THREE SCOTCH RHETORICIANS OF THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY KAMES, CAMPBELL, AND BLAIR By GORDON RANDOLPH CRECRAFT A. B. Miami University, 1918 THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS IN ENGLISH IN THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF ILLINOIS, 1922 URBANA, ILLINOIS \°J L \* ** ' ■ TABLE OF COUTE1JTS . Pages. Chapter I. The Revival of Letters in Eighteenth-Century Scotland ------ 1 - 12 Cliapter II. Karnes and his Element s of Criticism . -------------- IS- 4 3 Chapter III. Blair and his Lectures ------ — 44-68 Chapter IV. Campbell and his Phi lose \A-~j of Rhetoric . ------------- 69-87 Chapter V. Recapitulation and Interpretation.- - - 88-95 Bibliography --------------------94-95 THE REVIVAL OE LETTERS III El GHTEEITTH- CEiTTURY SCOTLAND . CHAPTER I. In this year, 1754, I remember nothing remarkable in the General Assembly. But this w as the year in 'which the Select Society was established, which improved and gave a name to the literati of this country, then beginning to distinguish them- selves. (1) oo states the Reverend Dr. Alexander Carlyle in his Autobiography. The italics of the word literati are Dr. Carlyle T s own; but they must do double duty and serve as mine, also, for it is toward this word literati that I wish to direct attention. The place is Edinburgh, Scotland. The time, the middle of the eighteenth century. The dramatis personae are self- confessed literati . Eor some hundreds of years past, Scotland has had her men of literature, law, and divinity, but the app earance of this new species, these literary cognoscenti, ’’then beginning to distinguish themselves”, is a new phenomenon, inviting scrutiny, ’.'/hence came they? Who are they? bhy do they appear now, and not until now? A survey of Scottish literature up to this point would scarcely lead us to anticipate their advent. As Hr. Gregory Smith expresses it: The Scottish Muse lias been charged with three serious breaches of "decorum", each serious enough to damn her higher hopes (1) Ed. I860, r. 296. Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2015 https ://arch i ve . o rg/detai Is/th reescotch rhetoOOcrec - 2 - of Parnassus. She has been called provincial, by which is ne ant no mere contrast with English or other standards, but a certain frumpishness or village -habit that goes badly with her national pretence. It has been said of her that often in taste and lan- guage she shows an unblushing defiance of the graces and propriet- ies. She has been blamed for being tediously reminiscent of family matters and neighbor- folk, of living' too much in the past and in her own past. Briefly, the indictment is that she is provincial (even parochial), rough mannered, and antiquarian. (1) How certainly these are no qualities from which we might expect the formation of a Select Society of literati . Yet "Jupiter” Carlyle was not claiming for himself and his contempora- ries of Edinburgh a title refused to them by the rest of the re- public of letters. The mid-eighteenth century found the literary reputation of Edinburgh decidedly ” loo king- up " . And although the capital of Scotland took unto herself and appropriated to her own glory most of the talent and genius of her dominions, yet 11 Scotland shared to an extent in the revival of letters. Glasgow and Aberdeen aspired in their own right to honorable mention among the centers of culture; and if Edinburgh boasted of her Robertson, her Smith, and her Hume, Glasgow pointed with pride to her Si ms on, (2), her Leechman, (S), and -- greater than either of these -- her Hutcheson, "whose fame" as Carlyle tells us, "had filled the Col- lege with students of philosophy." (4) As for Aberdeen, she had, among others, her Principal George Campbell, whose Philosophy (l) Scottish literature, Character and Influence, 1919. { - ) Robert Sims on. Professor of Mathematics at Glasgow, Vide Carlyle’s Autobiography . (5) William Leechman, Professor of Divinity at Glasgow, and after- wards head of the University. (4) Aut ob i ogr a phy , p. 82. . . standard of Rhetoric has lasted almost down to our own times as a text, and has been called "by far the most valuable contribution to criticism which came from Scotland during the century"; (l) though of that, more later. But — to return to our original question -- whence came this new breed of cognoscenti? The answer is that Scotland (inveterate borrower that she has always been!) has been again to London -- and for the third time. On her first visit in the person of the first Janes she borrowed ban Chaucer, and from her delighted disciple ship to this master there cane the Golden Age of Scottish Poetry. Later, when this impulse had died out and the Scottish Muse strove mightily, yet f all her striving attained but feeble expression, there came a new breath of life from the south; and Scottish bards tunned Elizabethan court poets, tile Scottish prose gave ground end melted before the Anglicani zing influence from within and without. How for the third time Scotland has been to London; and this time she has returned home "Augustan" . She has brought bad: with her. Pope, Addison, an! Swift ; she lias breathed- in the atmosphere of the eighteenth century, and has carried home the passion for explaining things; yea, more, she might have made a clean sweep of it and carried off Dr. Samuel Johnson, himself, ( 1 ) J. H. Millar, .1 Literary History of Scotland , 1901, p.S58. -4- we are, of course, still ini nr our metaphor — had not that worthy proved so erratic and. unceremonious in his dealings with Scots, that some were cowed into mingled respect and fear, while others were goaded into saying with Lord Monboddo that he was "neither a scholar nor a man of taste." (l) Yet for all this, Samuel did patch up a truce with the Scots, and after a time, possibly grown curious about the spread of classicism among them, lumbered off to Edinburgh to see abo ut it. The Union of the British and Scottish Parliaments (1707) marks the beginning of the peaceful invasion of England by Scottish adventurers. Professional and business men, unable to find adequate opportunities for their abilities at home, , armed down upon London and competed with the Englishman in his own fields. Lawyers, doctors, men of letters, publishers, — there was scarcely an oc- cupation which escaped invasion. Add to this the fact that Scots in increasing numbers began attending English schools and universities (£) and it will be apparent that the union of the two countries could not long remain a union in government only. The Scot was eager, proud, assertive; but he was also awed. It his pro- vincialism keenly, and partly as a matter of pride, partly as a (1) James Burnett, Lore Monboddo, C r 1 B 7 a , 1789, g f p. 271. (E) Erancis Jeffery and Adam Smith, among others. Hume advised tint his nephews should be sent to Eton, chiefly to avoid the risks of contracting Boots accent. -o- matter of policy, lie there was no question As might he lead in this national set about he of England's expected, the determination task of becoming English, since becoming Scottish. Scottish Universities tools the to be as English as the Engl is h Says Professor Millar in his Scottish Prose of the seventeenth mx eighteenth centuries : mother phenomenon in the Scottish aufkl&rung, if the dantic expression may be pardoned, is the emerging of out U niversities from a condition of comparative obscurity into the full blaze of European celebrity. A condition precedent of this fortunate transition was the establishment of the professorial monopoly which in the following century was to be so fiercely attached. It was the same alihe in Arts and sciences. The chairs were filled by first-rate men whose lectures, it was a, pleasure to listen to, and who exerted an influence which extended far beyond their respective classrooms. But, he adds, the movement was by no means confined to the uni- versities : The awakening of the Universities, too, was but one manifestation of the general, revival of intellectual interest among the educated classes. It is difficult for us to under- stand the enthusiasm with which grown-up men flung themselves into the struggle for knowledge, and debated in quasi- social gatherings vexed questions of philosophy and metaphysics. Eor was the zeal for improvement confined to merely spequ. - lative matters. Art, manufactures, and agriculture partook handsomely of the benefits which the mental activity of the age brought in its train, lien of considerable powers and marked aptitude for academic discussion devoted their leisure to planting trees, and to making two blades of corn grow where only one had brown before. fl) (1) pp. 176 - 177 . - ci- In this general revival of letters, arts , and sciences, the most important point for consideration here, is the complete abandonment of the Scottish dialect as the language of the learned, and the substitution of -English. Through a determination to write and speak nothing but the King*s English, these Scottish li ter at i were led to an unceasing study of the "best English models.' 1 Hot satisfied with this alone, they felt impelled to try their hands at reformulating the critical canons thus obtained, and out of these efforts came, among others, the three works which are treat- ed at some length in succeeding chapters of this paper. The efforts of Karnes, flair and Campbell (l) have been selected for this special treatment, not because they are more typical of this movement, but because they are the most ambitious and formal attempts to treat fully of rhetoric and criticism. Furthermore, there is apparent in these three a direct kinship. To what Karnes laid down as the e lenient s of criticism, Blair and Campbell acquiesced; £ind although the int nts and purposes of the two latter are certainly divergent, they owe a common debt to the Elements of Critic ism (2), in which, it is scarcely too much to say, they have their origin. (1) Henry Home, Lord Karnes, 1696 - 1782; Life by A. Eraser Tytle i 2 vols . 1807. Hugh Blair, minister of High Church and first pro- fessor of Rhetoric and Belles-Lettres, University of Edinburgh, 1718 - 1800; Life by John Hill', IS'-A ; also Life by Einlayson, appended to 31a i r 1 s S e rrn ons , London, 1801, vol. b. George Camp- bell, Principal of Uarischal College, Aberdeen, 1719 - 1796. Life in L ic ti onary of Rational Biography . (2) 1762, Henr 77 Home. Lor/ If^e s . -7- Postponing for a time oar consideration of these three, let us note the activities of some of their contemporaries. The first thing which strikes the student is the intense eager- ness of all professions to acquaint themselves and their brethren with the principles of English composition and criticism. Lawyers, philosophers, historians, political-economists, preachers, and printers -- all try their hands at it. D a vid Hume displaying his philosophic acuteness and his erudition at one and the same time, composed an Essay on Tragedy . Lor his own benefit and that of his friends he compiled a list of Scotticisms to be carefully avoided. (1) Adam Smith (remembered for his Wealth of ITati ons ) as early as 1746 gave a course of lectures in Edinburgh upon English Literature; a private speculation of his own which met with a large measure of success. A paper on Johnson T s Dictionary in the ill-fated Edinburgh Review of 1755 (2) is further indica- tive of his interest in the English language, and bits of his literary criticism found their way into his Theory of Moral Sentiments (1759) (5). James Beattie, author of The Minstrel and usually associated with Reid and Oswald in the "Common S e nse" school of philosophers, is responsible for an anonymous little volume, published in 1787, on Scotticisms . arranged in alpha — ( lT Vide Hume, Philosophical Works, ed Green and Grose, 1875, 4 p. 461 . (2) But two numbers appeared. (Z) Wordsworth planes him with Hume as a critic, and summarily disposes of the claims of both. V id e , Wo r d swo r t h T s Literary Cri t ici srn , ed. H. 0. Smith, London, 1905, p 178, Ho te 2. - 8 - betical order , designed to correct improorieti es of speech and writ ina . ( 1 ) Nor are the literati content with the mere conquest of English prose. Not only will they write histories, law-books, philosopies, and rhetorics, hut to the great perturbation of some of their own number they will write plays, and worse still, will produce them at Edinburgh. There are few more amusing incidents of this period than the furor that beset the church party when John Home’s Douglas was acted ih the old Scottish capital. ,T Jupiter Carlyle relates the matter with great gusto, and it is clear that he extracted much enjoyment from the ludicrous discomfort of some of his "belletristic” friends who scrupled not to treat "elegantly" of the drama in criticism, but dared not show their faces within a theatre. (2) There is great temptation to linger over the many ac- counts of the lives and doings of the polished society of old Edinburgh. No period in any literature has been better served (1) J. H. Millar, Literary History of Scotland , p 519. (2) Autobiography , p 525; "Lrs. Hobertson andBlair, though they both visited this great actress (Mrs. Siddons) in private, often regretted to me that they had not seized the opportunity which was given them, by her superior talents and unexceptionable character, of going openly to the theatre, which would have put an end to all future animadversions on the subject. This condrnt of theirs was keeping the reserve of their own imaginary irnporr— "fence to the last; and their regretting it was very just, for by that time they got no credit for their abstinence, and the struggle between the liberal and the restrained and affected man- ners of the clergy had been long at an end, by my having finally stood my ground, and been well supported by so great a majority in the Church.” -9- by its annalists. (l) But enough lias been said to prepare us for consideration of our subject proper; the formal treatment of rhetoric and 1 it e r a ry criticis m in the \ /or k s o f Karne s , .3lai r and Campb el 1 . ( 2 ) The history of Bhetoric from Aristotle to the eighteenth century is a record of interpretations, re- interpretations , mut- ilations, subversions -- and sometimes, in the Aristotelian sense of the term (B) -- almost anihiliation. Briefly, the tendency has been to divorce composition from what Aristotle had held to be (1) Besides Carlyle’s Autobi ograpliy there are the I.lemoirs of Hume, Beid, Robertson, and Dug ild - art . Th Tytler* emoirs of Kames and Herr’s Memoirs o f Karnes ’ s printer, Mr. William Smellie, etc . (2) Some mention should be made of James Burnett, lord Monboddo (1714-1790). A man of deep and extensive learning, with pro- round acquaintance with, the classics and metaphysics, he was nevertheless so eccentric in his likes and dislikes, and so un- compromising’ in devotion to certain pet theories, that he was seldom taken seriously by his own contemporaries. His Origin and Progress o f Language , 6 volumes, appeared in 1789. The primary idea of this work was that, for all philosophic truth, we must go back to Plato and Aristotle. It opens with an accou t of the origin of Ideas (according to Plato and Aristotle) next of the origin of Human Society, and next of language, language, it is maintained, is a human invention; man was originally an animal without speech or reason or affection. Orang-outangs are asserted to be not specially distinct from men, and on the author- ity of the traveller's tales, Monboddo vouches for the existence, in Ms day, of men with tails; he insists that all the higher attainments of the human race were the mere results of long ex- perience, continuous struggle, and artifice. After his history of the ’’rise and progress” of languages in general and critical comparisons of various languages, he devotes his sixth volume to the subject of rhetoric. The work was intended to rival the Elements o f Criticism , by Karnes, but it goes a great deal farther; there is a curious anticipation of the Darwinian theory of evolu- tion. This last idea of man monkeys seems to have shocked his _ con- temporaries more than any one other eccentricity of His lordship. - 10 - the soul of Rhetoric , its speculative and philosophic character. The art of thinking was forgotten in the art of sp eaking. Rhetor- ical devices, tropes, figures, mere ornaments of style, received undue attention; were standardized, in fact. Every one who has written upon the subject has quoted Hud i bras (l) upon the value of such practice. Sir Thomas Wilson's .'art o f Rhetoric (1552) af- fords instance of this mechanical scheme for avoiding the fatigue of thinking; he advocates "a gorgeous beautifying of the tongue with borrowed words and change of sentence.” Figures, he tells us, should not be "equally sparioled about the whole oration, but so dissevered and parted as stars stand in the firmament, or flowers in a garden, or pretty devised antiques in a cloth of Arras . " This preoccupation with diction lasted in England well up to the eighteenth century. It was not to be expected, then, that o c otland should wholly escape it, and for the further reason that we have seen how anxious was all Scotland concerning correct English diction. Happily, however, another consideration operated to prevent undue extravagances in this direction, at least upon the part of those who laid down the rules for their brethren . (1) Canto I. part I., 11 89 - 90; — "For all a rhetoricians rules Teach nothing but to name his tools". ■ - 11 - Emphasize diction most of them did, hut after the manner of phil- osophers. The taste for metaphysics and philosophy seems to he the 3cot3 T heritage; and partly because the task was so thoroughly enjoyable to them, partly because they recognized its true v; lue , they set about grounding their canons of criticism upon"true principles of taste." Philosophy, so long divorced from Rhetoric, was re- wedded to it. Hot that the two always enjoyed the happiest wedlock. Sometimes (as has been asserted in the case of Karnes ( 1 ) ) Philosophy seemed to assert claims to the great- er half of the partnership. -But on the whole the re- sult was desirable. But from another danger which has beset the art of Rhet- oric from its later infancy, these B 0 otch Rhetoricians were not so successful in saving it. Rhetoric was not considered by its founder, nor should it be considered by anyone, as being iden - tieal with literary appreciation . Aristotle wrote upon the art of Poetry as well as upon the art of Rhetor ic . Of this distinction (1) Professor Saintsbury, History of Briticism 2. p 465; -- "Of course this excellent Boots lawyer and ingenious ’Scotch meta- physician 1 had strong precedents to urge for making a muddle of Moral Philosophy and Literary Briticism, it has been pointed out that Aristotle is not a little exposed to the same imputa- tion." > ' - 12 - I shall have frequent occasion to remind the reader hereafter. Sufficient for the moment to remark that of the three men treated in succeed:' , a hell alone seems to have this c ' bine-' tion clearly in mind, (l) Sanies, indeed makes no pretense to treating formally or singly of the art of rhetoric ; the nature of his task, as we shall see, led him naturally to a considera- tion of literature as a fine art. But in -Blair T s lectures upon his profession subject. Belles - lettres quite overshadow Rhetor i c and the Aristotelian Art is as effectually swallowed up by literary appreciation, as the most ardent disciple of the latter c ould wi sh . (1) Bor which, along with general praise for Ms other excellen - cies,he receives mild blame from Professor Saintsbury. As I shall refer constantly to Professor Saintsbury, it may well be stated "in the deep calm of a footnote" that in the opinion of the present writer, the Professor's criticisms are often vitia - ted to a certain extent, by his determination to bring about an exact coincidence between literary appreciati on and rhetoric . It may be all very well for a man to dislike and distrust the speculative and philosophical character of the art of Rhetoric but that is a matter of opinion. Certainly his opinion should not blirn him to the fact, 1 t, if in i totle there appears a union of literary and philosophic material, Aristotle was probably aware of it, and intended it so. miES AND HIS ELEMENTS OE CRITICISM. CHAPTER II. Among the li terat i of the eighteenth- cent "ary Edinburgh, we scarce may find a more interesting and striking figure than that of Henry Home, Lord Kanes. (1) The limits pre- scribed for this discussion will restrict consideration of his work in great measure to his place in the history of rhetoric and literary criticism. Yet in so doing, we must add that we are considering but one side of a many-sided man; nor is this statement, in spite of its apparent triteness, unnecessary. It is precisely because Karnes, more than most of his contemporaries, was so many-sided, that his rhetorical and critical speculations acquire special interest. Lawyer, moral philosopher, historian, experimental and practical agriculturalist, he could not write upon the subject of criticism, or indeed upon any other subject, without bringing to his work something from each of his many characters. H, as has been said, "he occupied eveiy department of human thought for his province," (£) we should be greatly ( 1 ) Memoirs , by Alexander Eraser Tytler, 2 vols. 1807. ( 2 ) Scottish Prose of the seventeenth and e ighteenth Centuries, by J. H. Millar, 1912. -14- surprised if his omnisc ience were not a basis for his critical opinions. Henry Home was born at Karnes, in the county of Berwick, in 1696. Descended from a family whose name had been highly honorable in the history of Scotland, and whose estate had once been considerable, he found little to inherit from his fat lie r , George Home, except the family name. This gentleman, a country magistrate, had never attended University, nor had he been educated for any profession. Little wonder, then, consider- ing the state of higher learning in the country at that time, that George Home saw no necessity for burdening himself with his son's education, further than to engage for him a private tutor, and when this course of training was completed, to ap- prentice him in 1712 to a Writer to the Signet in Edinburgh. This training was to have prepared young Home for the profession of a writer, or solicitor, before the Supreme G 0 urt, but his ambitions grew as he realized how much more affluence and honor might be his if he were to become a successful advocate . Immediately he turned his attention to acquiring the equivalent of a University education. His Latin and Greek studies, begun under his former tutor, .V ingate, were resumed. Independently of » -15- any tutor, he applied himself to French, Italiaa , Mathematics, natural Philosophy, Logic, ethics, and Metaphysics. He labored to good purpose, and in 1724 was admitted to the bar. But admittance to the -Bar was not an earnest of success. There is a dry humor in Tytler’s statement (l) that "in the first years of Mr. Home T s attendance at the bar, he found abundant leisure to store his mind with miscellaneous learning, as well as to increase his knowledge of law." It v/as not until Home had brought himself into some prominence by the publication of a folio volume of the Benia r liable Decisions o f the Court of Session , (1728), "that" — to quote again from Tytler (2) -- "we find him enjoying' even a moderate share o f practice as a barrister." The reasons assigned for this initial failure will prove of interest when we cone to consider his Elements of Criticism . They will be spoken of in that connection. Success, if slow in coming, did finally arrive. The publication in 1752 of a volume of Assays upon law, seems to have lifted him into the ranks of the foremost advocates of the time. With the professional prominence thus achieved, came (1) Memoirs . p 60. (2) Memoi rs . p 65. . -16- social recognition. It was the fashion of the gay young men of the time to seek out and attach themselves socially to those men who had achieved distinction in science and philosophy. Such a circle formed around Karnes. (l) Their names mean little to the casual reader of today, yet they represent the fashionable and literary elite of the time, — the- precursors of those sturdier figures which were to he associated with Karnes in the latter half of his life. The Select Society was not formed, it mil he re- membered, until the year 1754, and Karnes was a man in the prime of life when such men as Blair, Robertson, and Hume were but be- ginning their careers. Meanwhile, he met Hume. Tytler gives 1757 as the probable date. It was in the latter half of this year that • Hume went to London for the first time to secure the publication (1) Tytler mentions (pp. 84-85) "Colonel Forrester, author of a valuable little tract entitled, -he Polite Philosopher . and of whom Dr. Johnson emphatically said, *He was himself -‘he Great Polite he drew! T Lord Binning, who wrote some of the mo: t tender and eloquent of the Scottish songs; Hamilton of Languor, whose poetical merits have deservedly assigned him to a place among the British Classics; and the Club of ..'its who frequented Balfour 1 s Coffeehouse ,( the : of Will’s or Button’s) in the early part of the eighteenth century. - 17 - of his Treatise on Human Nature , the principal doctrines o: wl ich were to receive further elaboration in his Philosophical Essays . The importance of the accua intanceship thus eel, and of Karnes’s subsequent study and animadversion upon these doctrines of Hume’s, cannot be overestimated when we- come to our consideration of the Elements of ^ritl cism . Por it was upon the doctrines which he maintained in direct opposition to Hume, that Karnes based not only his philosophy of life, but his philosophy of literature and literary criticism. The two chief points of dispute may be • stated here. To the theory of Hume, that Utility is the chief foundation of morals, Karnes objected. He contended that Hume had fallen into that error common to most philosophers: the error of attempting to simplify the objects of their research, by advanc- one or two general laws, to which they endeavor to reduce all phenomena of our moral nature. Karnes insists that man is a complicated being, motivated by innumerable passions and emotions, and influenced not by any one of them alone, but by all of them working in co-operation or in restraint of each other. The many springs of emotion and passion thus insisted upon here in a professedly moral treatise, we shall find recurring in the Elements, as the basis not alone of morals, but of taste. To thus * -le- as signing a common origin to morals and taste, Professor Saints bury takes great exception in his Hi story of Cyiti cism . It is not my present purpose to defend either of the two great views as to ah at shall constitute the province of criticism. It is here noted, merely, that the critical theories of Karnes are founded upon those same principles from which arose his theory of morals; of this more vail be said 3a ter. The second great point of dispute between Karnes and Hume was the doctrine of the latter which questions the reality of the connection between cause and effect. The alarm of Karnes here was occasioned by the fact that this doctrine tended to invalidate every argument to be dram from a study of natural religion, for the existence of God. He attacked it upon these grounds. Admitting that the connection of cause and effect CcJinot be demonstrated by reason, he insists, nevertheless, that we are assured of its reality by an inner conviction, an innate principle, whose authority is final. -he insistence of Karnes upon the reality of certain inborn principles of man iiich must be regarded as final causes for his thoughts and actions, is here proclaimed in the service of moral philosophy. It is later to -19- be insisted upon with no less vigor in the Elements , as the ultimate basis of taste in the fine arts. The remainder of ICames's life will be sketched hurriedly. He was married, in 1741, to Miss Agatha Drummond of Blair-Drummond . In 175 2 he was elevated to the bench; he re- tained his seat and discharged his duties up until a few days before his death in 1782. The formation of the Select Society in 1754 (1), brought him into closer touch with those men of eminence who had grownup around him in his middle life, and it is tempting to linger over an account of this unusual club in which were assembled the wit and wisdom of the old Scottish capital. Karnes was a charter member of this "insti tuti on, intend- ed partly for philosophical inquiry, and partly for the improve- ment of the members in public spesking," and he contributed greatly to those "debates, where the dignity of the speakers was not lowered by the intrigues of policy, or the intemperance of faction; and where the most splendid talents that have ever adorned this country were roused to their best exertions, by the liberal and ennobling discussions of literature and philosophy. "( 2 ) (1) Hull account of the formation of this society is given in a note written by hr. Alexander c a rlyle, and preserved by hugald Stewart as the first of the ITotes and Illustrations appended to Stewart's Life of Kobertson; in -L'he collected Works of lupald Stewart TTSbhT voI.lO, ‘ (2) Stewart's Life of Robertson. Collected dorks, 10, p 110. - 20 - But this must pass with mere mention; as must likewise the famous Poker Club of 1762, with which Karnes was heartily in sympathy, but which the consideration of his office and station prevented his joining. It would be delightful to dwell upon his association with such men as Blair, for whom he secured appointment as lecturer on Rhetoric and Belles-Lettres at the University of Edinburgh; David Hume, with vhom he remained on terms of intimacy in the midst of their philosophic bickerings; our own Benjamin lklin, with whom he became acquainted in the autumn of 1759 upon the occasion of Eranklin’s visit to Scotland, and with whom he corresponded later concerning the Elements of Grit ici sm . 17 or i s it amiss to mention his friendship for his own printer, Mr. William Smellie, to whose volunteered criticism of the Elements, he made grateful reply , and with whom he corresponded from time to time on terms of mutual esteem. (l) : = bters, however, interesting as they may be, must keep us no longer from our consideration of Karnes’s critical work. The Elements of Criticism appeared in 1762. It purposes to be far more than a work upon mere rhetoric , or even upon the belles- lettres , The entire province of the fine arts is to be examined (1) V id e Lmoirs of the Life . ■•ri tings . and G o r r e s no nd e nc e o f William EmeTTTe. by Robert Kerr. Edinburgh. 1611 . 2 vols . 1. p.545 if. - 21 - with purpose "to trace the objects that are naturally agreeable, as well as those that are naturally disagreeable; and by these means to discover, if we can, what are the genuine principles of the fine arts." (1) Truly an ambitious undertaking, and one in which the author, in spite of his "omniscience” and his usual * dogmatic utterance, seems to have had some misgivings; for he adds the following as a note to his Introduction: The Elements of G ri ti c i sm , meaning the whole , is a title too assuming- for this work. A number of these principles or elements are here unfolded: but as the author is far from imagining that he 1ms completed the list, a mo re humb le title is p ro pe r , s ue h a s may e xpr ess any number of parts less than the whole. This he thinks is signified by the title he lias chosen, vis. Element s of Grit i ci sm . In the Elements . as Tytler notes, Karnes is entering upon a field of research. Other authors, from Aristotle down, had made some attempt to list those passions and. emotions to which the artist might profitably appeal. Karnes purposes to go farther. By a study of man T s nature, he hopes to arrive at those basic principles which must be taken as the ultimate caus.es for his emotional reactions. In other words, psychology is to be brought into the service of criticism. Rhetoric, if understood in the Aristotelian sense of the art of public ress, we shall not find. Karnes, himself, /as not eloquent in the sense in which that word (1) lements . v 1, p 6, sixth edition, Edinburgh, 1785 - 22 - v;as used by the rhetoricians of the Universities. We have hinted before that the reasons assigned by Tytler for his initial failure as a barrister would have special importance in our consideration of his theory of composition. Ty^tler says: His first appearance may have given evidence of his talents as an ingenious reasoner; but as he never pos- sessed those shining powers of oratory which have frequently raised into notice, and brought into high employment, young men who were much his inferiors in solid abilities, it was not till after the publication of his first work on law, that we find him enjoying even a moderate share of practice as a barrister. (1) It is hazardous to attempt a guess as to how much influence this natural inaptitude for public address may have had upon Hames in determining the direction which his studies were to take. But certain it is that these studies are concerned scarcely at all with that eloouence ^ which Professor Millar designates as the bane of eighteenth- century Scotland. (2) IT or is Zanies pr inari - (1) Memoir s . p 60. v i. (2) L Literary History of Scotland, p 321. ,T It was in the Scottish Universities, however, that the^s^tdvin'g after eloquence was product- ive of most mischief. The word i‘S~~always cropping up in the de- scription of enhnent professors, franc is Hutcheson, when enforcing the moral virtues and duties, is said to have ’displayed a "fervid and persuasive eloquence which was irresistible. 1 Dugald Stewart tells us of the el of uence with which Maclaurin, the famous mathema- tician, ’knew how to adorn the most abstracted subjects.’ The’ Strid- ing and impressive eloquence’ of Dugald Stewart himself 'riveted the attention of ^ven the most volatile student' according to Scott, etc . T To which may be added the fact that in the Philosophy of Rhetoric of George Campbell , which we shall consider in another chapter, the term e loquence is used as synonymous with, and in preference to, the term rhetoric. ■ -23 ly ooncerned with written composition. We find this same friendly critic (Tytler) complaining that Karnes seemed TT to have no just conception of what constitutes the chief heauty of rhetorical composition: a variety in the structure of the periods, "both with respect to their length, and the order of their component parts, so as to excite pleasure by the contrast; while each is so framed, as separately by its melody to satisfy and fill the ear.” (l) Karnes, although he takes due notice of diction and sentence structure in a long chapter entitled Beauty of Lan guage is busied for the most part with cy. ite another matter; namely, that (of finding by a study of man 1 2 s own nature, those principles which are the foundation of the fine arts, and then insisting that the fine arts must "hold the mirror up to nature” — or forfeit their title. In such an inquiry, although not primarily concerned with mere rhetoric, Karnes was most certainly well within the classic tradition. Aristotle had pointed the way. Cicero had reiterated that the orator must be versed in all knowledge, and particularly in an understanding of human nature. (2) Thus, if (1) I.Iemoirs . v IT. p 214. (2) Be Or a tore . (See discussion of qualifications of orator in Book I.) - 24 - clii e fly concerned with the mere business of appreciative criticism Kames nevertheless went to the root of all criticism, and undertook a task of equal interest to the rhetorician and to the exponent of belles-lettres . His researches were vital to both fields. His findings and methods proved of value to such widely differing v. r orks as Blair 1 s Lectures and Campbell’s Philosophy of Rhetoric . Ho better commentary upon Karnes’s manner can be found than his treatment of rhetorical figures. Hot as mere parts of the mechanism of composition are they of interest to him, but because in their origin anduse, he can trace the workings-out of certain previously discovered principles of human nature. He says : The endless variety of expressions brought under the head of tropes and figures by ancient critics and grammarians , makes it evident that they had no pre- cise criterion for distinguishing tropes and figures from plain language. It was accordingly my opinion that little could be made of them in the way o f rational critic ism : till, discovering by a sort of accident, that many of them depend on pr inci pie s formerly explained . I gladly embrace the opportunity to_ sh ow the inf luenc e of these principles where i t woul d least be expected . Confining myself therefore to such figures, I am luckily freed from much trash; without dropping, as far as I remember, any trope or figure that merits a -25- proper name. (1) So essential to the grounding of all criticism, did Karnes’s contemporaries consider the Elements, that both Campbell and Blair clearly acknowledge their debt to, their master; and it is almost certain that neither of them would have written as he did had it not been for the work of one who was neither a rhetorician nor exponent of poetics . in the strict sense of the words; but who more than either Blair or Campbell could lay just claim to the title of Critic . Volume I of the El ements of Criticism is composed of seventeen chapters; for purposes of analysis it might well be thrown into three main divisions. Chapters I and II will stand for the first two of these three major parts; they are Perceptions and Ideas in a Train , and Passions and Emotions . The remainder of Volume I, Chapters III — XVII inclusive goes tO' make up the third division, and might be thrown under a general heading lifted from (1) Elements . v II, p. 227 (the underlining is my own). Apropos of Karnes’s treatment of the figures. Professor Saintsbury (History of Criticism, 2 p. 468) says: -- "They enjoy a space which, without being surprised at it, one grudges.” The inference here, if the present writer can judge from Professor Saintsbury’ s context, is that since it was the fad and foible of the age to main much of the classi c-stock-in- trade of the rhetorician, we must not oe surprised if we find Karnes trailing along with the herd. If such inference was intended, it is unjust — and w hat is more, entirely beside the point. Karnes’s words belie this. r -26- the text itself; An Inquiry into ,T such attributes , relations ana circumstances . as in the fine arts are c hie fly employe d to raise agreeable motions . " (l) It should be added that although Karnes here and elsewhere, professes to establish principles upon which to base a judgment in the matter of the fine arts as a whole, his attention directs itself chiefly towards literature, (2) It is an article of faith with Karnes that to attain respectability as a critic, one must approach an understanding of the whole nature of man. We may find faults with his results; his methods may seem antiquated; his psychology may be faulty; but surely in spirit and intent, his work could scarcely be more relevant to the business of criticism: "to trace the rules of criticism to their true principles in the constitution of the (1) Elements I, p 195 (2) Professor Saints bury, in Ins History of Criticism , has laid it down that "much" of Volume I is "irrelevant" to the subject of criticism, and offers as the only fitting title for the book, "Literary Illustrations of Morals." This last is scarcely fair. It is assuming that to Karnes morals and taste were synonymous terms. They were not. He asserted merely that the one was as capable of reasoned: analysis as the other, and that both sprang from certain fixed principles of human nature. If these principles were, as he stated, to be found in human nature, they could be arrived at only by a minute and care fill analysis of human nature. A moralist ay study the emotions and passions of mankind to determine their ethical im- port. surely a critic of letters may study these same emotions and passions to see if they be faithfully and naturally delineated in the literature which he must criticise. And if the preliminary ob- servations in both instances, have uch in common, is there anything remarkable or "irrelevant" in the fact? It is human nature which is analysed in both instances. Small wonder if the processes duplicate each other. - 27 - the human mind, and the nature of the passions and affections.” (1) Chapter I, Percept ions and Ideas in a drain, accompli sh- es a brief survey of the characteristics of the purely intellectual functions of the seat of consciousness. The theme is the associatioi of ideas; the inspiration is Locke. It is pointed out that vhile to a certain extent our chains of ideas rnay be formed involuntari- ly , yet the links of the chain are logically related by associa- tion; there is, moreover, in man the power to ive closer logical connection to his thoughts at will; that this power is based upon our perception of the law of cause and effect, and upon our innate relish for order and connection. This latter principle, our relish for order and connection, is fundamental to all the enjoyments of the intellect, whether it be logic, science, or literature. Since it is thus fundamental to all intellectual pleasure, it is as far as we can go with our analysis. It remains only to test the truth of the principle by an appeal to experience, and then apply it as a standard of judgment to the specimen to be criticised. Karnes makes the test and the application thus: (1) Tytler , I, p 378. ' - 28 - The principle of order is conspicuous with respect to natural operations; for it always directs our ideas in the order of nature; thinking upon a tody in motion, we follow its natural course; the mind falls with a heavy body, descends with a river, and ascends with flame and smoke; in tracing out a family, we incline to begin at the founder, and. descend gradually to the latest posterity: on the contrary, musing on a mighty oak, we begin at the trunk and mount from it to the branches: as to historical facts, we love to proceed in the order of time; or, which comes to the same, to proceed along the chains of cause and effect y (1) How, for the application of this principle to criti- cism. He says: Every work of art that is thus conformable to the natural course of our ideas, is so far agreeable; and. every work of art hat reverses that course, is so far disagreeable. Hence, it is required in every such work, that, like an organ- ic s stem, its parts be orderly arranged and mutually con- nected, bearing each of them a relation to the whole, some more intimate, some less, according to their destination: when d.ue regard is lad to these particulars, we have a sense of just composition, and so far are pleased with the "composition. (2) He then subjects Homer, Pindar, and. Horace, to the test by this canon, and finds that in spite of their genius they are censurable on this score; as likewise are Virgil and Sallust. Episodes in narrative poems, he allows a greater latitude than he will give to parts of exposition or argument; but he insists that (1) Element s . v I,p25. ( 2 ) Elements , v I , p 27 . ■ I - 29 - their introduction “be graceful and natural. He instances as a violation of this principle the descent of Aeneas in Hell, which employs the sixth hook of Aeneid. If it he objected that all this is wasting a prodigious amount of words to tell us what we already know and agree to perfectly; namely, that a composition should he coherent, I reply that such is not at all the case. Karnes is giving us a j ustification for our love of coherence in composition; namely, that the mind demands and always will demand coherence in any in- tellectual process, and that this demand is based upon the lav; of order and association of ideas which governs our thought pro- cesses. And this is quite a different thing from the charge brought in the criticism above. Chapter II . Emotions and Passions . is a long and labored attempt to analyze the character of our emotional pro- cesses. It Is this chapter, above all others in the Elements . that has laid Karnes open to the scoffers. There is no denying that his success is far from complete. Strive as he may, labor- ing valiantly through his Inductions, he cannot make a system rise out of his scattered and multitudinous observations. He himself recognized his difficulties, for he said: -3 0 - Human nature is a complicated machine, and is unavoidably so to answer its purposes. The public indeed have Ions- been entertained by many systems of human nature that flatter the mind by their simplicity: according to some writers, man is entirely a selfish being; according to others, universal benevolence is his duty; one founds morality upon sympathy solely; and one upon utility. If any one of these systems were copied from human nature, the present subject might soon be discussed. Ait the variety of nature is not so easily reached: end for con- futing such Utopian systems without the fatigue of reason- ing, it appears the best method to take a survey of human nature, and to set before the eye, plainly and candidly, facts as they exist, (l) nevertheless, he makes the attempt to bring some order out of his notes and observations. The terms emotion and passion are first examined to see if they be synonymous, and he finds that they are distinguished by the fact that passion is emotion plus desire(2); he notes the causes of emotion in general; objects of sigbtand sound (3); the causes of the emotions of joy and sorrow in particular (4); the fact that in many instances one emotion is productive of another (5); and so on and so forth for some one hundred and forty odd pages. As has been said, the system refuses to erect itself. The processes of induction seem to get little farther than the gathering of material. The material, /hen gathered, appears so diverse and intractable that it will not combine. Perhaps he succeeds as well as most such attempts do. ( 1 ) Elements , 1 , p 34 . ( 2l Elements . 1, p 41. (3/ Elements . 1. p 52 ( 4 ) Eleme nt s , 1 , p 57. (5) Elements , 1, p 66. ' - 31 - At least lie strikes out a great many single instances of various shades and degrees of emotion, and hastens in each instance to illustrate his point hy references to passages from literature. It is this constant practice, this exemplification of his observa- ins by reference to the classics, which seem to have suggested to Professor S a intsbury his title of "Literary Illustrations of Morals." It is only fair to note in this connection that the device is as truly an attempted testing of the worth of the literature, as it is an illustration of Karnes's contentions. I 1 he particular canons of judgment are first derived from Karnes's own observation, and then, and only then, are they sought for in literature. He may indeed feel some satisfaction in finding his points corroborated by other testimony, but he is, after all, applying the truth as he knows it to literature as he finds it. And that is my understan ing of the business of criticism. Observe the following example: Instinctive anger is frequently raised by bodily pain, by a stroke for example upon a tender part, which, ruffling the temper and unhinging the mind, is in its tone similar to anger: and when a man is thus disposed before- hand to anger, he is not nice or scrupulous about an object; the person who gave the stroke, however accidentally, is by an inflammable temper held a proper object, merely for hav- ing occasioned pain. It is still more remarkable that a stock or a stone by which I am hurt, becomes an object of my resnntment: I cm violently inclined to crush it to atoms, d'he passion indeed in that case can be but a single flash; for being entirely irrational, it must vanish with the first reflection. ITor is that irrational effect con- -52- fin ed to bodily pain; internal distress, when excessive, may be the occasion of effects equally irrational; per- turbation of mind occasioned by the loss of a dear friend, will, in a fiery temper, produce momentary sparks of anger against that very friend, however innocent: thus Shakes- peare, in the Tempest, Alonzo . . . Sit down and rest. Ev’n here I will put off my hope, and keep it ITo longer for my flatterer; he is drown’d Whom thus we stray to find, and the sea, mocks Our frustrate search on land. Well, let him go. Act 5, Sc. 5. The final wo rds , JelJL, let him go , are an expression of impatience and anger at Ferdinand, whose absence great- ly disturbed his father, dreading that he was lost in the storm. This nice operation of the human mind is by Shakes- peare exhibited upon another occasion, and finely painted: etc. (l) For lack of space this one example of Karnes’s method must suffice here. It sufficiently illustrates the point that he could find good critical use for his observations upon the nature of passions and emotions. The remainder of Volume I, that part which might be termed Part III will not lend itself to detailed and complete analysis much more readily than did the discussion of Passion and Emotions . The author busies himself with a study of sense im- pressions, particularly of sight and hearing. The immediate objects of his observations are "attributes, relations, and circumstances” of the objects of consciousness. These attributes etc . ar (1) Elements , 1, p 85. - ■ ’ - 55 - into chapters under such headings as, beauty . Grandeur and Sublimity l~o velty , Resemblance and P iss imilitude . etc. The typical method of investigation is as follows: Karnes observes that beaut:; , for ex- ample, invariably gives rise to emotions characterized by " sweet- ness and gaiety”; that is, beauty operating alone upon the mind, its resultant emotions uninfluenced by the operation of any other considerations .( 1 ) Very well, then; if by beauty we may secure emotions of "sweetness and gaiety", how may we analyze beauty? Con- sideration tells him that there are two kinds of beauty; intrinsic and relat ive . Intrinsic beauty is an object of sense merely; to perceive the beauty of a spreading oak, or of a flowing river, no more is required but singly an act of vision. The perception of relative beauty is accompanied by an act of the understanding and reflection; for of a fine instrument or engine, we perceive not the relative beauty, until we be made acquainted with its use and destination. In a word intrinsic beauty is ultimate; relative beauty is that of means relating to some good end or purpose. (£) How although he has just called intrinsic beauty "ultimate" he goes on to analyze it. A tree, for instance , may be beautiful in sever ' ways; for its color, shape, size and motion. Each of these beauties is susceptible of analysis or explanation. An example of his analysis of the beauty of shape or figure will suffice . A circle and a square are each of them perfectly regular ^ being equally confined to a precise form, which admits not the slightest variation, (thus both are pleasing or beautiful and their beauty may be traced to the (1) Elements, v 1. n. 197 (2) Elements , 1. p. 197 -54 inherent love of the mind for regularity and order, as explained above* ) But, "a square is less beautiful than a circle. And the reason seems to be that the at- tention is divided among the sides and angles of a square; whereas the circumference of a circle, being a single object, makes one entire impression. And thus simplicity contributes to beauty; which may be illustrated by another example; a square, tho T not more regular than a hexagon or octagon, is more beautiful than either; for what other reason, but that a square is more simple, the attention less divided? This reasoning will appear the more conclusive when we consider any regular polygon of very many sides; for of this figure the mind can never have any distinct impression. (l) So much for the method. As to the truth and value of the results, opinions may differ. Yet the present writer noted not long ago -- he cannot reme ber where, and of course is highly cen- surable for introducing anonymous testimony into a paper of this character -- an article of contemporary art criticism in which these same methods were employed in attempted analysis of the comparative beauty of straight and curved lines. Perhaps no one ill ever be able to tell us why beauty is beautiful; perhaps there is no ans- wer. But fames attempts it, and the at i t, regardless of its success or ft ilure, seems not quite ” irrelevant" to the business of criticism. Volume II of the Element s opens with a chapter entitled Beauty of Language . The chapter is a long one; one hundred and eighty- two pages. As might be expected from a study of Volume I, Karnes is not interested alone in giving us examples of beautiful language, and stating the rules of composition which may enable us (l) fie meat s . 1. p. 108. to imitate it. He wants to go farther. He wishes to ground the rules themselves upon human nature; and by this time we have seen enough of our- author to know that by human nature he means chiefly the sensitive powers of man. examples of choice literature, he does give in abundance, and for the most part quite excellent ones. Rules he does lay town; and they are not copied slavishly from the theories of the time, (l) But beyond all rules and examples lies a reason. This reason or cause is the goal of Karnes’s study. The root idea of the whole chapter is that expressed by Karnes in his discussion of beauty in "Volume I, above cited; namely that there is intrinsic and a relative beauty. Relative beauty is exemplified in composition when the separate members, bo Hi large and snail, are well adapted to the immediate end. Mere perspicuity is a beauty in this sense, because of the intellectual character of the composition as distinguished from its appeal to sense. But quite aside from this relative beauty, this adaptation of means to an end, there is purely a sensuous beauty of language. Under the section headed Beauty of Language with respect to Bound (1) His opinion concerning rhyme (and by rhyme he means particular- ly the heroic couplet) is not at all orthodox for his times. He ends his attack upon the couplet by the statement that "rhyme, in Great Britain, will in time be forc'd to abandon its unjust con- quests, and to confine itself within its proper limits." (Elements, 2. p. 176) Which limits, he who cares to read Karnes will find, are a direct challenge to the school of Pope. - - 26 - Kames begins: "This subject requires the following order. The sounds of the different letters come first; next these sounds as united in syllables; third syllables united into words; fourth, words united in periods; and in the last place, periods united in a discourse. (1) I shall not follow Karnes in his discussion of these various phases of composition. He is for the most part just and sensible. The point to be made is this. Karnes grounds his scheme upon direct appeal to the experience of sense. He would teach composition by teaching the truths of what is agreeable to the ear. How many classes in composition today ever have their at- tention drawn to the reasons for the rules which they are com- pelled to follow; or rather, the rules which are offered for their guidance? In the mere matter of vowel and consonant combina- tions, let the instructor ash his class to distinguish between the effects produced by the first and last stanzas of Poe's poem. The Bells . The answers he will get should be illuminating. But to return to the Elements : — a comparatively short chapter on Comparisons . a much longer one upon figures , and five more of approximately the same length, Barra ti on and Description . Epic and Dramatic Oompo sit ion . The Three Unities . Gardening and Architecture . together with an appendix. Terms Defined and Explained . complete the work. Here too, Karnes is constantly giving rules and (1) Elements . 2. p. 6. ■ -57- examples — unusually distinguished for their good sense and propri- ety. Seldom are his precepts slavishly adopted from the school of pseudo-classicism; he dares deny the ordinances of the gods, and supports his denials by good and stout reasons, as in his attacks upon the superstition of the three unities. (1) It is in exemplifying the reasons behind the rules, that Karnes takes chief delight. This is the avowed intent and purpose of his whole work, and In this he lays claim to originality. One more example of his methods will suffice. As noted earlier in this paper, Karnes spoke of the springs of human action as being extremely numerous and complex. The final action or emotional response, he asserted, was the result of many tendencies working in hanaony or in opposition. This final example illustrates the union of two principles. It occurs in the chapter entitled Res emb lane e and Kissimili tude in Volume I, but its special application is made in the chapter on Comparisons . Volume II, where, indeed it is cited (2) after a con- sideration of certain phenomena calculated to support his conten- tion inductively, Karnes says: Whatever is found more strange or beautiful than was expected, is judged to be more strange or beautiful than in re lity? Hence a common artifice, to depreciate before- hand what we wish to make a figure in the opinions of others. The comparisons employ’d by poets and orators, are of the kind last mentioned; for it is always a known object (1) Elements 2, p. 414. "Modem critics, who for our drama pretend to establish rules founded on the practice of the Greeks, are guilty of an egregious blunder." (Karnes) ( 2 ) Kleme nt s . v I , p . 29 2 . , - 38 - that is to be magnified and lessened. The former is effected by likening it to some grand object, or by contrasting it with one of the opposite character. To effectuate the lat- ter, the method must be reversed; the object must be con- trasted with something superior to it, or likened to some- thing inferior. The whole effect is produced ux-)on the principal object, which by that means is elevated above its rank, or depressed below it. In accounting for the effect that any unusual resemblance or dissimilitude hath upon the mind, no cause has been mentioned but surprise : and to prevent confusion it was proper to discuss that cause first. But surprise is not the only cause of the effect described; another con- curs, which operates perhaps not less powerfully, namely, a principle in human nature that lies still in obscurity, not having been unfolded by any writer, tho 1 its effects are extensive; and as it has not been distinguished by a proper name, the reader must be satisfied with the follow- ing description, Every man who studies himself, mm t be sensible of a tendency or propensity in the mind, to complete every work that is begun, and to carry things to their full perfection. There is little opportunity to display that propensity on natural operations, which are seldom left imperfect; but in the operations of art, it hath great scope : it impells us to persevere in our own work, and to wish for the completion of what another is doing’; we feel a sensible pleasure when the work is brought to perfection; and our pain is no less sensible when we are disappointed. Hence our uneasiness when an interesting story is broke off in the middle, when a piece of music ends without a close, or when a building or garden is left unfinished. The same propensity operates in making collections, such as whole works, good and bad, of any author. A certain person attempting to collect prints of all the capital paintings, succeeded except as to a few. La Bruyers remarks, that an anxious search was made for these; not for their value, but to complete the set. We need not lose time to describe the co-operation of the foregoing propensity with surprise, in producing the effect that follows any unusual resemblance or dissimilitude. Surprise first operates, and carries our opinion of the resemblance or dissimilitude beyond truth. The propensity we have described carries us still farther; for it forces upon the mind a conviction that the resemblance or dis- similitude is complete. We need no better illustration than the resemblance, that is fancied in some pebbles to a tree or an insect; which resemblance, however faint in reality, is conceived to be wonderfully perfect. » • • * -S9~ So much for the concurrence of two principles in the literary artifice of cornua ris on . Now for an example of direct ap- plication of all this to criticism? I have purposely chosen a faulty application, for it will not only illustrate the method, hut will point out its dangers and limitations; it may moreover tend to corroborate Tytler's estimate of Karnes's taste. (1) Most of the illustrations in Karnes's text are not open to this fault, hut occasionally he blunders badly; usually from a blind atten- tion to some particular "principle”, and a mechanical application of it. Karnes reaffirms in the chapter on comparisons that "it hath no good effect to compare things by way of simile that are of the same Kind; nor to compare by contrast things of different kinds An example of the first fault is given. It is just. Then he says: The next shall be of things contrasted that are of different kinds. Queen . What, is my Richard, both in shape and mind Transformed and weak? Hath Bolingbroke depos'd Thine intellect? Hath he been in thy heart! The lion thrusteth forth his paw And wounds the earth, if nothing else, with rage To be o'erpowered: and wilt thou, pupil-like. Take thy correction mildly, kiss the rod. And fawn on rage with base humility? (Richard II, Act. v. Sc. I.) (1) Tytler, v 1, p. 445. He asserts "that the general correctness of the author's taste was more the result of study and attention, than in any extraordinary sensibility in the structure of his mind to the emotions excited by the production of the fine arts." - 40 - This comparison has scarce an y force: a man and a lion are of different species, and are therefore proper subjects for a simile; but there is no such resemblance be- tween them in general, as to produce any strong effect by con- trasting particular attributes or circumstances. What is wrong here? Surely it takes but little of natural taste to realize that while the comparison may not be of the highest order, it is not actually censurable. I think we can best answer Karnes by an appeal to his own system. He admits that a man and a lion are "proper subjects for simile"; he might have added "metaphor". Intent upon his first canon, that dissimilar objects afford no basis for contract . he is utterly blind to the fact that in the passage quoted, a prince and a lion have been identified by the boldest of all devices, an implied metaphor. By this implied identification the two are placed in a situation where the queen may justly reproach the "lion" for belying his nature, and " fawning with base humility." Of course accidents will happen; but it is highly suggestive that this man who can tell us exactly why a simile or metaphor has its effect, is yet not capable of appreciating that effect in a striking example. I’he fault is after all not so much with the method as with the man. He can appreciate the effect of a given figure, be- cause his intellect tells him that the effect should follow. But where the effect of one figure, as in the instance above, depends ; ' ■ t -41- up on appreciation of a preceding figure, he copies to grief unless he has noted that preceding figure. This he failed to do. He has missed a link in the chain, and will come out in error with math- ematical certainty. Tytler has given other examples of this fai ling. ( 1 ) It remains only for us to take notice of Karnes’s conclusions u on the standard of taste in the fine arts. It is much easier to point out his failure in determining this standard, than it is to correct his error. His entire work has led us to believe that within each of us are those final and ultimate principles which will guide our judgment infallibly. Indeed, we might all expect to arrive at the same standard of judgment, and all set up for critics in our own right. What is to hinder? Hoes he not expressly state that "However languid and cloudy the common sense of mankind may be as to the fine arts, it is notwithstanding the only standard in these as well as in morals?” But, alas, he no sooner says this than he begins to qualify. We cannot all be critics all at once; for, "those T «vho depend for food on bodily labor, are totally devoid of taste; of such taste at least as can be of use in the fine arts. This con- sideration bars the greater part of mankind; and of the remaining part, many by a corrupted taste are unqualified for voting." The (1) Memoirs . I. p. 451. 55 - ■ ' jl ♦ - 42 - exceptions to these two classes, he adds, must decide matters. In other words, falling into that fallacy knoim to logicians as petitio principii . he says in effect: "Those only have good taste who — have good taste.” The standard by which he excludes the greater part of mankind as the judges of taste, is his own pre- conceived idea as to what is in accordance with good taste. His taste may be right; but if it be formed upon those unchangeable , fixed principles which are common to mankind, why are not all other men in accord with him? I think we shall have to agree finally that Karnes has chosen his title wisely : -Elements of Criticism , and not The Elements, it truly must be called. He makes a brave attempt, an original attempt, and in many ways an extremely valuable attempt, to sound the human mind. But it is not complete. Certainly some very important elements escaped him in his main treatment of the theme, and are suggested to him only at the close of his work. He turns from them hastily as though too tired to go on -- as perhaps he was. If he had not made a complete system, he had struck out many individual canons and standards which served well as measur- ing sticks for particular passages of literature. If to the spirit and inspiration of literature as a whole, he had not been too attentive, one man cannot do it all. Credit is due him that he did so well as a critic, with so little natural taste; that he escaped so well from the idols of his time, with so little chance . - 43 - of escaping them. To a boot, English was almost a foreign tongue; English literature, a foreign literature. He is no unworthy critic who can master an unfamiliar language and literature so thoroughly that he can make some pretence of teaching those to whom it is native . And above and beyond all this, he has the greater claim to our attention, that although neither an exponent of rhetoric nor a professor of belles lettres in the strictly classic sense of both words, he nevertheless did yeoman service in both fields, and laid down a method which proved of equal, value to those two men whose work I shall consider in the following chapters. , ■ . , BLAIR AND HIS LECTURES. CHAPTER III . Following close upon ICames, and building upon the foundations laid by him in the Elements of Criticism , comes the Reverend Dr. Hugh Blair (l) minister of the High Church, and Pro- fessor of Rhetoric and Belles lettres in the University of Edinburgh. His Lectures first appeared in their present form in 1785, but por- tions of them had been read to classes as early as 1759, the year which began his connection with the University of Edinburgh. So well were these Lectures received at that early date, that in 1762 a Chair of Rhetoric and Belles Lettres was installed and endowed by royal decree. This chair Blair continued to hold until the year 1785. Unlike Karnes, Blair laid little claim to omniscience. He was first a divine, and second a critic of letters. A detailed study of his life adds little of value to our appreciation of his critical worth. Much more to the point are the crisp, vivid characterizations given of him in "Jupiter” Carlyle* s Autobiography. (2) Contrasting his character with that of his friend and fellow (1) A Short Accoun t of the Life and Character of Dr. Hugh Blair, by James Finlay son, I). D. in Blair’s Sermons. London. 1801. vol.'*5. (2) P. 291. ff. - 45 - minister, Dr. Robertson, Carlyle says: Dr. Diair was a different kind of man from Dr. Robertson, and his character is very justly delineated by Rinlayson as far as he goes. Robertson was most sagacious, Blair was most naif. Neither of them could be said to have either wit or humour. Of the latter, Robertson had a small tincture — Blair had hardly a relish for it. Robertson had a bold and ambitious mind, and a strong desire to make himself considerable; Blair was timid and unambitious, and withheld himself from public business of every kind, and seemed to have no wish but to be admired as a' preacher, particularly by the ladies. His conversation was so in- fantine that many people thought it impossible, at first sight, that he could be a man of sense or genius. He was as eager about a new paper to his wife’s drawing room, or his , own, new wig , as about a new tragedy or a new epic __ _ _ _ 3^ >|C ^ poem# Robertson had so great a desire to shine himself, that I hardly ever saw him patiently bear anybody else's showing off but Dr. Johnson and Garrick. Blair, on the contrary, though capable of the moost profound conversation when circumstances led to it, had not the least desire to shine, but was delighted beyond measure to show other people in their best guise to his friends. TT Did I not show the lion well today?” used he to say after the exhibition of a remarkable stranger. Ror a vain man he was the least envious I ever knew. He had truly a pure mind, in which there was not the slightest malignity; for though he was of a ipuick and lively temper, and apt to be warm and impatient about trifles, his wife, who was a superi- or woman, only laughed, and his friends joined with her. I think that within this succint characterization of Blair, the student of his Lectures will find most of what is need- ful for an understanding of their merits and defects. To the modesty of the man is due the lack of that dogmatic utterance and assurance which characterised Karnes's work; to the impetuosity and liveliness of his disposition — qualities usually at variance , -46- with sober judgment -- may we ascribe his championship of the claims of Ossian; in his timidity we may find an explanation of that curious vacillation between his own instinctive judgments *- and the "rules Tt of pseudo-classicism: a conflict which I hope to make apparent in this chapter. As to the lack of humor at- tributed to him by Carlyle, and its effects upon some of his crit- ical judgments, I have some personal opinions of interest to my- self: but as they are far from orthodox, and would ta he time and space which I can ill afford for their justification, I have judged them of too little relative importance to include here. Various judgments have been passed upon the value of Blair’s work as a critic and rhetorician. Indeed, the same author- ities have at different times contradicted themselves concerning him. I offer as one instance of this, two estimates by Professor Millar. In his Literary History of Scotland. . (1902) , he says: Into the enormities perpetrated in the pulpit it is needless to enter. _ It is enough to refer to the egregious sermons of Lr . Hugh Blair, which in popularity had almost no competitor, and which seem to recapitulate into themselves all the most serious characteristic faults to which the prose writing of the eighteenth- century had become liable. (1) And a little later in the same volume he adds: The author whom his contemporaries most over- rated was probably Lr. Hugh Blair .... YYe have al- ready referred to his Sermons as typical of the worst sort of eighteenth- century prose, and his Lectures (1783) on his professional subject are not much better, though they have some value as an indication of what (1) pp. ?19-£20 -47- it was thought proper to think about literature at the date of their delivery. Blair's fault is that he can not say a plain thing in a plain way; nor is he comparable for originality and suggestiveness of view to Principal George Campbell, of Aberdeen (1719-96) whose Philo soph}/ of Rhe t or i c . though some- what discursive, is by far the most valuable contribu- tion to criticism which came from Scotland during the Century. (1) The foregoing are pretty flat condemnations of Blair’s pretensions to any worth. But in his volume entitled Scottish Pro se of the seventeenth and Eighteenth Centuries . ( 1912) Professor Millar seems to have suffered a change of heart. He reiterates his remarks about the general worthlessness of the sermons, though in far less vehement manner than that whieh characterized his earlier utterances; but he adds: "His Lectures appear to be more worthy of c onsideration. ,T He "owns" -- the word of an advocate and not an accuser -- "that they do not open too auspiciously," but once we have passed the beginning sentences, he asserts that we "come to better stuff; something much more manly and bracing." As one pursues the text, his wonder grows as to just how far Professor Millar had passed the beginning sen- tences in his work of 1903; at the end we come to this complete about-face : Once we admit that it (codification of criticism) is a legitimate operation, we shall find little difficulty in (1) pp. 357-558 -48- assigning a high place among its practicioners to Blair, etc. (1) As to the ill-fated Sermons which Professor Millar per- sists in condemning for their prose style, it may be remarked in passing that they pleased Dr. Johnson mightily. This, in itself, is no surety of their worth, to be sure. But I do not think that the reader of today will find them as bad as they are painted. Platitudinous they may be. In sentiment they lend themselves to the efforts of those who have delighted to extract choice morsels from moral essays, and foist them upon the public as "Beauties". (a) Yet for all their gentle platitudes, their style seems scarce- y ly to merit the charge of egregiousness. I have found much more of this nature to condemn in the Lectures themselves; — ■ though not an over amount there. I have hinted that in these lectures the student will find a conflict between Blair's own natural taste, and the neo- classic standards of taste to which he feels he must conform. Be- fore going on to the Lectures . we may note this conflict exemplified in his Dissertat ion upon Qssian . Lever did man come to more grief than did the good Doctor in his labors to justify a "romantic" pleasure, by pseudo-classic criticism. It was not the epic structure of Ossian that entranced him. Of this we have ample (1) Scottish Prose., p* 224. (2) I have before me a curious little volume entitled, "The Beauties of Blair," Boston, 1828. -49- proof in those beauties upon which he dwells when he dees not feel that he is defending Ossian. It was the passages of "sublimity" that thrilled and pleased him; the gloom and obscurity of the pictures; the melancholy of the emotions called forth. But accord ing to the pseudo-classic creed of "hind", all the beauties in the world will not save a piece if it be not true to the "rules". Bo Blair justifies Ossian by showing how he conforms to the rules. The absurdity of all this was mercilessly pointed out some years later by "Christopher North" (John Wilson), in a re- view entitled Have You Head Ossian ? (1) "Crusty, rusty, musty, fusty Christopher," as Tennyson named him, was a fine tantrum and laid about him with lusty blows ; but he hit the mark. Having amiably designated Blair as "the simplest of all professors that ever lectured on Rhetoric and 3elle s Lettres," he laughs the Dissertation out of countenance, as indeed it deserved to be. I quote the following only to comment upon the bare possibility that in 1903 Professor III liar may have oeen better acquainted with "Christopher North" than with Hugh Blair. Liston to Christopher; "What if all this, prodigious nonsense as it now appears to us, be true? Hugh Blair is a far higher name than Christopher North — and his Sermons, though not proper readings for Sundays, are not to be sneezed at, though they may be blamelessly yawned over; but his Lectures, they are indeed words of power to charm the couch of the wakeful, ’tired nature's sweet restorer, balmy sleep.'" (1) Blackwood' 3 Edinburgh Magazine, November, 1839 - - 50 - After reading this last paragraph, one familiar with Christopher 1 s methods and disposition, can only wonder who it was that told him that "Hugh Blair is a far higher name than Christopher north." But to proceed to the Lectures . Professor Millar, as we have seen, compares them with the work of Principal Campbell and pronounces them distinctly inferior in "originality and suggestive- ness of view," Comparisons are always dangerous. Particularly are they so when uttered without due regard as to whether the works are fit subjects for comparison. It is difficult to see how just comparative estimate can. be made so readily in the case of two works so widely different in aim and spirit as are the Lectures and a the Philosophy of Rhetoric . The first, although designated as dealing with Rhetoric and Belle s Lettres . concern themselves almost wholly with Bel le s Lettres ; or rather with the larger division of which Belles Lettres is a part. I refer to the ancient classical designation "Poetics". Campbell, on the other hand, concerns himself with Rhetoric proper, as understood by the Creeks and Romans. The aims and interests of the two men differ almost as much as do the problems of the teacher of literature and the teacher of public speaking today. Both Blair and Campbell are in- debted to Karnes for their philosophic and psychological grounding. This they have in common; but from this common starting point they . . ' -51- tread diverging paths. So far as I can discover, there is no re- cognition of this fact in the treatment which the two have hereto- fore received. The hectares of Blair are divided into five parts, dealing respectively with taste, language, style, eloquence (he lists the title and spends a prodigious amount of space upon it, but scarcely in the spirit of Campbell) and lastly a critical examination of the most distinguished species of composition both in prose and verse. In his Introduction, Blair follows hard upon the heels of Karnes in announcing that criticism is a rational pro- cess, subject to the dictates of reason. Sure, (he says) it is equally possible to apply the principles of reason and good sense to this art, as to any other that is cultivated among men? If the following Lectures have any merit, it will consist in an endeavor to substitute the application of these principles in the place of artificial and scholastic rhetoric; in an endeav- or to explode false ornament, to direct attention more to- wards subject than show, to recommend good sense as the foundation of all good composition, and simplicity as es- sential to all true ornament. (1) He then proceeds to define taste In art as "the power of receiving pleasure from the beauties of nature and of art." The ensuing discussion is founded upon Karnes, although it attempts to go beyond and correct him. 31air could not but be conscious that Karnes load left taste somewhat in a muddle. He does not want to agree (1) • Lectures . p. 10. Sixth American Edition, 1871. ' -52- \ with Karnes 1 s packed jury of judges. He is sure with Karnes that taste is based upon principles of human nature (1); that its bases are the ultimate sense likes and dislikes (2); with Karnes he as- serts that taste may be improved by the aid of reason (3); but like Karnes he sees that not all men are equal in critical discern- ment (4). In view of this last then, what shall be the standard of taste? He selves the difficulty to his own satisfaction by assert- ing that time will solve the difficulty. "To the ultimate sense of mankind the ultimate appeal must ever lie in all works of taste," is a statement that must be qualified by the added as- surance that in spite of the distractions of the moment and the warping influences of prejudice and ignorance, "in the course of time, the genuine taste of human nature never fails to disclose / itself." Hqw this has a specious appearance of solving the difficulty; I very much doubt if it does more than appear to solve. How, it may be asked, can the mere passage of time improve the taste of the vulgar? It is by a growth of reason, in the individual that he experiences a growth of taste. The vulgar of one genera- tion are not the elect of the next. They die off and are re- placed by new vulgarians whose discrimination in matters of taste (1) Lectures , p. 16. (2) Ibid, p. 17. (3) ibid, p. 19. (d) Ibid, p. 17. - 55 - is woefully in need of the aid of reason as was their forebears'. The intellectuals of one generation, those whose taste is admitted- ly discriminating, may indeed be freed from the prejudices which blinded the elect of a preceeding age; but the standard of taste is still in the keeping of the cognoscenti . The vulgar in any generation will come to the appreciation of genius, I am afraid, with no more readiness than did the vulgar of that generation in which the genius appeared. The man of the streets and the Loan of the soil would be in an overwhelming majority in any census of critical opinions of today. To neither would the literary critic turn for a judgment of Homer. This very difficulty with his own solution of the question seems to have occurred to Blair, although he does not suffer it to appear in company with his theory. He allows several hundred pages to go by before he permits the troublesome objection to show its head. Hear him: It i s vain to allege, that the reputation of the ancient poets and orators, is owing to authority, to pedantry, and to the prejudices of education, transmitted from age to age. These, it is true, are the authors put into our hands at schools and colleges, and by that means we have an early prepossession in their favour; but how came they to gain the possession of schools and colleges? Plainly, by the fame which these authors had among their own contemporaries. Por the Greek and Latin were not always dead languages. There was a time when Homer, and Virgil, and Horace, were viewed -54- in the same light as we now view Dryden, Pope and Addison. It is not to the commentators and univer- sities that the classics are indebted for their fame! They become classics and school boohs in consequence of the high admiration which was paid them by the best judges in their own country and nation. (1). (2). Alas for the good Doctor! He is fighting here only the battle of the ancients and the moderns — but with such spirit that he quite fails to notice the blows he is showering upon his earlier statements about the universal taste of mankind. How indeed did the classics get into the colleges! And how, we may add, did Dryden, Pope, and Addison get there? The Doctor has told us. They were put there "in consequence of the high admira- tion which was paid them b£ th e_ - e!3 ~k judges in their own country and nation." And so the question goes bach to where Karnes left it. Who has taste? Why -- "the best judges;" or they — who have taste! Ho one who reads this paper will, I venture to judge, disagree with Blair in his contention that Horner should be in the college curriculum. The point is: that nine tenths (1) Lee ton es . p. 389. (2) Vide Durham , p. 129; John Dennis, speaking concerning Taste in Poetry gives expression to this same view. Says he: -- "He who writes for the few today, writes for the many of tomorrow." This, in my opinion, is utterly false in so far as it means that the "best" things of this age wi. 11 be any surer of recognition by the day-laborer of a century hence, or any number of centuries hence, than they are by the day-laborer of today. -55- ox mankind do not care a twopence that he is there; or if they hatfe a care, it is that they may never have to read him* From the intricacies and subtleties of his remarks upon the nature of taste in general, -Blair emerges for a space to give us a sample of his own taste. It is here that v/e note again the perplexity of the Professor, torn between his own judgment and the "rules’', His timidity makes him compromise. The subject of his criticism is Bhakespeare: Shakespeare pleases, not by his bringing the transactions of many years into one play; not by his grotesque mixture of tragedy and comedy in one piece, nor by the strained thoughts and affected witticisms, which he sometimes employe. These we consider as blem- ishes, and impute them to the grossness of the age in which he lived. But he pleases by his animated and masterly representation of characters, by the liveliness of his descriptions, the force of his sentiments, and his possessing, beyond all writers, the natural language of passion; beauties which criticism no less teaches us to place in the highest rank, than nature teaches us to feel.(l) With what relief he is able in that last sentence to justify "nature” by "criticism” I Let us not be too harsh upon Blair for this pandering to the rules. It cannot be recalled too often that he was a Boot, and that the literature he criticised was English. Hr. Johnson was down at London, and unless one remembered that Samuel had turn- ed and rent his own litter in that memorable preface which exploded the three unities, — unless one happened to remember this, I say, (1) Lectures, p. 29. II II — — g— WWW — — — . -56 lie might scarcely suspect Samuel of having done it. On the whole, it must have seemed reasonable that the English should know the genius of their own language and literature. End Scotland was desperately trying to be English, There is some excuse for Blair if he rather helplessly submits to rules which torture his ingen- uity to justify his own taste. It is a point in his favor that he somehow or other got his admiration for Shakespeare recorded. Yet in spite of all this, one turns back with relish to Karnes, who threw the whole matter of the unities unceremoniously into the dust -bin. following hard upon this criticism of Shakespeare, Blair treats us to an analysis of Sublimity in Kames T s best manner. Sublimity, he tells us, has a tvo-fold aspect for the subject of criticism: Sublimity in Objects . and Sublimity in Writin g. Of the former, he lists the elements. l*hey are vastness, great power and strength, terror, obscurity, darkness, disorder, magnanimity, and heroism. After some further observations he arrives at the conclusion that the sin e qua non of the objective sublimity seems to be "mighty force or power, whether accompanied by terror or not . " ( 1 ) (1) Lectures , p. 57 * -57- Thence he passes to the sublime in writing. Here he warns us to be on our guard against the false sublime, or "sublime style." This he pronounces "for the most part a very bad style." But, "wherever a great and awful object is presented in nature, or a very magnanimous and exalted affection of the human mind is dis- played; thence if you can catch the impression strongly, and exhibit it warm and glowing, you may draw the sublime.” As an in- stance of the true sublime he gives us: M G-od said, let there be light, and there was light." As an instance of the false sublime style he quotes: "The soverign arbitrer of nature, by the potent energy of a si ngle word, commanded the light to exist." Very good. Would that diair could always follow his own precepts. 1 Professor Millar has accused -Blair of writing ex- ecrable prose. He gives the following example, which, although not typical of Blair's style by any means, is reduplicated far too often particularly in the Lectures . When Blair wishes to say that a good writer may be a bad man, he puts it thus: "Elegant speculations are sometimes found to float upon the surface of the mind, vhile bad passions possess the interior of the heart." (l) It is extremely difficult to see how a man who could criticise the one instance of the false sublime quoted above, could be guilty of the other. (1) Literary History of Scotland , p. 558. v. 1. -58- There follows this discussion of the sublime in Blair, mother typical Kamesian discussion of Beauty. The chapter affords but one passage of interest to us, and that of an incidental nature. I refer to Blair’s remarks upon gardening, which show that he was not thoroughly imbued with eighteenth- century English ideas. Witness his remarks: A straight canal is an insipid figure, in comparison with the meanders of rivers. Cones and pyramids are beautiful; but trees growing in their natural wildness, are infinitely more beautiful than when trimmed into pyramids and cones. The apartments of a house must be regular in their disposition, for the conveniency of its inhabitants; but a garden which is designed merely for beauty, would be ex- ceedingly disgusting, if it had as much uniformity and order in its parts as a dwelling house. (1) Next Blair enters upon a subject dear to the eight- eenth century heart: a history of the rise and progress of language from Adam to the eighteenth century. There is little to claim our attention till we come to the tenth lecture, a treatment of style. Here Blair wrestles with the problem of defining style. He recognizes that it is almost impossible to separate it from substance, yet he tries it. Insofar as it may be treated separate- ly, its qualities "may be ranged under two heads, perspicuity and ornament." Perspicuity is absolutely essential, and must be (1) Lectures . p. 51 ' -59- secured by attention both to single words and to their union into sentences. He will have it that there are no true synonyms, and his insistence upon the right word in the right place is suggest- ive of the care that Ruskin was to recommend; though perhaps Ruskin was more concerned v/ith the connotative value of a word, than with its mere accuracy. As to the structure of sentences, he will have us give regard to clearness and precision; unity; strength; and harmony. To secure strength in a sentence, we are instructed to "prune it of all redundant words” and to "contract the round- about expression. Here a severe eye should be employed; and we shall always find our sentences acquire more vigor and energy when thus retrenched: provided always that we do not run into the extreme of pruning so very close , as to give a hardness and dryness to the style. Hor here, as in all other things, there is a due medium. Some regard, though not the principal, must be had to fulness and swelling of sound. Some leaves must be left to sur- round and shelter the fruit." (l) (1) Lectures . p. 125 It must be under this last proviso that Blair wrote that sent- ence concerning "elegant speculations". Or the following sentence: "The expressions which come warm and glowing from the mind, during the fervour of pronunciation, will often have a superior grace or energy to those which are studied in the retirement of the closet." Or: "Infinitely better it is, to venture into the pulpit v/ith thoughts arid expressions which have occurred to themselves, though of inferior beauty, than to disfigure their compositions by borrow- ed and ill-sorted ornaments, which to the judicious eye, vail al- ways be in hazard of discovering their own poverty. " ? L e c tur e s . p. 521; and p. 525.) - 60 - Blair, here, is engaged with co nr. osition . which is certainly disputed ground between rhetoric and poetics . being ob- viously indispensable to both, Uor con we lay it down with certain- ty, as in some instances is possible, which of these two departments is more emphasized in his treatment. Her when he comes, after some further comments upon style, to a detailed examination of chosen specimens of composition, can we pronounce with any more certainty whether his observations are more pertinent to the useful art or the fine art. He condemns Shaft sbury*s extreme artificiality; praises Addison's prose style highly, and subjects four of his Spectator Papers to ’'sound, if somewhat meticulous" (1) examination; style is discussed as being diffuse or concise, feeble or nervous, dry, plain, neat, elegant, and flowery; and then he plunges into his treatment of eloquence and does not eusxge short of one hundred and twenty-six pages. Such an amount of space, ostensibly devoted to the needs of the orator and evidently intended to meet in some sort the desires of his classes in "eloquence", would at first seem inconsistent with the statement that ^lair is not directly cons ern- ed with rhetor ic . But even a cursory study of the nine lectures mailing up this division will show that Blair advances very little (1) The words are Professor Baintsbury's. History of Criticism. 2. p. 463. ! ! * - ‘ ; « - Gl- int o the field. (His treatment of Elocution is primarily concerned with the matter of diction, and his various ie ctures upon oratory do little more than repeat his previously uttered injunctions as to perspicuity, fluency, and elegance of style ^ The classic element of invent io . or gathering and arranging of material, which occupies such great place in the traditional rhetorical training; the insistence that the orator shall occupy the whole province of knowledge, which Cicero expounds (1); all this is scarcely touched upon by Blair. It is further noteworthy — though in this he is more pertinent to the subject than was Aristotle — that but one lecture out of the nine is devoted to dlivery. Of that lecture the less said the better. (2) Emerging from his treatment of oratory (which, then, was less a consideration of oratory than a reapplication of his (1) he Oratore, Book I. (2) The Story of The Univ e rsity of Edinburgh , oir Alexander Grant ( 1884] v. II. p. S57: —^Admired as Blair was as a preacher, his sermons were better in print than when delivered by him; for he had no graces of delivery, and ’independently of a very strong provincial accent, his elocution was but indifferent from a defect in the organ of pronunciation.' He appears to have been singularly deficient as an extempore speaker , and on this account declined to be made Moderator of the General Assembly, hr. Carlyle smiles at the idea of someone having written to ask Blair to instruct him in the art of preaching." -62- remarks upon diction and style) 31air is happy to return to avowed matters of literary criticism; but, alas, he lias largely spent himself, end has little new material — certainly little material of value — to give us. In rules of composition he was often happy; usually just. He now discusses in the following order: Comparative Merit of the Ancients and the Moderns: Historical Writing: Philosophical Writing -- Dialogue, Epistolary 'Writing, Fictitious History; Uature of Poetry, Its Origin and Progress, Versifica- tion; Pastoral Poetry, Lyric Poetry: Didactic Poetry, Descriptive Poetry; The Poetry of the Hebrews: Epic Poetry, Homer, Virgil, Voltaire, and Milton: Dramatic Poetry, Tragedy, Greek Tragedy, French Tragedy: Comedy -- Greek, Homan, French and English. Here indeed is a wealth of title; but observe the character of the titles; — they are ’’kinds” . Blair promises that in his discussion of these subjects he will "freely deliver {his) opinion: regarding authority no farther, than it appears to (him) founded on good sense and reason." There is something ominous in these last words-- "good sense and reason." One gets a sudden foreboding that B]air may confuse his own good sense and reason with that of the English Augustans. It is to be feared that he does so. It is rather a dreary journey to the end of the volume. We know what to expect, for example, when Blair enters upon his discussion of the origin and progress of poetry. He had said it all before in his history of the rise and progress of language. In his discussion of the heroic couplet he shows us how ■ 65 - uninspired he can really he. Says he: The present form of our English heroic rhyme in couplets is a modem species of versification -- Waller was the first who brought couplets into vogue; and Dryden afterwards established the usage. Waller, first smoothed our verse; Dryden perfected it. Mr. Pope’s versification has a peculiar character. It is flowing and smooth in the highest degree: far more laboured and correct than that of any who went before him. He introduced one considerable change into her- oic verse, by totally throwing aside the triplets, or three lines rhyming together, in which Mr. Dryden abounded. Dryden ’s versification, however, has very great merit; and like all his productions, has much spirit mixed with carelessness. If not so smooth and correct as Pope’s, it is however more varied and easy. He subjects himself less to the rule of closing the sense with the couplet; and frequently takes the liberty of making his couplets run into one another, with some- what the freedom of blank verse. (1) How all this may be very true, tho gh as to its being Waller who " first smoothed our verse," — there be those who doubt. But if it is all true, what of it I Vie want to know what Dr. Blair would have to say anent the liberties which Dryden took with the "rules". Does Dr. Dp sir approve of Pope’s having' ’’thrown, aside the triplets, in vhich Mr. Dryden abounded?" It is by answers to these questions that Dr. Blair should reveal himself fully. But Dr. Blair is silent. He says that Pope achieved a maximum of correctness in his verse. Does he mean to imply disapproval of Mr. Dryden for not (1) Lectures , p. 455. -64- having done the same? I am afraid he does. The admission that "Mr. Dryden f s verse, however , has great merit," bears suspicious resemblance to diair's "blemish- saved-by-beauty" criticism of Shakespeare. A genuine and almost- just tribute to Milton in the discussion of Lpio Poetry (1) revives our hopes for a time, ani when in the discussion of Tragedy we arrive at the following, we take decided heart. I give this long quotation in full to show how he build, s up our hope for him, along with his own mounting courage . "All that I have hitherto said, relates to the unity of dramatic action? In order to render the unity of action more complete, critics have added the other two unities of time and place. The strict ob- servance of these is more difficult, and, perhaps, not so necessary. The unity of place requires that the scene slhould never be shifted; but that the action of the play should be continued to the end in the same place where it is supposed to begin. The unity of time, strictly taken, requires that the time of action be no longer than the time that is allowed for the representa- tion of the play; though Aristotle seems to have given the poet a little more liberty, and permitted the action to comprehend the thole time of one day. "The intention of both these rules is, to over- charge as little as possible, the imagination of the spectators with improbable circumstances in the acting 01 the play, and to bring the imitation more close to reality. Vie must observe that the nature of dramatic exhibitions upon the Greek stage subjected the aa ci ent tragedians to a more strict observance of those unities than is necessary in modern theatres. I showed that Greek (1) Lectures . pp. 505-506 . t ■ -65- tragedy was one uninterrupted representation from beginning to end. There was no division of acts; no pauses or intervals between them; but the stage was continually full, occupied either by the actors or the chorus. Hence no room was left for the imagination to go beyond the precise time and place of the representation; any more than is allowed dur- ing the continuance of one act on the modern theatre. "But the practice of suspending the spectacle totally for some little time between the acts, has made a great and material change; it gives more lat- itude to he imagination, and renders the aicient strict confinement to time and place less necessary. While the acting of the play is interrupted, the spectator can, wi thout any great or violent effort, suppose a few hours to pass between every act; or can suppose himself moved from one apartment of a palace to another; and therefore, too strict an observance of these unities, ought not be preferred to higher beauties of execution, nor to the introduction of more pathetic situations, which sometimes cannot be accomplished in any other way, than by a transgression of these rules." (1) At length Blair has led us by a gradual ascent to the position attained by Karnes in a single bound. But now observe how he lias lifted us up only to dash us down. The unhappy man can not escape "the rules." (l) They plague and haunt him; (1) Professor Willard Higley Durham, editor of Critical Assays o f the eighteenth century . takes occasion to remonstrate against the tendency to pigeon-hole the eighteenth century as the age of "rules' He says (p. XI)"For the really thoroughgoing classicist or ration- alist in criticism it is necessary to go to the preceding century. If by pseudo-classic is meant the type of mind which carries its admiration for the ancients to the point of idolatry, to the point of inculcating a slavish imitation of the Greeks and Latins and of censuring departure from their methods, we can best find it in Thomas Ryner." Durham thinks it unfair to say that such a theory was dominant in the eighteenth century. It is true that side by side with the left-over ideas of the seventeenth century we find the .juster pro- nouncements of Johnson in his Preface to Shakespeare (before noted) and again in The Rambler (Ho. 151). True, also, that John D e nnis ridiculed Addison's unity of place in Oato ( The Impartial Critick . Spingarn' s Crit ical Assays of the seventeenth century . A. pp.148 - * - 66 - They plague and haunt him; he must relinquish ail that he has tried to save. He has used the rules to a purpose they will not serve. He must retract; or at least hedge: But though it seems necessary to set modern poets free from a strict observance of these dramatic unities, yet we must remember that there are certain bounds to this liberty. Frequent and mid changes of time and place; hurrying the spectator from one distant city or country to another; or making several days or weeks pass during the course of the representation, are liberties which shock the imagination, which give the performance a romantic and unnatural appearance, and (Footnote to page 65, continued) 197) True that Addison himself denies the rigidity of the ruins in The Spectator . (Ho. 592). But it is equally undeniable that the adoration of the unities was dying hard with the critics in general. Addison when he came to write, had followed the unities. Strong French influence was felt in England, and Voltaire had planted himself squarely for the "rules" in his Discours sur la Tragedie . a iiylord Bolingbroke (prefixed to Brutus , 1751 ) . It may be true, then, that Blair was awake to the opposition to the rules; but he was equally awake to their defense. Such an admission only blackens the case still more for the Doctor. "Hurrying the spectator from one distant city or country to another," and "making several days or weeks to pass dur- ing the course of the representation, *'''** cannot be allowed in any dramatic writer who aspires to correctness," says Blair. "It is rarely observed that minds, not prepossessed by mechanical criticism, feel any offense from the extension of the intervals between the acts; nor can I conceive it as absurd or impossible, that lie who can multiply three hours into twelve or twenty- four, might imagine, with equal ease, a greater number," says Dr. John- son (The Rambler, Ho. 156). It is only taking Blair's excuse away from him, to admit that from English critics he might have drawn the truth. -67- therefore cannot be allowed in any dramatic v.Titer who aspires to correctness. In particular we must observe that it is only between acts, that any liberty can be given for going beyond the unities of time and place. During the course of each act, they ought strictly to be observed; that is, during each act the scene should continue the same, and no more time should be supposed to pass than is employed in the representation of that act. This is a rule which the French tragedians regular- ly observe. To violate this rule, as is too often done by the English; to change the place and shift the scene in the midst of one act, shows great incorrectness, and destroys the whole intention of the division of a play into acts. Mr. Addi®n*s Cato is remarkable beyond most English tragedies, for regularity of conduct. The author lias limited himself in time, to a single day; and in place, has maintained the most rigorous unity. The scene is never changed; and the whol e action passes in the hall of Cato^ house, at Utica. (1) After this final relapse on the part of the patient, there is little need of considering his case further. If we can catch him when his fears of the proprieties are in abeyance, we can often get something of value from him; something of more value, at least, than praise of a tragedy because of its "regularity of conduct." The phrase is a delicious one. It is an almost irresist- ible invitation to a pun. There was some real and abiding merit in what he had to tell us concerning diction and sentence structure. Moreover, he could usually set us the example in his own composi- tion. One must search for the horrible examples of "eloquence" quoted early in the chapter. But it is clear that he has nothing more for us. We shall only be pained at each fresh instance of his (1) Lectures , p. 518. , * - 68 - vacillation. Let us pass on. CAl.jp 3ELL AUD HIS PHILOSOPHY OP RHETORIC. CHAPTER IV. Tlie third, and last, writer whom I have to consider, is Dr. George Campbell, Principal of the Marischal College, Aberdeen. His Philosophy of Rhetoric . which appeared in 1776, has received high praise from all those who have treated the subject of rhetoric and criticism. I have already quoted from Professor Millar concerning the value of his work; (1) to this acclaim 3e t there be added the voice of Gregory Smith, who speaks of him as "surpassing Blair." (2) And, if we may add one more testimonial let it be that of Professor Baintsbury, who lays it down that the Philosophy of Rhetoric . "however much we may disagree with occasion- al expressions in it, remains the most important treatise on the Hew Rhetoric (criticism) that the eighteenth century produced." (3) How, if one comes to the study of Campbell with this idea of his importance, he will certainly be struck by this singular circumstance; that although critics and literary historians are of one voice in acclaiming the high place of the Principal, they are also curiously of one disposition in their avoidance of treat irg (1) Vide sup ra, p. 35 (2) Scottish Literature , p. 199 (3) A History of Critic ism . 2. p. 470. -70- him in any detail. Gregory Smith, indeed, is circumscribed by the limits of his undertaking, and has little space either for Blair or for Campbell. Yet within that space, the two men receive curiously unequal treatment. There are five separate and distinct references to -Blair. The name of George Campbell appears but once, and that in a statement that he surpassed Blair. Professor Millar, v/ho it will be remembered called the Philosophy of Rhetoric . "the most valuable contribution to criticism which came from Scotland during the century,” contents himself in that instance with a mere statement of the fact. Lest it be pleaded that here too, the limits and purpose of his work forbade any fuller treatment, let us turn to his later and more expanded consideration of this period. In his Scottish Prose of the Seventeenth and Eighteenth Centuries . we find twenty- four pages dev ted to Karnes, (four of them dealing particularly with Karnes as a critic) (1); almost fourteen pages are devoted to an examination of Blair and his Lectures (2); but when we come to look for Campbell, we fiid that he has been given less than a full page, with the excuse that his work "goes too much into detail on many points to admit of profit- able summary here.” (5) Professor Saints bury, it would seem at first sight, (1) Scottish Prose . pp. 190 ff. (2) ibid, pp. 2^1 ff (3.) Ibid, pp. 230-231. ' -71- had gone t o so me pa ins t o make a survey of th e Philosophy ck Critic ism . His treatment of the wd ik. in his Hi story of Ori tici sm occupies four pages, a generous allowance of space in so crowded a volume. Professor Saintsbury is evidently bent upon establishing the point that in Campbell we have the true fusion of the critic and the rhetorician; or rather, that Campbell recognised that the terms criticism and rhetoric were synonymous. (1) I must con- fess that I cannot agree that such a fusion of criticism and rhet- oric is any more apparent in Campbell than in Karnes and Blair. Indeed, it might almost be said to be less apparent, though not necessarily less real. Bor do I find that Professor Saintsbury has supported his thesis by his treatment of Campbell’s work; a treatment made up largely of statements of opinion, almost entirely unsupported by reference. Direct reference, when given, is almost always to those passages which the critic designates as ’’more ex- crescent than properly episodic.” The passages which are thus quoted as deviations from the theme and purpose of the work, are so numerous and so extensive that just suspicion arises as to Saintsbury 1 s estimate* (1) "The Bew Rhetoric -- the Art of Criticism -- this is what Campbell really attempts." Saintsbury (2. p. 470) . A direct comparison of the three works under consider- ation in this paper, may serve to point out why Campbell has never received adequate treatment. The first thing brought out by such comparison is the great difference in organization and presentation of material between Campbell on the one hand, and Karnes and Blair on the other. Campbell is w r riting a text-book; Karnes and Blair are writing essays. The one is preparing his material and advai c- ing it in the form and order suggested by class need. Blair, although making some shift to do this in the first half of his Lectures, escapes from it eventually into the happier region of literary appreciation. Karnes frankly addresses the understanding of those who would criticise. Campbell is addressing those who create. It is this text- bo ok arrangement and treatment — which Professor Saintsbury may have had in mind when he spoke of’ the "singularly businesslike character of Campbell's work" (1) — that makes difficult any critical digest of the Philosophy of Rhetoric . Even metre than in the mere natter of arrangement and presentation do the three men differ in their conceptions of the subject to be handled. The Creeks, (as has been stated) had early (1) History of Criticism . 2. p. 475. 1 , r >. > •! - 73 - distinguished between two main branches of the literary art; the useful , and the ornamental; or rhetoric and poetics . However vague the boundaries between these two divisions might have been in actual practice, and however much the lb rely useful branch of the art had encroached upon the territory of the more purely literary art, the distincti on was nevertheless important. The province of the orator was that species of composition, the purpose of which is to persuade or enlighten. His art was the art of rhetoric. The more purely literary artist reserved for himself the drama and the epic, together with those lesser compositions best designated by the title lyric ; and his art was the art of poetics . In this distinction we have found the means of interpret- ing the work of Campbell;, and, indeed, of all three men. Karnes was interested, chiefly, in finding those basic principles in human nature which act as the ultimate and universal standards of taste, ^rom the nature of his inquiry, he was led into a consideration of those forms of literary expression identified as poe tics . Hven his chapters on composition and word values are concerned primarily with sense impressions. Scarcely, if at all, does he invade the province of the more strictly useful branch of the art. His study might justly be termed an essay on the psychology of aesthetics. Blair, building upon Hames, re-affirms his principles with but slight modifications. In neither his remarks upon taste or his literary appreciations in the latter half -74- of his Lectures does he encroach upon the province of the older rhe toric . In his remarks upon style and his subsequent examination of specimens of Swift, Addison, etc., he sL ips over the boundary for a time. Particularly is this true when his emphasis is upon mere matters of perspicuity and accuracy; his consideration of style, in its more highly literary aspects, might justly be claimed by either of the two arts, even as in practice the orator must often avail himself of the art of poetics . Campbell, however, approaches his task with the Aristotelian distinction (l) clearly in mind. What Professor Eaintsbury has chosen to designate as his "Aristotelian relapses" (2), are, it seems to the present writer, far from "relapses". They are in the main body of the work; integral parts of a plan most strictly classic in its conception of rhetoric as being a useful, rather than an ornamental, art. Hot that the Principal intends to blind himself to the value of the art of poetics as a necessary and ( 1 ) Aristotle on the art of Poetry , a revised text with critical introducti on , translation , and c ommentary . by Ingram Bywater (1909) p7"lT* ''Out subject being Poetry, I propose to speak not only of the art in general but also of its species and their respective capacities .... Epic Poetry and Tragedy, as also Comedy, -oithyrambic poetry, and most flute-playing and lyre-playing, are all viewed as a whole, modes of imitation." T]ie_ rhetoric of Aristotle r translated wi th an analysis and critical notes , by J. E. 0. Uelldon 11886), p. 10:"Hhetoric may be defined as a faculty of discovering all the possible means of per- suasion in any subject." (2t History of Criticism , v. 11, p. 470. -75- uaefu.1 adjunct to the art of the orator. "Poetry," says he, "is properly no other than a particular mode or form of certain branches of oratory." (1) Poetics . he will admit as handmaiden of rhetoric . but its subordinate position in his plan is intimated by the words "certain branches of oratory." Uor do we have to remain long satisfied with oere intimation. The Principal becomes explicit. In acknowledging his own debt to .Karnes, he takes occasion to com- pare his present aim with that of the Elements . and to point out exactly where the two part company. In Karnes^ work, he says, the various fine arts "are examined only on that side wherein there is found a pretty considerable coincidence with one another; namely, as objects of taste, which by exciting sentiments of grandeur, beauty, novelty, and the like, are calculated to deLight the imagination. In this view, eloquence comes no farther under consideration than as a fine art, and adapted like the others above mentioned, to please the fancy and move the passions. But to Treat it als