact and influence of human society, there is no trace. Even the most intelligent animal, the elephant, acquires reason only in its intercourse with men, and similarly the more or less trained apes, dogs, parrots, etc. All this is very interesting reading, and an English weekly, The Spectator, has from week to week given us similar anecdotes about wonderfully gifted animals from all parts of the earth, but these matters lie outside the narrow sphere of science. What then remains to enable us to study the earli est phase of development of the human mind accessi ble to us? If we go to savages, whose language we only understand imperfectly, these observations are of course still more untrustworthy than in the case of our own children ; at all events we must wait before we receive any really valuable evidence of the develop ment of the human mind from that source. I repeat that the human mind itself, as far as it perceives, must simply be accepted as a fact, given to us and inexplicable, whether in civilised or uncivilised races ; but only in its greatest simplicity, as mere self- conscious perception — a perception which in this simplicity can in no wise be denied to animals, al- 124 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD though we can only with difficulty form a clear idea of the peculiarity of their sentient perceptions. Where can we observe the first steps that rise above this simple perception ? I say, as I have always said, In language and in language alone. Language is the oldest monument which we possess of man's mental power, older than stone weapons, than cuneiform in scriptions, than hieroglyphics. The development of language is continuous, for where this continuity is broken, language dies. After every Tasmanian had been killed or had died, the Tasmanian language ipso facto ceased; and even if any literary remains had survived, the language itself would have to be reck oned, like Latin and Greek, with dead languages. Thousands of them may have disappeared from the earth; in its development a language may have changed as much as Sanskrit to Bengali ; but it suffers no break, it remains always the same, and in a certain sense we still speak in German the same tongue as was spoken by the Aryans before there was a San skrit, a Greek, or a Latin language. Consider what this signifies. Chronologically, we cannot get at this primitive Aryan speech. Let us assume that Sanskrit, Greek, and Latin were spoken as inde pendent national tongues at least fifteen hundred years before our chronology — what an age had elapsed before these three, as well as the remaining Aryan tongues, could have diverged so much as San skrit diverges from Greek and Greek from Latin. The numerals are the same in these three languages, LANGUAGE AND MIND 125 and yet katvaras sounds quite differently from reao-a- pe? and quatuor and our four. The words for eight, octo in Latin, oktco in Greek, and ashiau in Sanskrit, are nearly identical ; and it is even possible that the lesser deviations in the pronunciation of these words demanded no great interval of time. But now let us consider what lies behind these ten numerals. There is the elaboration of a decimal system from 1 to 10, no, to 100 (eicaTov), Sanskrit satdm, centum. There is the formation and fixing of names for these num bers, which must have been originally more or less arbitrary, because numbers only subordinate them selves with difficulty to one of those general ideas which are expressed in the Aryan roots. Besides these words are, even in their oldest attainable forms, already so weather-beaten, that in most cases it is im possible even to guess their etymology and original meaning. We see that the names for two and eight are dual, while those for three and four clearly have plural endings. But why eight in the primitive Aryan was a dual, and what were the two tetrads, which, combined in ash£-au, oct-o, okt-o), expressed the number eight, will probably never be discovered. It is possible that ashi-i was a name for the four phases of the moon, or for the four fingers of the hand with out the thumb. Analogies occur in other families of language, but certainty is beyond our reach. If we now consider what mental effort is necessary to work out a decimal system, and to secure general recogni tion and value for the name given to each number, 126 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD we shall readily realise what remote periods in the development of the human mind open up before us here, and of how little use it would be to try to estab lish chronological limits. Old as the Vedas, old as the Homeric songs may be, what is their age com pared with the periods that were required not only to work out the numerals but the entire treasury of Aryan words, and the wonderful network of grammar that surrounds this treasure, which also was complete before the separation of the Aryan languages began. The immeasurable cannot be measured, but this much stands immovable in the mind of every lin guist, that there is nothing older in the entire Aryan world than the complete primitive Aryan language and grammar, in which nearly all the categories of thought, and consequently the whole scaffold of our thinking, have found their expression. Of course it will be said that all this only applies to the Aryan race, and that they constitute only a small and perhaps the youngest portion of the hu man race. Well, it is difficult to prove that the Aryans constitute the least numerous subdivision. We know too little of their great masses to attempt a census. That they are the youngest branch of the human race is really of no consequence; we should then have to assume against all Darwinian prin ciples, various, not contemporaneous, but successive monstrosities, slowly ascending to humanity, and this would only be pure invention. Nothing ab solutely compels us to ascribe a shorter earthly life LANGUAGE AND MIND 127 to those races which speak Chinese, Semitic, Bantu, American, Australian, or other languages, than to the Aryans. That all races have begun on a lower plane of culture, and especially of the knowledge of language, will no doubt be universally acknowledged. But even if we only place the first beginnings of the Aryan race at 10,000 B.C., there is time enough for it and other races to have risen, and also to have again declined. The difference would merely be that the Aryans, in spite of many drawbacks, on the whole constantly progressed, while the Australians, Negroes, and Patagonians, forced into unfavourable positions, remained stationary on a very low level. That their present plane can in any respect, and especially in re gard to their language, supply a picture of the earliest condition of the human race, or even of certain branches of it, is again mere assumption, and as bare of all analogy as the attempt to see in the salons of London a picture of Aryan family life before the first separation. There are savages who are cannibals. Shall we conclude from this that the first men all de voured each other, or that only those who were least appetising remained over as survivals of the fittest? It is remarkable how many ideas are current in science which the healthy human mind, after short reflection, silently lays aside. Any one who has occupied him self with the polysynthetic tongues of the Redskins, or with the prefixes in the languages of the Bantus, knows how much time must have been needed to develop their grammar, and how much higher the 128 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD makers of these languages must have stood than those who speak them now. But even if language is the oldest chronicle in which the human mind has traced its own development, we must by no means imagine that any known language, be it as old as the pyramids, or as the cuneiform in scriptions, can offer us a picture of the first beginning of the mental life of the race. Long before the pyra mids, long before the oldest monuments in Babylon, Nineveh, and China, there was language, even writ ing; for on the oldest Egyptian inscriptions we find among the hieroglyphic signs writing materials and the stilus. Here perspectives open up to us, before which every chronological telescope gives way. There is a rigorous continuity in the development of a lan guage, but this continuity in no wise excludes a transformation as marked as that of the butterfly from the caterpillar. Even when, as for instance in Sanskrit, we go back to a number of roots, to which Indian grammarians such as Pamni have systemati cally traced back the entire wealth of their abundant language, we must not suppose that these roots really constituted the original and complete material with which the primitive Aryan tongue began its historical career. This is not true even of the Indian branch of this primitive tongue, for in its development much may have been lost, and much so changed that we dare not think of restoring a perfect picture from these fragments of the earliest mental development of the Indians. These things are so simple that phi- LANGUAGE AND MIND 129 lologists accept them as axioms ; but it is curious to observe, that in spite of the widespread interest that has been created in all civilised nations by the results of the science of language, philosophers who write about language and its relation to thought still trouble themselves over notions long since antiquated. I had, for instance, classified the principal ideas ex pressed in Sanskrit roots, and had reduced them to the small number of 121.1 With these 121 ideas, Ind ian philology pledges itself to explain all the simple and derivative meanings of words that fill the thick volumes of a Sanskrit lexicon. And what did eth nologists say to this ? Instead of gratefully accepting this fact, they asserted that many of these 121 radi cal ideas, as for instance, weaving or cooking, could not possibly be primitive. Impossible is always a very convenient word. But who ever claimed that these 121 fundamental ideas all belonged to the prim itive Aryan language. They are, in fact, the ideas that are indicated in the thousands of words in clas sical Sanskrit, but they have never made any claim to have constituted the mental capital of the primi tive Aryans, whether acquired from heaven or from the domicile of apes. And if now a few of these ideas, such as to weave, to cook, to clean, appear modern, what of that compared with the simple fact that they are actually there ? These ethnologists, too, always make the old mis take of confounding the learning of a language, as 1 See Science of Thought, p. 405. 130 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD is done by every child, with the first invention or formation of a language. The two things are as radically different as the labour of miners who bring forth to the light of day gold ore out of the depths of the earth, and the enjoyment which the heirs of a rich man have in squandering his cash. The two things are quite different, and yet there are books upon books which attempt to draw conclusions as to the creation of language from children learning to talk. We have at least now got so far as to admit that language facilitates thinking ; but that language first made thought possible, that it was the first step in the development of the human mind, but few anthropologists have seen.1 They do not know what language in the true sense of the word means, and still think that it is only communication, and that it does not differ from the signals made by chamois, or the information imparted by the antennae of ants. Henry Drummond goes so far as to say that " Any means by which information is conveyed from one mind to another, is language." 2 That is entirely erro neous. The entire chapter on sign language, interest ing as it is, must be treated quite differently by the 1 See the author's preface to his English translation (second edi tion) of Kant's Critic of Pure Reason, p. xxviii, to which we now add the prophetic words of Shelley, in his Prometheus Tin- bound (II, 4) : — " He gave man speech, and speech created thought, Which is the measure of the Universe." 2 Ascent of Man, 1894, p. 200. LANGUAGE AND MIND 131 philologist, compared with the ethnologist. When the sign is such as was used in the old method of telegraphing, and meant a real word, or, as in modern electric telegraphy, even a letter, this is really speak ing by signs; and so is the finger language of the deaf and dumb. But when I threaten my opponent with my fist, or strike him in the face, when I laugh, cry, sob, sigh, I certainly do not speak, although I do make a communication, the meaning of which can not be doubted. Not every communication, therefore, is language, nor does every act of speaking aim at a communication. There are philologists who maintain that the first words were merely a clearing of the ideas, a sort of talking to oneself. This may have been so or not, at any rate it appears to me that in such primitive times, practical ends deserve the first consideration. No one can distinguish the difference in the stages of mental development, between wiping the perspiration from the brow after work, which sig nifies and communicates to every observer, " It is warm " or " I am tired," and the man who can actually say, " It is warm," " I am tired." Thousands, millions of years may lie between these two steps. We do not know, and to attempt to fix periods of time where the means are lacking, is like pouring water into the Danaids' sieves. Just consider what effort was required to enable an Aryan man to say, " It is warm." We shall say nothing of " it " ; it may be a simple demonstrative stem, which needed little for its formation. But 132 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD before this " i-t " or " id " could become an impersonal " it," long-continued abstraction, or, if you prefer, long- continued polishing, was required. Take the word is. Whence comes such a verbal form, Sanskrit as-ti, Greek ea-Ti, Latin est ? Was the abstract " to be " onomatopo- etically imitated ? Often, of course, we cannot answer such questions at all. In this case, however, it is pos sible. The root as in asti, that we now translate as is, means as we see from as-u, breath, originally to breathe. Whoever likes may see in as, to breathe, an imitation of hissing breath. We neither gain or lose anything by this; for the critical step always remains to be taken from a single imitation of a single act, to the comprehension of many such acts, at various places, and at various times, as one and the same, which is called abstraction or the forming of a concept. This may appear to be a very small step, just as the first slight deviation in a railroad track is scarcely a finger's breadth, but in time changes the course of the train to an entirely different part of the world. The formation of an idea, such as to be, or to be come, or to take a still simpler one, such as four or eight, appears to us to be a very small matter, and yet it is this very small matter that distinguishes man from the animal, that pushed man forward and left the animal behind on his old track. Nay, more, this " concept " has caused much shaking of the head among philosophers of all times. That one and one are two, two and two, four, four and four, eight, LANGUAGE AND MIND 133 eight and eight, sixteen, etc., appears to be so very easy, that we do not understand how such things can constitute an eternally intended distinction between man and animal. I have myself seen an ape so well trained that as the word "seven " was spoken, he picked up seven straws. But what is such child's play in com parison with the first formation of the idea of seven ? Do you not see that the formation of such an abstract idea, isolating mere quantity apart from all qualities, requires a power of abstraction such as has never been displayed by an animal? If there were any languages now that actually had no word for seven, it would be a valuable confirmation of this view. I doubt only, whether the speakers of such languages could not call composition to their aid, and attain the idea of seven by two, two, two, plus one. We still know too little of these languages and of those who speak them. Of what takes place in animals we know absolutely nothing, and nowhere would a dose of agnosticism be more useful than here. Sense-im pressions an animal certainly has ; whether quite the same as man must remain uncertain. And sense- impressions enable an animal to accomplish much, especially in the realm of feeling ; but language — never. This fact, as a bare undeniable fact, should have startled the Darwinians, even as it startled the vener able Darwin, when I simply set the facts before him, and he immediately drew the necessary consequences. Of any danger there could be no fear. The facts are 134 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD there and show us the right path. And it is not only simple facts, but the consequences of preexisting con ditions which render every so-called transition from animal to man absolutely unthinkable. Language — as ethnologists should have learned — has neither originated from artificial signs, nor from imitation of sounds. That we can communicate with signs with out saying a word, that we even now use signs in our speech, is best learned in southern races, and in such pantomimes as Eenfant prodigue. We have long known that imitations of sound exist in greater or lesser numbers in every language, and how far they can reach has probably never been shown in such detail as by myself.1 But that our Aryan tongues, and also the Semitic, and all others that have been studied scientifically, originated from roots, is now generally known and recognised. That these roots may in remote times have contained an element of imitation, we may readily concede, for it is really self-evident ; only we should not from the beginning bar our way by conceiving them as mere imitations of sound. If this were so, the problem of language would long since have been solved, and the first formation of ideas would require no further reflection. It must be conceded on the other side that the origin of roots still contains much that is obscure, and that even Noire"s clamor concomitans does not explain every case. Only it is firmly established that a scientific analysis of language leaves a certain number of roots 1 Science of Language, 1891, p. 499. LANGUAGE AND MIND 135 which are not mere sound-imitations, such as " bow wow," or "moo moo." There are people who have taken much pains to discover whether the roots ever had an independent existence, or if they have merely been scientifically abstracted, or shelled out of the words in which they occur. These are vain ques tions, for we can never of course come at the matter historically, and the attempt to prove the necessity of the one or the other view is a useless undertaking. It appears to be the most reasonable plan to assume for the Aryan languages a period that approaches the Chinese, in which roots had the same sound and the same form as the corresponding noun, adjective, and verb. Even in Sanskrit roots appear at times still unchanged, although it is quite right that as soon as they take on grammatical functions, they should no longer be called roots. Much may be said in favour of both views, without arriving one step nearer our goal. If we now only remember that the whole San skrit language has been reduced to 121 primitive ideas, and that the roots denoting these (which are of course much more numerous) are not imita tions of sound in the strict sense of the word, but sounds about whose origin we may say much but can prove little, we have at least a 7roi> otco for our researches. I myself, like my deceased friend Noire-, have looked upon roots as clamor concomitans, that is, not as sound-imitations, but as actual sounds, uttered by men in common occupations, and to be heard even now. Why, however, the Aryans used and retained 136 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD ad for eat, tan for stretch, mar for rub, as for breathe, sta for stand, ga for go, no human thought can find out ; we must be content with the fact that it was so, and that a certain number of such roots — of course much greater than the 121 ideas expressed by them — constitute the kernels from which has sprouted the entire flora of the Indian mind. If we now return to our is, — Sanskrit as-ti, Greek eon, Latin est, — we see that it originally meant "to breathe out." This blowing or breathing was then used for "life," as in as-u, breath of life, and from life it lost its content until it could be applied to everything existing, and meant nothing more than the abstract " to be." There are languages that pos sess no such pale word as " be " and could not form such a sentence as " It is warm." The auxiliary verb " to have " is also lacking in many languages, espe cially the ancient, such as Sanskrit, Greek, and even classical Latin. If the words failed, the ideas failed as well, and such languages had to try and fulfil their requirements in other ways. If there was no such word as "be," "stand" was employed; where there was no word for " have," then " hold," tenere, would render the same, or at least similar service. But this implied not only different speech, but different thought. But here I should like to call attention to the long process through which a language must pass, before it could reduce " breathe " to " be " and form such a sentence as "It is warm." Even an animal feels LANGUAGE AND MIND 137 warmth, and can in various ways make known if it is overheated. But in all this it is only a question of feelings, not to ideas, and still less of language. Let us consider " warm." Of course " warm " may represent a mere feeling, and then a simple panting would suffice to express it. That is communication, but not language. To think a word like warm, a root and an idea are necessary. Probably, and in spite of a few phonetic difficulties, the root was in this case ghar (in gharmd, depuos), and this meant at first to be bright, to glitter, to shine, then to burn, to heat, to be warm ; that is to say, the observing mind of man was able to abstract brightness from the sense- impressions produced by sun, fire, gold, and many other objects, and, letting everything else drop, to reach the idea of shining, then of being warm. These ideas, of course, do not exist on their own account anywhere in the world ; they must be and have been constructed by man alone, never by an animal. Why ? Because an animal does not possess what man possesses : the faculty of grasping the many as one, so as to form an idea and a word. Light or lighting, warmth or warming, exist nowhere in the world, and are nowhere given in sentient experience. Every object of sense exists individu ally, and is perceived as such individually, such as the sun, a torch, a stove ; but heat in general, like everything general, is the product of our thought ; its name is made by us, and is not given us. Of all this, of course, when we learn to speak as 138 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD children, we have no suspicion. We learn the lan guage made by others who came before us, and pro ceed from words to ideas, not from ideas to words. Whether the relation between ideas and words was a succession, it is hard to say, because no idea exists without a word, any more than a word without an idea. Word and idea exist through each other, be side each other, with each other ; they are inseparable. We could as easily try to speak without thinking, as to think without speaking. It is at first difficult to grasp this. We are so accustomed to think silently, before speaking aloud, that we actually believe that the same is true, even of the first formation of ideas and words. Our so-called thinking before speaking, however, refers simply to reflection, or deliberation. It is something quite different, and occurs only with the aid of silent words that are in us, even if they are not uttered. Every person, particularly in his youth, believes that he cherishes within himself in expressible feelings, or even thoughts. These are chiefly obscure feelings, and the expression of feel ings has always been the most difficult task to be performed by language, because they must first pass through a phase of conception. If, however, they are actually ideas, they are such as have an old expres sion that is felt to be inconvenient, or inadequate, and must be replaced by a new one. We cannot do enough to rid ourselves of the old error, that thought is possible without words. We can, of course, repeat words without meaning; but that is not speaking, LANGUAGE AND MIND 139 only making a noise. If any one, however, tells us that he can think quite well without words, let this silent thinker be suddenly interrupted, ask him of what he has thought in silence, and he will have to admit that it was of a dog, a horse, or a man — in short, of something that has a name. He need not utter these words — that has never been main tained, but he must have the ideas and their signs, otherwise there are not, and there cannot be for him, either ideas or things. How often we see children move their lips while they are thinking, that is, speaking without articulation. We can, of course, in case of necessity, use other signs ; we can hold a dog on high and show him, but if we ask what is shown, we shall find that the actual dog is only a substitute for the abstract word " dog," not the re verse, for a dog that is neither a spaniel, poodle, dachshund, etc., is nowhere to be found, in rerum natura, or in domestic life. These things, that give us so much trouble, were often quite clear to the ancient Hindus, for their usual word for "thing" is paddrtha; that is, meaning or purpose of the word. But men persist that they are able to think without speaking aloud, or in silence. They persist that thought comes first, and then speech; they persist that they can speak without thinking, — and that is often quite true, — and that they can also think without speaking, which must first be proved. Consider only what is necessary to form so simple a word as "white." The idea of 140 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD white must be formed at the same time, and this can only be done by dropping everything but the colour from the sense-perceptions of such things as snow, snowdrop, cloud, chalk, or sugar, then marking this colour, and, by means of a sign (in this case a vocal one), elevating it to a comprehensible idea, and at the same time to a word. How this vocal token originates it is often difficult, often quite im possible, to say. The simplest mode is, for example, if there be a word for snow, to take this and to generalise it, and then to call sugar, for instance, snow, or snowy, or snow-white. But the prior ques tion, how snow was named, only recedes for a while, and must of course be answered for itself. Given a word for snow, it can easily be generalised. But how did we name snow ? I believe that snow, which forms into balls in melting and coheres, was named nix nivis, from a root snigh or snu, denoting every thing which melted and yet stuck together or cohered. But these are mere possibilities that may be true or false ; yet their truth or falsity leave undisturbed the fundamental truth, that each individual perception, as, for example, this snow or this ice, first had to be brought under a general conception, before it could be clearly marked, or elevated to a word. In such a case men formed, by living and working together, a general conception and a root, for an oft-repeated action, such as forming into balls ; and under this general concept they then conceived an individual impression like snow ; that is, that which is formed LANGUAGE AND MIND 141 into a ball, so that they had the sign, and with the sign the concept of snow, both inseparable in reality, distinguishable as they are in their origin. Having this, they could extend the concept in the vocal sign for snow, and speak of snowy things, just as they spoke of rosy cheeks. Only we must not imagine that it will ever be possible to make the origin of root sounds perfectly clear. This goes back to times that are entirely withdrawn from our observation. It goes back to times in which the first general ideas were formed, and thereby the first steps were taken in the development of the human mind. How is it possible that any recollection should have remained of such early times, or even any understanding of these mental processes ? We may settle many things, but in the end nothing is left but to say : It is so, and remains so, whether we can explain it or not. The first general concept ma)' no doubt have been, as Noire affirmed, an often repeated action, such as striking, going, rubbing, chewing — acts that spon taneously present themselves to consciousness, as manifold and yet single, that is, as continually repeated, in which the mind consequently found the first natural stimulus to the formation of concepts. Why, however, rub was denoted by mar, eat by ad, go by ga, strike by tud, we may perhaps apprehend by feeling, but we could not account for or even conceive it. Here we must be content with the facts, especially as in other families of languages we find entirely different vocal signs. No doubt there was a 142 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD reason for all of them ; but this reason, even if we could prove it historically, would always remain in comprehensible to us, and only as fact would it have any significance for science. At any rate, we can now understand in what man ner language offers us really historical documents of the oldest stages which we can reach in the devel opment of the human mind. I say, " which we can reach," for what lies beyond language does not ex ist for us. Nothing remains of the history of homo alalus. But every word represents a deed, an acqui sition of the mind. If we take such a word as the Vedic deva, there may have been many older words for god, but let us not imagine that a fetish or totem, whose etymology is or should be known, belongs to them. But at all events we know from deva and the Latin deus, that even before the Aryan separa tion a root dyu or div had been formed, as well as the conception " shine." If this root was first used actively for the act of shedding light, of striking a spark, of shining, it was a step farther to transfer this originally active root to the image which the sky produces in us, and to call it a " shiner," dyu (nom. dyaus), and then with a new upward tendency to call all bright and shining beings, deva, deus. Man started, therefore, from a generalisation, or an idea, and then under this idea grouped other single presentations, such as sun, moon, and stars, from which "shining" had been withdrawn, or abstracted, and thus obtained as a mental acquisition a sign for the LANGUAGE AND MIND 143 idea " shine," and further formations such as Dyaus (shiner) and deva (shining). Now observe how Dyaus, as " shiner," at the same time assumed the sig nificance of an otherwise unknown agent or author of light, and developed into the ancient Dyaus, into Zeus and Jove ; that is, into the oldest personal God of the still united Aryans. These are the true stages of the development of the human mind, which are susceptible of documentary proof in the archives of language. All this occurred, of course, on exclusively Aryan ground, while the Semitic and other branches went their own way in the formation of ideas, and of sounds for their ideas. Physiologically all these branches may have one and the same origin, but linguistically they have various beginnings, and have not, at least as far as scientific proof is possible, sprung from one and the same source. The common origin of all lan guages is not impossible, but it is and remains unde- monstrable, and to science that is enough, sapienti sat. If we analyse the Semitic and other languages, we shall find in them as many ancient documents of the development of the human mind as in the Aryan. And just as we can clearly and plainly trace back the French dieu, the Latin deus, the Sanskrit deva, divine, to the physical idea div, "shine," so we can with thousands of other words, of which each indicates an act of will, and each gives us an insight into the development of our mind. Whether the Aryans were in possession of other ideas and sounds for 144 THE SILESIAN HORSEHERD " shine," etc., before the formation of div, Dyaus, and deva, must be left uncertain; at all events we see how naturally the first consciousness of God developed in them, how the idea conditioned the language, and the language the idea, and both originated and con tinued inseparable one from the other. If we take any root of the Aryan language, we shall be astonished at the enormous number of its derivatives and the shades in their meaning. Here we see very plainly how thought has climbed forward upon words. We find, for instance, in the list of Sanskrit roots, the root bhar with the simple meaning to bear. This we see plainly in bhardmi, in bibharmi, in bibharti (I bear, he bears), also in bhdras or bhartdr (a bearer), and bhdrds (load) and bhdrman and bharti (bearing), etc. But these forms, with all their cases and persons and tenses, give us no idea of the fruitfulness of a root, especially if we follow its ramifications in the cognate languages. In Greek we have (peprn, in Latin fero, in Gothic bairan, in English to bear. The prin cipal meanings which this root assumes are, to carry, carry hither, carry away, carry in, to support, to main tain, to bring forth, etc. We find simple derivatives such as the German Bahre, English bier (French Mere, borrowed), and also (beperpov and feretrum, as well as fereulum (a litter). On the other hand there is (poperpov (a porter's wages), and aperpa (quiver). And barrow in wheel-barrow has the same origin. Burden is that which is borne, LANGUAGE AND MIND 145 then a load, as, for instance, the burden of years. A step farther takes us to dpo<; or $e/3e/ea/D7ro?. In German it becomes a mere suffix, as fruchtbar, dankbar, scheinbar, urbar. Like (popo';, ep/j,a. If Sfypos (carriage) stands for Bi(p6po';, it means originally a carriage for two persons, just as a/jL6po<: and