YALE UNIVERSITY LIBRARY From the Library of President and Mrs. Arthur Twining Hadley The gift of their children Mrs. Nicholas Mosely Morris Hadley, '16 Hamilton Hadley, '19 THE GEOUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHEISTIAN BELIEF THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF BY GEORGE PARK FISHER, D.D., LL.D. EMERITUS PROFESSOR OP ECCLESIASTICAL HISTORY IN TALE UNIVERSITY REVISED EDITION- IN GREAT PART REWRITTEN NEW YORK CHARLES SCRIBNER'S SONS 1902 COPYRIGHT, 1883, 1902, BY CHARLES SCRIBNER'S SONS Published Ootobek, 1902. NortoootJ $UB8 J. S. dishing & Co. — Berwick & Smith Norwood Masa. U. S. A. Ea WILLIAM SANDAY D.D., LL.D. LADY MARGAEET PEOPESSOR OP DIVINITY AT OXFORD AND CANON OP CHRIST CHURCH WHOSE WRITINGS ARE AN EXAMPLE TO CONTEMPORARY SCHOLARS OP THOROUGH INVESTIGATION AND FAULTLESS CANDOE SCfjis Uolutiw is JB.Sicat.B PREFACE When I found that this book after a score of years since its publication was still widely read at home and abroad, I felt something like an obligation to put it in a form more consonant with what I should wish to say at present. I have done much in revising and recasting its contents, especially since gaining as emeritus professor the continuity of time so favorable to literary work. The leading propositions in the book will not be found to be materially altered. The arguments in support of them have experienced modifications of some importance, and still more the language in which they are set forth. The rela tions of Christian Theism to natural and physical science are more elaborately discussed than in the earlier edition. The same is true of the evidence pertaining to the origin and author ship of the Gospels. In preparing to take up anew the first of these main topics, I have resorted to the writings of naturalists of the best repute and been aided by personal converse with adepts in these branches. I have meant to treat with just respect the authority of these sources of knowledge. At the same time every discerning student understands the necessity of drawing a line between the real data of science, with the conclusions fairly deduced and the metaphysics often mingled pretty largely in treatises which, on their own ground, may be safe guides. By German scholars, some of them of much celebrity, it is felt to be high time to utter a protest against what had grown to be a disrespect, as prevalent as it is unreasonable, for early ecclesiastical tradition relative to the date of New Testament writings. The reaction against the moribund formula of the impeccability of Scripture even outside the limits of moral and religious doctrine has opened the door to a boundless field of conjecture in handling the New Testament narratives, both as to the Introduction and in the special precinct of exegesis. Upon this license a sounder Biblical criticism is called upon to impose a proper restraint. In reference to the New Testament viii PREFACE narratives, I see no reason for setting aside the traditional ascription of the book of Acts — including the passages from a fellow-traveller of Paul, speaking in the first person — to the authorship of Luke, the writer of the third Gospel. Nor am I convinced of the non-apostolic or composite authorship of the fourth Gospel. The suggestion, for one thing, that there was a confusion of names on the part of Irenaeus — a mistaking by him in the discourses of Polycarp of one John when another was meant — appears to me improbable in the extreme. The inference, based on the Synoptics, for the negative position on the question of authorship strikes me as resting on misinterpre tation of the first three Gospels, and an indefensible scepticism concerning additional matter contained in the fourth. Of the two branches of Christian Evidences, the internal or moral, and the external proof from miracles, it will be seen that the precedence is accorded to the former. This is a point of difference from the older method usual in the school of Paley. In truth they are two mutually supporting species of evidence. I abstain, in deference to what might be their preference, to mention the names of friends whom I have consulted with profit in the composition and issue of this work. I must be allowed to make one exception, and to express my thanks to Professor Charles J. H. Ropes, of Bangor, who has kindly read the proof- sheets of several chapters, respecting which his learning and accuracy were especially helpful. I must expect that, among the readers who may be interested in the general subject of this volume, some will be less attracted by the sections that are concerned with the philosophical objec tions to theism, or with the details of critical evidence on the genuineness of the Gospels. But even this class, I trust, will find the major part of the book not altogether ill-suited to their wants. I venture to indulge the hope that they may derive from it some aid in clearing up perplexities, and some new light upon the nature of the Christian faith and its relation to the Scriptures. Fortunately readers as well as teachers are at liberty to exercise the right of omission. G. P. F. Yale University, October, 1902. EXTRACTS FROM THE PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION This volume embraces a discussion of the evidences of both natural and revealed religion. Prominence is given to topics having special interest at present from their connection with modern theories and difficulties. With respect to the first divi sion of the work, the grounds of the belief in God, it hardly need be said that theists are not all agreed as to the method to be pursued, and as to what arguments are of most weight in the defence of this fundamental truth. I can only say of these introductory chapters, that they are the product of long study and reflection. The argument of design and the bearing of evolutionary doctrine on its validity are fully considered. It is made clear, I believe, that no theory of evolution which is not pushed to the extreme of materialism and fatalism — dog mas which lack all scientific warrant — weakens the proof from final causes. In dealing with antitheistic theories, the agnostic philosophy, partly from the show of logic and of system which it presents, partly from the guise of humility which it wears, — not to speak of the countenance given it by some naturalists of note, — seemed to call for particular attention. One radical question in the conflict with atheism is whether man himself is really a personal being, whether he has a moral history distinct from a merely natural history. If he has not, then it is idle to talk about theism, but equally idle to talk about the data of ethics. Ethics must share the fate of religion. How can there be serious belief in responsible action when man is not free, and is not even a substantial entity ? If this question were dis posed of, further difficulties, to be sure, would be left in the path of agnostic ethics. How can self-seeking breed benevo lence, or self-sacrifice and the sense of duty spring out of the X FROM THE PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION " struggle for existence " ? Another radical question is that of the reality of knowledge. Are things truly knowable ? Or is what we call knowledge a mere phantasmagoria, produced we know not by what? This is the creed which some one has aptly formulated in the Shakespearean lines : — " We are such stuff As dreams are made of, and our little life Is rounded with a sleep." In the second division of the work the course pursued is different from that usually taken by writers on the Evidences of Revelation. A natural effect of launching an ordinary in quirer at once upon a critical investigation of the authorship of the Gospels is to bewilder his mind among patristic authorities that are strange to him. I have preferred to follow, though with an opposite result, the general method adopted of late by noted writers of the sceptical schools. I have undertaken to show that when we take the Gospels as they stand, prior to researches into the origin of them, the miraculous element in the record is found to carry in it a self-verifying character. On the basis of what must be, and actually is, conceded, the conclusion cannot be avoided that the miracles occurred. This vantage-ground once fairly gained, the matter of the authorship and date of the Gospels can be explored without the bias which a prejudice against the miraculous elements in the narrative creates against its apostolic origin. Then it remains to estab lish the truthfulness of the apostolic witnesses, and, further, to vindicate the supernatural features of the Gospel history from the objection that is suggested by the stories of pagan miracles and by the legends of the saints. ... In earlier and later chapters I have sought to direct the reader into lines of reflec tion which may serve to impress him with the truth contained in the remark that the strongest proof of Christianity is afforded by Christianity itself and by Christendom as an existing fact. G. P. F. CONTENTS CHAPTER I The Personality of God and op Man : The Selp-eevelation op God in the Human Soul PAGE The Two Beliefs associated 1 The Essentials of Personality 2 The Reality of Self 2 Self-determination 3 Theories of Necessity and Determinism 5 The Consciousness of Moral Law 16 The Aspiration to commune with God 18 Instincts of Feeling as Indicative of Truth 20 The Belief in Immortality 20 The Place of Will in Religious Faith 20 Anticipative Presentiment in Religion 22 CHAPTER II The Arguments for the Being of God: Their Function in General and as Severally considered The Ultimate Source of Belief in God 24 The Intuition of the Absolute 24 The Ontological Argument 26 The Cosmological Argument . 27 The Uncaused Being a Voluntary Agent 28 Disproof of Polytheism 29 The Argument from Design : its Significance 30 The a priori Basis of this Argument 32 Mind Discernible in Nature 33 Science the Reflex of Mind in Nature ...... 34 Distinction between Order and Design .35 Teleology Evident in Plants 36 Teleology most Manifest in Animal Organisms .... 37 Objections to the Design-argument answered 38 The Four Criticisms suggested by Kant 42 The Hypothesis of Chance 43 xi xii CONTENTS PAGE Evolution and Design : Meaning of Evolution 45 Design-argument strengthened by Evolution 46 Teleology and Mechanism 49 Variability in Organisms 49 Darwin on Variability and Design 49 Respecting the Attributes of God 53 The Moral Argument 55 The Problem of Evil 56 The Historical Argument 59 Personality consistent with Infinitude 60 The World like Man for a Purpose . 62 CHAPTER HI The Principal Anti-theistio Theories : Pantheism, Positivism, Materialism, Agnosticism The Four Terms defined .63 What is Pantheism ? 63 The System of Spinoza 63 The German Systems of Ideal Pantheism 65 No Place in Pantheism for Free Choice or Responsibility ... 67 Positivism ; Not Self-consistent 67 J. S. Mill's Modifications of Positivism 68 Materialism 68 Relation of Consciousness to Physical States 69 Materialism a Self-destructive Theory 70 The Doctrine of " Conscious Automatism " 71 The Agnostic System of Spencer 72 Spencer's Theory of Evolution examined 74 Later Expressions of Spencer 77 Agnosticism the Destruction of Science 78 Untenable Identification of Mind and Matter 79 The Question of the Reality of Knowledge 82 Locke, Berkeley, Hume, Kant 83 Hamilton and Mansel 84 Mill's Revival of Hume's Speculations 86 Relation of Spencer to Hume and Mill 86 How Philosophy to escape from its Aberrations .... 88 CHAPTER IV The Divine Origin of Christianity evinced in its Adapted- ness to the Deepest Necessities op Man The Practical Test of Christianity 89 The Soul's Need of God 90 CONTENTS XUI The Feeling awakened in the Miseries of Life The Experience of Goethe. Letter of Carlyle The Consciousness of Sin and Guilt . The Consciousness of Moral Bondage Recognition in the Bible of the Facts of Life Reconciliation to God through the Gospel Filial Union to God through Christ . Peace and Victory over the World . PAGE 91 92 929496 96 CHAPTER V The Divine Mission op Jesus attested by the Transforming Agency op Christianity in Human Society The Power of Christianity evinced in its Progress .... 99 The Beneficence of its Influence 100 Prediction of the Nature and Effect of its Progress . . . .101 New Ideal of Man and Society . , 101 Christianity and the Family 103 Christianity and the State 104 Christianity and Liberty 104 Christianity and International Relations 107 Christianity and Charity . , 108 Christianity and Social Reform 113 CHAPTER VI The Evidence op the Divine Origin op Christianity prom its Ethical and Religious Teaching and from the Comparison of it with the Greek Philosophy Through Christianity the Kingdom of God made Universal . . 115 Seeds of Truth in the Teaching of Jesus , 116 In his Teaching Religion and Morality Inseparable .... 116 Christian Precepts not merely Negative 117 In the Gospel Particular Obligations not Undervalued . . .117 Active as well as Passive Virtues enjoined 118 Christianity distinctively a Religion 119 The Greek Philosophy as an Intellectual Achievement . . . 119 The Greek Philosophy a Preparation for the Gospel .... 120 Socrates and his Teachings compared with the Gospel . . . 120 Plato and his Doctrines compared with the Gospel .... 122 Aristotle and his Doctrines compared with the Gospel . . . 126 Greek Systems become Practical 128 The Theology and Ethics of Epicurus 129 The Characteristic Principles of Stoicism 129 XIV CONTENTS The Special Character of Roman Stoicism The Teaching of Seneca and its Sources . Stoic Teachings compared with Christianity New Platonism : Philosophy lapses into Pantheism The Actual Aids of Philosophy Insufficient Its Imperfect Conception of God CHAPTER VII The Consciousness in Jesus of a Supernatural Calling rendered Credible by his Sinless Character The Facts of the Gospel indirectly verified The Credibility of the Testimony of Jesus respecting himself The Alternatives of Credence Untenable .... Summary of this Testimony of Jesus .... Proof of the Sanity and Sobriety of Jesus No Credulity then to warrant Disbelief now Words and Actions of Jesus consonant with his Claims The Sinless Character of Jesus insures Self-knowledge The Character of Jesus tried by Temptation His Sinlessness Plain to his Enemies . Unison of Virtues in his Character . His Freedom from Self-accusation . Moral Criticism of his Character Baseless . His Character tested by his Experience . The Direct Probative Weight of his Sinlessness CHAPTER VlH Mieacles : Their Nature, Credibility, and Place in Christian Evidences Revelation in Nature and Providence presupposed in Christianity Consistency of the Two Revelations . The Gospel not an Afterthought of the Creator The Purpose of the Christian Miracles The Untheistic Conception of Nature The Relation of Miracles to the Constancy of Nature The Credibility of Miracles : Hume's Objection Huxley's Criticism of Hume .... Criticism of Huxley's Position .... The "Order of Nature " not disturbed by a Miracle . Nature of the Miracle-working Power of Jesus . Precedence in the Proofs of Christianity belongs not to Miracles Value of the Proof from Miracles CONTENTS XV CHAPTER IX Proof of the Miracles op Cueist independently of Speci Inquiry into the Authorship of the Gospels Miracles professed to be wrought by the Apostles The Injunctions of Jesus not to report Miracles Cautions against an Excessive Esteem of Miracles Teachings of Jesus Inseparable from Miracles . Not True that Miracles then excited no Surprise No Miracles said to be wrought by Jesus prior to his Ministry The Persistence of the Apostles' Faith an Evidence of Miracles Miracles inwoven with the Nexus of Occurrences Evidence of the Fact of the Resurrection of Jesus Criticism of the " Vision Theory " . The Criteria of Hallucination Absent Keim's Denial of the Vision Theory . Keim's Admission of a miraculous Self-manifestation of Jesus The Naturalistic Theory of the Miracles Obsolete Strauss's Contempt for this Theory . Strauss's Mythical Theory .... Renan's Imputation of Conscious Deceit . Christian Evidences not Demonstrative : to be taken Collectively \l PAGE 178180182183188 189 189 190 102194196 107 100100 200 200 201 203 CHAPTER X The Gospels an Authentic Record of the Testimony given by the Apostles Authorship and Date of the Gospels : Why so Important Record of Miracles not a Ground for Distrust . Special Proofs of the Genuineness of the Gospels Authority of the Four acknowledged in the Churches But not dictated by Any Organization Testimony of Irenseus .... Tertulhan, Clement .of Alexandria, Muratorian Representative Character of Individuals . Value of Testimony of Irenseus Objections to the Witness of Irenaeus answered Justin Martyr : his Memoirs Outlines of his References to the Gospels . Why he quotes mainly from the Synoptics Few References in J. without Parallelisms in the Gospels His Memoirs substantially Coincident with the Gospels His Quotations not exceptionally Inexact . His Memoirs specially refer to the Four . Canon 204 204204 205205 205206 207 207 200 211 212214 215 217219220 XVi CONTENTS PAGE Tatian's Diatesseron 222 The Non-canonical Writings held in Honor 222 Apocryphal Gospels 223 The Gnostics had no Competitors with the Four . . . .224 Celsus an Indirect Witness for the Four 226 Papias : his Testimony 22" The Logia of Matthew 228 Marcion acknowledged the Four 229 The Prologue of the Third Gospel 230 Internal Evidence in the First Three Gospels 231 The Prophetic Discourse of Jesus 232 Other Water-marks of Age 233 The Mutual Relation of the Synoptics 234 The Integrity of the Gospels 235 The Credibility and Lukan Authorship of the Acts .... 237 Comparison of the Earlier and the Later Chapters . . . .238 The " Speaking with Tongues " 239 The Speeches in Acts 240 The Apostolic Conference, Acts xv. , compared with Gal. ii. . . 241 Paul's Rebuke of Peter 242 Decisive Proof the Verity of Acts xv 243 CHAPTER XI The Authorship op the Fourth Gospel Unlikeness of the Fourth Gospel to the Synoptics .... 245 Usual Belief respecting the Apostle John 245 The Apostolic Authorship until recently Virtually undisputed . . 246 The Tubingen School : The Theory of Baur 247 A much Earlier Date of the Gospel at Present granted . . . 249 Early References to Ancient Classics often Scanty .... 250 Evidence offered by Parties outside of the Church .... 253 Hypothesis that the Apostle was confounded with "the Presbyter " 254 Did Irenseus misunderstand Polycarp ? 254 What is known of the " Presbyter John " ? 257 Theory of a Confusion of Names Improbable 258 The Asian Residence and Influence of the Apostle .... 258 Testimony of the Gospel, ch. xxi 262 The Alogi 263 Hypothesis that Disciples of John wrote the Gospel .... 265 The Hypothesis of a Composite Authorship : Wendt . . .266 The Unity of Authorship Evident 268 Partition Theories excluded by John xxi. 24 269 Internal Evidences 270 CONTENTS xvii PAGE The Author a Palestinian Hebrew 270 The Author's Name not mentioned 271 The Author an Eye-witness 271 The Gospel virtually an Autobiography 274 The Author's Personal Love to Jesus 275 The Author's References to " The Jews " 275 Bearing of Other N. T. Documents on the Question .... 277 The Apocalypse and the Fourth Gospel 277 Frequency of Wrong Inferences from Diversity of Style . . . 278 Theory of Allegorical Facts Untenable 279 Examples of Historical Reminiscences in the Gospel . . . 280 Renan' s Citations of the Same Character 281 Critical Objections based on Misinterpretation 282 The Author's Estimate of Miracles 283 Theological Aspect of the Gospel 283 The Gospel and Alexandrian Judaism 284 Comparison of the " Logos " Doctrine in John and in Philo . . 284 Observations of Harnack on this Topic 285 Observations of Loofs on the Topic 286 John and the Synoptics 289 Frequent Misconception of the Design and Character of the Synoptics 289 A Certain Subjective (not Fictitious) Element in John . . . 290 The Duration of the Ministry of Jesus 291 The Cleansing of the Temple 292 The Date of the Crucifixion 292 The Doings and Sayings of John the Baptist 294 The Message of the Baptist to Jesus ... ... 297 Import of the Conversation at Csesarea-Philippi .... 298 The Method of Jesus in disclosing his Messiahship .... 300 The Discourses of Jesus in the Fourth Gospel 301 Mistaken Objections from their Character . . . . . 301 The Theology of the Synoptics and John not essentially Different . 304 The Character of Ancient Pseudonymous Writings .... 306 The Theory of a Close Relation of the Evangelist to the Apostle . 307 The View of Weizsacker 307 The View of Harnack 308 The Choice between Two Hypotheses 309 CHAPTER XII The Trustworthiness of the Apostles' Testimony as pre sented by the Evangelists Not a Question respecting Inspiration . . ... 310 The Choice of the Apostles : Their Function 310 xvm CONTENTS The Apostles consciously called to be Witnesses The Apostles always consciously Disciples Frankly relate Instances of their own Ignorance and Weakness Relate their Mistakes and the Reproofs of Jesus Relate their Serious Delinquencies Narrate Instances of Sinless Infirmity in Jesus Submit to Extreme Suffering and Death .... The Suspicion of Dishonesty in the Apostles Absurd To impute to them Self-delusion is Unreasonable Their Testimony not shaken by the Narration of Miracles Answer of Bishop Butler to Sceptics on this Subject The Accounts of the Birth and Early Life of Jesus . The Gospels not moulded by a Doctrinal Bias . The Mythical Theory not Less Untenable PAGE 312 313 313 315315 316 317318318319319 319 320321 CHAPTER XIH The Relation op the Christian Faith to the Bible and to Biblical Criticism Does Critical Science imperil the Foundations of Christianity ? . 322 The Bible the Source of Christian Knowledge 322 Its Life-giving Power 322 Special Problems and Distinctions respecting the Bible . . . 323 Origin of Rigid Maxims on Biblical Inerrancy 323 Distinction between the Bible and Christianity .... 324 Revelation in and through a Process of Redemption . . . 324 Revelation Historical in the Ancient and the N. T. Periods . . 325 Persons and Transactions in Revelation prior to the Scriptures . 327 The Occasion of the N. T. Writings 327 Composed to meet the Wants of the Churches 328 The Kingdom of God the Fundamental Reality .... 328 The Religious Consciousness of the Hebrew People .... 329 The End of the Kingdom the Transformation of Human Society . 331 The Rise of a Spiritual and Universal Community .... 332 Illustration from Secular Life and History 332 Obscurity as to the Beginnings of Old Kingdoms . . . .334 No Formulas as to the Scriptures in the Ancient Creeds . . . 335 Literary Questions as to the Scriptures 335 Organic Connection of Christianity with the 0. T. Religion . . 336 Open Historical Questions in O. T. Annals 336 Questions as to the Rise and Successive Eras of the 0. T. Religion . 337 Moses the Founder of Hebrew Legislation 338 Critical Investigation Consistent with Christian Belief . . .840 CONTENTS XIX The Authority of Jesus and of the Apostles Butler against dogmatizing on the Authority of Scripture The Apostles' Insight into the Gospel Progressive . The Order of Things to be believed PAGE 342 342342342 CHAPTER XIV The Gradualness op Revelation The Declaration of Jesus to this Effect Progress of Interpretation not Continuance of Revelation The Process of Historic Revelation in its Contents The Epochs of Law and of Grace Progress in the Conception of God . Progress in the Doctrine of Divine Providence . Gradual Unfolding of the Mercifulness of God . The Lesson from Jonah : The Prediction of Micah The Problem of Suffering The Discussions in Job The Reflections in Ecclesiastes .... Light in the Gospel on the Problem of Suffering The Gradual Revelation of Immortality . Gradual Exposition of the Nature of Sacrifice . Progress in the Messianic Conception Progressive Advance of Ethics in Revealed Religion Gradual Enthronement of the Law of Love Imprecations in the Old Testament . Accommodation in Law to Ages of Ignorance . Progress in the N. T. Revelation The Promise of Light through the Spirit . The Progress of the Apostles in Enlightenment Authority only Predicable of the Bible as a Whole 344345345 347348 350352353353354 355 356 357359 360 361302363364 365368369 369 CHAPTER XV The Relation of Christianity to Other Religions Classification of Religions 371 Christian View of Ethnic Religions 371 Christianity the Absolute Religion 372 Revelation the Self-revelation of God 372 In Christianity Alone a Full View of the Perfection of God . . 373 Polytheism and Monotheism 373 Mohammedanism 3/5 The Religion of India 376 XX CONTENTS PAGE Brahmanism Pantheistic 377 Buddha and Buddhism 377 The Merits of Buddha and Buddhism 379 Buddha in what Sense a Pessimist 380 Neither a Personal God nor Immortality Parts of his Teaching . 380 The Degeneration of Buddhism 381 Alleged Parallelisms between Hindoo Religions and Christianity . 381 Fitness of Christianity to be the Religion of Mankind . . .383 The Religion of the Old Testament and of the New, a Divine Revela tion 383 NoteNote NoteNoteNoteNote Note 1 (p. 23). 2 (p. 49). 3 (p. 50). 4 (p. 56). 5 (p. 66). 6 (p. 82). 7 (p. 83). Note 8 (p. 86). Note 9 (p. 93). Note 10 (p. 167). Note 11 (p. 172). Note 12 (p. 231). Note 13 (p. 252). Note 14 (p. 254). Note 15 (p. 269). Note 16 (p. 272). Note 17 (p. 280). Note 18 (p. 289). Note 19 (p. 305). Note 20 (p. 320). Note 21 (p. 203). Note 22 (p. 343). Note 23 (p. 343). APPENDIX Further Discussion of the Origin of Religion . 387 Other Statements of Huxley on Teleology . . 394 Other Statements of Darwin on Design in Nature 396 Further Remarks on the Problem of Evil . . 397 Professor Fraser on the Spread of Pantheism . 398 Spencer's Modification of Views on Correlation 399 Science the Discovery of the Principles and Laws of Nature 399 Matthew Arnold's Conception of God . . . 401 Possible Force of Self-accusation . . . 403 The Trend of Philosophy toward Objective Idealism 404 The Philosophical Opinions of Huxley . . 406 Unity of Authorship of the Acts . . . 408 Resch on the Authorship of the Fourth Gospel . 410 Neander on the Johannine Authorship of the Fourth Gospel 410 Haupt on Dislocations in the Fourth Gospel . 411 The Designation " Disciple whom Jesus loved " 412 Striking Reminiscence in the Fourth Gospel . 412 Professor Thayer on the Apostolic Authorship of the Fourth Gospel 412 Weizsacker and Thayer on the Divinity of Christ in the Gospels 412 The Subject of Discrepancies in the Gospels . 413 Heathen and Ecclesiastical Miracles . . . 421 The Relation of Biblical Teaching to Natural Science 435 The Relation of Biblical Criticism to Prophecy . 447 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF k_.\u>s, etftr], \lyei,, 6 "Zippta, • kcu iyd> re croi ipa> o airopu>, Kai av o8e, y ovk diroS-xeTai ra dprjpiva. ipol yap Sokei, u> So-icpaTes, we/o* tuiv toiovtiov lo-io, wo-irep Kal aol to piv cradtt, elSevat. iv ra vvv fiuo i) aSvvarov cfaai rj tray-^aXeiTOV ti, to p,evTOi av to, \eyopeva irepi airlov py oi)(i. iravrl Tpomo ik£yy(€iv koX p,rj irpoa " TavTa aovvarov, tov yovv {.cXtio-tov tuiv avdpumivuiv \6yu>v Xa(36vra Kal Sva-e^ekeyKToraTov, liii tovtov oyovpevov cbo-irep iirl o^eS-as KivSwevovra oiairXeuo-ai tov piov, el pr/ tis BvvaiTO dcr<^a/Veo"T€pov Kal aKivSvvorepov iirl (3cf3aiorepov oyripa- to,, koyov Oeiov twos, 8iairop£v6rjvai. Kal Bi] Kal vvv lycoyc ovk iirai- ayyvO-qo-opm epio-Oai, ore-Siy Kal crv Tavra Xeya,, 0110 ipjxvrbv aiTUWopai iv vo-Tepm \j>6vm or. vvv ovk cTttov a ipol Sokc.. Plato, Phcedo, 85 [the topic being ' The Concerns of the Soul.'] " Very good, Socrates," said Simmias ; " then I will tell you my dif ficulty, and Cebes will tell you his. I feel myself (and I daresay that you have the same feeling) how hard or rather impossible is the attain ment of any certainty about questions such as these in the present life. And yet I should deem him a coward who did not prove what is said about them to the uttermost, or whose heart failed him before he had examined them on every side. For he should persevere until he has achieved one of two things : either he should discover, or be taught, the truth about them ; or, if this be impossible, I would have him take the best and most irrefragable of human theories, and let this be the raft upon which he sails through life — not without risk, as I admit, if he cannot find some word of God which will more surely and safely carry him. And now, as you bid me, I will venture to question you, and then I shall not have to reproach myself hereafter with not having said at the time what I think. For when I consider the matter, either alone or with Cebes, the argument does certainly appear to me, Socrates, to be not sufficient." — From the Version of Jowett, ed. S. " The only question concerning the truth of Christianity is, whether it be a real revelation, not whether it be attended with every circumstance which we should have looked for ; and concerning the authority of Scrip ture, whether it be what it claims to be, not whether it be a book of such sort, and so promulgated as weak men are apt to fancy a book containing divine revelation should. And therefore neither obscurity, nor seeming inaccuracy of style, nor various readings, nor early disputes about the authors of particular parts, nor any other things of the like kind, though they had been much more considerable in degree than they are, could overthrow the authority of Scripture ; unless the prophets, or apostles, or our Lord, had promised that the book containing the divine revelation should be secure from these things. " — Bishop Butler, Analogy, Part II. chap. iii. THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF CHAPTER I THE PERSONALITY OF GOD AND OF MAN : THE SELF-REVELATION OF GOD IN THE HUMAN SOUL Theism signifies not only that there is a ground or cause of all things, — so much every one who makes an attempt to account for himself and for the world around him admits, — but also that the Cause of all things thus presupposed is a personal Being, of whom an image is presented in the human mind. This image falls short of being adequate, only as it involves limits, — limits, how ever, which cleave not to intelligence in itself, but simply to intel ligence in its finite form. Belief in the personality of man, and belief in the personality of God, stand or fall together. A glance at the history of religion would suggest that these two beliefs are for some reason insepa rable. Where faith in the personality of God is weak, or is altogether wanting, as in the case of the pantheistic religions of the East, the perception which men have of their own personality is found to be in an equal degree indistinct. The feeling of individuality is dor mant. The soul indolently ascribes to itself a merely phenomenal being. It conceives of itself as appearing for a moment, like a wavelet on the ocean, to vanish again in the all-ingulfing essence whence it emerged. Philosophical theories which substitute mat ter, or an impersonal Idea, or an " Unknowable," for the self- conscious Deity, likewise dissipate the personality of man as ordi narily conceived. If they disown the tenet that God is a Spirit, they decline with equal emphasis to affirm that man is a spirit. The pantheistic and atheistic schemes are in this respect con sistent in their logic. Out of man's perception of his own per sonal attributes arises the belief in a personal God. On this fact 2 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF of our own personality the validity of the evidence for theism is conditioned. The essential characteristics of personality are self-consciousness and self-determination ; that is to say, these are the elements com mon to all spiritual beings. Perception, whether its object be material or mental, involves a perceiving subject. The " cogito ergo sum " of Descartes is not properly an argument. I do not deduce my existence from the fact of my putting forth an act of thought. The Cartesian maxim simply denotes that in the act the agent is of necessity brought to light, or disclosed to himself. He becomes cognizant of himself in the fluctuating states of thought, feeling, and volition. This apprehension of self is intuitive. It is conditioned on experience. It is not a possession of infancy. Yet it is not an idea of self that emerges, not a bare phenomenon, as some philosophers have imagined ; but the ego is immediately pre sented, and there is an inexpugnable conviction of its reality. Idealism, or the doctrine that sense-perception is a modification of the mind that is due exclusively to its own nature, and is elicited by nothing exterior to itself, is, if anything, less repugnant to reason than is the denial of the reality of the ego. Whatever may be true of external things, of self we have an intuitive knowledge. If I judge that there is no real table before me on which I seem to be writing, and no corporeal organs for seeing or touching it, I never theless cannot escape the conviction that it is /who thus judge. To talk of thought without a thinker, of belief without a believer, is to utter words void of meaning. The indivisible unity and permanent identity of the ego are necessarily involved in self-con sciousness. I know myself as a single, separate entity. Personal identity is presupposed in every act of memory. Go back as far as recollection can carry us, it is the same self who was the subject of all the mental experiences which memory can recall. When I was a child I spake as a child, I understood as a child, I thought as a child ; but I who utter these words am the same being that I was a score or threescore years ago. I look forward to the future, and know that to me, and not to another, the consequences of my actions are directly chargeable. In the endless succession of thoughts, feelings, choices, in all the mutations of opinion and of character, the identity of the ego abides. From the dawn of con sciousness, as soon as recollection is awake, to my last breath, I do not part with myself. The abnormal experience, in certain cases, THE PERSONALITY OF GOD AND OF MAN 3 of double consciousness no more disproves this truth than occa sional instances of hallucination belie the fact of sense-perception. " If we speak of the mind as a series of feelings which is aware of itself as past and future, we are reduced to the alternative of believ ing that the mind, or ego, is something different from any series of feelings, or of accepting the paradox that something which is ex hypothesi but a series of feelings can be aware of itself as a series." So writes John Stuart Mill. Yet, on the basis of this astounding assumption that a series can be self-conscious, Mill' was minded to frame his philosophy, and was only deterred by the confessed insurmountable difficulty of supposing memory with no being capable of remembering. The second constituent element of personality is self-determi nation. This act is likewise essential to distinct self-conscious ness. Were there no exercise of will, were the mind wholly passive under all impressions from without, the clear conscious ness of self would never be evoked. In truth, self in that case would have only an inchoate being.1 " It is in the will, in purpo sive action, and particularly in our moral activity, as Fichte, to my mind, conclusively demonstrated, that we lay hold upon real ity. All that we know might be but a dream-procession of shadows, and the mind of the dreamer no more than the still mir ror in which they are reflected, if, indeed, it were anything but the shifting shadows themselves. But in the purposive ' I will,' each man is real, and is immediately conscious of his own reality. Whatever else may or may not be real, this is real. This is the fundamental belief, around which scepticism may weave its maze of doubts and logical puzzles, but from which it is eventually powerless to dislodge us, because no argument can affect an im mediate certainty, — a certainty, moreover, on which our whole view of the universe depends." 2 That I originate my voluntary actions in the sense that they are not the effect or unavoidable consequence of antecedents, whether in the mind or out of it, is a fact of consciousness. This is what is meant by the freedom of the will. It is a definition of " choice." Thoughts spring up in 1 The view of self-consciousness in the foregoing remarks is quite contrary to the view, if taken in the proper sense of the terms, that " individuals may be included in other individuals " and that there is " a genuine identity of Being in various individuals." 2 A. Seth, Two Lectures on Theism, p. 46. 4 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF the mind, and succeed one another under laws of association whose absolute control is limited only by the power we have of concentrating attention on one object or another within the hori zon of consciousness. Desires reaching out to various forms of good spring up unbidden. They, too, are subject to regulation through no power inherent in themselves. But self-determina tion, as the very term signifies, is attended with an irresistible conviction that the direction of the will is self-imparted. We leave out of account here the nature of habit, or the tendency of choice once made or often repeated to perpetuate itself. That a moral bondage may ensue from an abuse of liberty is conceded. The mode and degree in which habit affects freedom is an im portant topic ; but it is one which we do not need to consider in this place.1 That the will is free — that is, both exempt from constraint by causes exterior, which is fatalism, and not a mere spontaneity, shut up to one path by a force acting from within, which is determinism — is immediately evident to every unsophis ticated mind. We can initiate action by the exercise of an agency which is neither irresistibly controlled by motives, nor determined, without any capacity of alternative action, by a prone- ness inherent in its nature. No truth is more definitely or abun dantly sanctioned by the common sense of mankind. Those who in theory reject it, continually assert it in practice. The lan guages of men would have to be reconstructed, the business of the world would come to a standstill, if the denial of the freedom of the will were to be carried out with rigorous consistency. This freedom is not only attested in consciousness ; it is evinced by that ability to resist inducements brought to bear on the mind which we are conscious of exerting. We can withstand tempta tion to wrong by the exertion of an energy which consciously emanates from ourselves, and which we know that, the circum stances remaining the same, we could abstain from exerting. If motives have an influence, that influence is not tantamount to deterministic efficiency. Praise and blame, and the punishments and rewards, of whatever kind, which imply these judgments, are 1 Plainly, circumstances, including prior courses of conduct, may render a particular direction of choice more, or less, difficult. " There is a growth in moral freedom" (Ladd, Philosophy of Conduct, p. 138). But the difficulty thus arising is not of a kind or degree to destroy the capacity of freely deter mining the action of the will. THE PERSONALITY OF GOD AND OF MAN 5 plainly irrational, save on the tacit assumption of the autonomy of self. Deny free-will, and remorse, as well as self- approbation, is deprived of an essential ingredient. It is then impossible to dis tinguish remorse from regret. Ill-desert becomes a fiction. This is not to argue against the necessitarian doctrine, merely on the ground of its bad tendencies. It is true that the debasement of the individual, and the wreck of social order, would follow upon the unflinching adoption of the necessitarian theory in the judg ments and conduct of men. Virtue would no more be thought to deserve love ; crime would no longer be felt to deserve hatred. But independently of this aspect of the subject, there is, to say the very least, a strong presumption against the truth of a theorem in philosophy that clashes with the common sense and moral sen timents of the race. The awe-inspiring sense of individual respon sibility, the sting of remorse, the shame of detected sin, emotions of moral reprobation and moral approval, ought not to be treated as illusive, unless they can be demonstrated to be so. Here are phenomena which no metaphysical scheme can afford to ignore. Surely no theory can ever look for general acceptance which is obliged to eviscerate or explain away these familiar facts and leave an irreconcilable conflict in human nature. How shall the feeling that we are free be accounted for if it be contrary to the fact ? Let us glance at what famous necessita rians have to say in answer to this inquiry. First, let us hear one of the foremost representatives of this school. His solution is one that has often been repeated. " Men believe themselves to be free," says Spinoza, "entirely from this, that, though con scious of their acts, they are ignorant of the causes by which their acts are determined. The idea of freedom, therefore, comes of men not knowing the cause of their acts." * This is a bare asser tion, confidently made, but void of proof. It surely is not a self- evident truth that our belief in freedom arises in this manner. Further, when we make the motives preceding any particular act of choice the object of deliberate scrutiny, the sense of freedom is not in the least weakened. The motives are distinctly seen, yet the consciousness of liberty, or of a pluripotential power, remains in full vigor. Moreover, choice is not the resultant of motives, as in a case of the composition of forces. One motive is followed, and its rival rejected. Hume has another explanation of what he con- 1 Ethics, P. ii. prop. xxxv. 6 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF siders the delusive feeling of freedom. " Our idea," he says, " of necessity and causation arises entirely from the uniformity observ able in the operations of nature, where similar objects are con stantly conjoined together, and the mind is determined by custom to infer the one from the appearance of the other." * This con stant conjunction of things is all that we know; but men have "a strong propensity " to believe in " something like a necessary con nection " between the antecedent and the consequent. " When, again, they turn their reflections towards the operations of their own minds, and fee? no such connection of the motive and the action, they are thence apt to suppose that there is a difference between the effects which result from material force, and those which arise from thought and intelligence." 2 In other words, a double delusion is asserted. First, the mind, for some unex plained reason, falsely imagines a tie between the material antece dent and consequent, and then, missing such a bond between motive and choice, it rashly infers freedom. So far from this being a true representation, it is the mind's conscious exertion of energy that enables it even to conceive of a causal relation between things external. Hume's solution depends on the theory that nothing properly called power exists. It is assumed that there is no power, either in motives or in the will. Hume's neces sity, unlike that of Spinoza, is mere uniformity of succession, choice following motive with regularity, but with no nexus between the two. J. S. Mill, adopting an identical theory of causation, from which power is eliminated, lands in the same general conclu sion, on this question of free-will, as that reached by Hume. Herbert Spencer holds that the fact " that every one is at liberty to do what he desires to do (supposing there are no external hindrances)" is the sum of our liberty. He states that "the dogma of free-will" is the proposition " that every one is at liberty to desire or not to desire." That is, he confounds choice and volition with desire, denies the existence of an elective power distinct from the desires, and imputes a definition of free-will to the advocates of freedom which they unanimously repudiate. As to the feeling of freedom, Mr. Spencer says, "The illusion con- 1 An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, P. i. § 8 {Essays, ed. Green and Grose, vol. ii. p. 67). * Ibid., -p. 75. THE PERSONALITY OF GOD AND OF MAN 7 sists in supposing that at each moment the ego ... is something more than the aggregate of feelings and ideas, actual and nascent, which then exists." 1 When a man says that he determined to perform a certain action, his error is in supposing his conscious self to have been " something separate from the group of psy chical states " constituting his " psychical self." " Will is nothing but the general name given to the special feeling or feelings which for a moment prevail over others." 2 The " composite psychical state which excites the action is at the same time the ego which is said to will the action." The soul is resolved into a group of psychical states due to " motor changes " excited by an impres sion received from without. If there is no personal agent, if / is a collective noun, meaning a " group " of sensations, it is a waste of time to argue that there is no freedom. " What we call a mind," wrote Hume long ago, " is nothing but a heap or collec tion of different perceptions, united together by certain relations, and supposed, though falsely, to be endowed with a perfect sim plicity and identity." Professor Huxley, who quotes this passage, would make no other correction than to substitute an assertion of nescience for the positive denial. He would rather say, " that we know nothing more of the mind than that it is a series of percep tions."8 Before commenting on this definition of the mind, which robs it of its unity, it is worth while to notice what account the advocates of necessity have to give of the feelings of praise and blame, ten ants of the soul which appear to claim a right to be there, and which it is very hard even for speculative philosophers to dislodge. On this topic Spinoza is remarkably chary of explanation. " I designate as gratitude" he says, "the feeling we experience from the acting of another, done, as we imagine, to gratify us ; and aversion, the uneasy sense we experience when we imagine 1 Principles of Psychology, vol. i. p. 500. 2 Ibid., p. 503. It is sometimes said that " Hamlet is left out of the play," but this is seldom done, as in this instance, by an explicit avowal. It recalls the lines of Goethe : — " Wer will was Lebendigs erkennen und beschreiben, Sucht erst den Geist herauszutreiben, Dann hat er die Theile in seiner Hand, Fehlt, leider ! nur das geistige Band." 8 Huxley's Hume, with Helps to the Study of Berkeley, p. 75 ; also Collected Essays, vol. vi. 8 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF anything done with a view to our disadvantage; and, whilst we praise the former, we are disposed to blame the latter." * What does Spinoza mean by the phrase " with a view to our advantage " or "disadvantage"? As the acts done, in either case, were unavoidable on the part of the doer, — as much so as the circula tion of blood in his veins, — it is impossible to see any reasonable ness in praise or blame, thankfulness or resentment. Why should we resent the stab of an assassin more than the kick of a horse ? Why should we be any more grateful to a benefactor than we are to the sun for shining on us ? If the sun were conscious of shin ing on us, and of shining on us "with a view" to warm us, in Spinoza's meaning ofthe phrase, but with not the least power to do otherwise, how would that consciousness found a claim to our gratitude? What we are looking for is a ground of approbation or condemnation. When Spinoza proceeds to define " just " and "unjust," "sin" and "merit," he broaches a theory not dissimilar to that of Hobbes, that there is no natural law but the desires, that " in the state of nature there is nothing done that can properly be characterized as just or unjust," that in " the natural state," prior to the organization of society, " faults, offences, crimes, cannot be conceived." 2 As for repentance, Spinoza does not hesitate to lay down the thesis that " repentance is not a virtue, or does not arise from reason ; but he who repents of any deed he has done is twice miserable or impotent." s Penitence is defined as " sorrow accompanying the idea of something we believe we have done of free-will." * It mainly depends, he tells us, on education. Since free-will is an illusive notion, penitence must be inferred to be in the same degree irrational. To these opinions, not less superficial than they are immoral, the ablest advocates of necessity are driven when they stand face to face with the phenomena of conscience. Mill, in seeking to vindicate the consistency of punishment with his doctrine of determinism, maintains that it is right to punish ; first, as penalty tends to restrain and cure an evil-doer, and sec ondly, as it tends to secure society from aggression. " It is just to punish," he says, " so far as it is necessary for this purpose," for the security of society, " exactly as it is just to put a wild beast to death (without unnecessary suffering) for the same object."5 1 Ethics, P. iii. prop. xxix. schol. 2 Ibid., P. iv. prop, xxxvii. schol. 2. 8 Ibid., P. iv. prop. liv. * Ibid., P. iii. def. 27. 6 Examination of Sir W. Hamilton's Philosophy, vol. ii. p. 292. THE PERSONALITY OF GOD AND OF MAN 9 It will hardly be asserted by any one that a brute deserves punish ment, in the proper and accepted meaning of the term. Surely to behead a man requires a defence different in kind from that required to crush a mosquito. Later, Mill attempts to find a basis for a true responsibility ; but in doing so he virtually, though un wittingly, surrenders his necessitarian theory. " The true doctrine of the causation of human actions maintains," he says, " that not only our conduct, but our character, is in part amenable to our will ; that we can, by employing the proper means, improve our character ; and that if our character is such, that, while it remains what it is, it necessitates us to do wrong, it will be just to apply motives which will necessitate us to strive for its improvement, and to emancipate ourselves from the other necessity." 1 Here, while verbally holding to his theory of the deterministic agency of motives, he introduces the phrases which I have put in italics, — phrases which carry in them the idea of free personal endeavor, and exclude that of determinism. " The true doctrine of neces sity," says Mill, "while maintaining that our character is formed by our circumstances, asserts at the same time that our desires can do much to alter our circumstances." But how about our control over our desires ? Have we any more control, direct or indirect, over them than over our circumstances ? If not, " the true doctrine of necessity " no more founds responsibility than does the naked fatalism which Mill disavows. It is not uncom mon for necessitarian writers, unconsciously it may be, to draw a veil over their theory by affirming that actions are the necessary fruit of a character already formed ; thus leaving room for the supposition, that, in the forming of that character, the will exerted at some time an independent agency. But such an agency, it need not be said, at whatever point it is placed, is incompatible with their main doctrine. The standing argument for necessity, drawn out by Hobbes, Collins, et id omne genus, is based on the law of cause and effect. It is alleged, that if motives are not efficient in determining the will, then an event — namely, the particular direction of the will in a case of choice, or the choice of one object rather than an other — is without a cause. This has been supposed to be an invincible argument. In truth, however, the event in question is not without a cause in the sense that would be true of an event 1 Ibid., vol. ii. p. 299. IO THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF wholly disconnected from an efficient antecedent, — of a world, for example, springing into being without a Creator. The mind is endued with the power to act in either of two directions, the proper circumstances being present ; and, whichever way it may actually move, its motion is its own, the result of its own power. That the mind is not subject to the law of causation which holds good elsewhere than in the sphere of intelligent, voluntary action, is the very thing asserted. Self-activity, initial motion, is the dis tinctive attribute of spiritual agents. The prime error of the necessitarian is in unwarrantably assuming that the mind in its voluntary action is subject to the same law which prevails in the realm of things material and unintelligent. This opinion is not only false, but shallow. For where do we first get our notion of power or causal energy? Where but from the exercise of our own wills ? If we exerted no voluntary agency, we should have no idea of causal efficiency. Being outside of the circle of our experience, causation would be utterly unknown. Necessitarians, in the ranks of whom are found at the present day not a few students of physical science, frequently restrict their observa tion to things without themselves, and, having formulated a law of causation for the objects with which they are chiefly conversant, they forthwith extend it over the mind, — an entity, despite its close connection with matter, toto genere different. They should re member that the very terms " force," " power," " energy," " cause," are only intelligible from the experience we have of the exercise of will. They are applied in some modified sense to things ex ternal. But we are immediately cognizant of no cause but will, and the nature of that cause must be learned from consciousness ; it can never be learned from an inspection of things heterogene ous to the mind, and incapable by themselves of imparting to it the faintest notion of power. It is sometimes said that the doctrine of the liberty of the will is self-destructive. The will, it is said, is reduced to a blind power, dissevered from intelligence and freedom. But " freedom of the will " is a phrase which means " freedom of self," freedom of the mind, an indivisible unit — which includes intelligence and sen sibility, yet is enslaved to neither. But it is complained that if the operations of the will are not governed by law, psychologic science is impossible. " Psychical changes," says Herbert Spencer, " either conform to law, or they THE PERSONALITY OF GOD AND OF MAN n do not. If they do not conform to law, this work, in common with all works on the subject, is sheer nonsense ; no science of psychology is possible. If they do conform to law, there cannot be any such thing as free-will."1 Were uniformity found, as a matter of fact, to characterize the self-determinations of the mind, even then necessity would not be proved. Suppose the mind always to determine itself in strict conformity with reason ; this would not prove constraint, or disprove freedom. If it were shown, that, as a matter of fact, the mind always chooses in the same way, the antecedents being precisely the same, neither fatal ism nor determinism would be thereby demonstrated. If it be meant, by the conformity of the will to law, that no man has the power to choose otherwise than he actually chooses ; that, to take an example from moral conduct, no thief, or seducer, or assassin, was capable of any such previous exercise of will as would have caused him to abstain from the crimes which he has perpe trated, — then every reasonable, not to say righteous, person will deny the proposition. The alternative that a work on psychology, so far as it rests on a theory of fatalism, is " sheer nonsense," it is far better to endure than to fly in the face of common sense and of the conscience of the race. But psychology has left to it a wide enough field without the need of denying room for moral liberty. A book of ethics which is constructed on the assumption that the free and responsible nature of man is an illusive notion is worth no more than the postulate on which it is founded.2 Besides the argument against freedom from the alleged incon sistency with the law of causation which it involves, there is a sec ond objection which is frequently urged. We are reminded that 1 Psychology, vol. i. p. 621. This passage is not in the 4th ed. See vol. ii. p. 503. The doctrine remains the same. " That the ego is the passing group of feelings and ideas, ... is true if we include the body and its functions," p. 503. The action is determined by a "certain composite mass of emotion and thought," p. 501. 2 Of course, Spencer is not alone in these pleas for determinism. For ex ample, Wundt, who holds to the absolute sway of causality, "psychical causality," in the specification of choice, complains that without it there can be "no psychology, no science of mind" {The Principles of Morality, etc., P- S3)- Wundt, like Mill, is anxious to remind his readers that " motives are effects as well as causes," and that one's " whole previous history " lies back of any particular choice (pp. 10, 38). But, as with Mill, in these prior choices, of which character is the result, no real freedom of self is presupposed. 12 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF there is an order of history. Events, we are told, within the sphere of voluntary agency succeed each other with regularity of sequence. We can predict what individuals will do with a considerable degree of confidence, — with as much confidence as could be expected considering the complexity of the phenomena. There is a prog ress of a community and of mankind which evinces a reign of law within the compass of personal action. The conduct of one gen eration is shaped by the conduct of that which precedes it. That there is a plan in the course of human affairs, all believers in Providence hold. History does not present a chaotic series of occurrences, but a system, a progressive order, to be more or less clearly discerned. The inference, however, that the wills of men are destitute of self-activity, is rashly drawn. If it were thought that we are confronted with two apparently antagonistic truths, whose point of reconciliation is beyond our ken, the situation would have its parallels in other branches of human inquiry. We should be justified in holding to each truth on its own grounds, each being sufficiently verified, and in waiting for the solution of the problem. But the whole objection can be shown to rest, in great part, on misunderstanding of the doctrine of free-will. Free dom does not involve, of necessity, a haphazard departure from regularity in the actual choices of men under the same circum stances. As already remarked, that men do act in one way, in the presence of given circumstances, does not prove that they must so act. Again, those who propound this objection fail to discern the real points along the path of developing character where freedom is exercised. They often fail to perceive that there are habits of will which take their rise in self-determination, — habits for which men are responsible so far as they are morally right or wrong, and which exist within them as abiding purposes or voluntary principles of conduct. Of a man who loves money bet ter than anything else, it may be predicted that he will seize upon any occasion that offers itself to make an advantageous bargain. But this love of money is a voluntary principle which he can curb, and, influenced by moral considerations, supersede by a higher motive of conduct. The fact of habit, voluntary habit, springing ultimately from choice, practically circumscribes the variableness of action, and contributes powerfully to the production of a cer tain degree of uniformity of conduct, on which prediction as to what individuals will do is founded. But all predictions in regard THE PERSONALITY OF GOD AND OF MAN 13 to the future conduct of men, or societies of men, are liable to fail, not merely because of the varied and complicated data in the case of human action, but because new influences, not in the least coercive, may still set at defiance all statistical vaticinations. A religious reform, like that of John Wesley, gives rise to an essen tial alteration of the conduct of multitudes, changes the face of society in extensive districts, and upsets, for example, previous cal culations as to the percentage of crime to be expected in the re gions affected. The seat of moral freedom is deep in the radical self-determinations by which the chief ends of conduct, the mo tives of life in the aggregate, are fixed. Kant had a profound per ception of this truth, although he erred in limiting absolutely the operations of free-will to the "noumenal" sphere, and in relegat ing all moral conduct, except the primal choice, to the realm of phenomenal and therefore necessary action. A theist finds no difficulty in ascribing moral evil wholly to the will of the creature, and in accounting for the orderly succession of events, or the plan of history, by the overruling agency of God, which has no need to interfere with human liberty, or to constrain or to crush the free and responsible nature of man, but knows how to pilot the race onward, be the rocks and cross-currents where and what they may be. Self-consciousness and self-determination, each involving the other, are the essential peculiarities of mind. With self-determi nation is inseparably connected purpose. The intelligent action of the will is for an end ; and this preconceived end — which is last in the order of time, although first in thought — is termed the final cause. It is the goal to which the volitions dictated by it point and lead. So simple an act of will as the volition to lift a finger is for a purpose. The thought of the result to be effected precedes that efficient act of the will by which, in some inscrut able way, the requisite muscular motion is produced. I purpose to send a letter to a friend. There is a plan present in thought before it is resolved upon, or converted into an intention, and prior to the several exertions of voluntary power by which it is accomplished. Guided by this plan, I enter my library, open a drawer, find the proper writing-materials, compose the letter, seal it, and despatch it. Here is a series of voluntary actions done in pursuance of a plan which antedated them in consciousness, and through them is realized. The movements of brain and muscle 14 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF which take place in the course of the proceeding are subservient to the conscious plan by which all the power employed in realiz ing it is directed. This is rational voluntary action ; it is action for an end. In this way the whole business of human life is car ried forward. All that is termed "art," in the broadest meaning of the word, — that is, all that is not included either in the prod ucts of material nature, which the wit and power of men can neither produce nor modify, or in the strictly involuntary states of mind with their physical effects, — comes into being in the way described. The conduct of men in their individual capacity, the organization of families and states, the government of nations, the management of armies, the diversified pursuits of industry, what ever is because men have willed it to be, is due to self-determina tion involving design. The opinion has not wholly lacked supporters that man is an automaton. All that he does they have ascribed to a chain of causes wholly embraced within a circle of nervous and muscular movements. Some, finding it impossible to ignore consciousness, have contented themselves with denying to non-material states causal agency. On this view it follows that the plan to take a journey, to build a house, or to do anything else which presup poses design, has no influence whatever upon the result. The same efforts would be produced if we were utterly unconscious of any intention to bring them to pass. The design, not being cred ited with the least influence or control over the instruments through which the particular end is reached, might be subtracted without affecting the result. Since consciousness neither originates nor transmits motion, and thus exerts no power, the effects of what we call voluntary agency would take place as well without it. This creed, when it is once clearly defined, is not likely to win many adherents.1 The scientific doctrine of the conservation of energy is entirely consistent with the freedom of the will and with the reciprocal influence of mind and body. Whether the general notion of energy as inhering in material bodies and transmissible is any thing but a scientific metaphor, it is needless here to discuss. The doctrine is, that as the sum of matter remains the same, so is 1 For a clear exposition of the consequences of denying the agency of mind, see Herbert, The Realistic Assumptions of Modern Science, etc., pp. 103 segn 128 seq. THE PERSONALITY OF GOD AND OF MAN 15 it with the sum of energy, potential or in action, in any body or system of bodies. Energy may be transmitted ; that is, lost in one body, it reappears undiminished in another, or, ceasing in one form, it is exerted in another, and this according to definite ratios. In other words, there is a correlation of the physical forces. While this is believed to be true, there is not the slightest evi dence that mental action is caused by the transmitting of energy from the physical system. Nor is there any proof that the mind transfers additional energy to matter. Nor, again, is there the slightest evidence that mental action is correlated with physical. That mental action is affected by physical change is evident. That the mind acts upon the brain, modifying its state, exerting a directive power upon the nerve-centres, is equally certain. The doctrine of conservation, as its best expounders — Clerk Maxwell, for example — have perceived, does not militate in the least against the limited control of the human will and the supreme control of the divine. Attending the inward assurance of freedom is the consciousness of moral law. While I know that I can do or forbear, I feel that I ought or ought not. The desires of human nature are various. They go forth to external good, which reaches the mind through the channel of the senses. They go out also to objects less tangi ble, as power, fame, knowledge, the esteem of others. But dis tinct from these diverse, and, it may be, conflicting desires, a law manifests itself in consciousness, and lays its authoritative mandate on the will. The requirement of that law in the concrete may be differently conceived. It may be grossly misapprehended. But the feeling of obligation is an ineradicable element of our being. It is universal, or as nearly so as the perception of beauty or any other essential attribute of the soul. For an ethical theory to dis pense with it is suicide. It implies an ideal or end which the will is bound freely to realize. Be this end clearly or dimly discerned, and though it be in a great degree misconceived, its existence is implied in the imperative character of the law within. The con fusion that may arise in respect to the contents of the law and the end to which the law points does not disprove the reality of either. An unenlightened and perverted conscience is still a conscience. Shall the source and ground of nature and self-consciousness alike be placed in the object, the world without ? This cannot be. 1 6 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF " Nature cannot give that which she does not herself possess. She cannot give birth to that which is toto genere dissimilar." Nature can take no such leap. A new beginning on a plane above Nature it is beyond the power of Nature to originate. Self-consciousness can only be referred to self-consciousness as its author and source. It can have its ground in nothing that is itself void of consciousness. Only a personal Power above Nature can account for self-conscious ness in man. It presupposes an original and unconditioned, because original, self-consciousness. The spark of a divine fire is deposited in Nature ; it is in Nature, but not of it. Thus the consciousness of God enters inseparably into the con sciousness of self as its hidden background.1 " The descent into our inmost being is at the same time an ascent to God." All pro found reflection in which the soul withdraws from the world to contemplate its own being brings us to God, in whom we live and move. We are conscious of God in a more intimate sense than we are conscious of finite things. As they themselves are derived, so is our knowledge of them. In order to know a limit as a limit, as it is often said, we must already be in some sense beyond it. " We should not be able," says Julius Miiller, " in the remotest degree to surmise that our personality — that in us whereby we are exalted, not in degree only, but in kind, above every other existence — is limited, were not the consciousness of the Absolute Personality originally stamped, however obscure and however effaced the outlines may often be, upon our souls." It is in the knowledge of the Infinite One that we know ourselves as finite.2 Moreover, to self-determination, the second element of person- 1 Shall the conviction of the being of God that springs up in the soul in connection with feeling of dependence be regarded as the product of infer ence? It is nearer the truth to say that the recognition of God, more or less obscure, is something involved and even presupposed in this feeling. How can there be a sense of self as dependent, unless there be an underlying sense of a somewhat, however vaguely apprehended, on which we depend? The one feeling is an implicate of the other. The error of many who have too closely followed Schleiermacher is in representing the feeling of dependence as void of an intellectual element. Ulrici and some other German writers avoid this mistake by using the term " Gefuhls-perception " to designate that state of mind in which feeling is the predominant element, and perception is still rudimental and obscure. 2 See J. Miiller, Lehre v. d. Siinde, vol. i. pp. ioi seq. THE PERSONALITY OF GOD AND OF MAN 17 ality, like self-consciousness, a limit is consciously prescribed. The limit is the moral law to which the will is bound, though not necessitated, to conform. We find this law within us, a rule for the regulation of the will. It is not merely independent of the will — this is true of the emotions generally — it speaks with authority. It is a voice of command and of prohibition. This rule man spontaneously identifies with the will of Him who reveals himself in consciousness as the Author of his being. The uncon ditional nature of the demand which we are conscious that the moral law makes upon us, against all rebellious desires and pas sions, in the face of our own antagonistic will, can only be ex plained by identifying it thus with a higher Will from which it emanates. In self-consciousness God reveals his being ; in con science he reveals his authority and his will concerning man. Through this recognition of the law of conscience as the will of God in whom we live, morality and religion coalesce. Sir William Hamilton, in pointing out the basis of theism,1 sets in contrast the natural world in which the phenomena " are pro duced and reproduced in the same invariable succession," " in the chain of physical necessity," with the phenomena of man in whom intelligence is a " free power," being subject only to the law of duty, which he can carry into effect. This proves that in the order of existence, as we experience it in ourselves, intelligence is supreme, and as far as its liberty extends "is independent of necessity and matter." By analogy, Hamilton argues, we are authorized to carry into the order of the universe the relation which we find in the human constitution. The argument is sound, for it is on the path of Analogy that science has made its advance. It is not reflection, however, and reasoning, but that immediate self-revelation of God in the human mind which, as explained above, is at the root of theistic faith. It is obvious that the dictates of conscience, so far as its action is sound and normal, express the moral preferences, that is to say, the character, of God. His holiness is evidenced in the condem nation uttered within us of purposes and practices at variance with righteousness. The love of God is expressed in the mandate of conscience to exercise just and kindly feelings, to act conformably to them and to cherish a comprehensive good will. Whenever conscience is so awakened and enlightened as to discern that an 1 Metaphysics, pp. 21 seq. c 1 8 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF unselfish spirit is the law of life, the revelation in the soul is complete that God is Love. Not through the channel of intelligence and of conscience alone, but also through that of sensibility and affection, is God manifest to the soul. Religion is communion with God. If we look atten tively at religion in its pure and elevated form, as, for example, it finds expression in Psalms of the Old Testament, we shall best per ceive its constituent elements, and the sources within us from which it springs. We shall find that along with the sense of obli gation and of dependence in which the existence of a Supreme Being is recognized, there is intimately connected a native pro clivity to rest upon, and hold converse with, Him in whom we live. The tendency to commune with Him is an essential part of the religious constitution of man. To pray to Him for help, to lean on Him for support, to worship Him, are native and sponta neous movements of the human spirit. Man feels himself drawn to the Being who reveals Himself to him in the primitive operations of intelligence and conscience, and inspires him with the sense of dependence. As man was made for God, there is a nisus in the direction of this union to his Creator. This tendency, which may take the form of an intense craving, may be compared to the social instinct with which it is akin. As man was made not to be alone, but to commune with other beings like himself, solitude would be an unnatural and almost unbearable state ; and a longing for converse with other men is a part of his nature. In like man ner, as man was made to commune with God, he is drawn to God by an inward tendency, the strength of which is derived from the vacuum left in the soul, and the unsatisfied yearning, consequent on an exclusion of God as the supreme object of love and trust. These feelings are not to be discounted from the testimony in the soul to his being. John Fiske in his little book Through Nature to God,3 speaks of the nascent Human Soul vaguely reaching forth toward something akin to itself not in the realm of fleeting phenomena but in the Eternal Presence beyond. He adds: "If the re- 1 Cf. Ulrici, Gott u. die Natur, pp. 606 seq. " The general conviction of a divine existence we regard as less an inference than a perception." — Bowne, Studies in Theism, p. 79. 2 pp. 188, 189. THE PERSONALITY OF GOD AND OF MAN 19 lation thus established in the morning twilight of Man's existence between the Human Soul and a world invisible and immaterial is a relation of which only the subjective term is real and the objective term is non-existent, then I say it is something utterly without precedent in the whole history of creation." It contra dicts "all the analogies of evolution," so far as we understand it. To whatever just criticism some expressions of this author con nected with the foregoing observations may be open, these state ments on the " Everlasting Reality of Religion " are sound and impressive. " Our heart is restless," writes Augustine, " unless it repose in Thee." In sense-perception external objects are brought directly to our knowledge. Through sensations compared and combined by reason, we perceive outward things in their being and relations. There are perceptions of the spirit as well as of sense. The being whom we call God may, so to speak, come in contact with the soul. As the soul, in the experience of sensations, posits the outer world, so, in analogous inward experiences, it posits God. The feelings, yearnings, aspirations, which are at the root of the spiritual perception, are not continuous, as in the perceptions of matter ; they vary in liveliness ; they are contingent, in a remark able degree, on character. Hence religious faith may not have the clearness, the uniform and abiding character, which belongs to our recognition of outward things.1 The understanding is not the sole authority in the sphere of moral and religious belief. Rationalism has been defined as "a usurpation of the understanding." There are moral exactions and dictates which have a voice not to be disregarded. So, likewise, are there instinctive, almost irrepressible, instincts of feeling to be taken into account. It is the satisfaction of the spirit, and not any single organ or function of the soul, which is felt to be the criterion of full-orbed truth. " If a certain formula for expressing the nature of the world violates my moral demand, I shall be as free to throw it overboard, or at least to doubt it, as if it disap pointed my demand for uniformity of sequence." 2 " Just as within JOn the subject of the immediate manifestation of God to the soul, and the analogy of sense-perception, the reader may be referred to Lotze, Grund- zuge d. Religionsphil., p. 3 ; Mikrokosmos, vol. iii. chap. iv. ; Ulrici, Gott u. die Natur, pp. 605-624; Gott u. der Mensch, vol. i.; Bowne, Studies in Theism, chap. ii. 2 Professor William James, The WiU to Believe, etc., p. 147. 20 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF the limits of theism some kinds are surviving others by reason of their greater practical rationality, so theism itself, by reason of its practical rationality, is certain to survive all lower creeds."1 "There is a moral as well as a logical rationality to be satisfied," is a pithy sentence of the same author, who adds respecting the inquiries and suggestions of natural science that even " Physics is always seeking to satisfy our own subjective passions." Belief in a future life, in immortality, is closely connected with belief in God. The soul that communes with him finds in this very relation — in the sense of its own worth implied in this rela tion — the assurance that it is not to perish with its material organs. It is conscious of belonging to a different order of things. In proportion as the moral and religious nature is roused to activ ity, this consciousness gains in life and vigor. " ' But how do you wish us to bury you?' said Crito to Socrates. 'Just as you please,' he answered, 'if you only get hold of me and do not let me escape you.' And quietly laughing and glancing at us, he said, ' I cannot persuade Crito, my friends, that this Socrates, who is now talking with you, and laying down each one of these propositions, is my very self; for his mind is full of the thought that /am he whom he is to see in a little while as a corpse ; and so he asks how he shall bury me.' " 2 The consciousness of a free and responsible nature, of a law suggestive of a personal Lawgiver, of the need of communion with the Father of the spirit, of the sense of orphanage without God, are not all that is required for the realization of religion in the soul. There must be an acknowledgment of God which carries in it an active concurrence of the will. The will utters its "yea" and " amen " to the attractive power of God experienced within the soul. It gives consent to the reality of that dependence and obligation to obedience, in which the finite soul stands to God. " The holding fast to the personal God and to the inviolability of conscience, is an act of the soul, conditioned on a living sense of the supreme worth of this conviction." Faith springs from no coercion of logic. When a man is sorely tempted by plausible reasoning, but chooses to abide by the right, come what will, it is 1 Professor William James, The Will to Believe, etc., p. 1 26. 2 Plato, Phcedo, 115. THE PERSONALITY OF GOD AND OF MAN 21 a kind of venture. The inward satisfaction, with the decision once made, requires no other testimonial. We believe in God, not on the ground of a scientific demonstration, but because it is our duty to believe in him. Faith in its general sense is defined by Coleridge as " fidelity to our own being — so far as such being is not ahd cannot become an object of the senses," together with its concomitants, the first of which is the acknowledgment of God.1 The refusal thus practically to acknowledge God by a ratifying act of the will, the assent of the entire man, is to enthrone the false principle of self-assertion or self-sufficiency in the soul, — false because it is contrary to the reality of things. It is a kind of self-deification. Man may refuse " to retain God in his knowl edge." The result is, that the feelings out of which religion springs, and in which it is rationally founded, are not extirpated, but are driven to fasten on finite objects in the world, or on ficti tious creations of the imagination. Idolatry is the enthronement of that which belongs to the creature, in the place of the Creator. There is an idolatry of which the world, in the form of power, fame, riches, pleasure, or knowledge, is the object. When the proper food is wanting, the attempt is made to appease the appe tite with drugs and stimulants. Theology has deemed itself warranted by sound philosophy, as well as by the teaching of Scripture, in maintaining, that, but for the intrusion of moral evil or the practical substitution of a finite object, real or imaginary, for God as the supreme good, the knowledge of him would shine more and more brightly in the soul, from the dawn of intelligence, keeping pace with its advancing de velopment. The more one turns the eye within, and fastens his attention on the characteristic elements of his own spirit, the more clear and firm is found to be his belief in God. And the more completely the will follows the law that is written on the heart, the more vivid is the conviction of the reality of the Lawgiver, whose authority is expressed in it. The experience of religion carries with it a constantly growing sense of the reality of its object. The following extracts from two writers of marked ability, al though not in entire accord in their points of view, are excellent statements of a philosophical truth. 1 Fresh and instructive observations on the voluntary element in belief are contained in the work cited above, The Will to Believe, etc., by Professor James. 22 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF " Not only is the subject active in perception, but he necessarily and inevitably has an inchoate consciousness of himself as a sub ject in distinction from the subjects which that activity enables him to apprehend. . . . And the same is true of the idea of God which is presupposed in the division of the self from the not-self and in all other divisions of consciousness. . . . And, like the idea of self, the idea of God must at a very early period take some form for us, though it may not for a very long time take an ade quate form. Man may hide his inborn sense of the infinite in vague superstitions which confuse it with the finite ; but he cannot altogether escape from it, or prevent his consciousness of the finite from being disturbed by it." 1 " Anterior to and independent of philosophy, a tacit faith in the ego, in external things, and in God, seems to pervade human ex perience ; mixing, often unconsciously, with the lives of all ; never perfectly defined, but in its fundamental ideas more or less operative ; often intellectually confused, yet never without a threefold influence in human life. . . . Life is good and happy in proportion to the due acknowledgment of all the three. Con fused conceptions of the three are inexhaustible sources of two extremes — superstition and scepticism."2 But we have to look at men as they are. As a matter of fact, "the consciousness of God" is obscure, more latent than ex plicit, germinant rather than developed. It waits to be quickened and illuminated by the manifestation of God in nature and provi dence, and by instruction. Writers on psychology have frequently neglected to give an account of presentiment, a state of consciousness in which feeling is predominant, and knowledge is indistinct. There are vague an ticipations of truth not yet clearly discerned. It is possible to seek for something, one knows not precisely what. Were it discerned it would not have to be sought. Yet it is not utterly beyond our ken, else how could we seek for it ? Explorers and inventors may feel themselves on the threshold of great discoveries just before they are made. Poets, at least, have recognized the deep import of occult, vague feelings which almost baffle analysis. The German psychologists who have most satisfactorily handled the subject 1 E. Caird, The Evolution of Religion, vol. i. pp. 184, 186. 2Fraser, Philosophy of Theism, second edition, amended (1899). THE PERSONALITY OF GOD AND OF MAN 23 before us, as Lotze, Ulrici, Julius Miiller, Nitzsch, find in their language an expressive term to designate our primitive sense or apprehension of God. It is Ahnung, of which our word " presage " is a partial equivalent. The apostle Paul refers to the providential control of nations as intended to incite men " to seek the Lord, if haply they might feel after Him, and find Him." : He is not known, but sought for. Rather do men feel after Him, as a blind man moves about in quest of something, or as we grope in the dark. This philosophy of religion is conformed to the observed facts. There is that in man which makes him restless without God, discontented with every substitute for Him. The subjective basis for religion, inherent in the very constitution of the soul, is the spur to the search for God, the condition of apprehending Him when revealed (whether in nature, or in providence, or in Christi anity), and the ultimate ground of certitude as to the things of faith. 1 Acts xvii. 27. 2 For additional remarks on the origin of religion, see Appendix, Note 23. CHAPTER II THE ARGUMENTS FOR THE BEING OF GOD : THEIR FUNCTION IN GENERAL AND AS SEVERALLY CONSIDERED It will be clear, from the foregoing chapter, that the ultimate source of the belief in God is not in processes of argument. His presence is more immediately manifest. There is a native belief, arising spontaneously in connection with the feeling of dependence and the phenomena of conscience, however obscure, undeveloped, or perverted that faith may be. The arguments for the being of God confirm, at the same time that they elucidate and define it. They are so many different points of view from which we contem plate the object of faith. Each one of them tends to show, not simply that God is, but what He is. They fill out the conception by pointing out particulars brought to light in the manifestation which God has made of Himself. In presenting the several proofs of theism, which is the doctrine of a personal God, infinite in His attributes, we begin with the intuition which is denominated, in the language of philosophy, the Unconditioned, the Absolute. By " the Absolute " is signified that which is complete in itself, that which stands in no necessary relation to other beings. It denotes being which is independent as to existence and action. A cognate notion is that of the Infinite, which designates being without limit. The Uncondi tioned, in form a negative term, is more generic. , It means free from all restriction. It is often used as synonymous with "the Absolute," a term positive in its significance. We have an immediate conviction of the reality of the Absolute, that is, of being which is dependent upon no other as the condi tion of existence and activity. When we look abroad upon the world, we discern a multitude of objects, each bounded by others, each conditioned by beings other than itself, none of them com plete or independent. We perceive everywhere demarcation, mutual dependence, interaction. Looking within, we see that our 24 THE ARGUMENTS FOR THE BEING OF GOD 25 own minds and our mental processes are in the same way restricted, conditioned. The mind has a definite constitution ; the act of knowledge requires an object as its necessary condition. The spectacle of the world- is that of a vast aggregate of interrelated beings, none of them independent, self-originated, self-sustained. Inseparable from this perception of the relative, the limited, the dependent, is the idea of the Unconditioned, the Absolute. It is the correlate of the finite and conditioned. Its reality is known as implied in the reality of the world of finite, interacting, dependent existences. The Unconditioned is abstract in form, but only in form. It is not a mere negative ; it must have a positive content. It is negative in its verbal form, because it is antithetical to the conditioned, and is known through it. But the idea is positive, though it be incomplete ; that is to say, although we fall short of a complete grasp of the object denoted by it. The reality of the Unconditioned, almost all philosophers, except Positivists of an ex treme type, recognize. Metaphysicians of the school of Hamilton and Mansel hold that, as a reality, it is an object of immediate and necessary belief, although, according to their definition of terms, they do not regard it as an object of conceptive thought. But some sort of knowledge of it there must be in order to such a belief. Moreover, the Unconditioned is not merely subjective, it is not a mere idea, as Kant, in the theoretical part of his phi losophy, holds. He makes this idea necessary to the order, con nection, and unity of our knowledge. We can ask for no surer criterion of real existence than this.1 Unconditioned being is the silent presupposition of all our knowing. Be it observed, likewise, that the idea of the Absolute is not that of " the sum of all reality," — a quantitative notion. It is not the idea of the Unrelated, but of that which is not of necessity related. It does not exclude other beings, but other beings only when conceived of as a necessary complement of itself, or as the product of its necessary activity, or as existing independently alongside of itself. Again, the Absolute which is given in the intuition is one. It is infinite, not as comprehending in itself of necessity all beings, but as their ground and as incapable of any conceivable augmenting of its powers. It is free from all restrictions which are not self- imposed. Anything more respecting the Absolute is not here affirmed. It might be, as far as we have gone now, the universal 1 Cf. Trendelenburg, Logische Untersuchungen, vol. ii. p. 426, 26 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF substance, the impersonal deity of Spinoza, or it might be " the Unknowable " of Spencer. For the rectifying of these hypotheses, we depend on other considerations. The " arguments " for the being of God are usually classified as the ontological, the cosmological, and the teleological, or the argument of design. This last comprehends the evidences of design in Nature, together with the moral and historical arguments having a like probative value. I. The ontological argument. This makes the existence of God involved in the idea of Him. This argument does not profess to appeal to the intuition of the Absolute which is evoked in conjunc tion with our perceptions of relative and dependent existence. The ontological proof begins and ends with the analysis of the idea. The proposition is that the fact of the existence of God is involved in the very idea. In the argument of Anselm, it is affirmed that the great est (or the most perfect) conceivable being must be actual ; other wise, a property, that of actuality, or objective being, is lacking. To this it has been answered that existence in re is not a constitu ent of a concept. Anselm's contention was that it is not mere existence, but a mode of existence, a necessity of existence, that is the missing element in question. Still, it has been answered, the existence of a thing cannot be concluded from the definition of a word. In truth, that which Anselm presents in the shape of a syllogistic proof is really the rational intuition of Absolute Being.1 From the mere idea, except on the basis of philosophical realism, a corresponding entity cannot be inferred. Descartes alleges a double basis for our knowledge of the exist ence of God. The idea of an infinite self-conscious being is deduced from our own finite self-consciousness. That idea can not be a product of the finite self. Its presence in the human mind can be accounted for, only by ascribing it to the Infinite Being himself. But, further, Descartes follows in the path of Anselm, and holds that the fact of the existence of God is in volved in the definition of the Most Real Being, just as the equal ity of the three angles of a triangle is involved in the definition of a triangle. Here, moreover, the intuition of the Absolute is cast into the form of a proof. Dr. Samuel Clarke's "demonstration" only establishes a priori the existence of a being eternal and necessarily existing. For of 1 So it is interpreted by Harris, The Self- Revelation of God, p. 164. THE ARGUMENTS FOR THE BEING OF GOD 27 the intelligence of this being the proof is a posteriori. Facts are adduced, — namely, the order and beauty perceived in the world, and the intelligence possessed by finite, human beings.1 There is cogency in what has been called the logical form of the a priori proof. It is adopted by Anselm and Aquinas. It is impossible to deny that there is Truth ; the denial would be self- contradictory. But those ideas and truths which are the ground work of all our knowing — the laws of our intellectual and moral constitution — have their source without us and beyond us. They inhere in God. A like indirect proof has been presented as fol lows. The human mind goes out of itself to know the world, and also, by exertions of the will, to mould and subdue it. Yet the world is independent of the mind that seeks thus to comprehend it and shape it to its purposes. This freedom of the mind implies that the world is intelligible, that there is thought in things. Al though this proposition is denied by agnostics, yet it is tacitly admitted by them in all communications made from one to another. It implies that there is a common bond — namely, God, the Truth — between thoughts and things, mind and the world. Thought and thing, subject and object, each matched to the other, presuppose an intelligible ground of both. This presupposition is latent in all attempts to explore and comprehend, to bring within the domain of knowledge, and to shape to rational ends, the world without. II. The cosmological proof. As usually stated, this proof is made to rest on the principle of causation. Whatever begins to be, owes its being to a cause not itself. The minor premise is that finite things begin to be. But this proposition, if it be admitted to be probably true, is not capable of full demonstration. The consequence is that we must fall back on the intuition of the Abso lute Being. Here we find the origin and justification of the princi ple of causation. The hypothesis of an infinite series or regress, does not meet this demand. It is equivalent to saying that there is no cause, that the notion of cause is illusive. A phenomenon — call it a — calls for explanation ; it demands a cause. If we are told that the cause of it is b, but told at the same time that in b there is no fount of causal energy, so that we have precisely the same demand to satisfy respecting b as respecting a, then no answer has been given to our first question : we are put off with an eva- 1See, on Clarke's argument, Dr. R. Flint, in Encycl. Brit. vol. ix. p. no. 28 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF sion. That question takes for granted the reality of aboriginal causal energy. It proceeds from a demand of intelligence which is illegitimate and irrational, unless there be a cause in the abso lute sense, — a cause uncaused. The existence of an eternal being, the cause of the world, is veri fied. It is a reasonable judgment that the uncaused eternal being is a voluntary agent. For where do we get our idea of " cause?" For an answer to this question, we must look within. It is in the ex ercise of will alone that we become conscious of power, and arrive at the notion of causation. We act upon the world exterior to self, and consciously meet with resistance from without, which gives us the consciousness of external reality. It has been already ex plained that we have no direct knowledge of anything of the na ture of cause, nor could we ever get such knowledge, except through this exercise of energy in voluntary action. The will influences intellectual states through attention, which is a volun tary act. We can fasten our observation on one thing, or one idea, in preference to another. The nascent self-activity which we style the exercise of the will belongs to the earliest develop ment of the mind. It is doubtful whether distinct perception would be possible without a directing of the attention to one after another of the qualities of external objects, or at least without such a discrimination among the phenomena presented to the senses as involves the exercise of attention. Now, were it not for this consciousness of causal activity in ourselves, in our own wills, were we merely the subjects of utterly passive impressions from the world without, the conception of cause would be wanting. Inasmuch as the only cause of which we are immediately con scious is will, it is the dictate of reason to refer the power which acts upon us from without to will as its source. The theory that "forces " inhere in nature, which are disconnected from the agency of will, is without warrant from ascertained truth in science. If it be supposed that plural agencies, separate or combined, do exist, even then analogy justifies the belief that they are dependent for their being and sustained activity on a Supreme Will. In this case, the precise mode of the connection of the primary and the subordinate agency is a mystery, as is true of the muscular move ments of the human arm, so far as they originate and are kept up by volition. That the will of God is immanent and active in all THE ARGUMENTS FOR THE BEING OF GOD 29 things, is a legitimate inference from what we know by experience of the nature of causation. The polytheistic religions did not err in identifying the mani fold activities of nature with voluntary agency. The spontaneous feelings of mankind in this particular are not belied by the principles of philosophy. The error of polytheism lies in the splintering of that Will which is immanent in all the operations of nature into a plurality of personal agents, a throng of divinities, each active and dominant chiefly within a province of its own. How shall we confute polytheism? What warrant is there for asserting the unity of the Power that pervades nature ? In the first place, an example of such a unity is presented in the operation of our own wills. We put forth a multitude of voli tions ; we exert our voluntary agency in many different directions ; this agency stretches over long periods of time ; yet the same identical will is the source of all these effects. To attribute the sources of our passive impressions collectively to a single self without, as our personal exertions consciously emanate from a single self within, is natural and rational. Secondly, what philosophers call the "law of parsimony" pre cludes us from assuming more causes to account for a given effect than are necessary. The One self-existent Being, known to us by intuition, suffices to account for the phenomena of nature. To postulate a plurality of such beings — were a plurality of self-exist ent beings metaphysically possible — would compel the conclu sion that they are either in concord or in conflict. Thirdly, the fact that nature is one coherent system proves that the operations of nature spring from one efficient Cause. The progress of scientific observation tends to show that the world is a cosmos. Science is constantly clearing away barriers which have been imagined to break up the visible universe into distinct and separate provinces. The word " universe " signifies unity. Men speak of the heavens and the earth; but the earth belongs in the starry system. The earth is a planet, and with its associate planets is one of countless similar groups, not alien from one another, but linked together in the stellar universe. Scientific theory more and more favors the reduction of " forces " to unity. The theory of the conservation of force is an illustra tion. The unity of the world testifies to the unity of God. III. The argument of design. The personality of God is 30 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF proved by the argument of design. God is known to be intel ligent and free by the manifest traces of purpose in the constitu tion of the world. When we attend to the various objects, the human mind in cluded, of which the knowing faculty takes cognizance, we discover something more than the properties which differentiate one from another and the causes which bring them into being.1 In this very process of investigation we are struck with the fact that there is a coincidence and cooperation of what are named physical or efficient causes for the production of definite effects. These causes are perceived to be so constituted and disposed as to con cur in the production of the effect, and — the elective preferences of the will excepted — to concur in such a way that the particular result regularly follows. This conjunction of disparate agencies, of which a definite product is the outcome, is the finality which is observed in Nature. But our observation extends farther. We involuntarily assume that this coincidence of causes is in order that the peculiar and specific result may follow. This assumption of design is not an arbitrary act on our part. It is spontaneous. The conviction is one inspired by the objects themselves. We see a thought realized, and recognize in it a forethought. All must admit that the observation of order and adaptation in Nature, inspiring the conviction of a designing mind concerned in its origination, is natural to mankind. It has impressed alike the philosopher and the peasant. Socrates made use of the illus tration of a statue, as Paley, two thousand years later, chose the illustration of a watch. The proof from evidences of design is styled the argument from " final causes." In this expression, the term " final " refers to the end for which anything is made, as distinguished from what we style the mechanical causes concerned in its origination. The end is the purpose in view, and is so called because its manifes tation is last in the order of time. Thus, a man purposes to build a house. He collects the materials, brings them into the proper shape, raises the walls, and, in short, does everything need ful to carry out his intention. The final cause is seen in the com- 1 Be it observed that we use the term " causes," in this connection, in the sense in which it is popularly taken, and without reference now to the question whether forces distinct from the agency of the divine will and resident in matter are to be regarded as real. THE ARGUMENTS FOR THE BEING OF GOD 31 pleted dwelling for the habitation of his family. The final cause of a watch is to tell the time. The efficient causes are all the forces and agencies concerned in the making of it and in the reg ular movement of its parts. It is a familiar fact that a thing may be an end, and, at the same time, a means to another end more remote. When a mechanic is making a spoke, it is the spoke which is the immediate end in view. But the end of the spoke is to connect the rim of the wheel with the hub. The end of the wheel is to revolve upon the axle ; and the wagon is the end for which all its parts are fashioned and connected. The transporting of persons or things is a further end, ulterior but prior in the order of thought. There are subordinate ends and chief ends. We are not, there fore, to ignore the marks of design, even in cases where the chief end, the ultimate purpose, may be faintly perceived, or be quite in the dark. It is sometimes said that " we cannot reason from the works of man to the works of nature." Why not? We are seeking to explain the origin of the scene that is spread before us in the world in which we live. Is the cause intelligent? We know what are the characteristic signs of intelligence. These signs are obvi ous in the world around us. The marks of design in nature re veal to us its intelligent author. For the same reason that we recognize an intelligent cause in countless products of human agency whose particular origin and authorship we know not, we infer an intelligent cause in things not made by man. In them we discern equal evidence of an end reached by the selection and combination of means adapted to accomplish it. If it is not a literal truth, it is far more than a fancy, when we say that they conspire to produce it. This mode of reasoning is often considered an argument from analogy. We sometimes apply the term " analogy " to a merely figurative likeness which the imagination suggests ; as when we speak of the " analogy " between a rushing stream and the rapid utterance of an excited orator. This is the diction of poetry. But when we have always found that certain properties in an animal are united with a given characteristic — for example, speed — we expect wherever we meet the same collection of properties, to find in their company this additional quality. This we look for with a certain degree of confidence even when no specific connection 32 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF between such properties and their associate has yet been detected. This is an argument from analogy. J. S. Mill maintains that the argument of design is a genuine ' instance of inductive reasoning. " The design argument," says Mill, " is not drawn from mere resemblance in nature to the work of human intelligence, but from the special character of this resem blance. The circumstances in which it is alleged that the world resembles the works of man are not circumstances taken at random, but are particular instances of a circumstance which experience shows to have real connection with an intelligent origin, the fact of conspiring to an end. The argument, therefore, is not one of mere analogy. As mere analogy it has its weight, but it is more than analogy. It surpasses analogy exactly as induction surpasses it. It is an inductive argument." x But the argument of design has an a priori basis and consequently is universal in its application. Induction itself, as a method of reasoning, presupposes what is termed the uniformity of nature, or an order of nature — an established asso ciation of observed antecedents and consequents. This convic tion is not one of the intuitions constitutive of reason, and admitting of no possible or conceivable exception, but is a belief grounded on wide and long-continued experience, and thus serving as a " working postulate." But the idea of end or purpose as implied in all things and events, like the idea of what is termed efficient or physical or mechanical causation, has a strictly a priori origin. The idea of final purpose arises in our own experience in carrying out a desire by means chosen for this end. We are not less prompted to ask " what for " than to ask " how." Mechanism of itself explains nothing. The very term properly signifies means to an end. The world, if conceived of as only a vast mechanism, would be a fathomless mystery im pervious to reason,2 and not what it really is, the spectacle of forces realizing ideas. The objection that to attribute design to material things and to the world as a whole is anthropomor- 1 Three Essays on Religion ; Theism, pp. 169, 170. 2 For a clear exposition and proof of the a priori basis of the idea of Design, see Ladd, A Theory of Reality, ch. xiv. See also, Trendelenburg, Logische Untersuchungen, 3d ed., vol. ii. ch. ix., Zweck ; Dorner, System d. Christi. Glaubenslehre, vol. i. pp. 252-257 ; N. Porter, The Human Intellect, pp. 592-619. THE ARGUMENTS FOR THE BEING OF GOD 33 phic, has no real weight. It shares this character in company with the idea of mechanical causation. In each case the human mind finds its own rational constitution reflected and embodied in external reality.1 Our knowledge of the world without con sists in the projection of the categories in our mental processes into things without. It is undeniable that nature is a system, or proceeds according to a plan. The postulate of science is the rationality of nature. Science, in the words of Huxley, is " the dis covery of the rational order that pervades the universe." Without this presupposition of a rational order, scientific investigation would be the pursuit of a chimera. Nature, it is taken for granted, is the embodiment of thoughts. All nature is but a book which science undertakes to decipher and read. When the student explores any department of Nature, it is to unveil its laws and adaptations.2 Because Nature is a rational system, it is adapted to our cogni tive faculties. This correspondence proves that the author of the mind is the author of " the mind in Nature." What being, says Cicero, that is "destitute of intellect and reason could have pro duced these things which not only had need of reason to cause them to be, but which are such as can be understood only by the highest exertions of reason / " 2 What are the laws of Nature ? They are a description of the observed and customary interaction of things. To hypostatize " Law," either in the singular or the plural, if more than a figure of speech is meant, is to set up a crude species of Nature-worship. Laws are the rules conform ably to which the unitary power operative in Nature, or, if one pleases so to think, the multiple forces in Nature, act. We can not think of them otherwise than as prescribed, as ordained to the end that they may work out their effects. In other words, the order of Nature is an arrangement of intelligence. This explains the joy that springs up in the mind on the discovery of some great law which gives simplicity to seemingly complex natural phenomena. Thought gains access to reality through their mutual affinity. The mind recognizes something akin to itself. It discovers a thought of God. The norms according to which the knowing faculty discriminates, connects, and classifies the objects in Nature, imply that Nature herself has been pre- 1 What is deducible a priori by epistemological argument (see above, p. 18) can be shown inductively. 2 De Nat. Deorum, ii. 44. D 34 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF arranged according to the same norms, or is the product of mind. In conformity to the categories — time, space, quantity, quality, etc. — according to which the mind distinguishes natural objects, and thus comprehends Nature, Nature has been framed. That is to say, there is mind expressed in Nature. Science is the statement of the expressions of thought and purpose which are incorporated in Nature. A dog sees on a printed page only meaningless marks on a white ground. To us they contain and convey ideas, and bring us into communion with the mind of the author. So it is with Nature. Take a book of astronomy. If the stellar world were not an intellectual system, such a work would be impossible. The sky itself is the book which the astronomer reads, and the written treatise is merely a transcript of the thoughts which he finds there. This truth is pre sented with much force and eloquence by one of the most eminent mathematicians of the age, the late Benjamin Pierce. He speaks of Nature as " imbued with intelligible thought," 1 of "the amazing intellectuality inwrought into the unconscious material world," 2 in which there is " no dark corner of hopeless obscurity,"8 of the "dominion of intellectual order everywhere found,"4 "of the vast intellectual conceptions in Nature."5 To ignore God as the author of Nature as well as of mind is as absurd as to make " the anthem the offspring of unconscious sound." 6 " If the common origin of mind and matter is con ceded to reside in the decree of a Creator, the identity ceases to be a mystery." 7 Science is the reflex of mind in Nature. Nature is made up of interacting objects which constitute together one complete system.8 Order reigns in Nature, and universal harmony. Hence all these separate objects must be so fashioned and man aged that they shall conspire to sustain and promote, and not to convulse and subvert, the complex whole. It follows that the existence and preservation of the system are an end for the realizing of which the plurality of forces — if supposed to be plural — and their special activities are the means. That is, Nature in its totality exhibits design. 1 Pierce, Ideality in the Physical Sciences (1883), p. 19. 2 p. 20. - p. 25. 0 p. 32. SP-21- 6P- 26. 7P- 31. 8 It was a noble title of Cudworth, however ambitious it may sound : "The True Intellectual System of the Universe." THE ARGUMENTS FOR THE BEING OF GOD 35 The belief in design has been at the root of scientific discovery. It has suggested the hypotheses which investigation has verified. Such was the source of Newton's discovery of the law of gravita tion. Harvey was led to find out the true system of the circula tion of the blood by observing that in the channels through which the blood flows, one set of valves opens toward the heart, while another set opens in the opposite direction. He had faith in the prudence of nature. Robert Boyle tells us : — " I remember that when I asked our famous Harvey what were the things that induced him to think of the circulation of the blood, he answered me, that when he took notice of the valves in many parts of the body, so placed that they gave free passage to the blood toward the heart, but opposed to the passage of the venous blood the contrary way, he was invited to think that so prudent a cause as nature had not placed so many valves without a design, and no design seemed more probable than that, since the blood could not well, because of the intervening valves, be sent by the veins to the limits, it should be sent through the arteries, and returned through the veins, whose valves did not oppose its course that way." Kepler was moved to his discoveries by " an exalted faith, anterior and superior to all science, in the existence of intimate relations between the constitution of man's mind and that of God's firmament." 1 Such a faith is at the root of " the prophetic inspiration of the geometers," which the progress of observation verifies. The distinction between order and design, in the popular sense of the term, — meaning special adaptations, — is a valid and important one. Especially is this discrimination to be borne in mind since the advent of the modern theories of evolution. By order we mean the reign of law and the harmony of the world resulting from it. Both order and the relation of means to special ends imply intelligent purpose. Both order and special adapta tion may and do coexist, but they are distinguishable from one another. For example, the typical unity of animals of the verte brate class, or their conformity in structure to a typical idea, is an example of order. The fitness of the foot for walking, the wing for flying, the fin for swimming, is an instance of special adapta tion. In either case there is an immanence of ideas. 1 Pierce, Ideality in the Physical Sciences, p. 1 7. 36 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF What is meant by the explanation of any object of nature? What is it to explain any particular organ in a living being? What is it but to define its end ? There can be no explanation of an organism which does not presuppose adaptation. This is the meaning of organism : one whole composed of mutually depend ent parts. Says Janet : — " Laplace perceived that the simplest laws are the most likely to be true. But I do not see why it should be so on the supposition of an absolutely blind cause ; for, after all, the inconceivable swiftness which the system of Ptolemy supposed has nothing physically impossible in it, and the complication of movements has nothing incompatible with the idea of a mechanical cause. Why, then, do we expect to find sim ple movements in nature, and speed in proportion, except because we in stinctively attribute a sort of intelligence and choice to the First Cause? " Janet does not consider the idea of design to be a priori. But this question, and the whole paragraph which we are quoting, imply it. He goes on to say : — " Now, experience justifies this hypothesis ; at least it did so with Copernicus and Galileo. It did so, according to Laplace, in the debate between Clairaut and Buffon ; the latter maintaining against the former that the law of attraction remained the same at all distances. ' This time,' says Laplace, ' the metaphysician was right as against the geome trician.' " 1 Teleology is evident in the structure of plants as truly as in the structure of animals. The development and growth, the forms and colors, the habits, of plants presuppose and reveal the idea which is directive of the energy operative in their produc tion. Energy is not a substance. It is power dependent on guidance. The energy through which the tree, in defiance of inanimate forces, like gravitation, rises in the air, clothes itself in foliage and bears its proper fruit, until the antagonistic elements win the victory, and it yields to the verdict, " earth to earth," carries out an idea inseparable from it. " However we resolve the problem as to the connection of mind and matter, it is unques tionably a simplification to infer that wherever a material system is organized for self-maintenance, growth, and reproduction, as an individual in touch with an environment, that system has a psy chical as well as a material aspect." 2 The supposition of an inher- 1 Pinal Causes, p. 168. 2 Ward, Naturalism and Agnosticism, vol. i. p. 285. See, also, the context of this remark. THE ARGUMENTS FOR THE BEING OF GOD 37 ent "mind-stuff" is self-contradictory and absurd, but not more absurd than the supposition of a mindless energy. When the root of a tree is observed to strike a path through the sand in quest of moisture, the rustic gardener has been known to express his recognition of design and of an inward stimulus by saying that " the root sees what it needs." In the inorganic realm, teleology is less striking, and may not be in a form to excite attention. So the question as to mechanical causes may fail to suggest itself to the casual observer. But to the en lightened student, to the mineralogist, the geologist, the chemist, the manifestation of controlling ideas or ends is not thus obscure.1 There are "sermons in stones." In the structure of the globe are revealed an historic rise and a progress from step to step.2 The evidences of controlling intelligence are peculiarly impres sive in the organic kingdom. The very idea of an organism is that every part is at once means and end. Naturalists, whatever their opinion about final causes, cannot describe plants and ani^ mals without perpetually using language which implies intention as disclosed in their structure. " Biological facts cannot be known at all except in relation to some teleological conception." 3 The " provisions " of nature, the " purpose " of an organ, the " posses sion " of a part, " in order that " something may be done or averted, — such phraseology is not only common, it is well-nigh unavoid able. The very word " function " means the appropriate action or assigned part. No writer uses the language of teleology more spontaneously and abundantly than Darwin. Huxley speaks of " every part " of an organism " becoming gradually and slowly fashioned, as if there were an artificer at work in each of these complex structures." " Step by step," he tells us, " naturalists have come to the idea of a unity of plan, or conformity of con struction, among animals which appeared at first sight to be ex tremely dissimilar." * It is when we consider the human body in its relation to the mind, that the most vivid perception of design is awakened. To 1 Striking illustrations of " God's plan " are presented in the Lectures on Religion and Chemistry by Prof. J. P. Cooke (1864). It is shown what mighty forces, so to speak, are leashed, as it were, in the atmosphere and its elements. 2 For proofs of design in Beauty, see Newman Smyth's Through Nature to Faith, ch. vii. 8 Ladd, Theory of Reality, p. 379. 4 Huxley, Collected Essays, vol. ii. pp. 319, 325. 38 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF one not fettered to the opinion that the mind is itself the product of organization, and every purpose which the mind forms a phe nomenon of matter — a phenomenon as necessary in its origin as the motion of the lungs — that is, to every one who is conscious of being able to initiate action, the adaptation of his bodily organs to the service of his intelligence is obvious and striking. The hand bears more clearly marks of being designed, than the tools which the hand makes. The eye displays contrivance more im pressively than the optical instruments which man can contrive and fashion for the eye to use. I distinguish myself from the eye, and from my body of which the eye is a part ; and I know that the eye was made for me to see with. The end of its existence is apparent. It is what the word " eye " signifies. When we con sider the adaptation of the sexes to one another, the physical and moral arrangements of Nature which result in the family, in the production and rearing of offspring ; and when we contemplate the relation of the family to the state and the relation of the fam ily and the state to the kingdom of God, where the ideas and affections developed in the family and in the state connect them selves with higher objects, the evidences of a preconceived plan seem irresistible. It is objected that in all the works of man the efficient cause is distinct and separate from the object in which the end is realized. In Nature, we are told, the efficient cause operates from within, and appears to work out the end without conscious purpose. The forces of Nature, it is alleged, appear to produce the order and vari ety and beauty which we behold, of themselves, through no exter nal compulsion, and at the same time without consciousness. In an organism the structure grows up, repairs itself, and perpetuates itself by reproduction; but, it is averred, the active force by which these ends are fulfilled is not in the least aware of what it is doing. Thus, it is contended, the analogy fails between the arti ficial products of human ingenuity and the works of Nature. It is a blind intelligence, it is said, performing works resembling those which man does, often less perfectly, with conscious design. With out here subjecting to scrutiny this supposition of multiple unin telligent forces in Nature, it is still indisputable that, if matter is "blind," incapable of foreseeing the end to be attained, and of selecting appropriate means, it is "necessary to connect it with the operation of an intelligent author and his present agency. THE ARGUMENTS FOR THE BEING OF GOD 39 The accurate mathematics of the planetary bodies, the unerring path of the birds, the geometry of the bee, the seed-corn sending upward the blossoming and fruit-bearing stalk, excite a wonder, the secret of which is the evident inadequacy of any " blind " power to effect these marvels of intelligence and foresight. A popular objection to the argument of design imputes to it the fallacy of confounding use with forethought or intention. Is not the eye for seeing ? Yes, it is answered, that is its use or function ; but this is not to say that it was planned for this use or function, for, when you affirm design, you go back to a mental act. The rejoinder is, that we are driven back to such a mental act, and thus to a designing intelligence. The relation of the constitution of the organ to the use irresistibly prompts the inference. The inference is no arbitrary fancy. Design is brought home to us, just as the relation of the structure of a telescope to its use would of itself compel us to attribute it to a contriving intelligence. It is objected to the argument of design that what are styled adaptations are nothing but " the conditions of existence " of objects in nature. These conditions being what they are, the various objects in which design is supposed to be shown could not be different from what they are. For example, the bird is said to be adapted to the air through which it flies, and, it is said, could not exist but for the air in which its wings are moved. The objection is equivalent to an attempt to explain the objects of nature by mechanical agencies and conditions. If the existence of the bird were traceable to primitive atoms, it would follow that these are purposeful. In truth we find use so related to structure that the thought of design springs up unbidden. By clear-sighted naturalists who give large room for the potential ity of protoplasm and its plasticity under the conditions of environ ment, design is recognized as the means to a preconceived end. Function or future use is seen to be the formative idea which specializes organs, and determines structure. An acute naturalist thus writes upon sexual differences, one of the most impressive illustrations of design : — " Instead of thus eliminating by degrees every trace of finality in sex uality, till we merge into merely mechanical results, is it not just as log ical to say that the sexuality of mammalia and flowering plants was potentially visible in the conjugation of monera and Plasmodia t and 40 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF that the ' sexual idea ' has reigned throughout, function ever dominating structure, till the latter had conformed to the more complete function by becoming specialized more and more ? Or, in the words of Janet, < The agreement of several phenomena, bound together with a future determi nate phenomenon, supposes a cause in which that future phenomenon is ideally represented ; and the probability of the presumption increases with the complexity of the concordant phenomena and the number of relations which unite them to the final phenomena.' " * The writer last named also observes : — " Finality is certainly not destroyed, whether we believe organs to have been developed by evolution, or to have been created in some an alogous manner to the fabrication of a steam-engine by man. For my own part, I still hold to the theory that uses cause adaptations, on the principle that function precedes structure. Thus as a graminivorous animal has its food already (so to say) cut up into slices in grass-blades, it does not require scissors to reduce it to small pieces in order to make a convenient mouthful. But a carnivorous animal has a large lump of flesh in the shape of a carcass. It requires to cut it up. The action of biting, in order to do this previous to masticating, has converted its teeth into scissor-like carnassials ; and, as it can no longer masticate, it bolts the pieces whole. So, too, man would never have thought of mak ing scissors, unless he had had something that he wanted to cut up. The parallel is complete ; only in the one case it is spontaneously ef fected by the plasticity and adaptability of living matter, and in the other case it is artificially produced by the consciousness and skill of man." 2 To revert once more to the human eye : it is an instrument em ployed by a rational being for a purpose, as he employs a telescope or a microscope. When we see how the eye is fitted to its use, we cannot resist the impression that it was intended for it. The idea of the organ we discern. As Whewell well puts it : " We have in our minds the idea of a final cause, and when we behold the eye, we see our idea exemplified. This idea then governed the construc tion of the eye, be its mechanical causes, the operative agencies that produced it what they may." " Nothing," says an able writer, " has been proved against final causes when organic effects have been reduced to their proximate causes and to their deter mining conditions. It will be said, for instance, that it is not wonderful that the heart contracts, since it is a muscle, and con- 1 Janet, Final Causes, p. 55. "Final Causes," by Mr. George Henslow, in Modern Review, January, 1881. 2 Modern Review, loc. cit., p. 66. THE ARGUMENTS FOR THE BEING OF GOD 41 tractility is an essential property of muscles. But is it not evident that if nature wished to make a heart that contracts, it behooved to employ for this a contractile tissue, and would it not be very aston ishing were it otherwise ? Have we thereby explained the wonder ful structure of the heart and the skilful mechanism shown in it ? Muscular contractility explains the contraction of the heart ; but this general property, which is common to all muscles, does not suffice to explain how or why the heart contracts in one way rather than another, why it has taken such a form and not such another. ' The peculiarity presented by the heart,' says M. CI. Bernard, ' is that the muscular fibres are arranged in it so as to form a sort of bag, within which is found the liquid blood. The contraction of these fibres causes a diminution of the size of this bag, and consequently an expulsion, at least in part, of the liquid it contains. The arrangement of the valves gives to the expelled liquid the suitable direction.' Now the precise question which here occupies the thinker is, how it happens that Nature, employ ing a contractile tissue, has given it the suitable structure and arrangement, and how it rendered it fit for the special and capital function of the circulation." " The elementary properties of the tissues are the necessary conditions of which Nature makes use to solve the problem, but they in no way explain how it has succeeded in solving it. Moreover, M. CI. Bernard [a learned physiologist] does not decline the inevitable comparison of the organism with the works of human industry, and even often recurs to it, as, for instance, when he says ; ' the heart is essentially a living motor machine, a force-pump destined to send into all the organs a liquid to nourish them. ... At all degrees of the animal scale, the heart fulfils this function of mechanical irrigation.'' ... ' We may compare,' he says, ' the histological elements to the materials man employs to raise a monument. . . . No doubt, in order that a house may exist, the stones composing it must have the property of gravita tion ; but does this property explain how the stones form a house ? ' " x It might be said of a locomotive that — the boiler of iron, with its capacity to hold water, being present, and the water being in it, and fire beneath it, and a chimney above for the smoke to escape, and pipes through which steam can pass connected with the boiler and wheels beneath on which the locomotive can roll — it is suffi ciently explained. But the combination of these parts, in their 1 Janet, Final Causes, pp. 129-131. 42 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF peculiar forms, and relation of the whole to that which the loco motive does, are things which the foregoing statement altogether fails to account for. Kant has two criticisms on the argument of design. The first is, that it can go no farther than to prove an architect or framer of the world, not a creator of matter. But the special aim of the argument is to prove that the First Cause is intelligent. We will suppose for the moment that matter is such an entity as the criticism implies. The conclusion that the author of the wonder ful order which is wrought in and through matter is also the author of matter itself still appears probable. For how can the properties of matter through which it is adapted to the use of being moulded by intelligence, be separated from matter itself ? What is matter divorced from its properties ? We cannot under stand creation, because we cannot create. The nearest approach to creative activity is in the production of good and evil by our own voluntary action. How God creates is a mystery which can not be fathomed, at least until we know better what matter is. Philosophers of high repute so far favor hypotheses akin to the Berkeleian, as to dispense with a substratum of matter, and to as cribe the percepts of sense to the continuous action of the will of the Almighty. Whatever matter may be in its essence, we know that there is an ultimate, unconditioned cause. We know that this cause is intelligent and free. To suppose that by the side of the eternal Spirit there is another eternal and self-existent being, the raw matter of the world, " without form and void," involves the absurdity of two Absolutes limiting each other. The second difficulty raised by Kant is, that the existence of a strictly infinite being cannot be demonstrated from a finite creation, however extensive or wondrous. All that can be inferred demon stratively is inconceivably vast power and wisdom. The validity of this objection may be conceded. The infinitude of the attri butes of God is involved in the intuition of an unconditioned being, — the being glimpses of whose attributes are disclosed to us in the order of the finite world. These objections of Kant are in the Critique of Pure Reason. Elsewhere he brings forward an additional consideration. Admit ting that the idea of design is essential to our comprehension of the world, he raises the point that it may be subjective only, regu lative of our perceptions, but not objective or " constitutive." THE ARGUMENTS FOR THE BEING OF GOD 43 Not regarding the idea of design as a priori, like the idea of causation, he inquires whether it may not be a mere supposition, a working hypothesis, which a deeper penetration of Nature might dispense with. It is a sufficient answer to this scepticism that the thought of design is not artificially originated by ourselves ; it is a conviction which the objects of Nature themselves "imperiously" suggest and bring home to us. As Janet and other critics of Kant have pointed out, there are two classes of hypotheses. Of one class it is true that they are regarded as corresponding with the true nature of things ; of the other, that they are only a convenient means for the mind to conceive them. The question is, whether an hypothesis is warranted by the facts, and is perceived veritably to represent Nature. In the proportion in which it does this, its verity acquires fresh corroboration. Of this character is the hypothesis of design. We infer the existence of an intelligent Deity, as we infer the existence of intelligence in our fellow-men, and on grounds not less reasonable. " We are spirits clad in veils, Man by man was never seen ; All our deep communing fails To remove the shadowy screen." My senses take no cognizance of the minds of other men. I per ceive certain motions of their bodies. I hear certain sounds proceeding from their lips. What right have I, from these purely physical phenomena, to infer the presence of an intelligence behind them? What proof is there of the consciousness in the friend at my side? How can I be assured that he is not a mere automaton, totally unconscious of its own movements ? The war rant for the contrary inference lies in the fact, that being possessed of consciousness, and acquainted with its effects in myself, I regard like effects as evidence of the same principle in others. But in this inference I transcend the limits of sense and physical experiment. In truth, in admitting the reality of consciousness in myself, I take a step which no physical observation can justify. Were the brain opened to view, no microscope, were its power immeasurably aug mented, could discover the least trace of it. The alternative of design is chance. The Epicurean theory, as expounded by the Roman poet Lucretius, made the world the re- 44 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF suit of the fortuitous concourse of atoms, which in their motions and concussions, at length fell into the orderly forms in which they abide.1 The term " chance " does not denote the absence of cause — which would be an absurd supposition. The terms "chance " and "accident" are applied to events undesigned and unforeseen. We use these words to denote an occurrence, or an object the particular cause of which is not detected, and which bears in it evident marks of forethought. I drop a handful of coins on the floor. They fly in different directions, and the directions in which they fly, we say, are due to chance. On the theory which we are considering, the world is accounted for as the final result of what is equivalent to an almost infinite succession of throws of dice. This cannot be said to be literally impossible, as it is not literally impossible that a font of types thrown into the air should come down in the form of Homer's Iliad. It is, however, so unlikely an occurrence as to be next to impossible. Imagine time to be given for the repetition of the experiment billions of times — the unlikelihood of the issue is not perceptibly diminished. Cicero, commenting on this theory of the Epicureans, after speaking of the vast orderly system of things beheld above us and around us, exclaims : " Is it possible for any man to behold these things, and yet imagine that certain solid and individual bodies move by their natural force and gravitation, and that a world so beautifully adorned was made by their fortuitous concourse? He who believes this may as well believe that if a great quantity of the one-and-twenty letters — " the number of the letters in the Roman alphabet— " composed of gold or of any other matter, were thrown upon the ground, they would fall into such order as legibly to form the Annals of Ennius. ... If a concourse of atoms can make a world, why not a porch, a temple, a house, a city, which are works of less labor and difficulty?"2 But assume that the order of the universe is possible. The question is not whether it is pos sible, but whether it is possible without an intelligent cause. The Strasburg Minster is possible, but not possible without an archi tect and builder. If we accept the Lucretian hypothesis of the origin of the mate rial universe, as we behold it, from the movements of atoms after countless myriads of chaotic combinations, we do not get rid of 1 De Rerum Natura, i. 1021-1028. 2 De Nat. Deorum, ii. 37. THE ARGUMENTS FOR THE BEING OF GOD 45 the proof of design. Why did the multitudinous atoms fail to combine in an orderly and stable way up to the moment when the existing cosmos was reached? Manifestly they must have been, in their constitution and mutual relations, adapted to constitute the present structure of things, and no other. The present system was anticipated in the very make of the atoms, the constit uent elements of the universe. The atoms, then, present the same evidences of design which the outcome of their revolutions presents. We might be at a loss to explain why the Author of Nature chose this circuitous way to the goal ; but that the goal was in view from the beginning is evident. The difficulty of getting rid of the evi dence of final cause is illustrated in the circumstance that Haeckel actually attributes to atoms desire and aversion, or a soul both sen tient and volitional ! 1 The doctrine of evolution plays so conspicuous a part in the later discussions of Theism, that, at the risk of some repetition, it is worth while to examine critically its bearing on teleology. This doctrine undertakes to explain the diversity of animal species without resort to special acts of creation. As propounded by Darwin, it refers the origin of species to descent from a few pro genitors, the origin of whom, in his work on this subject, he ab stains from discussing. Some would extend evolutionary theory so far as to make life itself a development from inorganic forms, a view which thus far lacks support from scientific observation or experiment. In its widest extension, the network of evolutionary production is stretched over all things, living and lifeless, as far back as a nebulous vapor. Of those who believe in a genetic con nection of animal organisms, some hold to " heterogenetic gen eration," the production of new species by leaps, or by the metamorphosis of germs. Darwin's theory is that of unbroken development through minute variations. The law of heredity, under which like produces like, does not exclude in offspring slight variations without number. Darwin conceded that some inheritable variations might be produced by the conditions of the environment, but he maintained that, were variations perfectly indefinite in direction, his explanation of the origin of species would be tenable. The three causes in operation are the ten- 1 See the passage, with comments, in J. Martineau, Types of Ethical Theory, vol. ii. B. ii. Br. i. § 6, 2d ed. p. 399; also his Study of Religion, vol. i. p. 202. 46 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF dency of offspring to reproduce the forms of immediate or more or less remote ancestors, which Huxley denominates Atavism, the check on this tendency by a certain tendency to variation, and an influence from external conditions, such, for example, as climate.1 Among innumerable variations in structure, some are of such a nature as to give an advantage in the struggle for food and, gen erally speaking, in the struggle for existence. There ensues — in the phrase suggested by Spencer — "the survival of the fittest." As the effect of mating and propagation, these profitable varia tions grow, thereby imparting increased power, and lines of de marcation are created and perpetuated. Thus, in inconceivably long periods, definite and stable species arise. The process is called "natural selection," being analogous to the course pur sued in artificial breeding. The final effect of this kind of snail like advance through countless millenniums appears at last in the production of the human species. Another agency besides that of the struggle for existence, that of sexual preference, is a factor in working out the actual results of natural selection. The Darwinian doctrine, properly defined, lends additional strength to the argument of design. It brings before us a com prehensive system, which advances from the lowest forms of ani mal life until the terminus is reached in man. To quote the words of an eminent physiologist, Dr. W. B. Carpenter : — "The evidence of final causes is not impaired. 'We simply,' to use the language of Whewell, ' transfer the notion of design and end from the region of facts to that of laws ; ' that is, from the particular cases to the general plan. In this general plan the production of man is comprehended." At the same time, evolutionary theory does not annul the evi dence of adaptation in particular instances — in the eye, for ex ample—when regarded in its place and function in the human body, as the organ of vision. This function is so clear and unde niable that, whatever opinion may be held of the nature of per ception as a mental act, to withstand the proof of intention in the structure of this organ of vision is well-nigh impossible. Had Paley claimed for the principle of design an a priori basis and a universal application, it would have been well. Critics of Paley, however, seem often to forget that he devotes a whole 1 Huxley, Collected Essays, vol. ii. pp. 397-403. THE ARGUMENTS FOR THE BEING OF GOD 47 chapter (ch. ii.) to maintaining his ground on the supposition that the watch had the property of producing in the course of its movement another watch like itself. But the countless particular instances in Nature, when seen in their connection and place in the entire system, give to the proof of foresight and plan a redoubled force. Besides the single pillar, however exquisitely carved, we behold its relation to the vast edifice in which it has a fitting place. The system of animate beings has been likened to the cathedral of St. Mark, which owes its greatness " to the patient hands of cen turies and centuries of workers," and is built up from materials drawn from every quarter of the globe. After this analogy, the lower forms of animal life have contributed to the upbuilding of the human body. Even foreshadowings of mind antedate that stage of being wherein man, with his introspective vision and gift of language, is differentiated from the animal species beneath him. But man, erect in form, with reason enabling him to comprehend Nature, to know himself and the world of which he is a part, and with conscience and the capacity of religion — man is the goal to which Nature from the outset points. Now, when man appears, an end is put to the gradations of physical development. There is " an arrest of the body " ; Tor by means of his intelligence man fashions tools and instruments of every sort which enable him to do without additional and more complex physical organs. He can interchange thoughts with his fellows. He dominates the forces of material Nature. Henceforth, evolution is psychical. It is the story of the rise and of the stages in the progress of human civilization. The prolonging of the period of helpless in fancy is an essential condition of the evolution of motherhood. The permanent relation of husband and wife is dependent on physical characteristics which do not belong to the lower types of animal life. The being of the family, with the ties of affection developed within it, as well as the possibility of handing down a fund of knowledge to increase from generation to generation, are consequent on the birth of humanity with its distinctive peculiari ties. These were foreshadowed before, but never brought into being. A loftier stimulus than the struggle for existence — namely, altruism, a benevolent interest in others, and the spirit of self-sacri fice for their sake — sets bounds to self-love.1 1 For a more full statement of these particular features in the course of Evolution, see Drummond, The Ascent of Man, especially chs. iii. vii. 48 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF As to the agencies instrumental in building up the system of nature, it is plain that, in the first place, the origin of each requires to be explained ; in the second place, that their concurrence re quires to be accounted for ; and, in the third place, that neither separately considered nor taken in combination — regarded as blind, unintelligent forces — do they avail in the least to explain the order and adaptation of Nature which result from them. Why do living beings engender offspring like themselves? Why do the offspring slightly vary from the parents and from one another? How account for the desire of food ? How explain the disposi tion to struggle to obtain it? Why is beauty preferred, leading to " sexual selection " ? How is it that these laws coexist and co operate ? We see that they issue, according to the Darwinian view, in a grand result, a system of living beings. They are actually means to an intelligible end. They appear to exist, to be ordained and established, with reference to it. There is a " survival of the fittest." Who are the "fittest" except those who have been fitted to a given end? But how were "the fittest" produced? Natural selection merely weeds out and destroys the products which are not the fittest. It produces nothing. But it operates, in conjunction with the force described as " heredity," which includes "variability," to work out an order of things which plainly shows itself to have been preconceived. The selection, as far as it is positive, is dictated by stimuli within the organism. The fallacy of excluding design or final causes where it is possible to trace out efficient or instrumental causes would be astonishing if it were not so frequently met with. There is nothing in gradualness of development to disprove teleology. The progress of a pedestrian to a place a mile distant, by steps an inch long, presupposes volition and purpose as truly as if he had reached the place at a single bound. So it is with the continuity ascribed to Nature by the evolutionist. It were to be wished that all naturalists were as discriminating as Professor Owen, who says : — " Natural evolution by means of slow physical and organic operations through long ages is not the less clearly recognizable as the act of all- adaptive mind, because we have abandoned the old error of supposing it to be the result of a primary, direct, and sudden act of creational con struction. . . The succession of species by continuously operating law is not necessarily a ' blind operation.' Such law, however discerned THE ARGUMENTS FOR THE BEING OF GOD 49 in the properties of natural objects, intimates, nevertheless, a precon ceived progress. Organisms may be evolved in orderly manner, stage after stage, towards a foreseen goal, and the broad features of the course may still show the unmistakable impress of divine volition." ] Evolution has to do with the how, and not the why, of phenom ena. Evolution is a method, not an agent. Hence the evolution ist is powerless against the teleological argument. This is true of the theory of evolution in the widest stretch that the boldest speculation has given it. This is conceded, even if not consis tently, by its considerate advocates. This harmony of evolution with design is not denied by Huxley : — "The teleological and the mechanical views of nature are not neces sarily mutually exclusive. On the contrary, the more purely a mechan ist the speculator is, the more firmly does he affirm primordial nebular arrangement, of which all the phenomena of the universe are conse quences, the more completely is he thereby at the mercy of the teleolo- gist, who can always defy him to disprove that this primordial nebular arrangement was not intended to evolve the phenomena of the uni verse." 2 This intention is recognized in the outcome as related to the concurrent agencies leading to it, as well as in the constitution of these primordial agencies, — recognized by the same faculty of reason through which we are made capable of tracing phenomena to their physical causes. The antecedent idea is throughout controlling. Darwin himself was often impressed by the marks of design in the development of animal life, but he confessed to a perplexity and consequent scepticism on this point from the circumstance that the phenomena of variation seemed to him to be due to " chance." " This," as he explained later, " is a wholly incorrect expression, which simply indicates an ignorance of the cause of each particu lar variation." 3 He was puzzled by what he conceived to be the fact that variability shows nothing like adaptation to the prospective function of natural selection. Variability appeared to him to be, 1 Transactions of the Geological Society, vol. v. p. 90, quoted by Mivart, The Genesis of Species, p. 274. 2 Huxley, Critiques, p. 307. For other passages from Huxley, one in a less philosophical spirit, see Appendix, Note 2. 3 Origin of Species, vol. i. p. 137, vol. ii. p. 431. 50 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF figuratively speaking, haphazard. The materials for natural selec tion to do its work with, he compared to the numerous fragments of stone, of all shapes and sizes, which might be produced by the breaking up of a precipice by natural forces, including storm and earthquake. The builder picks out from the chaotic heap such fragments as he can work into the structure of his edifice. Hence to Darwin there seemed to be an antinomy, an irreconcilable con tradiction x — like what he conceived to exist between free-will and foreknowledge. He has no thought of denying that there are laws of variation. " Our ignorance," he says, " of the laws of variation is profound." 2 But what they are, what the causes of variation in plants and animals are, is a problem which he left unsolved.3 "Darwin," says Huxley, " left the causes of variation, and whether it is limited or directed by extended conditions, perfectly open. But in the immediate consequences of variability, he could not perceive marks of design, but rather the opposite. In other words, he missed a link in the process of rational development ; there seemed to be a vacancy — a place where foresight and plan are suspended, and control is left to chance." 4 Be this as it may, the organism and the conditions in which it lives, work out a result which exhibits clearly 1 Animals and Plants under Domestication, vol. ii. p. 428. 2 The impressions of Darwin are avowed with his wonted candor, especially in his correspondence with Asa Gray. Darwin's letters are in vol. ii. of The Life of Darwin. He speaks of" undesigned variability " (ii. 165), from which no definite results would follow. "I am conscious," he writes, "that I am in an utterly hopeless muddle. I cannot think that the world as we see it, is the result of chance, and yet I cannot look upon each separate thing as the result of Design " (ii. 146) . He writes in an earlier letter : " I am inclined to look at everything as resulting from designed laws, with the details, whether good or bad, left to the working out of what we may call chance. Not that this at all satisfies me" (ii. 105). He would have no doubt of design if he could " thoroughly " believe that there is any other " imponderable force " of which life and mind are the " function " ; that is to say, if he could believe that there is a designer — distinct from mechanical forces active in natural selection — for the designing of things to be assigned to (ii. 170). But "the forces active in natural selection," that is, in living organisms and their envi ronment, collectively taken, issue in the distinct species of animal and vege table life. In this product a rationality is to be discerned which implies that intention is involved in the existence and activity of the agencies, collectively taken, on which it depends. 8 See, respecting Darwin's views, Appendix,Note 3. 4 Huxley 's Life and Letters, vol. ii. p. 205 ; also, his article on " Mr. Darwin's Critics," Collected Essays, vol. ii. p. 120. For the advance of the theory of evolution, he says, the great need is a theory of variation. Ibid., p. 182. THE ARGUMENTS FOR THE BEING OF GOD 51 a designing agent. There is no room for denial that, as Mr. Sully expresses it, " every doctrine of evolution must assume some defi nite initial arrangement which is supposed to contain the possibili ties of the order which we find to be evolved, and no other possibility. This undeniable truth subverts every hypothesis which would substitute chance for design." But there is too much dissent from the supposition of limitless variability to reason upon it as a basis for scientific argument. Out of variations, says one critic, there must appear individual peculiarities adapted to give success in the struggle for existence. Then, in " this ocean of fluctuation and metaphorphosis," variations coinciding with these must appear, from generation to generation, to join on to them and to build up a highly organized species. The series of chances required to be overcome is infinite. If this were not the fact, the physiologist, Dr. W. B. Carpenter argues, the chances to be overcome in building up an organized species are infinite. " On the hypothesis of ' natural selection ' among aimless variations," says Dr. Carpenter, " I think that it could be shown that the probability is infinitely small that the progressive modifications required in the structure of each individual organ to convert a reptile into a bird could have taken place without disturbing the required harmony in their combined action ; nothing but intentional variations being competent to bring such a result." The proof of this prearrangement is furnished " by the orderly sequence of variations following definite lines of ad vance. It would be necessary to presuppose a miracle of luck. There is not, as in artificial breeding, a seclusion of favored offspring from their kin. Moreover, mere selection on the basis of aimless variability will not account for organs and members, which, however useful when fully grown, in their beginnings do not help, and may hinder the animal in its struggle for existence. From the geological record, which, to be sure, is defective, support cannot be drawn for the theory." Profes sor Huxley himself suggests that " further inquiries may prove that vari ability is definite, and is determined in certain directions rather than others. It is quite conceivable that every species tends to produce varieties of a limited number and kind, and that the effect of natural selection is to favor the development of some of these, while it opposes the development of others, along their predetermined lines of modifica tion." 1 The response of the organism to exterior influences is deter mined by impulses within itself. This is the teaching of eminent naturalists, such as Owen and Virchow. Dana held that variation is limited by " fundamental laws." Gray, an able advocate of Darwin's general theory, teaches that " variations " — in other words, " the 1 Encycl. Brit., vol. viii. p. 751, art. "Evolution." 52 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF differences between plants and animals — are evidently not from without, but from within; not physical, but physiological." The occult power " does not act vaguely, producing all sorts of variations from a common centre," etc. " The facts, so far as I can judge, do not support the assumption of every-sided and indifferent variation. Vari ation is somehow and somewhere introduced in the transit from parent to offspring. ... It is generally agreed that the variation is from within, is an internal response to external impressions. All that we can possibly know of the nature of the inherent tendency to vary must be gathered from the facts of the response. And these, I judge, are not such as to require or support the assumption of a tendency to wholly vague and all-directioned variation." 1 He affirms, that " as species do not now vary at all times and places, and in all directions, nor produce crude, vague, imperfect, and useless forms, there is no reason for sup posing that they ever did." 2 The philosopher Von Hartmann in geniously compares natural selection to the bolt and coupling in a machine, but affirms that " the driving principle,'' which called new species into existence, lay or originated in the organisms.3 Darwin, in his Descent of Man, frankly allowed that he has exaggerated natural selection as a cause, since it fails to account for structures which are neither beneficial nor injurious. Here, as in regard to the correlation of parts and organs, or " sympathetic " variation, he falls back on mystery. The fact of the sterility of hybrids has no explanation. In both cases, teleology cannot be dispensed with. The upshot of the matter is, that there is no occasion for puzzling over the design of chaotic and purposeless variations, — the stones of all shapes at the base of the precipice, — until a final verdict of natural science has been reached. Be the conclusion on this point what it may, the effects of variation must be considered an actual link in the series of causes, the outcome of which is an orderly and beautiful system of organized beings. Were there such a thing in nature as " aimless variability," the objection to the theistic argument, suggested by it, would be akin to the objection sometimes heard " from the waste of life and material " in organic nature, where the phenomena in question are familiar. In parts of both the vegetable and animal kingdoms, 1 Natural Science and Religion, p. 50. So stout an advocate of Darwinian doctrine as Huxley remarks concerning the effect of external conditions, climate, etc., on variations, " In all probability the influence of this cause has been very much exaggerated." Collected Essays, vol. ii. p. 182. 2 Darwiniana, pp. 386, 387. 8 See R. Schmid, The Theories of Darwin, etc., p. 107. THE ARGUMENTS FOR THE BEING OF GOD 53 we find a redundancy of germs and eggs. Blossoms numberless bear no fruit. Facts of this sort do not militate against the proof of design. The only doubt which they could inspire, must relate to the perfection of wisdom and skill in the Creator. It might be answered that the very notion of wastefulness involves the need less and useless sacrifice of that which is at the same time pos sessed of value, and provided not without cost of money or labor. If all the difficulty connected by Darwin with variability existed, it would be well to bear in mind an observation of Huxley : " There is a wide gulf between the thing you cannot explain and the thing that upsets you altogether. There is hardly any hypothe sis in this world which has not some fact in connection with it, which has not been explained."1 Gray presents from his own science of botany illustrations of usefulness in this " waste of life and material." One of them is afforded by the different means of dispersing the pollen of flowers.2 Darwin's own writings, one of which is entitled On the Contrivances in Nature for the Fertiliza tion of Orchids, are quite helpful in this same direction. The Darwinian hypothesis, in its essential principle, goes far toward disposing of the sceptical difficulties of the kind referred to. This is through what has been denominated " the comprehensive and far-reaching teleology," by which " organs and even faculties, use less to the individual, find their explanation and reason of being." Before closing this discussion, it is expedient to notice briefly a few not uncommon misconceptions of the argument of design, to which its advocates as well as dissentients are exposed. A fruitful error is the failure to perceive that a multitude of things in Nature which, regarded individually, might be judged to be unwise and even baneful, are incidental to a system of general laws, the ex istence of which is in the highest degree expedient. The law of heredity brings in its train numerous evils, yet it is, on the whole, an essential benefit. A conclusion unfavorable to the skill or to the benevolence of the architect of the world, is frequently based on the absence of what is deemed an ideal perfection in some part of Nature — it may be an organ in the human body. Thus a justly distinguished naturalist, Helmholtz, criticises the structure of the human eye, contrasting it with certain optical instruments of human invention. Yet he closes with a statement which is the main point in the 1 Huxley, Collected Essays, vol. ii. p. 466. 2 Darwiniana, pp. 375 seq. 54 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF argument of design : " The adaptation of the eye to its function is, therefore, most complete, and is seen in the very limits set to its defects. Here, the result which may be reached by innumerable generations working under the Darwinian law of inheritance, coin cides with what the wisest wisdom may have devised beforehand." ] It has often been taken for granted by theologians, or wrongly assumed to be their contention, that the world and everything in it was designed exclusively as a manifestation of the Creator to the human race. Hence everything not capable of this limited construction has been looked upon as, to say the least, super fluous. A lesson of modesty is contained in the familiar lines of Gray : — " Full many a gem of purest ray serene The dark unfathomed caves of ocean bear, Full many a flower is born to blush unseen And waste its sweetness on the desert air." Every gem and every blossom manifests in its very structure a pur pose, even without reference to the impression it is adapted to make on human observers. But one of the motives of their creation may be the self-expression, for its own sake, of the Author of their being.2 Still further, the partial if not complete hy pothesis has been virtually sanctioned that everything in the broad realm of nature was fashioned as an instrument to convey a specific benefit, larger or smaller, to the race of man, or to a portion of it. It is one thing to say that in innumerable arrangements the benevo lence of God is convincingly discovered. But to affirm this of every being and thing, simply leads to the caricature of the true view. To call in the idea of a distinct purpose, to account for the creation of whatever the convenience of man, aided by his ingenuity, may turn to some use, argues either impiety or ignorance. Especially presumptuous and misleading is the implied omniscience which professes to comprehend in full the final end of creation and providence, and to derive thence an infallible criterion for setting the right value on whatever is and whatever occurs. Apart from 1 See the comments of J. Martineau, A Study of Religion, vol. ii. B. ii. u I. P- 343- 2 Quite apart from peculiar adjuncts in his system, one may recognize truth in Professor Royce's emphatic words on what he calls the " Philistinism " "which supposes that Nature has no worthier goal than producing a man, Perhaps experiences of longer time-span are far higher in rational type than ours." The World and the Individual, p. 231. THE ARGUMENTS FOR THE BEING OF GOD 55 revealed truth, it is clear enough that "we know in part" and are incompetent otherwise to apprehend " the one far-off divine event, To which the whole creation moves." It is conceded that the argument of design does not demon strate the infinitude of God's power and wisdom. It is here that the ontological argument, or that which is the real gist of it, the intuition of the Infinite and Absolute, comes in to convert into a conviction the feeling that is begotten in the mind, in the form of an immediate suggestion by the inconceivably vast manifesta tion of these attributes of God in the universe, as far as our human vision can extend. The unconditioned being is independent of limitations inseparable from finite beings. The intuition of unconditioned being involves the infinitude of his natural attri butes. He is independent of temporal limitations ; that is, he is eternal. He is independent of spatial limitations ; that is, he is omnipresent. The categories of space and time cannot be ap plied to him, — a truth which we can only express by saying that he is above time and space. His power is infinite ; that is, it can do everything which is an object of power, and it admits of no imaginable increase. His knowledge, since final causes reveal his personality, is equally without limit. IV. The moral argument. The righteousness and goodness of God are evident from conscience. The phenomena, which have been shown to be the immediate source of faith in God,1 on re flection are seen to be valid in logic. Right is the supreme, sole authoritative impulse in the soul. He who planted it there, and gave it this imperative character, must himself be righteous. From the testimony of "the vicegerent within the heart" we in fer " the righteousness of the Sovereign who placed it there." But what are the contents of the law? What has he bidden man, by " the law written on the heart," to be and to do ? He has enjoined goodness. When we discover that the precept of the unwritten law of conscience is love, we have the clearest and most undeniable evidence that love is the preference of the Law giver, and that he is love. The argument from conscience is really a branch of the argu- 1 See ch. i. 56 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF ment from final causes. In this inward law there is revealed the end of our being, — an end not to be realized as if a part of physical nature, but freely. We are to make ourselves what our Maker designed us to be. The law is the ideal, the thought of the Creator, and a spur to its realization. It attests the holiness of God, as design in the external world reveals His intelligence. This truth is forcibly expressed by Erskine of Linlathen : " When I attentively consider what is going on in my conscience, the chief thing forced on my notice is, that I find myself face to face with a purpose — not my own, for I am often conscious of resisting it, but which dominates me, and makes itself felt as ever present, as the very root and reason of my being." "This consciousness of a purpose concerning me that I should be a good man — right, true, and unselfish — is the first firm footing I have in the region of religious thought ; for I cannot dissociate the idea of a purpose from that of a purposer ; and I cannot but identify this Purposer with the Author of my being and the being of all beings, and further, I cannot but regard his purpose toward me as the unmis takable indication of his own character." 1 Is this conviction, which the very constitution of our being com pels us to cherish, contradicted by the course of the world? There is moral evil in the world. But of moral evil, although He permits it, He is not the author. Nor can this permission be pro nounced unrighteous or unbenevolent, until it is proved that there are no incompatibilities between the most beneficent system of created things, including beings endowed, to the extent with which men are endowed, with free agency, and the exclusion, by direct power, of all abuse of that divine gift by which man resembles his Crea tor. Permission on this ground is not to be confounded with preference of moral evil to its opposite. If it were made probable that the bare permission of moral evil, so far as it actually exists in the world, is inconsistent with infinite power and infinite good ness, or with both, the result would simply be a contradiction between the revelation of God in our intuition of unconditioned being and in our own moral nature, and the disclosure of Him in the course of the world.2 We are in a world that abounds in suffering. How shall this be reconciled with benevolence in the Creator? Much weight 1 The Spiritual Order and Other Papers, pp. 47, 48. " See Appendix, Note 4. THE ARGUMENTS FOR THE BEING OF GOD 57 is to be given to the consideration of the effects flowing of neces sity from a system of general laws, notwithstanding the advantages of such a system. The suggestions relative to the occasions and beneficent offices of pain and death, which are presented by such writers as James Martineau, in his work entitled A Study of Reli gion, are helpful. Especially is the fact of moral evil to be taken into the account when a solution is sought for the problem of physical evil, its concomitant and so often its consequence. Let it be freely granted, however, that no explanations that man can devise avail to clear up altogether the mystery of evil. It is only a small part of the system of things that falls under our observa tion in the present stage of our being. It is not by an inductive argument, by showing a preponderance of good over evil in the arrangements of nature, that the mind is set at rest. There is no need of an argument of this kind. There is need of faith, but that faith is rational. We find, as we have pointed out, in our own moral constitution a direct and full attestation of the good ness of God. Our moral constitution is affirmed, by a class of evolutionists, to be a gradual growth from a foundation of animal instincts. Let this speculation go for what it may be worth. The same theory is advanced respecting the human intellect. Yet the intellect is assumed to be an organ of knowledge. There is no avoiding this conclusion, else all science, evolutionary science in cluded, is a castle in the air. If the intellect is entitled to trust, so equally is the moral nature. Are the righteousness and good ness of God called in question on the ground of perplexing facts observed in the structure and course of the world? Where do we get the qualifications for raising such inquiries or rendering an answer to them ? It must be from ideals of character which we find within ourselves, and from the supreme place accorded to the moral law which is written on the heart. But whence come these moral ideals? Who enthroned the law of righteousness in the heart? Who inscribed on the tablets of the soul the assertion of the inviolable authority of right and the absolute worth of love as a motive of action ? In a word, our moral constitution is itself given us of God, and if it be not the reflection of His character, it is, for aught we can say, a false light ; in which case all the ver dicts resting upon it, with all the queries of scepticism as to the goodness of God, may be illusive. The arraignment of the char acter of God on the ground of alleged imperfections in nature or 58 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF of seemingly harsh or unjust occurrences in the course of events, is therefore suicidal. The revelation of God's character is in our moral constitution. The voice within us, which is uttered in the sacred impulse of duty and in the law of love, is His voice. There we learn what He approves, what He requires, what He rewards. When this proposition is denied, we lose our footing; we cut away the ground for trust in our own capacity for moral criticism. Man has not one originating cause and the world another. The existence and supreme authority of conscience imply that in the on-going of the world righteousness holds sway. If there is a moral purpose underlying the course of things, then a righteous Being is at the helm. What confusion worse than chaos in the idea that while man himself is bound to be actuated by a moral purpose, the universe in which he is to act his part exists for no moral end, and that through the course of things no moral pur pose runs ! Even Kant, who bases our conviction as to the fundamental truths of religion on moral grounds, and asserts for it, not a strictly logical, but a moral, certainty, nevertheless declares this convic tion to be inevitable where there exist right moral dispositions. " The only caution to be observed," he says, " is that this faith of the intellect ( Vernunftglaube) is founded on the assumption of moral tempers." If one were utterly indifferent to moral laws, even then the conclusion "would still be supported indeed by strong arguments from analogy, but not by such as an obstinate sceptical bent might not overcome." It is not my object in these remarks to draw out in full the proofs of the existence and the moral attributes of God. It is rather to illustrate the relation in which these proofs stand to those perceptions, inchoate and spontaneous in the experiences of the soul, which are the ultimate subjective source of religion, and on which the living appreciation of the revelation of God in external nature is contingent. Let it be observed, moreover, that these native spiritual experiences of dependence, of obligation and accountableness, of hunger for fellowship with the Infinite One, wherein religion takes its rise and has its root, are them selves to be counted as proofs of the reality of the object implied in them. They are significant of the end for which man was made. They presuppose God. It is true that all our knowledge rests ultimately on an act of THE ARGUMENTS FOR THE BEING OF GOD 59 faith which finds no warrant in any process of reasoning. We cannot climb to this trust on the steps of a syllogism. We are obliged to start with a confidence in the veracity of our intellec tual faculties ; and this we have to assume persistently in the whole work of acquiring knowledge. Without this assumption we can no more infer anything or know anything than a bird can fly in a vacuum. All science reposes on this faith in our own minds, which implies and includes faith in the Author of the mind. This primitive faith in ourselves is moral in its nature. So of all that truth which is justly called self-evident. No arguments are to be adduced for it. In every process of reasoning it is presupposed. We can prove nothing except on the basis of propositions that admit of no proof. But if we leave out of account the domain of self-evident truth, which is ground common to both religion and science, religious beliefs, as far as they are sound, are based on adequate evidence. V. The historical argument. The philosophy of history is synonymous with the unveiling of the plan revealed in the course of human affairs. The discovery of this plan is the chief motive in the study of history, without which it would have, as it has been truly said, little more interest than the record of the battles of crows and daws. Divine providence is discerned in the fact that — "through the ages one increasing purpose runs." Hegel presents us with profound observations on the philosophy of history, notwithstanding the alloy of a priori speculation mingled with them. The thought that reason is the " sovereign of the world," he tells us, is the hypothesis in the domain of history which it verifies. Hegel shares in the approval given by Socrates to the remark of Anaxagoras that reason or intelligence governs the world, and quotes the saying of Aristotle that in this saying Anaxagoras " appeared as a sober man among the drunken," in ascribing nothing to chance. " The truth," Hegel adds, " that a providence, that of God, presides over the events of the world, consorts with that proposition." x History, as containing at once a providential order and a moral order enclosed within it, discovers God. Events do not take place in a chaotic series. A progress is discernible, an orderly succession of phenomena, the accomplishment of ends by the 1 Hegel, Philosophy of History, Sibree's Transl., pp. 9, 12, 13. 60 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF concurrence of agencies beyond the power of individuals to origi nate or combine. There is a Power that " makes for righteous ness." Amid all the disorder of the world, as Bishop Butler has convincingly shown, there is manifested on the part of the Power which governs, an approbation of right and a condemnation of wrong, analogous to the manifestation of justice and holiness which emanates from righteous rulers among men. If righteous ness appears to be but imperfectly carried out, it is an indication that in this fife the system is incomplete, and that here we see only its beginnings. In order to disprove the rectitude or the power of the divine Sovereign, the assailant must first make good the contention that the system as here seen is complete. On him rests the burden of proof. It is objected to the belief that God is personal, that personality implies limitation, and that, if personal, God could not be infinite and absolute. " Infinite " (and the same is true of " absolute ") is an adjective, not a substantive. When used as a noun, pre ceded by the definite article, it signifies not a being, but an ab straction. When it stands as a predicate, as remarked before, it means that the subject, be it space, time, or some quality of a being, is without limit. Thus, when I affirm that space is infinite, I express a positive perception, or thought. I mean not only that imagination can set no bounds to space, but also that this inability is owing, not to any defect in the imagination or conceptive fac ulty, but to the nature of the object. When I say that God is in finite in power, I mean that He can do all things which are objects of power, or that His power is incapable of increase. No amount of power could be added to the power of which He is possessed. It is only when " the Infinite " is erroneously taken as the synonym of the sum of all existence, that personality is made to be incom patible with God's infinitude. No such conception of Him is needed for the satisfaction of the reason or the heart of man. Enough that He is the ground of the existence of all beings outside of Himself, or the creative and sustaining Power. There are no limitations upon His power which He has not voluntarily set. Such limitation — as in giving life to rational agents capable of self- determination, and in allowing them scope for its exercise — is not imposed on Him, but depends on His own choice. An absolute being is independent of all other beings for its THE ARGUMENTS FOR THE BEING OF GOD 6 1 existence and for the full realization of its nature. It is con tended that inasmuch as self-consciousness is conditioned on the distinction of the ego from the non-ego, the subject from the object, a personal being cannot have the attribute of self-existence, can not be absolute. Without some other existence than himself, a being cannot be self-conscious. The answer to this is, that the premise is an unwarranted generalization from what is true in the case of the human, finite, dependent personality of man, which is developed in connection with a body, and is only one of numer ous finite personalities under the same class. To assert that self- consciousness cannot exist independently of such conditions, because it is through them that I come to a knowledge of myself, is a great leap in logic. The proposition that man is in the image of God does not necessarily imply that the divine intelligence is subject to the restrictions and infirmities that belong to the human. It is not implied that God ascertains truth by a gradual process of investigation or of reasoning, or that He deliberates on a plan of action, and casts about for the appropriate means of executing it. These limitations are characteristic, not of intelligence in itself, but of finite intelligence. It is meant that He is not an imper sonal principle or occult force, but is self-conscious and self- determining. Nor is it asserted that He is perfectly comprehensible by us. Far from it. It is not pretended that we are able fully to think away the limitations which cleave to us in our character as dependent and finite, and to frame thus an adequate conception of a person infinite and absolute. Nevertheless, the existence of such a person, whom we can apprehend if not comprehend, is verified to our minds by sufficient evidence. Pantheism, with its immanent Absolute, void of personal attributes, and its self-devel oping universe, postulates a deity limited, subject to change, and reaching self-consciousness — if it is ever reached — only in men. And Pantheism, when it denies the free and responsible nature of man, maims the creature whom it pretends to deify, and anni hilates not only morality, but religion also, in any proper sense of the term. The citadel of Theism is in the consciousness of our own per sonality. Within ourselves God reveals himself more directly than through any other channel. He impinges, so to speak, on the soul which finds in its primitive activity an intimation and impli cation of an unconditioned Cause on whom it is dependent, — a 62 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF Cause self-conscious like itself, and speaking with holy authority in conscience, wherein also is presented the end which the soul is to pursue through its own free self-determination, — an end which could only be set by a Being both intelligent and holy. The yearning for fellowship with the Being thus revealed — indis tinct though it be, well-nigh stifled by absorption in finite objects and in the vain quest for rest and joy in them — is inseparable from human nature. There is an unappeased thirst in the soul when cut off from God. It seeks for " living water." Atheism is an insult to humanity. A good man is a man with a purpose, a righteous purpose. He aims at well-being, — at the well-being of himself and of the world of which he forms a part. This end he pursues seriously and earnestly, and feels bound to pursue, let the cost to himself be what it may. To tell him that while he is under a sacred obligation to have this purpose, and pursue this end, there is yet no purpose or end in the universe in which he is acting his part — what is this but to offer a gross affront to his reason and moral sense ? He is to abstain from frivolity ; he is to act from an intelligent purpose, for the accomplishment of rational ends ; but the universe, he is told, is the offspring of gigantic frivolity. The latter is without purpose or end; there chance or blind fate rules. CHAPTER III THE PRINCIPAL ANTI-THEISTIC THEORIES : PANTHEISM, POSITIVISM, MATERIALISM, AGNOSTICISM The three inseparable, yet distinct, data of consciousness are self, material nature, and God. Pantheism would merge the first two in the third — in its essence an impersonal Deity. Materi alism would merge the first and the third in the second, and so deify matter. Positivism abjures belief in all three, and resolves the universe, so far as we have any means of knowing, into a "Succession of appearances." Agnosticism would place behind these phenomena an inscrutable " energy," its definition of the third element. Pantheism identifies God with the world, or the sum total of being. It differs from Atheism in holding to something besides and beneath finite things, — an all-pervading Cause or Essence. It differs from Deism in denying that God is separate from the world, and that the world is sustained and guided by energies exerted from without. It does not differ from Theism in affirm ing the immanence of God, for on this Theism likewise insists ; but it differs from Theism in denying to the immanent Power dis tinct consciousness and will, and an existence not dependent on the world. Pantheism denies, and Theism asserts, creation. With the denial to God of will and conscious intelligence, Panthe ism excludes design. Finite things emerge into being, and pass away, and the course of nature proceeds through the perpetual operation of an agency which has no cognizance of its work except so far as it may arrive at self-consciousness in man. In the system of Spinoza, the most celebrated and influential of modern Pantheists, it is asserted that there is, and can be, but one substance, — una et unica substantia. Of the infinite number of infinite attributes which constitute the one substance, two are discerned by us, — extension and thought. These, distinct in our perception, are not disparate in the substance. Both being mani- 63 64 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF festations of a simple identical essence, the order of existence is parallel to the order of thought. All individual things are modes of one or the other of the attributes, that is, of the substance as far as it is discerned by us. There is a complete correspondence or harmony, although there is no reciprocal influence, between bodies and minds. But the modes do not make up the substance, which is prior to them ; they are transient as ripples on the surface of the sea. The imagination regards them as entities; but reason looks beneath them, to the eternal essence of which they are but a fleeting manifestation. No philosopher, with the possible exception of Aristotle, has been more lauded for his rigorous logic than Spinoza. In truth, few philosophers have included more fallacies in the exposition of their systems. The pages of the Ethics swarm with paralogisms, all veiled under the forms of rigid mathematical statement. His fundamental definitions, whatever verbal precision may belong to them, are, as regards the realities of being, unproved assumptions. His reasoning, from beginning to end, is vitiated by the realistic presupposition that the actual existence of a being can be inferred from the definition of a word. He falls into this mistake of find ing proof of the reality of a thing from the contents of a concep tion, in his very first definition, where he says, " By that which is the cause of itself, I understand that whose essence involves exist ence, or that whose nature can only be conceived as existent." His argument is an argument from definitions, without having offered proof of the existence of the thing defined. Spinoza fails to prove that only one substance can exist, and that no other sub stance can be brought into being which is capable of self-activity, though dependent for the origin and continuance of its existence upon another. Why the one and simple substance should have modes ; why it should have these discoverable modes, and no other ; how the modes of thought and extension are made to run parallel with each other ; how the infinite variety of modes, em bracing stars and suns, men and animals, minds and bodies, and all other finite things, are derived in their order and place, — these are problems with regard to which the system of Spinoza, though professing to explain the universe by a method purely de ductive, leaves us wholly in the dark.1 1 One of the hard questions proposed to Spinoza by Tschirnhausern, his correspondent, was, how the existence and variety of external things is to be THE PRINCIPAL ANTI-THEISTIC THEORIES 65 The ideal Pantheism of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel pursues a different path. It undertakes still to unveil the Absolute Being, and from the Absolute to trace the evolution of all concrete exist ences, mental and material. The Absolute in Fichte is the univer sal ego, of which individual minds, together with external things, the objects of thought, are the phenomenal product, — a univer sal ego which is void of consciousness, and of which it is vain to attempt to form a conception. The impression we have of exter nality is from the check put upon the self-activity of the mind by its own inward law. From this Solipsism — Panegoism, it is some times styled — Fichte sought in his ethical philosophy for a place for a plurality of egos, and a substitute for Theism in the system of moral order. Schelling, avoiding Idealism, made the Absolute the point of indifference and common basis of subject and object. For the perception of this impersonal Deity, which is assumed to be indefinable, and not an object of thought, he postulated an impossible faculty of intellectual intuition, wherein the individual escapes from himself, and soars above the conditions or essential limits of conscious thinking in a finite mind. Hegel advances upon the same path. He discerns and repudiates the one-sided position of Kant in resolving our knowledge of nature, beyond the bare fact of its existence, into a subjective process. The divine reason is immanent in the world and apprehensible by man. There is a rationality in nature and in human history. But Hegel swings to the opposite extreme, and identifies object and subject, thing and thinker, as in essence one. Starting, like Schelling, with this assumption that subject and object, thought and thing, are identi cal, he ventures on the bold emprise of setting down all the suc cessive stages through which thought in its absolute or most general form, by means of a kind of momentum assumed to inhere in it, develops the entire chain of concepts, or the whole variety and aggregate of particular existences, up to the point where, in the mental movement of the philosopher, the universe thus constituted attains to complete self-consciousness. In the logic of Hegel, we are told, the universe reveals itself to the spectator with no aid from experience in the process of its self-unfolding. The complex organism of thought, which is identical with the world of being, evolves itself under his eye. deduced from the attribute of extension. See Pollock, Spinoza, His Life and Philosophy, p. 173. 66 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF There is a difficulty, to begin with, in this self-evolving of " the idea." Motion is presupposed, and motion is a conception de rived from experience. Moreover, few critics at present would contend that all the links in this metaphysical chain are forged of solid metal. There are breaks which are filled up with an unsub stantial substitute for it. Transitions are effected — for example, where matter, or life, or mind emerge — rather by sleight of hand than by a legitimate application of the logical method. But if it were granted that the edifice is compact, and coherent in all its parts, it is still only a ghostly castle. It is an ideal skeleton of a universe. Its value is at best hypothetical and negative. The universe is more than a string of abstractions. This was forcibly stated in the criticism by Schelling in his later system. If a world were to exist, and to be rationally framed, it might possibly be con formed to this conception or outline. Whether the world is a real ity, experience alone can determine. The highest merit which can be claimed for the ideal scheme of Hegel is such as belongs to the plans of an architect as they are conceived in his mind, before a beginning has been made of the edifice, or the spade has touched the ground. The radical fault of the Hegelian system, and its erroneous implications, are not averted by the numerous enlight ened comments on the constitution of nature, and especially on the philosophy of history.1 Independently of other difficulties in the way of the various theories of Pantheism which have been propounded in ancient and modern times, it is a sufficient refutation of them that they stand in contradiction to consciousness, and that they are at vari ance with conscience. It is through self-consciousness that our first notion of substance and of unity is derived. The manifold operations of thought, feeling, imagination, memory, affection, con sciously proceed from a single source within. The mind is revealed to itself as a separate, substantial, undivided entity. Pantheism, in resolving personal being into a mere phenomenon, or a phase of an impersonal essence, and in abolishing the gulf of separation between the subject and the object, clashes with the first and clearest affirmation of consciousness.2 1 Of course, there was a Theistic school of interpreters of Hegel. Other- have sought to graft Theism upon Hegelianism. The consideration of these phases of opinion, including the more recent " Neo-Hegelian " speculation, would be out of place here. 2 See Appendix, Note 5. THE PRINCIPAL ANTI-THEISTIC THEORIES 6y Every system of Pantheism is necessitarian. It is vain to say, that, where there is no constraint from without, there is freedom of the will. A plant growing out of a seed would not become free by becoming conscious. The determinism which refers all volun tary action to a force within, which is capable of moving only on one line, and is incapable of alternative action, is equivalent, in its bearing on responsibility, to fatalism. On this theory, moral accountableness is an illusion.1 No distinction is left between natural history and moral history. Pantheism sweeps away the absolute antithesis between good and evil, the perception of which is the very life of conscience. Under that philosophy, evil, wher ever it occurs, is normal. Evil, when viewed in all its relations, is good. It appears to be the opposite of good, only when it is con templated in a more restricted relation, and from a point of view too confined. Such a judgment respecting moral evil undermines morality in theory, and, were it acted on, would corrupt society. It would dissolve the bonds of obligation. In the proportion in which the unperverted moral sense corresponds to the reality of things, to that extent is Pantheism in all of its forms disproved. Positivism is the antipode of Pantheistic philosophy. So far from laying claim to omniscience, it goes to the other extreme of disclaiming all knowledge of the origin of things or of their interior nature. A fundamental principle of Positivism, as expounded by Comte, is the ignoring of both efficient and final causes. There is no proof, it is affirmed, that such causes exist. Science takes notice of naught but phenomena presented to the senses. The whole function of science is to classify facts under the rubrics of similarity and sequence. The sum of human knowledge hath this extent, no more. As for any links of connection between phenom ena, or any plan under which they occur, science knows nothing of either. But where do we get the notion of similarity, and of simultaneity and succession in time ? The senses do not provide us with these ideas. At the threshold, then, Positivism renounces its own primary maxim. The principle of causation and the perception of design have a genesis which entitles them to not less credit than is given to the recognition of likeness and temporal sequence. A Posi- tivist, however disposed, with M. Comte, to discard psychology, 1 This has been shown above, in ch. i. See, also, J. Martineau, A Study of Spinoza, p. 233. 68 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF must admit that there are mental phenomena. He must admit that they form together a group having a distinct character. He must refer them to a distinct spiritual entity, or to a material origin, in which case he lapses into Materialism. The law of three successive states, — the religious, the meta physical, and the positive, — which Comte asserted to belong to the history of thought, — this law, in the form in which if was pro claimed by Comte, is without foundation in historical fact. Belief in a personal God has coexisted, and does now coexist, in con nection with a belief in second causes, and loyalty to the maxims of inductive investigation. J. S. Mill, while adhering to the proposition that we know only phenomena, attempted to rescue the Positivist scheme from scepti cism, which is its proper corollary, by holding to something exterior to us, which is " the permanent possibility of sensations," and by speaking of " a thread of consciousness." But matter cannot be made a something which produces sensations, without giving up the Positivist denial both of causation and of our knowledge of any thing save phenomena. Nor is it possible to speak of a " thread of consciousness," if there be nothing in the mind but successive states of consciousness. Mr. Mill was bound by a logical necessity to deny the existence of anything except mental sensations, — phenomena of his own individual consciousness ; or if he over stepped the limit of phenomena, and believed in "a something," whether material or mental, he did it at the sacrifice of his funda mental doctrine.1 The principal adversaries of Theism at the present day are Materialism and Agnosticism. Materialism is the doctrine that mind has no existence except as a function of the body : if is a product of organization. In its crass form, Materialism affirms that the brain secretes thought as the liver secretes bile. This exploded view involves the notion that thought is a material sub stance contained somehow in the brain. In its more refined state ment, Materialism asserts that thought, feeling, volition, are phenomena of the nervous organism, as magnetism is the property of the loadstone. Thought is compared to a flame, which first burns faintly, then more brightly, then flickers, and at length goes out, as the material source of combustion is consumed or dissipated. 1See remarks of Dr. Flint, Antitheistic Theories, pp. 185, 186. THE PRINCIPAL ANTI-THEISTIC THEORIES 69 Materialism is a theory which was brought forward in very ancient times. It is not open to the reproach, nor can it boast of the attraction, of novelty. And it deserves to be remarked, that the data on which its merit as a theory is to be judged remain substantially unaltered. It is a serious though frequent mistake to think that modern physiology, in its microscopic examination of the brain, has discovered any new clew to the solution of the prob lem of the relation of the brain to the mind. The evidences of the close connection and interaction of mind and body, or of mental and physical states, are not more numerous or more plain now than they have always been. That fatigue dulls the attention, that narcotics stimulate or stupefy the powers of thought and emo tion, that fever may produce delirium, and a blow on the head may suspend consciousness, are facts with which mankind have always been familiar. The influence of the body on the mind is in countless ways manifest. On the contrary, that the physical organ ism is affected by mental states is an equally common experience. The feeling of guilt sends the blood to the cheek ; fear makes the knees quake ; joy and love brighten the eye ; the will curbs and controls the bodily organs, or puts them in motion in obedience to its behest. But there is no warrant in the interaction of mind and body for the opinion that the latter, or any other extra-mental reality, is the cause or the subject of mental cognition. Not only are the facts on either side familiar to everybody, but no nearer approach has been made toward bridging the gulf between physical states — in particular, molecular movements of the brain — and consciousness. Says Tyndall, " The passage from the physics of the brain to the corresponding facts of conscious ness is unthinkable. Granted that a definite thought and a defi nite molecular action in the brain occur simultaneously, we do not possess the intellectual organ, nor apparently any rudiment of the organ, which would enable us to pass by a process of reasoning from the one to the other. They appear together, but we do not know why. Were our minds and senses so expanded, strength ened, and illuminated as to enable us to see and feel the very molecules of the brain ; were we capable of following their mo tions, all their groupings, all their electric discharges, if such there be; and were we intimately acquainted with the corresponding states of thought and feeling, — we should be as far as ever from the solution of the problem, How are these physical states con- 70 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF nected with the facts of consciousness?"1 This is said, be it observed, on the supposition of a sweeping psycho-physical paral lelism between physical and mental states, which is incapable of proof. Close as is the relation of the brain and the mind, the field is often left in the main to the self-activity of each according to its own nature. Not even a Materialist, however, doubts that there is a class of phenomena which no physical observation is capable of revealing. If the brain of Sophocles, when he was composing the Antigone, had been laid bare, and the observer had possessed an organ of vision capable of discerning every movement within it, he would have perceived not the faintest trace of the thoughts which enter into that poem, — or of the sentiments that inspired the author. One might as well cut open a bean-stalk, or search a handful of sand, in the hope of finding thought and emotion. It is easy to prove, and it has been proved, that Materialism regarded as a theory is self-destructive. If opinion is not the product of the mind's own self-activity, but is merely a product of the molecular motion of nervous substance, on what ground is one opinion preferred to another? What is the criterion for the judgment? Is not one shuffle of atoms as normal as another? if not, by what criterion is one to be approved, and the other rejected? How can either be said to be true or false, when both are equally necessary, and there is no norm to serve as a touch stone of their validity? It is impossible to pronounce one kind of brain normal, and another abnormal ; since the rule on which the distinction is to be made is itself a mere product of molecular action, and therefore possessed of no independent, objective va lidity. To declare a given doctrine true, and another false, when each has the same justification as the rule on which they are judged, is a suicidal proceeding. Like absurdities follow the assertion by a materialist that one thing is morally right, and an other morally wrong, one thing noble, and another base, one thing wise, and another foolish. There is no objective truth, no crite rion having any surer warrant than the objects to which it is applied. There is no judge between the parties ; the judge is himself a party on trial. Thus Materialism lapses into scepticism. 1 Fragments of Science, p. 121 ; 5th ed., p. 42. Declarations apparently of the same purport occur occasionally, — yet, as in Tyndall, inconsistently,— in Spencer. See his Psychology, vol. i. §§ 62, 272. THE PRINCIPAL ANTI-THEISTIC THEORIES 71 Physiology is powerless to explain the simple fact of sense-percep tion, or the rudimental feeling at the basis of it. A wave of tenu ous ether strikes on the retina of the eye. The impact of the ether induces a molecular motion in the optic nerve, which, in turn, produces a corresponding effect in the sensorium lodged in the skull. On this condition there ensues a feeling; but this feel ing, a moment's reflection will show, is something totally dissimi lar to the wave-motions which preceded and provoked it. But, further, in the act of perception the mind attends to the sensation, and compares one sensation with another. This discrimination is a mental act on which Materialism sheds not the faintest ray of light. The facts of memory, of conception, and reasoning, the phenomena of conscience, the operations of the will, — of these the Materialistic theory can give no reasonable or intelligible account. The Materialist is obliged to deny moral freedom. Vol untary action he holds to be necessitated action. The conscious ness of liberty with the corresponding feelings of self-approbation or guilt are stigmatized as delusive. No man could have chosen or acted otherwise than in fact he did choose or act, any more than he could have added a cubit to his stature. Of the origin and persistency of these ideas and convictions of the soul, Mate rialism hopelessly fails to give any rational account. Materialism, as it is usually held at present, starts with the fact of the simultaneity of thought and molecular changes. This is so far exaggerated as to make it inclusive of all mental action. This is the doctrine of " psycho-physical parallelism " or " conscious automatism." If there were ground for this untenable assumption, the task would remain of showing how the former are produced by the latter. How do brain-movements produce thought-move ments? If consciousness enters as an effect into the chain of molecular motion, then, by the accepted law of conservation and correlation, consciousness, in turn, is a cause reacting upon the brain. But this conclusion is directly contrary to the Materialistic theory, and is accordingly rejected. It will not do to allow that force is convertible into consciousness. There must be no break in the physical chain. Consciousness is excluded from being a link in this chain. Consciousness can subtract no force from matter. It will not do to answer that consciousness is the attend ant of the motions of matter. What causes it to attend ? What is the ground of what parallelism exists between the series of mental 72 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF and the series of material manifestations? Is it from the nature of matter that both alike arise ? Then, how can thought be denied to be a link in the physical series ? If it be some form of being neither material nor mental, the same consequence follows, and all the additional difficulties are incurred which belong to the monis tic doctrine of Spinoza. A refuge is sought in the self-contradictory notion of " epiphenomena," or concomitants which are not effects but which are figuratively designated as shadows of molecular action ! There are limits to the interaction of the brain and the mind ; there are distinct groups of phenomena ; all mental states, including sensations so far as consciousness is involved, have then- invisible centre and source in the indivisible self. Such is the mire into which one falls upon the attempt to hold that man is a conscious automaton. It is not escaped by imagining matter to be endowed with mystical and marvellous capacities, which would make it different from itself, and endue it with a heterogeneous nature. Secret potencies, after the man ner of the hylozoist Pantheism of the ancients, are attributed to the primeval atoms. " Mind-stuff," or an occult mentality, is imagined to reside in the clod, or, to make the idea more attrac tive, in the effulgent sun. The Platonic philosophy is said to lurk potentially in its beams. This is fancy, not science. The reality of a mental subject, in which the modes of consciousness have their unity, is implied in the language of Materialists, even when they are advocating their theory. The presence of a personal agent by whom thoughts and things are compared, their order of suc cession observed, and their origin investigated, is constantly assumed. The proposition that the ideas of cause and effect, substance, self, etc., which are commonly held to be of subjective origin, are the product of sensations, and derived from experience, is disproved by the fact that experience is impossible without them. In estab lishing the a priori character of the intuitions, Kant accomplished a work which forever excludes Materialism from being the creed of any but confused and illogical reasoners. Agnosticism, the system of Herbert Spencer, includes disbelief in the personality of God, but also equally in the personality of man. There is, of course, the verbal admission of a subject and object of knowledge. This distinction, it is even said, is "the THE PRINCIPAL ANTI-THEISTIC THEORIES 73 consciousness of a difference transcending all other differences."1 But subject and object, knower and thing known, are pro nounced to be purely phenomenal. The reality behind them is said to be utterly incognizable. Nothing is known of it but its bare existence. So, too, we are utterly in the dark as to the rela tions subsisting among things as distinguished from their transfig ured manifestations in consciousness ; for these manifestations reveal nothing save the bare existence of objects, together with rela tions between them which are perfectly inscrutable. The phenom ena are symbols, but they are symbols only in the algebraic sense. They are not pictures, they are not representations of the objects that produce them. They are effects, in consciousness, of un known agencies. The order in which the effects occur suggests, we are told, a corresponding order in these agencies. But what is "order," what is regularity of succession, when predicted of noumena, but words void of meaning ? " What we are conscious of as properties of matter, even down to its weight and resistance, are but subjective affections produced by objective agencies which are unknown and unknowable." 2 These effects are generi cally classified as matter, motion, and force. These terms express certain "likenesses of kind," the most general likenesses, in the subjective affections thus produced. There are certain likenesses of connection in these effects, which we class as laws. Matter and motion, space and time, are reducible to force. But " force " only designates the subjective affection in its ultimate or most general expression. Of force as an objective reality we know nothing. It follows that the same is true of cause, and of every other term descriptive of power. There is power, there is cause, apart from our feeling ; but as to what they are we are entirely in the dark. " The interpretation of all phenomena in terms of mat ter, motion, and force, is nothing more than the reduction of our complex symbols of thought to the simplest symbols; and when the equation is brought to its lowest terms, the symbols remain symbols still."3 Further, the world of consciousness and the world of things as apprehended in consciousness, are symbols of a reality to which both in common are to be attributed. "A Power of which the nature remains forever inconceivable, and to which no limits in Time or Space can be imagined, works in us 1 Spencer, Principles of Psychology, 2d ed., i. 157. 2 Ibid., i. 493. 8 First Principles, 2d ed., p. 558. 74 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF certain effects." x Thus all our science consists in a classification of states of consciousness which are the product of the inscrutable Cause. It is a " transfigured Realism." Reality, in any other sense, is a terra incognita. With these views is associated Mr. Spencer's doctrine of evolu tion. Evolution is the method of action of the inscrutable force. He is positive in the assertion that " the phenomena of Evolution are to be deduced from the Persistence of Force." By this he means the " Absolute Force" — "some Cause, which transcends our knowledge and conception." It is " an Unconditioned Reality without beginning or end."2 But persistence applied to phenome nal forces signifies that these in their totality are quantitatively constant. This could not be said of the Absolute Force, the Unknown Cause. Yet, it is forces in the phenomenal sense, or the conservation of energy, which is made the starting-point of evolu tion. " But the conservation of energy is not a law of change, still less a law of qualities," whereas the celestial, organic, social, and other phenomena which make up what Mr. Spencer calls cosmic evolution, are so many series of qualitative changes.4 " The con servation of energy," as Mr. Ward points out, " does not initiate events, and furnishes absolutely no clew to qualitative diversity. It is entirely a quantitative law." The confusion in the meaning attached to " Persistence of Force " makes shipwreck ofthe entire evolutionary scheme in which this vague and ambiguous phrase plays so important a part. We can only glance at the steps of the process. Homogeneous matter, it is assumed, diversifies or differentiates itself. A passage from inorganic being to life is gained only by a leap. The develop ment is represented as going on until nervous organism arises, and reaches a certain stage of complexity, when sentience appears, and, at length personal consciousness, with all its complexity of contents. But consciousness is a growth. All our mental life is woven out of sensations. Intuitions are the product of experience, — not of the individual merely, but of the race, since the law of heredity transmits the acquisitions of the ancestor to his progeny. So mind is built up from rudimental sensations. The lowest form of life issues at last in the intellect of a Bacon or a Newton. And life, it seems to be held, is evolved from unorganized matter. 1 First Principles, p. 557. 2 Ibid., § 147. * Ibid., § 62. 4 Ward, Naturalism and Agnosticism, vol. i. p. 214. THE PRINCIPAL ANTI-THEISTIC THEORIES 75 What, according to Spencer's own principles, are " matter," and " nervous organism," and " life," independently of consciousness and when there is no consciousness to apprehend them ? How can Nature be used to beget consciousness, and consciousness be used, in turn, to beget Nature? How are reason, imagination, memory, conscience, and the entire stock of mental experiences of which a Leibnitz or a Dante is capable, evolved from nerve-sub stance? These and like questions we waive, and direct our atten tion to the doctrine of "the Unknowable." What is " the Absolute " and " the Infinite " which are declared to be out of the reach of knowledge, and which, the moment the knowing faculty attempts to deal with them, lead to manifold con tradictions? They are mere abstractions. They have no other than a merely verbal existence. They are reached by thinking away all limits, all conditions, all specific qualities. In short, " the Absolute " as thus described is nothing. The attempt is made to exhibit a synthesis of " the detailed phe nomena of life and mind and society in terms of matter, motion, and force." x But the " synthesis," like the prior " analysis," confounds abstraction with analysis. " Knowledge is to be verified by ruth lessly abstracting from the concrete real all qualitative specifica tions. Celestial bodies, organisms, societies, are to be reduced to their lowest terms, viz., Matter, Motion, Force." What is merely " a generalization from the material world " is turned into an instru ment for retracing a path, which is development only in name. In this way, the world of things, material and mental, is reconstructed. Things are evolved which were not involved. If this fictitious Absolute be treated as real, absurdities follow.2 1 Ward, Naturalism and Agnosticism, i. 255 seq. 2 The antinomies which Kant and Hamilton derive from a quantitative con ception of the Infinite are the result. The antinomies of Kant, and of Hamilton and Mansel, are capable of being resolved. They involve fallacies. A quanti tative idea of the Infinite is frequently at the basis of the assertion that con tradictions belong to the conception of it. The Infinite is treated as if it were a complete whole, .._¦. as if it were a finite. Hamilton's doctrine of nescience depends partly on the idea of " the Infinite " and " the Absolute " as mere abstractions, and unrelated, and partly on a restricted definition of knowledge. We cannot know space, he tells us, as absolutely bounded, or as infinitely un bounded. The first, to be sure, is impossible, because it is contrary to the known reality. The second is not impossible. True, we cannot imagine space as complete ; we cannot imagine all space, space as a whole, because this, too, is contrary to the reality. But we know space as infinite ; that is, we know space y6 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF The Absolute which Spencer actually places at the foundation of his system is antithetical to relative being ; it is correlated to the rela tive. Moreover, the Absolute comes within the pale of conscious ness, be the cognition of it however vague. Only so far as we are conscious of it, have we any evidence of its reality. Moreover, it is the cause of the relative. It is to the agency of the Absolute that all states of consciousness are referable. " It works in us," says Spencer, " certain effects." Plainly, the Absolute, the real Abso lute, is related. Only as related in the ways just stated is its exist ence known. Mr. Spencer says himself that the mind must in "some dim mode of consciousness posit a non-relative, and in some similarly dim mode of consciousness, a relation between it and the relative." : Plainly, we know not only that the Absolute is, but also, to the same extent, what it is. But let us look more narrowly at the function assigned to the Absolute, and the mode in which we as certain it. Here Mr. Spencer brings in the principle of cause. The Absolute is the cause of both subject and object. And the idea of cause we derive, according to his own teaching, from the changes of consciousness which imply causation. "The force," he says, " by which we ourselves produce changes, and which serves to symbolize the cause of changes in general, is the final disclos ure of analysis." 2 In other words, the experience of conscious causal agency in ourselves gives us the idea of " force." This is " the original datum of consciousness." This is all we know of force. Only as we are ourselves conscious of power, do we know any thing of power in the universe. Now, Mr. Spencer chooses to name the ultimate reality " Force " — " the Absolute Force." He declares it to be inscrutable; since the force of which we are immediately conscious is not persistent, is a relative. Yet he says that he means by it " the persistence of some cause which tran scends our knowledge and conception." Take away cause from the Absolute, and nothing is left ; and the only cause of which we have any idea is our own conscious activity. If Mr. Spencer would make the causal idea, as thus derived, the symbol for the interpre tation of " changes in general " he would be a Theist. By deftly and know not only that we cannot limit it, but positively that there is no limit to it. We know what power is. We do not lose our notion of power when we predicate infinitude of it. It is power still, but power incapable of limit. 1 Essays, vol. iii. pp. 293 seq. 2 First Principles, p. 169. THE PRINCIPAL ANTI-THEISTIC THEORIES "j-j resolving cause into the physical idea of " force," he gives to his system a Pantheistic character. It is only by converting the a priori idea of cause, as given in consciousness, into a " force " which we " cannot form any idea of," and which he has no war rant for assuming, that he avoids Theism.1 Let us observe the consequences of holding the Agnostic rigidly to his own principles. According to Mr. Spencer's numerous and explicit avowals, all of our conceptions and language respecting nature are vitiated by the same anthropomorphism which he finds in the ascribing of per sonality to God. All science is made out to be a mental picture to which there is no likeness in realities outside of consciousness. To speak of matter as impenetrable, to make statements respecting an imponderable ether, molecular movements, atoms, even respect ing space, time, motion, cause, force, is to talk in figures, without the least knowledge of the realities denoted by them. It is not a case where a symbol is adopted to signify known reality. We cannot compare the reality with the symbol or notion, because of the reality we have not the slightest knowledge. When we speak, for example, of the vibrations of the air, we have not the least 1 Later expressions of Mr. Spencer indicate a nascent disposition to cross the limit of bald phenomenalism and to concede that the " Infinite and Eternal Energy," from which all things proceed, " is not, as far as our knowledge is concerned, an absolute blank." " In the development of religion," he says, " the last stage reached is recognition of the truth that force as it exists beyond consciousness, cannot be like what we know as force within consciousness, and that yet, as either is capable of generating the other, they must be different modes of the same. . . . Consequently . . . the Power manifested throughout the world distinguished as material, is the same Power which in ourselves wells up under the form of consciousness." " We are thus led," it is added, "to rather a spiritualistic than a materialistic interpretation of the universe." But in the context these qualifications of absolute neutrality between the two hypotheses, and from absolute ignorance of the nature of the primal Energy, are studiously guarded. See Spencer's Principles of Sociology (1896), vol. iii. P- x73) §§ 659, 660. Mr. John Fiske goes, perhaps, farther in the right direc tion than Mr. Spencer. He believes that " the Infinite Power which is mani fested in the universe is essentially psychical in its nature, that between God and the Human Soul there is a real kinship, although we may be unable to render any scientific account of it." Through Nature to God, p. 162. He protests against attempts " to take away from our notion of God the human element " (p. 166). Yet he fails to justify explicitly in our conception the elements which are essential in real personality and warrant us in containing in it, for substance, the truth that He hears and answers prayer. 78 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF knowledge either of what the air is, or of what vibrations are. We are merely giving name to an unknown cause of mental states ; but even oi cause itself, predicated of the object in itself, and of what is meant by its agency in giving rise to effects in us, we are as igno rant as a blind man of colors. Mr. Spencer says that matter is probably composed of ultimate, homogeneous units.1 He appears in various places, to think well of the atomic theory of matter. But if he is speaking of matter as it is, independently of our sensa tions, he forgets, when he talks thus, the fundamental doctrine of his philosophy. He undertakes to tell us about realities, when he cannot consistently speak of aught but their algebraic symbols, or the phenomena of consciousness. The atomic theory of matter carries us as far into the unknown realm of ontology as the doc trine of the personality of the Absolute, or any other proposition embraced in Christian Theism. It is obvious that Agnosticism is the destruction of science. All the investigations and reasonings of science proceed on the founda tion of axioms, — call them intuitions, rational postulates, or by any other name. But these, according to Agnostics, denote simply a certain stage at which the process of evolution has arrived. What is to hinder them from vanishing, or resolving themselves into another set of axioms, with the forward movement of this unresting process? What then will become of the doctrines of Agnosticism itself ? It is plain that on this philosophy, all knowl edge of realities, as distinct from transitory impressions, is a house built on the sand. All science is reduced to Schein — mere sem blance. It is impossible for the Agnostic to limit his knowledge to experience, and to reject as unverified the implications of experi ence, without abandoning nearly all that he holds true. If he sticks to his principle, his creed will be a short one. Conscious ness is confined to the present moment. I am conscious of remembering an experience in the past. This consciousness as a present fact I cannot deny without a contradiction. But how do I know that the object of the recollection — be it a thought, or feeling, or experience of any sort — ever had a reality ? How do I know anything past, or that there is a past? Now, memory is necessary to the comparison of sensations, to reasoning, to our whole mental life. Yet to believe in memory is to transcend 1 Principles of Psychology, vol. i. p. 157. THE PRINCIPAL ANTI-THEISTIC THEORIES 79 experience. I have certain sensations which I attribute collectively to a cause named my " body." Like sensations lead me to recog nize the existence of other bodies like my own. But how do I know that there is consciousness within these bodies ? How do I know that my fellow-men whom I see about me have minds like my own? The senses cannot perceive the intelligence of the friends about me. I infer that they are intelligent, but in this inference I transcend experience. Experience reduced to its exact terms, according to the methods of Agnosticism, is confined to the present feeling, — the feeling of the transient moment. When the Agnostic goes beyond this, when he infers that what is remembered was once presented in consciousness, that his fellow- men are thinking beings, and not mindless puppets, that any intel ligent beings exist outside of himself, he transcends experience. If he were to predicate intelligence of God, he would be guilty of no graver assumption than when he ascribes intelligence to the fellow- men whom he sees moving about, and with whom he is conversing. The Spencerian identification of subject and object, mind and matter, is illusive and groundless. They are declared to be " the subjective and objective faces of the same thing." They are said to be " the opposite faces " of one reality. Sometimes they are spoken of as its " inner and outer side." On the one side, we are told, there are nerve-waves ; on the other there are feel ings. What is the fact, or the reality, of which these two are "faces" or "sides"? From much of the language which Mr. Spencer uses — it might be said, from the general drift of his remarks — the impression would be gained, that the reality is material, and that feeling is the mere concomitant or effect. But this theorem he disavows. He even says, that, as between ideal ism and materialism, the former is to be preferred.1 More, he tells us, can be alleged for it than for the opposite theory. The nerve-movement is phenomenal not less than the feeling. The two are coordinate. The fact or the reality is to be distinguished from both. As phenomena, there are two. There are two facts, and these two are the only realities accessible to us. The sup posed power, or thing in itself, is behind, and is absolutely hidden. The difference between the ego and the non-ego " transcends all other differences." A unit of motion and a unit of feeling have nothing in common. 1 Ibid., vol. i. p. 159. 80 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF " Belief in the reality of self," it is confessed by Mr. Spencer, is " a belief which no hypothesis enables us to escape." a It is im possible, he proceeds to argue, that the impressions and ideas " which constitute consciousness " can be thought to be the only existences ; this is " really unthinkable." If there is an impres sion, there is "something impressed." The sceptic must hold that the ideas and impressions into which he has decomposed consciousness are his ideas and impressions. Moreover, if he has an impression of his personal existence, why reject this impres sion alone as unreal? The belief in one's personal existence, Mr. Spencer assures us, is "unavoidable"; it is indorsed by "the assent of mankind at large " ; it is indorsed, too, by the " suicide of the sceptical argument against it." Yet the surprising decla ration is added, that " reason rejects " this belief. Reason rejects a belief which it is impossible to abandon, and against which the adverse reasoning of the doubter shatters itself in pieces. On what ground is this strange conclusion reached? Why, "the cognition of self," it is asserted, is negatived by the laws of thought. The condition of thought is the antithesis of subject and object. Hence the mental act in which self is known implies " a perceiving subject and a perceived object." If it is the true self that thinks, what other self can it be that is thought of? If subject and object are one and the same, thought is annihilated. If the two factors of consciousness, the ego and the non-ego, are irreducible, the reality of self is the natural inference. The " un avoidable " belief that self is a reality is still further confirmed by the absolute impossibility of thinking without attributing the act to self. But let us look at the psychological difficulty which moves Mr. Spencer instantly to lay down his arms, and surrender an " un avoidable " belief. In every mental act there is an implicit con sciousness of self, whether the object is a thing external or a mental affection. From this cognition of self there is no escape. Suppose, now, that self is the direct object. To know is to dis tinguish an object from other things, and from the knowing sub ject. When self is the object, this distinguishing activity is exerted by the subject, while the object is self, distinguished alike from other things and from the distinguishing subject. The subject distinguishes, the object differs in being distinguished or dis- 1 First Principles, 4th ed., p. 66. THE PRINCIPAL ANTI-THEISTIC THEORIES 8 1 cerned. Yet both subject and object, notwithstanding this formal distinction, are known in consciousness as identical. If, again, self as the subject of this activity is made the object, then it is to one form of activity, distinguished in thought from the agent, that attention is directed, while at the same time there is a conscious ness that the distinction of the agent from the power or function is in thought merely, not in reality. That self-consciousness is a fact, every one can convince himself by looking within. No psy chological objection, were it much more specious than the one just noticed, could avail against an experience of the fact. We are fortunately not called upon by logic to part with an " unavoida ble " belief.1 To explain the complex operations of the intellect as due to a combination of units of sensation is a task sufficiently arduous. But, when it comes to the will and the moral feelings, the difficul ties increase. The illusive idea of freedom, as was explained above, is supposed by Mr. Spencer to spring from the supposition that " the ego is something more than the aggregate of feelings and ideas, actual and nascent, which then exists," — exists at the moment of action. The mistake is made of thinking that the ego is anything but " the entire group of psychical states which con stituted the action " supposed to be free.2 Yet the same writer elsewhere, and with truth, asserts that this idea of the ego is " verbally intelligible, but really unthinkable." 3 Mr. Spencer's system has been correctly described by Mansel as a union of the Positivist doctrine, that we know only the relations of phenomena, with the Pantheist assumption of the name of God to denote the Substance or Power which lies beyond phenomena.4 The doctrine, which is so essential in the system, that mental phenomena emerge from nervous organism when it reaches a certain point of development, is Materialistic. Motion, heat, light, chemical affinity, Mr. Spencer holds, are transformable into sensation, emotion, thought. He holds that no idea or feeling JThis objection of Spencer is a part of Herbart's system. It is confuted by Ulrici, Gott u. der Mensch, pp. 321, 322. 2 Principles of Psychology, vol. i. pp. 500, 501. 8 First Principles, 4th ed., p. 66. 4 The Philosophy of the Conditioned, p. 40. " The truth is that this new philosophy owes its monism to the a priori speculations of Spinoza, while its agnosticism is borrowed from Hume and Hume's successors." Ward, Nat uralism and Agnosticism, vol. ii. p. 208. G 82 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF arises save as a result of some physical force expended in produc ing it. " How this metamorphosis takes place ; how a force existing as motion, heat, or light, can become a mode of conscious ness ; how it is possible for the forces liberated by chemical changes in the brain to give rise to emotion, — these are mysteries which it is impossible to fathom." x They are mysteries which ought to shake the writer's faith in the assumed fact which creates them. If forces liberated by chemical action produce thought, then thought, by the law of conservation, must exert the force thus absorbed by it. This makes thought a link in the chain of causes, giving to it an agency which the theory denies it to pos sess. If chemical action does not " give rise to " thought, by producing it, then it can only be an occasional cause, and the efficient cause of thought is left untold. This evolution of mind from matter as the prius, even though matter be defined as a mode of " the Unknowable," and the subjection of mental phenomena to material laws, stamp the system as essentially Materialistic. " The strict mechanical necessity of the physical side is upheld, and, as a consequence the spontaneity and purposiveness of the psychical side is declared to be illusory, a thing to be explained away." 2 The arguments which confute materialism are applicable to it. Underneath modern discussions on the grounds of religious belief is the fundamental question as to the reality of human knowledge. The doctrine of the relativity of knowledge has been made one of the chief props of scepticism and atheism. If the proposition that knowledge is relative, simply means that we can know only through the organ of knowledge, it is a truism. We can know nothing of the universe as a whole, or of anything in it, beyond what the knowing agent by its constitution is capable of discerning. The important question is, whether things are known as they are, or whether they undergo a metamorphosis, converting them into things unlike themselves, by being brought into contact with the perceiving and thinking subject. It is tantamount to the question whether our mental constitution is, or is not, an instru ment for perceiving truth. The idealist would explain all the objects of knowledge as modifications of the thinking subject. Knowledge is thus made an inward process, having no real coun- 1 First Principles, 2d ed., p. 217. 2 For the modification of Spencer's opinion, see Appendix, Note 6. THE PRINCIPAL ANTI-THEISTIC THEORIES 83 terpart in a world without. Nothing is known, nothing exists, beyond this internal process. Others, who stop short of Idealism, attribute to the mind such a transforming work upon the objects furnished it, or acting upon it from without, that their nature is veiled from discovery. The mirror of consciousness is so made that things reflected in it may, for aught we can say, lose all resemblance to things in themselves. That which is true of sense- perception, at least as regards the secondary qualities, color, flavor, etc., — which are proximately affections of man's physical organism, — is assumed to be true of all things and of their relations. This is a denial of the reality of knowledge in the sense in which the terms are taken by the common sense of mankind. The doctrine was propounded in the maxim of the Sophist, Protagoras, that " man is the measure of all things." J Locke made sensation the ultimate source of knowledge. Berkeley withstood materialism by making sensations to be affections of the spirit, ideas impressed by the will of God, acting by uniform rule. Hume, from the premises of Locke, resolved our knowledge into sensations, which combine in certain orders of sequence, through custom, of which no explanation is to be given. Customary association gives rise to the delusive notion of neces sary ideas, — such as cause and effect, substance, power, the ego, etc. Reid, through the doctrine of common sense, rescued rational intuitions and human knowledge, which is built on them, from the gulf of scepticism. There is another source of knowledge, a subjective source, possessed of a self-verifying authority. Kant performed a like service by demonstrating that space and time, and the ideas of cause, substance, etc., the concepts or categories of the understanding, are not the product of sense-perception. They are necessary and universal ; not the product, but the condition, of sense-perception. They are presupposed in our perceptions and judgments. Moreover, Kant showed that there are ideas of reason. The mind is impelled to unify the concepts of the under standing by which it conceives, classifies, and connects the objects of knowledge. These ideas are of the world as a totality, embrac ing all phenomena, the ego or personal subject, and God, the unconditioned ground of all possible existences. But Kant founded a scepticism of a peculiar sort. Space, time, and the categories, cause, substance, and the like, he made to be purely subjective, characteristics of the thinker, and not of the 1 See Appendix, Note 7. 84 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF thing. They reveal to us, not things in themselves, but rather the hidden mechanism of thought. Of the thing itself, the object of perception, we only know its existence. Even this we cannot affirm of the ego, which is not presented in sense-perception. The same exclusively subjective validity belongs to the other ideas of reason. They signify a tentative effort which is never complete. They designate a nisus which is never realized. Since the con cepts of the understanding are rules for forming and ordering the materials furnished in sense-perception, they cannot be applied to anything supersensible. The attempt to do so lands us in logical contradictions, or antinomies, which is an additional proof that we are guilty of an illegitimate procedure. From the consequences of this organized scepticism, the nat ural as well as actual outcome of which was the systems of Pan theistic Idealism, Kant delivered himself by his doctrine of the Practical Reason. He called attention to another department of our nature. We are conscious of a moral law, an imperative man date, distinguished from the desires, and elevated above them. This implies, and compels us to acknowledge, the freedom of the will, and our own personality which is involved in it. Knowing that we are made for morality, and also for happiness, or that these are the ends toward which the constitution of our nature points, we must assume that there is a God by whose government these ends are made to meet, and are reconciled in a future life. God, free-will, and immortality are thus verified to us on practical grounds. Religion is the recognition of the moral law as a divine command. Religion and ethics are thus identified. Love, the contents of the law, is ignored, or retreats into the background. Rectitude in its abstract quality, or as an imperative mandate, is the sum of virtue. The doctrine of the relativity of knowledge is presented by Sir William Hamilton in a form somewhat different from the Kantian theory. The Infinite and the Absolute — existence uncondition ally unlimited, and existence unconditionally limited — are neither of them conceivable. For example, we cannot conceive of infinite space, or of space so small that it cannot be divided ; we cannot conceive of infinite increase or infinite division. Positive thought is of things limited or conditioned. The object is limited by its contrast with other things and by its relation to the subject. Only as thus limited can it be an object of knowledge. The object in THE PRINCIPAL ANTI-THEISTIC THEORIES 85 sense-perception is a phenomenon of the non-ego ; the non-ego is a reality, but is not known as it is in itself. Thought is shut up be tween two inaccessible extremes. But although each is incon ceivable, yet, since they are contradictories, one or the other must be accepted. For example, space must be either infinite, or bounded by ultimate limits. An essential point in Hamilton's doctrine is the distinction between conception and belief. The two are not coextensive. That may be an object of belief which is not a concept. This distinction is elucidated by Mansel, who says, " We may believe that a thing is, without being able to con ceive how it is." " I believe in an infinite God ; i.e. I believe that God is infinite. I believe that the attributes which I ascribe to God exist in him in an infinite degree. Now, to believe this proposition, I must be conscious of its meaning ; but I am not therefore conscious of the infinite God as an object of concep tion ; for this would require, further, an apprehension of the man ner in which these infinite attributes coexist so as to form one object." x But in this case do I not know the meaning of " infi nite"? Does it not signify more than the absence of imaginable limit, a mere negation of power in me? Does it not include the positive idea, that there is no limit? In the case of opposite in conceivables, extraneous considerations, according to Hamilton, determine which ought to be believed. Both necessity and free dom are inconceivable, since one involves an endless series, the other a new commencement; but moral feeling — self-approba tion, remorse, the consciousness of obligation — oblige us to be lieve in freedom, although we cannot conceive of it as possible. The fact is an object of thought, and so far intelligible, but not the quo modo. This dilemma in which we are placed, where we have to choose between two contradictory inconceivables, does not imply that our reason is false, but that it is weak, or limited in its range. When we attempt to conceive of the Infinite and the Absolute, we wade beyond our depth. They are terms signi fying, not thought, but the negation of thought. Our belief in the existence of God and in his perfection rests on the suggestions and demands of our moral nature. In this general view Hamilton was in accord with Kant. Mr. Mansel differed from Sir William Hamilton in holding that we have an intuition of the ego as an entity, and in holding that the idea of cause is a positive notion, 1 The Philosophy ofthe Conditioned, pp. 127, 129; cf. pp. 18 seq. 86 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF and not a mere inability to conceive of a new beginning, or of an addition to the sum of existence. But Mr. Mansel applied the doctrine of relativity to our knowledge of God, which was thus made to be only anthropopathic, approximative, symbolic; and he founded our belief in God ultimately on conscience and the emotions.1 Under the auspices of James Mill, and of his son John Stuart Mill, the philosophical speculations of Hume were revived. Intui tions are affirmed to be empirical in their origin. They are im pressions, which through the medium of sense-perception, and under the laws of association, stamp themselves upon us in early childhood, and thus wear the semblance of a priori ideas. But this is only a semblance. There are, possibly, regions in the uni verse where two and two make five. Causation is nothing but uniformity of sequence. The Positivist theory of J. S. Mill led him to the conclusion that matter is only " the permanent possi bility of sensations " ; but all these groups of possibilities which constitute matter are states of the ego. And Mill was only pre vented from concluding that the mind is nothing but a bundle of sensations by the intractable facts of memory. On his view of mind and matter, it is impossible to see how a man can know the existence of anybody but himself. He says that he does "not believe that the real externality to us of anything except other minds is capable of proof." But as we become acquainted with the existence of other minds only as we perceive their bodies, and since this perception must be held to be, like all our percep tions of matter, only a group of sensations, we have no proof that such bodies exist. The Agnostic scheme of Herbert Spencer accords with the the ory of Hume and Mill in tracing intuitions to an empirical source. But the experience which gives them being is not that of the indi vidual, but of the race. Heredity furnishes the clew to the solu tion of the problem of their emergence in the consciousness of the individual. He inherits the acquisitions of remote ancestors. Then the notion of energy is superadded to the Positivist creed. With it comes the postulate of a primal Power, of which we are said to have an indefinite consciousness, or "the Unknowable," — the Pantheistic tenet grafted on Positivism. The doctrine of the relativity of knowledge is taken up from Hamilton and Man- 1 Respecting Matthew Arnold's conception of God, see Appendix, Note 8. THE PRINCIPAL ANTI-THEISTIC THEORIES 87 sel as the ground of nescience respecting realities as distinct from phenomena, and respecting God. The facts of conscience which have furnished to Kant and Hamilton, and to deep-thinking phi losophers generally who have advocated the relativity of knowl edge, a foundation for belief in free-will and for faith in God, meet with no adequate recognition. Little account is made of moral feeling, and its necessary postulates are discarded as fictions. Our knowledge of God is knowledge and not an illusive sem blance of knowledge. It is not meant that our knowledge is commensurate with the object — the infinite and absolute Being. The question of Zophar, " Canst thou by searching find out God?" is explained by what immediately follows, "Canst thou find out the Almighty to perfection?" Knowledge may be very limited, yet real as far as it goes. But it is not even meant that the present forms of our knowledge of God correspond literally to the reality. With the expansion of knowledge, the symbols that now express it may be modified, may even be superseded. What is meant, in opposition to Agnosticism, is that they are substan tially true. In them the reality is bodied forth up to the measure of our finite capacity at this stage of our existence. This position is at a world-wide remove from that sort of Agnosticism — that spe cies of phenomenalism — which can be called knowledge only by an utter perversion of the ordinary understanding of the word. A very acute critic of Mr. Spencer, speaking of his use of the distinction of appearance and reality, a " distinction which has ever been the stronghold of Agnosticism," and of his confining strict knowledge to " appearances behind which God remains wholly and forever concealed as Inscrutable Reality," writes thus: "We have allowed that strict knowing, if it is to mean the resolution of the course of Nature into coexistence and succession, and these again into a world-formula in terms of matter and motion, does not reveal God at all, or mind of any sort. . . . But if we de cline to call anything an appearance, unless it is either perceived or perceptible, why then should we attach to it the bad sense of concealing, rather than the good sense of revealing? Why should appearances not be reality? How can reality appear, shine forth, and yet remain totally and forever beyond the knowledge of those to whom it appears? Let us turn, as we have done before, to 88 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF the case we know best — the communication of one human mind with another. Assuming good faith, we never regard a man's acts and utterances as masking, but rather as manifesting the man. If they mask when it is his intention to deceive, surely they cannot also mask when his intentions are the precise opposite. These acts and utterances may be beyond the comprehension of men on a lower intellectual level, and with narrower horizons, but they are not the less real and true on that account. And why should we argue differently, when reflection leads us to see in a universe de clared to be ' everywhere alive ' the manifestations of a Supreme Mind?"1 The rescue of philosophy from its aberrations must begin in a full and consistent recognition of the reality of knowledge. Intui tions are the counterpart of realities. The categories are objec tive ; they are modes of existence as well as modes of knowledge. Distinct as mind and nature are, there is such an affinity in the constitution of both, and such an adaptation of each to each, that knowledge is not a bare product of subjective activity, but a reflex of reality. Dependent existences imply independent self-existent Being. The postulate of all causal connection discerned among finite things is the First Cause. From the will we derive our notion of causation. Among dependent existences the will is the only fountain of power of which we have any experience. It is reasonable to believe that the First Cause is a Will. The First Cause is disclosed as personal in conscience, to which our wills are subject. The law as an imperative impulse to free action and as a preappointed end implies that the First Cause is Personal. Order and design in the world without — not found there merely, but instinctively sought there — corroborate the evidence of God, whose being is implied in our self-consciousness, and whose holy authority is manifest in conscience. 1 Ward, Naturalism and Agnosticism, vol. ii. p. 275. CHAPTER IV THE DIVINE ORIGIN OF CHRISTIANITY EVINCED IN ITS ADAPTEDNESS TO THE DEEPEST NECESSITIES OF MAN Every religion has to undergo a practical test. It verifies or disproves itself in the degree in which it answers to the spiritual nature and wants of man. Christianity does not come forward as a new philosophy having for its primary end the solving of specu lative problems. It professes, to be sure, to be in accord with reason. It claims to rest upon a truly rational conception of the universal system of which man is a component part. But it also founds its title to confidence on more practical grounds. It ap peals immediately to the conscience and the affections. It calls for a rectification of the will. It promises to minister to necessi ties of human nature which pertain in common to men of the most exalted intelligence and to minds of the humblest cast. In its adaptedness to such deep-felt necessities, which spring out of man's constitution and condition, which cleave to him as a finite, moral, responsible being who looks forward to death, and, with more or less of hope or of dread, to a life hereafter — in this adaptedness lies a proof of its truth ahd supernatural parent age. If Christianity is found to be matched to human nature as no other system can pretend to be, and as cannot be accounted for by any wisdom of which man of himself is capable, then we are justified in referring it to God as its author. In the propor tion in which this fitness of Christianity to the constitution, the cravings, the distress, of the soul, to man's highest and holiest as pirations, becomes a matter of living experience, the force of the argument will be appreciated. It will be understood in the de gree in which it is felt. Here the data of the inference are drawn from experiences of the heart. The impressions which carry one to this conclusion are contingent on the state of the sensibility, the activity and health of conscience, and the bent of the will. The conclusion itself is one to which the soul advances 89 90 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF spontaneously ; one in which, rational though it be, the affections and the will are the determining factors. There is in the human spirit a profound need of God. This grows out of the fact that we are not only finite, but consciously finite, and not sufficient for ourselves. But, whether the source of it is reflected on or not, this need of a connection with the Eternal and Divine is felt. In reality, the hunger for God, whether it be consciously recognized or not, is deeper in the heart than any other want of human nature ; for example, than the instinct that craves friendship, or that impels to the creation of domestic ties, or that inspires a thirst for knowledge. The need of God may be, it often is, latent, undefined. It stirs in the soul below the clear light of consciousness. Its very vagueness has the effect to send man off in pursuit of a variety of finite objects, which are sought for the sake of filling the void, the true significance of which is not yet discerned. Now it is wealth, now it is honor and fame and power, now it is the acquisitions of science. Or it may be sensual pleasure, or the entertainment afforded by social inter course, or any one of myriad sorts of diversion. The different sorts of earthly good, when worthy of esteem, are estimated be yond the value which experience finds in them. When they are gained, disappointment ensues. The void within is not filled. If these remarks are commonplace, their very triteness demon strates their truth. In childhood, we find the world into which life is opening sufficient. We do not tire of its novelty. The future stretches before us with a seemingly infinite attraction. The charm of mystery is spread over it. The scene captivates by its variety. In the human beings about us, in the spectacles pre sented for the eye to gaze on, in the work and in the play that await us at each day's dawn, there is enough. It is only in excep tional instances, in the case of unusually thoughtful and deep-souled children, that there appears a sacred discontent with the things that are comprised in the life about them. When we emerge out of immaturity, there will arise within us a sense of the unsatisfacto- riness of existence — a feeling not in the least cynical, not always, certainly, due to disappointments, though experiences of hardship and bereavement, or of whatever makes the heart ache, do cer tainly aggravate the discontent of the soul. It may be that there will coexist an inexpressible feeling of loneliness. There is a reaching out for something larger than human love can provide, ADAPTEDNESS TO HUMAN NECESSITIES gi and for something which human love, when tasted to the full, leaves unsupplied. Study, travel, absorption in pleasant labor, experiments in quest of happiness from this or that source, much as they may do to drive away temporarily the feeling of want, fail to pacify it permanently. A thirst, slaked for the day, revives on the morrow. There is a cry in the soul, even if not so articulate as to be distinctly heard by the soul itself, to which the world makes no response. Gifted minds which of set purpose shut their ears to this voice within have their moments in which they cannot avoid hearing it. Goethe is one of the most prominent examples of the deliberate purpose to confine the attention within the finite realm, and to live upon the delights of art, literature, science, love. Whatever could disturb the repose of the spirit, the dark side of mortal experience, harassing questions respecting the future, he would banish from thought. Yet this serene man said to his friend : " I have ever been esteemed one of fortune's chiefest favor ites ; nor can I complain of the course my life has taken. Yet, truly, there has been nothing but toil and care ; and in my sev enty-fifth year I may say that I have never had four weeks of gen uine pleasure. The stone was ever to be rolled up anew." x Rest was not attained. There was a lurking sense that the peace which came and went had no perennial source. " We may lean for a while," he once said, " on our brothers and friends, be amused by acquaintances, rendered happy by those we love ; but in the end man is always driven back upon himself. And it seems as if the divinity had so placed himself in relation to man as not always to respond to his reverence, trust, and love ; at least in the terrible moment of need." "There had then been," writes Mr. Hutton, in his thoughtful Essay on Goethe, "there had then been a time when the easy familiarity with which the young man scruti nized the universe had been exchanged for the humble glance of the heart-stricken child ; and he had shrunk away from that time (as he did from every hour of life when pain would have probed to the very bottom the secrets of his nature), to take refuge in the exercise of a faculty which would have been far stronger and purer, had it never helped him to evade those awful pauses in existence when alone the depths of our personal life lie bare before the in ward eye, and we start to see both ' whither we are going, and whence we came.' Goethe deliberately turned his back upon 1 Eckermann, Conversations of Goethe, p. 76. g2 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF those inroads which sin and death make into our natural habits and routine. From the pleading griefs, from the challenging guilt, from the warning shadows, of his own past life, he turned reso lutely away, like his own Faust, to the alleviating occupations of the present. Inch by inch he contested the inroads of age upon his existence, striving to banish the images of new graves from his thoughts long before his nature had ceased to quiver with the shock of parting ; never seemingly for a moment led by grief to take conscious refuge in the love of God and his hopes of a hereafter." ] It is sometimes made a reproach to Christianity that it is a refuge of the weak, the disappointed, the desponding. But a full proportion of its disciples have been won from the ranks of men of even marked virility. But the question is whether the realities of existence are not best discerned from the point of view gained by those who have experience of pain — whether the mental vision of such is not clearer. Not long after the death of his wife, Thomas Carlyle wrote to his friend, Erskine of Linlathen, as follows : — "'Our Father which art in Heaven, hallowed be thy name, thy kingdom come, thy will be done,' — what else can we say ? The other night, in my sleepless tossings about, which were growing more and more miserable, these words, that brief and grand prayer, came strangely into my mind, with an altogether new emphasis, as if written and shin ing for me in mild pure splendor on the black bosom of the night there ; when I, as it were, read them, word by word, with a sudden check to my imperfect wanderings, with a sudden softness of composure that was most unexpected. Not perhaps for thirty or forty years had I ever formally repeated that prayer ; nay, I never felt before how in tensely the voice of man's soul it is, — the inmost aspiration of all that is high and pious in poor human nature ; right worthy to be recommended with an, * After this manner pray ye.' " The just criticism of Goethe brings us to another deep feeling of the human soul, — a more solemn experience, a more imperi ous need. The yearning of the finite soul for an infinite good is not its most agonizing emotion. The craving which an intelli gent creature, however pure, would feel, — the craving for an object commensurate with its boundless desires, — is far from comprising the whole need of man. A self-accusation, more over, sooner or later, with more or less persistency, haunts the 1 Hutton's Essays, vol. ii. {Literary), p. 77. ADAPTEDNESS TO HUMAN NECESSITIES g3 soul. It may exist only as an uneasy suspicion. It will fre quently arise in connection with special instances of wrong-doing, or of neglect of duty in relation to other men. One finds himself reproached within for being selfish in his conduct. The con sciousness of secret purposes which his moral sense condemns inspires him with a feeling of unworthiness and of shame. He falls below his own ideals ; he detects in himself a lack of courage, of truth, of purity, of magnanimity, of loyalty to the just claims of relatives, or of neighbors, or of society at large. Epochs are reached in the course of life when, as he glances backward over a long period, cherished habits of feeling rise in memory to con demn him. Self-accusation may go so far as to induce self-loath ing. The more he probes his own character, the more aware does he become that there is something perverse at the very core. He is living to the world, is making the good which the world yields, or self-gratification in a more gross or more refined form, the goal and end of his striving. Not only is he without God, he is alienated from him; and in this alienation, carrying in it an idolatry of the creature and of finite good, he discerns the root of the evil that is in him. Then the sense of guilt attaches itself to the impiety or ungodliness out of which, as an innermost fountain, flows a defiled stream of ethical misconduct. We are drawing no fancy picture. The sense of unworthiness is not a morbid experience. It is not confined to transient moods ; it is not limited to characters of exceptional depravity ; it does not belong alone to men of the spiritual elevation of Pascal and Luther, of Augustine and Edwards ; it does not pertain to one nation exclusively, or to any single branch of the human family; it is not an artificial product of the teaching of Christianity, or of any other of the religions that have prevailed on the earth. It is a human experience, giving, therefore, the most diversified mani festations of its presence in the confessions of individuals, in poetry, and in other forms of literature, in penances, sacrifices, and other rites of worship. The " whole world is guilty before God," and in varying degrees sensible of the fact, despite the obtuseness of conscience which the practice of evil-doing engen ders, the natural efforts to stifle so humiliating and painful an emotion, the partially successful devices to divert the attention from it, and the sophistry which labors to make it seem unreal. 1 1 On this subject, see Appendix, Note 9. 94 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF Then the sense of being without God is converted into a sense of estrangement from Him. The feeling of responsibleness for sin, while it brings God more vividly to mind, awakens the con sciousness of being excluded from communion with Him. The sense of condemnation drives one away from God, and yet com pels the thought of Him. The soul hides itself "among the trees of the garden," yet is followed, and held, and mysteriously attracted by the offended Being from whom it has chosen to separate itself. Besides a sense of unworthiness there is a consciousness of bondage. It may be that particular habits, which the will has suffered to gain control, have now come to be felt as a chain. Sensual appetite in one form or another, vanity, ungovern able resentment, covetousness, or some other base purpose or corrupt form of conduct — may have established a mastery, which, when the conviction of guilt arises, and with it discontent, is felt as a galling tyranny. If there be no single predominant passion, the general principle of worldliness which has enthroned the crea ture in the place of the Creator oppresses the soul that has now awoke to a perception of its culpable and abnormal state. Strug gles to break loose from the yoke of habit — which has become bound up with the laws of association that determine the current of thought, has enslaved the affections, and taken captive the will — prove ineffectual. " What I would, that do I not ; but what I hate, that do I " ; or, as the heathen poet expresses it, — " Video meliora proboque ; Deteriora sequor." Of course the struggle against inward evil may be weak, but in strong and earnest natures it may amount to an agony. The insurrection against the power to which the will has yielded itself may rend the soul as a kingdom is torn by civil strife. The unaided effort at self-emancipation turns out to be fruitless. It is the vain struggle of Laocoon in the coils of the serpent. It may end in a despairing submission to the enemy. But this description does not complete the account ofthe experi ence of the soul in its relations to God, as long as it is yet practi cally ignorant of the gospel. The misery of human life' must be taken into consideration. Where there is youth, health, prosperity, and the buoyancy of spirits which is natural under these circum- ADAPTEDNESS TO HUMAN NECESSITIES 95 stances, there is commonly but a slight appreciation of the count less forms of distress from which even the most favored class of mankind do not escape. It is possible, to be sure, to understate the amount of happiness in the world of mankind. That there is no sunshine in human life, even in situations that are adverse, only a cynic would be disposed to deny. But he is equally blind to facts who fails to recognize that the earthly life of men is a scene which abounds in trouble, in pain of body and anguish of spirit, in hearts lacerated by fellow-beings who have been loved and trusted, made sore by bereavement, anxious with numberless cares, often weary or half-weary with the burden of toil and the bitter ness of grief. Then there approaches every household and every individual the dark shadow of death. The love of life is an instinct so strong that only in exceptional cases is it fully overborne by the pressure of despondency. Yet death stands waiting. More than half of the race expire in infancy. Before every individual is the prospect of this inevitable event, which he endeavors to avert and to postpone as long as possible, all the while, however, aware that his painstaking will at length be fruitless. The feelings sketched above are not peculiar to any single generation. They are not the result, as they are sometimes said to be, of a gloom engendered by Christian teaching. He who imagines that life of old was nothing but sunshine, has forgotten his Homer and a thou sand pathetic laments strewn through the noblest literature of antiquity. None but the superstitious consider that pain and affliction are distributed in strict proportion to transgression, and that the hap piest lot falls uniformly to the least unworthy. But, while this notion is abandoned as a falsehood of superstition, we may recog nize in it the distortion of a truth which is embedded in the con victions of mankind, — the truth that natural evil and moral evil are connected in the system of things ; that one is the concomitant and shadow of the other ; that suffering, to a large extent, to say the least, is a part of a retributive order. Certain it is, that pain and sorrow tend to provoke self-judgment and that feeling of ill-desert which is inseparable from conscious impiety and self ishness. The presage of judgment arises spontaneously in the soul. Especially the prospect of death is apt to excite remorseful apprehension. The vivid presentiment of retribution to come, or an undefined dread of this nature, springs up unbidden in the g6 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF mind, in the presence of that solemn crisis which breaks up our present form of being, and sends the spirit out of its fleshly tene ment into the world beyond. To a mind haunted by reproaches of conscience, death itself wears a penal aspect ; it is felt to be something incongruous, a violent rupture of a bond, which, if dis solved at all, we might look to see loosened by a gentler process, by a transition not attended with the pangs of dissolution. When the moral and spiritual perceptions have thus been quickened, the mind is struck with the fact that Christianity, as set forth in the Scriptures, recognizes to the full extent all the facts which it has been aroused to discern. Not only are they admitted in the Scriptures, and spread out with no attempt to disguise them : they are insisted on, and are set forth with a startling im pressiveness. An individual thus awakened to the realities of exist ence finds depicted there man's need of God, — his thirst for God, — and the futility of seeking to slake the thirst of the soul for the Infinite from any earthly fountains of pleasure. " Why do ye spend money for that which is not bread ? " What is unworthy in human character and conduct he finds proclaimed there with a piercing emphasis. There is no extenuation of human guilt, whether as connected with immorality or with ungodliness. Every disguise is stripped off. The actual condition of men, as regards the sufferings to which all are exposed, and those from which none escape, is very often referred to and is everywhere latently assumed. Death is held up to view as the goal which all are approaching. The real source of the " sting of death " is brought out. The forebod ing of conscience, the product of the sense of ill desert, is dis tinctly sanctioned in a solemn affirmation of coming judgment. In short, the malady of the soul, in all its characteristic features, is laid bare in a way to evoke and intensify the spiritual needs and fears which have been adverted to. This outspokenness of the Bible, this unmasking of the evil and of the danger, invites confidence. The diagnosis is unsparing. It suggests at least the hope that where the disorder is so fully understood, an adequate remedy will not be wanting. The need of the soul is Reconciliation. This is the first want of which it is conscious. It needs to be brought near to God, and into personal communion with Him, through Forgiveness. It needs, moreover, help from without, that it may subdue the prin ciple of sin and attain the freedom of a willing loyalty. It needs ADAPTEDNESS TO HUMAN NECESSITIES 97 deliverance from death, as far as death is an object of dread either in itself or for what is feared in connection with it. How can one who is in this mood fail to be deeply impressed at the outset by the circumstance, that, while the Scriptures assert without palliation the guilt of sin and the righteous displeasure of God on account of it, they at the same time announce, not an inevitable perdition, but a complete rescue? There is a procla mation of "good tidings." First, there is the momentous an nouncement of a merciful Approach made by God to the race of mankind. This simple declaration, apart from methods and details, will excite a profound interest. The initiative in the work of deliverance has been taken by Him from whom alone forgive ness and deliverance can proceed. Then comes the explicit an nouncement of a mission of a Saviour. There is a manifestation of God to men through a man ; a man, yet in such an intimacy of union to God, that his most fit designation is " the Son of God," — a union such that no one knows the Father but the Son, and whoever has seen him may be said to have seen the Father, — a union the mysterious springs of which precede his life among men. He brings a proclamation of the pardon of sin. The fatherliness of God, never absolutely withdrawn by Him who is " kind to the evil and the unthankful," is brought into the fore ground. Ill-desert is to be no barrier to the coming back of the estranged to the Father's house and heart. Death need no longer be an object of dismal foreboding. It is converted into a door way to an immortal life hereafter. All this is said by the divine Messenger. But the redemption thus declared is represented as achieved by him. A man among men, born of woman, subject like ourselves to temptation, absolutely identifying himself with his race in sympathy, not less than with the condemnation felt by God for the sin of mankind, he makes a free, absolute surrender of his own will to the Father's will, with every new access of trial raises this surrender to a higher pitch, carries human nature vic toriously through life, and through the anguish of an undeserved death, — the final test of loyalty to God and of devotion to men, willingly endured because it is a cup given him of the Father to drink. In that death is the life of the world. Here is the response of Christianity to the call of the conscience and heart for an Atonement for sin. Through death the Saviour rises to a consummated life, invisible, — to the vantage-ground whence to ex- 98 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF tend his life-giving power to draw men to himself and to make them partakers of his own perfection, to begin now and to be fully realized hereafter. Jesus came to plant within the soul a life of filial union to God. In the assured confidence and peace of that life there would be a conscious superiority to the world, an independence of the changes and chances of this mortal state. In that life of heavenly trust, fears and anxieties of an earthly nature would lose their power to break the calm of the spirit. There would inhere in it a power to overcome the world. Resentful passions would die out in the rec ollection of the heavenly Father's patience and forgiving love, and in the sense of the inestimable worth and the possibility of perfec tion that belong to every soul, however unworthy. A secret life, serene in the midst of sorrow and danger, a perennial fountain of rest, and stimulus to kindly and beneficent exertion, — such was the gift of Christ to men. " My peace I give unto you." This life he first realized in himself. He maintained and perfected it through conflict. He imparts it through the channel of personal union and fellowship.1 Christian serenity leaves room for the full flow and warmth of all human sympathies and affections. The follower of Christ is empowered to use the world without abusing it, or being enslaved to it. He is not obliged to fling away the good gifts of God ; but, by making them servants instead of mas ters, he can enjoy, and yet can forego, that which he possesses. He carries within him a treasure sufficient when all else is lost. How shall this adaptedness in Christianity to man's spiritual being be accounted for? Can it be attributed to the Nazarene and to the group of fishermen who followed him, they being credited with no more than a merely human insight? Is there not reason to conclude that a higher than human agency, even a divine wisdom and will, was active in this great movement? Leaving out of view other kinds of proof, as that from testimony to miracles, the practical argument for the supernatural origin of Christianity, from its proving itself the counterpart of human need and the satisfaction of the soul's highest aspirations, is one difficult to controvert. It is of a piece with the response of the man born blind, who replied to the objections of the Pharisees, " Whether he be a sinner or no, I know not : one thing I know, that, whereas I was blind, now I see." s 1 As set forth in that classic, The Imitation of Christ. " John ix. 25. CHAPTER V THE DIVINE MISSION OF JESUS ATTESTED BY THE TRANSFORMING AGENCY OF CHRISTIANITY IN HUMAN SOCIETY In the preceding chapter we have touched on the adaptedness of Christianity to minister to the needs and yearnings of the in dividual. We have now to glance at the power and beneficence of Christianity as evinced in the broader field of history. Not the supernatural origin of a religion, nor even its truth, can be decided by the number of its adherents : else Buddhism, with its four hundred and fifty millions, would hold the vantage-ground over against Christianity with its four hundred millions ; and Mo hammedanism, with its one hundred and seventy-five millions, might put in a plausible claim to a higher than human derivation. It is necessary to consider in what way the converts of a religion have been won. Mohammedanism was a fanatical crusade against idolatry, that achieved its success by the sword and by the fierce energy with which it was wielded. Force was exerted, to some extent, for the spread of Christianity by the successors of Constan tine ; and force has been exerted in other instances, like that of the conquest of the Saxons by Charlemagne : yet there is no doubt that coercion — which, it may be observed, was used in the cause of Buddhism by the kings who embraced it — has, on the whole, hindered, instead of helped on, the progress of the gospel. The victory of the religion of the cross in the Roman Empire was really gained by moral means. The reactionary movement of Julian proved futile, for the reason that the faith which it at tempted to succor was in a moribund state. When we consider the small beginnings of Christianity, in its Galilean birthplace, and watch its progress against the organized and violent opposition of Judaism, and the successive attempts to extirpate it made by im perial Rome, from the cruelties of Nero and Domitian to the sys tematic persecution by Diocletian, its triumph over the ancient heathenism excites a wonder that is not lessened by theories which 99 IOO THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF have been invented to explain it. All the proximate causes of the downfall and disappearance of the Grseco-Roman religion, through the preaching of the gospel, presuppose behind them, as the ultimate cause, the personal influence of Jesus Christ and his life and death. When we see the same gospel, amid the ruins of the Roman Empire, subduing to itself the victorious barbarian tribes by whom it was overthrown, we get a new impression of the mysterious efficacy that resides in it. An Asiatic religion in its origin, it became the religion of Europe. Yet its adaptedness to races beyond the limits of the Aryan peoples has likewise been fully demonstrated. But in order to complete the argument for the truth and divine origin of Christianity, drawn from its effect, we must go farther, and investigate the particular character of that effect. The impres sion which the spread of the other religions — whether the national faiths, like the native religions of China, or the universal systems, Mohammedanism and Buddhism — might leave upon us is largely neutralized when we mark the character and limit of the influence exerted by them on human nature, culture, and civilization. We may, to be sure, recognize enough of good to prove that those religions inculcated important truths. We may discern a value in the moral and religious sentiments which they partially express and respond to. But the idea that any of those religions is the absolute religion, or the religion revealed from Heaven to be the perpetual light of men, is dispelled the moment we find that the work wrought by them upon the human soul is one-sided and defective, and that their final result is an arrested development. The individual is impelled forward to a certain limit. There he halts. Even deterioration may ensue. The nation feels a trans forming agency for a time, but at length it reaches an impassable barrier. An imperfect civilization becomes petrified. Christian ity, on the contrary, never appears to have exhausted its power. It moves in advance, and beckons forward the individual and the people who embrace it. When it is misconceived in some respect, and a partly perverted development ensues, it frequently develops a rectifying power. It forever instigates to reform : its only goal is perfection. We are not to forget that gradualness in the transforming effect of the Gospel is the character attributed by Jesus himself to its progress and influence in the world. It was to be first the POWER OF CHRISTIANITY TO TRANSFORM SOCIETY IOI blade, then the ear, then the full corn in the ear.1 It was to grow as the seed of the mustard plant.2 It was to operate in the heart of society, on its institutions, habits, and sentiments, like the yeast hidden in the " measures of meal." 3 Moreover, the consequence of this nature of the gospel — of what seems a slow conquest and spread, of the imperfect discern ment of its meaning, and the moral defects of its disciples — was foreseen and predicted.4 It is to be remembered that their sins as individuals, and especially crimes committed, even such as cruel persecution of fellow-Christians, are chargeable not to real Christi anity, but to misconceptions of it. We are not to forget, of course, that Christendom is something besides a religion. It is composed of particular races — races hav ing distinctive traits which have entered as one factor into the spiritual life and the civilization of this society of peoples. They have inherited from the past, especially from the Roman Empire and the cultivated nations of antiquity, invaluable elements of polity and culture. The Teutonic peoples were specially hospitable to the religion of the gospel. They were docile, as well as virile. They had these native traits to begin with : they received much, besides the gift of Christian faith, from those whom they conquered. Yet it is Christianity which leavened all. It is Christianity which fused, moulded, trained, the European nations. It is in the light of Christianity that their vigorous life unfolded itself. In that light it still flourishes. Jesus Christ brought into the world a new ideal of man — man individual and man social. This was not all. Had this been all, the condition of men might not have been materially altered. He brought in at the same time a force adequate to effect — though not magically, but by slow degrees — the realization of this ideal. It is in its double character — in the perfection ofthe moral ideal, and in the wonderful stimulus to the practical realization of it — that the transcendent superiority of the Christian religion is mani fest. The sages of antiquity presented high though always imper fect conceptions of what man and society should be ; but those conceptions remained inoperative. They did not avail for the elevation of many individuals even. Their effect on social and political life was small. Culture was attained by the intellectual and versatile Greek, but the ideal of manhood was faulty. Truth- JMarkiv. 28. 2 Matt. xiii. 32. 8 Ibid., 33. * Ibid., 34 seq. 102 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF fulness, " the gold of character," was not one of his characteristic virtues. There was no life-giving force to save the Greek from degeneracy and corruption. No more was there a saving power in the law and polity which Rome created. Neither Greek learn ing and philosophy, nor Roman politics and jurisprudence, could rescue mankind from degradation, or even keep up what power they had exerted. With Christ there came in a nobler ideal and a force to lift men up to it. That force resided in Jesus himself. The central thought of Jesus was religion — man's relation to God. Take out this idea of man's true life as consisting in that filial relation to the heavenly Father, and the vital principle is lost from the system of Jesus. The sources of its power are dried up : the root is dead, and the branches wither away. For with this idea is inseparably connected his estimate of the worth of the soul. Every individual, according to the teaching of Christ, has an incalculable worth. This does not depend on his outward condition. Lazarus, the beggar at the gate, was on a footing of equality with Dives at his luxurious table. To the sur prise of the disciples, Jesus conversed with a peasant woman at a well. What was a woman, and a poor woman, even a depraved woman, that the Master should waste time in order to enlighten her ? Little children he took in his arms when the disciples " for bade them." It was not the will of the Father that one of these little ones should perish. The transgressor of human and divine law, the male or female outcast — he saw in each something of imperishable value. With this idea of the worth of man, there is associated the recognition of every individual as an end in himself. No man is made merely to enhance the interests, or minister to the gratification, of another man. " Thou shalt love thy neighbor as thyself." He is the greatest who has most of the spirit of self-sacrifice. For one man to use another man or a woman as an instrument of his own pleasure or advancement, is an act of incon ceivable cruelty and baseness. The equality of men as regards worth or value, be their talents, property, station, power, or con dition in any particular what they may, is a cardinal truth. It is a deduction from their common relation, as creatures and children, to God, and from the common benefit of redemption, in which all alike share. In the community of God's children there was no distinction of bondman or freeman, rich or poor, male or female, POWER OF CHRISTIANITY TO TRANSFORM SOCIETY 103 Greek or barbarian. All — be their nationality that of the strong and intellectual branches of mankind, or of those little esteemed ; be their lot among the prosperous or the unfortunate — are on a level. They are " brethren." The Christian ideal embraced the sanctification of the entire life. It did not subvert established relations between man and man, as far as they were conformed to nature and right. It infused into them a new spirit. It set to work not to pull down, but to purify, the family and the state, and to raise each of these institutions to the ideal standard. Each was to be led to fulfil its true function, and to become a fountain of the highest possible beneficence. One of the great changes which Christianity made, and is mak ing, in the family, is the abolition of domestic tyranny. The authority ofthe father in ancient Rome, as in many other nations, was without hmit. As far as restraints of law were concerned, he was a despot in the household. He had over its members the right to inflict death. From the time of the introduction of Chris tianity, the authority of the father began to be reduced. In the second century the paternal prerogative, the patria protestas, was curtailed in the Roman law. The Stoic ethical teaching contributed to this result, as to other humane reforms. How far milder sentiments that were shared by the Stoics in the early Christian centuries were unconsciously imbibed from the gospel, which was already active in modifying the atmosphere of thought and feeling, is a question difficult to settle. This is certain, that Christian teaching from the beginning tended strongly to such a result, and evidently, at a later date, had a powerful effect. The more Christianity gained influence, the position of the wife in rela tion to the husband's will and control was wholly changed for the better. The freedom of divorce which existed by Roman law and custom met in the precepts of Christ and in the teaching of the Church a stern rebuke. The wife could no longer be discarded in obedience to the husband's caprice. Marriage became a sacred bond — a bond, except for one cause, indissoluble. Of the im measurable influence which the religion of Jesus has exerted in shielding the purity of woman, it is needless to speak. The power which the unsparing injunctions of the Sermon on the Mount have exercised for the defence of the helpless and innocent against law less passion, it would be impossible to estimate. As fast as Chris tianity spread, respect for the rights of woman extended. The 104 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF more deeply Christianity leavens society, the more does all unjust discrimination in laws and social customs, by which their rights and privileges have been abridged, disappear. The words of Jesus on the cross, when he committed his mother to the care of John, have inspired in all subsequent ages a tender feeling for the sorrows of woman. If reverence for the Virgin was at length exaggerated, and became a hurtful superstition, that unauthorized worship was connected with a sentiment toward the wife and mother which genuine Christianity fosters. The State is the second great institution having a divine sanction, and springing out of essential tendencies and needs of human nature. It is one of the most remarkable features of Christianity, and one of the marked signs that a wisdom higher than that of man was concerned in it, that from the first it asserted the inviola ble authority of the civil magistracy. There was all the temptation that religious zeal could afford, to cast off the rule of the State. This temptation was aggravated a thousand-fold by the circum stance that against the early Christians the civil powers arrayed themselves in mortal antipathy. Yet from the beginning the injunction was to honor the ruler. Nay, he was declared to be the minister of God for the execution of justice. Civil government was affirmed to be a part and instrument of God's moral govern ment of mankind. Christians were to pray for the ruler at the very time when Nero was burning them alive. No priestly usur pation in later periods, when it was carried to its height, was ever able to extirpate in the Christian mind the feeling of obligation to obey the magistrate, and the conviction that the powers that be are ordained of God. Christianity exalted justice, and revered the State as its divinely appointed upholder between man and man. Christianity honored rightful authority, and recognized it as com mitted to the rulers of a political community. At the same time, the religion of Christ brought in liberty. Wherever it has been understood aright, it has been the most powerful champion and safeguard of natural and political rights. In heathen antiquity the State was supreme, and practically om nipotent. The individual was absorbed in the political body of which he was a member. To that body he owed unlimited alle giance. There was no higher law than the behest of the State. Socrates is one instance of an individual refusing, out of deference to the Divine Will, to obey a prohibition of the State. He would POWER OF CHRISTIANITY TO TRANSFORM SOCIETY 1 05 not promise to refrain from teaching when he might have saved his life by doing so. We meet here and there with a shining example of one who was ready to disregard a civil mandate which required of him some flagrant act of injustice. But these are exceptions that prove the rule. They are anticipations of a better era than existed, or could exist, as long as polytheism was dominant, and while there was no broader form of social unity than the civil com munity. Christianity founded a new kingdom. It was a kingdom not of this world ; but it was a real sovereignty, which was felt to be supreme over all human enactments. The first preachers of the gospel felt obliged to obey God rather than man. The early Christians had to disobey the laws and decrees of the Jewish and the Roman authorities. It was a new thing when prisoners who were brought before Roman prefects, and commanded to worship the image of the emperor or to curse Christ, refused, and persist ently refused, to do so. Such contumacy, such insubordination, struck these administrators of law as a marvel of audacity and of treasonable hostility to the supreme authority. By this means, through that higher allegiance to the revealed will of God, which Christianity made a widespread, practical fact, the power of the State, up to that time virtually boundless, was cut down to reason able proportions. The precepts of the State were subjected to the private judgment of the subject. The individual decided whether or not they were consistent with the laws of the King of kings. He inquired whether they enjoined what God had forbidden, or forbade what God had enjoined. The eternal laws of justice and right, of which Sophocles wrote in the highest strain of Greek religious thought, became, in the Christian Church, the everyday, absolute arbiter of conduct. There might spring up a new despot ism. There might grow up an ecclesiastical authority not less tyrannical than the State had been. But this could only be a tem porary abuse and perversion. Christian truth could not be perma nently eclipsed. Meantime, even in the days when ecclesiastical control over the individual was overgrown, it still afforded a most wholesome check to the unrestrained power of chieftains and kings. The Papacy, in the periods when it mistakenly strove to govern the laity with a supreme sway, and even to build up a universal mon archy of its own, a spiritual despotism, did, nevertheless, do a vast service in its unceasing assertion of a spiritual law above the will of any man, however strong, and of the right of spiritual ideas to 106 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF prevail over brute force. Guizot, speaking of the period which en sued upon the fall of the Western Empire, says, " Had the Christian Church not existed, the whole world must have been abandoned to purely material force." J When Christianity had liberated the human mind from the yoke of secular power, it proved itself en lightened enough and strong enough to emancipate it from the yoke of the ecclesiastical institution through which, in great part, that deliverance had been achieved. Looking at the constitution of the State itself, we see plainly how Christianity has introduced, and tends to introduce, a just meas ure of political liberty, and a fair distribution of political power. The constitution of the Church as its Founder established it, the fraternal equality of its members, the mutual respect for opinion and preference which was enjoined, the forbidding of a lordship like that which existed in secular society — all tended strongly to bring analogous ideas and parallel relations into the civil commu nity. Liberty was prized by the ancients ; but what sort of lib erty? At Athens, the citizens were but a handful compared with the entire population. In Rome, citizenship was a privilege jeal ously guarded by the select possessors of it. When, at last, polit ical equality was attained, it was through the absolute rule of the emperors, after liberty had vanished. Christianity presents no abstract pattern of civil society. It prescribes no such doctrine as that of universal suffrage. But Christianity, by the respect which it pays to man as man, by its antipathy to unjust or artifi cial distinctions, by its whole genius and spirit, favors those forms of polity in which all men of competent intelligence, who have a stake in the well-being of the community, are allowed to have some voice in its government. So far, Christianity is not a neu tral in the contests relative to political rights and privileges. As concerns natural rights, which are always to be carefully distin guished from political, the religion of Christ continually protests against every violation of justice in the laws and institutions of society. The Golden Rule it holds to be not less applicable to those acts of the community which determine the relations of its members to one another than to the private intercourse of individ uals. Who that examines the governments of Christian nations to-day can fail to see what a mighty influence Christianity has 1 Lectures on the History of Civilization, ch. ii. p. 38. Power of Christianity to transform society 107 already exerted in moulding civil society into a conformity with human rights and with the rational conception of equality? Christianity fundamentally alters the view which is taken of in ternational relations. Slowly, but steadily, it makes mankind feel that injustice is not less base when exercised between nation and nation than between man and man. Prior to the Christian era, the more closely the members of a tribe or people were bound together, the more regardless they generally were of the rights and the welfare of all beyond their borders. Pretexts were easily found — very often they were not even sought — for enterprises of conquest and pillage. As intercourse increased, and commerce spread, there was required some mutual recognition of rights. Covenants were made, and sometimes were kept. Occasional glimpses of a better order of things, in which mankind should be regarded as a kind of confederacy, were gained by Stoic philos ophers. Such ideas were now and then thrown out by rhetorical writers on politics and morals, like Cicero. But international law existed only in its rudiments. Selfishness was the practical rule of national conduct. The strong domineered over the weak. Christianity subordinated even patriotism to the law of righteous ness and human brotherhood. It insisted on the responsibility of the nation, in its corporate capacity, to God, the Father of all. It held up a nobler ideal for the regulation of nations in their mutual intercourse. It need not be said how much remains to be done in order that the Christian law should be even approximately carried out. Yet the contrast between the Christendom of to-day and the spectacle presented by the tribes and nations of antiquity is like the contrast between winter and spring. In the middle ages, the Church, as an organized body, through the clergy, under took to pacify contention, and curb the appetite for aggression. Vast good was accomplished, but a new species of tyranny incident ally came in. In modern days, equitable treaties, amicable nego tiations, and, above all, arbitration, are resorted to more and more, for the settlement of disputes, the redress of wrongs, and the pre vention of war. Ambition and greed do not avail to expel from thought the ideal of the gospel. If clouded for a while, it reap pears in its full effulgence. Christianity does not absolutely for bid war, as it does not prohibit, but rather approves, the use of force for the maintenance of law within the limits of each commu nity. But against all wars of aggression, against all wars which 108 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF might have been avoided by forbearance and reasonable conces sion, the religion of Jesus lifts up a warning voice, which is more and more heard. A glance at the history of Christianity, and at the present condition of the world, makes it manifest that a mighty force is incessantly at work in the bosom of mankind, which prom ises at last to bring in an era when righteousness shall prevail in the dealings of the nations with one another, and men shall learn war no more. The work which Christianity has done in the cause of charity, of kindness and beneficence, constitutes a topic of extreme inter est. There was charity before the gospel. Men were never brutes. There was compassion ; there was a recognized duty of hospitality to strangers. Among the Greeks, Jupiter was the protector of strangers and suppliants. There were not absolutely wanting combined efforts in doing good. Institutions of charity have not been entirely unknown in heathen nations. In China there have long existed, in the different provinces, hospitals for two classes, — for old people and for foundlings. In ancient times men were not indisposed to befriend their own countrymen. This was preeminently true of the Jews. Among the heathen, in various towns of the Roman Empire, physicians were appointed by the municipality, whose business it was to wait on the poor as well as on the rich. Yet, when all this is justly considered, the fact remains, that charity was comparatively an unmeaning word until Christianity appeared. Largesses bestowed on the multitude by emperors and demagogues were from other motives than a desire to relieve distress. Considerations of policy had a large part in such benefactions as those of Nerva and Trajan for poor children and orphans. Nothing effectual was done to check the crime of infanticide, which had the sanction of philosophers of highest repute. The rescue of foundlings was often the infliction upon them, especially upon the females, of a lot worse than death. Gladiatorial fights— the pastime which spread over the Roman Empire in its flourishing days, and against which hardly a voice was ever raised — could not fail to harden the spectators, who learned to feast their eyes on the sight of human agony. From the beginning, the outflow of charity was natural to Christians. God had so loved the world, that he gave His Son. Christ loved men, and gave himself for them. The Christian principle was love, and love was expressed in giving liberally to POWER OF CHRISTIANITY TO TRANSFORM SOCIETY 109 those in need. The disciples at Jerusalem were so generous in their gifts to the poor of their number, that they are said to have " had all things in common " ; although other passages in the Acts prove that there was no actual communism, and Christianity never impugned in the least the rights of property. Wherever a church was established, there were abundant offerings regularly made for the poor, systematic provisions for the care of the sick, of orphans, and of all other classes who required aid. Gifts were poured out, even for the help of Christians in distant places, without stint. In the second and third centuries there were scattered all over the Roman world these Christian societies, whose members were bound together as one family, each taking pleasure in relieving the wants of every other. Through their bishops and other offi cers, there was a systematic alms-giving on a scale for which no precedent had ever before existed. Nor was it indiscriminate, or in a way to encourage idleness, as it too often was, even when the motive was laudable, in the middle ages. There is an exhortation of the Apostle Paul, in which the spirit of the gospel, as it actually embodied itself in the early Church, is impressively indicated. " Let him that stole steal no more ; but rather let him labor, working with his hands the thing which is good, that he may have to give to him that needeth." * There were reclaimed thieves in the church at Ephesus. The apostle urges them to industry in order that they may have the means of aiding those in want. Nothing could better set before us the influence of the new religion. The Apostolic Constitutions, which disclose the rules followed among the churches as early as the Nicene age, ordain that the poor man shall be assisted, not according to his expecta tions, but in proportion to his real needs, of which the bishops and deacons are to judge ; and to be assisted in such a way as best to secure his temporal and spiritual good.2 It is added, " God hates the lazy." The exercise of discrimination, and of care not to foster idleness, is a frequent theme of exhortation during several centuries. In one of the earliest post-apostolic writings, the Didache, or Teaching of the Twelve Apostles? the Christian disciple is cautioned to keep his money in his hands until 1 Ephesians iv. 28. 2 Const. Apost, iv. 5, iii. 4, 12-14. See Chastel's The Charily ofthe Primi tive Churches, p. 79. 8 Ch. i. 6 (see, also, i. 5). IIO THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF he makes them " sweat." Asylums for orphans, hospitals for the sick, sprang into being under the auspices of the Church. In process of time noscomia, or hospitals for the diseased, including the insane, were founded in all the principal cities, and even in smaller towns, and in some country places. Nor did the vast stream of benefaction flow out for the help of Christians alone. When pests broke out, as at Alexandria in the third century, and somewhat earlier at Carthage, the Christians, under the lead of their clergy, instead of forsaking the victims of disease, or driving them from their houses, as the heathen did, showed their courage and compassion by personally ministering to them. The parable of the Good Samaritan had not been uttered in vain. Among the numerous recorded examples of charity to the heathen is the act of Atticus, Archbishop of Constantinople (a.d. 406-426), who, during a famine in Nicea, sent three hundred pieces of gold to the pres byter Calliopius. This almoner was directed to distribute it among the suffering who were ashamed to beg, without distinction of faith. Acacius, Bishop of Amida, about a.d. 420, persuaded his clergy to sell the gold and silver vessels of the church, that he might ransom several thousands of suffering Persian captives who had been taken by the Romans. On one occasion Chrysostom, passing through the streets of Antioch, on his way to the cathe dral, saw a multitude of poor, distressed persons. He read to his audience the xvith chapter of the first epistle to the Corinthians. Then he described the blind, the crippled, and diseased throng which he had just seen, and proceeded to exhort his hearers to exercise toward their " brothers " the compassion which they themselves had need of at the hands of God.1 " Christian charity extended over all the surface of the empire, like a vast tissue of benevolence. There was no city, no hamlet, which, with its church and its priest, had not its treasure for the poor ; no desert which had not its hospitable convent for travellers. The compassion of the Church was open to all." 2 These meagre references to the charitable work of the early Church may call to mind the miracle that Christianity wrought in penetrating the human heart with a spirit of kindness, the like to which the world before had never known. That same spirit, not always discreetly it may be, has been operative among Christian nations ever since. It is ever detecting forms of human want and 1 Opp., vol. iii. pp. 248 seq. See Chastel, p. 159. 2 Chastel, p. 304. POWER OF CHRISTIANITY TO TRANSFORM SOCIETY III infirmity which have not been previously noticed, and devising for them relief. No superior prudence in administering charity, derived from social and economic science, could have ever called into being, nor can it ever dispense with, that temper of unselfish pity and love out of which the charities of Christian people, age after age, have continued to flow. In this feature of beneficence, the Christendom of to-day, contrasted with heathen society of any age, is like a gar den full of fruits and flowers by the side of a desert. Christianity is the only known corrective of the evils out of which socialism arises. The enrichment of the few, and the im poverishing of the many, can be remedied by no infraction of the right of property, which would bring back barbarism. The only antidote is to be found in that spirit of beneficence which prompted Zaccheus to give half of his goods to feed the poor. That spirit, when it prevails, will dictate such arrangements between capitalist and laborer as will secure to the hitter a fair return for his toil. It will check the vast accumulation of wealth in a few individuals. And the Christian spirit, as in ancient days, will inspire patience and contentment, and a better than an earthly hope, in the minds of the class whose lot in life is hard.. In speaking of the improvement of society through the agency of Christianity, it is natural for us to think of the two great scourges of mankind, — war and slavery. Iniquitous wars are undertaken in modern days. Yet, if we compare the motives that lead to warfare now with those which in ancient times filled the world with incessant strife, we cannot but perceive, much as remains to be accomplished, a vast and salutary change. The laws and usages of war have felt the humanizing touch of the gospel. The manner in which non-combatants are treated is a signal illustration. Once they were at the mercy of the conqueror, who too often knew no mercy. Their lives were forfeited. Reduction to slavery was a mitigation of the penalty which it was lawful to inflict on them. A military commander who should treat his prisoners as com manders like Julius Caesar, who were thought in their time to be humane, treated them, would be an object of universal execration. A like change has taken place, even as regards the property of a conquered belligerent. The extinction of a nationality like Poland, even when arguments in favor of it are not wholly destitute of weight, is a dark blot on the reputation of the sovereigns or nations by whom it is effected. Formerly it would be the expected and 112 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF approved result of a successful war. In the provisions now made for the care and cure of the wounded, for the health and com fort of the common soldier, including the voluntary labors of devoted physicians and nurses, we perceive a product of Christian feeling. The Romans had their soldiers' hospitals (valetudinaria) ; but the vast and varied work of philanthropy in this direction, which belongs to our time, was something of which no man dreamed. Ancient slavery was generally the servitude of men of the same race as the master. It involved the forfeiture of almost all rights on the part of the slave. It was attended with a kind and degree of cruelty which the intelligence of the victims, and the danger of revolt resulting from it, seemed to require, if the system was to be kept up. In extensive regions it had the effect, finally, almost to abolish free labor, to bring landed property into the hands of a few proprietors, to enervate the Roman spirit, and thus to pave the way for the downfall of the empire through the energy of un civilized but more vigorous races. Christianity found slavery everywhere. It preached no revolution; it brought forward no abstract political or social theory ; but it undermined slavery by the expulsive force of the new principle of impartial justice, and self-denying love, and fraternal equality, which it inculcated. From the beginning it counselled patience and quiet endurance ; but it demanded fairness and kindness of the master, brought master and slave together at the common table of the Lord, and encouraged emancipation. The law of Constantine (a.d. 321), which forbade all civil acts on Sunday, except the emancipation of slaves, was in keeping with all his legislation on the subject of slavery. It is a true index of the state of feeling which is mani fest in the discourses of the eminent teachers of the Church of that period. Ancient slavery, and, afterward, serfdom in the medieval age, disappeared under the steady influence of Christian sentiment. The revival of slavery in modern times has been followed by a like result under the same agency. A century ago the slave-trade on the coast of Africa was approved by Protestant Christians. At first, after his conversion, John Newton, the pastor of Cowper, did not condemn it. But at length the perception dawned on his mind, and became a deep conviction, that the capture and enslave ment of human beings is unchristian. The same conviction en tered other minds. It grew and spread, until, in the treaties of POWER OF CHRISTIANITY TO TRANSFORM SOCIETY 1 13 leading nations, the slave-trade has been declared to be piracy. This amazing change was not wrought by a new revelation. It was the effect of the steady shining of the light of Christian truth long ago recorded in the Scriptures. If it were practicable to dwell uppn the varied consequences of the religion of Christ as they are seen in the actual state of Chris tian civilization, we should have to trace out the modifications of political science under the benign influence of the gospel, the transforming effect of Christian ethics in such departments as prison discipline and penal law, the new spirit that breathes in modern literature, which emanates from Christian ideas of human nature, of forgiveness, and of things supernatural — a spirit which is vividly felt when one passes from the dramas of _3ischylus to the dramas of Shakespeare — the way in which the arts of music, painting, and sculpture have developed new types of beauty and harmony from contact with the Christian faith, the indirect power of Christianity in promoting discoveries and inventions that con duce to health and material comfort, the softening influence of Christianity upon manners and social intercourse, and even move ments to protect animals from cruel treatment. But the topic is too broad to be pursued farther. To appreciate the magnitude of the results of Christianity, one must bear in mind that they do not consist alone or chiefly in ex ternal changes. There is a transformation of thought and feeling. The very texture of the spirits of men is not what it was. The conscience and the imagination, the standards of judgment, the ideals of character, the ends and aims of human endeavor, have undergone a revolution. When a continent, with its huge moun tains and broad plains, is gradually lifted up out of the sea, there is no doubt that a mighty force is silently active in producing so amazing an effect. What is any physical change in comparison with that moral and spiritual transformation, not inaptly called " a new creation," which Christianity has already caused? Now, the total effect of Christianity which Christendom — past and present, and future as far as we can foresee the future — pre sents, is due to the personal agency of Jesus of Nazareth. It can even be shown to be largely due to a personal love to him which animated the Christians of the first centuries, and which still per vades a multitude of disciples who call themselves by his name. Had this bond of personal gratitude and trust been absent, this 114 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF vast result could never have come to pass. The power of Chris tianity in moulding Christendom is undeniably owing to the reli gious and supernatural elements which are involved in the Ufe, character, and work of Jesus Christ. Had he been conceived of as merely a human reformer, a teacher of an excellent system of morals, a martyr, the effect would never have followed. Subtract the faith in him as the Sent of God, as the Saviour from sin and death, as the hope of the soul, and you lose the forces without which the religion of Jesus could never have supplanted the ancient heathenism, regenerated the Teutonic nations, and begotten the Christian civilization in the midst of which we live, and which is spreading over the globe. Men may raise a question about this or that miracle recorded in the gospels. The miracle of Christen dom, wrought by Christ, is a fact which none can question. CHAPTER VI THE EVIDENCE OF THE DIVINE ORIGIN OF CHRISTIANITY FROM ITS ETHICAL AND RELIGIOUS TEACHING AND FROM THE COMPARISON OF IT WITH THE GREEK PHILOSOPHY Christianity stands in an organic relation to the ancient reli gion of the Hebrews. The very name " Christ " is an Old Testa ment title. It is equally true, however, that Christianity is a signal advance upon the Old Testament religion. The Hebrew Scrip tures themselves point forward to an era when the system of which they are the records is to resolve itself into something almost inconceivably higher. That Christianity is on that higher plane foreshadowed of old, the New Testament distinctly and emphati cally declares, and it is quite evident. It did not confine itself to the reform of a system which had fallen into degeneracy. Far from it. Rather does it present itself in the teaching of Jesus, and elsewhere in the New Testament, as the absolute religion. It carries out to perfection whatever revelations had preceded. In this way alone could the ideal of the kingdom of God, before imperfectly conceived and dimly sketched, be realized. Through Christ the relation of God to the world is fully disclosed. In the long crusade against heathenism, along with the unity and personality of God, his transcendence was set forth in bold relief. It was left to the religion of the New Testament to emphasize its counterpart, his immanence. He is in the world, although not to be identified with it. Through Christ the kingdom of God actually attains its universal character. Religion is not coincident, as in all the ancient communities, with the limits of a single com munity. It is not restricted as was the cult of the Hebrew faith. The heavenly good of the gospel is of such a nature that it can be, and must be, offered indiscriminately to all men. The sense of a common relationship to Christ and to God melts away all differences. Appealing to a common religious sentiment, a com mon consciousness of sin and of the need of help, and offering a remedy that is equally adapted to all mankind, Christianity shows "5 Il6 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF itself possessed of the qualities of a universal religion. Christianity vindicates for itself this character, as being a religion of principles, not of rules. Where the aim of the teaching of Jesus is accom plished, the soul becomes a law to itself. The end which the soul sets before it is itself a criterion of what is to be done and what omitted. The purpose in view is to infuse a new life. The work of the gospel, as it is depicted both by Jesus and by the Apostles, is to effect a new creation in humanity — to render his disciples new creatures in the fellowship with him. It thereby establishes a filial connection between man and God. In its inculcation of seminal principles, not seeking to dictate or restrain conduct farther than these may prompt, it shows itself the ultimate type of religion. As to things external, those who insist on a leaden uniformity, unmodifiable forms of polity and ritual, misconceive the teaching of Jesus and the catholic quality which permeates it. The injunctions of the gospel are not a closed aggregate of precepts, cut and dried. They are truths containing seeds of development, so that the compass of perceived obligations, the ramifications of Christian duty, are perpetually spreading. The sphere of moral culture and of Christian beneficence, in its basis ever the same, is continually opening out in new directions.1 Thus it is-never outgrown and never obsolete. The ethical teaching of Jesus, confining moral good and evil to cherished feelings and inward purposes, attaches approval and condemnation, not to expressions in word and conduct in them selves, but, in the case of evil, to the hidden germs within the soul, the impure desire, the vindictive wish, the unjust or unchari table judgment, permitted in the heart. This is the exalted ideal of the gospel. In the teaching of Jesus, ethics and religion are inseparable. The essential nature of both is reducible to a single principle. In this particular His teaching is of transcendent worth. The duty is love to God in no confined measure, — love to the infinite Being, but like unto this law, that is, of a piece with it, and is impartial love to one's neighbor, — love to man. The sum of all obligations is the one principle of love to the universal society of which God is the head, and of which every man, being made in the image of God, yet finite in his nature, is a member and, in essential worth, the peer of every other. No simplification could be more 1 As illustrated admirably in fesus Christ and the Social Question, by F. G. Peabody. ETHICAL AND RELIGIOUS TEACHING OF CHRISTIANITY 117 complete or exhaustive. It extends over the whole field of human obligation, and goes down to the root of character. Christian ethics is sometimes charged with serious defects. J. S. Mill observes, " I believe that other ethics than that which can be evolved from exclusively Christian sources must exist side by side with Christian ethics to produce the moral regeneration of mankind." 1 He guards against misunderstanding by adding, " I believe that the sayings of Christ are all that I can see any evidence of their having been intended to be ; that they are irrec oncilable with nothing which a comprehensive morality requires ; that everything which is excellent in ethics may be brought within them, with no greater violence to their language than has been done by all who have attempted to deduce from them any prac tical system of conduct whatever." 2 If nothing more were meant than that the New Testament does not pretend to define all the particulars of duty, but leaves them in some cases to be inferred, Mill's observation would be just. He refers, in support of his criticism, to the absence of any recognition, in Christian ethics, of duty to the State, to the negative character of Christian precepts, to an exclusive emphasis laid upon the passive virtues, and to the want of reference to magnanimity, personal dignity, the sense of honor, and the like — qualities which, he says, we learn to esteem from Greek and Roman sources. The imputation that Christian precepts are preeminently nega tive, is surely not well founded. It is not " a fugitive and clois tered virtue " which is enjoined in the New Testament. To do good is made not less obligatory than to shun evil.3 The religion which has for its work to transform the world is not satisfied with a mere abstinence from wrong-doing. It is not true that by insisting on mutual benevolence, Chris tianity thereby weakens the force of particular obligations. The gospel does not frown upon patriotism any more than upon the domestic affections. Not the love of country, more than the love of kindred, is chilled by Christian teaching. The State, as well as the family, is recognized as a part of the divine, order. Jesus was moved to tears by the doom of Jerusalem. It was an Apostle who loved his own people so ardently that he was willing to be accursed for their sake.4 1 On Liberty, p. 93. B See e.g. Matt. v. 16, xxv. 43. 2 p. 94. * Romans ix. 3. Il8 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF If the passive virtues are prominent in the Christian system, it is not as the substitute, but as the complement, of qualities of another class. Revenge is unlawful ; truth is not to be propagated by vio lence ; but unrighteousness in every form is assailed with an earnest ness that admits of no increase. The non-resistance enjoined in the Sermon on the Mount is not a prohibition to inflict suffering upon wrong-doers, but to do this with retaliation as a motive, and not discerning the efficacy of the practice enjoined in the precept- " overcome evil with good." Nor does the religion of the New Testament discountenance the use of force for the protection of society. The magistrate is the minister of God for the execution of justice. As for magnanimity, the sense of honor, and kindred feelings, they are included in the category of whatsoever things are true, honest, pure, lovely, and of good report.1 Christianity ex cludes nothing that is admirable from its ideal of character ; and if there be virtues which have flourished on heathen ground, Chris tianity takes them up, while at the same time it infuses into them a new spirit — the leaven of self-renunciation. Robust and aggressive elements enter into the Christian ideal of character ; yet there was a reason why, at the outset, stress should be laid upon meekness, patience, resignation, and the other virtues called passive. The foes of a Christian were of his own household. All the forces of society, civil and ecclesiastical, were combined against him. There was the strongest possible need for the exercise of just these qualities. Particular affections, like the love of home and of country, have a root in Christian ethics. But since Christianity came into a world where patriotism, and other affections limited in their range, exercised a control that supplanted the broader principle of philanthropy, it was requisite that the wider and more generic principles should be inculcated with all urgency, not with a view to extirpate or enervate, but to keep within bounds and to purify subordinate principles of action. In Christian ethics, all the virtues, the milder and the more nega tive, with the bolder and the more heroic — courage in suffering and courage in action, the self-sacrifice of the mother in her house hold, of the patriot on the battle-field, of the missionary to dis tant nations — find a just recognition. In these inquiries it is important not to overlook the distinctive 1 Phil. iv. 8. See also I Cor. xiii., a chapter which evidently reflects the spirit of the ethical teaching of Jesus. ETHICAL AND RELIGIOUS TEACHING OF CHRISTIANITY Iig character of Christianity. It is a religion. It is not primarily or chiefly a code of moral precepts. Morality finds a broader state ment and a more impressive sanction, and, above all, it gains a new motive. But the morals of the gospel are not the first nor the main thing. Gibbon plumes himself on finding in Isocrates a pre cept which he pronounces the equivalent of the Golden Rule. He might have collected like sayings from a variety of heathen sources ; although neither Confucius nor any other of the authors in whom these sayings are found contains the Christian precept in a form at once positive and not merely prohibitive, and in a form universal, and not merely in reference to certain particular relations in life — as to that of father and son. But an ethical precept, not very remote in its tenor, may undoubtedly be cited from a number of ethnic teachers, and also from ancient Rabbis. Nowhere, to be sure, has it the preeminence assigned to it in the legislation of Jesus.1 But the originality of the gospel does not consist in particular direc tions pertaining to the conduct of life, however pure and noble they may be. On special points of duty it is true that Christianity speaks with an impressiveness never equalled elsewhere. But while an awe-inspiring tone is heard in its moral injunctions, not everything in them is absolutely novel. Christianity is, in its essence, a religion. Nor is the substance of Christianity to be found either in its doctrine of the immortality of the soul, nor in various other propositions which it is usual to classify under the head of religious beliefs. Christianity has been truly styled the religion of redemption. Here lies its defining characteristic. It is the approach of heaven to men, the mercy of God coming down to lift them up to a higher fellowship. The originality of Christianity is to be sought in the character and person of Christ and in the new life that goes forth from him, to be appropriated by the race of mankind. Probably no achievement of the human mind in the same field of thought outranks the Greek philosophy. In modern ages the literature on like themes is composed not without the potent aid of the Christian Scriptures, and the light which has spread 1 In the gospel, however, it does not supersede the need of the Christian exposition of that which the individual may rightfully claim or desire for him self. It is given to rid the disciple of the misleading effect of a selfish bias- in other words, to brace him up on the weak side. 120 THE GROUNDS OF THEISTIC AND CHRISTIAN BELIEF from this source. As indicating the native power of the human intellect to ascertain the truth in the sphere of ethics and re ligion, there is nothing which rises to the level of that develop ment of philosophical thought which Bacon styles " the pagan divinity." Hence a comparison of it with the teachings of Christ and His disciples ought to aid us in solving the question whether there is a likelihood that Christianity owes its being to man alone, or, as, according to the Evangelist, the question is stated by Christ Himself, — whether the teaching be of God, or whether He speaks of Himself.1 The Greek Philosophy was a preparation for Christianity in a threefold way. It dissipated, or tended to dissipate, the supersti tions of polytheism ; it awakened a sense of need which philoso phy of itself failed to meet ; and it so educated the intellect and conscience as to render the gospel apprehensible, and, in many cases, congenial to the mind. It did more than remove obstacles out of the way. Its work was positive as well as negative. It orig inated ideas and habits of thought which had more or less direct affinity with the religion of the gospel, and which found in this religion their proper counterpart. The prophetic element of the Greek philosophy lay in the glimpses of truth which it could not fully discern, and in the obscure and unconscious pursuit of a good which it could not definitely grasp. Socrates stands at the beginning of this movement. The pre ceding philosophy had been predominantly physical. It sought for an explanation of nature. The mystic, Pythagoras, blended with his natural philosophy moral and religious doctrine ; but that doctrine, whatever it was, appears to have rested on no scientific basis. Socrates is the founder of moral science ; and the whole subsequent course of Greek philosophy is traceable to the impulse which emanated from this remarkable man. He was aptly styled by the Florentine Platonist of the Renaissance, Marsilius Ficinus, the John the Baptist for the ancient world. i. The soul and its moral improvement was the great subject that employed his attention. All his inquiries and reflections, writes Xenophon, turned upon what was pious, what impious ; what honor able, what base ; what just, what unjust ; what wisdom, what folly ; what courage, what cowardice ; what a state or political commu nity, and the like. This searching method of laying bare weak- 1 John vii. 17. ETHICAL AND RELIGIOUS TEACHING OF CHRISTIANITY 121 ness and folly finally had the effect, as Xenophon records, that many " who were once his followers, had forsaken him." Who can fail to be reminded of the ptrdvoia — the self-judgment and reform — which were required at the very first preaching of the gospel? 2. Socrates asserted the doctrine of theism, and taught and ex emplified the spiritual nature of religion. It is true that he believed in " gods many and lords many." But he believed in one su preme, personal being, to whom the deepest reverence was to be paid. He taught the truth of a universal Providence. " He was persuaded," says the same disciple, "that the gods watch over the actions and affairs of men in a way altogether different from what the vulgar imagined ; for while these limited their knowledge to some particulars only, Socrates, on the contrary, extended it to all ; firmly persuaded that every word, every action, nay, even our most retired deliberations, are open to their view ; that they are everywhere present, and communicate to mankind all such knowl edge as relates to the conduct of human life." x He had only one prayer, that the gods would give him those things that were good, of which they alone were the competent judges. No service is so acceptable to the Deity as that of "a pure and pious soul."2 He counselled absolute obedience to the Deity, and acted on this principle. He chose his career in compliance with an inward call from God, which he did not feel at liberty to disregard. At his trial, in his Apology, he said, " Be of good cheer about death, and know this of a truth — that no evil can happen to a good man, either in life or after death." 3 3. Socrates had a belief, not a confident belief, in the future life and in the immortality of the soul. The last word in his final address is : " The hour of departure has arrived, and we go our ways — I to die, and you to live. Which is better, God only knows." 4 His last words to his friends, if we may trust the Phcedo, were significant of a hope. 5 4. In the ethical doctrine of Socrates, virtue is identified with 1 koi yap 4Tip.e\ei(r8ai Beois ivbpifev av8pi!nrwv, ob% ov rptnrov 0. troWol voplfrviriv, oEtoi piv yap otovrai toi). Beois ra pAv elSimi, ro 8' o6k e.S.xa.. 1.uKpi.Tr]s Se ir&vTO. piv i)ye?TO Beois elSivai, tA. t_ \eybpxva Kal irpairbpieva Kal ra