\n 'f'f vers n r or rcc rTvo^^ j ON THE RELATIONS OF PSYCHOLOGY TO OTHER ! SCIENCES. 1 A S has been pointed out by Herbert Spencer, the growth of scientific knowledge is no exception to the laws of evolution. Human sciences, as well as human industries, have undergone a continuous differentiation. To the mind of primitive man the shock of an electric discharge and the ravages of cerebral disease were alike manifestations of spirit¬ istic volition. Even when the hypothesis of animism had for centuries been abandoned by philosophic observers, Lucretius sought in one work to expound the theory of all known phe¬ nomena . 1 But in recent years the increase of knowledge has brought with it a host of ‘ologies,’ the specialist in any one of which is often quite ignorant of all others. Nowhere has this differentiation of the sciences been shown more clearly than in psycho-physical problems. The work now ( done in psychological laboratories was begun by physicists and physiologists. A physicist made the first known measure¬ ment of the least noticeable difference of light , 2 and an as¬ tronomer discovered the personal equation . 3 When the laboratory at Leipzig was founded, the ground was broken for the separation of psychological problems from those purely physical and physiological. Apparently not feeling sure of his position, Wundt called the new science 4 physiological psychology,’ and devoted the first volume, in which its exposi¬ tion was undertaken, principally to physiological questions. But though at first an unwelcome appendage to physiology and physics, the new psychology has now asserted her right to recog¬ nition as a science separate and distinct from other sciences, and that too at times with such vigor as to disclaim all relationship ^ to them. Thus Professor Titchener objects to the use in psy- m 1 De Rerum Natura. 1 2 J. H. Lambert, Photometria , 1760. mt 8 According to Wundt, Bessel {Physiolog. Psychologies 4. Aufl., Bd. II, p. 320). 49 ° THE PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW. [VOL. V. chology of anthropometric methods , 1 and Professor Fullerton pleads for the complete separation of psychology and physiology . 2 It would, however, be misleading to consider the relations of the sciences only from this point of view. The progress of science is marked not only by increasing specialization, but also by a corresponding unification. Physiology is largely dependent on physics for the laws of arterial pressure and electrotonus; and secretion and meta¬ bolism are on their face complex chemical processes. Optics, acoustics, and the other branches of physics were in Newton’s time quite independent of one another; they are now united in the endeavor to explain all phenomena as transformations of energy. Chemical reactions can no longer be considered merely transformations of matter, for the principle of conser¬ vation of energy has been applied to atomic combinations as well as to molar and molecular phenomena. A few years ago botany, zoology, and physiology had little in common ; they are now taught as branches of biology. In psychology, perhaps, more than in any other science, this unifying tendency is manifest. In spite of the increasing recognition of the new science, psychological literature bristles with technical terms of physics and physiology. If we survey the problems now under investigation, we shall find that even when the aims and methods of psychological research are sui generis , the theoretical interpretation of its results is often ini terms of the biological sciences. When psychological meth-l ods are inadequate, the student of mind is often driven to biology for the explanation of mental phenomena. The study of the range and quality of sensations leads inevitably to the physics and physiology of nerve stimulation ; fatigue is a function of consciousness, but it is also a function of muscle and nerve ; space perception may be due to psychic synthesis, but such synthesis would be impossible without sensory data, and these data depend upon the motor mechanism of the eye ; association can no longer be considered an ultimate psychic 1 Titcbener, Philosophical Review, March, 1893. 2 Fullerton, Psychological Review , January, 1896. No. 5.] PSYCHOLOGY AND OTHER SCIENCES. 491 function, now that pathology has demonstrated its neural basis ; attention is either another ultimate activity of mind, or else an associative reflex phenomenon ; volition and move¬ ment cannot be separated from the automatism of all living matter ; psychogenesis can now be studied only from the bio¬ logical standpoint ; mental diseases are no longer explained on the purely psychological theory of obsession ; the super¬ stitions of the illiterate can be interpreted only by anthropo¬ logical methods ; and even those that adopt the psychological theory of suggestion to explain hypnotic phenomena, feel called upon to deduce their theory from physiological principles . 1 The laws of mental phenomena thus seem to be so en¬ tangled with those of living matter, that it would seem impos¬ sible to say where one science ends, and the other begins. But does the converse relation hold ? Is physiology similarly dependent on psychology ? Let us consider the history of the science. In its early development physiology was as independent of physics and chemistry as psychology was independent of physiology. But since the application to vital phenomena of the principle of conservation of energy and the successful preparation by synthesis of organic compounds, a knowledge of physics and chemistry has been essential to the physiologist. It is yet to be seen whether physiology will be equally indebted to mental science ; but, inasmuch as mental phenomena accompany human life as certainly as do chemico- physical phenomena, we may infer that they also may be found to be necessary links in the physiological chain of causation. But apart from the question of the ultimate relation of mind and body, the physiologist has been, and is now, dependent upon psychology for one important method of investigation ; for but a small part of what little is known of the functions of the brain and sense organs is got without the use of intro¬ spective methods . 2 Thus, in the present ignorance of cerebral processes, the physiologist is by his use of psychological methods forced to 1 Cf. Lehmann, Die Hypnose. 2 Cf. Fullerton, op. cit., for an analysis of Foster’s Physiology from this point of view. 492 THE PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW. [Vol. V. become also a psychologist; for the facts he has to observe are psychical facts. As we know nothing of the ultimate relations of mind and body, the only resource left the philosophical investigator is the observation of the phenomena of organic life in their totality. Since conscious processes are inseparable from human life, the physiologist cannot but consider these processes as parts of a connected whole. He has no right to assume that any one group of organic phenomena has no connection with other organic phenomena. I even see no good reason why conscious phenomena should not be admitted provisionally as causes and effects of bodily processes. If a sensation follows the excitation of a nerve, or if a muscular contraction follows a volition, the state of con¬ sciousness may be assumed to be part of the causal chain. It matters not whether there are other unknown links in the chain. The states of consciousness, being in whole or in part antecedents or consequents of physiological processes, must be considered in a comprehensive view of such phenomena. It may be argued that the concept of cause and effect cannot be applied in this way. But since the time of Hume, science has had no right to speak of cause and effect with ontological implications. To deny to the physiologist the right to intro¬ duce sensations and volitions into his causal series, would be to deny to the psychologist the right to assume material processes as causes of sensation ; yet this he is obliged to do, since we know nothing of a mental counterpart of the stimulus. The mental counterpart may exist, but experience gives us no clue of its existence. Consequently science, being the systematiza¬ tion of experience, must neglect it until there is other than a metaphysical reason for admitting it in the causal series. Even the advocates of parallelism assume the physical causa¬ tion of sensation implicitly, if not explicitly. Fechner holds that all matter has a psychical substratum, but speaks of the “ bodily causes of sensations .” 1 Wundt , 2 Bain , 3 and others use 1 Fechner, Elemente der Psycho-Physik, 2. Aufl., Bd. I, p. 18. 2 Wundt, op. cit.y vol. I, p. 334. 3 Bain, The Senses and the Intellect , 4th ed., p. 101. No. 5 .] PSYCHOLOGY AND OTHER SCIENCES. 493 similar expressions. Klilpe distinguishes between the cause of a physiological process and the condition of a psychical process, but admits that the physiological concept of cause includes the psychological concept of condition . 1 Hoffding, it is true, criti¬ cises the doctrine of physical causation of psychic states, but fails to tell us what mental processes take the place of the physi¬ cal stimulus . 2 They are, therefore, an unknown hypothetical factor. But that is to give them up for purposes of scientific explanation. I have spoken especially of physiology, but we may easily extend our conclusions to the other biological sciences. Physi¬ ology, the science of function, and morphology, the science of structure, are but parts of a connected whole. The structures of plants and animals have been determined by evolution, and the process of evolution is a physiological process. It may seem absurd to conclude that psychology and anatomy overlap, but the Lamarckian theory assumes consciousness as a determin¬ ing cause. As mental phenomena undoubtedly occur in the lower animals and are clearly related to those of man, the zoologist cannot avoid trespassing on psychological ground. Even bot¬ any cannot be wholly separated from mental science, for who can draw the line between plant and animal ? Protoplasm was discovered in vegetable cells, and botanists are acquainted with many cases of instinct in plants. That the methods of psychology are often those of anthro¬ pology, and conversely, is well known. If the psychologist would know the phenomena of mind, he cannot content himself with observing simply those of his own individual mind. That great errors and misunderstandings may arise from the failure to use the anthropological method is known to all who are acquainted with the fact of individual differences in mental imagery. Yet the first exact examination of this fact was made by an anthropologist . 3 It has even been claimed that great systems of epistemology owe their character to the'se individual peculiarities . 4 Anthropometric methods are not 1 Kiilpe, Psychologie, p. 81. 2 Hoffding, Outlines of Psychology , English translation, p. 65. 3 Galton. 4 Fraser, American Journal of Psychology , IV, p. 2. 494 THE PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW. [VOL. V. always as exact as those of a psychological laboratory; but these methods are the only ones by which a vast range of psychological problems may be investigated. One crying need of the psychology of to-day is a more definite knowledge of individual constants and their relations. Even in the present embryonic stage of the development of psychology, it has many points of contact with the inorganic sciences. In his study of sensation the psychologist has to call upon the physicist, for the relations of stimulus and sensation can be understood only when we know what the stimulus is. It is to physical science that we owe the demonstration to a high degree of probability of that stupendous truth that sensa¬ tions and their stimuli are qualitatively different, and that there exists a whole series of physical phenomena that have no coun¬ terpart in consciousness . 1 That the physicist is in his turn forced to become psychol¬ ogist is shown by his discussion of color theories, after images, contrast, and space perception . 2 Though starting with the assumption of common-sense realism, the physicist is forced to conclude that the assumed correspondence of sensation to stim¬ ulus is illusory. As his aim is knowledge of objective phenom¬ ena, he cannot but consider the relation of such phenomena to his perceptions. The investigation of such relations is a physi¬ cal as well as a psychological problem. The physicist studies the effects of certain physical phenomena, whereas the psychol¬ ogist has for his problem the physical causes of these psychic effects. Thus, psychology and physics unite in psycho-physics. The debt of physics to mental science may even be greater. The more physical science has reduced objective phenomena to transformations of matter and energy, the greater the difficulties in the mechanical interpretation of nature . 3 All such phenom¬ ena were once ascribed to matter and its properties, but now we are told that energy is an objective reality, and, like matter, indestructible. Energy is transmitted through the ether, a 1 I refer, of course, to different forms of ether waves, actinic and electromagnetic. The Rontgen rays might here be included. 2 Cf. Ganot’s Physics , pp. 605 et seq Barker’s Physics , pp. 472-6. 3 Cf. Stallo, The Concepts and Theories of Modern Physics , 1885. No. 5 .] PSYCHOLOGY AND OTHER SCIENCES. 495 second immaterial reality. As electricity is not energy, but is indestructible, it is considered a third immaterial reality . 1 Matter is reduced to atoms, but these atoms are such stumbling- blocks that some would deny their existence altogether , 2 and others consider them to be vortex rings of ether . 3 But this ether, on which science lays so heavy a burden, has properties that seem to be contradictory, and is therefore, it may be argued, inconceivable. But if the objective universe should prove unintelligible on the mechanical theory, it is not improb¬ able that physical science may have to abandon its time-honored realism and assume mind as the final reality. That such a sup¬ position has some basis of fact is shown by the attitude of such men as Balfour Stewart , 4 Tait , 4 and Lodge . 5 According to the reports of the Society for Psychical Research, we may have to admit the existence of phenomena subject to laws apparently contradictory of the axioms of mechanics, and determined by conscious processes . 6 We have seen that psychology and her sister sciences are often greatly indebted to one another for results as well as for methods. But is this integration of the sciences limited to an assimilation of methods and results ? At first sight it would seem that the differentiation of problems has increased in pro¬ portion to this assimilation of methods and results. In physics, for example, the problems seem quite distinct from those of other sciences, since the physicist, as physicist, studies only transformations of energy. But if mental processes should be found to be conditions of physical phenomena, the explanation of such phenomena would be psychological as well as physical. In biological science we find many problems that are identical with problems of psychology. The nature and origin of instinct, mental evolution, and heredity are obviously psychological 1 This appears to be the most recent view. Cf. Barker, Physics , p. 538. 2 Ostwald, quoted by Remsen, Science , III, p. 59. 3 Sir William Thomson. See Clerk Maxwell, Article “ Atom,” Encycl. Brit. 4 Stewart and Tait, The Unseen Universe , London, 1895. 5 See Lodge and Richet in Journal of the Society for Psychical Research , March and April, 1895. 6 Cf. Myers, “ The Experiences of W. Stanton Moses,” Proceedings of the S. P. R., pt. XXV, vol. IX, and pt. XXVII, vol. XI. 496 THE PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW. [Vol. V. problems. They are, however, but parts of a larger whole, but special cases of more general problems that belong to biology. Again, the relations of mind and body are problems of psychol¬ ogy, but they are also problems of physiology and pathology. This is evident if the conclusions be admitted as to the right of the physiologist to consider conscious processes as causally related to other activities of living matter. That the problems of psychology and pathology are sometimes identical, is known to all who are interested in what is called ‘abnormal psychology,’ but which is after all but a branch of pathology. The mental phenomena of disease and degeneration are but parts of the psychic totality, which it is the business of psychology as the science of mind to systematize and explain. Moreover, what is termed the ‘ normal mind ’ is but an ideal of popular psychology. The weaknesses and eccentricities of the normal man are quali¬ tatively akin to the morbid feelings and impulses of mania, and the delusions of paranoia. Alienists cannot draw the line between sanity and insanity; much less can psychologists draw the line between the normal and the abnormal. But if we can¬ not distinguish between the normal and the abnormal, we cer¬ tainly cannot differentiate the problems of ‘ normal ’ and ‘ ab¬ normal’ psychology. That the problems of anthropology and those of psychology are often the same, may also be shown. Many of the most common mental phenomena, from the feelings and beliefs of civilized man to the play activities of the civilized child, can be interpreted only as survivals from prehistoric ages. The expla¬ nation of such or any other mental phenomena is of course a problem of psychology ; but it is also a problem of anthropol¬ ogy, since that science has to do with all activities of man as a member of the human race. Language and religion, social customs and ethical ideals, — all had their being only by virtue of psychological laws. Their explanation is therefore a psy¬ chological problem. That this problem also comes within the province of anthropology is shown by the space given to it in treatises on the science. In fact, comparative psychology might well be called ‘ psychological anthropology.’ i'i?ivri5f;rTv or ff.f.rr:off? - -v ; . ■ ■ . , vr:fi F t! r, No. 5.] PSYCHOLOGY AND OTHER SCIENCES. 497 I have now discussed the relations of psychology and other sciences from the historical or a posteriori point of view. We have found that their problems as well as their methods are often the same. We turn now to a brief a priori examination of the question. As the relations of mental and physical phe¬ nomena are included in those of mind and body, I shall only discuss the theories of these relations. But first I shall endeavor to show that these relations must be considered in all branches of theoretical psychology. The purpose of psychological investigation may be considered to be the knowledge, first, of the qualities or attributes of mental phenomena ; secondly, of the relations of such phenom¬ ena to one another ; and thirdly, of their relations to conditions which are apparently not mental. The method of investigating the first of these groups of problems is primarily introspection. Such knowledge may be quite independent of the objective world. But knowledge of individual facts, uncoordinated and unrelated, is not science. Only by understanding the relations of phenomena can we make those predictions of phenomena which should form the ideal aim of science. The investigation of such relations leads, it may be shown, to the relations of mind and body. For, when the psychologist fails to find in any purely mental law the explanation of any phenomenon, he is justified in looking for an explanation in the properties of living matter. The other relations of mental phenomena are either to the body or to the environment. The relations to the environ¬ ment cannot be interpreted apart from bodily processes. Thus psycho-physics leads to psycho-physiology. In all branches, therefore, of theoretical psychology we may be confronted by the problems of mind and body. According to the theory of parallelism, as generally under¬ stood, mental phenomena form an independent series superim¬ posed upon a purely mechanical series. Even on the assumption that the activities of the body may be explained on mechanical principles, it is doubtful if psychology and other sciences could remain independent. If there be complete parallelism, the relations of the series would require investigation. But who, 498 THE PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW. [Vol. V. if not the psychologist, should investigate these relations ? As science is but classified knowledge, the knowledge of these relations must come under the scope of some science. No one, I think, would hesitate to call Fechner’s law a psychological law, or deny that it has a place in a text-book of mental science. Yet, as formulated by Fechner, the law gives the relation of these very physical and psychical series. Then, too, if there be complete parallelism, this parallelism must extend into the inorganic world. If so, it is probable that the two series are, as Spinoza believed, but modes of one and the same reality. In fact, on the theory of parallelism it is difficult to hold to any dualistic ontology. If the ultimate reality is mind, it is quite possible that the physicist will some day look to psychology for the solution of problems that his science fails to give. For physical and biological science would then be, theoretically at least, branches of psychology. If, on the other hand, the final reality be matter, or other non-mental substance, it is clear that psychological laws are not ultimate, but would have to be deduced from physical laws. In that case, psychology and all the biological sciences would be subordinated to physics and chemistry. The differentiation of the sciences would be a differentiation for convenience, not a logical necessity. It is generally assumed in speaking of parallelism that all physiological processes are mechanical, but of this we have no proof. The most recent biological theories do not favor a mechanical interpretation of life. Even if consciousness be epiphenomenal, it is quite possible that the complete explana¬ tion of vital phenomena will include other than mechanical causes. We may therefore assume, as one form of the autom¬ aton theory, that parallel series of mental and material phe¬ nomena occur only in organic matter. Such parallelism may hold for all activities of organic matter, or only for certain ones of these activities. If the parallelism hold for all terms of the two series, the conditions would be the same as those just dis¬ cussed ; the relations of the series would require investigation and these relations would be both psychological and biological. Hence psychology and biology would have the same problems. No. 5 .] PSYCHOLOGY AND OTHER SCIENCES. 499 If the parallelism be incomplete, the psychologist and physiol¬ ogist will seek to know at what point the mental series begins and at what point it ends. Such knowledge would, however, only open up the question why the mental series began or ended at one point rather than at another, — a question both physiological and psychological. On the Cartesian theory we may assume matter and con¬ sciousness to be causally related, or matter and mind, conscious and unconscious. In either case psychology and the biological sciences would overlap. We may even admit that the field could be divided up so that the biologist and the psychologist should each investigate his own series, the material or the mental. But what of the point where they meet ? The inves¬ tigation of this borderland would be physical, biological, and psychological. But there may be in organic phenomena no independent mechanical series ; all cellular activity may be intelligible only from the subjective standpoint. In this case the provinces of psychology and biology would be logically undistinguishable. From this examination of the hypothetical relations of mind and body we conclude, then, that we cannot, by assuming any one of these hypotheses, define the province of psychology as distinct from those of other sciences. To attempt any arbitrary division of the ground that is properly psychological and that which is not, would from this point of view be absurd. Obviously, just how far the domain of psychology extends into that of biology and other sciences, depends upon the unknown relations of mental and other processes. The conclusions to which we are led are largely negative. They may, however, be put into positive form : the problems of psychology and other sciences may coincide ; the unity of all science is not simply a unity of methods and results. The extent of this unity cannot, however, be determined except by experience. A priori reasoning leads to different results, according as we make different ontological assumptions. But, it may be said, are not these conclusions at variance with our generalization as to the progressive differentiation of 500 THE PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW. [Vol. V. science ? This differentiation will continue if Spencer’s formula of evolution is even an approximation to the truth. But the differentiation will, I hold, be a differentiation with reference to particular objects of cognition, rather than to the subjective classification of our cognitions, or to the methods which we employ. We will, perhaps, have a science of color rather than three or four sciences that treat of the subject from different points of view. The practical advantage, even now, of thus examining a phenomenon from every point of view is shown by the remarkable discoveries of Helmholtz in sciences before considered quite independent . 1 Had Helmholtz not been a great physicist he would not have been the physiologist and psychologist that he was ; nor, had he avoided problems other than physical, would he have solved the mystery of timbre. It may be claimed that the common ground of psychology and other sciences is in many cases pure philosophy ; that the relation of mind and matter, for example, is a problem for philosophy, not for science. But no one doubts that we have some scientific knowledge of the relations of mind and matter. Just how far such problems may be solved we cannot say. Then it is open to question whether the sharp Kantian distinction between science and philosophy will be sustained. Even now, with all his dislike of ‘guesswork,’ the man of science cannot steer clear of metaphysical rocks. Thus physics, the queen of sciences, has for its foundation-stone a highly metaphysical principle. The speculations of modern mathema¬ ticians on the fourth dimension are essentially metaphysical. In biology the origin of terrestrial life and the evolution of man are wrapped in such mystery that some would invoke transcendental causes . 2 In mental science space perception, association, and other processes are quite entangled with the problems of epistemology ; and, if Myers 3 is right and retro- 1 An interesting exposition of Helmholtz’ services to psychology is given by Stumpf, Archiv f Geschichte d. Phil., Bd. VIII, Heft 3, 1895. 2 Wallace, for example. 3 Myers, Proceedings of the S. P. R., pt. XXIX, vol. XI. No. 5 .] PSYCHOLOGY AND OTHER SCIENCES. 501 cognition and precognition are facts, science may yet have to consider the hypothesis of an immanent world-soul. Thus objective science has to face the problem of ontology, and sub¬ jective science also that of epistemology. And this is but what we might expect. After all, the scientist and philosopher have the ‘same object ; both seek truth, though they seek it by different paths. Harold Griffing. < 0 V i