•YAnJEWKniVIEIRSJnnr- Gift of Ovl.tG, 190 3 A.T01TE1/LE!1TT. REVIEW OF "ATONEMENT AND LAW." (armour.) S* G.rBURNEY, D.D., LL.D., Professor of Systematic Theology, Cumberland University. "He that is first in his own cause seemeth just; but his neigh bor cometh and searcheth him." "Christ died for us" — not in our place, but in our interest, on our behalf NASHVILLE, TENN. Cumberland Presbyterian Publishing House. 1S87. 6ra PREFATORY. THE following Review of "Atonement and Law" was written at the request of members of the Theological Class of Cumberland University of ' 1885-86, and is now, by their request and that of oth ers who have read the manuscript, offered to the public. Mr. Armour's object, of course, was the vindication of what he believes to be the truth. I claim no more, no less, for myself. He, in the exercise of his indefeasible right of free dom of speech, has written boldly and earnestly. I, in the exercise of the same right, have written plainly and freely. Though I have controverted many of his positions and arguments with some freedom, I have done so without the slightest unkindly feeling, and oft en with high admiration of his candor, courage, and ability. The differences between us are not diversities of purposes, but of judgments, not concerning the fact, but concerning the nature of the atonement. On this, as on other difficult questions, Christians can very w.isely agree to disagree, and love as though they fully agreed. Free discussion is the crucible of truth, and is reprehensible only when attended with acerbity of feeling, or prosecuted in the interest of victory or party merely. Theories, it is allowed, are answerable for their nec essary consequences. A theory absurd in its conse- ¦ 3 4 Prefatory. quences can not be true in itself. I have attempted to test Mr. Armour's fundamental positions by this rule. It is probable that I have educed many consequences from his theory that he would not be willing to admit logically inhere in it. Possibly in some instances I may have misapprehended him, and thereby done him an unintentional injustice. If at any time I perceive that I have done this I will cheerfully make suitable amends. The reader in the meantime will assume the right to judge between us. I am fully aware of the fact that in controverting Mr. Armour's Substitutionary and Penal theory of Atonement, I also controvert some of the fundamental principles of the whole Substitutionary School. It will therefore be exceedingly difficult for substitution- ists of any school to judge impartially of the argu ments presented against Mr. Armour's theory. We very naturally look with suspicion upon an argument that tends to subvert a long cherished and generally accepted theory. But while I expect rash condemnation from those who have never investigated for themselves, whose faith is purely an inheritance, and not the product of their own patient and painstaking labor, I do as confidently expect support from those who have the ability and the courage to think for themselves. Substitution has been the generally accepted theory for centuries by those who hold to any theory of atone ment. I certainly hazard nothing in saying that not one in ten thousand of those who receive it has inves tigated the prime question, Whether substitutionary atonement with invariable double imputation is taught in the Holy Scriptures? This has not been the real point of inquiry. This has been gratuitously assumed, Prefatory. t and the great mass of thought has been expended in efforts to explain this substitutionary and penal scheme — e. g., Mr. Armour's book is a bold effort not to prove the doctrine from the Bible, or from any thing else, but to explain it — to put it in harmony with common sense, and with science, etc. Nothing is more difficult of explanation than non entity. Hence, the great diversity of explanations. Scarcely any two leading substitutionists agree. Mr. Armour, dissatisfied with the arguments of all his predecessors, attempts a new line of explanation and defense. Do not these facts throw grave suspicion upon the substitutionary principle itself? After patient investigation, I am compelled to be lieve the whole substitutionary and penal theory of atonement an impossible conceit, unauthorized by the Bible, incompatible with the fundamental principles of moral government, and indefensible before the bar of reason. I therefore beseech the discriminating reader to weigh carefully and as impartially as possible the arguments against Mr. Armour's theory. It is better to sacrifice prejudice to truth than truth to inherited error. I have not attempted in the following pages to say all that truth requires against substitution. My object has been rather to reply to Mr. Armour's peculiar views. In doing this, however, I have stated facts that are incompatible with a substitutionary atonement of any kind. I have attempted little more in these pages than td test the strength of Mr. Armour's new defenses of the substitutionary scheme. I have not even outlined an adverse theory. This may be something of a disap- 6 Prefatory. pointment to the reader. This defect — if it Is indeed a defect— I hope to supply, Providence permitting, at no distant day. These arguments against Mr. Armour's scheme of atonement, may be ignored, denounced, ridiculed — this is easy — but they, I think, will not be answered. Be lieving that this little book will, in the good providence of God, be the occasion of stimulating its readers to a more critical examination of the doctrine of atonement, and that it will in this way contribute to the advance ment of evangelical religion, I commit it to the gen erous consideration of the Christian public. S. G. BURNEY. Lebanon, Tenn., November, 1SS6. CONTENTS, PAGE. Animadversions upon Mr. Armour's Preface, , . . . 10 Animadversions upon the Introductory Chapter, . . 13 Section I. The Divine Nature the Source of Divine Law, etc., . . 19 Section II. Law as Force 43 Section III. Law in Commandment, 47 Section IV. Sundry Topics — Divine Sovereignty, Voluntary Necessity, Confirmation, 77 Section V. The Will SS Section VI. Sin Strictly Debt, 87 Section VII. " Substitution Normal in Law," 95 Section VIII. Substitution Proved to be Abnormal by the Impossibility of itsConditions 115, Section IX. The Great Antitype Substitution, 131 Section X. Suretyship an Re-instatement, 150 Section XI. Penalty — Meritorious and Unmeritorious, . . . 159 (7) S Contents. Section XII. Equivalent Penalty, 169 Section XIII. Relaxation of Law and Self-condemnation, . . . 186 Section XIV. Suretyship and Covenant Engagement, .... 193 Section XV. Atonement a Variable Quantity, 196 Section XVI. Intervention by Adequate Power 203 Section XVII. Illustrations of Intervention, 218 Section XVIII. Scientific Pretensions, ....... 232 ATONEMENT. "ATONEMENT AND LAW: OR, REDEMP TION IN HARMONY WITH LAW, AS REVEALED IN NATURE. BY JOHN M. ARMOUR." This is an octavo of 240 pages, gotten up in good style, pub lished by the Christian Statesman Publishing Company, 1520 Chestnut street, Philadelphia. THIS book has produced something of a sensation among those who are specially interested in the study of theology. It has re ceived high commendation from many that hold to the doctrine that the great atonement is substitutionary and penal in character, and is provided for only a part of mankind. Some, also, whose views are so far liberalized as to allow that the great atonement is provided for all men indiscriminately, are somewhat lavish in their praise of the work. Of course these claim the privilege of dis senting from our author's ungracious limita- rianism. Whether these high commendations have been wisely bestowed remains to be seen. If Mr. Armour has rendered any valu- (9) 10 Atonement Reviewed. able service to our common evangelical Chris tianity, if he has so presented its great central doctrine as to commend it with greater clear ness and force to the reason and consciences of men, and make it a greater power for good, then due honor should be accorded to him, both for his good intentions and for his sagaci ty and skill in defense of truth. I confess to very grave doubts as to such results. The ground of this distrust will be indicated in the following pages. ANIMADVERSIONS UPON MR. ARMOUR'S PREFACE. In his preface our author says: "The views presented in this volume have not been hasti ly adopted. They are the result of many years of patient and absorbing study. They have, moreover, been fully submitted to the judgment of many eminent scholars and theo logians, and have received their unequivocal and hearty approval." Remarks. — Approval by many "eminent scholars and theologians" is not proof of the soundness of Mr. Armour's "views." Papal supremacy, transubstantiation, general atone ment, etc., receive " the unequivocal and hearty approval of many eminent scholars and theo- Comments on Preface. n logians." But Mr. Armour does not, on this account, believe these doctrines. Such ap proval may give something of respectability, but on strongly contested questions is not even presumptive evidence. Mr. Armour continues: " While I have been led strongly to dissent from certain views and statements with which the scriptural doctrine of Atonement has been overlaid, that doctrine in its historical evangelical form will be found to be maintained in these pages." Remarks. — From this we learn that our author does not object to the old substitution ary theory as such, but to the manner in which it is stated. These defective statements he points out and attempts to correct in his subsequent pages. He continues: "The views here pre sented indicate the ground from which the or thodox doctrine of the great satisfaction must at last be defended." Remarks. — Our author has fully persuaded himself that he has founded the doctrine of atonement (improperly called the great satis faction) upon an everlasting rock. So thought the great Turrettin, when he demolished the Copernican theory, and proved to the stisfac- 12 Atonement Reviewed. tion of orthodoxy that the earth did not move. He, however, was in error, but possibly not more so than is Mr. Armour. Mr. Armour says: "That the great redemp tion was wrought out in perfect accordance with law as revealed in nature and providence ; that it was no departure from the divinely or dained order in the administration of law ; that it was merely the highest exemplification of principles, recognized everywhere through out the divine government, are conclusions to ward which Christian thought has been tend ing in all the ages past." Remarks. — (i) That the plan of salvation should be in strictest accord with the moral law which is intended for the government of the moral world, is a conclusion fully author ized by every thing we know of God and nature. (2) That a rational and religious creat ure should crave a religion that does not require an implicit faith in palpable absurdities is a most reasonable thing. For both these rea sons Mr. Armour's theory of atonement will be rejected by thousands of thoughtful men. That our author's theory of atonement in stead of being a satisfaction of law, is a breach of law, a nullification of law " by sovereign prerogative " — an ingenious piece of sophistry, Comments on Preface. 13 which is unworthy of rational acceptance, will be made sufficiently manifest in the fol lowing pages. ANIMADVERSIONS UPON INTRODUCTORY CHAPTER. "Atonement and Law " comprises two parts, with an " Introductory Chapter." The intro ductory chapter discusses " The scientific ob jections to the prevalent theory of Redemp tion. The real question at issue: Is Re demption the great exception? Recognized analogies and correspondences; Scripture emblems; False theories of atonement fore doomed; No relaxation of law in accepting the satisfaction of Christ; Sovereignty in re demption as in creation; The miracle of re demption, like all miracles, by intervention of adequate power, not by suspension of law." QUOTATIONS FROM THIS CHAPTER. 1. " Christian apologists have generally, in the face of the enemy (skeptical scientists), admitted that revealed religion is, in the main features, the ' great exception.' . . . Redemp tion by intervention and by substitution an exception that is not provided for in the nature of law." (p. 20.) 14 Atonement Reviewed. Remarks. — This admission in reference to substitution is a high compliment both to the sagacity and candor of these Christian apologists. If Christians generally, and sci entists universally, have adjudged substitution to be " not provided for in the nature of law," then Mr. Armour ought to furnish us with some convincing reasons before he asks us to set aside this testimony and accept his state ments; for there is, perhaps, no question with in the range of human knowledge, in which Christians and scientists are more fully agreed than that substitution is not provided for in the nature of law. 2. " There are mighty arguments in favor of a bolder course. The attack of the enemy will constrain the Christian hosts to seek firm er ground." (p. 20.) Remarks. — (1) Our author here assumes that the whole Christian hosts are substitution- ists — a slight mistake. (2) He here concedes that substitution can not be defended without firmer ground than that upon which it has hith erto been maintained — that is, if substitution is "not provided for in the nature of law." Then the whole theory of substitutionary atonement is incapable of defense. I think our author is fully justified in staking the Comments on Preface. 15 whole issue upon the simple question as to whether substitution with double imputation is provided for in the nature of law. This is an admission that Turrettin, Hodge, Syming ton, and Christian apologists generally have asserted substitution on insufficient grounds. 3. "The Bible, more than any other book in the world, appeals to nature with boundless confidence. The proper study of nature is quite as necessary to the understanding of the Bible as is the study of the Bible to the prop er interpretation of nature." (p. 22.) Remarks. — This is admissible. But having appealed to nature, why does not our author stick to it, and abide by its faithful teachings ? Why does he shun nature when he wishes to find analogies in the interest of substitution with double imputation ? Why appeal to fickle, whimsical, human laws for such analo gies ? Mr. Armour knows why. The vam pire does not go to the cucumber for blood. Instinct directs it elsewhere. 4. " Theories of the Atonement, constructed in defiance alike of Scriptural Truth and Natu ral Law, are foredoomed." (p. 24.) Remarks. — (1) In this I fully concur. As Mr. Armour's substitutionary atonement, with its 16 Atonement Reviewed. double imputation, is " constructed in defiance alike of Scriptural Truth and Natural Law," and rests exclusively upon some supposed analogies with human law, I deem it hopeless ly " foredoomed." (2) But why does our au thor persist in insinuations that substitution is provided for in natural or physical law? He does not, dares not categorically affirm it; yet he puts the matter before his readers as if such substitutions were a universally known fact. Perhaps he wishes us to believe that such substitutions are provided for, but that they do not occur because the Creator has neglected to provide adequate substitutes. 5. "The Saviour once provided, and having freely come under law, thenceforward all was done in obedience to law. All that was needed for our Redemption the law itself then required of him who became our surety, and who was under law, and was ' mighty to save.' " (p. 26). Remarks. — (1) The doctrine is that Christ having become a substitute for the elect, and fulfilled the penalty and precept of the law in their stead, the law imperatively requires their salvation. If they are not willing to be saved the law requires that they should be made willing— regenerated and necessitated to be lieve, repent, be justified, and saved. The Comments on Preface. 17 process smacks of physical rather than of moral law. (2) Mr. Armour, of course, be lieves himself one of the elect, and, hence, be lieves that God or Christ is bound by the law, or something he calls law, to save him. Now, it would be a matter of interest to psycholog ical science to know whether his faith and his feelings have always been in exact har mony on this subject. Though, according to his theory, he was actually saved before Adam was created, he has not always been conscious of that fact. I have never known any person, except vulgar blasphemers, who could say that they either believed or felt that God is under obligations to save them, when speaking of their personal salvation. What a nondescript state of feel ings would arise out of the two inhomogeneous beliefs — that I am a miserable and guilty sin ner, and that God is under obligations to save me, or rather has already saved me ! Creed-blind theorists alone, I think, are capable of holding such incongruities as that a man may be innocent before the bar of Divine Justice, but guilty before the bar of conscience; justified in heaven, but condemned on earth; have a law-title to eternal life, but subjective ly fit only for spiritual death. 6. "God provided a Saviour for all men; no 18 Atonement Reviewed. sovereign choice of part of our race; God gave Christ to die, and Christ died, alike for all men." (p. 27.) Mr. Armour quotes these words reprobative- ly, and vents over them a flood of emotional rhetoric. As there is neither logic nor poetry in his rhetoric, I will not quote it. His sensi bilities seem to be shocked at the idea that Christ died alike for all men. That, with him, means universalism, though it does not with any except substitutionists of the closest school. He quotes, exclamatively, the words, "No sovereign choice ! Ah ! What do we meet? Sovereignty, actually determining some to life and some to destruction, and this after all had been alike embraced in one glorious purpose of love; nay, had been redeemed by the same precious blood!" Mr. Armour seems horrified at the idea that God can be sovereign, and yet make sal vation conditional. He understands the word sovereign in the sense of the unconditional, for which he has no authority. He also es teems it monstrous heresy to allow that any for whom Christ died could, by possibility, be lost. Paul, however, was of a different opin ion. (Rom. xiv. 15.) SECTION I. IN PART I. MR. ARMOUR DISCUSSES LAW, MORAL AND NATURAL. This comprises four chapters. The first treats of " Motion, Force, and Life;" the second of "The Latest Idol — the Nature of Things;" the third of "The Nature of Moral Law," and the fourth of " The Will." THESE several topics are not very closely discriminated in the discussion — are, in fact, very much blended. The most of these topics have only the slightest connection with the main subject of the book, the Atonement, and for this reason will not be specially no ticed. In our author's estimation, the atonement is purely a matter of law. Law, consequently, is the obtrusive theme of discussion, running through the whole book. On the subject of law he says many true things, many good things. His utterances, however, are vigorous rather than clear; they impress rather than instruct. His vehe mence and earnestness make the reader feel (19) 20 Atonement Reviewed. that he ought to believe something, without showing him exactly what he is expected to believe. I will briefly refer to a few instances: i. Under the head of "Motion, Force, and Life" (p. 33), he says: " Law has its origin in the nature of God. This is true of natural as well as of moral law, for they are not separated; they are not separable; they do not merely co-operate, nor is it the whole truth to say that they become one — they are one in awful, onward movement in the universe." Remarks. — (1) Here we have a combina tion of strong, plain words, but I do not know exactly what I am expected to believe. The first proposition gives me no distinct idea as to the source of the law. If our author means that law grows spontaneously and necessarily out of the nature of God, he evidently logically involves himself both in fatalism and atheism; for acts only, not natures, are productive or causative. If God's being and nature are necessary, not voluntary, and if that necessary nature is necessarily the source of law, it is of course the origin of every thing else, and fate, or God, as fate, rules the world. Hence, if our author's words are taken in their ordi nary forces, he teaches essential error when Law, Moral and Natural. 21 he says, " law has its origin in the nature of God." If he does not mean his words to be taken literally, then I do not know what he means. Any philosophy that refers the origin of law, or any thing else, to the nature of God instead of his acts, is chargeable with atheism. Action alone gives origin to things, but natures never act. They are only the characteristics of the presupposed actors. (2) I am also in a fog as to our author's meaning in what he says about the relation of natural and moral law. Does he mean that they are the same or different laws ? He says "they do not mere ly co-operate." This means that they are dis tinct. Again, he says, " Nor is it the whole truth to say that they become one." This means that they have been distinct, but have coalesced and become one. Again, he con tinues, " They are one in awful, onward move ment." This means, or seems to mean, that they have lost their distinct individuality and become one. If our author means that physical and moral law in relation to the individual have the same general, not specific, ends, then no protest need be offered. If he means that neither can be violated with impunity, no dissent should be offered. But if he means that they are so related that the violation of one necessarily 22 Atonement Reviewed. involves the violation of the other, he evident ly deceives himself. It is probably true that no one can violate the moral law without ex periencing more or less physical evil. But the law of our physical well-being may be violated without a violation of moral law, otherwise all deaths by accident are murders. Our author says these laws " are one in aw ful, onward movement in the universe." Here the exact meaning is obscured by the glitter of the rhetoric. 2. Mr. Armour, in his onslaught upon the " latest idol, the nature of things," has some thing more to say about the source of law (pp. 49, 50): "There is nothing determined by the nature of God which is not determined by the will of God. To attribute certain de terminations to the will of God, and others to his nature, is to make a distinction for which there is not only no foundation, but one that is inconsistent with the very conception of an infinitely perfect being. What proceeds from the nature of God proceeds from the will of God." Remarks. — There is no want of clear ness in these propositions. God is a necessary being; his nature is equally necessary. His will is in all determinations identical with his Law, Moral and Natural. 23 nature. Hence, his acts are as necessary as his being; or Mr. Armour here concedes that the divine nature determines and the divine will determines: "What proceeds from the nature proceeds from the will; and to discrim inate between these determinations, or be tween what proceeds from the nature and what from the will, is to make a distinction which has no foundation." Now, to determine is the highest conceiv able form of action. But to act is to be caus ative of something. If the divine nature acts at all, it must cause or originate law, all divine law. Now, this is all the worshiper of the " latest idol " claims — especially those who say that the absolute standard of right is the divine nature. The real point of difference between Mr. Armour and the idolaters seems to be this: The latter make the divine nature the absolute standard of right, while the former makes the divine nature, inclusive of the divine will, the absolute standard; for he says (p. 51): "But if God's nature, which makes right right, is a nature wherein his will has place, and is in glorious activity and dominancy, how can his will be spoken of as, in any sense, excluded from making right right? " The single point of difference between the theories seems to be 24 Atonement Reviewed. that one makes the will a part of the divine nature, and the other excludes it. Whatever may be the value of this difference, it is de cidedly against Mr. Armour. First, if the will is included in the divine nature, and the divine nature as thus consti tuted determines the right, or originates law, then the will itself can not be the standard of right, as our author alleges; for this would be to make a -part of the divine nature determi native of the right or law, which is simply absurd. Those who make the divine nature determinative of the right are involved in no such absurdity. Secondly, Mr. Armour, I think, gains noth ing to compensate his theory for this serious loss. He can not afford to make the will a part of the divine nature, and at the same time in dependent of that divine nature. This would make the will independent of itself. Nor can he afford to make the will a part of the divine nature, and yet say that the divine nature determines the will to action; for this would make the will, so far as it is a factor in the divine nature, determine itself, which in volves, as Edwards has clearly shown, the absurdity of an endless regressus. The theory against which Mr. Armour is Law, Moral and Natural. 25 battling avoids this absurdity. It would be exceedingly difficult to put all Mr. Armour's statements in harmony with himself. Note the following: (1) "What is determined by his nature is determined not for but by his will." (p. 50.) Then it follows, of course, that the will be ing a part of the nature we have the will de termining itself. This again involves the fatal regressus. (2) The will "in glorious activity and domi nancy." The will, then, being a part of the divine nature, the will is in a state of domi nancy over the will. (3) " The will of God, being of his nature, is itself the absolute standard of right." (p. 50.) If the will was the whole of the divine nature the proposition would not be absurd. But it is only of, or a part of that nature, conse quently can not of itself, or independent of other factors in that nature, be the absolute standard of right. Just as well say a -part is equal to the whole. It seems to be sufficiently clear that our au thor has worsted himself in his battle against the "latest idol," not because the "latest idol" is invulnerable, but because our author seeks to replace it with something far less defensible. Both theories of the source of the divine 26 Atonement Reviewed. law or rule of right are radically false; both, when carried to their logical consequences, lead to fate, and to atheism as well. To posit the rule of right outside of God, and make it independent of him, as Dr. Haven and many others do, or to make it the product of the divine nature, whether that nature in cludes or excludes the divine will, is to ex clude freedom from the whole world and put God under the dominion of necessity. The first theory asserts that God is not the author of moral law, but is bound by it, and somehow comes to be the executive of it. This denies to God supremacy. But if he is not supreme, then he is not God at all. In regard to the other theory, it is hardly necessary to say that God has as little control over his being and nature, or what makes him what he is, as he has over any thing that might be outside of him, or inde pendent of him. If he can act only as impelled by a power within him, called his nature, then he of course has no more power over himself than has the heart over its necessitated contractions, or the oak over its growth. The following quotations (pp. 54-56) will further enlighten the reader concerning the relation of law to the law-giver: Law, Moral and Natural. 27 " What we recognize in the realms of moral or natural law, as that which could not but be, we should recognize as logically connected with the absolute perfection of the one being whose existence, and whose perfection, and whose will, rendered necessary that entire nature of things of which so much is predicated." Remarks.— Here are named three factors by which the nature of things is necessitated — the existence, the perfection, and the will of God. Which is the determining force? Or, are they all equally determinative of the result? It is manifest that perfection presup poses existence, and our author makes will an essential part of the perfection or nature. It hence follows that for God to be is to necessi tate the "entire nature of things," or what ever is possible. 2. Again, " The necessary existence of God settles every thing, leaves nothing conditional or contingent, determines all the axioms in the realms of moral and natural law. The nature of God being what it is, these could not but be as they are, and this is true of what are called the free and sovereign works or acts of God, even as of those distinguished from them as his necessary acts. This view, in no re spect interferes with the doctrine of pure and 28 Atonement Reviewed. mere sovereignty; for the sovereign acts of God proceed from his nature as do those we call his necessary acts, for these were deter mined from eternity as fully and irrevocably as his necessary acts. When God says, ' I will have mercy on whom I will have mercy,' he assuredly means to set before us his will in its utmost freedom and sovereignty. But this supreme act of free and sovereign grace is the act of God himself — an act unto which the whole nature of God (his will being in cluded in that nature) moved him. "That God might have done otherwise in this matter, and yet have been the God he is, is a theory of well-meaning theologians — a theory inconsistent with the highest concep tion of God. That the saved deserved noth ing, that they had no claim upon God, that there was noobligationwpon God from without, must never be forgotten; but to hold that the will of God acted for our salvation when his nature did not require it, is to glorify the will of God at the expense of a supposed nat ure of God. In fact, we discover what the nature of God requires him to do mainly by what he, by his will, actually does. Freedom or sovereignty in God does neither imply («) any dissociation of the act from the nature of God, nor (b) any doubt or contingency as to Law, Moral and Natural. 29 the result. To attribute to God a sovereignty that does either of these, is not to honor but to dishonor him. There are, and perhaps ever will be, those who are unable to accept the doctrine that acts may be predetermined and certain from eternity, and yet be, in the fullest sense, free acts. There may be those who imagine that freedom, whether in God or in man, necessarily involves uncertainty. For such notions there is perhaps no effectual cure." Remarks. — (I have made this long quota tion that the reader may fully understand the animus of Mr. Armour's philosophy. He certainly displays admirable courage. His mode of presenting his theory stands in bold contrast with the timid, half-apologizing style of many who hold substantially the same phi losophy.) (1) The basal and all-controlling principle of his theory is that all things in the universe, God included, are just as they are from re morseless necessity. The logic is substan tially thus: God exists not of choice but of necessity — his nature is not optional, but nec essary, and his will is included in his nature (properly no will at all). This necessitated nature necessitates all divine acts, so called. 30 Atonement Reviewed. These necessitated acts necessitate all the en tities and events of the universe. ' God being necessarily what he is, it was not possible for him to necessitate any thing more or different from what he has necessitated; nor possible for any event that occurs in the dominion either of matter or of spirit not to occur just as it does occur; nor for any other event to occur than what does actually occur. The God of the Armourian philosophy seems to be an omnipotent, conscious force shut up by an indigenous necessity to move, and to move in a particular way; not free not to act, nor free to act differently from what he does. This conscious, omnipotent force is free in Mr. Armour's esteem, but it is freedom without a possible alternative — free like -the revolving earth. (2) Mr. Armour seems to be involved in grave embarrassment concerning the divine nature. He makes the will a part of the nat ure, yet God does what he does by his will. He says: "In fact we discover what the nature of God requires him to do mainly by what he, by his will, actually does." Here we have the strange doctrine that God is required by his will, as a factor in his nature, to do what he does — that is, the nature and the will are confounded, and yet distinct. Law, Moral and Natural. 31 Mr. Armour may understand this; certainly no one else understands it. (3) Again, all requirements or imperatives are laid upon the will. Requirements are never made of stones or things without will. But according to our author, the will, as a fac tor in the divine nature, lays imperatives upon the will. Here master and servant are confounded. The will that obeys the require ment is the will, which, as a factor in the nature, requires the obedience. (4) Again, according to our author, God is not under obligations from without to save any body, but his nature requires him to save some; for "to hold that the will of God acted for our salvation when his nature did not re quire it, is to glorify the will of God at the ex pense of a supposed nature of God." But there is no such thing as a Divine Being apart from the divine nature. We might as well talk of matter apart from all the properties of matter as of a Divine Being apart from his nature. There consequently is absolutely ¦nothing upon which the divine nature can lay its imperatives to save some. Again, admitting all our author's impossible conceits, it is pertinent to inquire: If the di vine nature requires God to save some, why 32 Atonement Reviewed. not all? According to our author's philosophy, the divine nature required God to make man, just as he is, sins and all. Now, the point pleading for solution is, whether this same di vine nature requires God to save a part and destroy a part of those whose being and character his own nature necessitated? Might we not as well say that gravity requires one apple to fall to the earth and another, from the same limb, to take a jaunt to the moon; or that vitality requires of one grain of corn to project its roots into the soil and another into the air? Is the divine nature, which is as sumed to give law to God, nothing more than a capricious, lawless something which can Stultify itself by doing contradictory things? Again, if the nature of God requires him to do " by his will what he actually does," then does not the nature of man require him to do what he actually does?1 or, rather does not the nature of God, which necessitated man's nat ure, require man to do all that he actually does? Certainly, and this is predestination by " the necessary nature of God." Mr. Armour's philosophy furnishes every man with a revelation of all God's secret de crees concerning himself. To experience a thought, a feeling, a purpose, is to know that Law, Moral and Natural. 33 God decreed it. The history of every man is a history of God's eternal purposes concern ing the man. If the reader will study Mr. Armour's phi losophy he can not fail to recognize it as one of the most relentless and most bunglesome schemes of fatality ever conceived by the hu man mind. Its logical consequence is atheism. (5.) Mr. Armour deems it inconsistent with the highest conception of God to concede it possible for him ever to act otherwise than as he does. He also thinks it a great weakness to deny that predestinated or necessitated acts in God or men are inconsistent with such free dom as renders a true morality and a rational religion possible. Among those guilty of this weakness, I will mention Herman Lotze, who was confessedly one of the brightest lights of the scientific world. The following quotations taken from " Philosophy of Religion " may be profitably studied in connection with Mr. Armour's views of freedom. He asserts freedom with the possibility of an alternative. He says (pp. 99-102): "But we know surely that we only demand this formal free dom because we regard it as the conditio sine qua non for the fulfillment of ethical com mands, whose obligatory majesty we consider 3 34 Atonement Reviewed. to be the most absolute certainty, and one that needs no derivation from any other source whatever. This conviction is the ab solutely fundamental point upon which the en tire religious character of our view of the world depends. And for him who does not directly experience and acknowledge this, all questions of religious philosophy are altogeth er superfluous. " The ideas of freedom are not induced by speculation, but they rest entirely upon the fact of that penitence and self-condemnation in which we believe we find the immediate assurance of the possibility that the choice, whose failure is now repented of, might have been reached even sooner than it was. "This idea is, in an obscure way, the first and most natural, the one that has precedence in human culture. It was not till a later period that the scientific contemplation of nature disclosed the conception of a ' neces sary causal connection,' and then extended it over the whole course of the world, so that now the idea of freedom seems like a strange exception, and, as such, is denied (denied by atheists, who assert a universal necessity, but this very necessity is what necessitarian theists call the highest possible form of freedom). It is acknowledged that even the ethical ideals Law, Moral and Natural. 35 originate in the mechanical course of psychic al development. " But how much influence they have upon our action, depends entirely upon the involun tary states and movements within our own inte rior being. It is, therefore, due to a process of nature that the impulse to good actions, or even to bad actions, preponderate within us, and the mechanical conditions for such results may be strengthened by a correct or by a per verted education. (So reason the atheist and the necessitarian theist). "But to be consistent and candid about it, an action in the proper sense, such as would issue from our own ego, will then no longer exist. And even the inducement to all such reflections — that is, the feeling of penitence — will be regarded as a disagreeable state, about like a feeling of sickness; and it will be main tained (by the necessitarian) that the wish in volved in this feeling — the wish that we had acted differently — gives no assurance what ever of this having been possible at an earlier moment. " Such views as the foregoing are not to be got at by speculation; they involve no contra diction of cognition. If they are abandoned, it can be done only upon the basis of an un- demonstrable belief that after all there is di- 36 Atonement Reviewed. rectly disclosed in the aforesaid self-condem nation the possibility of a free choice, without which 'the bad conscience' and the pain of 'penitence' would continue to be totally inex plicable phenomena in a rational order of the world." This brief but clear statement of the doc trine of freedom, with an alternative in oppo sition to the doctrine of necessity, is followed by a concise and cogent reply to the objections that are often urged against true freedom. We should not fail to note the difference in the methods of Armour, the Christian theologian, and Lotze, the Christian philosopher. The former adopts the scholastic a priori method, and infers that God's acts are necessarily as they are because he is necessarily as he is; or that his being and nature necessarily cause, determine, limit his acts, so that they must be, but can not be different from what they are. Having reached this conclusion, it is an ob vious and necessary corollary that the same principle applies to every thing in the universe, both entities and events; hence, whatever is, is of necessity, and necessarily is as it is. But to save theism, moral distinctions, and religion,, this necessity must, by a monstrous abuse of terms, however, be called freedom. The Christian philosopher adopts the Ba- Law, Moral and Natural. 37 conian, the a posteriori, method. Instead of attempting to determine the actions of intelli gent beings from abstract ideas of their nature, he determines the nature of such beings by their acts. Instead of assuming to know the nature of things and then infer their effects from this nature he pursues the less preten tious but more rational method of judging of causes by these effects — of things by their phenomena. Instead of inferring that men act under necessity because God necessarily exists, he infers that men act freely from the effect of their acts upon their own psychical states, their feelings, their consciences. He takes it for granted that God in nature is consistent with himself — does not contradict himself by necessitating an act and then necessitating pain, remorse, a bitter sense of self-condem nation for committing that necessitated act. Penitence, self-condemnation, remorse are unimpeachable witnesses of freedom with an alternative. If freedom with an alternative is an essen tial characteristic of the human mind, it is the sum of absurdities to deny it of the divine mind. This I suppose would be universally conceded. SECTION II. LAW AS FORCE AND LAW AS COM- MANDMENT. MR. ARMOUR says (p. 34): "Natural law is but the name we have given to the ob served uniform method of the acting of the Su preme Power, whether acting directly or by means of any series of second causes however extended. When in common language we speak of any result as produced by the operation of natural law, we can mean nothing else than the acting of some power or being, according to an established and uniform method." Remarks. — The principal objection to this statement in regard to law is its indecision as to the manner in which the Supreme Power acts, " whether acting directly or by means of any series of second causes." Our author seems sometimes to favor one and sometimes the other method. My principal object in making the citation is to compare it with what he says of natural (38) Law as Force and Commandment. 39 law on p. 68: "Law as force and law as com mandment, these are the two forms of law known to us. They are both directly from the will of God. Infinite power confessedly insures the inviolability of every natural law. Infinite power sustains every moral law." Remarks. — (1) Here we have natural "law as force." We can put this in harmony with what he has previously said of law as a "uni form method of acting " by taking the word law to mean the force that acts according to uniform method. But this reduces his "law as force " to the unmeaning form force as force. (2) He says: "They (natural and moral law) are both directly from the will of God." Then law must be something distinct from that will, must have objective reality, must be some thing more than "the observed uniform act ing of the Supreme Power," or conception of the mind; must be itself a force capable of action, for action is the only test of existence. (3) " Infinite power confessedly insures the inviolability of every natural law." In what sense must we take the word law in this state ment, in that of an observed order of acting, or of that which acts? If we understand it 40 Atonement Reviewed. in the sense of an observed order of acting, then we can never, intentionally or otherwise, do physical harm to ourselves, others, or any thing else; for its inviolability is insured by in finite power, and no harm can come except by violation of law. But if we take law to mean that which acts "according to an estab lished and uniform method," then inviolability seems to be an unnatural and unmeaning predicate of it. The earth, the sun, the air, the horse, etc., all act, but we would not be willing to predicate either violability or invio lability of such things. What our author really means by " law " in these propositions, I do not know, but suppose that in the last he means " the observed and uniform method of acting." But if the word is taken in this sense, then the question arises, Is it true that infinite pow er confessedly insures the inviolability of every natural law? Our physical well-being depends upon compliance with certain conditions. These conditions and their established conse quence may be expressed by the word law. But infinite power does not insure the inviola bility of this law. It insures only the relation between cause and effect, antecedent and con sequent. Not to comply with this established Law as Force and Commandment. 41 order of antecedence is what is universally understood by violating the law. If I violate this I must take the consequences. (4) Why does our author discriminate be tween physical and moral law, making infinite power insure the inviolability of one and only sustain the other? Both, he tells us, are directly from the will of God. One sustains exactly the same relation to the physical world that the other does to the moral world. Taking the word law in either of the senses named above, I see no sufficient reason for the distinction indicated by our author. In the quotation from page 38, Mr. Armour seems to reject realism in toto; but in the last quota tion he seems, but perhaps only seems, to adopt it. The word law is a convenient abstract term, expressive of the ascertained relation of ante cedent and sequence, condition and result. But " law as force " has absolutely no existence. There is no power, no force, no action in law. Nor is the term properly used to express any such an idea. It is simply a convenient ab stract term for expressing, in a brief manner, our conception of the orderly and uniform ac tion and reaction of the forces or powers of what we commonly call nature; or the orderly and uniform methods by which God, imma- 42 Atonement Reviewed. nent in all things, sustains and governs the physical and moral world. God himself is the motive power of the world; nor has he delegated this power to subalterns, improperly called law, as forces, which he sustains by his " infinite power." He is immanent in every thing, and acts in and through every thing. ' The marvelous ac tion and reaction of one thing upon another is but the continuous exercise of his power. What we call second causes are not his deputized agents, but the instrumentalities and condi tions of the exercise of his ubiquitous and omnipotent power in the on-going of the world. This divine action in nature, in every thing, is conditioned — one event conditions another. Hence, the relation of antecedence and se quence, of cause and effect; hence the order and trustworthiness of nature, or rather of this ubiquitous and omnipotent power in nature. The exercise of this divine power in the physical and moral world is purposedly so conditioned that man, in a limited sphere, may furnish the requisite conditions of certain events, and thus render the exercise of this power, the source of good or evil, to himself or to others. In fact, the whole of human ac tivity consists in supplying the conditions of the influence of this power for good or evil. Law as Force and Commandment. 43 To do certain things is to supply the ante cedents or conditions of good. To do the contrary is to supply the conditions of evil. The antecedents, the conditions given, the consequences, the good or the evil, the re ward or punishments inevitably follow. The conditions are, in an important sense, from men; the reward or punishment is from God. This is God's method or rule of action in dealing with men; and because it is his rule of action, we call it his law. Hence, it is plain that law is not in itself a force — is not an agent or substitute for God — but is simply the immutably fixed method, or rule, or plan, according to which God himself acts in sus taining and governing the world. Hence, to do those things which God has fixed as the conditions of Good is to obey the law; to do the contrary things, is to disobey the law. To obey is to insure the reward; to disobey is to incur the penalty. The law itself is simply our perception of this divinely established relationship between antecedents and their consequences — causes and effects. This fixed relationship is of course "from the will of God," but our ap prehension of it is no more from the will of God than are our other cognitions — is no more sustained by " infinite power " than other hu- 44 Atonement Reviewed. man conceptions. The mechanic and the rule he works by are different things. The me chanic is an entity — a power, a cause. The rule is not an entity, or a cause, but a concep tion of the mind — a pure ideal, and can never do the work of the mechanic. Again, God acts in all things, and through this action all things exert their claims to ex istence. Hence, philosophy requires us to be lieve that action, or influence of some kind, is the only test of being. Whatever acts exists, for action implies an actor or power that acts. What does not act does not exist, for exist ence itself is action of some kind. Laws neither act nor are acted upon. They cause nothing, modify nothing, receive or suffer nothing, consequently have no claims to ex istence as entities. They exist only as thoughts or images in the mind. When we speak of the supremacy of law, the majesty of law, the authority of law, the inflexibility of law, the requirements of law, the prohibitions of law, the rewards of law, the penalties of law, the satisfaction of law, we personify law, and attribute to it the func tions of the law-maker. What Mr. Armour wishes his readers to understand by his Law as Force, is a puzzle. Law as Force and Commandment. 45 He tells us so many diverse things about it that we are simply bewildered: 1 . It is "the acting of some power or being ac cording to an established and uniform method." 2. "It has its origin in the nature of God." 3. It is not God himself, for it is the perpet ual demonstration of his presence and power. (Is not a thing and its demonstration different things ?) 4. It is not the divine will, for it is some thing " directly from the will of God." 5. It can not be a mere conception of the mind, for "infinite power insures its inviola bility." 6. Natural and moral law, he tells us, " are both directly from the will of God," and of course not the will itself; and yet he tells us that "the law for all moral beings is the will of God in commandment." Solve the riddle, who can? Note. — Since writing the above I have read Drummond's Natural Law in the Spir itual World, and am gratified to find myself sustained by his views on this subject. He says (pp. 5, 6): "The fundamental conception of law is an ascertained working sequence, or constant order among the phenomena of nature. This impression of law as order it is 46 Atonement Reviewed. important to receive in its simplicity, for the idea is often corrupted by having attached to it erroneous views of cause and effect. In Its true sense natural law predicates nothing of causes. The laws of nature are simply statements of the orderly condition of things in nature, what is found in nature by a sufficient number of competent observers. What these laws are in themselves is not agreed. That they have any absolute existence even, is far from certain. They are relative to man in his many limitations, and represent for him the constant expression of what he may always expect to find in the world around him. But that they have any causal connection with the things around him, is not to be conceived. The nat ural laws originate nothing, sustain nothing; they are merely responsible for uniformity in sustaining what has been originated, and what is being sustained. They are modes of oper ations, therefore, not operators; processes, not poWer. The law of gravitation, for instance, speaks to science only of processes. It has no light to offer as to itself. Newton did not discover gravity — that is not discovered yet. He discovered its law, which is gravitation, but that tells us nothing of its origin, of its nature, or of its cause." SECTION III. LAW IN COMMANDMENT. MR. ARMOUR says (p. 69): "All beings and things lower in the scale than moral beings having free will, have the law which governs them wholly ' implanted in the very constitution of their nature; ' while moral beings are under law which is wholly unto them in the form of commandment. There is, indeed, in the very constitution of their nature, capacity for perceiving and obeying law when and in what wTay soever made known unto them, and this capacity creates an obligation to obey law; they are not law unto themselves, they have not the moral law revealed in the very constitution of their nature. The law for all moral beings is the will of God in com mandment -made known unto them, and not an inward principle." Remarks. — Aside from the main issue I have somewhat against these statements: (1) Our author makes it a distinctive char- (47) 48 Atonement Reviewed. acteristic of moral beings that they have the capacity for perceiving law when made known unto them. He says: "There is, indeed, in the very constitution of their nature, capacity for perceiving and obeying law when and in what way soever made known unto them." Is this a revelation, or only an empty truism? A stone or any thing else, I should think, would have the capacity of perceiving a thing when made known to it. Such a capacity is hardly a distinctive characteristic of a " moral being." (2) Does capacity create obligation? Our author says " this capacity creates an obliga tion to obey law." This, I think, is a new revelation. But is it true? I should think there could be no obligations to obey when there is no capacity to perceive law; nor any obligation when there is no capacity to obey law, unless the capacity has been willfully de stroyed. But it is loose thinking, or something worse, to say that the capacity of perceiving or of obeying, or of both perceiving and obey ing, creates the obligation to obey. Such ca pacity conditions obligation, but certainly does not create it. If the principle is true in one case, it is so in all; but a universal application of it would make the sphere of human obliga tion a sphere of darkness and confusion. If Law in Commandment. 49 human capacity creates obligations, then to whom or to what are all men obligated? The philosophy seems to need revision. Our author, in support of his doctrine that " moral beings are wholly under law in com mandment," says (pp. 70, 71): "His (Adam's) sin consisted in making his own sinless nature the law of his conduct; whereas God had made his own revealed will, his command ment, such law. The problem of the origin of sin on any other view is darkness itself. . . . If sin be conceived of as consisting in follow ing natural sinless propensities in disregard of outward law .... it is then much less diffi cult to conceive how holy beings might trans gress." Remarks. — (1) Mr. Armour considers this solution of the difficult problems of moral evil sun-clear. Certainly it is very clear to anybody who happens to be able to conceive things which are contradictory. The solution has condemnation written upon its face. To follow "natural sinless propensities in disre gard of outward law " is a feat impossible of accomplishment by man, or angel, or any con ceivable creature. To follow natural sinless propensities is an act of will; to disregard out ward law is also an act of will. The first act 4 50 Atonement Reviewed. is sinless, the second is sinful, but the two acts are really one; therefore the same volun tary act is both sinless and sinful. Mr. Armour, instead of pouring a flood of light on the hard problem, as he believes he has done, has only intensified the darkness. A propensity for an unlawful object may naturally and sinlessly arise in the mind, but the instant it is cherished, or not repressed by an act of will, criminality intervenes. The voluntary indulgence of the propensity itself is the sin. Sin consists not in following a sin less propensity, but in gratifying the desire for unlawful objects. He that hateth his brother without cause is a murderer. Hatred may arise naturally and innocently, but to cherish it, foster it, converts it into murder. But the angels — does not Mr. Armour's philosophy make them quite unhappy? If they can not follow their natural and sinless propensities without sinning, and if all happi ness in heaven and earth consists in the grati fication of desire, as philosophy and the Bible teach, then the angels can not be happy. But I think the angels are happy, and that our au thor's philosophy needs reversing. I conceive it possible for the angels, and re deemed spirits as well, to attain a state in which their strongest, or rather their only, de- Law in Commandment. ci sire will be to do those things that accord with the will of God, and that the gratification of this desire will constitute their highest and only blessedness. But according to Mr. Armour, the Creator seems to have formed all rational creatures with such a "sinless nature," "natural and sinless propensities" — inward promptings and aspirations, "to be above all," that they are and must ever continue to be inclined to re bellion — an irrepressible spirit of rebellion in heaven, and of necessity a corresponding de gree of unhappiness! Is this pessimism? If not, what is it? Bit and bridle for the mule, and a rod for the fool's back! In opposition to subjective law, our author says (p. 72): "'Of the trees of the garden thou mayest freely eat.' We then need a di vine warrant for the indulgence of the sinless appetites of our nature." Remarks. — Is Mr. Armour quite certain that Adam never ate any thing before he re ceived this permission? How does he get his information? Suppose the divine warrant had never been given, then what? Would it have been sin to taste an apple if the permission had been withheld? Is it sinful for the millions of human beings 53 Atonement Reviewed. now living, who never heard of Eden, and have no law in commandment, to eat? If so, whose fault is it, theirs or that of another? The more reasonable view is, that this per mission was given only for the purpose of more definitely marking out the interdicted tree, and emphasizing the prohibition put upon it. Mr. Armour continues: "'Of the tree that is in the midst of the garden thou shalt not eat.' A limit must, then, be set by divine commandment to the gratification of natural sinless promptings." Remarks. — (i) The text does not prove, as Mr. Armour assumes, the non-existence of law written in the heart, or concreated law, or that law in commandment, and subjective law? are mutually exclusive of each other. On the contrary, the prohibition itself presupposes • in the human mind such a relation between hu man acts and their necessary consequences, that the acts as conditions are determinative of moral good or moral evil, according to the intentions of the actor. This divinely estab lished relation between antecedents, or condi tions, and their consequences, is concreated or subiective moral law. It was manifestly the violation of this sub- Law in Commandment. 53 jective law, rather than disobedience to the objective prohibition that caused the humiliat ing change in Adam's conscious relations to his Creator. Had his sin consisted solely in disobedience to the outward precept, it having no corre sponding response in his heart or moral nature, the feelings consequent upon disobedience could have been only those of fear or terror, arising from the apprehension of external in jury or external punishment, of which self- condemnation or remorse forms no part. On the contrary, he betrayed no apprehension whatever of external injury or punishment coming from without; but the evil experienced is from within. Of this changed and vitiated state of his moral nature he evinces the full est consciousness from the moment of diso bedience, and before he was arraigned face to face with his Creator. (2) This concreated law, while it is suffi cient to reveal to us a sense of dependence and of the rectitude of our motives, is not to us an infallible guide. This is not because the law itself is imperfect, but because of our ina bility rightly to interpret it. We accept the Bible as a standard infalli ble in itself. But it is not so to us because 54 Atonement Reviewed. we misread it; so of the laws of the physical world. Mr. Armour seems to think that if subject ive law exists at all, it must be in every re spect incapable of misinterpretation. (3) Of course it was impossible for Adam to violate this prohibition without violating this subjective law, which required him to love or obey God. But, according to our author, the only sin possible to Adam was to eat the "interdicted fruit." No other moral law had been given to him in commandment, and of course no other sin was possible. No sin possible except to eat of the fruit of a par ticular tree? Marvelous philosophy! If this was so with Adam, how comes it to be different with his posterity? Has God revised his plan of moral government and made it harder on the un fortunate children than upon their father? Was it not possible for Adam to lie to his wife, or to abuse her, or even kill her, or even to curse God to his face? Certainly. But he had received no com mandment not to do such naughty things, and of course it would have been no sin to do so, as no law in commandment would have been transgressed by doing it! (4) Mr. Armour tells us that "law in com- Law in Commandment. 55 mandment is the Only law, the only kind of law moral beings can possibly be under." To be under law is to be under obligations to obey law. If no law to moral beings is pos sible, except law in commandment, then it is the giving of the commandment that creates the obligation. Mr. Armour, as we have seen, also tells us that the " capacity (of perceiving and obey ing) creates an obligation to obey law." Ac cording to his philosophy, it seems that the command creates the obligation, and the ca pacity to perceive and obey creates the obli gation to obey law. How can his readers harmonize these contradictory things? As we have seen, capacity to perceive and obey law does not create the obligation to obey. Nor is it true that the command of itself creates an obligation to obey; the utmost that the command can do is to direct, authori tatively, how a previously existing obligation shall be discharged— e. g., the prohibitory command to Adam did not of itself create the obligation to obedience, but simply made known to him how God would have him dis charge a previously existing obligation. Of course not to obey the command will be a violation of that obligation, and will of neces sity involve the offender in conscious guilt or g6 Atonement Reviewed. remorse. But if the command does not rest upon a prior obligation, then disobedience to it will involve no such conscious guilt, no sense of self-degradation or remorse; and what evils may result will of necessity be physical and not moral — calamities, and not the penal ties of moral la.w. The prohibition, therefore, under which Adam was placed rested for its authority upon a prior obligation or law written upon the heart by the Creator, immutably connecting good with obedience and moral evil with dis obedience; and the words "in the day thou eatest thereof thou shalt surely die" are sim ply a revelation of the consequence of a viola tion of this obligation or subjective law. (5) The rational presumption is that there was nothing in the forbidden fruit itself capa ble of producing spiritual death (which was the death intended), and nothing in the out ward act of eating; but in the willful disobe dience in eating, or rather in the purpose to eat it, in disregard of divine authority, did the sin consist. The prohibition, then, of itself was of no consequence, except as a practical and sensi ble test of love and obedience to God; very much as God's commmand to Abraham to sacrifice his son Isaac — a test of obedience or Law in Commandment. 57 self-denying love. But the command not to eat of this particular tree no more implies that Adam did not have an internal sense of obliga tion to God than does the command to Abra ham imply that he had no previous knowledge of God; or both commands imply a knowl edge of the will of God prior to the commands and independent of them. The act of eating the forbidden fruit was simply an outward and sensible manifestation of logically prior and internal lawlessness in opposition to sub jective" law. Further proof of this fact will be elsewhere given. Mr. Armour says (p. 71): "All beings hav ing law within them, or in the constitution of their nature, were safe — safe because not ex alted." Of course the reference is to animals. Safe from what? Of course they are safe from moral evil. Are they safe from physical evil? Instinct or concreated law is sufficient for the general purposes of their being; but it is by no means an infallible preventive against evil — suffering, death, etc. Does Mr. Armour know that law written on the heart of a rational creature would be an infallible guaranty against moral evil? He as sumes this, and makes it an argument against subjective moral law. Is this reasoning, or sheer postulation? 58 Atonement Reviewed. Again (pp. 72, 73): "The philosophy (?) which places men, in this respect, in the same rank with animals, is beastly and horrible The buffalo on the plains are law to them selves — their nature, their appetites, their pro pensities, .... determine every thing." Remarks. — (1) God, it is conceded, is a law unto himself, and the buffalo unto himself, and man is intermediate between them. Ii subjective law in men is "beastly and horri ble," why is it not so in the Creator, whose image they bear? (2) Is it necessarily so that " appetites and propensities determine every thing " in all be ings possessed of subjective law? Does subjective law necessarily exclude rea son and conscience as determining factors in action? Our author evidently thinks so. Does he, by his philosophy, honor or dishonor his Creator? Even the abandoned sensualist does not make his "appetites and propensities the rule of his action," but his intellect furnishes him the rule by which he seeks their gratifi cation. Our author, in further opposing subjective law, quotes Rom. xv. 3 : " Even Christ pleased npt himself," and says, "This is the strongest Law in Commandment. 59 form of asserting that no subject of law may please self." Remarks. — Mr. Armour here confounds sensibility and will. Certainly, Christ denied himself personal ease and temporary pleasure for the sake of others, as all Christians are required to do. But this no more proves self- denial incompatible with subjective than it is with objective law; for as we have seen " appetites and propensities " form the rule of action with no rational beings. The motive to action is not the rule of action. Having briefly noticed Mr. Armour's prin cipal argument against law written upon the heart, and in support of law in commandment only, I wish to say a few things in reference to subjective law. 1. I have no sympathy with those who as sert an incongruity between subjective and objective law — law written upon the heart, and law in commandment; or that the former excludes either the possibility, or the utility, or (for the attainment of the highest excellency) the necessity of revealed law. 2. I have no sympathy with those who as sert subjective law to be sufficient to enable ever}' man in his fallen state clearly to dis criminate between right and wrong in the 60 Atonement Reviewed. concrete, or as the eye discriminates between colors, or the ear between sounds. We intuitively know that every effect must have a cause, but we do not intuitively know the cause of every effect. These are given only by the tuitive reason. In like manner we intuitively know that our motives of action are right or wrong, but we do not intuitively know what acts accord with the divine will. This we learn from the word of God and the tuitive judgment. 3. If moral law is purely and exclusively ob jective and mandatory, like civil or human law, then of necessity its rewards and penalties are purely and exclusively objective, and do not affect the internal or moral states of the mind at all; and there seems to be no more reason for calling such law moral than for calling the laws of the State moral. Mandatory law is properly moral only so far as it meets a re sponse in the human conscience. Civil law only so far as it meets this response in human nature is obeyed from a sense of moral obliga tion. Other civil laws that are not supported by such moral convictions, or are purely and exclusively mandatory, are obeyed — if obe}'ed at all — purely from motives of fear, honor, or policy. If these statements are true, our au thor's theorv can not be true. Law in Commandment. 6i 4. The consequences or penalties of a vio lation of law exclusively in commandment can not be transmitted by heredity. The consequences of the violation of sub jective law alone may be transmitted by pa rent to progeny. Adam transmitted his cor rupted moral nature to his posterity, just as he transmitted his animal, intellectual, and aesthet- ical nature. Permanently to corrupt his moral nature (so that the corrupted man is in the Bible called " the natural man "), and to trans mit that depraved nature through all time was impossible, except on the presupposition that in eating the forbidden fruit he did actually violate subjective moral law. The penal con sequences in their civil aspects visited upon thieves, murderers, etc., are not transmitted to their children. The thievish or murderous nature may be propagated, but to say that the punishment of these lawless acts is transmissi ble would be to talk nonsense. But the consequences of Adam's sin come on all his children. Why this difference? Manifestly for the simple reason that the thief violates law in commandment. But Adam violated law written upon his heart. The actual effects of the first human sin upon the human race practically demonstrate the fallacv of our author's theory. 62 Atonement Reviewed. Possibly Mr. Armour might say that this argument is not conclusive; but that God brought the corruption of Adam upon his pos terity by a sovereign judicial act, and not by natural heredity. To this it is sufficient here to say that this method of accounting for uni versal depravity is absurd, for the law of he redity is a product of a sovereign divine act, and it is incredible that God should by one sovereign act set aside a law which he by an other sovereign act has established. This judicial theory moreover requires the supposition of a perpetual miracle, which con verts the natural into the supernatural. It also violates the law of parsimony; for if the laws of heredity are sufficient for the trans mission of the first man's animal and intellect ual nature, it is unreasonable to suppose them incapable of transmitting his moral nature. The judicial theory is likewise incapable of scientific defense, and its natural tendency is to draw into infidelity those who happen to believe that a rational Creator would not im pose upon rational creatures a religion which contradicts the very rationality with which he has endowed them. God visits the iniquities of the fathers upon the children. This is certainly done through the laws of heredity, and is capable of scientific Law in Commandment. 63 defense. But to say that God visits iniquities through law in commandment seems little less than a burlesque on law. 5. Science and the Bible are in full accord in affirming the existence of subjective moral law as an essential characteristic of human nature. Paul is the metaphysician of the New Testament. He says (Rom. ii. 12-15): "For as many as have sinned without law shall also perish without law: and as many as have sinned under law shall be judged by law; for not the hearers of a law are just before God, but the doers of a law shall be justi fied: for when Gentiles, which have no law, do by nature the things of the law, these, hav ing no law are a law unto themselves; in that they shew the work of the law written in their hearts, their conscience bearing witness therewith, and their thoughts one with anoth er accusing or else excusing them." This is so plain that comment can scarcely make it plainer. (1) Paul here affirms the existence of the revealed or written law, or law in command ment; and also a law written in the hearts of the Gentiles. This, of course is the subjective or unwritten law. If this law is by nature written in the hearts of the Gentiles, then it is t>\ Atonement Reviewed. of course a common characteristic, or com mon possession of mankind. (2) Men having this law, and not the law in commandment, deal with it just as men deal with the written law — that is, it is an object of thought, study, inquiry, conscience; also has its appropriate functions as a witness bearer for or against them, according to the fidelity or infidelity of the will to the convictions of the judgment. This is the identical psycho logical process common to those who have the written law. The latter is simply the voice of God from without interpreting the voice of God from within. Had sin never spread its dark shades over this inner solar light, the outer light would be less imperative ly required, though possibly would have been always necessary to man in some form. (3) This subjective law is of such conse quence and of such authority as to constitute a distinct rule of moral administration, and of independent judgment. " For as many as has have sinned without law shall also perish without law, and as many as have sinned under law shall be judged by law." In this verse (12) we are plainly taught that those that have not the objective law in commandment may sin; sin is a trans gression of the law; what law do they trans- Law in Commandment. 65 gressr Not the law in commandment, for they have no such law. Then it is of necessi ty this subjective law written in the heart. This contradicts Mr. Armour's philosophy. Again, those who have no law in command ment may perish — that is, suffer the penalty of the law. But how is it possible to suffer the penalty of the law, unless the law has been broken? But how is it possible for those who never heard of the law in commandment to break any moral law if there is no such thing as subjective law? Paul's facts and our author's philosophy seem to be in hopeless conflict. 6. We have in part the same truth taught in Rom. v. 13, 14: "For until the law, sin was in the world: but sin is not imputed when there is no law. Nevertheless death reigned from Adam until Moses, even over them that had not sinned after the likeness of Adam's transgression, who is a figure of him that was to come." In this text a number of facts bearing di rectly on the question of subjective law are clearly stated: (1) That from Adam till Moses there was no law in commandment in the world. (2) That sin nevertheless was in the world all this while from Adam till Moses. Of what 5 66 Atonement Reviewed. law was sin then a transgression? There was no law in commandment; and objective and subjective are the only forms of law possible to men. It is infallibly certain that subjective law did exist; otherwise sin could not have existed at all. (3) That sin is not imputed when there is no written law. The exact meaning of the word impute in this text is of importance. The verb allogeo is not the verb generally translated impute. It is used but twice in the New Testament, herq and in Philemon xviii. 5. It can not mean in this place that sin did not actually exist as sin, for this would contradict the text; nor can it mean that it was not punishable, for the peo ple actually suffered death, which is the pen alty. It must mean, then, that sin is not known, or recognized, or apprehended as sin; or in its true character when there is no law in commandment to define or characterize it. The sinner is, of course, conscious of his mental state, of his unrest, and of fearful ap prehensions of evil; but is unable to under stand the reason of all this abnormality in his mental state. His condition is much like that of a diseased man, who knows not the cause or nature of his disease. This view of the subject is favored or rather Law in Commandment. 67 confirmed by Rom. iii. 20: " By the law is the knowledge of sin." Rom. vii. 7: " Howbeit I had not known sin, except through the law, for I had not known coveting, except the law had said, thou shalt not covet." (4) That death reigned over all from Adam till Moses, and death being the effect of sin proves that all were sinners, as effect proves cause. (5) That men living between Adam and Moses did not sin after the likeness of Ad am's transgression. But what is the exact difference between the sin of Adam and others till the giving of the law? The answer to this question is easy and unquestionable. Adam sinned against law in commandment, which was also a trans gression of subjective law. But his children, prior to Moses, sinned against subjective law only. (6) These facts prove the possibility of sins of ignorance — that is, men may know that they are under law, but not know what par ticular things are permitted, and what forbid den by the law — e. g., a man might be con scious of covetousness, and yet not know that covetousness is sin, except the law in com mandment had said thou shalt not covet. 68 Atonement Reviewed. The principle is true in regard to any other particular sin. (7) It is also proven by the facts that the penalties of subjective law are just as inevita ble as are the penalties of revealed law, or law in commandment. Death reigned just as tru ly from Adam until Moses without mandatory law as it does subsequent to that period. In this respect subjective moral law is strictly analogous to subjective physical law. Every body knows that good health depends upon conformity to certain pre-established condi tions; but we may not know exactly what those conditions are, or what hygienic law requires; we consequently may ignorantly, or unintentionally, violate them, and thus destroy health, or even life. Poison taken ignorantly or unintentionally is as fatal as when taken knowingly and intentionally. So of the viola tions of subjective moral law. (8) Subjective and objective law, Paul teaches us, (Rom. ii. 13,) constitute different rules of judgment: "For as many as have sinned without (revealed) law shall perish without (revealed) law, and as many as have sinned under law shall be judged by law." Whatever criminality attaches to the man who, ignorantly or unintentionally, destroys his life, attaches solely to his ignorance or care- Law in Commandment. 69 lessness. Such a one is less criminal than he who knowingly and intentionally destroys his life. But the same act, whether intended or unintended, is followed by the same conse quences. So it is in regard to the violations of subjective moral law and law in command ment. The latter involves the greater crim inality and the greater punishment. The pun ishment in both cases is spiritual death. Hence there are different degrees of spiritual death, as there are different degrees of spiritual life; even as there are different degrees of health and vitality in those who conform more close ly, and those who conform less closely, to the laws of health. The facts stated by Paul, and the logical conclusions that grow necessarily out of them, seem to establish be yond all controversy that the law of God is written in the heart as an essential character istic of human nature, and that Mr. Armour's assumption is utterly at fault. Some of its nec essary consequences are as follows: 1. It quite excludes the possibility of sins of ignorance. He says men have the "capacity of perceiving and obeying law when and in what way soever made known unto them, and this capacity creates the obligation to obey law; they are not law unto themselves; they have not the moral law revealed in the consti- 70 Atonement Reviewed. tution of their nature. The law for all moral beings is the will of God in commandment made known unto them, and not an inward principle." This is very explicit and clear. The law is not an inward principle; it is commandment made known. Thus, of course, it is impossible to violate ignorantly a law made known. But we know that the Bible fully recognizes sins of ignorance; and that a large part of the sins of humanity against both phys ical and moral law consists of sins of igno rance. 2. The theory excludes the possibility of sins against self. But the Bible recognizes such sins. The law in commandment was given on two tables of stone — one specifying our duties to God, and the other our duties to our neighbor. No table was given specifying our duties to ourselves. The reason is simply that all duties to our neighbors are primarily duties to God, and all duties to God are duties to ourselves. Hence, all sin against God is also and necessarily sin against ourselves. But this manifestly could not be true, unless we have the divine law written in the heart. The feelings arising out of the violations of "law wholly in commandment" are quite dis tinguishable from those that arise out of the violations of subjective law. The first is a sin Law in Commandment. 71 against authority; the second, a sin against self as well. The punishment of the former is merely objective, that of the latter subject ive. 3. In strict accord with the preceding, it should be said that the peculiar feeling called conscience is the psychological complement of subjective law, and hence if there is no sub jective moral law, there can be no such thing as conscience. The penalties of mandatory law are purely external; they come from with out. They in no sense involve the conscience unless subjective law is also violated. All law in commandment, both human and divine, that does not meet a response in sub jective law, appeals to the fears of men, and not to the conscience, as motives of obedi ence. The horse, the ox, the dog, though a law unto themselves, are to a degree capable of law in commandment. But such law appeals only to their fears as inducements to obedi ence, and of course not in any sense to moral feelings. The ox fears the lash, and therefore obeys. Take from him the capacity of sensa tion and he would defy all law in command ment. The same would be true, I doubt not, of all created intelligences but for this moral law 72 Atonement Reviewed. written upon the neart. Conscience and con created law are inseparable; but if we reject subjective moral law, a true psychology re quires us to reject the doctrine of conscience, and substitute in its stead the feeling of servile fear — the apprehension of evil from without. All motives of action become motives of policy or prudence, and no sin could be regarded as a sin against self, or as an act of self-degrada tion. There could be no cases of conscience. No Judas could hang himself because of the goadings of remorse. Men may die of fear as may other animals. The feeling called remorse, and the feeling called fear, are radi cally distinct. This is sufficiently obvious to all that are able to refer these different emo tional states to their respective causes. 4. Law in commandment admits of object ive rewards and punishments only. All the consequences of obedience and disobedience come from without, or proceed only from the will of another, and in no sense from the dis turbed harmony of the mind itself. Hence, all moral retributions belong not to the sphere of the natural, but of the supernatural, and the administration of the moral world is a per petual miracle. All human law is law in com mandment, and its rewards and punishments are objective, are delivered by the will of the Law in Commandment. 73 law-giver, irrespective of the character of the obedience or disobedience of the subject; or the character of an offense is in no sense de terminative of the character of the punish ment. All this is not less preposterous than it would be to say that sickness — disease of every kind — comes upon us from the violations of law in commandment. Of course, Mr. Armour does not deny to men a conscience. This he can not afford to do; for no scheme of ethics or of theology would be tolerated, if it should fail to recog nize conscience in some form. Mr. Armour really has much to say about conscience, but the calamity is that he destroys the possibility of a conscience proper, and appropriates the term to something radically different. 5. According to Mr. Armour's philosophy man is not with propriety called a moral be ing; for it is in fact concreated moral law that constitutes man properly a moral and relig ious being. Capacity to know, to feel, and to will of course are indispensable prerequisites to moral ity in the creature. But this capacity does not of itself constitute a moral nature. Nor does law in commandment make him a moral being any more than it does the horse or dog. This law written in the heart — this internal sense 74 Atonement Reviewed. of Tightness and wrongness in our motives of action — is the subjective ground of both mo rality and religion, and without it both would as inevitably die as would the animals if de prived of their concreated instincts. Hence it is, that just in so far as they hap pen to repress this inner sense of obligation — this internal solar light — do men become skep tical as to morality and religion. We also know that nations that have not moral law in commandment have their codes of morals and their forms of religion as truly as those that have it. This shows the exist ence of this subjective law as a common pos session of all men. The universality of the religious sentiment and of ideas of moral rec titude can be accounted for on no other prin ciple. Mr. Armour of course is not ignorant of the fact that the Bible sharply discriminates between law in commandment and law writ ten in the heart; but the exigencies of his theory — " substitution normal in law " — imper atively requires him to obliterate this distinc tion. This he does by the assumption that moral law, " in what way soever made known," is law in commandment. This he may deem very good strategy, but it is certainly very bad philosophy. To confound things, in them- Law in Commandment. 75 selves essentially distinct, is one of tne com mon methods of errorists. No distinction needs to be broader or clearer than that be tween law made known by command and law made known in nature, and to confound them for strategic purposes is simply unpardonable. If Mr. Armour can succeed in removing men from the dominion of subjective law and in putting them wholly under the dominion of mandatory law, then he can bewilder his readers with a brilliant display of the marvel ous capabilities of law, and the wonderful analogies and typical relations of human and divine law. He then can, by the magic pow er of substitution transport sin, and guilt, and penal fire from one pole of the world to the other, and insure to the guilty the reward proper to the innocent, and to the innocent the punishment proper to the guilty. Mr. Armour objects to skeptics because they deny both the necessity and the possibil ity of objective law, and allege the sufficiency of subjective law. In this he is manifestly right. It is certainly true that subjective law in itself is insufficient to men in their sinful state for the attainment of the highest destiny. But we should not, on this account, divest them of the noblest concreated power of their nature — their consciousness of moral distinc- 76 Atonement Reviewed. tions, without which men are quite incapable of mandatory law in such form as to bind the conscience. But Mr. Armour errs scarcely less fatally than the skeptic, when he rejects subjective law and puts rational creatures wholly under law in commandment. The skeptic reduces religion to a sentiment, Mr. Armour to an institution, having all its imper atives, its motives in things external to the mind itself — God is recognized as supreme over nature, and not as supreme in nature — as the executive of statute law, and not of concre ated law. I have no sympathy with Higher lawism; nor with those who deny the necessity of Revelation; but to deny subjective law is to cut the heart out of Christianity, and out of Christian ethics as well, and leave them mere lifeless forms. Happily for humanity the moral world is not constructed according to our author's artificial method. SECTION IV. i. SUNDRY TOPICS BRIEFLY NOTICED. M1 ~R. ARMOUR makes some gratuitous and perilous assertions concerning di vine sovereignty. He says (p. 26): "Divine sovereignty is to be recognized in determining to save any fallen ones, in determining who should be saved," and much more to the same effect. Remarks. — I suppose that all God's acts are purely sovereign; but I should not choose to dishonor him by putting him on parity with fate, or by assuming that he can not be free without utterly excluding all freedom fromthose created in his own image. There is as much sovereignty (and withal a higher order of sovereignty) in creating men free as there could be in creating them with a predeter mined and inevitable destiny. Why can not the Creator authorize men to choose between good and evil, life and death, without surren dering his sovereignty? Can our author show (77) 78 Atonement Reviewed. why or how God can not be sovereign without determining who shall be saved or who shall be lost? He repeatedly commands men to choose life that they may live. Is he merely mocking their helpless misery? I prefer not to impute to my Maker such gratuitous cruel ty. It is not difficult, through false notions of sovereignty, to present distorted and un worthy views of the divine character. 2. VOLUNTARY NECESSITY AND NECES SITATED FREEDOM. Mr. Armour says (p. 80): "Right action in God is a necessity." This is cloudy. Does he mean that God necessarily acts? If so, this is fate, and God is its first victim. Or does he mean that the act is free, but that it is nec essarily right? If so, in what sense does he intend the word right to be taken? in the sense of morally good, or only pertinent or proper? We know that all acts are only means to an end, and as such have fitness or perti nency, but of themselves have no moral qual ity. Now, our author leaves us quite in dark ness as to whether he means that action itself in God is a necessity; or whether divine action is necessarily morally good, or whether it is only necessarily pertinent as a means to an end. Sundry Topics Briefly Noticed. 79 What follows does not relieve, but rather intensifies the darkness. He continues: "Yet since this necessity arises from the infinitude of his perfections, it is, in the fullest sense, voluntary and praiseworthy." This is marvelous! Necessity " in the fullest sense voluntary ! " Necessity " in the fullest sense praiseworthy!" A voluntary necessi ty! Could skepticism assert any thing more inconsistent with the doctrine of moral dis tinctions or rational religion? But while our author is pleased to put the Creator under a voluntary necessity, he chooses to allow to rational creatures freedom of a different kind. He says: "Right action in the case of any mere creature ... in order to be praise worthy must be action the opposite of which was possible." Here he asserts, and seems to mean, that men have freedom with the power of contrary choice. Philosophers generally consider freedom with an alternative, the high est form of freedom possible. But our author says "necessity in God is, in the fullest sense, voluntary" — in his estimation freedom, with the power of contrary choice, is only a lower, perhaps the lowest, form of freedom. Why he makes this distinction, contrary to the gen eral method of necessitarians, he does not choose to inform us. 80 Atonement Reviewed. But after all, this inferior freedom with an alternative can not be of much value. It can not, according to our author's philosoph}', free the world from a remorseless despotism, for if all things — entities and events — are neces sarily as they are, because God is necessarily as he is; or if all things are irreversibly fixed from eternity by the necessary nature of God, then all freedom in the Creator and in the creature is a tantalizing illusion. If the Creator acts from a necessity from within himself, and his necessitated volitions have determined the destiny of all men and things, and freedom of every form is a mere illusion, then the very conception of freedom is a calamity — that is, if illusions are calam ities. But are not necessity and freedom with an alternative contradictory things? Our author thinks not; he affirms a voluntary necessity in the Creator, and a necessitated freedom in the creature — that is, a freedom with an alterna tive, but which is in harmony with a predes tined end. To ordinary minds these things seem to be the plainest contradictions, but to the astute mind of our author they seem to be in the utmost harmony. According to his philosophy of the creature-will, the elect, having the power of contrary choice, might Sundry Topics Briefly Noticed. 8l choose the means which condition eternal death, and be lost; or the reprobate might choose the means which condition eternal life, and be saved. But according to his theology such things are impossible, because the divine nature, or a necessitated decree, has settled the destiny of all. Would it not be well for Mr. Armour to revise either his philosophy or his theology, and put them in some sort of decent harmony? 3. SOME DOUBTFUL THINGS ABOUT CONFIRMATION. Our author says (p. 81): "Confirmation, whether of men or of angels, is due to Christ alone, to Christ the one only servant of God, whose obedience is assured by his divine nature. Christ, the divine servant of God, is pledged for and insures the standing of all holy creatures." Remarks.-^ 1) If Mr. Armour fails to put the moral world in harmony with his ideal, it will not be for the want of courage, or some thing more censurable. Parenthetically — What authority has our author to call Christ the divine servant of God? As divine, he was not a servant of God, but God himself. How can God be a servant of God? 6 82 Atonement Reviewed. (2) How does our author know that the confirmation of the "angels is due to Christ alone," or that Christ " is pledged for and in sures" their standing? He speaks as one having authority. He may be right; or he may be only "wise above what is written." If Christ "is pledged for and insures the standing of all holy creatures," how happened any of them to fall? According to Mr. Ar mour's creed, were not all — Adam and all the angels — originally holy? If Christ insures their standing, how came any such to fall? Alas! Armourism foreordained the fall of a part of them. This was, of course, " for wise and holy ends." For such Christ was not a surety; hence they could not keep their first estate. Our author should replace the word "all" with the word some, or else take the word holy in a sense adverse to his creed. (3) But consistency is not always one of Mr. Armour's jewels. He elsewhere informs us that Christ could not become a mediator for men without taking to himself man's nat ure. But we are expressly told (Heb. ii. 14) that he did not take the nature of angels. How, then, could he become their surety? Again, how can our author reconcile the power of contrary choice with the impossi bility of disobedience? May not the power of Sundry Topics Briefly Noticed. 83 contrary choice be destroyed by habits volun tarily formed ? "Can the Ethiopian change his skin, or the leopard his spots? then may ye also do good that are accustomed to do evil." Have the fallen angels the power of contrary choice? If habitual disobedience has confirmed them in a state of enmity against God, why may npt the unfallen angels be confirmed in their love to God by persistent and uniform obedience? If angels are created with no predisposition to disobedience, why may they not be truly con firmed in that state by the force of habit? Again, how does Christ insure the standing of the holy angels? Does he compel them to love God for themselves? If so, what becomes of the power of contrary choice ? Or does he love God for them? As a man, he confessedly can love God only for himself. Hence, if he loves or obeys, as God, then God's love to God, or obedience to himself, insures the standing of the holy angels. This is darkness itself. The truth is, Mr. Armour has indulged his propen- sion for bold, ill-considered utterances on this subject which admit of no rational compre hension; utterances far more likely to impress the timid reader with the awe that comes from mystery than to enlighten or satisfy the thoughtful. SECTION V. THE WILL. MR. ARMOUR, in his chapter on the will, says some things that are true, some things equivocal, some doubtful, and many that are not true. He says (p. 88): " The will is self-assert ing, seeks supremacy, aspires to be above all. This is an inherent and essential element in the nature of will; and if in any instance it is brought to acquiesce in, accept and delight in, a state of subjection, or subordination to the will of another, it is always for good and sufficient reasons duly considered, and not because it sought or desired a subordinate place? The underscoring is his, and indicates the high importance that he attaches to his ex planation of the will. I do not propose to controvert his psycholo gy; for I am not able to gather it from his book — further than to learn that it is some sort of necessitated freedom — freedom with (84) The Will. 85 an alternative which nevertheless reaches a predetermined end. The quotation just given sufficiently indi cates our author's confused notions of the will. If he had made his assertions of the whole man, instead of a particular faculty, he would have been less liable to criticism; for it is the man that is self-asserting, that seeks suprema cy, that aspires to be above all. The will may be said to accept or acquiesce, but it is not a function of will, but of the sensibility, to de light in any thing. The will does not con sider nor desire, as our author alleges. He seems to agree with no known theory of the will; nor has he given us any intelligible theo ry of his own. He denies that rational creat ures could be endowed with free will and yet be incapable of sinning. In this he dissents from Augustine, Anselm, and many other dis tinguished authors. In this respect he evi dently Is right. He also denies that such a state is attainable in this world or another. He does not, with Hodge, discriminate be tween freedom and ability. With him the loss of ability to sin would be the loss of free dom. Still, Christ, in some inexplicable way, "insures the standing of all holy creatures." Yet they are free. He seems to teach that all such creatures are free, and not free; can sin, 86 Atonement Reviewed. and can not sin; their disobedience "ever naturally possible, and only impossible because of the power, grace and faithfulness of Christ who stands for them." (p. 81.) I have now noticed a few of the many errors of the first part of Mr. Armour's book. Those noticed will give the reader a general idea of the character of this part of the work. The first part of the book is intended as a prepara tive to the discussion of his principal theme — the atonement. The foundation, as we have seen, is not all of solid marble; much of it is of rotten sand-stone. The whole is no stronger than its weakest part. The superstructure is ho stronger than its foundation. To this I propose now to direct attention. I do not propose to follow Mr. Armour's order in the discussion of the several topics, but will confine my remarks to the fundamental doc trine of his atonement and its collateral sub jects in what seems to me to be the most nat ural order, and will leave minor points to take care of themselves. SECTION VI. SIN STRICTLY A DEBT. MR. ARMOUR considers sin strictly a debt, and nothing more nor less. The establishment of this position he seems to deem of vital interest to his theory of atone ment, and puts forth his characteristic logic in its support. He says (p. 136): "In the Lord's prayer we read, ' Forgive us our debts? Why this word if sin be not debt? That this is deeper debt than the wealth of this world can pay — debt of another kind, so that material wealth can pay no part of it — is most true; but because it is debt so great shall we say it is not debt at all? " His theory is that sin is, in its nature, strict ly debt, and, as such, is transferable from one party to another, and may be punished in a substitute as a debt may be collected from a surety. He, however, is not always consist ent with himself. He says (pp. 135-6): "In the last analysis sin and debt agree; not merely in the sense that in the one case as in the other there is ob- (37) 88 Atonement Reviewed. ligation to the law, but that the obligation in the one case as in the other arises from the withholding from the law what was due." Remarks. — (i) Mr. Armour in. the first quotation asserts the identity of sin and debt; in the second he asserts their agreement or similarity. That there are some points of similarity between sin and debt, I suppose no one would care to deny. Every particle of mat ter has something common to every other par ticle of matter; hence, some agreement or analogy between them — so all mental states and acts. But agreement in some particular or analogy is not sameness. Agreement, sim ilarity, etc., imply diversity, not sameness. Is sin debt? or is it in some conceivable re spect similar to debt? According to our author it is both, which is somewhat difficult to comprehend. (2) Our author specifies two points of agree ment between sin and debt. First, he says there is in both an obligation to law. Suppose this to be granted, it no more proves them to be identical than the common property of gravity proves iron and feathers to be iden tical; or the act of volition, common to obe dience and disobedience, proves them to be identical. Sin Strictly a Debt. 89 Parenthetically — "Sin and debt are obliga tion to law?" This savors of realism. All obligations lie between persons, and not be tween persons and things. If sin is a debt the obligor, as well as the obligee, is a person — not something which we may happen to call law. (3) The second point of agreement between sin and debt, according to our author, is " that the obligation in one case, as in the other, arises from withholding from the law what was due." If this statement was true it would prove nothing to the point; or would prove only a single point of agreement be tween sin and debt, but not their identity. But the statement, interpreted in the light of its own terms, is an absurdity. For no act can by possibility create the obligation which it violates. This would be to say that the fail ure to pay a debt creates the obligation to pay, and this is exactly what our author's words teach. "Withholding what was due" violates a prior obligation, but creates none whatever. What it does create is liability to evil consequences. But Mr. Armour under stands himself. What he is determined to do at all peril is to establish the identity of sin and debt, and also to make it appear that to suffer the penalty of law is to discharge an go Atonement Reviewed. obligation to the penal side of law. To ac complish this important point, he, with strat egic intent, uses the word obligation where decency and common usage required him to use the word liability or its equivalent. No one, it is presumed, is so blind as not to see that to suffer the consequences of not paying a debt when due, is not to pay the debt; and so of sin, if it is a debt, to suffer the pun ishment of it is not to pay the debt itself. Let this simple, but immensely significant fact not be forgotten in the following discussion. He says (p. 136): "Both the sinner and the debtor are under condemnation of law." In another place he denies that an obligation to pay in the future is debt at all — that is, if A borrowed money from B, with the promise to pay in twelve months, A is not debtor to B until the note matures. According to this philosophy, a man can never be a debtor with out being a criminal. But usage, and common sense as well, re gards A as a debtor to B from the hour the money changed hands. Our author is a shrewd strategist. He clearly saw that to admit A to be a debtor before the maturity of his note, would be to admit a radical difference between sin and debt — that is, a man may be a debtor without being a criminal, but can not be a sin- Sin Strictly a Debt. 91 ner without being a criminal. Mr. Armour's bold assertion that " both the sinner and the debtor are under condemnation of law," turns out to be not true. (4) Debt is properly an obligation arising out of a consideration. It is not an obligation to law as such, but to a person, or community of persons, and the parties concerned have absolute power over it, as to when or how it shall be paid, or whether it shall be paid at all. The law has nothing to do with it, unless in voked to prevent one party from wronging another. Can our author say all this of sin? If he can not, why attempt to identify things so radically different? (5) His philosophy is often in conflict with one Saul of Tarsus. If debt, like sin, is neces sarily condemnation of law, then, of course, all debtors are in a state of condemnation — are suffering the penalties of the law. But Paul declared himself to be " a debtor both to the Greeks and to the Barbarians, to the wise and to the unwise." Hence, according to our au thor, Paul was under condemnation of law, and was, when he wrote, actually suffering the penalty of the law; for the transgression and penalties of moral law are as inseparable as cause and effect. Paul uses the word debtor in the sense of obligation, to do what is good 92 Atonement Reviewed. or right. Mr. Armour uses it, as we have seen, in the sense of liability — or, as he im properly calls it, "obligation — to punishment." We can choose between them. (6) " In the last analysis sin and debt agree." Mr. Armour affirms — Paul denies. I concur with the latter, and affirm that sin in the last analysis is lawlessness — enmity to God, carnal- mindedness, and a state described as spiritual death. Debt is not necessarily so. It implies no alienation, no enmity, no motive or desire to injure the creditor, is not necessarily a breach of good morals, implies no disregard to the rights of others, or criminal intention. It often results from providential occurrences, from misfortune, often from benevolent and pious purposes. Certainly one man may intentionally de fraud another; but then he becomes more than a debtor — a criminal, a sinner in fact. Debt, unaccompanied with bad intention, brings no moral retribution upon the debtor. If it results from unavoidable circumstances it may bring regret, but not remorse; for it is a calamity, not a crime. If it results from imprudence — its most fruitful source — it is followed with the ordina ry penalties of imprudence, and not with the sting of conscious guilt. Whatever temporal Sin Strictly a Debt. 93 evils may arise from it, the soul's salvation is not imperiled by it. Can Mr. Armour say these things of sin? If he can not, why does he strategetically assert the identity of sin and debt? (7) Again, it is not improper to say that debt is not necessarily an offense to the cred itor, even if it should never be paid. The creditor is often the best friend to the debtor — loves him most, has the utmost faith in him, and permits him to increase his indebtedness with little, perhaps no, prospect of ever re ceiving payment. Is this true of sin? Is it not necessarily offensive to God — the abomina ble thing that he hates? offensive and hateful, not because it personally injures him, but be cause it is a willful abuse of the beneficent and infinitely wise provisions he has gracious ly made for the happiness of his rational creatures. It is as truly a curse to the creat ure as it is an offense to the Creator; for ev ery sin against God is a sin against the trans gressor himself, being an infraction of the conditions upon which his good necessarily depends. Sin is to the sinner himself what the self-injected poison of the viper, which, in its delirium of rage, thrusts its fangs into its own flesh and dies of its own venom. Can all this be said of debt? If not, why attempt to 94 Atonement Reviewed. identify them? To do this is to maximize debt and minimize sin — to convert the mole hill into a mountain, and the mountain into a mole-hill. (8) But Mr. Armour makes much ado over the word "debts" in the Lord's prayer. He, however, is presumed to know that the original, opheilemata, is used both of debts and also of sins or trespasses; that the word, as used in Matt. vi. 12, is explained in verse 15 by the word paraptomata, trespasses; that Luke, in the prayer itself, uses the word sins, hamartia, instead of the word debts; that Mark, in the parallel text, uses trespasses pa raptomata. Mr. Armour is also presumed to know that neither paraptoma nor hamartia is ever translated debt, but that opheilema is used in the sense of sin. To build up a mammoth theory on so shallow a foundation is certainly extremely perilous to truth. But this is the only show of Bible authority our author has for calling sin a debt. But the Bible gives no authority for the assumption that sin is debt in any proper sense, or in such sense that it may be transferred from one person to another, as human obligations may be transferred by con sent of parties. SECTION VII. '< SUBSTITUTION NORMAL IN LAW." SUCH is the heading of Mr. Armour's third chapter on atonement. Very properly re jecting the dream that sinful men can make atonement for themselves, he says (p. 127): " For if atonement by the sinner be a manifest impossibility, atonement, perfect atonementyb^ the sinner is also an impossibility, unless sub stitution be a normal provision of law, unless law in its own nature provide for substitution and for atonement thereby. But law, in its whole range and extent, and in all the ways in which it is made known to us, reveals won drous provision for substitution." Again (p. 128): "Law in its own nature provides for, admits and is fully satisfied with an adequate substitute? Remarks. — (1) Our author assumes in the first quotation that what he knows as to how an atonement can be made is the sum of all that can be known. With less arrogance, he might have said that he could not see how (95) 96 Atonement Reviewed. atonement could be made without substitution. Such a statement would have defied criticism. (2) "Substitution normal in law" is the key stone of the arch which is to bear the weight of Mr. Armour's colossal superstructure. The normality of substitution as a provision of law, is the talismanic power by which the " Great Atonement" is to be triumphantly and forever freed from the humiliating reproach of being the "Great Exception" to God's otherwise uniform and orderly method of governing the world. This marvelous capacity of law is to place the doctrine of substitutionary atone ment upon impregnable foundations, and ren der it forever defensible before the bar of reason on rigidly scientific principles. But what if Mr. Armour should happen to be mistaken; what if substitution should hap pen not to be a normal provision of law? How hopelessly sad this would be! For, according to our author, who speaks with the confidence of an infallible oracle, if substitution is not a normal provision of law, then atonement is simply impossible, and the hope of deliverance from the terrible consequences of sin, through a Mediator, is utterly incapable of realization. For, as the reader will observe, our author conditions salvation absolutely on atonement, and the possibility of atonement upon the Substitution Normal in Law. 97 normality of substitution in law — that is, no salvation without atonement, and no atone ment "unless substitution be a normal pro vision of law." Mr. Armour seems to me to base the possibility of salvation upon fear fully precarious grounds, the new discovery that substitution is a normal provision of law. (3) All the great authors — philosophers and theologians— have, as far as I know, uniform ly admitted substitutionary atonement to be unique, or abnormal, not according to nature generally and an exception to the general character, of moral law especially. Some who hold firmly to substitutionary atonement go so far as to admit that the doctrine is of bad moral tendency. They therefore hold that the Great Atonement is not an exception, but "The Great Exception'''' to the divinely established course of things. Mr. Armour rebukes these grand old au thors for making these concessions, which he alleges (and rightly too) are " fatal to the doc trine of atonement " by substitution. To escape the logical consequences of these frank con cessions, our author boldly announces the new and startling doctrine that "substitution is a normal provision of law." This is certainly bold strategy; but whether, in freeing substitution from one absurdity, he 7 98 Atonement Reviewed, is not involved in a greater one remains to be ,seen. (4) " Substitution normal in law! " In what law? All law, human and divine. He uses the word law generically, and names no excep tions. To affirm and re-affirm is easy. To prove is a different thing. This our author holdly attempts, but not in a very systematic way, but in a way satisfactory to himself. But does he, in fact, prove his postulate? If I may anticipate the answer, as it will appear in the sequel, I reply: If hypothetical analogies can prove it, then he proves it. If the perversion of a few Bible texts can prove it, then he proves it. Let us test the value of his leading argur ments: 1. What does our author mean by substitu tion? He says (p. 139): "As debt is imputed to the surety or substitute, the discharge or release is imputed to the debtor We have then in this transaction, so familiar to all, a clear case of substitution, of imputation of legal obligation, and imputation of legal right eousness. In no creed in Christendom can 'substitution' and 'double imputation' be found more clearly and distinctly set forth. That the principles on which these (substitu tions and imputations) are admitted are prin- Substitution Normal in Law. 99 ciples which prevail in the entire range of law, there is no reason to doubt. In the moral, as in the natural, world the greatest as well as the least results are attained on principles common to both." Our author gives us much more to the same effect, but this is sufficiently explicit to give us a distinct idea of what he means by substitu tion. Two points deserve to be specially no ticed. The first is that the essential charac teristic of substitution is double imputation, or that there can be no substitution without "double imputation." As we shall subse quently see, our author is not always scrupu lously faithful to his own explanation of his substitution. The second noteworthy point given in the quotationis"thatthe principles of substitution," etc., prevail in the entire range of law, includ ing natural and moral law as well as civil law. (Mr. Armour uses the word natural in the sense of physical, and as antithetical to moral law. Is not the moral as truly natural as the physical? Is not all concreated law, whether physical or moral, properly natural law? The Bible so teaches, and this is very good author ity. Rom. ii. 12-15.) Mr. Armour takes his principles from di vine law, but his exemplifications and illustra- ioo Atonement Reviewed. tions from human law. This may be good strategy, but is very suspicious logic. To as sert a principle as common to all law, divine and human, and then illustrate only by exam ples taken from human law, savors more of ingenuity than of ingenuousness. Pretermit ting natural or divine law as impractical or unproductive of suitable examples, he names four cases in which human law admits of some kind of substitution. He says (pp. 129, 130): 1. "Work for the public benefit, required by law of able and qualified citizens within the limits of certain age, may be performed by any substitute who is free from like obligation, willing and able? 2. " By universal consent even military serv ice, required for the defense of the country, may be rendered by any substitute offered who is himself free from the same obligation, etc." 3. "Even in the case of crime, law, as un derstood and administered by men in all lands, provides that the penalty may be met by a substitute, in all cases in which the penalty prescribed is such that a substitute may meet it consistently with the obligations he is al ready under." 4. "So also in the case of debt, which is obligation unto law, a substitute is always ad- Substitution Normal in Law. ioi mitted. A surety, who is always a true and proper substitute, when he discharges the obligation does ' ipso facto ' release the debtor, and fully satisfy law. In each of the above four classes of instances adduced, there is un deniable substitution." Remarks. — (i) In order to prove substitu tion normal in divine law, Mr. Armour pre sents four classes of substitution (so called) in the sphere of human law. Remarkable logic! Suppose all he says, or could possibly say, of such cases to be true, what force has it on the case in hand? Does it follow because my neighbor can discharge a civil obligation in my place that he therefore can discharge a moral obligation for me? Because he can work the streets in my place, does it follow that he can eat or sleep in my place? or love God or my neighbor in my place? Is it normal, or even possible, for him to do such things? (2) Human law creates no obligations. It presupposes obligations arising outside of it self, and indicates in what manner these prior obligations shall be discharged. The fact that it in some trivial cases, such as working streets and military service, admits of some sort of substitution, is rather proof of abnormality — is a proof of the imperfection of human law- 102 Atonement Reviewed. makers, and of the inadequacy of human laws to secure exact justice among men. In allow ing any form of substitution it becomes ab normal, and in forcing any uniform rule it is often unjust, because no human legislation can adjust civil duties in exact accordance with human ability. The best of human laws are only proxi mately just. Of course all such substitutions as are admissible by such laws, are abnormal, because only proximately just or equal, or do not have their requirements in exact accord with ability, every thing considered. There possibly never was, and never will be, a case of substitution in the lowest sphere of laws which did not, or will not, involve more or less of injustice to one or the other party, or to some one directly or indirectly connected with them. So of all cases of security for debt — more or less of injustice, in some form, results to some person sooner or later. Nothing that involves injustice can be properly called nor mal. Normal injustice! All substitution in human law involves injustice, and injustice is abnormality itself. Divine law alone is rigidly just — is in exact accord with ability, all things taken into the account, as no human law can Substitution Normal in Law. 103 be; and for this reason divine law utterly ex cludes all substitution. Two men may be hung from the same gal lows; one maybe atrociously criminal, the other less so; or one may be perfectly innocent; but human law inflicts the same penalty upon both. This is the best human law can do. But divine law alone can meet out its awards according to the real deserts of the parties. How can substitution, with its double imputa tion, in such cases possibly be just? and how normal, if unjust? (3) Why does Mr. Armour use the words "substitute" and "surety" as synonyms? They are not so etymologically, nor by good usage, nor as law terms, nor so used in the Bible. A substitute is one who actually as sumes the place or obligations of another; a surety is one who binds himself in case of the failure of the principal. The substitute has no recourse upon the principal. The surety has such recourse if he has to fulfill the obli gations of the principal, Mr. Armour's asser tion to the contrary notwithstanding. A man can not be a substitute and a surety at the same time. One effectively excludes the other. Mr. Armour, of course, knows this; but the distinction brings trouble to his theory, and therefore must be blotted out. 104 Atonement Reviewed. (4) Mr. Armour's third and fourth classes of substitution — for crime and debt — deserve some special attention. The third is a most crafty and cautiously worded attempt to say something and nothing at the same time. Will the reader turn to it and study it a little? The pretentious statement fairly destroys itself by its own limitation. It suggests the old ridiculous story of the snake that swal lowed itself. Mr. Armour might just as pertinently and truthfully say that " law as understood and ad ministered by men in all lands, provides " that a man may steal his neighbor's horse "in all cases in which the " theft may be committed " consistently with the obligations he is already under." Both statements are equally true, and equally worthless as facts. Mr. Armour knows that there are no " cases in which the penalty prescribed is such that a substitute may meet it consistently with the obligations he is already under." Why then deal in great swelling words that mean noth ing, and yet tend to make the impression that penal substitution is normal in law, or is an actual provision of law, and belongs to the common course of things? He, of course, does not wish to deceive; yet what he Substitution Normal in Law. 105 says tends to make false impressions upon the thoughtless reader. I certainly hazard noth ing when I say that no law, human or divine, provides for penal substitution, but on the con* trary all such law is utterly antagonistic to it, and deems such a substitution a crime. This is fairly implied by Mr. Armour's utter failure to specify a single case of substitution under criminal law. If a starving mother were to steal a mutton-chop for herself and hungry children, and she were sentenced to a day's imprisonment as a punishment, and her father were to propose to take her place, the offer could not be legally accepted; or if accepted, the prison-keeper would be liable to indict ment for false imprisonment. Nor could a thousand substitutes, if all imprisoned, release the hungry woman. So it is of murder and all other criminal of fenses. No substitution is admissible foi the simple but sufficient reason that to transfer the penalty from the guilty principal to the inno cent substitute is to commit a double wrong — in excusing the guilty and in punishing the in nocent. "Substitution a normal provision in (criminal) law!" But Mr. Armour might seek to justify his broad assertions concerning criminal substitu tion by saying that when a law breaker is as- 106 Atonement Reviewed. sessed in a crime, a friend may pay the fine and thus become a substitute for the criminal. This, however, is no relief, for there is absolutely no substitution in the case. The friend who furnishes the money is in no sense a substitute for the criminal, but a friend or benefactor only. This will be more fully considered in another place. (5) Mr. Armour's fourth class of substitu tions — debts — is that upon which he chiefly relies for illustration and proof of his postu late, "Substitution normal in law." He says "debt is obligation unto law." As we have seen, debt is obligation to a person, and not to law as such. Whether law is intended to be here taken in a realistic or in a personified sense is not clear. Of course it is not taken in its literal and proper sense, and gives us no distinct idea. He says "in the case of debt .... a sub stitute is always admitted." That, however, is wholly at the option of the creditor. The debtor can not force the creditor to accept a substitute against his will. To accept a sub stitute is to release the principal. I have pre viously noticed the difference between a sub stitute and a surety, to which distinction our author is blind, with or without a purpose. He says " a surety who is always a true and Substitution Normal in Law. 107 proper substitute, when he discharges the obli gation does ' ipso facto'' release the debtor, and fully satisfy law." Here we have a very plain subject muddled by a vicious use of terms. If we take the word surety in the sense of substitute, as our author intends, then the creditor or the law releases the debtor the in stant he accepts the substitute, and not when the money is paid. But if we take the word surety in its proper sense, then the surety, when he pays the debt, does not necessarily " ipso facto release the debtor and fully satisfy law." If A owes B ten dollars, and B owes C ten dollars, by consent of parties C may accept A as a substitute for B. This releases B, but if C accept A only as a surety for B this does not re lease B. But if A, as surety, pays the debt, he does not by that act release B. On the contrary, A cancels the obligation to C, and becomes the legal substitute of C, and holds the same legal claim against B originally held against him by C. Of course there may be some diversity in the provisions of statutory law in relation to substitution and suretyship as to money interests in different States. But what I have said accords with the general Custom, and is withal in strict accord with common sense and common justice. 10S Atonement Reviewed. These facts make fearful havoc with Mr. Ar mour's whole theory of substitution and surety ship, both in the sphere of commercial and moral law. Of this fact, Mr. Armour seems quite sensi ble. This he evinces by an elaborate effort to establish the preposterous idea that the pay ment of debt by a surety releases the princi pal from all legal obligation, and imposes upon him only a debt of gratitude (which of course may be repudiated with the utmost impunity). He says (p. 140): "The rescued debtor owes to him who became his surety a deep and inextinguishable debt of gratitude. This all right-minded persons at once recognize. But this new obligation is not a legal obliga tion. The most talented lawyer would not assume to put it into legal form. No Legisla ture has ever proposed to enact a law by which a surety might afterward recover from the original party for whom he acted. Surely this has not been for want of deep conviction of real obligation, but because even average legislators were able to see that this obliga tion, though sacred and weighty, was not a legal obligation. They have therefore allowed it to stand in all its weight and sacredness. It is a true and striking type of our ob!i prions to Christ, who delivered us from the infinite cieox Substitution Normal in Law. 109 we were under. Even the befriended debtor is not under law, b?it tinder grace, as are and must be for evermore all the redeemed." Remarks. — (I will not comment on the rashness of these utterances. The reader can readily satisfy himself, if he does not already know, whether a surety, when he is forced to pay the debt of his principal, is left utterly without legal claim against the party on whose account he has lost his money. But I have something to say of his scheme of suretyship.) 1. It opens wide the door and presents a strong temptation to fraud — downright rascal ity. The love of money is said to be the root of all evil. If I, by flattery, or duplicity, or in any way, work myself into the good graces or confidence of my neighbor, and induce him to become my surety, I can put myself in a condition to defy the law, and thus force my innocent neighbor to pay the debt; or I might collude with the creditor and persuade, or even bribe, him to force payment from my neighbor. I can conceive of no scheme of swindling so sure of success, and at the same time so exempt from punishment. Legislatures, seeing this, have wisely ad judged it proper to make sureties, who have no Atonement Reviewed. been forced to pay the debts of their princi pals, the legal substitutes of the creditors. Laws which should allow suretyship at all, and yet make no provision for the protection of sureties, would be an intolerable nuisance. This is too plain to require elaboration. 2. But our author tells us that the debtor whose debts have been paid by another owes his surety a debt of gratitude. But suppose the debtor should refuse to pay this debt, then what? 3. But this new obligation is not a legal ob ligation, we are told. Mystery here! The obligation was orig inally legal. The creditor, having received his money of the surety, of course has no claim upon the debtor. But how comes the debtor, having paid nothing, to pass from un der a legal obligation into a non-legal? The debtor did justly owe the debt, has not paid it, it has not been forgiven, he is presumably able to pay it, and yet does not legally owe it! But we are graveiy told that he owes, as a sort of substitute, I suppose, for his legal obligation, a debt of gratitude, which he can, of course, fully pay or repudiate at pleasure, and with utmost impunity. Is this accepta tion, relaxation, or abrogation of law? Or, is it, in fact, only an empty fiction? In the Substitution Normal in Law. hi meantime, let it be remembered that the sure ty has lost his money, hopelessly, and, having no legal claim, may never be able to collect a particle of that substituted debt — debt of grat itude which is said to be due. In the light of this philosophy, it seems far worse to be a surety than to be a debtor. 4. But we are told that "even average leg islators were able to see that this {new) obli gation, though sacred and weighty, was not a legal obligation." Certainly, "even average legislators " may be able to see that the obli gation to gratitude can not be enforced by a process of law or any other means; but they can not very clearly see how a legal obligation can, by the rascality of the debtor, be con verted into a non-legal obligation, and his surety left to suffer on his account, and with out any possibility of redress. 5. All the interest connected with the dis cussion of suretyship and substitution in com mercial law, arises out of the fact that Mr. Armour assumes these substitutions to be di vinely preordained types and adumbrations of the so-called substitutionary work of Christ in behalf of the elect portion of humanity. He accordingly informs us that this new obli gation " is a true and striking type of our ob- ii2 Atonement Reviewed. ligation to Christ, who delivered us from the infinite debt we were under." I have somewhat against this preordained scheme of typology: (i) As we have seen, Mr. Armour mispresents the doctrines, both of human substitution and of suretyship; or, rather he constructs a scheme of human sub stitution to fit his conception of what he calls the " great substitutionary work of Christ." That he misconceives the atonement of Christ, assuming him to be a substitute for the elect, both as to the preceptive and penal side of the divine law, is, I think, capable of irre futable proof. Constructing his types from a false antitype, it is not at all strange that he should give us a group of fictions instead of facts; or that he. should misrepresent both human and divine law. (2) With all his marvelous, inventive abilities, he signally fails to make his type fit his antitype — notably in this, that Christ's substitution compels, necessitates the gratitude of all for whom he is a substitute. Christ ac cordingly is somehow compensated for his vicarious work, but the human substitute has no such guaranty, but is liable to irreparable loss for his kindness to his fellow-man. This we may more fully see. 3. "Christ delivered us from the infinite Substitution Normal in Law. 113 debt we were under." So it is said. Is there no extravagance in this? Infinite debt! Is a finite creature capable of an infinite obligation or debt? or of an infinity of any thing? Again, this infinite debt is not the joint debt of humanity. This would involve the salva tion of the reprobate; but the individual debt of the elect. How many infinite debts is one personality capable of paying? Christianity would have more friends if its advocates had less propension to exaggerate its doctrines. Exaggeration may make the simplest truth in credible. All the plausibility of Mr. Armour's discussion of substitution in commercial law arises out of his vicious use of terms, his as sumption that substitution and suretyship are in law identical. This fallacy corrected, his analogical argument in favor of a substitution ary atonement vanishes into thin air. But suppose that it could be proved beyond all doubt that substitution, in our author's arbitrary sense of terms, is just, and normal because just — normal in criminal law, in com mercial law, in all human law — would it log ically follow that Christ, as a substitute, " de livered us (the elect) from the infinite debt we were under?" or that he obeyed the precept and " paid the penalty " of the divine law, in the place of the elect? Such a conclusion 1 14 Atonement Reviewed. from such premises would be a veritable non sequitur, and would be accepted as satisfac tory on no other subject. The argument in its simplest and most plausible form would be substantially as follows: Substitution is normal in all human law. But human laws are the divinely foreor dained types of divine law. Therefore substi tution is normal in the divine law, ordained for the government of the moral world. This, I think, is the gist of the whole argu ment, founded on substitutions, so called, in human law. What is it worth? It is scarce ly necessary to say, what the reader can not fail to see, that the major proposition is false; that the minor proposition is an extravagant assumption — a graceless figment, and the con clusion a non sequitur. SECTION VIII. i. SUBSTITUTION PROVED TCLBE ABNOR MAL BY THE IMPOSSIBILITY OF "ITS CONDITIONS. WE have seen that substitution, in Mr. Armour's use of the term, is abnor mal because essentially unjust in itself; be cause it oppresses the innocent, and rewards the guilty — very well illustrated by the case of Christ and Barabbas — also because it of fers a premium to fraud without liability to punishment. I propose now to prove it abnormal, be cause it is impossible in its conditions. Our author, in order to strengthen his doc trines of substitution and give to them an air of universality, deems it proper to define the qualifications of a substitute, which he im properly identifies with a surety. These qualifications, it may be seen, are not the pro ductions of any law-making power, human or divine. They are the pure elaborations of our author's fertile brain. The process, though ingenious, is not extremely difficult. ("5) 116 Atonement Reviewed. He first assumes — scarcely attempts to prove — that Christ is the legal substitute of all the elect in such a s^nsethat their debts — sins — are laid on him, and his non-indebtedness is accounted to them. To give this proced ure the appearance of a legitimate and normal legal process, he makes Christ his model sub stitute; and whatever he conceives to be an essential characteristic of this model substi tute he lays down as an indispensable prerequi site in all substitution; and then sweeps, with the exultation of one who has made a grand discovery, to the conclusion that substitution is a normal provision of all law, human and divine. Let us now look briefly into these indispen sable characteristics of substitution. He does not educe his theory from well-as certained and admitted facts, but constructs his facts to fit his theory. He first forms his conclusion, and then adroitly fabricates the facts. Thus the assumption that Christ is the sub stitute of all the elect is made by the marvel ous ingenuity of our author to prove that sub stitution, with double imputation, is a normal provision of law. Let us now glance briefly at these indispen sable qualifications of a substitute. It is not Substitution Abnormal. 117 necessary to notice them all in detail — a few of the more prominent will answer my pur pose. 1. He says (p. 129): " Substitution among men is indeed confined to a narrow limit " — (elsewhere, as we shall see, he makes it in clude all benefactions) — "but this is wholly owing to the fact that man is not qualified to be a substitute for his fellow-man, except in those cases in which the obligations he is required to meet, whether fulfilling the precept or suf fering the penalty, be such that he may assume, meet, and discharge them in consistency with his already existing obligations and duties." Marvelous philosophy! Substitution confined to a narrow limit! If a normal provision of law — all law, I should think it would have a very large range, not only " among men," but through the whole dominion of law — that it should be the most common thing in the law-engirdled universe. But why so limited a range? Well, it is wholly owing to the fact that man can not be himself and somebody else at the same time, or be two equal personalities, one under obli gation and the other free from obligation, and capable of a voluntary alternation of positions. In the trivial so-called substitutions possible among men there is nothing more than a com- nS Atonement Reviewed. pensatory exchange of what are deemed equivalent values — as in working roads, serv ing in the army, etc., and this is possible only in the sphere of human law, but is quite ex cluded in moral law. In such cases one party does not discharge the duty of another, but does something in his own interest which does not release the other party from an obligation, but only from the necessity of discharging an obligation in a particular way. If A works the streets on B's account, B is not released from legal obligation by that act, but is legally bound for the value of the work. A, therefore, is not a substitute for B, in Mr. Armour's sense of the term, but is the legal substitute of the State. Nor is this obligation for the value of the work " a new obligation," but is the original obligation, which may be discharged by money in lieu of work. Of course it is not a legal obligation transmuted into a debt of gratitude which may be paid or repudiated at pleasure. Money and gratitude are not legal equivalents, there being no law for the transmutation of one into the other. I heartily concur with our author that sub stitution, in his sense of the word, has " a nar row limit," and the reason is exceedingly plain. Every man has his own duties — his own place to fill. One man was not made to do Substitution Abnormal 119 his own duty and the duty of others. Just as well say that one sun was made to fill its own place and the place of others. Such an ar rangement cf nature would involve a dispro portion between obligations and obligees; would be an imputation upon the wisdom and beneficence of the Creator; or, rather the thing itself is inconceivable. If one man does something as a gratuity for another, he does it as a benefactor, and in no sense as his sub stitute. In the sphere of moral law, substitu tion, as we shall see, is certainly excluded, and this is the kind of law with which this discussion is concerned. 2. "Law (p. 28) in its own nature provides for, admits, and is fully satisfied with an ad equate substitute? What law makes this provision? Mr. Ar mour's answer would be, All law; yet no proof or illustration is attempted. But is the reader instructed, or, rather mystified, by the bold and unqualified assertion? He may very appropriately inquire whether Mr. Armour means that law is satisfied with the obedience of one person instead of that of another, or of one hind of obedience instead of another. He holds to both these views — that is, A may be come the substitute of B, and may satisfy the law by a service different in kind from what 120 Atonement Reviewed. is required of B. This is double substitution; substitution as to the subject, and as to the requirement of the law. The latter our au thor is pleased to call equivalent penalty, as we shall see. What a flexible, accommodat ing thing law must be? But from this apparent absurdity Mr. Ar mour escapes by the unobtrusive, but well- nigh omnific word, "adequate'''' — "adequate substitute." The eye thoughtfully fixed on this word, we see at a glance that this underscored prop osition can not but be true; but we also as readily see that this word adequate reduces his pretentious proposition to a nullity. For it is self-evident that what is inadequate to an end is nothing as to that end. Mr. Armour's emphasized proposition then reduces to this: "Law in its own nature pro vides for, admits, and is fully satisfied with any substitute that is provided for, admitted and fully satisfies it." Such empty propositions of course prove nothing. They may perplex, but can not in struct the reader. We, I suppose, might admit that law in its own nature provides for substitution, or any thing else that is possible in its conditions. It certainly is true that what is impossible in its Substitution Abnormal. 121 conditions is impossible in itself. Mr. Armour might say, with equal fidelity to truth, that Archimedes could have turned the earth up side down, if he could have furnished a place for his fulcrum and whatever else was neces sary to this end. Who would have temerity enough to deny that the earth would be thrown from its orbit if all the necesary con ditions of such an achievement were at com mand? So far as we know there may be no diffi culty about law itself as it exists in Mr. Ar mour's imagination, but the necessary condi tions may be very impracticable things. What is incumbent in our author is not to astonish, and even awe his readers by high-sounding periods that mean nothing but to prove that law — all law, human and divine — admits of substitution with double imputation. This posi tion established, he will have proved that the physical and moral world may be run on his substitutionary principles, or rather that God does not rule the world according to law or a fixed order of antecedence and consequences at all, but by lawless caprice. The impossibility of procuring adequate sub stitutes with twofold imputations is, if possi ble, made more manifest by a brief examina tion of what our author says of the indispensa- 122 Atonement Reviewed. ble characteristics of a substitute. He teaches (pp. 194-6) in various forms of expression that the surety must be free from the obligation which he assumes, must come under it freely, must not injure himself permanently, must survive, must not fail of full reward. To give emphasis to these statements, he variously affirms that the substitute "must survive," " must be in the end no loser," " must be fully rewarded." Again (p. 196): "Every one of these conditions above adduced may be found meeting in an ordinary case of suretyship among men, as well as in the great example of which they are but types." . . . "A surety for debt survives, is not in the long run a loser, provided he were justifiable in becoming sure ty. His reward is assured beyond doubt by the Righteous Judge of all the earth." Remarks. — 1. Mr. Armour is like a woman who determines that her dress pattern shall measure fifteen yards. She accordingly ad justs the yard-stick to serve her purpose, and then measures her cloth with it. Of course she has fifteen yards. But in doing this, has not Mr. Armour proved substitution to be well-nigh or quite abnormal to human law by making well-nigh Substitution Abnormal. 123 or quite impossible its indispensable condi tions? 2. " The substitute must survive." I know what our author means in relation to the Great Atoner; but I do not know what he means in relation to sureties for debts — whether the substitute must survive his sure tyship financially, or live till the surety debt is paid, or be restored to life in the resurrec tion? Of course he means something in some way analogous to the resurrection of Christ, of which he deems it a divinely constituted type. We know that thousands of men and their families are reduced to poverty and wretched ness by security; that thousands die in this condition, and that many of them seem to die premahirely because of these substitutionary troubles. Or, perhaps Mr. Armour means to set aside all such troubles by the application of his talis- manic salvo, "provided he were justifiable in becoming surety? (The underscoring is mine.) This happy device will authorize Mr. Armour to say any thing he may choose to say, or rather any thing he could possibly say, about the qualifications of substitutes. 3. "He must be in the end no loser." What end? The end of the debt, or the end 124 Atonement Reviewed. of life, or the end of eternity? Mr. Armour does not say what end, and I of course do not know; but from what he says about the Righteous Judge, the idea is suggested that he means the end of eternity — a long time to wait. Crowded as is the legal profession, all the jurists in America, with Mr. Armour to help them, could not convince one of a thou sand of those unhappy men who have lost all by security debts, that they have not been permanently injured by becoming security. Still Mr. Armour, like a pagan oracle which can never be convicted of verbal error, is on the safe side; for he can easily say of these surety wrecks or dupes that they were not "justifiable in becoming security," and there is an end of the matter. Mr. Armour is right, and the poor dupe ought to suffer irreparable loss for his unjustifiable kindness in becom ing surety! 4. " Provided he were justifiable in becom ing surety." This seems about equivalent to saying that all 's well that ends well — all ill that ends ill; and this again smacks profusely of that form of utilitarianism which makes the right and wrong in action depend upon consequences. But who besides Omniscience can know whether he is or is not justifiable in becom- Substitution Abnormal. 125 ing surety? We poor, blind mortals know not what a day, or even an hour, may bring forth — can not see the end from the beginning. May be to-day the happy owner of thousands, to morrow miserable bankrupts. fustifiableness, then, it seems, is a prime prerequisite to suretyship. For without it the surety loses all. As a man can never fore see the consequences, he of course can never know whether kindness to a friend, as his surety, is justifiable or criminal; and hence, to become surety is to incur the liability of perpetrating criminal kindness. 5. The surety "must be rewarded fully." ' " His reward is assured beyond doubt by the Righteous Judge of all the earth." Certainly, he that giveth a cup of cold wa ter in the right way shall not lose his reward. But Solomon says: "He that is surety for a stranger shall smart for it." But according to Mr. Armour this reward is assured only on condition a man is "justifiable in becoming surety," and this he can never know but by the consequences of the act, and, hence, not till after the act is done. Hence, I do not see how he is to get " beyond doubt" as to this reward until after his doom is fixed. But there is another aspect of this full and assured reward that requires some attention. 126 Atonement Reviewed. (i) Whence comes this reward? Who pays it? Mr. Armour does not inform us. He tells us that it is assured by the Righteous Judge; but he may not mean that the Righteous Judge actually pays it. Now we must suppose that the surety is paid either by the law, or cred itor, or by the original debtor. If by the for mer, then the law or creditor receives less than his just claims by exactly the value of this re ward. Mr. Armour does not specify the amount of this reward, but says it is " a full reward." If full, then it can not be less than the sum actually paid by the surety — ought, in justice, to be greater. If you pay to A $1,000 for B, you would not think any thing less than $1,000 a full reward for your kindness; you might reasonably expect more. Hence, it is as plain as A B C, that if Just ice, or the Creditor, pays this full reward, then the whole debt at least is lost, and justly some thing besides. Now, I submit whether it would not be bet ter to forgive defaulting debtors outright, and at once, than for Justice to require all this tur moil, and then lose the whole debt at last? But possibly Mr. Armour does not mean that the law pays this "full reward," but that the original debtor pays it. This is probably Substitution Abnormal. 127 his meaning. But the original debtor is con fessedly bankrupt, and can not of himself pay this " full reward." How, then, can it be paid? Two ways are conceivable. The Righteous Judge, the Creditor, becomes the sinner's as surer, or surety, to the substitute. This assur ance justifies the man in becoming surety for the debtor. The case now stands exactly thus: The substitute stands as surety for the debtor to the creditor, and the creditor stands as surety for the debtor to this substitute for the payment of " a full reward" for his substi tutionary services. The substitute fully pays the debt. How now is he to be fully reward ed by the debtor? The latter being utterly bankrupt, the surety must look to his in- dorser, the " Righteous Judge." The surety pays the debt of the principal to the creditor, and the creditor pays it back to the surety — a circular process — nothing gained. Accord ing to Mr. Armour's definition a debt is "not something that ought to be paid, but something that ought to have been paid" — the creditor is as truly a delinquent debtor to the substitute as the substitute was to the creditor. But this indebtedness may be dis charged in either one of the two conceiva ble ways. First, he may pay the substitute directly out of his own coffers, which, as we 128 Atonement Reviewed. have before seen, is equivalent to paying the debt himself. Or, secondly, he may arbitra rily invest the debtor with ability to pay this full reward and necessitate his payment of it; but this, again, is to pay the debt himself by an indirection. On any plan possible to Mr. Armour's theory, we are driven to the inevitable conclusion that the sinner owes justice or the law or God a debt, and just ice or law or God pays the debt and turns the sinner free from all obligation to law, and puts him under grace. This last view of the subject is probably what Mr. Armour really means to teach. He holds that payment by a substitute releases from legal obligation, yet it actually creates obligations of grace. He says (p. 199): "But it must be remembered that deliverance from law in this way, so far from being deliverance from obligation, involves their coming under even greater obligations. The obligations of grace are weightier . . . than legal obliga tions." (Parenthetically, it would be the easiest thing imaginable here to convict our author of antinomianism. The difference between being under law and under grace is not a dif ference as to obligations, but purely and ex clusively as to the possibility and means of Substitution Abnormal. 129 meeting the obligations under which men are necessarily placed. But I forbear.) From this quotation it may be inferred that Mr. Armour, by the full reward assured to the substitute means, the services rendered to him by the debtor under the obligations of grace. Hence, that the substitute pays in legal currency, or penalty, and receives his full reward in gracious currency, or in the gratitude of the debtor or the redeemed. This, however, can bring no relief to the theory. For, if the debtor is ever able to reward his substitute with gratitude or any thing else, it is exclusively because, accord ing to the theory the Righteous Judge, his security, unconditionally causes or necessi tates this gratitude and necessitates the dis charge of the obligation of grace (so-called). Much more might be said in disproof of the sweeping proposition that substitution is a normal provision of law. But enough has been said. We have seen that substitution is abnormal; first, because it generally, if not in every possible case, involves more or less injustice — often the greatest injustice. Sec ondly, because it is rarely possible in any form, because it is generally impossible in its conditions, and what is impossible in its con ditions should not be considered normal in 9 130 Atonement Reviewed. itself. We have also seen that if the prin ciple is admitted it can be of no advantage to the creditor if the substitute has to receive a full reward — that is, substitution costs the creditor as much as it secures to him, or even more, and in better currency, accord ing to Mr. Armour, because " the obligations of grace are weightier than legal obligations." For the creditor to invest the debtor with the ability to pay, and even necessitate him to pay, is simply to pay himself or " relax the law," or set aside its penalty without any legal consideration at all. But relaxation is Mr. Armour's " holy hor ror; " but, like other frail mortals, what he hates that he does. " Happy is he that con- demneth not himself in that which he allow- eth." SECTION IX. THE GREAT ANTITYPE-SUBSTITUTION. MR. ARMOUR admits, that though sub stitution is a normal provision of law, yet that among men it has "indeed a narrow limit; " not because law objects to it, but be cause of the impossibility of finding adequate substitutes. But in all this elaborate and ingenious dis cussion, he has his eye steadfastly fixed on Christ, whom he deems the great antitype sub stitute, feeling assured that in him he would readily find every prerequisite of a substitute fully adequate to obey the law and meet its penalties for as many as it might be deemed advisable to save. Let us see whether his success equals his sanguine expectations. He says (p. 188): "A surety must be one who was free from the obligation of law, not under law? Note this fact, freedom from law is an in dispensable qualification of a substitute. Again he says (p. 189): "Scripture clearly (13O 132 Atonement Reviewed. teaches that Christ, being a divine person, was not under the law, and being possessed of perfect human nature he was qualified to be our surety, or substitute. This has all along been so clearly and fully taught by the orthodox that there is no need to do more than refer to it in this place." Remarks. — 1. Where does the Scripture teach this doctrine? Nowhere. 2. Does Mr. Armour make orthodoxy, or the Bible, his supreme authority? He gen erally slaps orthodoxy in the face, except when it happens to support Armourism. But orthodoxy he deems sufficient authority on this, one of the most intricate and vital ques tions in the whole substitutionary theory. 3. Does the reader know exactly what our author means when he says, " that Christ be ing a divine person was not under the law?" Does the reader know that in this proposition, so unobtrusively made, he begs the whole question in the interest of substitution, and gently lays the responsibility on the broad shoulders of orthodoxy? His logic runs thus: "A substitute must be free from the obligation of law." Christ being a divine person was not under the law. Therefore, Christ was an adequate substitute The Great Antitype Substitution. 133 for all for whom he might choose to engage as such. The logic is good, but the concluT sion is false, because the minor proposition is a glaring petitio principii. Let us look after it a little. I do not know Mr. Armour's notions of the Godhead. He however admits the divinity of Christ, and this is sufficient. The word Christ is here used in the sense of the God-man. Now it is very evident that Christ as God is not un der law, as a rule of obedience; for his will is law. Christ, then, as God, is not under law, nor is it possible for him in any sense ever to come under or obey law; for Mr. Armour has told us that obedience consists in the surren der of the will to the will of another; but there is, of course, none above God to whose will he (God) can surrender. Hence, Christ as God can never come under law, or obey it either for himself or another. But Christ, as a man, was born under law (Gal. iv. 4), is yet under law, and will ever be under law. Hence, it is as clear as the sun in the heav ens that Christ as God can not be a substitute for men, Armour being judge; and equally as clear that Christ as man can not be a substi tute for men, Armour still being judge. But may there not be something in the union of these two natures that takes the hu- 134 Atonement Reviewed. man from under law, and renders the God- man capable of becoming a substitute? I answer, No. The union is not an amal gam. The human does not become inhuman, nor the divine undiv'me. No tertium quid is formed. The two natures remain ever dis tinct. Every act Christ ever did was either wholly divine or wholly human — no act was ever partly human and partly divine. Such an act is inconceivable. The truth, in the light of these irrefutable facts, is fairly demon strated that if Christ, as God, could not be a substitute for men, nor Christ, as man, such a substitute, then he as the God-man could not be a substitute at all. Here we are brought face to face with the same irrepressible obstacles that beset substi tutions among men — the impossibility of an adequate substitute. We find them, too, at the very point where Mr. Armour expected to have the least trouble. When Mr. Armour says, " that Christ, be ing a divine person, was not under law," he does not mean, as we subsequently learn, that Christ never came under law, but that he voluntarily assumed an obligation which was not natively his own. The leading postu lates of his theory on this subject are that God was under no obligations to save any The Great Antitype Substitution. 135 part of fallen humanity, but, moved by sov ereign free grace, he sent his Son to redeem a part of humanity — the Son, under covenant engagements, voluntarily consented to assume humanity, and come under law, in order to become their legal substitute, and fulfill the precepts of the law, and pay its penalties in their stead. The following quotation pretty fully sets forth his scheme. He says (p. 207): "The law had no claim upon the Son; there was no obligation upon him to come under its commandment. His doing this was pure, mere free grace. To this he was moved by nothing but his divine compassion. But found under law, under that law which, with its precepts and its pen alties was against us, he as the result of his own act of grace in joining himself to us, and by virtue of his being every way fully qualified to rescue us from ruin, was under imperative obligation. The law then directly demanded of him, since he was found under the very law which was upon us, all that we owed, whether payment of penalty or obedi ence to the precept." Again, he says (p. 209): "The law avails itself instantly of the glorious perfections, qualifications, and resources of the Mighty One, the Almighty One, who comes under it." 136 Atonement Reviewed. Remarks. — In these quotations Mr. Ar mour strangely interblends truth and error. In this case the error largely predominates. To remove the chaff will require a little pa tience. 1. Whether the great Creator was under any obligations to provide salvation for sinful humanity is a question which I am glad I am not required to settle, for I am certain I should not know how to decide. Mr. Armour as sumes to understand it, and volunteers a neg ative answer. He may be right. He has some unique notions about freedom and re sponsibility. It will be remembered that he puts the Creator under a nondescript voluntary neces sity. What that is he alone is presumed to know. But, the question very naturally arises, If the Creator always acts both voluntarily and yet necessarily, how can he do what he is under no obligation to do? It is a blessed truth that the Creator has provided salvation for men — at least a part of them. If this was exclusively a voluntary act, then it may be supererogatory If it was purely a necessary act, then it is simply childish to say either that he was or was not under obligation to provide salvation. The Great Antitype Substitution. 137 But if the act was both voluntary and nec essary, then Mr. Armour alone, it is pre sumed, is able to settle the perplexing ques tion. As he has been pleased to settle it negatively, the world has abundant reason to rejoice that the Creator, compelled by neces sity or something better, has transcended the terms of the obligations imposed upon him by Armourism, and has actually provided sal vation for men — at least for the elect. 2. There is something of truth in what our author says about Christ's being under law — the same law that requires men to love God with all their heart, etc., made it his impera tive duty to espouse the cause of humanity, and, by his obedience unto death, make him self a sacrifice in the interest of humanity. But Mr. Armour has, essentially, misstated this vital truth— has so blended it with unmit igated error as to give his readers only a confused and, withal, a radically false notion of Christ's subjection to law. His first grand error is his failure to dis criminate between the divine and human side of Christ's character. Hence, he falsely puts the whole God-man under law in the same sense in which a mere man is under law, than which a greater absurdity is not possible. For Christ, as God, was not under law at all. 138 Atonement Reviewed. Christ as man alone was under law, he as man alone was capable of obedience unto death. But if he, both as God and man, was under law — was obedient unto death — then, of necessity, he suffered and died both as God and man. Is Mr. Armour willing to ac cept the logical correlates of his own postu lates? 3. Our author represents both sides of the God-man as coming voluntarily under law. This, too, is fatal error. Christ, as God, voluntarily allied himself with humanity — assumed humanity which was under law, but did not and could not thereby become subject to law as God. The human spirit is, in a sense, allied with a material body, but does not, and can not, on this account, become subject to physical law. But while Christ, as God, voluntarily allies himself with humanity without assuming the obligations of humanity, he, as man, comes under law from necessity, just as Mr. Armour and all other men. He was born of a wom an — born under the law. How is it pos sible for one born under the law to come vol untarily, by an act of will, under the law? It is hence too plain not to be seen by all that have eyes that Mr. Armour attributes to The Great Antitype Substitution. 139 both natures in Christ what is true only of the divine — namely, voluntariness; and to both what is true only of the human — namely, subjection to law. Such indiscriminate and wholesale blending of the human and divine spawns " darkness itself," and renders a for mulation of the doctrine of atonement on a scientific basis utterly hopeless. 4. The impracticability of Mr. Armour's scheme of substitution will further appear from the following rash, if not unpardonable, utterances (p. 209): " The law avails itself instantly of the glorious perfections, qualifi cations, and resources of the Mighty One, the Almighty One, who comes under it. The law itself commands him, and requires of him that he who is fully able should obey it by rendering all that it demanded, and this by one offering." Repressing whatever of unsavory feelings these bold words may awaken, let us glance at the attitude in which Mr. Armour is pleased to put " the Mighty One, the Almighty One." " The law avails itself of the " abilities of the Almighty One! "The law itself com mands him!" "The law itself . . . requires of him! " Requires him to do what? To obey it. How? By rendering to it all that it demands of all sinful men — at least of the 140 Atonement Reviewed. elect. Marvelous doctrine! Marvelous for its absurdity! If Mr. Armour had said this of Christ's human nature exclusively, or as distinguished from his divine nature, it would be partially true — true in relation to his personal obliga tions to the law, but not true as to any substi tutionary obligations — that is, he obeyed the law for himself and none else. But to predi cate these things of " the Almighty One " is the sum of all absurdities. Properly may we ask, What is this super- theistic law — this law above omnipotence that imperiously commands the Almighty One " to do this and he doeth it? " Well, strange to say, it is simply the will, or the behests of the will, of " the Almighty One " himself. The Almighty One obeying the will of the Al mighty One! The Almighty One surety to the Almighty One for the adjustment of all legal claims against sinful men!! Certainly all those for whom the Almighty One has assumed all obligations, and for whom he stands as surety against his own anger, have no reason to concern themselves about their salvation! Possibly Mr. Armour, when he says, " the law commands him (the Almighty One) and requires of him that he who is fully able should obey it," means that The Great Antitype Substitution. 141 God, as the Son, was under law to God, as the Father. No relief can be found, however, in the mystery of the Trinity; for if there are three divine persons, there are not three divine wills; else there would be three Gods. Hence, the Almighty One can net surrender his will, or render obedience to a superior will, for there is no such will. Mr. Armour's scheme of substitution logically requires us to believe either that there are verily three Gods, or that God is under law (in command ment of course) to God, and actually sur renders his will to his will. Neither is credi ble. 5. It is not quite apparent how Mr. Armour can escape universalism; or, rather it is suf ficiently clear that he can not escape it all. He says, in one of the quotations above given, that Christ " as the result of his own act of grace in joining himself to us (taking human nature), and by virtue of his being every way fully qualified to rescue us from ruin, was under imperative obligation. The law, then, directly demanded of him, since he was found under the very law which was upon us, all that we owed, whether payment of penalty or obedience, to the precept." Here we are plainly taught that Christ, by 142 Atonement Reviewed. joining himself to us, or by taking our nature, came actually under law, and he being able to deliver humanity from sin, the law directly demanded of him all that we owed. Again, he says: "Christ's voluntarily coming under law was his voluntarily consenting to be our substitute." Now, it is sun-clear that if Christ's taking our nature, put him under law, and his being under law makes him the substitute of those whose nature he had assumed, and if all for whom he is a substitute are necessarily saved, as Mr. Armour often asserts, then the salvation of all is assured. A universal and a necessitated salvation is the logical result of our author's scheme of substitutionary atone ment. To this logical result of the theory Mr. Ar mour (if not in fact a universalist) would ob ject, and allege that the Son, by covenant en gagement, became the substitute of a part of mankind only. To this the following is an adequate reply: 1. It was not any covenant engagement, real or imaginary, between the Father and the Son that put Christ under law, but the actual taking of human nature — his being born of a woman — that put him under law. Without this assumption of human nature he could The Great Antitype Substitution. 143 not save one man. But in assuming it as to one man, he necessarily assumed it as to all; for human nature is the common property of all. Hence, the law which makes Christ the substitute of a part necessarily makes him equally the substitute (so called) of all. I will illustrate after our author's method. Suppose a business firm of ten men break with a bank debt against the firm of $10,000. An outsider, having a special friend in the firm, generously proposes to relieve him alone, and does become his substitute in the firm and releases the bankrupt debtor from all lia bility. He thus, by becoming the substitute of one, does, by the law, inevitably become the substitute of all. The application is easy. Christ, Mr. Armour would have us believe, makes a covenant engagement to save some men, but not all. But he could not save them without taking their nature. But in taking their nature he necessarily becomes their substitute; for in taking the nature of a part he took the nature of the whole. More for mally thus: Christ is, by the divine law, made the legal substitute of those whose nature he assumed. He assumed the nature com mon to all men. Therefore he is the legal substitute of all men. There is no possible method of escape from 144 Atonement Reviewed. this conclusion, except by relaxing the law which required Christ to become a sin offer ing for mankind; or, as Mr. Armour would prefer to express it, a substitute for the elect. What law is this? The great moral law of the world ! " Thou shalt love the Lord thy God, and thy neighbor," etc. The law that binds man to obedience is the same law that required Christ to make his soul an offering for the sin of all those whose nature he had taken. Mr. Armour must of sheer necessity relax this law and release Christ from its obligation in reference to the non-elect; otherwise his own theory binds him inevitably to the fort unes of universalism. It ought to be uni versally known, and never forgotten, that the great moral law — the law of universal love — ¦ is the law that required Christ to die for hu manity. To die for all was to fulfill the law; not to die for all was to break the law — just as not to love our neighbor is to break the law. To make atonement for one was, from the nature of the law, to make atonement for all; not to make atonement for all was to make it for none. Mr. Armour very properly denounces re laxation of law as the greatest of all possible calamities. He criticises Turrettini, Hodge, The Great Antitype Substitution. 145 and other standard authors, for conceding some kind of relaxation. He advises, scolds, and rebukes substitutionists generally in re gard to the bad consequences of "relaxation of law." Yet, marvelous to tell, he, to save his lim- itarianism, unwittingly relaxes the law, so as to release the Great Atoner from the obliga tion of dying for all men! Mr. Armour denies utterly the possibility of relaxation of law by sovereign prerogative, or anything else, on its penal side; but by logical implication asserts it on its beneficent side. Turrettini, Hodge, and other standard au thors, admitted relaxation on the penal side that some men might be saved. But Mr. Armour's theory admits and logically asserts relaxation on the beneficent side, so that some men might be hopelessly damned. Every man to his own liking; but I some what prefer the Turrettinian relaxation. But why does Mr. Armour relax the law on the beneficent side, which leaves untold millions of helpless souls without atonement and without the possibility of salvation? He seems quite unconscious that he has relaxed it, and probably would insist that he has not done so. He, however, can escape the charge only by proving, first, the actual 10 146 Atonement Reviewed. existence of a covenant engagement on the part of the Son to redeem only a definite num ber of souls; secondly, that this covenant en gagement (so-called) takes precedence of the great moral law — thou shalt love God and thy neighbor — and actually released Christ from all obligation of law to make atonement for millions of those with whom he had allied himself by taking their nature. Neither of these propositions is capable of proof. But if they were actually proved, this fact of itself would fully prove the relaxation of the law on its beneficent side. Mr. Ar mour is one of the boldest of relaxationists, and yet has a holy horror of relaxation! I will see him again on relaxation. But why does our author deem it necessary, by covenant stipulation between the high con tracting parties, Father and the Son, to limit the atonement to a part of mankind? I will vouch for him that it is not because he is not philanthropic, or generous hearted. He would be glad to know that all men could be saved. Why, then, does he limit the atone ment? It is not his warm, Christ-like heart that limits it. It is only his cold, cast-iron logic that is guilty of this ungenerous thing. But what has his logic to do with the ques tion? After this method Mr. Armour has The Great Antitype Substitution. 147 fixed up an atonement by substitution which necessitates the salvation of all for whom it is provided. But the Bible teaches that all are not saved. Therefore, the atonement is not provided for all. Hercules could not break this chain of steel. But the conclusion is utterly false, because it denies that Christ did actually fulfill the law which required him to make an atonement for all men. The fault is not in the logic as such, but in Mr. Armour's atonement. But why does our author put God in com mandment under law to God? Why require "the Almighty One" to abnegate his will and submit to the will of "the Almighty One," as if there were two or more almighty ones? Why make " the Almighty One " a substitute for sinful men? Why impute all the infamous and abominable crimes of which men are guilty to " the Almighty One ? " Why require " the Almighty One " to obey the precepts of his own law, obedience to which alone can secure the happiness of his creatures? Why make "the Almighty One " suffer the penalties of his own law in the place of transgressors, when these penalties or sufferings are the natural and inevitable subjective consequences of a violation of a law which is the only con servative of good? 148 Atonement Reviewed. Why do Mr. Armour and other substitu- tionists commit themselves to these revolting absurdities? Not because they are wholly blind to their enormities; nor for the want of earnestness and candor in their search for truth; nor be cause their natural instincts do not revolt at them; but for the simple reason that the exi gencies of the substitutionary scheme of atone ment imperatively require their acceptance and defense. Knowing that Christ did make atonement; believing that atonement by substitution is the only atonement possible; and accepting the fact that Christ was both God and man; and knowing that as man he could fulfill the law only for himself, and consequently could not fulfill it for millions of others, they are driv en by sheer necessity to the conclusion that Christ, on his God-side, actually became a sub stitute for men, obeyed the law in their stead, both as to precept and penalty. The logic is severe and faultless. But the great vitiating fallacy is in the assumption that atonement can be made by substitution, and by substitu< tion only. This assumption, accepted as an unquestionable truth, it leads by logical con-. sequence to a legion of the grossest contradic tions. The only method of escape from these The Great Antitype Substitution. 149 insuperable troubles is the rejection in toto of the assumed, unproved, and preposterous no tion that atonement, in any proper sense, pan be made by substitution. SECTION X. SURETYSHIP AND RE-INSTATEMENT. MR. ARMOUR'S scheme of atonement requires and necessitates re-instatement. He says (p. 140): "Perfect suretyship .... is always and manifestly suretyship which, in its own nature, secures and necessitates the re instatement of every one in whose behalf it is undertaken? (The italics are his.) Again (p. 142), he says: "Christ's perfect obedience satisfies the whole debt, the entire obligation the sinner was under to the law of God." Again (p. 144), he says: "Re-instatement is necessitated by and virtually included in all real atonement." Again (p. 145), he says: "This very re instatement is itself part of, and an essential part of, true suretyship, true and full satisfac tion of law." He also teaches that Christ fully satisfied the law both as to precept and penalty. He says (p. 143): "To satisfy fully the law, the (150) Suretyship and Re-instatement. 151 obedience and suffering of Christ must fully insure the re-instatement and restoration to obedience of his redeemed." Again (p. 189): Christ delivered us from "our debts — that is, from all that law demand ed of us whether in its penalty or its precept." Again (p. 207): "The law, then, directly demanded of him . . j . all that we owed, whether payment of penalty or obedience to the precept." Remarks. — 1. No one can deny that Mr. Armour is a " restorationist " of the strictest sect. He makes restoration an essential part of the atonement itself. No restoration, no atonement, is his philosophy. 2. This necessitated restoration sweeps to the winds his doctrine of freedom with the power of a contrary choice. This is only one of his inconsistencies. According to his teach ing, the elect have no more power not to be saved than they have to save themselves. This, of course, is not fate — it is only cer tainty. 3. Mr. Armour seems to put the substitute upon double duty; or seems to require of him supererogatory obedience. First, Christ, as substitute, obeys the precept of the law for the elect, and, secondly, pays the penalty fo,r 152 Atonement Reviewed. them at the same time. How can this be? Obedience and penalty are mutually exclusive of each other. If there is perfect obedience, there can be no penalty — no cause, no effect. If there is penalty it is because there is dis obedience. The theory seems to require of the substitute an impossible thing; first, tp pay a penalty when there is none; or, second ly, to obey the precept and pay the penalty of disobedience for the same party at the same time — that is, to love God substitutionally, and at the same time endure the penalty or con sequences of not loving him. This is to love and not love at the same tim£. Contradic tions, it is allowed, are impossible things with God, but not exactly so with Mr. Armour. Possibly Mr. Armour may mean (though he nowhere, I think, so explains) that Christ first "pays the penalty" for the elect, and then, after that, obeys the precepts of the law for them foiever. This, however, brings no relief, as the fol lowing contradictions clearly show: (1) According to the theory, Christ by cov enant engagement became the substitute of the elect from eternity, and was as truly their surety in law before they were born as he is now, being a lamb slain from the foundation of the world, as Mr. Armour rightly says. Suretyship and Re-instatement. 153 How, then, was it possible for the elect to sin at all? Or, if it was possible to sin in any way, how could they possibly come into con demnation, or endure penalty, seeing that Christ was obeying the precepts of the law in their stead? How Mr. Armour could clear away this darkness that enshrouds the substitutionary theory is, to me, inconceivable. If he should say that God decreed their sin that he might illustrate his glorious grace in their redemption, then I would like to inquire, Where did he get his information? Is he the custodian of God's secrets? (2) According to Mr. Armour, the substi tute not only obeys the precepts and pays the penalties of the law, but also restores the sin ner himself to obedience. So that the law receives a threefold obedience — twice by the substitute, once in precept, and once in pen alty, and once by the re-instated sinner. In the judgment of common men, obedience to the precept of the law excludes penalty, and obedience by the substitute excludes obedience by the principal, but our author has decided otherwise; so, for the sake of his substitution ary atonement, the world is required to be lieve the law capable of a threefold obedience. 4. Mr. Armour admits that justice, like 154 Atonement Reviewed. some men, is very prompt and persistent in demanding its dues, but often very slow to pay its debts. He often distinctly avows that substitution instantly, and fully, and forever releases the principal from all obligations, pains, and pen alties in all ordinary suretyships. But some how this grand characteristic of substitution fails in the most important of all substitutions — the great antitypal suretyship of Christ for the elect. It does not instantly deliver. But why this ungracious failure? Are types more perfect than their antitypes? Human law more efficient than divine? Man more just than God? Mr. Armour perceives the difficulty, but adroitly shrouds it in mystery, and passes on to less difficult matters. Good strategy! He says (p. 144): "Re-instatement is necessitated by and virtually included in all real atone ment. That this result is reached only after, and it may be as we judge long after, is a consideration that detracts nothing from its true connection. Time is for us; with God lapse of time divides not, separates not, things that in his purpose, and in their own nature, are joined together." Remarks. — 1. According to Mr. Armour, real atonement is never made until re-instate- Suretyship and Re-instatement. 155 ment actually occurs. For if re-instatement is virtually included in real atonement, then there is no real atonement prior to the re-in statement. On page 145 he makes the point with more distinctness: " This very re-instate ment is itself part of, and an essential part of, true suretyship." But Mr. Armour, I think, did not mean to teach this absurdity, but in his great eager ness to make the atonement save all for whom it was made he incautiously commits himself to it. 2. But the material point in the case is this unaccountable tardiness of justice — its delay of the re-instatment guaranteed in substitution. We can very well afford to let Mr. Ar mour's incongruities take care of themselves; but we can not afford to admit, without better reasons than Mr. Armour has given us, that justice, or rather the " Righteous Judge," is a tardy or reluctant pay-master. I should cer tainly think him more a charlatan than a phi losopher who should pretend to comprehend the incomprehensible God. But what now concerns us is not to com prehend the Deity, but Mr. Armour's substi tution. There is, however, but sparse hope of success, for he makes substitution necessi tate instant re-instatement in God's purpose, 156 Atonement Reviewed. but it does not re-instate as to men " it maybe as we judge till long after" it has re-instated in God's purpose — that is substitution instant ly re-instates the sinnner in the divine pur pose, but does not actually re-instate him till long after this important event; or the sinner is really acquitted and stands guiltless before • the bar of justice, and yet in bitter reality is involved in sin, and condemned in the court of conscience, and actually realizing the pun ishments of his sins. A guiltless human soul writhing in penal fire, or remorse! A sinner, all of whose debts are fully paid, against whom neither law nor justice has the shadow of a claim, manacled and dungeoned, it may be, scores of years for debts that have no ex istence? Such is Armourism. Relaxation of law, it will be remembered, is our author's " pet aversion," yet he is palpably guilty of relaxation of law, or something worse, when he permits the guiltless to suffer as the guilty alone can justly suffer. But why is this? Well, let our author explain it. He, it is pre sumed, understands it. He says: "Time is for us; with God lapse of time divides not, separates not, things that in his purpose, and in their own nature, are joined together." The explanation seems to need explanation as much as the thing sought to be explained. Suretyship and Reinstatement. 157 "Time is for us." Well, what of that? How does this account for the sinning and suffering of justified souls? "With God lapse of time divides not .... things that in his purpose, and in their own nature, are joined together." This, at best, is only partially true. But let it all be granted, how does it explain, or re lieve, or even mitigate the unjust sufferings which our author's theory imposes upon those for whom Christ has fully met all liabilities. To blink a difficulty is not to remove it by any means. A suitable illustration of the point in hand is furnished by the thief crucified with Christ. (Luke xxiii. 39—43.) This thief and malefac tor was without doubt saved, which proves to Mr. Armour's satisfaction that he was one of the elect. His substitute had settled all his debts, and he stood unchallenged and unchal lengeable before the law. But his re-instate ment, though his legal right had been some how deferred for a long time, and he, purely for the want of this rightful re-instatement and restoration to happy obedience, fell into gross sins — became a bad mar. a malefactor, a thief. The Romans crucified him, and he said justly, too, for his wickedness. Remark able case! Really justified before God, 158 Atonement Reviewed. but justly condemned before Pilate! Whose fault was it that he was a thief? If he had been restored to obedience, as substitution re quired that he should, he would not have died a malefactor. Mr. Armour, of course, would not admit a delinquence in the law, nor can he think it possible that his substitution is at fault. What, then, must be done with this case? Take refuge in mystery! " Time is for us," but not for God. SECTION XI. PENALTY— MERITOEIOUS AND UNMERI- TORIOUS. MR. ARMOUR says some true things about penal sufferings, and some things doubtful. He says (p. 119): "Law is mandatory as regards the payment of penalty; therefore vol untariness is an essential element in one case as in the other (obedience to precept), so that neither passive involuntary sufferings endured, nor mere willingness to endure sufferings in flicted, but sufferings voluntarily rendered, can satisfy law." Again (p. 120): " Involuntary sufferings not only do not satisfy law, they render absolutely nothing unto the law? Again (p. 121): "In what sense can he be said to have fulfilled the law, who merely suf fered — that is, who was passive — that is, who did nothing? How can the inflicting of suffer ing upon him without and against his will be regarded as fulfillment of law by him?" Again (p. 123), he says: "Not mere will- (r59) 160 Atonement Reviewed. ingness to suffer, but active and willing en durance . . . satisfies law." Again: "Atone ment by involuntary sufferings is a manifest absurdity." (Mr. Armour discusses this sub ject at considerable length; but the quotations above given present his principal points.) It will be observed that he rejects the doctrine of passive obedience, as held by orthodoxy. In this he is assuredly right; for a passive obe dience is a contradiction in terms. It, how ever, has been generally accepted for cen turies. Mr. Armour also rejects the equally prepos terous notion that there is any merit in penal suffering as generally held. If he had consist ently done this he would have freed the sub stitutionary scheme of atonement from the pre posterous idea that the saints are saved in whole or in part by penal righteousness. He, how ever, consistently denies that there can be any penal righteousness in perdition or elsewhere. This absurdity the orthodox form of the doc trine seems to allow; for if penal righteous ness, or the bearing of penalty, can save one man, why not save all? Hence, passive obe dience would ultimately save all rebels under penalty. Beyond these two vital points, I do not deem it safe to indorse Mr. Armour. Penalty. 161 While he denies the possibility of atone ment by passive penal sufferings, he asserts atonement by active penal suffering. Hence, he does not deny the possibility of penal right eousness; and in fact saves the elect, wholly or in material part, by it. On this account I think his scheme only a slight, immaterial im provement upon the old one. The orthodox theory asserts passive obe dience to penalty. Mr. Armour rejects this, and asserts in lieu of it active or voluntary obe dience to penalty. His order is thus stated (p. 122): "What now is the real and full de mand of the law? Is it not this: Pay what thou owest, penalty first, then obedience to the precept?" Christ as a substitute first pays the penalty, then renders obedience to the precept. Hence, of necessity the elect are saved largely by Christ's penal obedience. (We have previously had occasion to sympa thize with our author over his troubles in ref erence to obedience to the preceptive side of the law.) But the voluntary obedience to penalty is something unique. But Mr. Armour under stands himself. He clearly sees that passive obedience to the penal side of the law would release all the disloyal spirits of rebeldom. On the other hand, if he denies penal obedience 11 162 Atonement Reviewed. in toto, then there will be no method by which the multitudinous debts of the elect can ever be paid by a substitute. Happily his fertile imagination is equal to the emergency. Vol untariness — this will exclude salvation by pas sive penal suffering on one hand, and on the other secure the salvation of the elect by the voluntary penal suffering of an adequate sub stitute. What a happy expedient! No won der Mr. Armour so highly prizes it. Such immense consequences depend upon it. It seems almost cruel to dispel the fascinat ing illusion. Nevertheless, but not without high admiration of its brilliant author, a few things need to be said of it somewhat unfa vorable. i. The conception of a voluntary obedience (excuse the tautology) to penalty is born of a vague and, ill-defined notion of the nature of penalty itself. Reward and penalty are of course anti thetical: the former the natural and neces sary sequence of obedience to law; the latter the natural and necessary sequence of diso bedience. The one is as inevitable as the other. This is true of all law, and there are absolutely no exceptions except in the sphere of supernatural Providence. The obedience, and also the disobedience, Penalty. 163 are alike voluntary or active — hence no pas sive obedience to law in any form, for a pas sive obedience implies that an act is both voluntary and involuntary at the same time, which none can fail to see is a contradiction. But while the act of obedience, and also the act of disobedience, are both strictly volun tary, the reward — the consequent of obedience and the penalty — the consequent of disobe dience — are strictly and in the highest sense involuntary — utterly beyond the control of the voluntary power. The reward may be desired; the voluntary act may be put forth exclusively, as a means to procure it; but the reward comes of necessity; comes as the nec essary, not the voluntary, result of the vol untary act. If a man strictly obeys hygienic law, good health is the desirable, but neces sary, consequence or reward. The obedience is voluntary, but the reward is necessary. Exactly the same relation exists between disobedience and penalty. The disobedience is voluntary, but the pen alty — the divinely appointed consequence — is necessary. The consequence ma)' be known or not known. May be desired or not de sired — the result, the penalty is all the same — is not voluntary but necessary. 164 Atonement Reviewed. This is well illustrated by the cases named by our author (pp. 220-25). The following will answer my purpose: "Three men stepped into the electric light works, in the city of Syracuse. One of them was observed to stoop over and reach out his hands to a thirty light dynamo machine. In-? stantly he was drawn close to the generator, without a noise, and without uttering a sound. He had unwittingly grasped the positive and negative rods, and was dead." Unwittingly and voluntarily the unfortunate man grasped the fatal rods; death was the penalty. What power, voluntary or otherwise, has man over the consequences of his voluntary acts? A voluntary "payment of penalty," a vol untary " suffering of penalty," a voluntary " en durance of penalty," a voluntary " obedience to penalty," is one of the most illusive of all conceits. Even in the sphere of commer cial law, which is Mr. Armour's special hob by, voluntary obedience to penalty is simply impossible. Whatever "obedience" there may be to it, or "endurance" of it, or "pay ment" of it, comes purely from necessity, and is in no. sense voluntary. , If B owes C $100, and refuses to pay, and Penalty. 165 is compelled by law to pay it, I suspect our author would consider this forcible payment the penalty, and insist that B had some sort of voluntary power over it. This, however, would be to mistake the precept of the law for the penalty of it. The $100 is the very thing the law requires, and is in no sense the penalty or consequence of a violated obliga tion. The penalty in this case would con sist in the state of consciousness arising out of the refusal to pay, and the facts connected with the case. This consciousness is purely necessary, and is no more voluntary than is personality itself. If voluntariness to penalty is impossible in the principal, it is (if there are degrees in im possibilities) a thousand-fold more so in a substitute. How could the good health se cured to B by obedience to the laws of health be taken voluntarily or otherwise by C, and C's physical condition be transferred to B? How could another man have voluntarily tak en the penalty of the man who unwittingly grasped the positive and negative rods of the dynamo machine and was dead? How can one man take the consciousness of another who refuses to pay a just debt? If men had voluntary power over the con sequences Qf their acts, then there would be 166 Atonement Reviewed. no fixed relation between means and ends, cause and effect. If this were true, a man might be a rebel against all law, and yet, by an act of will, set aside the consequences of . his universal lawlessness; might be happy, might be any thing at will. Science and all government, except by perpetual miracle, would be impossible. To invest man with voluntary power over the consequences of his own or another's vol untary acts, whether of obedience or disobe dience, is to put him in the place of Omnipo tence himself; or rather is to give him power to do what Omnipotence himself can not do without abrogating his own established order of things, and reconstructing the world on a new and different plan. If there are such things as infinite impossi bilities, Mr. Armour's voluntary obedience to penalty is one of the number. But if there is no such thing as a voluntary penalty, and if there is any such thing as obedience or merit in suffering or paying penalty, then lost spir its have ground for hope and gehenna may be come "a land not inhabited," our author's voluntary obedience to the contrary notwith standing. 2. Let us learn something of the nature of this penalty which, according to Mr. Armour, Penalty. 167 Christ actually "obeyed," "paid," "suffered," "endured." Paul says, It is the wages of sin, that it is death. This is spiritual death. It is car- nal-mindedness. "To be carnally-minded is death." It is enmity to God. "The carnal mind is enmity against God." It is the sec ond death, the worm that never dies, the ven geance of eternal fire, "destruction from the presence of God and the glory of his power." Now, how was it possible for the sinless Christ, voluntarily or otherwise, to " pay this penalty," to " obey it," " suffer it," " endure it?" The assumption is suicidal. It assumes that Christ, as to his human nature, was capa ble of bearing all the penal consequences of the sins of all the elect, or it assumes that Christ, as to his God-nature, was capable of suffering the remorseless penalties of his own law; and that Christ, as to his human nature, was capable of loving God with all the heart, and of being happy in that love, and at the same time capable of being at enmity against God and of suffering the tortures of the un dying worm — feeling " the vengeance of eter nal fire," or else that Christ, as God, was in rebellion against God and suffered the wrath of God, or of himself, as God. Of course, no substitutionist' believes these 168 Atonement Reviewed. rabid absurdities. It is immensely to their credit that they do not believe them; but they owe their escape from them, if I mistake not, to a happy fallacy of logic. How does Mr. Armour escape? Let us see. SECTION XII. " EQUIVALENT PENALTY." WITH these words for a caption, Mr. Armour gives us a labored presenta tion of substitution and equivalent penalty. He says (p. 156): "Law as apprehended and administered by men in all lands, and in all ages, has not only admitted substitution in every case in which a really adequate substi tute was offered, but it has admitted equiva lent penalty." He says (p. 164): "When all men claim and exercise the right to enact and adminis ter laws in which equivalent penalty is pro vided for, how can we assume that the Su preme Lawgiver is not able to administer law, in its utmost range, in accordance with this principle?" Answer. — Why is the wise man not able to do what the fool does? Simply because he is a wise man. Why can not God do what man does? Simply because he is God. Cer tainly, the Almighty has a right to take les sons from human legislation if he can do no (169) 170 Atonement Reviewed. better? But I should hate to degrade the Supreme Lawgiver by even intimating that he had predetermined the possibilities, real or imaginary, of human law as types of his own law. It may be worthy of mention that when Mr. Armour wishes to emphasize the power, the rigor, or unrelaxibility of law, he appeals for types, analogies,'and illustrations to divine law. But when he wishes to clear the way for sub stitution, equivalent penalty, etc., he appeals to human law. In this he is strategetically wise. A glance over the field fully assured him that, for substitutionary purposes, the less he had to do with divine law in the realm of nature the better. He saw that it could sometimes be made to answer other valuable ends, but should never be invoked in favor of " substitution and equivalent penalty." He asserts a beautiful and predetermined analogy between substitutions in human law and the moral law (which Christ fulfilled), considering these human substitutions preor dained types of substitution in moral law. See pp. 158-59. If God ordained these analogies, he, of course, ordained the laws, both human and divine. What human laws? All laws — no distinction is made. I should hesitate to at- Equivalent Penalty. 171 tribute to the Supreme Lawgiver all the idi otic and cruel laws that have disgraced hu man codes. But Mr. Armour is a bold man, and possibly sometimes " wise above what is written." 2. " Equivalent penalty 'J '" What is that? It is the substitution of one penalty for anoth er of equal value. If I owe a debt, and you become my surety, and I fail to pay, and you have it to pay, you do not incur the penalty; because you render to the law just what it re quires — the money. You then obey the law on its preceptive side. But I am the delin quent. I suffer the penalty or the consequences of not paying. If the civil law authorizes it, I may be made to suffer stripes or imprison ment. If the law does not authorize such measures, then I am left to the retributions of moral law, self-condemnation, self-degra dation, remorse of conscience — God enforc ing in the soul the law of moral retribution. This is natural penalty, and divine because it is natural. It is God's anger, God's curse upon the transgressor of moral law. It is my penalty, exclusively mine, and I can no more rid myself of it than I can rid myself of my personality. It is, in every respect, exactly what the law, or God in nature, re quires it shall be. 172 Atonement Reviewed. Now, Mr. Armour, being horrified at the idea of putting the sinless Christ into this state of degradation and death, proposed to find another penalty of exactly the same value. Which, if it is another, must of necessity be in some respects different. But if in any respect different, then it is not the equivalent. But why? Simply for the reason — the imperative reason — that the penalty is itself exactly what the law requires, or what God in nature makes it. Hence, any variation in the penalty would be a relaxation or deflection of the law, or, if you please, a setting aside of God's decree. These facts which, I think, defy the power of refutation crush utterly Mr. Armour's scheme of equiva lent penalty, and reduce him to the humili ating necessity of utterly relaxing the law, for doing which he has so soundly berated others, or of putting the sinless Christ in the sinner's actual state of mind, self-condemnation, re morse, a state of spiritual death. He can choose which horn to hang on. Possibly Mr. Armour, if confronted with this difficulty inherent in his equivalent pen alty, might seek to escape by an appeal to mystery, or to the incomprehensible, because the "Almighty One " is the substitute and the penalty-bearer. Equivalent Penalty. 173 There is no relief by this route. God, it is universally conceded, can not contradict him self. It, I suppose, will be admitted by Mr. Armour, and all other sensible men, that God himself has ordained the necessary relations between cause and effect, antecedent and sequence, and that disobedience and penalty are causally connected. Hence, the disobe dience given, the penalty is just what it is by the immutable purpose of God. It then fol lows that if he changes it in the slightest, or substitutes another for it, he contradicts him self, or changes what he himself has made unchangeable. 4. But it may be asked, Are there no such things as equivalent penalties? I answer none, absolutely none in the sphere of moral retribution. This is sufficiently apparent from the facts just stated, but may become more appreciably so if we attempt to conceive of an exactly equivalent penalty in any given case. You may analyze the penalty to your own liking, and make it consist of many or few elements. Suppose you say it comprises dis honor, shame, remorse, self-condemnation, hatred of God, and divine wrath. Then when you attempt to construct your equivalent penalty what will you put into it 174 Atonement Reviewed. as the exact equivalent of dishonor, or of shame, or of remorse, or of self-condemna tion, or of hatred to God, or of divine wrath? Can you construct one to your own satisfac tion? Is such a thing possible? Can the Al mighty himself do it without reversing his own laws and reconstructing human nature? It is an easy matter for men to deceive themselves as to " equivalent penalty," by such illustrations as that a dollar in gold is equivalent to a dollar in silver. This is pure sophistry. As to commercial value, this is not equivalency at all, but simply identity. A dollar is a dollar, and not the equivalent of a dollar, whether it consists of a gold, or silver, or " rags and lamp-black." Moreover, gold, silver, etc., are pure enti ties, having positive values, and are in various ways comparable one with another by weight, measure, etc. Very different is it with re wards and penalties in the sphere of moral law. These are not entities that can be weighed or measured, but simply mental states, which are the respective and necessary results of obedience and disobedience. The value, too, of penalty, if we must attribute it to value, is purely negative, consisting in the privation of the good that comes from obedi ence to law, just as small-pox or leprosy is Equivalent Penalty. 175 the negative of good health. But penalty, like small-pox and leprosy, though negative, is intensely real. If equivalent penalty was possible, it would be like changing one dis ease for another. What is wanted is not the substitution of One penalty for another, but the removal of penalty, which can be done by a restoration to obedience, and in this way alone. Mr. Armour, when he represents law as saying, "Pay what thou owest, penalty first, then obedience," turns philosophy, and theology as well, upside down, or runs the cart before the horse. To remove the cause is to remove the ef fect; to obey is- to destroy the penalty or pre vent the penalty. The first thing, then, is obedience, and not penalty, as Mr. Armour puts it. This is God's method of deliverance, which Mr. Armour seems not to understand. 5. Mr. Armour speaks of " substitution and equivalent penalty " as if they were the most natural and common things imaginable. From many of his expressions one, who might happen not to know better, would readily infer that human government and God's government were chiefly run on the substitutionary scheme. 176 Atonement Reviewed. He, however, admits that "substitution among men" is indeed confined to a narrow limit, but this is owing to the impossibility of finding adequate substitutes. I suppose we would not perpetrate a verbal falsehood, but a deal of nonsense, if we should say that gehcnna might become a substitute for paradise, provided, and if — if and provid ed — it was adequate fully and satisfactorily to answer the purpose both of gehenna and par adise. But this terrible proviso makes the statement hardly less than ridiculous. It has previously been seen that what is impossible in its conditions is impossible in itself. If this is not true then nothing is im possible. Hence, all our author's parade about substitution being a normal provision of law, is only a prodigal waste of brain power. 6. In reading Mr. Armour's extraordinary book, I was constantly expecting to come to some historic fact — some real occurrence — besides little incidental substitutions in the lowest sphere of human law, which would strikingly exemplify, or, at least, clearly illus trate his doctrine. But this reasonable ex pectation was never realized. The best he has thought proper to give us — possibly the best he or any one else could give us — is a supposititious case. To this he seems to at- Equivalent Penalty. 177 tach immense importance, and for this rea son will receive brief attention. Mr. Armour presents his hypothetical case at considerable length, with much particulari ty, and in glowing style. As we are more con cerned with the pertinency of the case to the question in hand than with its style of pre sentation, I will give only its essential points. Of two young men, kinsmen of the same country, one was faultless, the other prodi gal. The latter plunged into sin, broke the laws, and was consequently arraigned before the court and convicted. The sentence pro nounced upon him by the wise and righteous judge was, according to the requirements of the law, a fine of a thousand talents or per petual banishment. The criminal, unable to pay the money, had no hope of escape from perpetual banishment. At this juncture the faultless young man ap peared and said to the judge: "I am ready to take the place of my condemned kinsman. Lay on me the penalty, be it what it may." The judge informed the faultless young man that the law would not permit any one to be banished as a substitute for the criminal, but that the other branch of the penalty might be assumed by another. Whereupon the thou sand talents were paid by the faultless young 12 178 Atonement Reviewed. man. " The culprit was not banished. The kinsman proved to be the heir of an im mense estate, and his poor friend, who so narrowly escaped perpetual banishment, be came a joint heir with him to that vast inher itance." (Pp. 161-63.) (I think every essential is included in this abbreviated statement.) Here we have the supposititious facts stu diously framed to fit the case. Now the application: 1. This righteous judge represents God, the righteous lawgiver. 2. The law represents his will. 3. The prodigal represents the sinner — all sinners. 4. The " thousand talents, or perpetual ban ishment," represents an alternative penalty. 5. The faultless young man represents the substitute, who is assumed to bear an equiva lent penalty. Mr. Armour is evidently much pleased with his invention. He seems to re gard it as both proof and illustration of his scheme of " substitution and equivalent pen alty," and hence, occasionally refers to it in the subsequent part of his discussion. I, however, have somewhat against it. 1. Civil law very rarely prescribes penalty with an alternative. But if it always did so, Equivalent Penalty. 179 this would be absolutely nothing to the ques tion at issue. We are not discussing human but divine law. God's ways are not as our ways. If Mr. Armour had only been considerate enough to furnish from God's word just one instance — only one — of an alternative penalty in the sphere of moral retribution it would have been of immense service to inquirers after truth. Instead of doing this most reasonable and desirable thing he puts them off, much to their disappointment, with a glowing picture of his fertile imagination. Why is Mr. Armour so unaccommodating? Why, when the child asks bread, does he give a stone? fictions for facts? ideals for realities? The history of all the past can not furnish a solitary example of an equivalent penalty in the sphere of divine law; but imagination can idealize them by scores!!! "In the day thou eatest thereof thou (not somebody else) shalt surely die." What would be the equivalent of this death? "The soul that sinneth it (not another) shall die." Who can name the equivalent? " To be car nally-minded is death." Where is the equiva lent? " The wages of sin is death." If Mr. Armour had only thought to give us this 180 Atonement Reviewed. equivalent of spiritual death, who knows but that it might supersede the necessity of any atonement at all? It no doubt would if it should not happen to be like some of his sub stitutions — impossible in its conditions. Parenthetically, it is of little consequence, but is it strictly true, that if a man suffers the alternative of a penalty fixed by law that he suffers the equivalent of the penalty? Does he not suffer the penalty itself, and not an equivalent of it? Mr. Armour thinks not, and that settles it. 2. The kinsman, ..." the heir to an im mense estate," who is he, and what of him? He represents the Lord Jesus Christ, who is both God and man. Then, does he, as God or as man, become the substitute of the elect, and suffer in their stead? According to Mr. Armour, it was as God that Christ became the substitute of men. This he assumes to be true when he represents the substitute as "the Almighty One," as previously noticed; also when he says (p. 176): "The infinitude, the divinity of Christ, and this alone, furnishes grounds for believing that he rendered perfect satisfaction to the law." Here it is distinctly admitted that Christ, as man, could not satisfy the law for others. But his assumed satisfac tory obedience to law as a substitute for oth- Equivalent Penalty. 181 ers is expressly referred to his infinitude, to his divinity. When Mr. Armour teaches that Christ, as man, could not render obedi ence to the law for others, he teaches the simple truth. But he did as man, born of a woman, keep the law, and if he could not keep it for others, then he, of course, kept it for himself. But when he teaches that Christ, as God, or because of his infinitude, or of his divinity, obeyed the law for others, he teaches essen tial error. For exactly in the sense in which he was a substitute for others did he obey the law for others; hence, if he as divine was a substitute for others, then he as divine was obedient unto death, even the death of the cross; as divine he suffered, shed his blood, died on the cross, lay in the grave, and rose the third day. Mr. Armour, bold as he is, would not be willing to admit such results, though they inhere in his scheme of substitu tion. These two indubitable facts — first, that Christ, as man, could not fulfill the law for all men, and secondly, that he, as God, could not be born, suffer, die, etc. — demonstrate the im possibility of his fulfilling the law as a substi tute for others in any sense. Mr. Armour seems unconscious of the fatal predicament in which he places himself when 182 Atonement Reviewed. he makes Christ, as divine, the heir to the im mense estate, because, this amounts simply to saying God is the heir of God. An equally great absurdity is involved in his saying that the poor prodigal " became a joint heir with him to that vast estate." Joint heirship im plies equality of nature among the heirs. If Christ, as divine, is the heir, then the poor prodigal, in becoming a joint heir, of necessi ty became divine. Can Mr. Armour stand the consequences of his substitution and equivalent penalty? If so, contradictions are not impossible of belief. The plain teaching of the Bible is, that Christ, as human, is the heir, and those that believe in him are the joint heirs. Hence, he is called " the first-born among many breth ren." But if he, as divine, is the heir of God or of himself, then it follows of necessity that all joint heirs are divine. The stronghold of Mr. Armour is mystery. He says (p. 175): "How Christ could fully satisfy the claims of law, endure 'in strict rigor of justice the unrelaxed penalty of the law ' in his person, must be to all created in telligences for evermore a mystery as incom prehensible as that of creation itself." In this I fully concur, and deem it something more difficult to comprehend what does not Equivalent Penalty. 1S3 exist than that which is known to exist. But I question Mr. Armour's right to call a con tradiction a mystery, and ask us to believe it as something incomprehensible. He continues: "When we deal with the infinite, it is the mysterious and the incom prehensible that is credible." Facts often compel us to believe things in themselves in comprehensible. But we never believe a thing because it is incomprehensible. That is a mystery. But contradictions are incapable of rational belief. Certainly, it is not the in finite that is incredible, but Mr. Armour's substitution. Can I not believe in the infinite without believing in our author's substitution? Is one involved in the other? If not, why at tempt to excuse the enormities of one by an appeal to the mysteries of the other? In Mr. Armour's studied, hypothetical case, what the faultless young man did for the prod igal was not done as a penal substitute, but purely as a benefactor. He was not a crim inal in any sense. He paid no penalty, for none was imposed upon him by the court, and no man can impose one upon himself; for what is self-imposed, or voluntarily assumed, is not a penalty. To call the voluntary pay ment, the thousand talents, a penalty is an un- 184 Atonement Reviewed. pardonable abuse of terms. It was purely a benefaction to the prodigal. No two words need to be more sharply discriminated than are the words benefaction and penalty. (1) Benefaction is always voluntary, never necessary — that is, if an act is voluntary it is not penal. But, as we have previously seen, no penalty is voluntary. Benefaction and necessity exclude each other. So penalty and voluntariness exclude one the other. If one could be hung, at his own urgent request, in the place of another, it would not be penalty, but pure benefaction. To confound words so radically different excludes the possibility of clear and exact statements on any subject. According to Mr. Armour's method of put ting things, if a man pulls a thorn out of a dog's foot he is a substitute for the dog, and, of course, in some way pays the penalty of his mishap. We might say he is a benefac tor, not a penalty-sufferer. (2) Benefaction is honorable — at least not disreputable. But penalty for the violation of just law is dishonorable, infamous. (3) Benefaction is a blessing — a double good — a blessing to the benefactor, because it is more blessed to give than to receive; a blessing to the beneficiary, because it is in Equivalent Penalty. 185 some way helpful and pleasing. But penalty is in itself no good to anybody, but the reverse of all good. It is evil, and only evil. The utmost that can be expected from it is that it may be the means of preventing subsequent lawlessness, and its consequent evils. What an unpardonable misuse of words is it in Mr. Armour to parade the benefaction of the faultless young man, to the amount of a thou sand talents for the relief of his kinsman, as a penalty ! Or, if Mr. Armour is right, then the most of the good that comes to men in this world comes in the form of penalties. The more and greater the penalties a man suffers, the more good he does, the happier he be comes. The angels, too, those generous min isters to the heirs of salvation, are penalty payers for men. Pretty dream! but alas! when we wake we learn that penalty is the stern retribution of violated law, or the fire of God's indignation in the lawless human soul. Enough for the present. SECTION XIII. RELAXATION OF LAW AND SELF-CON DEMNATION. OUR author has an irrepressible antipa thy to all "relaxation of law," "wav ing of penalty," etc., "by sovereign preroga tive." He indicates the errors of others, and reprobates the concessions made by his prede cessors of the substitution school. No writer seems to be sufficiently anti-relaxationist to satisfy him. He seems emulous of the high distinction of being the extremist of extrem ists on this subject. In opposition to all he has to say on this point, I have no protest to offer. I should not choose to express myself in all cases as he does. But the idea of sav ing sinners by relaxation of law, or by setting aside the divinely ordained penalty, is contrary alike to reason and revelation. But while he properly insists that all the requirements of the law shall be f illy met in the matter of human salvation, he, I think, has not the faintest conception of the true method by which these law claims are met. But the (186) Relaxation of Law. 187 object of the present discussion is the consid eration of Mr. Armour's theory of salvation, and not the presentation of an adverse theory. If some of the old orthodox substitutionists, such as Turretini, and others, had the privi lege of replying to Mr. Armour's criticisms of their sins in the matter of " relaxation by sov ereign prerogative," they might very perti nently and sharply say, " Physician, heal thy self," or, " He that lives in a glass house should not throw stones." I have read no author holding that the atone ment satisfies moral law in any proper sense who goes, to my thinking, further in the direc tion of relaxation than Mr. Armour. In fact, he seems to relax law in every conceivable vital aspect of it, except as to the bare amount of what it claims to be due. The law in his hands remorselessly demands the last pound of flesh, but seems by no means scrupulous as to whose flesh it is, or who pays it, or what kind it is. The following instances of relaxation, or variation, are observable; some of which I have previously noticed: 1. Our author relaxes the moral law on its beneficent side as to exclude a part of the human race from the possibility of salvation. Christ was born of a woman, born under 188 Atonement Reviewed. the law to redeem them that are under the law. Mr. Armour, by some sort of secret and special covenant engagement between the Fa ther and the Son, released Christ from the law, so far as to redeem a par! only of those under the law whom he come to redeem. This has been previously more fully explained. A false faith that tends to deaden the sym pathies of the human soul for our fellow-men is worse than a false faith of the contrary ten dencies. 2. According to Mr. Armour's exposition of law it requires the instant re-instatement to happy obedience of all for whom satisfaction has been made. But the law is so relaxed or modified, or is so lax in its execution, that all for whom satisfaction has been rendered are denied rightful re-instatement for a longer or shorter period of time, and some for scores of years, all the while sinning and suffering be cause their dues have not been given them. Illustrated by the thief who was crucified with Christ. Our author's apology for this deflec tion, or delinquency of law, is that "time is for us," but not for justice or God. To this dereliction of law (if this is the right word) is due all the sins and sufferings of the elect in this world. Query: If law can withhold its dues for a Relaxation of Law. 189 score of years, may it not for ten score? Or, if for a day, why not forever? 3. According to Mr. Armour substitution involves double imputation. The legal status of the criminal is transferred to the substitute, and that of the innocent substitute is trans ferred to the criminal. Now, this is palpable relaxation, or rather abrogation, of the whole law as to the person of the criminal. Christ having become the sub stitute of the elect, both as to precept and as to penalty, they are in no sense the subjects of law, though they may be thieves, liars, murderers, etc. Such is the theory. (This is not the doctrine of the Bible. Even those who believe in Christ are not released from obligation to the law in the sense that they are not required to love God and their neighbor, much less are all for whom Christ died released from authority of law.) Still it is claimed that the law received all its claims as to quantity of obedience in the person of the substitute, and is therefore fully satisfied. This assumes that law exists for its own sake, and not for the sake of its subjects. Such a release from law, if it were possible, would be a calamity, and not a benefaction. This may be readily seen. All good in the physical world comes from obedience to law, 190 Atonement Reviewed. and all ill from disobedience. It is equally true that the good that necessarily comes of obedience, comes directly to those that obey; and the evils that come from disobedience come directly to those that disobey. Mr. Armour's philosophy seems to deny this proposition, and makes evil (at least for the present) come to the obedient substitute, and perpetual good comes to the disobedient principal. But in this it separates effects from their causes, and makes evil the consequence of obedience, and good the consequence of disobedience. Another result of this theory, not less ab surd, is the following: If good comes necessarily from obedience, and comes directly to the obedient alone, then the substitute realizes all this good, and those for whom he is a substitute realizes none of it; for only those that obey are blessed. The converse of this proposition is true in the principal and substitute on the penal side of law. It is, hence, clearly apparent that substitu tion not only relaxes the law in regard to the person of the principal, but deprives him of all the good that comes from obedience and concentrates all the evils, the natural conse quences of disobedience, upon the substitute. Relaxation of Law. 191 To say that such fantastic tricks are normal in law — are normally provided for in law — is simply a burlesque on law. 4. Our author also relaxes the law in the matter of his " equivalent penalty." This is too plain to be possible of concealment. The re ward of obedience grows naturally, inevitably out of obedience, and the penalty of disobe dience comes inevitably out of disobedience. The reward of loving God is the bliss that comes of loving him, and the penalty of not loving him is the negation of that bliss and its concomitants. These facts, it is presumed, none that can reason at all will think of deny ing. How, then, is a substituted equivalent penalty possible? Nothing short of a change of the law of cause and effect can make a sub stituted equivalent penalty possible. 5. Our author relaxes the law by substitut ing a temporary for a perpetual or continuous obedience. Obedience and reward we know to be related as cause and effect. So of dis obedience and penalty. It is equally certain that cause and effect are co-existent and co terminous. But Mr. Armour sets aside this invariable characteristic of the law of cause and effect by affirming a temporary (momentary it may be) cause and a perpetual effect — that is, 192 Atonement Reviewed. Christ's one act of temporary obedience as a substitute forever secures to the elect the re wards of obedience. Hence, we have a tem porary obedience and a perpetual reward, or an effect without a co-existent cause. To reach this result, our author is under the necessity of assuming that this obedience was rendered by an infinite power who could in a brief space of time render both a preceptive and penal obedience equivalent to the obe dience of all the elect through all eternity. But, in making this assumption, he also as sumes that Christ as God obeyed his own law as a substitute for the elect. The monstrous consequences of this assumption have been sufficiently indicated. Mr. Armour's refuge from such monstrosi ties is of course mystery. "When we deal with the infinite it is the mysterious, and the comprehensible that is credible." If these several positions are well taken, Mr. Armour is a relaxationist of the first wa ter. In fact, he sets aside well-nigh all real law, and gives us in lieu a code of monstrous fiction. SECTION XIV. SURETYSHIP AND COVENANT ENGAGE- MENT. M' R. ARMOUR gives us an elaborate dis cussion of suretyship. He gives a quotation from an unnamed author which gives us a pretty clear insight into his theory. It is as follows (p. 191): "Suretyship is a relation constituted by covenant engagement by which parties be come Legally One, and can be dealt with as such in Law, each individual of the Unit be ing bound injustice to suffer for the Unit, if necessary ; but the stffering is not the suffer ing of a part, but of the whole, in law, '¦Be cause we thus jtidge that if one died for all then all died."1 " Remarks. — 1. This unit, let it be remem bered, is purely a legal fiction for special tem porary purposes. To it there is absolutely nothing analogous in moral law. 2. Christ, as God or divine, never came under law by covenant engagement, or oth- 13 (r93) 194 Atonement Reviewed. erwise — as man he was " born under the law? These facts have been sufficiently established. 3. Supposing all the extravagant things said by Mr. Armour in regard to suretyship in the sphere of human law should be granted, they are not worth a farthing as illustrations of the Bible doctrine of atonement. 4. Christ is nowhere represented in the Bible as the surety of all for whom he suf fered, but as the surety only of those that be lieve in him. The Scriptures plainly teach that some for whom he died will perish be cause they will not have the man Christ Jesus to reign over them. 5. The gravest objection to the quotation just given is its unpardonable perversion of 2 Cor. v. 14: "Because we thus judge that if one died for all, then all died." Our author assumes that when Christ died on the cross, all those for whom he died did, by virtue of special covenant engagement, die legally unto sin, Christ having by his death adjusted all legal claims against them. This is an utter perversion of the text as might be demonstrated in numerous ways. The context utterly disallows it. Paul teach es the same important truth here that he teaches Rom. v. 6-10, Rom. vi. 1—4, Eph. ii. 1. If our author's application of 2 Cor. v. Covenant Engagement. 195 14 is the true one, then there is only small difference, at least in this life, between being dead to sin and dead in sin, and the atone ment is a nondescript legal myth rather than " the power of God unto salvation to every one that believeth." SECTION XV. ATONEMENT A VARIABLE QUANTITY. ONE of the most remarkable characteris tics of Mr. Armour's atonement is that it seems to have no fixed or distinct nature of its own. Proteus like, now it is one thing, now it is something else; now it is something in the place of- — instead of; now it is some thing on account of, in the interest of, in be half of for the sake of; now it is substitution, involving as its essential elements double im putation — an exact reversion of the legal states of substitute and principal; now it is no more than generous benefaction, differing not in kind but in degree only from what one man, good or bad, may do for another. Now, this is truly a grave charge, and if true Mr. Armour's atonement dissolves into thin air. Let us see if this is true. His doctrine as generally stated, involves a change of places in law between the substi tute and the principal, or, as he calls it, " double imputation." I submit a few quota tions. (196) Atonement a Variable Quantity. 197 He says: " To satisfy the law the obedience and sufferings of Christ must fully insure the re-instatement and restoration to obedience of his redeemed." " Suretyship that does not necessitate the re-instatement of him in whose behalf it is undertaken is fatally de fective." " Re-instatement is necessitated by, and virtually included in, all real atonement." " Christ's suretyship is perfect, satisfies law, satisfies conscience .... because it insures the perfect re-instatement of the sinner." " This very re-instatement is itself part of, and an essential part of suretyship, true and full satisfaction of law." Much more to the same effect might, but need not, be given. This is substitution in the most exact and rigid form conceivable. It is purely an affair of law. Whatever feeling or motive may prompt the individual to become a substitute for an other, the discharge of the duties of the sub stitute is exclusively a matter of law, is obe dience, suffering, etc., in the place of, and not suffering or benefaction on account of, or for the sake of. Having read Mr. Armour's statements con cerning the obligations of the substitute to obey law, both preceptively and penally, and 193 Atonement Reviewed. the necessitated re-instatement of the princi pal, his attempt to identify substitution with benefaction, charity, etc., awakens no slight degree of surprise. Certainly it would wonderfully strengthen his cause if he could successfully identify these things so radically different. Mr. Armour is a shrewd strategist. We have previously seen his bold attempt, for strategic purposes, to identify objective and subjective law — law in commandment and law written upon the heart. He rightly deems that his scheme of substitutionary atonement will be wonderfully assisted, its extravagances, its impossibilities, its inherent deformities measurably mitigated if he can ally it with all benefaction, all charity. The prize is worth the effort, and he boldly makes it. He quotes Paul to Galatians (chap. vi. 2): " Bear ye one another's burdens, and so fulfill the law of Christ," and proceeds to identify Christian charity and benefaction with sub stitution. He says (p. 204), "What Christ does for those whom he redeems and saves differs not in its nature, but only in extent, from that which is required of all in befriending and helping those who are in trouble and in Atonement a Variable Quantity. 199 need." "In fact (p. 205), whatsoever is done for another in the way of charity is done in his place and as his substitute. Substitution true and proper enters into the ordinary acts of brotherly kindness between friends and neighbors. . . . To say that law sets a limit to substitution, is to say that it forbids the utmost helpfulness." "Job (p. 206) sums up his life of benevolence and charity, and sets forth at the same time the true nature of all charitable deeds when he says: lLwas eyes to the blind, feet was I to the lame? The reader will remember that substitution involves in every possible case double impu tation — assumption of obligation on the part of the substitute necessitates exemption from obligation on the part of the principal. Is this true in all or in any case of benefac tion or alms-giving? Does the benefactor assume the obligations or take the place of the beneficiary, and the beneficiary the place of the benefactor? No sane man, I think, would say so, unless the exigencies of a the ory xequired it. Was Job, when he was eyes to the blind, himself blind; and did the blind have eyes? When feet to the lame, was he without feet? and were the feetless footed? I put these ridiculous questions only because Mr. Armour's absurdities require them. 200 Atonement Reviewed. Job, in being eyes to the blind, and feet to this lame neighbor, simply discharged his duty to his neighbor, but did. not discharge his neighbor's duty. He loved his neighbor, but happily he did not do his neighbor's lov ing. How cruel that would have been! All happiness in heaven and earth comes of lov ing. To be deprived of eyes or feet is a great calamity, but not to love (love is the fulfilling of the law), or to have another to love in our place, is immensely worse. Per dition itself is no worse, for not to love is perdition itself. Job was a benefactor to the blind and to the lame, but he was not a substitute in any sense. He obeyed law for himself and for others' sake, but not in their stead. If atonement is substitution, and substitu tion is benefaction, then it seems that all di vine benefactions are substitutionary. The Father of lights, from whom cometh every good and perfect gift, is the universal atoner or substitute. Wherein do his substitution ary acts differ from those of the Son? If benefaction is substitution, and the Father is a universal benefactor, sending rain upon the just and upon the unjust, and the Son is a substitute for a part of mankind only, is there not conflict and confusion in the divine work? Atonement a Variable Quantity. 201 If substitution or benefaction necessitates the re-instatement of beneficiaries, will all or only a part of mankind be saved? By confounding substitution and benefac tion, Mr. Armour has evidently involved his atonement in utter darkness, or rather resolved it into no atonement at all. This rash attempt to confound benefaction, substitution, and atonement is, to say the least that can fairly be said, an unpardonable abuse of terms. Benefaction, as we have previously seen, has distinct characteristics of its own. This I have previously indicated. Mr. Armour's substitution, as we have seen, is also distinct ly characterized — nothing like it in heaven or earth — the guilt and punishment of the diso bedient becomes voluntarily the property of the obedient; and the innocence and blessed ness of the obedient become the involuntary property of the guilty. Atonement, too, is neither substitution, in any proper sense, nor is it ordinary benefac tion. If our author had said that atonement, con sidered as something done in the interest of another, is a species or form of benefaction — of benefaction of the highest conceivable value — no serious objection would lie against his proposition. But to identify benefaction and substitution, involving; double imputation, 202 Atonement Reviewed. is to take all benefit out of benefaction and render it absolutely worthless; for the simple reason, as has been intimated, that substitu tion, in Mr. Armour's sense of the term, is itself absolutely worthless. It in no sense increases the sum of happiness in the moral world. For if Christ "obeys the penalty" in my place, then he endures all the unhappiness due to me, and the sum of happiness is not increased. But if he obeys the precept of the law in my stead, then to him comes the blessedness, and I am, of necessity, deprived of the blessedness that comes from obedience. But the absence .of this blessedness, or my deprivation of it, is exactly the penalty of disobedience. Here, then, is of necessity a double penalty. Or, if Christ's obedience to both precept and penalty restores me to actual obedience, then the law receives a double obedience, first from the substitute, and then from the principal. In view of these facts, it appears that if our author can establish a complete identity be tween benefaction and substitution, then he will prove that benefaction is no benefaction at all, but a positive evil rather than a good. Our author, in seeking to identify benefac tion, charity, helpfulness, etc., with substitu tion, has fairly renounced the fundamental principles of his theory. SECTION XVI. INTERVENTION. OUR author closes his marvelous book, Atonement and Law, with a chapter on " Intervention." By this intervention he means the interposition of Christ as the penal preceptive substitute of the elect in relation to the moral law. The following quotations will sufficiently indicate his singular conceptions of the man ner in which law is dealt with or satisfied. He says (p. 215): "The hope of deliver ance for those exposed to evil or danger from the power of law, whether natural or moral, is not that the law shall be suspended, relaxed, or turned aside from its aim, or its penalties in any way mitigated or modified, but that there shall be, in some way, intervention of ade quate power operating in a way to meet the force of law." Again (p. 216): "Nature everywhere sug gests, and Scripture everywhere plainly and abundantly reveals, the one only door of hope. It is the intervention of power or means ade quate to deal with law, meet its force and (2°3) 204 Atonement Reviewed. thus protect and deliver those exposed to evil." Again (p. 217): "The one only way of de liverance is by intervention of power ade quate to deal with law, meeting its full force." These statements are made in reference to law in general; but he proceeds to apply his universal principle to the intervention of Christ. Thus "The Great Atonement is in exact ac cordance with the one only way of deliver ance from the power of violated law, as taught throughout the entire kingdom of Nature and Providence — viz.: Intervention of power, adequate to deal with law and deliver the exposed." Again (p. 218): "Intervention is the act of powers or persons themselves under law, and is performed under and in accordance with law. It is not and can not be the direct and mere act of the Lawgiver. This is taught in Nature and in Providence, but especially in Redemption, in that God himself, when he would rescue those exposed to evil, sent his own Son, ' made under the law.' " Remarks. — 1. In these quotations Mr. Ar mour speaks of law as a force scarcely less than omnipotent. He seems to array force against force, law against law, and Omnipo- Intervention. 205 tence against Omnipotence. But does he give his readers any definite or intelligible idea of how deliverance comes by the intervention of adequate power? Is the reader not startled rather than instructed? Evidently vehemence and vagueness of utterance are not mutually exclusive. 2. These expressions, taken apart from others, would seem to mean relaxation, modi fication, abrogation, or vanquishment of law. He also says (p. 219): "Law triumphs over law and honors the law over which it tri umphs." Here, it seems, law grapples law in mortal conflict, and law is the victor and law is the vanquished — both omnipotent; for he says (p. 68): "Infinite power confessedly insures the inviolability of every .natural law." Yet one seems stronger than the other. But the victor honors the vanquished. This may be a becoming courtesy to vanquished law, but how, I do not understand. It seems very much as if Omnipotence was in conflict with itself. In all earnestness, I do not know what our author means. I can conceive of a phenomenon as the result of a single force, and of phenomenon as a resultant of two or more forces, but have not been able to under stand how one law or force can triumph over another law. This seems to smack of abro- 206 Atonement Reviewed. gation of law. But relaxation, in Mr. Ar mour's estimation, is the sum of all evils. We must, therefore, allow that he does not mean to teach what his language seems to teach. I presume what our author really means by such expressions as " power adequate to deal with law, meeting its full force," "to deal with law and deliver the exposed," or guilty from penalty; and " Law triumphs over law," is simply a power adequate to suffer the pen alty of law, and by this means satisfy law, and thus deliver the guilty. He formulates this idea, and attaches to it all the authority of an axiom, thus: "The one only source of danger — Violated Law. The one only source of deliverance — The satis faction of Law." To the first part of this proposition there is no serious objection. The latter part merits unmitigated condemnation. " The only source of deliverance — The satisfaction of Law ? " Our author expresses much the same thing when he personifies law and makes it say, " Pay what thou owest. Penalty first, then Obedience to precept." Others put it after this order: "No punishment, no pardon? The conceit seems to be an old superstition of the Dark Ages, revised and elaborated into another form, as follows: Intervention. 207 Satan, by fraud, captured mankind, who, by this method, became in some real sense the lawful property of his satanic majesty. To dispossess him of his captives without the payment of an equivalent value would be to defraud him of his rights, or would be a viola tion of justice. Hence, to satisfy or meet the demands of justice, a ransom must be paid to Satan. In the light of this superstition, Christ is made to suffer to satisfy justice in the in terest of the prince of darkness. This theory had more or less currency among theologians up to the eleventh or twelfth century, when the claims of Satan came to be denied, and a false conception of justice and penalty of law was made to take his place. Herce, the suf ferings of Christ are represented as a payment to justice, a satisfaction to law, and the law is represented as demanding the payment of penalty — the obedience to penalty — and as be ing satisfied by the suffering of punishment. Hence, no punishment, no pardon. "Penalty first, then Obedience to precept." " The one only way of deliverance — The satisfaction of Law." The figment in the last analysis re- , duces to this. That effects have powers over their causes or power to remove their causes; hence that pandemonium may be expected sooner or later to become " a land uninhabited." 2o8 Atonement Reviewed. If sin is a debt, what the law or the creditor lequires, what satisfies law or the creditor is the payment of debt, and not the penalty or consequences of not paying. The penalty sat isfies nothing, neither creditor nor justice; and justice, instead of being satisfied with the non-payment, is actually defrauded of its dues. Accordingto Mr. Armour, the consequences or penalties of not paying a debt is a satisfac tion of jusfice. The creditor, however, is not likely to be satisfied with this view of justice or law. According to the theory, "obedience to penalty," is more meritorious, more powerful than obedience to precept. It is, perhaps, always easier to get into trouble than to get out. It requires more skill or power to cure a disease than to prevent it. Obedience to precept keeps men out of death, but obe dience to penalty, according to our author, restores the dead to life. If obedience to pen alty, by a substitute, restores the principal to spiritual life, of course the payment of the penalty by the principal must have the same effect. Hence, if Christ, by paying the pen alty of the law, as a substitute for the elect, brings them out of spiritual death, the repro bate will come out by virtue of his own penal Intervention. 209 obedience. Certainly his robe of righteous ness will not be overly bright and clean, being nothing but a penal righteousness. But he will have the consolation of knowing that it is made of the same stuff as that of his elect brother, and is every way as good. He will also have the additional satisfaction of know ing that he is the artificer of his own fortune. To this merit his elect brother of course can set up no claim. Such the consequences of the Armourian philosophy. We have previously seen how Mr. Armour seeks to free himself from this propension of his theory to universalism — that is, by asserting a distinction between a voluntary and an invol untary obedience to penalty. We have also seen the insufficiency of this strategy to save him from universalism; for the simple but all- sufficient reason that no voluntary act can be a penal act, or voluntariness necessarily ex cludes penalty. 3. Mr. Armour's salvation by adequate power is as unsatisfying to the reason as is his postulate that " Law triumphs over law," or his dictum concerning the satisfaction of penalty. But what power is this which is " adequate to deal with law, meeting its full force," and then " protect and deliver those exposed 14 210 Atonement Reviewed. to evil?" We are told that it is the power of the " Mighty One, the Almighty One." We have previously seen the absurdity of putting the Almighty One under law, and of making him the penal and preceptive substi tute of men. Mr. Armour attempts to escape this absurdity by a fictitious distinction, or a distinction without a difference. He says: "It (intervention) is not and can not be the direct and mere act of the Lawgiver." What he means is the Father is the Lawgiver, and the Son comes under the law and obeys unto death as a substitute for men. The Son, as man, confessedly could not become this sub stitute. Hence, this Son, as God, becomes the substitute. Still, we are required to be lieve that intervention " is not and can not be the direct and mere act of the Lawgiver," or that one Almighty One gives law, and another Almighty One obeys law, as a substitute for men; or God, as Father, gives law, and God, as Son, obeys law. Mr. Armour seems to have some misgiving in denying that " intervention " is the act of the Lawgiver; hence, he cautiously qualifies this act. " It is not . . . the direct and mere act of the Lawgiver." This may bring some relief to Mr. Armour's mind, but unfortunately none to the trouble in Intervention. 211 hand. It raises a little fog, which may some what obscure the absurdity, but can not or- move it. A " direct and mere act of the Lwa- giver?" An act in the last analysis is a sim ple volition. Are there any indirect volitions? If not, then all acts are direct acts. So of mere acts. Is any act more or less than a mere act? Nothing needs to be clearer than this, if intervention is not a direct and mere act of the Lawgiver, then it is not his act at all, but the act of some other Almighty One. Then there must be a plurality of Almighty Ones. Mr. Armour can not find his power ade quate to deal with divine law in Christ as a man, nor in Christ as God. He is, therefore, under the necessity of finding it in the two natures so united as to constitute something neither human nor divine, but a sort of amal gam, a veritable tertium quid, which is, how ever, properly designated as "the Almighty One," who is capable of coming under law, obeying law in precept and penalty as a sub stitute for men. I forbear to trace the meta physical consequences of this view of the God- man. Its utter enormousness has been pre viously indicated. The method by which Mr. Armour and substitutionists generally deceive themselves 3i2 Atonement Reviewed. seems to be this: They allow that Christ is the God-man, and have learned to designate him as the second person in a union of three distinct personalities in the divine nature. Un der the specious guise of this distinct person ality, which is conceived of as infinite, they predicate of him impossible things — impossi ble, because contradictory. False or indis tinct conceptions of the word person, as ap plied to the Godhead, is largely responsible for these extravagances. If we choose to predicate three personali ties of the divine nature, and do not take the word person in a unique and nondescript sense — in a sense utterly exclusive of the will, which is the central attribute of person in its ordinary and proper sense, we are hopelessly involved in Tritheism. For if there are, in some unique and indefinable sense, three per sonalities in the divine nature, there are not certainly three wills, or if there are, then it is sun-clear that there are three Gods. This is exactly the metaphysical outcome of our author's doctrine: One Almighty One giving law and another Almighty One obey ing law. This is a logical affirmation of two Almighty wills, for the Almighty will that gives law is not the Almighty will that obeys law. It is not one Almighty One that gives Intervention. 213 law, and another Almighty One that is born of a woman, born under the law, suffers and dies. Such things are predicable of the God- man only as to his human nature. If these statements are even substantially true, it deserves to be noted that they sweep to the winds the much-paraded figment of a covenant engagement between the Father and the Son for the redemption of a part of man kind; said covenant engagement implying the existence of two distinct, independent wills. This is too plain to require elaboration or illus tration. These facts also disprove Mr. Ar mour's oft-reiterated affirmation that Christ, as a divine personality, voluntarily came un der law. The sum of the truth on that sub ject is that the divine nature, or God, volun tarily allied himself with humanity, and was, as to this humanity, born of a woman, and was born under the law as are all other men. The voluntariness was all on the divine side, and none on the human side. The human alone is under law, and not the divine in any sense; else there are two divine wills, or two Gods, one giving and one obeying law. These facts also demonstrate with utmost clearness that Mr. Armour's scheme of sub stitution is an utter impossibility. The God- man, as man alone was under law, and as man 214 Atonement Reviewed. could obey law for himself alone; as God he was not under law, because he is the Law giver, and can not both give and obey law as a substitute for men. But for the sheer assumption that Christ, by virtue of his divine nature, could and did, in some mysterious and incomprehensible manner, become the substitute for men, and actually suffer and die in their stead, the doc trine of substitution, of equivalent penalty, of plenary satisfaction, could not live an hour in a thoughtful mind. This unproved and unprovable assumption is the foundation — a foundation of quicksand — upon which the whole superstructure of substitutionary and penal salvation rests. 4. Mr. Armour's "intervention of power, or means adequate to deal with law and meet its force, and thus protect and deliver those exposed to evil," deserves, on account of an other aspect of it, a brief notice. What is this "power adequate to deal with law and meet its force?" Mr. Armour in forms us that it is "the Almighty One." What is this law with which the Almighty One deals, and whose force he meets? Mr. Armour gives the following answer: " They (natural and moral law) are both directly from the will of God. Infinite power Intervention. 215 confessedly insures the inviolability of every natural law. Infinite power sustains every moral law." (p. 68.) This suggests war among the gods. But the gods, however great, are not almighty ones — are less than omnipotent — not quite in finite. This conflict, too, is only ideal. But our author gives us a conflict, or a col lision, or a struggle between " the Almighty One " and a law which is " directly from the will of God," and is sustained by "infinite power." The conflict is not ideal, but is in tensely real. God dealing with his own law, which his infinite power sustains — God meeting the "force" of his own law to "protect and de liver those exposed " to the divinely appointed penalties of his own divinely sustained law! This seems to be something of a puzzle — the Almighty One seems somehow in conflict with himself, or with his law, which his infinite power sustains. " What meaneth this ? " Hard to say. The infinite is dealing with the infinite. The in finite is enforcing his own law upon the infinite. The Almighty One is dealing with his own law, " meeting its force," fulfilling its pre cepts, bearing its penalties, and satisfying all 216 Atonement Reviewed. its demands, as a substitute for lawless, guilty men? Even Mr. Armour does not quite under stand this marvel of marvels, but seems to believe it because he does not understand it. " When we deal with the infinite it is the mys terious and incomprehensible that is credible." Nothing is credible because it is mystery, but we believe a mystery because we can not be lieve a contradiction. Between these radi cally different things, mystery and contradic tion, Mr. Armour does not always distinguish. For the Almighty One to give law to men, and support it with infinite power, and yet for the Almighty One to come under that law, deal with it, meet its force, and deliver those who are exposed to its penalties, is a many- sided absurdity — as Omnipotence dealing with Omnipotence, Omnipotence meeting Omnip otence, Omnipotence delivering from Om nipotence, Omnipotence bearing the punish ment inflicted by Omnipotence, Omnipotence satisfying Omnipotence, Omnipotence tri umphing over Omnipotence, or one divine law over another divine law, both equally support ed by " infinite power." These flagrant contradictions Mr. Armour is pleased, with ineffable substitutionary satis faction, to call mysteries. From such mys- Intervention. 217 teries we should ever devoutly pray, " Good Lord deliver us! " Another ugly consequence of our author s theory may be indicated. I have previously noticed the fact that obe dience and good are, by divine and immuta ble law, related as cause and effect, and that whoever obeys receives the good. This must be as true of the substitute as it is of the prin cipal. If A loves God for himself, and aiso as a substitute for B, then he of necessity re ceives a double good or reward. Now, if the Almighty One could become a substitute for men; or, as a substitute love himself (love is the fulfilling of the law), then would he not receive an accession of good? or, in some un imaginable way, receive something he did not have before, and that by his own act? But this would seem. to be an addition to infinity; but infinity can not be more than infinite. My apology for writing such things is found in the revolting absurdity of making "the Almighty One" the substitute for men. SECTION XVII. ILLUSTRATIONS OF INTERVENTION. M1 "R. ARMOUR gives us a number of illustrations of deliverance by interven tion which merit brief attention. I. THE FALLING STONES AND CHILDREN. He says (pp. 218, 219): "Stones and rub bish from a lofty scaffolding are seen to com mence their fall to the ground. A group of children are beneath. Strong, brave men are the onlookers. . . . They place a shield over the defenseless heads, regardless of wounds and bruises to themselves. When this takes place no law is violated. Rather the scope and resources of law are unfolded. Law triumphs over law, and honors the law over which it triumphs." (Between the first and last part of this quotation our author gives us over a page of matter concerning "the unrelaxibility of law," and "modern thought," and other subjects, which have no vital connection with his illus tration.) (218) Illustrations of Intervention. 219 Remarks. — (1) I bring no railing accusa tion against that scaffolding for permitting those stones to fall, nor against the stones for falling, nor against those children for being in danger, nor against those strong, brave men for placing a shield over the defenseless, nor against Mr. Armour for using a fictitious illustration, for such illustrations are admissi ble when pertinent real ones are not available, provided they do not transcend the limits of possibility. But that against which I do protest is that our author should attempt to impose upon us this example as an illustration of his doctrine of deliverance from penal law by substitution ary intervention. It is not difficult to find the intervention, though it is not quite certain whether Mr. Armour means us to take the strong, brave men or the shield for the intervener — the shield was what literally intervened between the falling stones and defenseless heads. The point of extreme difficulty is to find any thing in the case answering to our author's substi tution involving double imputation. (2) If we attempt to find a substitute for defenseless heads in the shield, we are promptly put under inhibition by Mr. Ar mour's law imperatively requiring " volunta- 220 Atonement Reviewed. t'ariness" in the substitute. Besides, com mon sense requires us to say that the shield was a protection to the defenseless heads. A shield a substitute for heads! Mr. Armour does not, of course, mean that. (3) If we attempt to find the substitute in these strong, brave men, we have the requi site voluntariness, but the naked, hard facts utterly disallow any substitution. They did not take the place of the children, nor did the children take the place of the men in re lation to the falling stones — no imputation at all; not even single, much less double, as the theory imperatively requires. (4) Mr. Armour says in this case, " No law is violated. . . . Law triumphs over law." It is really difficult to see the harmony between these statements. It would seem that if one law triumphs over another, that one is in some way rather worsted, or crip pled, or vanquished. How can there be a triumph without a defeat, a victor without a vanquished party? It would have been some relief if Mr. Armour had given us the name of the triumphant law, and also that of the untriumphant, or vanquished. It would also be gratifying to know how, or in what sense, a law over which another law triumphs can be a satisfied law? Illustrations of Intervention. 221 (5) According to the facts in this imaginary case, these strong, brave men were benefac tors, not substitutes in any sense — saviors of the children, if we chose so to express our selves. These strong men obeyed no law, dis charged no duty that devolved upon the children. They simply obeyed law, or dis charged duty, imposed upon them by divine laws — duty to God, to the children, and to themselves. But they did not save by substitution or equivalent penalty. Nor did Christ ever save a sinner by any such impractical method. Substitution, as we have seen, with its inva riable double imputation, would have killed outright these strong, brave men unless their heads had been too hard for those falling stones. And even in this event substitution would have failed of its requirements, because the penalty to which the children were ex posed was simply death, and nothing short of death could satisfy the law. Mr. Armour has wonderful aptitude in making distinctions where none exist, and of confounding things rffdically different. To confound benefaction with substitution is simply an unpardonable abuse of terms, and is, withal, an utter abandonment of substitu- 222 Atonement Reviewed. tion involving double imputation, which is the essential characteristic of his scheme. 2. THE WIND AND THE SHORN LAMB. Mr. Armour administers nearly two and a half pages of rather caustic rebuke to certain poetic theologists who are wont to temper the wind to the shorn lamb. He says (pp. 219, 220): "God tempers the wind to the shorn lamb? By direct inter ference with the fierce law that governs the wintry storm? God tempers the wind to the shorn lamb ? Sentiment, mere sentiment unsup ported by a solitary shred of evidence. I beg pardon of those sweet souls whose philoso phy of redemption, whose system of theology, whose creed, beginning and end of it, is sim ply this: 'God tempers the wind to the shorn lamb.' I ask, What god? Assuredly not the God who rules this world. Let there be a 'scientific test,' a test by the thermometer. On the bleak hill top let the shorn lamb stand side by side with the unshorn. Ah! your poetic fancy is driven as chaff before the wind. Proclaim it in this world, proclaim it in all worlds. God does not temper the wind to the shorn lamb. That is Satan's theology, the same he taught in Eden: ' Ye shall not surely die.' It is not in accordance with Illustrations of Intervention. 223 Scripture, with man's experience and obser vation; it is not simply nonsense, it is a decep tive and ruinous error. The shepherd who should accept this as his creed could not be called ' the good shepherd.' The good shep herd is not, must not be, a fool." Remarks. — (1) All this vehement invect ive against those who express their faith in a gracious providence by the use of the familiar proverb, " God tempers the wind to the shorn lamb," is not only gratuitous, but an unpar donable injustice. By taking in a strictly literal sense lan guage intended by those who use it to be taken in a tropical sense, Mr. Armour manu factures " a man of straw," a pure vacuity, which he finds himself quite able to demolish. Those who use the proverb do not mean that the rise and fall of the mercury are de termined by the amount of wool a lamb may chance to have, or that God adjusts the tem perature of the wind to the condition of the lamb. They rather mean that the condition of the lamb is adjusted to the temperature of the wind. They do not mean to assert the relaxation of law, or the inutility of means, or any thing of the kind. The reader may be a little surprised to find 224 Atonement Reviewed. our author guilty of the identical sin which he charges against those who use the proverb which he calls the theology of Satan. He says (p. 221): "He (the brave shepherd) bat tles with, and so far as the lamb is concerned, vanquishes the storm, rescues its victim, wards off its fierce blasts." This is in every aspect a more extravagant and therefore more objectionable expression than the proverb, " God tempers the wind to the shorn lamb." According to the proverb, " God tempers the wind" so far as the shorn lamb is con cerned. According to our author, " the brave Shepherd," the Almighty One, battles with the storm — the storm which is but the on-going force of his own law sustained by " infinite power." The proverb says " tem per the wind to the shorn lamb." Mr. Ar mour vehemently protests, calls this Satan's theology, and says "battles with, and van quishes the storm, rescues its victim, wards off the fierce blasts." As to terminology, I somewhat prefer that of the proverb to that of Mr. Armour. Of course I do not mean that I prefer Satan to Mr. Armour, but sim ply prefer his way of putting things — that is, if he teaches that " God tempers the wind to the shorn lamb." Illustrations of Intervention. 225 But is it not possible that Mr. Armour is mistaken when he says of this proverb that it is " Satan's theology, the same he taught in Eden?" How does Mr. Armour know this? Has he had any private communication on the subject? I myself have learned from a sor rowful experience that " His Plutonic High ness " has no great respect for the ninth com mandment. Our common mother, too, had a sad experience of the same kind. But I am indebted to our author for the information that Satan has a theology, a part of which is that " God tempers the wind to the shorn lamb." Satan said to our overcredulous moth er, "Thou shalt not surely die." Because this utterance was false, and because Mr. Ar mour thinks the proverb, " God tempers," etc., is false, he therefore feels at liberty to call it "Satan's theology." Well, if it is Satan's theology, is it not Mr. Armour's also? The proverb says God tempers the wind, etc. Mr. Armour says the Almighty One battles with the storm, vanquishes the storm, wards off the fierce blasts of the storm. The reader can choose between Satan's theology, so called, and that of Mr. Armour. Happy is he that condemneth not himself, etc. (2) But the real point of interest in this case lies in another direction. Our author set *5 226 Atonement Reviewed. out to give us an illustration of deliverance by substitutionary intervention, but wittingly or unwittingly blinks the real issue, and gives us an illustration of deliverance by beneficent in tervention. Is Mr. Armour unwilling or un able to see what every body else can not fail to see, viz.: The radical difference between bene faction and substitution? He seems determined by his vehement and dogmatic declarations and reiterations, to compel his readers to take leave of common sense, so far at least as to admit that benefaction and substitution are identical. He might as well attempt to over turn the mountains as to blot out this distinc tion between benefaction and substitution with its double imputation. (3) Mr. Armour closes his labored disquisi tion on the wind and shorn lamb with the fol lowing sweeping assertion (p. 222): "Every theory of atonement save that which regards Christ as our substitute, meeting the full de mands of law, enduring its penalty, making a 'proper, real, and full satisfaction to God's justice,' is ruled out at once as fatally, foolish ly defective, delusive, deceptive." (4) If our author had said that he is igno rant as to how atonement could be made without substitution, his assertion would have been neither incredible nor arrogant. But Illustrations of Intervention. 227 what right has he to assume to know all the possible? Nothing but the contradictory is impossible with God. (5) The strength of his assertion lies wholly in its arrogant dogmatism. Not a particle of proof is given, or even attempted. On the contrary it has condemnation writ ten on its face. Thus "meeting the full de mands of the law, enduring its penalty." The law demands obedience, but obedience ex cludes the possibility of penalty. But penalty presupposes disobedience. Hence, if Christ as our substitute met the full demands of the law, then there could be no penalty to endure. But our very discriminating author makes him both meet the full demands of the law and en dure its penalty, which is clearly impossible. This has been previously noticed and needs nothing more. 3. THE WHEEL AND THE DYNAMO MACHINE. Our author gives two instances of the power of physical law. An immense wheel was in rapid motion. "A lad passing near by it, by a single mis step, fell against it, and was instantly hurled sheer across the immense building, and was taken uo moaning, mangled, bleeding, dy ing." 228 Atonement Reviewed. The other example is that of the man who grasped both rods of the thirty-light dynamo machine "and was dead." Mr. Armour seems to think that he is won derfully enlightening the world on the force and impartiality of law. Of course, the boy and the man were killed. But why? In brief, because they were not omnipotent, and, therefore, could not vanquish a force " sustained by infinite power." Was the wheel or the force or the law by which it was impelled satisfied when it killed the lad? or the dynamo machine when it killed the man? Of course the law was avenged, and, therefore^ quite satisfied. So the theory. I hesitate to make the suggestion, the thought is so preposterous and repulsive withal, but if Mr. Armour could have put the Almighty One as a substitute in the place of the boy or the man, what would have been the consequence? Mr. Armour, I suppose, and he alone is able to answer. Mr. Armour's whole scheme of intervention appears to me in the light of a hideous caricature, both of our Creator and his beneficent law. A law whose necessary penalties are as satisfactory as well as pleas ing to the Lawgiver as is obedience, is, I think, not the law of the Father of all our mercies. Illustrations ok Intervention. 229 A law which only the "Almighty One " can fulfill is not the law imposed upon finite creat ures, nor the law to which Christ was " obe dient unto death." Mr. Armour is right in insisting upon the integrity of law, and on the inevitableness of penalty to the trangressor. For all good comes from obedience, and to disobey is to forfeit, to lose, this good, and this deprivation of good is the penalty of disobedience. Obe dience is what the law imperatively requires. Penalty satisfies nothing, pleases nobody, repairs no injuries, can not remove its causes, is itself an evil, and yet is inevitable to the disobedient, for the simple and all-sufficient reason that it is impossible for a man to have and not have the good conditioned upon obe dience at the same time. A child can not at the same time have and not have the good that comes from eating. If it can not eat, of course it must suffer the consequences of not eating. Mr. Armour proposes to relieve its suffer ing by a double process, viz.: By having a substitute, first to eat for it; secondly, to suffer its hunger pains in its stead. If there is any virtue in substitution one of these processes ought to be sufficient — in fact, one excludes the other — that is, the eating 230 Atonement Reviewed. excludes the hunger pains, or takes away their cause. Hence, for the substitute to eat and at the same time suffer the pain that comes from not eating is a sheer impossibility. The Bible and common sense propose a different method of procedure. If the child eats according to the requirements of hygienic law it can not suffer hunger pains, or the pen alty of not eating. If it is in a condition that disables it from eating, it is the merest charla tanry to have a substitute to eat for it, or to take its hunger pains. A D.D. only could propose such a remedy and keep out of the asylum, and the M.D. who should suggest such a remedy would be justly deemed, not a quack, but a madman. The hunger law is inexorable in its demands. It can not be ab rogated or relaxed; nor can its penalties be avoided. But the only possible method of removing the penalty, or the hunger pains, is to gratify the hunger appetite. If the child can not eat of itself, then help it to eat — not by eating what it ought to eat, but by putting it in a condition to eat itself. The application of these common sense truths is so obvious that I need not stay to make it. To cure a patient is to relieve him of the pain which is the complement of his disease. Illustrations of Intervention. 231 No divine law requires penalty, but obedience, and the penalty is only the complement of disobedience. To restore the disobedient to obedience is to satisfy law, or nature, or God, and also to remove the penalty. While the sinner is in a state of disobedience he suffers the penalty or consequence of his disobedi ence himself, and no substitute is possible; just as the sick man suffers the pain of his disease, which no substitute can suffer in his stead. Whatever may be done for one or the other is done in the way of benefaction, and not in the way of substitution with its im practicable double imputation. When the sinner is restored to obedience, and is enabled to love God, which no one can do in his stead, then there is no penalty to bear, for obedience excludes penalty. This is what the blessed, loving Christ does for us — he helps miserable sinners back into a state of obedience, and sustains them in that state, and hence their penalties subside, as do effects when their causes are removed. SECTION XVIII. SCIENTIFIC PRETENSIONS. MR. ARMOUR'S object in "Atonement and Law" seems to be not to prove atonement by substitution the only possible method of atonement, but assuming this to be an established fact, his chief design seems to be to relieve this doctrine of the reproach of being the "Great Exception" to the regular on-going of the world. It is flatly alleged by skeptics, and generally admitted, that atonement by substitution is exceptional to the ordinary course of things — unique, without a parallel in nature. Mr. Armour, feeling this to be a reproach to Christianity, formed the laudable purpose of wiping it out by showing that atonement rests on the impregnable foundation of im mutable law, and incapable of defense by strictly scientific methods. Certainly every lover of Christianity should commend his praiseworthy endeavor. If suc cessful in the achievement of his noble end he (232) Scientific Pretensions. 233 merits high commendations. If unsuccess ful he ought to be respected for his good in tentions, and his failure attributed, not to his want of ability, but to the impracticability of his method. Has he achieved success? Has he given us an atonement capable of defense on scientific grounds? Having deliberately reconnoitered the field, he found three things which he deemed necessary to establish — the identity of sin and debt, moral law in com mandment only, and substitution a normal pro vision of law: 1. Sin is debt, though the greatest of all debts, which no human resources can possi bly pay, still it is strictly and only debt. What will scientists have to say of this? Will their skepticism be diminished or in creased? The latter, I feel sure, will be the result. 2. Moral law in commandment only. This is a vital strategic point. If this can not be established — if it can not be proved that law is wholly objective, and in no sense subjective — then substitution involving double imputa tion becomes simply impossible, and hence, substitutionary atonement on scientific grounds must be an inglorious failure. We have pre viously seen with what tenacity of purpose, and adroitness too, Mr. Armour attempts to 234 Atonement Reviewed. identify law in commandment, or law from without, and law written on the heart, or law from within. We have also seen that in this persistent effort to blur a distinction, which the Bible clearly and in divers forms recognizes, our author dispenses with the moral sense, or con science proper, and substitutes fear, or the apprehension of evil from without. Certainly Mr. Armour has a conscience, but his philosophy has none. True he gives us the name, but it is a pure sham, a wolf in sheep's clothing. Would not eagle-eyed sci entists be astonished beyond measure to find something in the realm, either of matter or of mind, that is free, utterly free, from con created law? something in no sense a law unto itself? wholly under the dominion of law in commandment, or from without. Suppose no one should choose to put this nondescript under law in commandment, then what? I suspect what Mr. Armour would say. But the point of interest at present is what will scientists, for whose special interest he seems to write, have to say? 3. Substitution a normal provision of law. In defense of this position, Mr. Armour puts forth all his wonderful resources of strat egy, learning, and logic. His inventive pow- Scientific Pretensions. 235 er is marvelous, his achievements fascinating and sparkling, his courage little less than sublime. It seems cruel, but fortune does not always favor the brave. Napoleon had his Waterloo. To fail here was to lose all. Mr. Armour failed only because he attempted the impossible — that is, to prove substitution a normal provision of law. The proposition is itself incapable of proof — can be proved nei ther metaphysically nor by any other method. We have seen that substitution is generally, perhaps always, even in the most trivial hu man affairs, unjust, and that in the Great Atonement it is utterly impossible in its con ditions, Mr. Armour himself specifying these conditions. Granting every thing he asks, he can prove substitution only by involving himself in poly theism, or attributing to the Divine Being two wills — one giving law, and the other obeying the precept and suffering the penalty of that law in the place of men. Now, can any scheme of atonement be properly accounted scientific which impera tively requires us to attribute to the Godhead more than one omnipotent will? If scientific minds admit the existence of one Almighty will at all, does not more than one such will appear to them an impossible conceit? 236 Atonement Reviewed. Again, as we have seen, Mr. Armour's substitution is impossible in its conditions — impossible for the want of an adequate sub stitute. Now, can any thing be truly scien tific which is impossible in its conditions, or for any other reasons? That the theory is incapable of defense on scientific grounds might be shown in various other ways, but enough has been said to sat isfy an unprejudiced mind. Mr. Armour, so far from proving substitu tion normal in moral law, has proved, if he has proved any thing, that moral law itself is abnormal. For according to the theory, causes and their effects may not only be sev ered, but the effects of adverse causes may be interchanged, and one substituted for an other. Thus one man may eat and another be nourished; one man may sleep and anoth er be refreshed; one man may obey law and another receive the good that is the effect of that obedience. But the abnormality is double. One man may suffer hunger pains, and by the endurance of these pains another man's hunger pains may be relieved; one man may suffer all the pains of insomnia, and another, on this account, be relieved of such pains. One man may suffer the penalty of Scientific Pretensions. 237 disobedience, and another thereby made to enjoy the reward of obedience. If such is the character of moral law, then the law is itself abnormal, or is a lawless law, not the divinely ordained rule of order, but of confusion. If substitution is capable of defense before the bar of reason, and on scientific grounds, then there is manifestly nothing unreasonable or unscientific, and the less we have of it the better. I reject atonement by substitution with double imputation in toto, as an assumption alike contrary to reason and to the Bible. But if we must have it, then I think the new wine is worse than the old, and that Mr. Ar mour has rendered a positive disservice to the cause of Christianity by his futile attempts to free atonement from the reproach of being the " Great Exception," for the sufficient reason that it is better to admit a fault than to at tempt to justify it — better to admit the atone ment to be abnormal in law than to make the law itself abnormal. Thinking and scientific men might reverently accept the first as a solemn mystery, but the latter I think will by such be generally rejected as an absurdity. But in the good providence of our gracious and all-wise heavenly Father good — great 238 Atonement Reviewed. good — may come from Mr. Armour's able effort to establish substitution on scientific grounds. He has asserted the substitutionary and penal theory, if not with more consisten cy, yet in such a manner as to expose more clearly its inherent absurdities and weakness than any of his predecessors known to me. The natural consequence will be that many that have hitherto been measurably satisfied with the penal theory will be stimulated to a more thorough investigation. Such investiga tion, I am quite confident, will result in a re jection of the whole scheme as unscriptural and impossible, and the adoption of something wholly different and better — something, the natural tendencies of which will be to draw men to the cross rather than to drive them from it. As to the effect of Mr. Armour's book upon scientists skeptically inclined it will, I presume, be evil, and only evil. That such will be the result is clearly indicated by the following quotation from " Philosophy of Re ligion," by Herman Lotze, whose reputation as a profound thinker and Christian scientist is unsurpassed by that of any other name of this century. He says (p. 151): "It is impossible to speak of God's honor as receiving ' satisfac- Scientific Pretensions. 239 tion' through the sacrificial death of a single person for the injury done it by the sin of man. For such a view, aside from its some what crude conception of God, is based upon the altogether impossible conception of a solidaric unity of the human race, and of the possibility of a transfer of its guilt and obliga tion to a single representative." If such a protest against penal satisfaction by a substitute comes from a profound Chris tian scientist, what may we not expect from non-christian scientists? APPENDIX. Lebanon, Tenn., April 26, 1SS6. Dr. S. G. Burney: — We, the undersigned, have been ap pointed by a unanimous vote of the senior class in the Theolog ical School of Cumberland University to represent to you our wishes concerning your Review of "Atonement and Law," by Rev. John M. Armour, which you have read before us. Having previously studied carefully your theory of the atonement, and having read Mr. Armour's book on the subject, we were some what curious as to how you would deal with his arguments, which to some minds appear very forcible. We, however, felt quite sure that when you had carefully analyzed them and traced them to their ultimate conclusions, they Mould be found, in the main, not only without foundation, but to involve contra dictions and absurdities sufficient to prove their falsity. We have not been disappointed. Your analyses are so clear and your refutations so complete that we believe the pviblication of the Review would serve greatly to quicken thought, encourage investigation, and to establish in the minds of many the true doctrine on this great subject. Therefore, we hereby request that it be given to the Church and the world in book form as soon as practicable. Respectfully, T. A. Cowan, C. H. Talley, R. A. Cody, Cumberland University. Committee. Class of 1886. — Bachelor of Divinity. Winstead Paine Bone, George Gary Hudson, Joe W. Caldwell,. James A. Longbottom, Thompson A. Cowan, Ewing L. Mc Williams, Eoberi A. Cody, James Henry Miller, James. Douglas Gold, John Henr* Miller, Lemuel J. Hawkins, Reuben Thomas Phillips, James Robert Henry, Morton E. Pratiier, John Yakt Stephens, Campbell' H. Talley, Charles B. Wellborn, Thomas Noel Williams, Isaac n. Yokley. In the foregoing request the Junior class concurred. The names are as follows : Robert Franci3 Adair, FungEwura Delzell, La Lande Bussle Bare, Edward E, Morris, John Douglass Black, Henry Franklin Smith, John B. .Cross, John Calvin Talley, John Robersoh Walker, William Heney Jones. (240) YALE UNIVERSITY LIBRARY 3 9002 01460 0234