YALE UNIVERSITY LIBRARY ixi AN ANALYSIS OF BUTLER'S ANALOGY OF RELIGION, AND THREE SERMONS ON HUMAN NATURE. BY JOSEPH ANGUS, D.D. THE RELIGIOUS TRACT SOCIETY: 56, Paternoster Row ; 65, St. Paul's Churchyard ; aku 164, Piccadilly. J Ji PREFATORY NOTE. This Analysis is not intended to supersede the Text, but simply to help in studying it. It is therefore as brief as possible, and so framed as to require continual reference to Butler himself. From experience, the Editor can afiErm that, with raost students, some such aid is essential to the mastering of the arguments of the volume. The Text recommended for use with this Analysis is that published by the Religious Tract Society. i CONTENTS. PACt Analogy ; Its Nature and Use . . . • 9 Introduction • . • • • • • 'S ^AKT .1.— ON NATURAL RELIGION. CHAP. I. On a Future Life ...••••" II. Ofthe Government of God dv Rewards and Punish ments; AND particularly OF TKE LATTER . H III. ' Of TitE Moral Govern m knt of God . . .27 IV. Of a State of Prodation as implying Trul, Diffi culties, AND danger . . . • .32 V. On a State of Prodation as intended for Moral Discipline and Lmprovement . • .34 VI. On the Opinion of Necessity, considered as Influ encing Practice . . . • -39 VII. Of the Government of God, considered as a Scheme or Constitution, Imperfectly Comprehended . 4; PART II.-OF REVEALED RELIGION. I. Of the Importance of Christianity . . .46 II, Of the supposed Presumption against a Revelation, CONSIDERED AS MIRACULOUS . . . .5° tn. Of our Incapacity of Judging what were to df. expected in a Revelation ; and the Credibility, from Analogy, that it must contain Things ap pearing liable to Objections . . • S^ ViaCUAI>, IV. V. VI. vn, VIII." I. II. ; Contents. Of Christianity, considered as a Scheme or Con- stitution, Imperfectly Comprehended Of the Particular System of Christianity ; ths Appointment of a Mediator, and the Redemption of the World by Him .... Of the Want of Universality in Revelation : and OF the Supposed Deficiency of the Proof of it On the Particular Evidence for Christianity On the Objections . which may be .made against Arguing fro.m the Analogy of Nature, to Re ligion , DISSERTATIONS. Of Personal Identity , , , Of the Nature of Virtue , , I.. II., III. SERMONS. Upon Human Nature , 57 59 646873 . 79 . 84 , 89-94 THE ANALOGY OF RELIGION TO THE CONSTITUTION AND COURSE OF NATURE. ANALOGY! ITS NATURE AND USE. Analogy, the principle of reasoning adopted in this volume, needs to be carefully defined, " no word in our tongue being more loosely used " (Mill). Quintilian, whose language Butler has placed on the title of his book, indicates by the term a part of grammar. So regarded, its business is to fix the declension or gender or conjugation of unknown words, by comparing their forms with those of other words already familiar. The Schoolmen, on the other hand, used it to describe terms in connexion with Rhetoric. With them, analogous words were words founded on resemblance ; pro perly applicable to one object, and less properly to another. "Greek nouns in i^iyc are generally patronymics, as are Scotch names with Mc, so therefore are these " — is an example of the first ; "A Smiling landscape " is an example of the second. In both these senses the word analogy is still used in common life ; and on analogy in the second sense, nearly all the technical language of moral and mental science is framed. A very httle examination will show that these senses of the word are closely connected with the sense in which Archbishop Whately uses it: i Similarity of relation is implied in each case. , ' RhctorU, Part I. chap. ii. § 7. 10 Analysis of Butlet's Analogy of Religion. Properly spealdng, analogy is a kind of resemblance j and an argument from analogy is founded upon such resemblance'. • Not any kind of resemblance, but a particular kind. Re semblances in appearance, in incidental circumstances, or even in properties, considered by themselves, form no sufficient basis for analogy. They often form the basis of figures of speech, or allegories, but they prove nothing. They do not even appeal to the reason, only to the fancy ; and their use is — illustration or embellishment If, however, the resemblance involves, or is supposed to involve, a similarity or identity of relation, there is analogy. It appeals, more or less, to the reasoning faculty, and may form a solid argument. Hence it is defined by Aristotle as a "likeness" or "parity of reason,"i and by Dr. Copleston, as a similarity, not " of two thmgs," but " of two relations." ''¦ " As two is to four, so is four to ^ight, or three to six:" "As the law of projectile forces is to the motion of a stone thrown from the hand, sb is . the law of central and centrifugal forces to the motion of the heavenly bodies through space : " " In nature, means apparently un desirable are used by God (the deist admits) to produce desirable ends, the use of similar means for similar ends in a revelation, is therefore consistent with the supposition that the revelation is from God : He does sometimes use them in the one, He may use them in the other : some means He nearly always uses in the one ; some means, therefore, He will most probably use in the other." All these are examples -of analogy, and in each case, it is not the things which are alike^2, 4; 3, 6, but their relations to each other, or to other things. It will be observed, thilc the two sets of relations compared may consist - . of three distinct terms, one reappearing in each set, or of four ; and that the reasoning is unaffected by this circumstance. 1 \ltyiiiv inoiir-ris : laSr-iis Kiyov, Ethic. Nic, v. 3. ' Enquiry into the Doctrines of Necessity and Fredestination', Notes to Disc. iii. A.' Analogy: Its Nature and Use. II ¦¦ In studying "The Analogy," it is of the utmost importance to keep in mind the chief uses of this kind of reasoning. 1. As an argument, it is demonstrative only in proving results or causes to be not improbable. It meets objections by a direct negative. It defends Christianity, without in the first instance contributing materially to the positive evidence on its side. Origen, for example, affirms " that he who believes the Scripture to have proceeded from Him who is the Author of Nature, may well expect to find the same sort of difficulties in 'it as are found in Nature." This is an analogical statement. None, however, can say that the difficulties of Scripture prove it to be Divine; though it is conclusive to say, "The difficulties of Scripture do not justify us in denying its Divine origin, for in Nature there are similar difficulties, and Nature is admitted to' have sprung from Him." So, should the atheist affirm that there is no God, and thence infer that there can be no future state of reward and punishment, Analogy replies — " In this hfe, though, as is said, there be no God, men are rewarded and punished; that is, they are under government. If so, that . there is no God is no reason why they raay not be under like government in the life to come." "No-God" is consistent with government now ; nor will it be inconsistent with govern ment hereafter. To repel objections, therefore, is the first business of analogy ; and in that department its argument amounts to demonstration, and its conclusions, expressed in negative forms ("not inconsistent witli," "not incredible that,") or their affirmative equivalents (" it may notwithstanding "), are irrefragable. The whole of the reasonings of Bishop Butler may be put in this form; and it will be observed that the second part of his work uses analogy for these defensive purposes exclusively. 2. There , is, however, a wider application of analogical reasoning, and indeed it may be said, that there is a wider 12 Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion. meaning of the term itself. Whately, Copleston, and others, use the woi-d Analogy in the strict sense, as meaning re semblance of relations. But by many metaphysical writers, including Locke, Hartley, Mill, and Butler himself, it is used to express an argument founded on resemblance of any kind, though generally falling short of full proof Sir Humphrey Davy, for example, discovered that potash has a metallic base. But other alkalies have sensible properties hke potash. He therefore concluded, that it was probable they had also metallic bases ; a conclusion verified by subsequent discovery. Evidence resting upon analogy in this sense admits, of course, of different degrees. It may amount to the highest moral certain ty,it may give no more than the lowest presumption. The positive evidence, for example, in favour of a future life, founded on the single analogy of the changes of the chrysalis is small ; i while the evidence founded on the uniform fact that in Nature nothing is ever wasted ot anmhilated^ihtx&foxe, not the soul ^ — is strong : the force depending, in each case, on the frequency of the supposed analogous facts, and the real resemblance between the things compared. Examples of this use of analogy abound in the first part of this treatise. - It is important to remark, that in the affairs of life, all evidence is of the kind described in the last paragraph. Mathematical reasoning is demonstrative, and its conclusions certain, because .they are virtually included in the premises ; so are thfe conclusions of logic. But in matters of fact, and in maxims of prudence, we are guided simply by what is probable. What is often called even positive proof belongs to the same class. Testimony, written records, the very evidence of our senses, to take the strongest case, are none of them certain : they are probable, and probable only.^ The remark ^ Butler, Part I. chap. i. ' Is it Possible to make tlie Best of both Worlds^ p. 220. ^ ' See Gambier on Moral Evidence, p. 67. ' , Analogy: fts Nature aiid .Use. 13' of Butler, therefore, is just, that analogy differs from other evidence only in degree, not in kind; and that its force depends on the completeness of the resemblance (in what is raaterial), of the things we compare. 3. By some Writers, as t)r. Hampden, forms of induction itself are included under this term ; and Butler seems to concur in this view. When once an inquirer understands what a cause is, and why or how it acts, so as to be able to point out the connexion between it and the result, and then applies this knowledge to connect other and similar results with the same or similar causes, testing the accuracy of the process by experiment, the analogy becoraes induction in the strictest sense. The existence of a present moral government is proved in this way, by Butler; and the fact of a future government is (admitting a future life) all but proved : for the evidence is traced up to qualities in man, and to attributes in God, which we can hardly conceive to be capable of change. Still, as human nature is fallen, the doctrine of causation abstruse, especially when applied to God and His perfections, and reasoning from the known to the unkno^\•n, from what is to what will be, extremely uncertain ; positive arguraents from analogy in, relation to religion, must be received with great caution. Arguments against objections to revelation, and involving negative conclusions, rest on different premises, and may be admitted without distrust. To show from Nature what God will do or reveal in Scripture, is one thing : To show from Nature that parts of Scripture which speak of His doings,, form no valid objection to its Divine authority, is another.! 1 The language of Dugald Stewart seems on tlie whole just. After referring to the opinions of Dr. Reid and Dr. Campbell, and expressing his doubts " whether both of these ingenious writn-s have not soniewhat underrated the importance of analogy as a medium of proof," he adds. 14 Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religiou. The reader may find these questions more or less fully discussed in Locke, Book v. chap. 16, sec. 12 ; Reid's Enquiries, chap. 4; Stewart's Elements, ii. chap. 4, sec 2, § 3 ; Mill's Logic, ii. 426 ; and in Hampden's Essay on the Philos. Evidence of Christianity, p. 60, etc. All these writers concur in giving the wide? meaning of analogy. Tappan's Logic, Book iv. sec. 10; Dr. Tatham's Chart and Scale of Truth, vol. i. p. 50-62 ; Wayland's Intellectual Philosophy, chap. vi. sec. 4 ; and Chal mers" Lectures on Butler's Analogy, favour the narrower view. See also the works of Whately, Copleston, and Gambler, already quoted. The precise place of analogy in the Christian Evidences is easily assigned to it. It is part of the Internal .Evidencs, resting on the message itself, not on the credentials of the messengers. It appeals, not to a priori reasoning, but to facts and principles already learned by experience in Nature ; not to minute coincidences between the sacred history and other records, or to the feelmgs and spiritual insight of renewed men, but to the consciences and judgments of all. It requires less learning than External Evidence, involves no assumptions, and is appreciable by the whole race. In Scripture, it is of constant occurrence : Every parable and rairacle, every com parison and figure, being intended to explain and in sorae degree to enforce Divine truth by things and facts already familiar. See Matt. v. -viL ; i Cor. xv. 36. " I acknowledge, at the same time, that between the positive and the negative application of this species of evidence, there is an essential difference. When employed to refute an objection, it may often furnish an argument irresistibly and unanswerably convincing. When employed as a medium of proof, it can never authorize more than a probable conjecture. ... In some instances, however, the probability resulting from a concurrence of different analogies may rise as high as to produce an effect on the belief scarcely distinguishable from moral certainty." — Elements, ii., 423, note. ¦ \ INTRODUCTION. A. Of the nature of analogical evidence in general.! 1. Such evidence is various in degrees, from low presumptions to moral , certainty : one slight presumption cannot make anything probable ; but many can. Ebb and flow of tide. 2. Its foundation is verisimilitude, or likeness to some truth, or fact ; hkeness either in the thing itself, or in its evidence or circumstances. Here the degree of probability is as the frequency with which we have observed the same or like things. It becomes presumption, opimon, conviction, and forms a rule of hope and judgments. 3. Its measure imperfect, but obligatory : a. Imperfect, and fit for limited capacities, for to God nothing is probable ; b. Yet obligatory, however low the presumption in favour of any opinion, or practice. Indeed, where men must act, ' In these outlines the connexioii and subordination of thoughts are indicated thus : — A 1 a 1 (a) (1) B 2 b 2 (b) (2) C 3 c 3 (c; (3) and very occasionally (a) (l) where, for example, (1) is a subdivision under (a), as (a) is under 1, and 1 under a, and a under 1, and 1 under A. Ordinarily A, B, etc., represent distinct subjects. Corresponding letters .and figures will be found in tha margin of the text pubhshed by the Religious Tract Society. l6 Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion. prudence will select the course which seems right, even though the chances of success are even or adverse. B. Of the utility of such evidence, and its application to rehgion. Its measure not discussed, but yet its utility obvious. 1. In determining our judgments and practice in common life ; 2. In relation to religion and God's present govemment. From it one may reason with Origen, a. That difficulties must be expected in Scripture as in Nature ; b. That a denial of the Divine origin of Scripture on this ground will end in a denial of the Divine origin of the world ; and, c. That both systems have the same Author ; or, at least, that objections against the one are answered by the other. 3. In forming our notions ofreligion, it is superior, a. To reasoning on assumed principles : b. To reasoning on true principles, the applicability of which is assumed, and hence, c. Butler intends to apply it to religion, natural and revealed, assuming an Author and Governor of Nature ; which assumption has no prior improbabihty, and has often been proved by accumulated evidence : d. To vain speculations how the Woild might have been better : which speculations may be shown to be vain thus — 1. Probably the speculator himself would admit his plan to be not the w^y best, ^whether he contemplated the greatest amount of virtue or of happiness, or of both. 2. And certainly foolish and extravagant plans would be formed, involving conclusions like these,— all creatures must be made at once perfect, free from all hazard and toil, and without dread or risk of punishment. 3. For such speculations men have not faculties. (a) Of ends we may judge : hence we believe that the greatest amount of virtue and happiness is God's .fl'- ^r Introduction. 17 >i: end in providence, a belief to which our whole nature impels us, and of which that nature is an evidence ; (b) But of means we cannot— no, (c) Not even of the best means of training a single person, much less a system ; and, (d) Hence men cannot judge each other ; how then can they judge God ? C. Practical conclusion : Leave speculation, and mark, 1. The conduct of Nature with respect to inteUigent creatures. 2. The laws to be gathered from it ; and, 3. The analogy between what we ^>ui in Nature, and what we beheve or expect m religion; whence it will appear that they are both of a piece. D. The force of this analogy, 1. Varies, being sometimes a practical proof, somethnes a con firmation, of what is otherwise proved. 2. Shows that religion is not ridiculous, unless Namrebe so; and 3. Answers objections against the system of religion, and to a large extent objections against its evidence. E. The treatise is divided into two parts, and is thus analysed : The first, On religion in general, i.e., on natural religion: wherein it IS shown that there is a future life, Chap. I. : a cultural go vemment, present and fiiture, Chap. II.; a moral govemment, Chap. III.; that life is a probation state, involving risits. Chap. IV. ; promoting impro-vement and testing character, Chap. V. • that the /acts of moral government are not affected by any opinions on necessity, Chap. VI. ; and that the perfection of God's govemment cannot be objected to, for it is as a scheme incomprehensible. Chap. VII. The second. On Christianity in , particular, i.e., on revealed reli gion: where it is shown that Christianity is important, Chap. I,; thatas w?>a<:«/(7Mjno objection can be urged against it. Chap. II! • c 1 8 Analysis of Butler's Analogy of ReHgion, that as a scheme, no valid objections can be urged against it, either against it as a. fact, though differing from our expecta tions. Chap. IIL; or against the moral perfections displayed in it, Chap. IV., § I ; or against the system of means and general laws whereby it is carried on, Chap. IV., § 2; or against media tion, Chap, v.; or against its want of universality and supposed' deficient proof, Chap. VI.; or against its evidence, prophetic, miraculous, or general, Chap. VIL; and, lastly, that analogy is strongly and in various ways on the side of religion, general and revealed {a, b, c), Chap. VIII. ^^ PART I. ON NATURAL RELIGION. -^-^ The first part of this treatise, it must be carefully noted, discusses natural religion — such truths as 7?iay be learned from creation and providence ; and the language used is generally such as an imperfect revelation of that kind suggests. The second part discusses revealed religion — such truths as may b^ learned from Nature, and are taught in Scripture, together with such as are peculiar to the Christian system. The distinction between natural and revealed religion is itself very liable to be misapprehended. Some hold that there are not even the elementary truths of such a science as the religion of Nature. Others, overlooking the fact that "natural religion has had the opportunity of rekindling her faded taper by gospel light" (Da\'ison on Prophecy, p. 8), ascribe to it truths which it cannot claira. It is, moreover, at all times difficult to distinguish between the possible dis coveries of reason and the "wisdom that is from above:" and good men are jealous of dishonouring the Holy Sphit by ascribing to unassisted reason what is due to His teaching. In studying this treatise, however, there need be no misgivings on these points. By natural religion Butler means simply such truths in relation to God (His character and govemment) and man (his duties and destiny) as nuiy be learned from God's works and deaUngs — the pretensions of natural religion in 20 Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religiou. this respect being set forth with much, moderation and reserve. He holds, moreover, that in fact these truths were not learned in the first instance by unassisted reason, but that miraculous instruction was needed to teach men to perceive them (Part IL, chap. vil.). At the same time such instruction no more destroys the proof of these truths frora reason, than the admission of the authority of Euclid as a mathematician destroys the independent proof which reason gives of his demonstrations. Happily, if we admit an authentic and enlarged communication from God, our only business is to examine how far Nature leads us on in the same path, and how she confirms the evidence and illustrates the teaching of revelation. CHAPTER I ON A FUTURK LIFK Though Butler reckons the doctrine of a future life among the truths of natural religion, he does so rather for the reasons stated in chapter i., than from any conviction that the truth is, taught clearly and impressively by Nature. A future life is natural, as he has shown ; and yet if knowledge imply proof and conviction, then it must' be adraitted that, apart from revelation, there is no knowledge of that life, and that in the gospel alone it is revealed. Whately has proved the accuracy of this conclusion. (Essays on some of tlie Peculiarities of the Christian Religion, Essay i.) ' At the same time the expectation of another life (sometiraes hope, generally fear) has always been stronger araong nations without the Bible than any evidence they seem to have possessed would warrant This expectation Douglas ascribes partly to tradition, and partly to the aptitude of the soul to receive this truth. {Truths ^l ^ ^•^ A Future Life. 21 of Religion, p. 22.) Cicero ascribes it to the same cause — omnium consensus, natures vox {Tusc. Quest., L, § 15) — though holding that the truth none but a god could tell, while what was likest truth was extremely uncertain. A. A. future life is probable : 1 From similar changes already undergone in, a. Ourselves, and in, b. Other creatures^worms, birds, etc 2. From our present powers, which are likely to continue, unless death destroy them. We fear death may, but there is 7io proof that it will, a. Either from the nature of death. We know not what it is, nor do we know on what the existence of our powers (not their exercise) depends. b. Or from the analogy of Nature, which shows only that the ' sensible proof oi our powers (not the powers themselves) may be destroyed ; and gives presumptions on the other side, as above. B. Still men imagine death will destroy them. This imagina tion unfounded. Take the question in three forms : 1. Is death the destruction of Uving beings f No reason to think it is, for this supposes we are compounded, and so dis- cerptible ; but the contrar>' is probable, having metaphysical and experimental proofs. a. Metaphysical : consciousness is indivisible ; so must the sub ject in which consciousness inheres : hence our bodies are not the living being, nor is the matter in which the living being thinks. The living being may exist out of the body, may animate other bodies, and be as Uttle affected by the dissolution of all these bodies, as of any other foreign matter. b. Experimental : part of the body (limbs) may be lost, the body may be larger or smaller, or even entirely (though gradually) changed, and the /zVz«^fe«j-r£//w/«. Note, moreover, 22 Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion. 1. Even if man is material, still death may not destroy the elementary particles in vvhich the hving being inheres; and if not, death does not destroy him. 2. So, as the destruction of the bodily system (by gradual changes, by amputation) destroys not the living being, neither will the destruction of any other (say internal) system. Death, indeed, is a sudden not a ghadual change, and the living being is affected by the body ; but the first fact is not decisive, nor is the latter more true of the body than of other foreign matter that affects the soul. 3. The body has organs of perception, etc., which may be removed or destroyed without affecting the living being ; so may all other organs — eye-glasses, wooden limbs^perception without organs, as in dreams. In those cases the organ is an instrument which may be laid aside ; so the dissolution of matter or of organs is not the destruction of the being himself. Obj. It may be objected, this applies to brutes, which must, therefore, be immortal, and moral too. To which answer, a. Be it so ; brutes may have latent powers, which fit them to ' be immortal: and, b. It does not follow ; brutes may have a natural immortaUty without any higher faculties ; and God may dispose of them as He shall please. 2. Is death the destruction (not of the living being, but) of our present Uving powers of reflection, as it is of those of sensation ? a. Man lives in two states— sensation, and perception or re flection. b. Ideas once gained, sensation may be destroyed and reflection remain untouched; for now, 1. We can and do reflect independently ofthe senses; and, . 2. In mortal diseases reflection is unaffected up to the moment of death, and after sensation has ceased. c Each state, indeed, affects the other ; but the destruction of A Future Life. 23 'i .' ¦¦',\ one thing which affects another is not necessarily the destruction of the two. d. Diseases even give a presumption to the contrary (see B b 2). 3. Is death even the suspension of our present powers of reflec tion? No; for, a. Such suspension is no part of the idea of death, which is simply dissolution ofthe body. b. Death may be like birth, a continuation and perfecting of our powers ; and, c. At all events, suspension of powers and destruction so differ, that we cannot argue the second from the first. I Obj. Death is after all our destruction, as is clear from vegetable decay. But the things compared differed in the essential point of comparison— the possession of hving powers of perception. Repeat conclusion in a positive form. C. The future life here shown to be probable is natural: 1. We enter it naturally, by a change like our birth. 2. It is naturaUy social. 3. Ruled by natural yf.jrfi/ laws, according to virtue. 4. Nor less natural that these laws are administered by God, not , by men, etc. D. This probable proof of a future life helps rehgion as much as deraonstration would do ; for, 1. Demonstration would not silence an unbeliever in religion, since his unbeUef may- admit a future Ufe as it admits this ; and, 2. Probable proof silences objections, and prepares the mind to attend to the proper evidence of religion. 24 Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion. CHAPTER IL OF THE GOVERNMENT OF GOD BY REWARDS AND PUNISHMENTS ; AND PARTICULARLY OF THE LATTER. Carefully mark that, in chap, ii., Butler is speaking of govemraent simply, not of moral government, which is the subject of chap. iii. "Acts have consequences, and those consequences are foreseen," is the argument here: ''virtuous acts have happy consequences, and those consequences are foreseen," is the arguraent in the next chapter.' . . Professor Fitzgerald has appropriately remarked, that in the outset of this argument, we have an answer to all who regard religion as a mere tJuory. It belongs not to speculation, but to those practical matters on which our condition compels us to make ' up our minds one way or other. The Creator is not only the first Cause of all, He is moral Governor; and our etemal destiny is suspended upon our treatment of His claims. INTRODUCTION. A future life is probable (chap, i,), and im portant, because (chap, u.) our happiness in it may depend on our present conduct, i.e., we are under government. Consider that we are under govemment generally; and, under govemment by punishment, as well as by rewards. A, Under govemment generally ; i. e., 1. Our present happiness and misery depend on our behaviour. a. Life is preserved through care. b. The possession of external goods depends on exertion, and c. Enjoyment and misery are consequences of rashness, passion, neglect, and their opposites. Obj. 1. One may ask why, and wish that God had given happi ness promiscuously ; but, in answer, remember Government by Rewards, and Puniskments. 25 a. Such an arrangement may be impossible. b. The present plan may produce more happiness than any other. c. God's goodness may be a disposition to make (not all but only) the good happy. d. The goodness of moral agents may be more pleasing to God and better for the universe than mere happiness. e. The reason may be to us incomprehensible— as colours to the blind ; and f. At all events the/a 2. Good actions are never punished, considered as such, but through mistake, as the contrary. 4. Vice is punished as vice, and virtue rewarded as virtue Where note a. This statement implies that an action may have one effect, and the quality of an action another (gain, for example,' as gain, brings pleasure : gain, as dishonest gain, brings misery). b. It afiirms that virtue brings advantages to the virtuous, and vice evils to the vicious; and the following are examples: 1. In our own temper virtue produces peace ; vice, vexation and self-reproach ; and that these feelings are owing to the quaUty of the actions is plain, for, etc. 2. Nor ought ^e. present fear of future punishment to be left out of this view, and the present peace in prospect of future happiness. 3. In common Ufe, also, virtue has rewards, and vice punish ment; a virtuous man being befriended because ofhis character, and in public life advantages are the natural rewards of fidelity, patriotism, etc., as such ; while external annoyances often foUow vice. 4 In domestic government, children and others are rewarded for veracity, etc., aS such; and punished for falsehood, as such. i \ n ^ The fHoral Government of God. 29 6. In civil government, though law regards actions chiefly, yet the viciousness of the actor, or the opposite, will often secure the infliction of the penalty, or induce men to remit it. c. The conclusion to which these facts lead is that, as our moral nature is a proof that we are under moral govern ment, and will be finally treated as responsible, so ex amples justify this reasoning, and prove an existing moral government now, d. If it be asked, whence it is that virtue is rewarded and vice punished, and that this rule is not reversed, answer, it is - because L Virtue brings present satisfaction to out-own minds ; and 2, With this moral nature God has made our happiness 1 depend largely upon one another; so that vice, being infamous, brings punishment. Nor is there any such regard for injustice and falsehood as for their opposites. If examples can be quoted to the contrary, they are felt by aU to be monstrous perversions. e. Not, indeed, that the degrees of reward given to virtue are always proportionate to it ; but it is rewarded, and vice punished ; so much is clear. f. It is admitted, also, that sometimes happiness and misery are distributed according to other rules. But this is ex plained ; for, 1. It may be as mere discipUne. 2. It may be the result of the operation of general laws, which may render persons prosperous, though wicked. 3. It is, after aU, not a natural arrangement, since we intuitively expect fhe opposite. 4. It will be found to be owing, in most cases, to the perversion of some passion. g. From the whole it is plain that this arrangement is a declaration, upon God's part, that He is on the side of virtue, which assurance is itself a fresh source of comfort to the good man. 5. In the nature of things there is a tendency in virtue and vice to greater rewards and punishments than <>'i present; 30. Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion. which tendencies are a strong argument in favour of a perfect moral govemment in tlu: future. This tendency is seen in individuals; for virtue would be more fully rewarded, and vice punished, but for accidental causes ; and in society, where power under the direction of virtue has a tendency to prevail over power not under its direction ; as power with reason is stronger than power without it This, however, needs to be explained. a. Power with reason will conquer power without it, not neces- ¦- ¦ sarily, but commonly, under certain conditions ; L There must be some proportion between the two powers. 2. Union among those who possess rational power. 3. Time and scope for the development of rational power. Sometimes, however, want of reason will succeed. 4. From its inability to foresee danger. .6. From its attempting through ignorance what prudence would avoid. 6. From certain conjunctures of weak ness and discord. 7. From the force of a union based upon instinct, and free from the divisions which the passions of rational beings sometiraes produce. / b. So, with regard to virtue, it has a tendency to prevail through the union of the good for the sake of justice and veracity. That this tendency is natural, and the hindrances to it accidental, may be shown, either 1. By looking at the -whole universe, where, the visible and the invisible being supposed analogous, virtue will finaUy prevail ; as is shown by the analogous case of reason ; provided, however, the same conditions be fulfiUed. See above, a. 1, 2, 3-7, ' Obj. This tendency, indeed, is hindered, but it is by causes which are accidental, and are likely to be removed in a future state, which will give the requisite scope for the operation of virtue, etc. This supposition of a boundless universe, and virtue triumph ant throughout, is only a supposition, but it is credible. 2. Or by looking at a human society, perfectly virtuous and united, and working for a succession of ages (indefinite ' time, not as before, indefinite space). T/te Jiforal Government of God. . \ 31 (a). At home, such a society would certainly prosper ; and (b). Abroad, it would become the basis of a universal kingdom. c. Hence these tendencies are a distinct testimony, upon God's part, to morality and virtue ; a testimony of great importance, ifit be considered what the effect would be if vice had the advantageous tendency of virtue, and virtue the opposite. C. The application of this analogy to a future moral govern- . ment is obvious. It may, indeed, be objected at the outset. a. That good and evil may hereafter be mixed as now : Answer, 1. The nature of that future Ufe belongs to religion, which it is not here intended to prove, but only to confirm the proper proof of it 2. Even if these facts did not confirm that proof, the proof itself remams in aU its force. b. But these facts confirm the proper proof of reUgion in various ways. 1. They show that God is in favour of virtue, and against vice. 2. They show that future perfect moral govemment wiU be the corapletion of what has already begun ; differing from the present, not in kind, but only in degree. 3. They give reason to a hope that virtue MAY BE more highly rewarded, and vice more severely punished, in the next hfe than in this ; and they even, 4. Give reason to conclude that these rewards and punishments will exist in a higher degree than here. D. On the whole, conclude that, besides arguraents drawn from our moral nature, the etemal relations of things, the fitness of actions, there are arguments for a present ' moral govemment, and for a future perfect moral government, based upon facts, B 1—6. The notion, therefore, of such a future government is natural, and even probable. 32 Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion. CHAPTER IV. OF A STATE OF PROBATION AS IMPLYING TRIAL, DIFFICULTIES, ANt) DANGER. In this chapter the difficulties and risks of a religious course, the aggravatioh of those risks by the acts of others, are all shown to correspond with what is experienced in coraraon life, so that if we give up on these grounds the "God of religion," we raust also give up the " God of Nature." Commonly probation has the same raeaning as moral govern ment It is here used, however, to indicate the difficulties and risks consequent upon teraptatioa In this light it deserves special consideratioa A. That religious probation iraplies danger and risk (trial) in regard to the future is not iraprobable, from the analogy of our present natural probation, which makes interest depend upon behaviour. The two are analogous in many particulars. 1. lufact our interests in both respects are in danger from our selves, as is clear from the foUowing : a. God has made our happiness to depend on our own acts. b. We blame ourselves for misconduct in temporal affahs. c. We actuaUy miss happiness and incur misery through our own acts. d. The acknowledged hazards of the young, and the temptations to vices which are yet mischievous. 2. The occasions or causes of our natural and religious probations are analogous. These causes are in our nature or in our circumstances. a. Circumstances or temptations often betray men : so do their passions ; the two mutuaUy implying each other. b. So close is the analogy, that in both cases the same passions Probation as implying Trial, etc. 33 •r are excited by the same means ; so that we may , describe both by similar terms. 3. The effects of these temptations on men's behaviour are analogous. a. Some gratify themselves without looking at the future. b. Some are deceived by passion. ' c. Some &XQ forced away by it against their judgment d. Some shamelessly avow their preference for vice in spite of consequences ; and e. At the very least, men do voluntarily go wrong in both cases. 4. The way in which these difficulties and dangers are increased, and in some sense made, is alike in both cases. a. Others give us a bad education, set a bad example, encourage dishonest practices, corrupt religion, and diffuse false notions of happiness. b. We ourselves increase our difficulties, by negligence ; by , indulgence which weakens our moral powers ; by accumulated irregularities, which make the course of virtue perplexed and disadvantageous. B. It is indeed objected that this state is improbable in two respects. 1. Our condition thus appears to be unfavom-able to our interests. Answer : a., StiU it is not to be complained of, for with care our difliculties may be met ; and, as to God, it is equitable that He should put upon us what it is clear we can do, nor can we complain unless, etc. b. Our very condition in nature makes a similar condition in religion probable, from the analogy between the two. 2. This condition involves hazards, and may work ruin, and must be foreseen to work it : Such an arrangement is im probable. No doubt, a. Such hazai-d is a mystery, which, however, the whole case may enable us to explain ; b. At all events tha constitution of Nature is in favour of such hazard ; and, c. As for the certainty of the ruin, it is as much contingent as our conduct is. 34 Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion. C. The conclusion : in both capacities our interest is offered, not to our acceptance, but to our acquisition ; we are in danger of missing it ; and, without attention and self- idenial, it must be missed. CHAPTER V. ON A STATE OF PROBATION AS INTENDED FOR MORAL DISCIPLINE AND IMPROVEMENT. Introduction.— Why should there be the risk indicated in the last chapter? is a question attended with insuperable difficulties, a. All vice, indeed, is voluntary, and many miseries have some good effects; yet the reason for the existence of vice and misery we cannot give, and perhaps, b. it is beyond our faculties to understand it, or it may be better for us not to know it Yet, c. the existence of these conduces to our fitness for another life. Though this be d. partial reason only, it shows at least what our present business is— improve ment in holiness; A, The present trial, preparing us for a future life, is analogous to the education raen now undergo in one state of life preparing thera for another. This analogy will appear from some considerations comraon to both probations (1) 2) ; and. from a distinct consideration of each, the natural (3) and the religious (4). 1. All creatures have capacities, etc., for a particular way of life. Happiness depends now upon the agreement between their capacities and their condition. So it must be in the future. 2. The constitution of creatures is such that they may become qualified for states of life for which they were once un qualified, on which observe, V Probation as intended for Moral Discipline, 33 ¦ a. Men experience increased facility of action, a settled altera tion of character, an improvement by exercise of their intellectual facuUies.* The first two are habit, as perhaps is the third. b. Habits are, according to their nature, either perceptive or passive and af/«'wy or, according to man's ntX-a-c^, bodily and mental; which last are either inteUectual or moral. 1. Our habits are formed by repeated acts, which acts, in the case of moral habits, are either the carrying out of practical principles and resolutions, or attempts to induce others to act 2. Passive impressions, it must be noticed, are weakened by repetition, and will not of themselves form habits. 3. From the two previous remarks it follows that, with repetition, the motives and excitements to act become feebler, as passive impressions, but stronger, as active principles. Three examples, (a), (b), (c). 4 Hence habits are not strengthened by admonitions or passive impressions, but by appropriate action. 6. Of much connected with them we may be ignorant, and whether they can be formed in any other way, etc. The facts, however are clear, and are such as the foregoing. 6. With repeated acts, the faciUty and the pleasure increase, etc., tiU a new character is gained. 3. Looking more closely at our present natural probation only (one state oflife preparing us for another), we note, a. Men start in hfe unfumished ; «^^^/«f acquired quaUfications of knowledge and experience to fit tliem for after life. , 1. If man were bom with matured faculties, yet without training, he would be distracted how to use them; and, probably, 2, so self-willed as to be unfit to leam. b. This need Nature supplies, by placing us in the outset in a condition for acquiring the necessary discipUne and improvement 1. Children learn graduaUy the objects and facts around them ; are placed under domestic government, where 36 Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion, they are taught self-control and obedience, and after wards by experience they acquire caution and ac quaintance with rules of conduct innumerable. 2. This learning, however, depends much upon them selves ; though part is communicated by others. 3. Upon their behaviour and use of this discipline their character and station depend. c. To all this our religious probation is analogous, so that Even if the manner of that religious probation is not quite discernible, this is no objection. For we see not the manner of our present probation, though we see its results (sleep, food, restraint). , 4. Looking more closely at our present religious probatioi\ only (the present life preparing us for another), note, a. That future lifo will apparently be moral, social, with scope for virtue, and requiring it, though there is much not revealed. b. Our capability of moral improvement in preparing for that state has already been proved (see above, 2, b, 1-6). c. Our need of moral improvement will appear from the foUowing considerations. 1. In fact, mankind are wicked, and at best imperfect. 2. From our nature, as finite beings, we are in danger of deviating from right (a) through particular affections,', which fix on external objects, are excited by them independently of the moral principle, and our only securityis(b) from the moral principle strengthened into habit, as Butler describes. To apply this to a future life supposes that particular affections will exist there. If they do, then this discipline will be required. If they do not, still the discipline will secure increased happiness, if the government of the universe is moral. 3. The conclusion, and a fresh proof is, that a nature originally upright may, through these laws, fail or be improved in virtue. (a) An upright nature may fail ; not through liberty, which can account for nothing, but. through parti- Probation as intended for Moral Discipline, 37 cular affections in themselves sinless, the operation of which Butler describes in five particulars. (b) Or be improved to higher and securer virtue, by following the moral principle, which would be strengthened as the particular affections would be weakened, till at last security would be perfect ; though a fall would always be possible, because the affections and the moral principle would never be absolutely coincident. (c) Hence creatures made perfect may need discipline as a security against faUing, and a state fit for discipline may be requisite even for them. 4, If an upright nature needs improvement, much more does one that is faUen. d. The present state is peculiarly fit for such discipUne, for 1. It teaches moderation and self-restraint 2. Shows peculiarly our liability to vice ; a different thing from speculative knowledge. 3. It puts us on our guard, exercises self-denial, the moral principle, and forms virtuous habits. Self-denial, indeed, is not necessary to virtue, but it conduces to form habits of virtue. 'B. ^Objections — 1. It may be said, this state of discipUne overtaxes our powers, and supposes a degree of improvement greater than we are capable of. 2. It is said that, in fact, this life is rather a discipline in vice than in virtue. Answer : a. It is not intended to give all the reasons why men are placed here, but some only. b. And, in fact, this life is a discipline in virtue to aU who are willing to make it so. c. The fact that such discipline is wasted with sorae is only analogous to other facts of waste ; of seeds, for example, which yet God created to becoine fruitful. The things here compared are, indeed, different in value, but the facts are equaUy unaccountable. 38 Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion, 3. It is said, against the whole of this discipline, that it makes moral conduct proceed from fear and self-love, and so is not properly moral discipline at all. To which answer, a. To do God's commands because He gives them is obedience, even though it proceed from fear or hope ; and repeated acts of obedience will form the moral habit. b. This distinction between self-love and regard to God's authority may be too finely drawn. Both are coincident, and may coexist as just principles of action. He, moreover, who begins to act from the first, wUl come ultimately to act morally in the highest sense. ¦ 4. The discipline here spoken of includes passive resignation, and this can have no place in heaven, because tlure are no afflictions. Answer, a. Prosperity may beget discontent, as well as affliction. b. And, though resignation is not needed in heaven, the habit may be, for, without such habits, self-love and particular aftections may be excited beyond their proper hmits. And, C. Submission to God's sovereignty, which is not usurped and precarious, but just and etemal, requires in heaven the same temper as resignation upon earth. 5. But might not all the difficulty and risks of this discipline, have been prevented, if men had been made at once what they were to be ? To which answer, a. The law of life is not to save us trouble, but to impose it, and enable us to go through it. What we become seems ever dependent upon what we do. b. Improvement by habit supplies natural deficiency, and creates natural security, as acquirement in natural things meets our bodily needs. c. And everywhere we are to choose improvement at the price of effort, or misery as the result of neglect. C Probation not only iraplies risks (ch. iv.) and aids improve ment (ch. v.), but it seems also intended for a third purpose — manifestation of character. . ¦ ^ Opinion of Necessity as influencing Practice. 39 1. This manifestation may refer only to this life ; but it may refer also to the next : God intending to show what men are, in order to make it clearer on what principles He deals with them. 2. Certainly in this life such manifestation is a means of present moral govemment, and seems essential to it ; always un- proving men, if they act well. CHAPTER VL ON THE OPINION OF NECESSITY, CONSIDERED AS INFLUENCING practice. On the supposition that necessity is reconcilable with the experienced constitution of Nature, the question, Is it also with religion : answered in the affirmative. Thus far the controversy has been with the deist Atheism, however, may be supposed to maintain that necessity itself accounts for the existence of things— an opinion which needs first to be examined, A. Does necessity (supposed reconcilable with Nature) destroy the proof of an inteUigent Author, and so support Atheism? No; for, 1. Necessity does not set aside an agent ; 2. Nor does.it exclude design and intelligence, either m men or , in God. ' , ' 3, It is trufe that men ascribe (in a loose way) the existence of God to necessity ; but this is a new meamng of the word, and is intended merely to imply that, prior to design iix Nature, there must be a Divine existence. Answer re stated. 40 Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion. B. Does necessity, supposed reconcilable with Nature, destroy the belief that we are under moral government ? No ; for, > L When applied to practical matters (therefore religion included) necessity is as if it were false : e.g., a. Let a child act upon it, and he will find that it is either not true, or not acted upon as true. b. Or a man in common life. Hence, probably, men are free. Upon this, however, Butler does not here insist Nor let any be surprised that, upon the opinion of necessity being true, we act upon it as false, and thence blame our reason ; for God has given us practical principles, which we follow instead of reason, and to object to these is mere conceit 2. Necessity, if true, is reconcilable with the possession of a moral character, the foundation of veracity, benevolence, and justice, both in us and in God. a. That He possesses such a character is shown by His natural character, and by final causes. b. Necessity is reconcilable with some kind of character in us, for it hinders neither truth nor falsehood. If this be denied, and it be said. Admit necessity, and there can be no moral characterin us, and so no just punish ment. Answer, The necessity which destroys the in justice of an act destroys the injustice of a punishment ; and, after all, our conviction of a character remains ; we StiU deem ourselves just or unjust, necessity notwith standing. c. So necessity is reconcilable with the character of God : as reconcilable with veracity and justice as with any other. Obj. And if it be objected that necessity destroys the proof of such character, by making the happiness that follows virtue a mere necessity, and no part of God's arrangement- answer, 1. Happiness follows conduct, and is a consequence of it, and not of necessity or fate: besides. Opinion of Necessity as influencing Practice, 41 2. God governs according to some rule ; and veracity and . justice seem the natural rule with One who can have no competition with His creatures. C. Nor, further, does necessity destroy the obligations and proofs of religion, such as the following : — L .The proof, from final causes, of an inteUigent Creator ; » 2. The proof, from present govemment, ofa future govemment; 3. The proof, from our moral faculty, of the final reward of virtue : Which faculty is a rule, having authority, and enforcing its decisions wilh sanctions. Every rule impUes such sanc tions. But, in Oiis rule, the sanctions are expressed in the very sense of good or ill desert connected with it, and the dread of future punisiiment Nor does any objection of necessity lie againsti this faculty or its conclusions ; the existence of the faculty being a fact, and the conclusion being drawn immediately from it. 4. This reasoning is confirmed by various facts, such as the ten dencies of virtue and vice; the punishment of vice, as mis chievous to society, and as vice. 5. The external evidence of religion, as, a. .The general consent of aU ages and countries : b. The early belief in religion, which implies either the natural ness of religion, or the Divine origin of it ; which latter is probable on various grounds : and, c. Ancient tradition of a revelation, which has force irrespective of tlie claims of any particular book, or the present purity of any religious system. • Note carefuUy, that in studying all such doctrines our facul ties are peculiarly Uable to err ; so that, though we are not to neglect them, we must be on our guard. D. After all, the objector may say, I cannot confute this argument, or answer these proofs ; nor need I. We are not free, whatever we think, and so are not to be 42 Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion. '' punished; and any systeni that affirras we are must be rejected. But answer. Experience shows The conclusion is false wherever the fallacy lies. Either we are free, and so punished; or, being necessary agents we are punished still,— now and in the life to come. From the whole gather a double conclusion : 1. Necessity, supposed consistent wth the present constitution of things, does in no sort prove. that we shall not be rewarded eternally according to our deserts; nor does it affect the proof that we shaU. It leaves untouched all religion, natural and revealed, 2. Hence the only senses in which necessity, if taught in religion, can be said to destroy religion : a. Practically, by leading atheists to encourage themselves in vice : b. ReaUy, by contradicting our experience that we are free, and the course of Nature : ' " c Though not in this sense, that it is reconcileable with Nature, but not with religion. V CHAPTER VIL OF THE GOVERNMENT OF GOD, CONSIDERED AS A SCHEME OR CONSTITUTION, IMPERFECTLY COMPREHENDED. The subject of this chapter is a favourite one with many emuient writers ; and Butler himself (Serraon xv.) has stated, it at~ large. Leibnitz has repeatedly enforced the sarae arguraent, as has Addison in the Spectator, No. 207. fmpcrfect Comprehension of God's Government. 43 Objections against ih&fact of raoral govemraent have been considered. There are others against its moral character : Is it wise aud good, and can objections to its wisdom and goodness (founded on the existence of evil) be answered? They may indirectly, thus : A. God's moral and natural governraent are so analogous, '''that it is credible His raoral government is like His natural govemment, an incoraprehensible scheme. And this general fact raay answer particular objections. Note the fact itself, 1, 2 : 1. God's natural government is an incomprehensible scheme. a. A scheme, 1, with parts and correspondences ; 2, relations between different events and actions throughout all , space ; and, 3, through all time. b. An incomprehensible scheme ; so that we can, 1, give no account of things in all their connexions; nor can we, 2, say that anything, however insignificant, is not a necessary condition of something most important 2. God's moral government is also an incomprehensible scheme : a. A scheme, as appears from ' ' 1. The connexion between the two govemments ; 2. The subservience of the natural to the moral ; and, 3. The analogy between the two. b. And so incomprehensible. Hence no objections against parts of this scheme can be insisted upon by reasonable men. 3. Our ignorance (though often overlooked) is a satisfactory ', ,' answer to objections against the wisdom and goodness of the whole arrangement, as it will further appear ' a. From the weakness ofthe assertions on which the objections J ' rest : " in some way (by repeated interpositions, or by making all acts single and unrelated), things might be better:" — which is saying but little; and is, after all, . only arbitrary assertion without proof. 44 Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion. I. b. From the nature of our ignorance, which includes the very related parts to which existing works belong. Did we see the related parts, our objections might at once cease. B. Some particular analogies between the two govemments further show the weakness of these objections.' 1. In both, means are connected with ends; and, a. In natural government, undesirable means are connected with desirable ends; and so, b. May it be in moral government Obj. And though an absurd conclusion is thence derived that evil is better than good, yet this may be answered ; for to permit evil may be better than forcibly to prevent it ; yet the non-commission of it may be better still, as health is better than disease, and yet some diseases are remedies for others which are worse. 2, In both, govemment is carried on by general laws. a. God's natural govemment is; and those laws are wisest, be cause general, though not preventing (so far as we at, present see) great irregularity. Obj. 1. It may be said that this irregularity might be prevented by dhect interposition ; but such interposition would have other and bad effects (in promoting negligence, for example). 2. And if it be said that these bad effects might be pre vented by further interposition, this is mere random talk. b. So God's moral government may be : the general laws wise and good, but admitting of irregularity, and forbidding interposition. C Obj. To the whole of this arguraent We must judge of God's govemment from what we know, not from what we do not know. At any rate such answers (founded on ignorance), to objections against God's government are answers to the proofs of it To which, reply Imperfect Comprehension of God's Government. 45 L Total ignorance precludes both objections and proof ; but partial does not. We may know, for. example, the character of an agent, and the ends he wiU pursue, but not the means he will use. So here we have distinct proofs of God's character and of His ends : how best to attain those ends we may not know. '2. Even if our ignorance invalidated the proofs of God's moral government, moral obligations would remain, because They rise frora our nature, which we cannot neglect without self-condemnation ; and, as the possibiUty of moral government is established, prudence leads us to obey them. 3. What answers objections against God's moral govemment our ignorance — does not invalidate the proofs of that government 4. The answers above given are founded not upon our 1 ignorance, however, but upon our incompetency through ignorance ; a very different thing. Our • incompetency is taught by experience, and is reaUy knowledge. PART n. OF REVEALED RELIGION. CHAPTER L OF the IMPORTANCE OF CHRISTIANITY. Introduction. — To two revelation is not obvious. classes the importance of ' a a. Some reject it as incredible or superfluous, and they are answered by the state of the heathen. b. Others neglect it (even when they admit its truth), suppos ing that it is only the teaching of Nature in another form. c. As a fact, however, God has given it, and it may thence be presumed to be important A. Christianity may be shown to be important by considering it 1, As a republication of natural religion (God, His government, laws, etc.). a. In its genuine simplicity : b. With authoritativeness— /. e., with new proofs, as miracles and prophecy. These latter add 1. To the evidence of natural religion, inasmuch as natural religion is part of revealed, and they confirm both. They also give authoritative or -n&w proofs. 2. Though Nature is in a sense a miracle, and so has its own miraculous evidences; yet, practicaUy, the miracles of Scripture are more authoritative, as is seen in two cases— a teacher working miracles among an ignorant V I Of the fmportance of Christianity. 47 people, and an intelligent inquirer who has leamt all that Nature can teach, and is waiting to have his doubts removed. c. With fiew light, especially on a future state, repentance, etc. ; d. With a visible church, having positive institutes and pubUc worship ; the first, 1, As a form ever reminding men of the reality ; and the second, 2. Instructing and reproving them ; both tending to perpe tuate and diffuse the tmth, as may be seen 3. If we compare the state of the world be/ore and since revelation was given. It may indeed be said, 4. That Christianity in this visible church has been perverted and uninfluential, and so is unimportant But answer, (a) Such reasoning sets aside all religion, for natural religion has also been perverted ; and (b) The good effects of Christianity are not small, whUe its bad effects are not effects ofit at aU. (c) These effects, moreover, are exaggerated, ¦ or are charged to Christianity as a pretence ; and (d) In all dispensations we must judge them by their tendencies, if men did their part, and not by their perversion. e. With express commands to aU Christians to preserve and transmit it. 2, As a revelation of a distinct dispensation ; . whh new truths and duties. a. New truths : redemption by the Son and Spirit ; and b. New duties to the Son and the Spirit ; which duties spring from our relations to each, as our duty to God springs , from our relation to Him ; more particularly these duties are all internal or external. 1. Internal: natural religion referring to the internal acts , or states of the heart in religion to God ; revealed, to internal acts or states in relation to the Son and the ¦•.^ Spirit These duties arise out of our relations ; nor is 48 Analysts of. Butler's Analogy qf Religion. I it important how we come to know them (by reason or by revelation) : and external; expressions, that is, of intemal states, according to revealed command : whether as to the Father, the Son, or the Spirit These duties also ariie .out of relations ; and are many of them 2. Moral ; i. e. — (a) The obligations we owe the Son are as moral as the obligation of charity ; they spring out ofthe nature of the case : (b) While the violation of them has evil consequences, and is as inexcusable in the case of revelation as in the case of reason, a truth appUed to the Son and to the Spirit Conclusion. B. Note two deductions to illustrate the foregoing and prevent mistakes. 1. Mark the distinction between moral and positive in religion. a. In moral duties we see the reason for them ; in positive we do not. b. Moral duties arise out ofthe nature of the case (relations), positive from external command. c. How we come to know relations and duties is a question that does nothing in deciding what duties are positive and what moral : external obligations due to God and Christ are positive ; though the relation of the Father to us is taught by reason, — the relation of the Son, by Scripture, etc. d. Positive institutions (though always fixed by external com-- mand) , are founded either on natural religion or on revealed. 2 Mark, that from this distinction we gather the ground of the preference given in Scripture to moral over positive duties. a. Carefully note, however, that positive duties, as a whole (though not any particular modes), are morally binding ; and the two must not be contrasted further than as they differ. , ' , Of the fmportance of Christianity, 49 b. If they interfere, fulfil the moral, because, 1. The moral has always a reason in its favour, and 2. It is itself an end, whUe positive duties are only means. C. Popularly speaking, both are commanded, and so both are binding, yet still the moral are also written in our hearts, and so are to be preferred. d. The question, moreover, is settled for us. The moral is decided to have superior claims — 1. By the nature of the case, which tells us that nothing can be acceptable to God without holiness (moral virtue), and, 2. By Scripture, which lays stress ever on the moral, and teUs us of our Lord's declarations (Matt. ix. 13, etc.), which are general and decisive. e. -Guard, however, against the mistake of supposing that be cause positive are less important than moral duties, therefore they are of no importance. Positive Divine commands lay us under a moral obUgation to obey them. C. Another deduction or inference (afterwards expanded, chap. ill.) is, that as Christianity is not discoverable by ', reason, its- scheme must be sought in Scripture ; nor is it an objection to any interpretation of Scripture that it discloses a doctrine or a precept, not contrary to reason and natural religion, but above them, that is neither discoverable through their teaching nor made obligatory by their authority. so Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion, CHAPTER IL OF THE SUPPOSED PRESUMPTION AGAINST A REVELATION, ' CONSIDERED AS MIRACULOUS. Christianity is, as we have seen (chap, i.), important Before considering particular objections to it, revelation in general is objected to ; because, from the very nature of the case, it is above Nature, and so miraculous. The miraculous ness of revelation, and miracles generally, will therefore be first considered. Are objections to revelation on this ground well founded? A. The objection lies, not against the particular doctrines of Christianity, but against revelation ; and that on one of two grounds ; either 1. Because the scheme of religion is not discoverable without revelation. But this is no just objection ; because there are in Nature innumerable things not discoverable by our natural faculties, but yet true and real. 2. Or, because revelation, as miraculous, is unlike the known course of Nature. But this is no just objection ; because a. It is not probable that everything in the unknown course of Nature, is like something in the known. b. And, even in the known course of Nature, many things are unlike one another. c. The course of Nature is not so unUke revelation as many suppose, and this will hereafter appear. - ' Whether the above examples include aU that is meant by miraculous, may be questioned. But the general idea expressed by the word being clear, note further V \ Presumption against Miraculous Revelation. 51 B. That against revelation as miraculous, or against miracles as proofs of it, there could be no presumption at the , beginning of the world ; for, 1. A miracle has reference to the course of Nature, and implies something different from it But at first no course had been established, and so there is no other objection to miracles at that time than to any other fact. 2. Or the argument may be put thus. The power exerted in creation (whether called miraculous or not), was different from what is exerted in the present course of nature ; and ,, , whether that power was exerted so as to give a revelation, is a question that affects the degree, not the kind of power put forth. If this power bc caUed miraculous, then the presumption against the use of such a power to give a ¦ revelation, is even less. 3. Add, that from history it seems that religion was not first reasoned out, but revealed— a fact that confirms natural - religion, and may remove prejudices against subsequent communications. C. Nor is there any presumption against miracles, or revelation as rairaculous, after the course of Nature has been settled ; for , L Generally, we need a second ruined world, from which to take , ¦ the analogy; and, even from that case (a single one), .our proofs would be precarious ; and, 2. Particularly, though there be presumption against mhacles, yet a. As, in common facts, even a small amount of proof in their favour may set aside the presumption against them. b. We know so little upon what the course of Nature depends, that we cannot say miracles, are more improbable than many general facts. c. Looking at the religious interests of the race, we see reasons for them. 52 Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion, d. Comparing them, as we ought, with extraordinaiy events (as comets, earthquakes), the presumption against them seems almost as unfounded as the presumption against those events. D. Hence Conclude 1. That there is no such presumption against miracles as renders them incredible, 2. That, on the contrary, as there are reasons for them, there is a presumption in their favour ; and 3. That, as compared with the extraordinary facts of Nature, there is no peculiar presumption against them at all. CHAPTER IIL OF OUR INCAPACITY OF JUDGING WHAT WERE TO BE EXPECTED IN A revelation; and THE CREDIBILITY, FROM ANALOGY, THAT IT MUST CONTAIN THINGS APPEARING, LIABLE TO OBJECTIONS, The objection to Christianity, as miraculous, has been already considered (chap. ii.). Other objections agamst its deficiencies, its doctrine of redemption, its want of universality, its evidences, are considered hereafter. In this chapter, objections against Christianity as a scheme (not against its evidences), are shown to be frivolous. It is probable, from analogy, that Christianity will contain rauch that is different FROM OUR EXPECTATIONS (or anticipations, see note 3), antj therefore objectionable. A. Apply the first part of this statement to Christianity, as a whole. It is likely to contain much that is different from our expectations. fncapacity in Judging of Revelation. 53 1; In Nature we find that God rules and instructs according to ¦ certain laws. In Scripture we are told new truths con- ^ nected with His government j and these two make together one scheme of Providence. ' 2. We are, in fact,, incompetent judges of the first, as has been shown. It is, therefore, probable that we shall be in competent judges of the second. Both are likely to appear objectionable, B. Apply this statement to instruction by inspiration. It is hkely to differ from what we expect In the case of natural religion, we know not, before experience, by what laws or means, or to what degree, or by what evidence, or in what mode, or even through what faculty it will be imparted. So in what is revealed. And, if any object that we are competent judges oni ' some points, that oral revelation, for example, is a' better means of avoiding mistakes than written, it is answered, that we are not told what God's purpose is, and so cannot compare the different means for securing it C. Hence the following conclusions : 1. As to Christianity as a whole, w'e are incompetent judges ol what may be expected in a revelation. Therefore, the only question is, whether Christianity is a real revelation ; not whether it is what we expect it to be. The only valid objection to it, if there be any, is against its evidence. 2. As to the way in which its instruction is given, the only question is, whether it is a Divine book, not whether it is such or such a book. For deficient style, or deficient evidence of genuineness, or various readings in the text, are no proofs against it, unless it was promised that a Divine revelation should be free from these presumed difficulties. And 54 Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion. Obj les?.l , "' """^'T^ "°' '^'^^ ^"y "•'^"io" that it is less clearly expressed than we hoped. '^L'^'TuT'^^t"'' '' ™*y "^^ °'^J"t'=''. that internal improbab.ht.es (that is, things contrary, to expectation) weaken external probable proof. True. But, as has been seen, real intemal improbabilities are overcome by the most common testimony. And, in revelation, we scarcely know what improbabilities are. D. To^expand this last statement, and explain the second part ofthe statement made at the outset, that revelation is likely to contam much that appears objectionable, note ' 1. That the instmction given to men and brutes respectively, is very objectionable in its limits, thus : it is objectionable a. That we should be instrt.cted in the laws of matter more easily and truly than in the cure of diseases. b. That we discover, as by accident, what years of inquiry fail to attain. ? ¦^ c. That language is liable to infinite abuse ; and is, at best ambiguous. > d. That brute instinct is. often more skilful than human prudence. , , 2. So is revealed instmction likely to be liable to similar objections, as to its character and degrees. Nor are these objections more numerous than we might expect them to be. E. Apply this reason to a particular case, to see, more clearly its force and applicability. It is said, the gifts in the apostohc age were not miraculous, because not used in an orderly manner. To which answer L Those who used them had power over them ; and the use ot them depended, as might be expected, on the prudence or imprudence of the possessor. So they are like other gifts ; ' X '\ V fncapacity in Judging of Revelation, 55 and, if it be said, these gifts should have been given only to the prudent or that prudence ought to have been added to the gift, or that God should have interposed. Answer— 2, We cannot judge what ought to have been the degree of the gift ; nor are gifts generally given in Nature according to the pmdence of those who own them. Nor is instmction generally given in common life, in such forms only as best commend it to us, F. The analogy between the natural and revealed methods of instruction, raay be further applied, L In Nature, practical rules of conduct are generally plain. So are the faith and behaviour of practical Christianity. 2, In Nature exact thought is sometimes required for the study of parts ; so in the study of parts of Scripture, 3. Progress in each department is hindered by the same, or similar, causes. 4, In Nature, as in Scripture, the full discovery of tmth seems to depend on the progress of leaming, of Uberty, and upon the diligence of the studious. All the Bible is not now understood ; nor is the whole of Nature. G. To these analogies, between the instruction imparted by the two schemes (l),«and between the two schemes themselves (2), it is objected, 1. That natural instmction is comparatively unimportant ; whereas religious instmction is essential. ' Answer— a. This distinction is not material to the argument ; which is, that Nature gives, not as we expect, but differently. - b. Some ofthe things not told us in Nature are important, and even essential, to comfort ; and c. Whatever be thought of these statements, still, neither in Nature, nor therefore in religion, does God dispense in struction according to our notions of it§ importance. 2. That Christiaiiity, being professedly a remedial system, is not $6 Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion. likely to be so open to objections or perversions, as natural revelation. Answer — a. If both are from the same hand, this an-angement is by no means incredible ; since remedies in Nature (for diseases reaUy fatal) are often late discovered, doubted, and perverted, etc. And further, on this principle of reasoning, b. If the remedies, natural or Christian, are not true, because not what we might expect, then the diseases themselves are not tme, for they also are against expectation, H. From the whole gather two conclusions ; the one negative, and the other positive. 1. Not that reason is no judge of anything in regard to revela tion (because it is not judge of everything), for reason may judge— a. Of the meaning of Scripture, and also, b. Of its morality ; that is, not whether it is what we might expect from a holy God, but whether it is plainly not contrary to holiness, and to what Nature teaches us of Him. It is true that objections are taken to Scripture morality, but they apply equally to the constitution of Nature. Particular precepts also are objected to, but they are temporary, and refer to actions, not habits ; and though liable to be perverted by enthusiasm, are of a piece with religion as a system of probation, c. Of its evidence. 2. Positively, the truth of Christianity is cleariy not affected by objections against its scheme. a. For such objections are founded upon principles which Nature contradicts. And the particular things objected to are reaUy analogous to the course of Nature. b. The scheme of Christianity may even supply positive arguments in its favour, if it differs from the schemes which enthusiasm and imposture have framed. Christianity Imperfectly Comprehended, S7 CHAPTER IV. OF CHRISTIANITY, CONSIDERED AS A SCHEME OR CONSTITUTION, IMPERFECTLY COMPREHENDED. The aphorisms of three very different men are worth quoting in connexion with this chapter. " Either nothing is mysterious," says Dr. Thomas Brown, "or everything is." "The last step of reason," says Blaise Pascal, " is to know that there •is an infinitude of things which surpass it." " Of the dark parts of revelation," says Warburton, " there are two sorts : one which may be cleared up by the studious application of well-employed talents; the others, which will always reside within the shadow of God's throne, where it would be impiety to intrude." A Christianity without mystery is a shallow faith, as nnphilosophical as it is unscriptural. It raay be true, as shown (chap, ill.), that we are imperfect judges ofthe Christian system. Still are the things objected to really wise and good ? And, before proceeding to notice these things in detail, there is a general argument, similar to the one given in Part I. chap, vit., which needs to be remembered — viz., that Christianit)' is a scheme, like God's natural government, imperfectly comprehended; that the ' whole is credibly consistent with goodness, and iUustrative of it ; and tliat, if we knew all, it would appear to be so. A. As moral govemment, so Christian, is an incomprehensible scheme. 1. It is a scheme, under the plan of Providence, seeking the final perfection of man ; beginning with our recovery, and , mvolving the office of a Messiah, a sanctifying Spirit, 58 Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion. ' invisible government over the Church, a gradual prepara tion ofthe redeemed for heaven, and a final judgment. 2. And it is a scheme imperfectly comprehended ; a mystery of godliness ; the things revealed ever running up into mysteries, and a large part of it still undisclosed. B. Note two important particular analogies between the two : 1. As the natural govemment of God, so Christianity uses, to accomplish ends, means, undesirable it may be, or foolish, yet, in Nature, none the less appropriate to secure the desired result. 2. As the natural government of God, so Christianity is carried out by general laws, a. That God's natural government is so carried on We conclude from the many cases in which we can trace those laws. " By analogy " we apply to all what we see to be tme of a part So, b. We may conclude that Christianity is carried on by general laws, even though, in particular cases, we see only the fact, and not the law, as in miracles. Hence, though some exigencies may be met by miracles, yet every exigency may not be so met ; a reason for miraculous interposition in some cases, and not in all, ^ C. Hence conclude that, as Christianity is a scheme with means and general laws, it is liable to objections frora apparent deficiencies and irregularities, which would cease if the whole case were known. C, Objections to a Christian scheme, as a fact, have been met (chap, iii.). Objections against its consistency with wisdom and goodness have been already met in this chapter. Objections to particular parts of the scherae may be met by particular analogies in Nature, In the following chapter other parts are taken up. There it is intended to notice a particular objection The System of Christianity. 59 to the scheme as a whole, involving especially a use of intricate means for the salvation of the world. No just objection to Christianity can hence arise ; for 1. In Nature and in Providence (the seasons, the progress of nations, for example,) means equally intricate and tedious are employed, so that the objection applies equally to Nature and to religion. And, further, 2; We distinguish means and ends ; while, in fact, the distinction may be absurd. And certainly, with God, means may be as important a part of the proccss as the end itself. These are expanded. CHAPTER V. OF THE PARTICULAR SYSTEM OF CHRISTIANITY ; THE APPOINT MENT OF A MEDIATOR, AND THE REDEMPTION OF THE WORLD BY HIM. The mediation of Christ has been greatly objected to, but without reason; for A. The analogy of Nature supplies no presuraption against the general notion of mediation, but the contrary : For upon the instrumentality or mediation of others we depend for our birth and nature ; for happiness and misery. B. The moral government of God, which mediation presup poses, and which religion tells us extends into another life, is natural. L Present punishment, one effect of moral govemment, is cer- 6o Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion. tainly natural, ever following vice ; and, in the same way, future punishment may naturaUy follow vice. 2. Nor need any object that, upon this supposition, justice is taken out of God's hand, and given to Nature ; for a. It is God who does what Nat'&re is said to do ; and b. In Scripture natural punishments are ascribed to God, and yet are deemed natural, as distinguished from miraculous ; and c. By "natural" is meant, not arbitrary, but just and reason able ; such, moreover, as are in accordance with general laws. 0. All the present penal consequences of vice are not always inflicted, but a provision is made to prevent them, and so may some of the future consequences be prevented. 1. Men may think that it would have been better for evil not to have existed ; still it does exist, though God often provides remedies even for such evils as are penal. 2. Such provision might have been withheld ; an arrangement severe, perhaps, but not unjust. 3. In fact, however, there is such a provision, and analogously wc may hope that it will extend into the future, so that the consequences of vice may not follow universally in all cases. 4. Some may be surprised that this is stated as a supposition only. But if the consequences of irregularities even (not vice) be so serious, and of vice often extreme misery and death, what may we not fear that the consequences of irreligion will be, looking at the disorder it introduces ? However, some of the future penal consequences of sin may be prevented. D. We have no reason, however, to suppose that these consequences can be prevented by anything we can do ; for. Tite System of Christianity. 6i 1. We know not what reasons for punishmeAt may exist, or what ' the natural consequences of vice are, and so cannot tell what can prevent them. ,2. Nature, moreover, leads to the conclusion that we cannot pre- , vent them ; for min is often the consequence of vice, nor i' I ¦ can repentance repair the evil. Our ability to repair it is often weakened ; and, even if not, we have to depend on • others. 3, Our notions of government are all against the supposition that repentance wiU prevent the future painful consequences of 4. This conclusion is favoured by the general sense of mankind, who add sacrifices to their repentance. E. The general doctrine of revelation on these questions confirras these views. It confirras our fears, and tells us of the future consequences of vice. It supposes a , state of ruin (a supposition not contrary to reason) ; teaches us that we cannot be pardoned through repentance alone, yet affirras that pardon is possible, therein revealing God's goodness in preventing punish ment and bestowing salvation through the suffering of another, all which is consistent with what we already .. know of God ; and if any object 1. That this doctrine is inconsistent with goodness ; answer, that even the supposition that the whole creation had perished would not be inconsistent with it, therefore much less is this. Or, 2. That it presupposes a degraded state ; answer, a. That Christianity does not put us into this state. b. That the fact we are in this state is confirmed by aU ex perience (the best complain, and most grow worse with age) ; and c. How we are so, and why, may be difficult to explain ; yet the Scripture account is analogous to' much around us, and to our recovery by Christ 62 Analysis of Butler's Analogy qf Religion, F, These considerations show that mediation generally is analogous to what we see in Nature; nor can any valid objection be taken to the particular manner in which Christ Interposed. 1, The doctrine of Scripture is in general, that Christ came to teach, and then to die for us. This last fact, especially set forth in the law, and clearly revealed in the gospel, 2, More particularly He appeared a. As a Prophet ; teaching the law of Nature, purely, authori tatively, with new light, and adding many truths peculiar to Himself, besides leaving us His own example, b. As King ; mling in His Church ; the number of which He is about to perfect, and to receive to glory. C. As Priest ; offering up Himself a sacrifice, universal, effica cious, and final. Men may ask how this sacrifice is availing. But this question is not answered ; our conjectures are, therefore, uncertain. Scripture teaches that He makes repent ance acceptable, and our wisdom is to accept the blessing without curiously inquiring how it affects its , end. G. Hence, since we are ignorant of much that mediation involves, objections against the scheme of mediation generally, and against the Scriptural scheme, are futile ; whetiier against ' 1, The necessity of it. 2. The nature, parts, and duties of the Mediator's office, unless such objections are founded upon the unfitness of the means to the end proposed. 3. Of unfit means, the suffering of Christ, as innocent for guilty, is supposed to be an example ; but the answer is obvious : a. In the constitution of Nature men thus suffer. b. Against that constitution the argument is stiU stronger, for Christ suffered w/««i^ar/^. ' . -. The Systein of Christianity. - 63 I V I c. In the end, aU (Christ included) will be treated according to their deserts. d. Such suffering is found, in fact, to contribute largely to the relief of man ; and e. The, reasonableness of the doctrine, and its fitness for the end, is seen in its natural tendency to vindicate God's laws, and deter men from sin. f. The objection, moreover, really means that it is not fit, because we do not see it to be so, 4.- Such objections are all unreasonable, for they are based upon our ignorance; that is, the reason of the arrangement isnot told us, and yet we object to it; they are most unreasonable ' because, so far as we can judge, it is analogous to natural facts ; besides, it is part of the doctrine in which we are not actively concemed ; further 5. From Scripture and from analogy we leam that, while our duty is made clear, we are not to expect the same cleamess in what Scripture tells us ofthe Divine conduct a. In Nature we gather mies oflife by experience. Ofthe vast scheme of Providence we know little ; so, b. Analogously in Scripture, the things not understood relate to God's part, not to human duty. In both there is much we can understand; but our duties are always clear, whe ther moral or positive, and the reasons for them; and ' even if they were not, the fact that they are commanded is sufficient to make them binding. 64 Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion. CHAPTER VI. OF THE WANT OF UNIVERSALITY IN REVELATION : AND OF THE SUPPOSED DEFICIENCY IN THE PROOF OF IT. The evidence of revelation is deficient, it is said,, and so the revelation is not true. Revelation is not universal, it is said, and therefore not true. These objections, which are made (it will be noticed) positive arguments against religion, are against both natural and revealed. Note — A. These objections are groundless, for they rest upon these two groundless suppositions : 1, That God will not bestow favour upon us, except in that de gree which we think most advantageous, 2, That God will not bestow blessings upon some, except He bestow them upon all. Suppositions which the general analogy of Nature contradicts. B. These objections are answered by analogies in God's natural governraent 1. The evidence, it is said, is doubtful, because deficient. But so is the evidence a. Of what constitutes our temporal interests ; and b. Of the best and surest means of attaining it 2. Revelation is not, it is said, universal. But so neither is the bestowal of natural gifts ; which want of universality, how ever, is no argument against God's natural government, nor against the prudent management of our affairs under it. This evidence, and the partial bestowment of tmth, illus trated in the successive ages of Judaism and Christianity ; in the condition of the heathen and of Mahometans, and of those who live under a corrupt religious system, etc; and the whole shown to be analogous to facts in Nature, and in the providence of God.' "^ Want of Universality in Revelation. 6$. C. ,This reasoning, defended by the fact, that every man will be treated according to his light and privileges; though this statement does not imply either 1, That all rrlen's religious condition is equally advantageous; or 2. That we ought not, therefore, to improve our own condition, or that of others, D.' What the reasons of this arrangement are, we cannot tell ; but it may be said, 1. Generally, that the same principle which disposed God to make various orders of creatures, and with various capacities, disposed Him to place creatures of the same order (and even the same creatures, at different periods), in different positions. 2. More particularly, it is very difficult to give a reason; as may be seen from our own case. A system like ours, implies / ' Things past and future, unknown to us, but possibly con- i taining the explanation : It requires, too, variety ; which may supply the reason. And, at all eVents, the reason why we are placed in a state of ignorance, is probably also the reason, why the reason of our being in that state is not told us. E. That this arrangement is no ground of complaint, appears from the follo\ving facts : — 1, The deficiency of Christian evidence may be part ofour intel lectual probation, intended to e.xercise our minds virtuously ' in examining the evidence. Such e.xercise in inteUectual matters may as easily test our fairness and candour as pro bation in practice. 2, It may be part of our general moral and religious probation, that it proves our character, thus: — If religion is only supposably credible, a. Serious inquiry, and moral self-control, are made obligatory; and profanity, carelessness, and presumption are thereby condemned : especially ¦ F 66 Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion. b. As our example will have influence with others ; the reason being, L That doubt supposes some evidence; and 2, The lowest evidence ought to have some practical in fluence. The degree of that influence depends on the fairness and honesty of our character ; the practical neglect of any evidence showing moral deficiency, just as the incapacity to discern it shows our intellectual deficiency. 3. It may constitute moral discipline and improvement ; as do difficulties in practice, when the truth is believed. Temptation of any kind (as to evidence, for example), exercises, and so proves, the moral principle, a. Teaching us not thoughtlessly to reject evidence, nor to conceal it, and to act virtuously, even though the results are uncertain ; and b. What is thus exercised and proved is thereby strengthened.' So that there is the same reason for deficient evidence, as for our trials ; nor is it unlikely C. That with some (whose external temptations are small), these difficulties form the chief part of their discipline; as in common life some are tried, not by having to practice pmdence, but by having to find out what pru dence is. F. After all, though it is thus far supposed that the deficiency ¦ of the evidence of religion belongs to the evidence itself, it is possible that the deficiency may be owing to something in the objector; either 1. To his fault— virant of earnestness in attention to evidence, etc., just as in practical matters ; or ' 2. To his requiring more than a popular proof of Christianity, without applying the necessary examination or knowledge. That evidence is level to the common understanding; but is liable to objections. Many see those objections, with out giving time to see through them. Still the evidence. \ Want of Universality in Revelation. 67 property regarded, or thoroughly considered, is real and conclusive. It may, indeed, be objected, 3. That, whatever the, source of this deficiency, the evidence ought to be without doubt, as the directions of earthly masters are. To which, answer — a. That wherever the fallacy lies, there is fallacy ; for in tem poral affairs, God (our Master) does not give evidence free from doubt : moreover, b. Religion differs from aU external commands. It seeks not external obedience simply, but the testing and exercise , ofour principles. That is best secured by commands less plain. Besides, God's wiU is conditional; ending in either obedience and reward, or vice and punishment G. In conclusion, as religion Implies probation, the probation may consist in the very things which are here made grounds of objection : 1, Judging from the reason of the thing, it seems that we may be tried by deficient evidence, as easily as by inattention or passion. - 2, Judging from experience, we are as often tried by causes which produce doubts (imperfect information, etc.), as by inattention or passion. 3. Hence (to sceptics), it may be said, that scepticism may spring from want of solicitude, not fi-om want of evidence; and that in daily life we act, where the probability is against success, and if only it 'impossible we raay succeed. 68 Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion. CHAPTER VIL ON THE PARTICULAR EVIDENCE FOR CHRISTIANITY. BuTLER now passes from the truths of Christianity to its evidence. He has met objections against Christianity, he now > meets objections against the proof of it In previous chapters he seeks to free the gospel from groundless objections, and so to leave it to the support of its proper evidence. In this chapter he frees the evidence itself from objections, and so leaves it with its proper force to support the gospel Having considered objections against any revelation, and against the Christian revelation particularly, consider now the positive evidence for Christianity, and the objections against that evidence; the whole divisible into two parts — (1.) The evidence from miracles and prophecy ; (ii.) The direct and collateral evidence considered as making one argument i. A. On miracles as evidence for Christianity, note 1. The Bible gives the same evidence for miraculous as for common history. a. The narrative of miraculous and of common history is equaUy plain. b. The accounts of miracles are quoted as genuine. c. The accuracy of the account of miracles is attested by con temporaneous and by later events. d. And the most obvious explanation of the reception of this history is its tmthfulness, so that e. It ought to be received tiU there is reason for rejecting it. 2. Paul's Epistles, which are proved genuine, are an additional and peculiar proof of the miracles of Christianity. Particular Evidence for Christianity, 69 . a. Additional, because Paul received the gospel direct from God ; and b. Peculiar, because he speaks of a great variety of miracles as wrought by himself and by others, and as admitted. 3. Christianity demands to be received for its miracles— a fact peculiar to it — and it was received at first on that ground, a. The demand is peculiar, for Mohammedanism was not founded upon miracles ; and other systems, whether of popery or of paganism, were founded upon alleged miracles, only after they had been instituted, and not BEFORE, b. In part Christianity was received on the ground of its miraculousness, a fact which, under the circumstances, proves the reality of these miracles, and is testimony for them, additional to the testimony of history. Conclusion. Hence there is a large historical evidence in favour of Christianity which ought to be credited. B, The objections to this reasoning are obvious : L Under the influence of enthusiasm men lay down their lives for every kind of folly : Answer, a. Perhaps so, when the foUies are matters of opinion ; but here the thing attested, in the case of the first Christians, is fact, and for testimony to the reality of facts en thusiasm cannot account. b. And, if it be said that the evidence of religious facts is weakened by enthusiasm, answer, - 1. Yes, if the facts are in themselves incredible, a thing not shown ; and, besides, 2. ReUgious facts, as attested, are not more liable to the influence of enthusiasm than common facts are to other influences, party spirit, etc., which yet are believed. 2. A mixture of enthusiasm and knavery, it is objected, weakens the evidence for miracles. 70 Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion. That there is this mixture in human nature is certain, but it is seen also in common matters, which yet are beUeved on testimony. 3. However, men have been themselves deluded by pretences to miracles. Answer, Not more so than by other pretences, of honesty or benevolence, for example 4. Fabulous miracles have historical evidence ; yet, Answer. Even if this be admitted, that would not prove the falsehood of Christian miracles, even though they fumish a precisely analogous example. C. Conclusions : — 1. From objections, note a. They weaken the evidence, but cannot destroy it b. Nor can that evidence be destroyed but by proof of the un- tmstworthiness ofthe witnesses. c. This very mode of speaking implies that there is something in the evidence itself ; an important reflection on such a subject d. It should be remembered that the importance of Christianity and its precepts on veracity must have made the early Christians pecuUarly careful not to deceive or be deceived. 2. Frora the -whole argument it is plain that the proof of miracles is of real weight and sufficient : and so men ought to admit it where there is nothing in reUgion itself incredible. D. On evidences from prophecy the following reraarks are iraportant : — L Not perceiving the wJu)le sense of a prophecy does not weaken the proof of foresight, nor does the not understanding the whole fulfilment 2. If a long series of prophecies be applicable to certain events, the applicability proves such an application is intended. This meets the objection, that the application of each prophecy apart may not be apparent, and so was not intended. ' ' ' ^ • . t^ Particular Evidence for Christianity. yi Note the analogous case of mythological or satirical writing ; and mark, that Old Testament prophecy was understood by the Jews generally as it now is by Christians. 3. A prophecy may be completed in a sense different to the sense of the prophet, and a prophecy may seem applicable; to other events than the aUeged completion ; but neither weakens the evidence, for a. The Scriptures are the work, not of the men who wrote thera, but of the Spirit, and the forraer may not have known aU the meaning. b. The applicability to more than one event may have been intended by the Spirit Conclusion. The conclusion is, that this evidence is real, though not peifect, and needs fahness and modesty in weighing it. E. On other direct and collateral evidence, note L Introduction. This evidence is peculiarly important, for a. It is what is commonly given us in practice ; and . ¦ b. Such evidence, being circumstantial, is, when taken together, of great weight, and , c. Would if considered simply as matter of fact, have great influence with unbelievers. d. It is intended then to prove that God has given us a system of natural religion and of revealed ; the first ascertainable by reason, and thc second not ; the latter intended to secure our recovery and hoUness. , 2. Note what this religion is, as a real or supposed history. ^ a. It teaches the creation ofthe world as God's world ; reveals the Son as Creator. b. It teaches the histoi-y ofreligion in its various aspects. c. It teaches as much of politics as is needed to make the history of religion complete. 72 Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion. d. It gives an account of. the origin of mankind, and a thread of history extending over 4,000 years, with many particulars which need to be carefully noted, and ending in the establishment ofthe Christian faith. 3. Let it be asked, "Is this true?" and take, as answer, the, following facts, first separately, and then Unitedly. - a. Natural religion has owed its establishment in a large degree to the Scriptures, as many allow, so that Scripture has claims upon our natural piety. Nor must it be thought that the establishment of natural religion by re velation destroys the proof from reason. b. The first parts of Scripture are of acknowledged antiquity, I and its history and chronology credible, both from 1. Common history, and 2. Intemal evidence, c. The Jews, the peculiar people of God, owed most of their history to their religion, and preserved (and they alone)' the tmths of natural religion uncormpted. d. A Messiah has appeared, fulfiUing ancient prophecies, whose religion, sometimes above, but never contrary to reason, became the religion of the worid ; the Jewish polity in the mean time destroyed, and the Jews scattered yet preserved ; each part, and much more the whole, in ' fulfilment of prophecies, supplying fresh evidence. Note further, 1. That, though the immediate facts may be explained on natural principles, the correspondence between these facts and predictions cannot, as in the case of the dis persion of the Jews and the birth of the Messiah. 2. There are to be added many prophecies still in course of fulfilment, the fulfilment of which is highly probable from the fulfilment of prophecy in the past. e. Let all this be considered apart and together, and then add other obvious examples of harmony between prophecy and facts. ' ' V V Obf ect ions against Arguing from Analogy. 73 F. In conclusion,' let it be remembered, I, The force of this evidence depends on the whole taken unitedly ^ and must be admitted to have great weight. 2. Even as far as it has been here given, the evidence is more than human— miracles, prophecies, other proofs, , 3. These proof, taken together, not only add to the evidence— they multiply it, 4, And, though proofs to the contrary may also be set down, yet in matters of conduct (not in case of events or of specula tion) the question ofwhich view is safer is important A mistake on the one side, in rejecting Christianity, is more ., ' dangerous than a mistake on the other, in accepting it: and the more so, as, 5, C:hristianity is tme, not only if one particular fact prove it, ' but unless all the things herein aUeged can reasonably be supposed to be accidental, ¦ 6. There being no presumption against Christianity as mhaculous, ^ or against its scheme or parts, this evidence, though it may ,be lessened, cannot be destroyed. ' CHAPTER VIIL ON THE OBJECTIONS WHICH MAY BE MADE AGAINST ARGUING FROM THE ANALOGY OF NATURE, TO RELIGION. Against reasonings founded on analogy some may raise objections ; and a few of these it is intended here to consider. A, Enumerated 1—5. It is alleged, for example, 1, It is a poor thing to meet difficulties in revealed religion by saying that there are the same difficulties in Nature, when we want to clear religion from aU difficulties. Answer, 74 Analysis of Butlers Analogy of Religion. a. The thing wanted is, it seems, to comprehend Providence and God. b. To reason from the known (natural religion), to the unknown (revealed) is not a poor thing, compared with no know ledge ; so it is aUowed in science and medicine. c. If natural religion is admitted to be true, it is important to show that objections to revealed reUgion apply equally to natural, for so revealed reUgion is vindicated. 2. But it is surely a strange way of convincing men of the obligations of religion to show that they have as little reason for their worldly pursuits. Answer, a. Religion is a practical thing, as business is; and, like reasons, or any reasons, may be sufficient to guide us in both cases, and ought, from prudence, to guide us. b. If the objection be that religion should not have doubtful evidence ; then note that worldly pursuits are often doubtful, yet men foUow them. Besides, the case of religion, though not free from all doubt, is much stronger than the case of worldly conduct. 3. It is a strange way of vindicating God's character in religion for goodness and justice, to show that like objections lie against Providence, when we ought rather to answer the objections themselves. Answer : a. The treatise does not profess to vindicate God's character, but to show men their obligations; and to do this, aU that is needed is to show that, for aught we know, the objec tions are consistent with goodness and justice, and may be even proofs of them. b. It is attempted to answer objections to God's goodness and justice, not by showing that the like objections {supposed toiulusive), be against Providence, but by showing that the objections are not conclusive, applying equally to God's present govemment as a matter of fact c. Even if these objections are not answered in this way, the facts of religion remain as credible, in spite of the objec tions. 'I Obf ect ions against Arguing from Analogy. 75 d. Though objections to the reasonableness of reUgion cannot be answered without considering its reasonableness, ob jections against its credibility may : for L It is a systera of facts, and 2. Though sometimes useful to show how reasonable any part is, this cannot always be necessary, and 3. The obligations of religion depend upon the reasonable ness, not of thc system, but of the practice, and so it is enough if in the system there be nothing unreasonable; and e. Analogy may supply no answer to objections against the goodness of the system, but it does to objections against the credibility of the system as a matter of fact This is what is meant in these remarks. 4. Religion rests on unsatisfactory evidence; that is, on evidence not sufficient for certainty ; but a. So is the evidence of any system of life — what is best — what rules will secure it ? Religion, theiefore, is like every other real thing in this world, its evidence real, but not certain ; uncertainty belonging to our very condition. b. Moreover, religion is simply intended to try and discipline our virtue. It is a probation, as it would not be, if its evidence were overbearing. c. So that the only question is, whether its evidence is sufficient in pmdence to influence thejudgment aud practice, while thus testing our virtue. 5. In fact (it will be said) men are not influenced by this evidence, and that is a fatal objection. Answer : a. The question is not what men do, but what they ought to do in practice. ,b. The objection is nothing against religion, which answers its end in testing men, whether they are influenced by it or not. c. It is aUowed the evidence of religion has some weight, but so it ought to have some influence ; and if such influence be allowed to this treatise, it has not missed its end. , 76 Analysis of Butler's Analogy^ of Religion. B. On the argument of the treatise Butler notes, 1. That he reasons, not upon his own ^inciples, but upon (that is, notwithstanding) the principles of his opponents, admit ting fatalism, and affirming nothing of the moral fitness of moral acts, independent of the wiU of the Creator. , 2, He treats religion siraply as a matter of fact ; as a history which, moreover, reveals as facts God's moral government, present and future, etc., and which are proved, not demon stratively (a thing impossible in matter of fact), but prac tically. Abstract questions, and the principles of things involved in all those facts, are not discussed. 3. Hence the force of this treatise. a. To those who hold liberty and moral fitness it is an additional proof of the tmth of religion, and to those who deny them it is a new proof. b. To believers, it strengthens existing evidence, and answers objections; to unbelievers, it proves Christianity credible, and, ^ c. More generally, analogy confirms aU facts to which it can be appUed, and is the only proof of most It is on the side of religion, and ought to be followed especiaUy by aU who profess to follow Nature. >/ DISSERTATION I. OF PERSONAL IDENTITY. The question to which this dissertation is devoted is metaphysically of considerable interest. Does each man continue, through his whole existence, the same thinking being; and if so, wherein does the sameness consist, and what is evidence of it ? The question is now not often discussed ; but in the writings of the last century it was one of the most popular subjects of inquiry.^ ,, As the question is generally expressed, It Is, unhappily, ambiguous.^ Person or substance, for example, may mean, or be taken to include, the material elements of which the body is composed ; and as it is known the human frame is gradually changed ' every few years, the question whether a man is in this sense, and for seven years together, the same person or , substance, must be answered in the negative. It raust be noticed also that sameness (like identity) is used in two senses. It \% properly applicable to a single object which we affirm to be not another. In a secondary sense it is applied to objects which are very much alike ; as when we say that one house is built of the sarae raaterials as another, raeaning that the materials are of similar quality. In the first sense, sameness does not involve the idea of sirailarity — "The same person, but how altered !" In the. second sense similarity is essential ' See Martinus Scriblerus, ch. vii. ' Shaftesbury's Characteristics, iii. 172, ed., 1745. l\ '?¦-' 7$ Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion. The secondary sense admits of degrees ("nearly the same"); the proper sense does not^ It is in forgetfulness of this last distinction that some have stated the question to be, whether the thinking being (person or substance) continues to possess hke qualities through its whole existence. In fact, men's minds, affections, judgments, all change. A man raay even be renewed, and still be, in the proper sense, the sarae man. The question is really, freed from all ambiguities. Does each man continue, througli his whole being, the same person, or does he become another f a question that carries with it its answer. What constitutes this sameness, and what is its evidence, are questions less easily answered. Clearly, the sameness does not depend on the identity of the particles of our bodies, nor even upon the possession of any body. Through life, we have the same body ; that is, in the secondary sense of same, our bodies are "natural;" the resurrection (or spiritual) body is not yet given to us : in the proper sense of same our bodies are not the same, they are ever changing. Nor does this sameness consist in or depend on our consciousness, as Locke seems to have held. In states of disease or in intemperance a man may lose all consciousness of identity, and yet not cease to be the same person. It is true our conviction of personal identity and the idea of it raay be obtained through conscious ness and raemory, as in fact they are, but our identity itself is prior to this consciousness, as (to use Butler's comparison) truth is prior to knowledge. I ara now conscious of existence ; I ara conscious, moreover, of the memory of prior states of existence : I conclude, therefore, instinctively and intuitively, as Butler seeras to teach, that the being (or person) in whom this double consciousness inheres is the same being, and not another. The evidence is intuitive, and the identity is of the ^ Whately's Zo^ic, book iv., iv, § I, Of Personal Identity. 79 V conscious substance or thinking being — not of consciousness, still less of material substance,' The importance of this speculation, as a practical question, in connexion with a future life is obvious. If in that life each raoral agent is uo longer the same, but another, moral government, in the largest sense, is at an end. That govern ment implies the dependence of the condition of our future selves upon our present behaviour. It is also worth noting, that the consciousness of mental identity is a presumption, as Dr. T. Brown has intiraated, that the raind is not material. It seems free at least from the common quality of all that is material — liability to change and decay. " The sameness of person " implied in our living in a future life has created strange difficulties, and stranger solutions of them ; ending in the denial that we shall ever enter it Hence it may be worth considering. What "personal identity "is, is a question not easily defined. It is clear, however, 1., In relation to consciousness, That the comparison of two or more acts of consciousness of one's self gives the idea of this identity, and proves it. Yet such consciousness does not mahe the identity, nor is it necessary to it The notion that consciousness makes identity seems to sprino- from the fact, that consciousness is inseparable from our idea of person or thinking substance ; and so sameness of , , consciousness, it is concluded, makes sameness of person. In fact, however, wc may be the very persons who did past acts, though the acts are all forgotten. 2. In relation to material substance or properties, identity or sameness is generaUy used in a secondary sense only ; to ' See Reid's Works, Hamilton's edition, pp. 344 and 350. So Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion. indicate the qualities possessed or the uses to which things may be applied. A tree is the same, though all the material particles of it are changed, and tho properties inherent in those particles, and inseparable from them, have been withdrawn and succeeded by others. Conclusion. Personal identity, therefore, is neither identity of consciousness, nor identity of material qualities or proper ties ... It is really, as Locke's statements imply, the sameness of the person, or conscious substance, or thinking being : those terms having the same meaning. 3. Objections : 1. But, it is said that identity is ascertained by two or more acts of consciousness : can we be sure that those two acts refer to the same person ? Answer : As sure as that two perceptions of one object are to be referred to the same object 2. Others go further, and say consciousness is personaUty ; and as the first is successive, and ever changing, so is the second. Answer : Then is not our present self interested in the self of yesterday or of to-morrow ; for certainly our consciousness in each case differs. Is this true ? And if it be said we are the same, as far as we remember ; then, it is answered, that this either gives up the question, uses " same "in a nevv sense, or maintains the absurdity that personality is the same, while consciousness, which alone constitutes it, is not. The futility of objections to this "sameness," founded on variations in consciousness and actual changes of raaterial substance, is thus proved: — a. The supposition that a man may become another man is (1) contradicted by our natural sense of things ; and (2) even if true, is never applied to temporal concerns, and so ought not to religion. b. Suppose a being without memory, yet with life. It will continue the same while it hves, though not able to Of Personal Identity. 8i sr v, ' remember previous states. Add memory, suppose some states remembered and others forgotten, why doubt that it is still the same being as before ? c. All are conscious that a man is thc same person as far back as he remembers. But personality is either a sub stance or a property. If a substance, then consciousness proves the sameness of substance. If a property, then it proves the sameness of the property, and therefore the sameness of the substance, for the same property cannot be transferred. 3. But does not our conviction of personal identity, or memory on which it rests, deceive us? We are conscious of sameness, are we the same? An objection which leads to absurd results, for (a) if we cannot tmst consciousness or a perception of memory, neither can ' we our reasoning, which includes memory ; and besides (b) it requires us to prove the tmth of perceptions or faculties, by means of the very faculties we suspect and eondenm. G 02 DISSERTATION IL OF THE NATURE OF VIRTUE. To appreciate this dissertation, we need to keep in mind the theories in vogue when it was published. Within a hundred years Hobbes had published his theory of Human Nature, in which he taught that personal gratification was the sole end of every act, that every exercise of passion or faculty was equally authoritative, and that raan has no moral faculties of perception or action. Cudworth and Clarke held in opposition to this theory that the distraction between right and wrong is eternal, and that the quality of moral , acts is discerned by our reason. The first and last parts of Hobbes' theory Butler here refutes; the second he notices in his sermons. He admits, with Clarke, that the distinction between right and wrong is eternal, and that the distinction is founded on the fitness of things; but with- characteristic wisdom he seeks the evidence of this distinction and one foundation for it in human nature. He holds also that our approbation of virtue is not an act of reason simply, but an eraotion. His account of the origin of the idea of merit, and of its connexion with a reflex sense, is probably taken from Shaftesbury, to whose " Characteristics " he frequently refers. By giving prudence a place among the vhtues, he opposes Hutcheson, allows whatever of truth is to be found in Hobbes' systera, and explains it By denying that prudence is the whole of virtue, he meets the abuse which Hobbes committed, and which some modern writers have revived. Benevolence T Of the Nature of Virtue. 83 ¥ he reckons a most important virtue, and yet denies, against Leibnitz, that all virtue is resolvable into it. In his doctrine of a moral sense he agrees substantially with Hutcheson, his contemporary, and in the iraportance he attaches to the distinction between mere acts and the dispositions or principles from which they spring, he condemns Hobbes and sanctions Malebranche. , In his thhd division he gives an idea of the "fitness of moral acts;" an idea more practical at all events than that of Clarke. His fifth division answers by anticipation the theory of Bentham, that virtue is a regard for the happiness of others ; as the dissertation throughout answers the theory of Paley. Of course he maintains that virtue and happiness generally coincide, and in the long run will always comcide —the first parts of the Analogy being largely based on this view ; but he denies that happiness or interest can be a rule to us, our^ rule being, in truth, God's wil, as revealed in His word' or in the moral nature He has given. A. Introduction. 1. Moral government impUes a moral nature and moral faculties. 2. Proofs ofthe existence of such faculties are various. 3. Nor is there doubt as to the general qualities which these faculties approve, such as veracity, justice, and a regard for the public good. B. Note then a few things concerning it. 1. Its object is not events but actions in connexion with prin ciples or character ; including therein will and intention. without necessary regard to the actual /^a/^r ofthe agent. 2. Our sense of actions as good or bad implies a sense of good or ill desert, which again involves ,' a. That they deserve punishment Or reward, b. Irrespective of any mischief or advantage to society ; for an innocent action, which is yet mischievous, would be , differently regarded. ,, . 84 Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion. c. Ill desert supposes guUt, and seems necessarily connected with misery. d. In common cases of virtue good desert is thought but smaU, because little virtue may induce men to act well. e. In vice ill desert is lessened according to the temptation. 3, 111 desert implies a comparison of an act with the capacities of the agent ; compare a child or idiot and a man. Unfit, unnatural, describe this perception, 4. Pmdence (a reasonable desire to secure happiness) is approved, and imprudence condemned. a. This feeling quite independent of the tendency of impru dence to lessen happiness. We condemn the conduct, while pitying the condition. b. Though not so strenuously condemned as falsehood or cruehy, because (1) impmdence brings immediately its punishment, and is so self-corrective, and (2) then punish meut excites pity, which lessens displeasure, c. Still it is condemned. d. Hence pmdence is a species of virtue, and impmdence of vice, e. Whether or not we give them these names. 5. Virtue is not wholly benevolence, or vice whoUy the opposite ; for if they were a. Benevolence would be approved equally to whomsoever it was shown, and falsehood would be condemned only as injurious. ' b. To take from one and give to another, so adding to the sum of happiness, would be a virtue, whatever the moraUty. c. Injustice would be no fault, if it added to the sum of happi ness ; moreover, d. We are so made that we condemn falsehood, etc., without respect to overbalance of happiness, so that even if benevolence be God's sole end, it is not ours. e. Hence moral government must consist, not in the exercise y'i Of tlie Nature of Virtue, 85 of benevolence simply, but in treating men according to their moral nature. f. Most, perhaps, agree in these last principles, yet many seem disposed to hold that the whole of vice consists in its tendency to increase misery — a terrible mistake, which if admitted would excuse many flagrant crimes. g. And in tmth creatures like men know not what they are about, when they attempt to promote happiness other wise than through veracity and justice, h. When these are not opposed, however, then benevolence is our duty, L Caution : though veracity is our mle, this does not forbid all acts or words not designed to deceive, nor likely to deceive, but through want of care and thought § — "S : — '^ r- ^ :-'' — --° — —— ----^ SERMONS UPON HUMAN NATURE. There are two ways of treating morals. One begins from the abstract relation of things, as in the systeras of Cudworth and Clarke ; the other begins with the nature of man. In these discourses the latter order is adopted, and the author mtends to show in what sense virtue consists in following man's nature, and vice in deviating from it Man's nature, it must be carefully marked, includes two distinct things : the parts or elements of which it is composed, and_the relation or connexion of those parts. The frst sermon is devoted to the consideration of the " distinct parts of our internal frame." It is there shown that these parts are distinct, and not resolvable, as some have supposed, into one or more elements, as benevolence or self-love. The parts are also enumerated and classified. The second and third sermons discuss the relation between the several elements of our nature, proving the superiority, as a principle of action, of self-love over passion, and of conscience over both. Frora man's nature or constitution, as thus explained, it is shown that virtue is following nature; i.e., it is obedience to the principles of action of which that nature is coraposed in due subjection to the laws which subsist among them. This view of the connexion of the three sermons is important, and is taken partly frora Butler's own preface, which should be carefully read — and partly frora the close of the thhd sermon. For a brief view of some doctrines which Butler quietly refutes, see Introductory Note to the " Dissertation on 90 Analysts of Butler's Analogy of Religion. Virtue.'' "In these serraons," says Mackintosh, "Butler has taught triiths more capable of being exactly distinguished from the doctrines of his predecessors, more satisfactorily established, more comprehensively applied to particulars, more rationally connected with each other, and, therefore, more worthy ofthe name of discovery, than any with which we are acquainted." Sermon i. Human nature— xa. its principles, private and social. II. Human nature— \n its constitution ; or these principles in relation to each other ; the. supremacy of conscience. in. Human nature, as thus explained, in relation to virtue, SERMON' L A. Original reference of the text : each member of the body of Christ connected with the rest for the good of the whole. B. Applying this principle, there are tendencies in man to his own good, and tendencies to the good of society : distinct in themselves, though coincident in their results. 1 L There is in man a natural principle of benevolence, which is to 1 , society what self-love is to the individual. Proofs : friendship, compassion, parental love. These coincide in their results, and each requires the exercise of the other, a fresh proof that we are made for both. (Note on Hobbes' account of benevolence, that (1). It is love of power. (2) Origin of this theory, and un satisfactoriness of it (3) Cases in which benevolence cannot be love of power. (4) If true, cruelty, when displaying more power than kindness, is more benevolent. (6) A question of fact, and proved by facts. (6) Whence it appears that benevolence is as independent a thing as resentment, though needing cultivation.) a.b. t Upon Iiuman Nature. 91 2. There are in man other affections contributing to public and private good. a. They may be classified thus : Passions distinct from bene volence, tending to pubUc good ; passions distinct from self-love, tending to private good. (Note, on the distinction between self-love and other affections. They differ in themselves, though sometimes using the same means of gratification. 1. Difference where the same means are used ; hunger ' shame. ' 2. Difference where the same means are nbt used. . Note on this classification. Hunger and desire of esteem : theforraer not self-love • the latter not benevolence.) ' b. Social affections have respect to others, though tending also ' to individual good. c. The public good is not necessarily contemplated m each , act by men themselves. d. Conclusion. 3. There is in man a conscience or reflex sense, whereby we survey ourselves and pass sentence on our acts. a. Its tendency to the good of society. b. Shown to differ from affection. c. Proved to exist d. Not intended to compare its relation to public and private good, but to note that it tends to both, especiaUy the former. ,; ¦, Conclusion from these three-fold facts : men are made for , , society, as weU as for themselves, whence may be drawn a new picture of human nature and of the relations of men. Nationalities, etc., spring from their nature more than from other causes. Obj. There are in man tendencies mischievous to society ¦ answer. 93 Analysis of Butler's Ahalogy of Religion. a. So are there tendencies mischievous to himself ; so that if the good of others iS not part of our nature, neither ' ' is self-love. - , . ,b. But these are good tendencies abused. Note on envy and emulation. They differ not in their end, which is equality and superiority, but in their means. The end good ; the means, in the case of envy, bad. C, There are exceptions to the rule in both cases. Some have no aifection for others ; some, none for tiiemselves, Ex. Summary. Men are led by their nature to seek the happiness of themselves and also of others, though it must be noted (a) that men fulfil those duties imperfectly, and (b) often violate their nature in both respects, SERMONS IL, IIL 1. Morality, or the course God intends meri to take, may be known from our nature. a. Moral obUgation admits this kind of proof. b. Man's nature may be knovra, and so God's intention, though with some difficulty. c. Such reasoning is as just, as that from our physical con stitution. '"- X The elements of our nature have been aheady ascertained and so morality may be defined. 2. But herein, it is objected, there can be no law. " Nature " means passion, emotion, reflection, yet these differ in different men : it is their " nature," therefore, to follow the strongest. So that vice and morality, the violation of mies and the observance of them are alike natural ; answer, a. Ancient writers and Scripture concur neverlheless in affirm ing a " natural law," and in describing vice as deviation from that law. j; ¦ .1 upon Human Nature. 93 b. Nature, moreover, has different meanings ; 1, It means any principle in man, whatever its kind or degree, as anger, benevolence. This cannot be the meaning here, for in this sense angeris both "natural" and unnatural. 2, It means any principle that is strongest : pride is the nature of a proud man. This meaning must be re jected : for in this sense, vice is often following nature. 3, It means a good law, not identical with feeling, though it is said to be written on the heart 3. This law of nature is conscience, with the prerogative qf supremacy over other principles. a. Some such supremacy shown from what is unnatural; following desires like bmtes. b. Some such supremacy shown from what is natural, making passion subservient to self-love ; whence one principle is clearly superior to another. c. Such supremacy part of the idea of conscience ; not in fact perhaps (power), but at least of right (authority) : d. Hence it has not only some place in our nature, but the first ; passion and interest may rebel ; stiU its authority and rights are sacred. e. If this be questioned, suppose that conscience has no su premacy, then nothing done in accordance with natural feeling or passion is unnatural or wTong. Parricide and filial obedience, being both expressions of emotion, are equally approved. 4. The constitution of human nature, thus explained, gives rules of virtue, and creates an obligation to obey them. a. A constiution implies not only parts, but parts in their connexion and dependency. b. A constitution is violated, not only by removing parts but by giving to the lower the supremacy; hence the saying that injustice is contrary to nature. (Note on the meaning of "a constitution." 94 Analysis of Butler's Analogy of Religion. 1. Constitution defined, in relation to man especially, f 2. Its nature iUustrated, 3. Constitution conceived of as perfect when, virtuous ; though actually imperfect.) c. Whence man, having in his make parts lower and supreme, IS a law to himself. ^' "^^^onlw ^"' '^'^"^'^ ^'" '''^ "'° '""'' important qualities 1. It is easily appUed, and 2. It brings with it its own obligation. " - 5. Against this law it is objected— a. It teaches us to regard others, and places us under restraints : better be free, and seek only our own good. Answer- I. You cannot disregard others, and secure your own good. 2. Nor can you gain anything without restraints of some kmd. b. To which it is objected again- Then we are it seems to seek happiness, and so far to regard others and practice restraints, as these restraints bring greater convenience ; hence We agree,ani our own happiness is, after all, h seems, the measure and end of virtue. Yes, only note, 1. That not vice, but virtue, secures happiness. 2. That vice, not virtue, has most restraints, especiaUy when virtue becomes habitual However, 3. Duty and interest (i. e., happiness) really coincide ; gene-, raUy even here, and certainly in the end. Conscience and enlightened self-love therefore lead the same way, though of the two the former is supreme. Summary. V y^ \'t'' EDUCATIONAL WORKS published by ^h^ 'gzlxQionsi "^xntt §ocut^. LONDON : KNIGHT, fRINTER, MIDDLE STREET, B.C. The Analogy of Religion to the Constitution and Course of Nature; also Fifteen Sermons. By JosapH Butler, d.cu, Bishop of Durham. With a Life of the Aiillior, a copious Analysis, Notes, and Indexes, by Joseph Angi;s, d.d. Crown Svo. as, cloth boards. Ditto, The Analogy, with the three Sermons on Human Nature only. Crown Svo. is. cloth boards. The Bible Handbook; or, an Introduction to the Study of Sacred Scripture. By J. Angus, d.d. izmo edition map, Ss, 6d. calf. Cloth bds. ss. Half-Bound 7s. Handbook Of the English Tongue. By J. Angus, d.d. izmo. 5^. doth Boards, ji. half-bound. 8*. 6rt. calf. Handbook of English Literature, By J, Angus, d.d. ss- cloth boards ; 6s. 6d. extra boards ; -js. half-bound ; Zs. 6d. calf. Handbook of Specimens of English Literature. By J. Angus, d.d. i2mo. Sf, 6d. cloth boards ; js. dd. half-bound ; 91. calf. Wayland's Moral Science; viiih Notes, &c. By Dr. Angus, ramo. jj. cloth boards. The Wisdom of our Fathers. Each with Memoir. 2j. 6,/. in glazed cloth ' covers. I. Selections from Archdishop Leighton. 3. Selections from Lord Bacon. 3. Selections from Thomas Fuller. 4. Selections from Isaac Baurow, d.d. 5. Selections from Robert South, d.d. 6. Selections from Stephen Charnock, d.d. Paley's Evidences of Christianity, with Introduction, Notes and Supple ment, BytheRev,T.R. BlRKs,A,M, i2mo. 31. cloth boards. 5i. Si half-bound. Paley's Hora Paulina; with Hone Apostolica:. By Rev. T. R. Birks. 3*. doth boards. '5*. €if. half-bound. Handbook to the Grammar of the Greek New Testament. Together with complete Vocabulary, and nn Explanation of Uie chief New TesUment Synonyms. By the Rev. S. G. Green, d.d. Svo. js. 6d. cloth boards. 1 1 •JgUt aUclifltottSi "(Erjut .grwictB'i* OEitttrttiottaX JJxxhltrathmfli The Resurrection of our Lord Jesus Christ, an Historical Fact. With an Examination of Naturalistic Hypotheses. By the Rev. John Kennedv, d.d. Author of ff'orA a»d ConJlUt, etc Crown 8vo. ! m. td. cloth boards. Critical Handbook. A Guide to the Study of the Greek New Testament. By E. a Mitchell, d.d. Map, Diagrams, etc. 3»- 6ared by Captain Conder, of the Palestine Exploration Fund. Crown Svo. 31. 6d. cloth boards. Biblical Atlas and Scripture Gazetteer. With Sixteen finely Engraved Coloured Maps by W. and A. Keith Johnson, and a very elaborate Gazetteer. 5i. cloth boards. Grounds of Christian Hope: a Sketch of the Evidences of ChrisU^ity. Iiv STANLEY LEATHES, M,A„ Prebendary St. Paul's, Professor of Hebrew, King's College, Crown Svo, 41. 6d. cloth boards The Chain of Life in Geological Time: a Sketch of the Origin and Succes- sion of Animals and Plants. By J. VT. Dawson, ll,d Author of^«5lc JPPB •!• PE]M -t- 7I]S[D '^ PENCIL -5- gE^IE^. t^ \[3 Irish Pictures (Continued from pa ^e -z.) A Series of Imperial Svo finely UlustratQcl Table Books (size of page, 11 by 1\ Ins). Bound in handsome cloth, gilt, EIGHT SHILLINGS EACH, or for special prosontatlon, in mo rocco, elegant, 26s. each. IltTSU riCTURKS. Drawn with Pen and Pencil, By Richard Lovett, m.a. With a Map and over one hundred Illustrations from Sketches and Photographs. Imperial Svo, 8s., handsome clolh boards, gilt edges, or 28s. in morocco, gilt. *'A really splendid volume."— Cork Herald. "The illustrations arc ex cellent." — Irish Ecchsiaslical Gazette, JjOKDON PICTIfJiKS. Drawn udth Pen and Pe^icil. By the B. KrCHARD Lovett, M.A. , Author of "Norwegian Pictures." "Jrish Pictures," etc. Profusely Illustrated, 8s. handsome cloth, gilt. "The handsome form of the book, with its admirable print ing, is fullyjustificd by the inte resting nature of its contents." — The Times. "This pleasant, chatty account of London — with just enough arcbffiology and historv to in struct and yet not to bore — is the very book to interest both Ihe dweller and the visitor to the metropolis." — The Record. *' One of the bent books written on London. The style is graphic, the usual humdrum statistics are happily absent, and historical and geographical Lon don is portrayed in a most in teresting manner. The book is nicely printed, well-bound, and is admirably suited for presenta tion." — The Metropolitan. "An interesting book, admi rably adapted for being taken away from thc metropolis by country cousins, or by American and Colonial kinsfolk.',' — The Graphic. L°^P,TUBES -:?;i;-(Hi r; i'i, PATERNOSTER ROIV, LONDON; and o/ all Booksellers. rilE RELIGIOUS TRACT SOCIE'/'YS LIST, HANDSOME GIFT-BOOKS FOR AXiy liBCRK.iTIONS. A popular Encyclopaedia for Boys. Edited bj' G. A. Hutchison. Including chapters bv J. N, MaSKELVNE, Lt.-Col. CuTlfKLL, JV. Gordon Stables, r.n., Kev. A. N. Malan, m,a., C. Stans- field-Hicks, Dr, Sthadling, and others. With nmny En gravings. Quarto. A splen did Giit-book or Prize fnr Boys. 528 p.igcs (Zh by oi). Ss. cloth boards, gilt cclges. " No more valuable g;ift-book could bc chosen for young people with active brains."— !S«//(/ti'<(y hei'iciv. Tll±: QIRJj'S ovx IXnOOR BOOK. Edited by Charles Peters. 528 pages (8j by 65). with over one nund red and hfty Illustrations. 83. cloth, gilt edEfcs. " A complete repertory of female occupation." — Tinies. '* Our girls who profit by the teaching will cer-j tainly be as u.-icful in domestic life as ornamental in society." — Graphic, 'ijii The BoviO*" [indoor BOOKSHI G TJU: GIRL'S oir.v ovmooR HOOK. , Containing Practical Hnlp on Subjects relating to Girl-Life when out of doors or when absent from the F.amily Circle. Edited by Charles Peters. Profusely Illustrated. 528 pages. Quarto. (Size of page SA by oA.) 8s. cloth boards, ciit edges. "So interesting and useful a book would make an excellent present." — Thc Record. " An excellent compen dium of open-air games and exer cises."— 5ai'Hrrfay Review^ 56, PATERNOSTER ROIF, LONDON ; mid of aU Booksellers. V ^ THE RELIGIOUS TRACT SOCIETY'S LIST. 4 SO "imiiinHr'"*!^ 4, Hich/-*''" ILLUSTRATED GI FT-BOOKS. THIJ TIA R VEST OR A ^UIET ICY12 f or, Lelfiure ThoUff'hts for* Rn.9*/ lAvea, By thc Rcv. J. R. Vernon, m.a. With numerous En- f ravings. 63. 6d. cloth, gilt edges. never saw anything more gracefully or more rightly done— more harmoniously pleasant in text and illustration."— il/r. Ruskin.RANDOM TRUTHS TX COJIMOX THIXOS, Occasional Papers from my Sludy Chair. By the Kev. J. R. Vernon, m.a,. Author of "The Har vest of a Quiet Eye." With numerous Illustrations. 7s. cloth gilt. "It seems even better than 'The Har vest of a Quiet Eve.* "—Mr. RiiskiM. "Should be placed next to Wordsworth on every student's bookshelf."— S/a^rfora'. ITArS AXD MEAXS; or, I'nirr.-^ front tho Ilif/hirat/8 aiul Ilrd^ct. A Scries of Sketches on Social Subjects, By Isabella P-i-viE Mayo, Author of "Thc Occupations of a Retired Life," etc. Imperial i6mo, 5s. cloth, gilt edges. "At almost evcrypage we are disposed to slop and exclaim, ' How true and wise this is ! ' There is a deep, sound underl3ing principle throughout, and the suggestions are such, thatall concemed with homes as a means of influencing others may well be helped by reading it.' —Thc Guardian. ROMAXCE OF REAL LIRE. True Incidents in the Lives of the Great and Good. With Illustrations by well-known artists. Large Quarto. 3s. 6d. cloth boards, gilt edges. A scries of twenty-four inlr- resting sketches, giving true incidents frora the lives of nun renowned in the world's history, amongst them being Sir John Franklin, Commodore Goode nough, Bishop Hanninpton. Sir Henry Havelock, john Knox, President Lincoln, Lord .Shaftesbury, Sampson Wilder, James Braidwood, and many otiiers. Thc admirable lessons suggested, and the attractive appear.ince of the book gene rally, well adapt it for Prizes in Schools and families. K,b, PATERNOSTEH EOlV, LONDON; aiidofallBontse/ler.;. 6 THE RELIGIOUS TRACT SOCIETY'S LIST. 7'HE RELIGIOUS TRACT SOCIET'i^'S LIST. THE I'OR ALL READERS. The " Siinjloicers Series " is /or Adults, rather than /or Children. Tht books firm very use/ut volumes/or ISirlhday Ci/ls, and/or Presentation at aU seasons.to readers, say /rom 16 lo (a. They are in Crown Bvo, mith illustnulons, pretty dolh cavers, and with ciit edges. OP ALL DEGREES. By Leslie Keith, Author of "Great Grandmnirma Eiiiivn?^/; ^.'iii.'P!! ^'!l^°^= Opportunity," etc. Crown Svo, 3s. 6d. SHAYNINQ CASTLe. By Ellen L. Davis. Illustrated. 3s: 6d. cloth, ellt edge,*;, ^ ' RAL>H ELLISONS OPPORTUNITY, AND EAST AHD WEST. By Leslie ...A";""- illustrated, is. 6d. doth, irilt cdires. MARCUS STRATFORD'S CHARGE ; or, Roy'k Temptation. By Evelyn - "¦ C CoAPE. Illustrat.:d. js. cloth, gilt. JOINT GUARDIANS. By E. Everett Green. Illustrated, ss. cloth, gilt edges, ' JOYCE GRAHAM'S HISTORY; or, Overcoming Evil with Good. By H, ANOTHpT'UTHr "''!!"¦'",=''• Crown 8vo 3s. 6d, cloth, gilt edges.'' ANOTHER KING. By Janet Lden. Illustrated by Tj. Wijymper, n„Ti''?.S,'2 ^"'°- 3S, Sd. cloth, gilt edges, THE HEAD OF THE HOUSl!. a" Story of Victory over Passion and TT^ll ktpAi.iJt •t,'^'^""''' Illustrated. Crown 8vo. 5s. cloth, gilt. IDA NIOOLARL By Eglanton Thorne. Illustrated. 3s. 6d. cloth, gilt edges. ° THE OLD MANUSCRIPT ; or, Anaise Robineau's Historv. A T.ale of the Huguenots of La Vendee. By Blanche M. Moggridce. Illustrated „-,Sy J" Whymper. Crovvn Svo. 5s, cloth, Eilt edces. YOUNG SIR RICHARD. By H. Woer.ck CHrRLES. Illustrated. Crown Svo. 5s. cloth, mit edges, MAMJALEHAj The WALDENSIAN MAIDEN AND HER PEOPLE. TiinHfi^ i^^.^X.i""^ S.""*^,";- Illustrated. 35. 6d. doth, gilt edges, TURNING POINTS; or. Two Years in Maud Vernon's Life. By L. C. t.f.ni'v'Jn' mU'i'^^™''='l- Crown Svo. 3S. 6d. cloth, gilt edges, , HEAPING THE WHIRLWIND. A Story of Three Lives. Illustrated. „„ ^''Si''" ^^°' 3S, 6d, cloth, gilt edges. ONE DAY AT A TIME. By Blanche E, M. Gkene. Illustrated by E. -,,,„ X.'i''"™''- Crown Svo, 3s. fd, doth, gilt edges. THE MISTRESS OF LYDOA'fE PRIORY; or, TBe Story of a Long Life. «.._ i'^'^^'-''" I^" Green, Crown 8vo, 3S, 6d, cloth, Kilt edircs. THE TWO CROWNS. iBy Eglanton Thorne. With ilfustratfons; Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d, clolh, gilt edges. LENORE AHNANDALE'S STORY. Bv Evelyn E. Green. With Illus- tralions. Crown Svo. 5s. cloth, gilt edges. CAROLA. By Hesba Stretton. Vvith Illustrations. 3s. 6d, cloth. Eilt edges, ** SUNFLOWERS. A Story of To-day. By G. C. Gedge. Illustrated. Crown Svo, ;s, 6d, cloth, gilt edges. ,^' ^i^. .•f> 56, PATERNOSTER POIV, EOiVpOiY,- and of all Bogisellers, nm BffLF-eRoojn book? SUITED FOR ALL READERS. This is a veri/ cheap Sr.rie.K of Pnpiiliir lifpriiiln. Eitrfi book contains 3S4 paaes with Illustrations. C'rnirn Sm, Ss. Oil., in bevelled, cloth boards, yilt ctli/cs. I THE BLACK TROOPERS, and other Tale«. a STRANGE TALES OF PERIL AND ADVENTURE. 3 REMARKABLE ADVENTURES FROM REAL LIFE. 4 ADVENTURES ASHORE AND AFLOAT. 5 FINDING HER PLACE. By Howe Benning. 6 THE MOUNTAIN PATH. By Lily Watson, 7 AMONG THE MONGOLS. By James Gilmour, ILA. 8 WITHIN SEA WALLS. By G, E. Sargent and Miss Walshe. 9 THE FOSTER BROTHERS OF DOON. A Talc of the Irish Rebellion of 1798. By the Author of " Cedar Creek." 10 CEDAR CREEK. A Talc of Canadian Life. II CHRONICLES OF AH OLD MANOR HOUSE. By G, E. Sargent. 12 A RACE FOR LIFE, and other Tales. 13 THE STORY OP A CITY ARAB, By G, E. S.\rgent. 14 MERLE'S CRUSADE. By RosA Nouchette Carey. 15 ONLY A GIRL WIFE. By Ruth Lamb. 16 THE STORY OF A POCKET BIBLE. By G. E. Sargent. 17 HER OWN CHOICE. By Ruth Lamb. 18 THE AWDBIE8 AND THEIR FRIENDS. By Mrs, Prosseh. 19 FRANK LAYTON. An Australian Story, By G. E, Sargent. 20 SHADES AND ECHOES OF OLD LONDON. ByJouN Stoughto.v, D.D. It RICHARD HUNNE. By G. £. Sargent. 23 ONCE UPON A TIME; or, The Boy's Book of Adventures. 33 GEORGE BURLEY: His Historj', Experiences, and Observations. By G. E. Sargent, 24 SUNDAY EVENINGS AT NORTHCOURT. By G. E. Sargent. 25 LUTHER AND THE CARDINAL. Given in English by Julie Sutter. 26 CAPTAIN COOK: His Life, Voyages, and Discoveries. By W, H. G. Kingston. 27 POMPONIA; or, The Gospel in Ca3sar's Household, By Mrs. Webb, 28 IHE PILGRIM'S PROGRESS, By John Bunyan. Wiih Illustrations by Sir John Gilbert. i6, PATERNOSTER ROW, LONDON; md of all Booksellers. TIIE RELIGIOUS TRACT SOCIETY'S LIST. Jllustrateb ^ Stories* .T.*. rarh. A YACHT VOYAGE ROUND ENGLAND. By William H, G, Kingston, Author of "Captain Cook: His Life, Voyages, and Discoveries," etc. New Edition revised and enlarged, and profusely illustrated. Small 4to, Clolh gilt. ss. NO CHOICE. A Story of thc Unforeseen. By Rcv. T, S. Millincton, Author of "Straight to thc Mark," etc. Illustrated. Crown Svo. Cloth boards, 5s. ,7,«, (Id. each. THE PERCIVALS; or, A Houseful of Girls. By Evelyn Everett Green. Author of "Joint Guardians," etc. Illustrated. Crown Bvo. Cloth boards, gilt edges. 3s. 6d. IDA HATHERLEY AT SCHOOL. By Constance Evelyn, Author of " Miss Nellie's Girls," etc. Illustrated. Crown Svo, Cloth boards, gilt edges. 3s, 6d, HOT BY BREAD ALONE. By Isabella Fvvie Mayo, thc Author of "The Occupations of a Retired Life," etc. Illustrated. Crown Svo. Cloth boards. 3s, 6d, ' .• ¦ A YOUNG OXFORD MAID IN THE DAYS OF THE KING AND THE PARLIAMENT. By Sarah Tytler. Illustrated. Crown Svo. Cloth hoards. 3s, 6d, NOT HIS OWN MASTER; or, Ronald's Experiences. By Mrs. Lucas Shadwell, Author of " Golden Sheaves," etc. Illustrated. Crown Bvo. Cloth boards. 3s. 6d. FROM PRISON TO PARADISE, A Story of English Peasant Life in 1537, By Alice Lang, Author of " Eield Court," " Angel Meadow," etc. Il lustrated, Crown Svo. Cloth boards. 3s, fid, RALPH ELLISON'S OPPORTUNITY, AND EAST AND WEST, By Leslie Keith, Author of " Great Grandmamma Severn," etc. Cloth, gilt edges, 3s, 6d, 3s. each. HIS YOUNG NEIGHBOUR. By Ellen Louisa Davis, Author of "Shayning Cistlc." Ilinstr.ited. Cloth. 3s, PETER'S SISTER. By Janet Eden, Author of "Another King," etc. Illustrated. Clolh, 35. By FOR FRANCE AHD FREEDOM Emma Leslie, Illustrated. A Tale of the French Revolution. Cloth. 3s, THE TENANTS OF PARADISE ROW. By the Author of "Constable 43 Z," " Adopted," ete. Illustrated, Crown Bvo. Cloth boards. 33. 3s. Gd. each. ADOPTED ; or, An Old Soldier's Embarrassments, By E, A. B. D., Author ot " Constable 41 Z," etc. Illustrated. Crown Svo. Cloth boaids. 2S. fid, TOM DOUGLAS ; or, A MarVed Man. Bv E. A. P. D„ Author of " Young Ishmael Conway," " Constable 42 Z"," etc. Illustrated. Crown Svo. Cloth boards, 2s, fid. MYRTLE AND RUE. A Storv for the Young. Illustrating the Twenty- third Psalm. By Margaret Scott Haycraft. Illustiated. Cloth boards. 2s. fid.' SHADOW ON THE THRESHOLD ; or, A Little Leaven, Armstrong, Author ot " Frank Horton's Vintage," etc. Cloth boards. 2s, fid. Bv Jessie illustrated. '^ THE RELIGIOUS TRACT SOCIETY'S LIST. 9 Jllustrateb * Stones. *«. each. HESS AND JAMIE. A Story of London Life, By Henry Johnson, Author of " All lor Number Onc," etc. Illustrated., Cloth. 28. HAROLD'S FRIENDS; or, The New Rector of Grcythorpe. By C. A, BuKNABY, Illustrated, Cloth boards. 28. CHRISTIE'S NEXT THIHGS. By the Author of " Mrs. Morse's Girls," etc. Illustrated. Crown Svo. Cloth. 23. DOT-AND-GO-ONE. By M. Blanche Hayward. Illustrated. Crown 8,^0, CloLh toai'ds, 2s. THE MUSGROVE RANCH, A Talc of Southern California. By I. M. Bhowne. Illustrated. Coth. ss. Js. Oti. each. WITHIN SIGHT OF THE SHOW 1 A Slory of a Swiss Holiday : and " A burrcv Idyl." By Lily Watson, Author of "The Mountain Palh," etc. Crown Bvo, Cloth, is. fid. HOT LIKE OTHER FOLKS. A City Story. By Jessie Armstrong. Il lustrated. Cloth. IS, Cd, MR. FARRER'S BIG O's. By Emily Brodie, Author of "Dandy Blue," etc. Illustrated, Crown Svo. Clolh. is, fid, HONOUR HOT HONOURS. Bv Mrs, Austin Dobsqv, Author of " Cbcrn- bui'n," etc, illustrated. Cloth. . is. fid. ************** InvQC ?r^pe Boofta for YOUNG READERS. /•ach In very large ty/e, ^L.ith /imrraz'tngs. Small Ato, is. in Coloured Cavers, crts.6.i. cloth, gilt edges. WHEN JESUS WAS HERE AMONG MEN. By Mrs. E. M. Waterworth. THE NAME ABOVE EVERY NAME. By Mrs. E. M. WamrworiiI. THE BEAUTIFUL HOUSE AHD ITS SEYEH PlLLiRS. By Irakces M. Savill. READINGS WITH THE LITTLE ONES. By Agnis Giberne. STORIES OF BIBLE CHILDREN. A Sonday Book for very Little Chil dren. By Mrs, E. M, Waterworth, LISTENING TO JESUS. A Sunday Book for Uie Little Ones. By E. M, Waterworth. BLESSINGS FOR THE LITTLE ONES. THE LILIES OF THE FIELD, and other Readings for the Little Ones. WALKING WITH JESUS. A Sunday Book for Children. THE THREE BRAYE PRINCES, and other Bible Stories. SUNDAY AFTERNOONS AT ROSE COTTAGE. Bible Talks with Mamma. By Mrs. Waterworth. THE CHILDREN'S KING, and other Readings for the Young. Sd, PATERNOSTER ROIV, LONDON; and of all Booksellers. ^6, PATERNOSTER ROIV, LONDON; and of all Booksellers. to THE RELIGIOUS TRACT SOCIETY'S LIST. .[\ ILLUSTRATED BOOKS BY mR$. 0. F. tDALTOn, TAe Mifslerlous Uouse. With trontispiece by M. E, Edwards. Crown Svo. is. cloth boards. Vtutcr's Follif. i8 Illustrations. Crown Svo. as. cloth boaids. OoldeH Threads for Dalh/ Weavtnif. A Text, Meditation, and Verse for each Morning and Evening of a Week, fid., ex quisitely printed in colours, Christie's Old Orf/an i or. Home, Sweet Home. is. cloth. AngeVa Christinas, ifiino. fid. cloth. Launch tlie Lifeboat. With 44 Coloured Pictures or Vignettes. 4to. 3B. Coloured Cover. Little Dot. Coloured Frontis piece, fid. Little Faith ; or. The Child ofthe Toy Stall, is. cloth. Author of ••Chrislie's Old Organ." tte. Nobodi/ Loves JUe. is, cloth. Olive's Story; or, Life at Ravcns- cliire. 2S. cloth, gilt. iras I Jtl(ihf/ illustrated. 3s. fid. cloth, gilt. Our Oraelons Queen 1 Pictures and Stories from Her Majesty's Life. With many illustrations. IS, cloth. Taken or Left. Crown 8vo. is. cloth. '* ..^''"i' liehlnd the Scones. Illustrated. Imperial ifiino. 3s. u-. cloth, gilt edges. Popple's Presents. IS. cloth. Saved at Sea, Crown 8vo, A Lighthouse Story. New and Cheaper^Edi'tion. IS. cloth boards. Shadows. Scenes in the Life of an Old Arm Chair. Illustrated. 45, cloth, gilt edges. ILLUSTRATED BOOKS BY Be^BA $TRGTTOn, Aittltor 0/ Alone in London, is. fid yessica's First Prayer," etc. A Miserable Christmas and a UapPU Ifew Year. gd. A yight and a Day. gd. A Thorny Path. 2s. licdc's Charity, ss. fid. Carola. 3s, fid. Cassy. IS. fid, Christmas Child, fid. Children of Cloverlcy, 2S. Cobwebs and Cables. 5s. Crow of the Dolphin, is, fid. Enoch Roden's Training, ss. Pern's Hollow. 2S. Fishers of Derby Haven. 2S. Friends till Death, gd. JIow Apple-Tree Court u-as Won. 6d. Jessica's First Prayer, is. Left Alone, fid. Little Meg's Children, is. fid. Lost Oip, IS, fid. Ma.-e liromar, is, fid. Michel Lorlo's Cross, fid. No Place Like Itom«. is. _ Only a Dog. fid. Pilgrim Street, 23. Sam Franklin's Dank. fid. Storm of Life. is. fid. The King'a Servants. Under tlie Old Hoof. Worth of a Baby, fid. Savings \ IS. fid. IS. 56, PATERNOSTER ROIV, l,ONpON; and of all Booksellers. y ] , I ^l' THE RELIGIOUS TRACT SOCIETY'S LIST. 11 F01^ ?^EgEj\lT3 W^ PJ^IZEg. FOURPENNY BOOKS IN CLOTH BOARDS. A Series of Thirty-two Story Books, each with Illustration. "LITTLE DOT" SERIES OF SIXPENNY BOOKS. A pretty Scries of 112 Story Books, each \vith Coloured Frontispiece ~ and bound in cloth. NEW NINEPENNY SERIES. A .Series of Sixty-two ' Children's Story Books wilh Coloured Frontispieces and other illustra tions. Bound in attractive cloth boards. NEW SHILLING SUNDAY BOOKS for Little Children. Large type. Illustrated, is, in very attractive coloured paper boards ; IS, fid, ill cloth, gilt edges, SHILLING LARGE-TYPE BOOKS FOR ADULTS. A Cheap Series of 120 Story and other Hooks for Working People. Large crown Svo. Illustrated. Cloth boards. MONTHLY SHILLING VOLUMES FOR THE YOUNG Upwards of 200 \'olumes of Stories. Each Illustrated and bound in attractive cloth boards. "R. T. S." LIBRARY. A Series of Thirty Books, n-osily reprints of Popular Books for Adults. Illustrated, Each book with ig2 pages. 3d, iu paper covers ; fid. cloth. The Society also Issues a great variety of cheap paper-covered Boobs tor Sunday School Rewards and for distribution. Amongst thoso aro the SILVER SERIES OF THREEPENNY BOOKS. A. twu' Series of 24ino Dool.-s for the I'ouuff. With. Copers prlntf'fl, tmek. and frotit, in Colours, on jiolrt aud silver grouud, Faell book in clear typo with a I.'roitti.f2'iccc i'li- graving. "FLORAL COVER" SERIES OF - TWOPENNY REWARD BOOKS. Fetch containing 48 pages of clearly-printed Letterpress, in siuipio language for Children. With Numerous Fn- gravings, and in attractive coloured covers, SIXPENNY AND SHILLING PACKETS OF PIC-' TURE AND STORY BOOKS FOR THE YOUNG. Cnnttiining Penny, Jlalfjicnuy. atid Farthing Books, also Coloured Leaflets and small 'Iracts for Children. ¦ 56, PATERNOSTER ROIV, LONDON,- aud of all Bookseller.^. J 12 THE RELIGIOUS TRACT SOCIETYS LIST, popular Hnnuala lUsion of Illustration.; aud l.-eruaU^l'ct'lZ'bl::,'!!,,^''. " ^'¦"- THE LEISURE HOUR ANNUAL. ' ^?*.uP°5'^''' J"'PS''ial 8vo. Profusely llluslratecl. vs. in han,l<:n„,„ cloth ; 8s. extra boards, gilt edges ; ics. fid. half bound in «lf'''°""' THE SUNDAY AT HOME ANNUAL THE BOY'S OWN ANNUAL. The Volume of the Boy's Own Paper, Sii iwo-es Will, .„ r„l„, j g!l? s^^ld^r;^ ^Sfcc^^ - ^S:^.^l^:^f^si. THE GIRL'S OWN ANNUAL. The Volume of the Girl's Own Paper. 8,3 pages- prof sclv illns S\'ll-.l?arf:"o,';rc'of™^^ '""''¦' '^- "'¦ --"'i' s£°^and'\d'^'e"s^: THE CHILD'S COMPANION AND JUVENILE INSTRUCTOR ANNUAL. ind"oirnl™',?l"? ""?¦ 'n"^'-«ling Papers with superior Engravings and Oleograph Frontispiece, is, fid, in ornamental cover -ss rlni U boards, -with coloured design ; 2S, fid. cloth, e egant, gilt edges! OUR LITTLE DOTS' ANNUAL. Pretty Stories and Pictures for Little People cover ; as, cloth boards, with coloured desisrn ; edges, full gilt. " ' THE COTTAGER AND ARTISAN: THE PEOPLE'S OWN ANNUAL. 144 large pages. Profusely Illustrated. Forming quile a family scrao- pUedgcs. """"¦'P""'"'''" °" Colours; "2?. fid. cloth ioards, FRIENDLY GREETINGS; Illustrated Reading for the People, Half-Vearlv Vouibies. With manv I.arge ingravings and Coloured Pictures. 2s. fid, cloth boards lhe y early Volume (or 1S90, h.indsomely bound, 5s, cloth boards. ' THE TRACT MAGAZINE ANNUAL. Short Stories Biographical Sketches, and interesting Papers. With many Engravings, is. fid. cloth boards. a r a. IS. fid, in ornamental 25. fid. cloth, bevelled 56, PATERNOSTER ROIV, LONDON; and of all Boaksellets. .\ I TIIE RELlCtOUS r/UCf SOCtErY'S LIST. 13 y 'This is a Series of Vopuliir Iteprints frotnvolutncs of the It01''S OinV FAPEJt, -most of xvhich arc now quite out of print,\ The Boohs are vi:ry a.iractirely bound, and arc freely illustrated. ADVENTURES OF A THREE-GUINEA WATCH. By Talbot Baines Reed. Illustrations. New Edition, reduced in price. Crovvn Bvo. 3s. fid. FOOTBALL. This Volume contains the Rules ofthe Game, With Papers on how the Game should be played, by such authorities as C. W. Alcock and Dr. Irvine. Illustrated, is. fid. CRICKET, By Dr, W. G. Grace, Rcv. J, P\cRoiT, Lord Charles Russell, Frederick Gale, and others. Many Illustrations. Crown Svo. 2s, A GREAT MISTAKE. ByT. S. MiLLiNGTON. With many Illustrations. Small 4to. 3s. fid. THE FIFTH FORM AT ST. DOMINIC'S. By Talbot B. Reed, Author of " The Adventures of a Three-Guinea \Vatch," etc. Illustrated. Crown Svo, 3s. fid, THROUGH FIRE AND THROUGH WATER. A Story of Adventure and Peril, By T. S, Millington, Author of " Straight to the Mark," etc. Illustrated. Crown Svo. 3s. fid. HAROLD, THE BOY EARL, A Story of Old England, ByJ, F. Hodgbtts " ¦¦" ' ¦' - Vikin; Norseman, ' 3s. fid. * Kornak the Author of "Edric the etc. illustrated. Crown Svo, MY FRIEND SMITH. By Talbot Baines Reed, Author of "Adventures of a Three-Guinea Watch,' etc. With an Introduction by G. A. Hutchison. Illustrated. Crown Svo. 5s. 56, PATERNOSTER ROIV, LONDON; and vf all Booksellers. -il '^"'^ liELfGtOUs TRACT SOC/Etys LtsT, '•THE QIItL'S OWN BOOKSHELF" is a Series of Heprtnts of some of thc chief stories and articles from "THE OIFL'S OWN PAPEIt." As most ofthe annual volumes of this popular periodical are tioxv out of pritU, fhe Girl's Own Bookshelf is the only fortn in which ihese productions can be obtained. They nre mostly in imperial IGmo, cloth boards. ^^ ^?r°'^?^OW W^^^^^°-.. ^y ECLANTON Thorne, Author ol The Old Worcester Jug," etc. 3s, fid "°^foT?ri^^,^^ COMMON THINGS. A Handy Book for Girls. With many Illustrations, is. CORA ; or, Three Years of a Girl's Life. Illustrated by M. E. U-DWARDS. 2S. 6d. "^ "^^^ nl\vK?^.'^s,°^^ COOKERY BOOK. By P„ill.s THE QUEEN O- THE MAY. By Anne Beale. 2s. 6d. THE MASTER'S SERVICE. A Practical Guide for Girls, i^Lwoo^J. iTd"""' °°"^ "•""'' ^•¦"^'^ '^""¦" »"<» M-^"^- "^"^ 2^.^d^^^^^ °^ '^^^ FACTORY, and other Stories. ESTHER CAMERON'S STORY. By Rosa N. Carey. 3s. 6d ^^^^,?fid^^^^^ ^°^ RACHAEL. By Anne Beale. HOME HANDICRAFTS. Edited by Charles Peters gilt c°d' °es" ^""''^ °^™ Indoor Book," etc. Illustrated. 2s."6d,' THE TWIN HOUSES, and other Stories. By Anne Beale, cloth boa°ds ^""" "'" ^^''^'" ¦="=• "'"^"--"^d. 2S, fid, THE SHEPHERD'S FAIRY. By Darley Dale, Author of The Great Auk s Eggs." 2s. fid. AUNT DIANA. By Rosa Nouchette Carey, Author of "Not 23 fid ^"'^^¦" "Esther Cameron's Ston'," etc. Illustrated, SERVAN-rS AND SERVICE. By Ruth Lamb, Author of "Comfortable Mrs, Crook," etc, is. fid. HER OBJECT IN LIFE. By Isabella Fy\'ik Mayo, as. 6d. 56, PATERNOSTER ROIV, LONDON; aud of all Bookselfers. I . ' 1' j; V: t J WE ktUCtOUS TRACT SOCIErV'S UST. 15 SUNDAY BOOKS, FOR YOUNG PEOPLE. ©ur Xfttle Dot's picture Scrap=313ooh0, First and Second Series. Royal 4to, Ss. ed. each Series; tn hantisotne coloured boards, or the TWO Series COMPLETE in ONK VOLUME, Ss, cloth. - Each series contains a large number of Piciurcs by well-known Artists, with iusf enough descriptive letterpress lo suggest an interesting storv connected Wl fi each picture. A most useful book lor parents nnd others who havc the care ol young children, BIBLE STORIES AHD PICTURES. With Twenty-four Coloured page Pictures and Forty Vignettes. With simple letterpress in large type. 4s, handsomely bound, cloth gilt. BIBLE TALES FOR CHILDBEH. With Forty illustrations. Small 410. 3s. fid cloth, gilt edges. THE HAPPIEST HALF-HOUR; or, Sunday Talks with Children Frederick Langbridge, m.a. With many 111 410, 3S, fid. cloth boaids, gilt edges. CCRAP v/'plCTUR^ many lii usi rati ons. SmaJi Stepping Stonea to Bible TIMstor^. A scries of books for children and young people, intended lo cover in time the whole Bible History. Each volume embraces a period complete in lisell, ihe writers arc selected lor their known aptitude in wnling for clii dren, and alao for their accurate acquaintance with Scripture, and their rower of making It attractive lo the vouog. The style is such lhat rtic book can be read by children of eight years old and upwards. It will also be lound very suitable lor reading to very Utile children. 1. STOniES FBOM OENE.IIS. By Annie R. Butler, Author of •Ijlimpscs of Maori Land," and "Stories of the Children's Medical Mission. With thirty-nine Illustrations. Small crown Svo, 2s. fid, cloth, g. THE PBOMLSED KING : Tlie Story of the Children's Saviour. Bv Annie R, Butler, Author of "Stories Irom Genesis," etc. Wo. a. Wuh many Illustrations. Small crown Svo, 25. fid. clolh. 3. STOBIES FBOM THE LIVES OF MO.SES AND .JOSHUA. By Joseph Johnson, Author of •' The Master's Likeness." " Dibs " etc. Illustrated. Crown Svo, 2s. fid. cloth. 56, PATERNOSTER ROIV, LONDON; and of all Bookseller^. zine^ foil BVeri Sixpence Monthly! One Penny l'-- Weekly. ; THE SUNDAYn / .¦ AT HOME. . A FAMILY MAGAZINE FOR SABBATH READING. Sixpence Monthly. One Penny Weekly. ' THE (ilRL'S OWN ;"" PAPER. One Penny Monthly. In Cover. THE CHILD'S . COMPANION AND JUVENILE INSTRUCTOR. The Magazine FOR Little Folks. New Series. One Penny Monthly, • , THE TRACT ^ ' MAGAZINE. , SPECIALLY USEFUL FOR LOCALISATION. New Series. Sixpence Monthly, THE • LEISURE,.,- r •vx'^^--V;HduR; '' -A MAGAZINE FOR FAMILY & GENERAL READING Sixpence Monthly. One Penny Weekly. TIIE ¦ BOY'S OWN PAPER. New Series. ' One Penny Monthly. THE - COTTAGER AND ,. ... -ARTISAN. THE I'EOf'LE'S OWN PAPER, lourpence Monthly. Halfpenny Weeklj-. FRIENDLY GREETINGS. ILLUSTRATED READINGS FOR THE PEOPLE. OUR LITTLE DOTS:''-^^^^-^^^:^"'' , ,„Sixtecn Pages. Large Type. Easy Words. One Penny Monthly. London : 56, Paternoster Row, and of all Newsagents. HAIELI, WATSON * VIHtY, LP, J YALE UNIVERSITY a39002 00227i*620b