OF THE U N 1 VERS ITY or I LLI N O 1 5 19Z . ;; ' i)r , ■> i f f'Kv > -ji2 - "f. Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2017 with funding from University of Illinois Urbana-Champaign Alternates https://archive.org/details/analysisofsirwmhOOjard 'u\ J % w ■j ■' ' '/f'' -■':t « ^ ”. ‘.',S ' '■rf- ■ '■ ' ' ■\ "V /a'-'] .4 AN ANALYSIS OF SIR Wm. HAMILTON’S, Lectures on Metaphysics. WITH NOTES EXPOSITORY AND CRITICAL. BY THE Key. EGBERT JAEDINE, B.D., D.Sa PRINCIPAL OP THE GENERAL ASSEMBLY’S INSTITUTION CALCUTTA. I Author of “ The Elements op the Phychology of Cognition and ‘‘What to Believe.” For sale at the General Assembly’s Institution, Calcutta by Babu Raj Kumar Chandra, Printed by K. C. Doss, at the University Book Press, 127, Manicktolah Street, Calcutta. 1877 , \ Price Ps. 1-4* PREFACE. This little work is intended to be an aid to students in the study of Sir W. Hamilton’s Lec- tures on Metaphysics. The Analysis is almost the same as I have given during the past six years in the lecture-room of the General Assembly’s Insti- ^ tution and the notes v ill I trust be of service in or § enabling students the better to understand import- ant philosophical doctrines. ir I have endeavoured to make the Analysis as as possible, and would warn students against the adoption, in their ordinary writings, of the forms of expression which I have employed. The mathe- matical symbols ( + and =) which I have made use of are intended to aid in securing brevity and clear- ness by avoiding periphrases and connecting par- ticles and by bringing together as closely as possible related ideas. A little study and practice will soon enable the student to see the meaning of these sym- bols in different cases. I trust that both the Ana- lysis and the Notes may be of service to those who make use of them. V R. J. The General Assembly’s Institution, Calcutta^ IQth February 1877 . \ CONTENTS. Page. General Analysis . . . . 1 Special Analysis of Parts Part I — ■Introduction 2 ,, II Philosophy in General 5 „ III Introduction to Psychology 11 ,y IV The Consciousness . 15 „ V The Cognitive Faculties 30 y, VI The Feelings . 63 Notes Expository and Critical Note A. The Pelativity of knowledge . 77 „ B. Sir W. Hamilton s Doctrine of Consciousness 86 „ C. Sir W. Hamilton’s Classification of mental Faculties . . . 104 „ D. Reid’s Doctrine of Perception . 106 „ E. Natural Realism . Ill » E. Classification 121 „ G. The Logical Doctrine of the Proposition . 131 „ H. Implied Predications 151 » I. A Priori Regulative Principles . 158 GENERAL ANALYSIS. Sir William Hamilton’s Lectures upon Meta- physics may, in general, be divided into the following parts : — Part 1. — Introduction : — in which is studied the Absolute Utility of Philosophy Subjective and Objective. Lectures I., 11. Part II. — Philosophy in General : — compre- hending a discussion of the Nature of Philosophy and the manner in which it should be studied. Lect. III.— VIL Part III. — Introduction to Psychology : — being an explication of the most important philosophical terms. Lect. VIII. — X. Part IV. — Consciousness : — classification of its contents, its special conditions, its authority, and general questions connected with it. Lect. XI, — XX. . Part V. — The Cognitive Faculties : — compre- hending the Presentative, the Conservative, the Reproductive, the Representative, the Elaborative, and the Regulative. ... ... Lect. XX — XL. Part VI. — The Feelings : — their Character, Explanation and Classes. ... Lect. XLI. — XL VI. SPECIAL ANALYSIS OF PARTS. PART I. INTRODUCTION. The Utility of any branch of knowledge is its value as a means towards an end + is of two kinds Relative and Absolute. Relative Utility = value of any study in relation to other studies ; Absolute Utility = its value in itself. We study here only the latter. The Absoluute Utility of Philosophy of two kinds ; — A, Subjective, as it cultivates the mind or knowing subject by calling its faculties into exercise + The Useful=a mean towards an end + a mean towards a higher end constitutes a higher utility than a mean towards a lower end + there prevail two errors with reference to the comparative utility of different studies. I. The first consists in supposing that man is not an end to himself but a mean to some- thing out of himself A. By nature man is an end to himself=his own perfection and happiness constitute the goal of his activity -{- by attaining these he chiefly glori- fies God. B. In the actual conditions of society men are divert ed from their chief end to serve the purposes of others. SPECIAL ANALYSIS OF PARTS. S G. Hence the distinction between a liberal education desiofned to cultivate man's faculties, and a professional education designed to fit him for the service of society. II, The second consists in subordinating intel- lectual cultivation to the acquisition of know- ledge. A. The mere acquisition of knowledge is not iden- tical with intellectual cultivation = it does not necessarily or always involve a high kind of mental exercise which is the condition of mental culture. B. Knowledge is subordinate to mental culture. I. In practical knowledge ex liypothesi not truth but practice is the end. II. In speculative knowledge the pleasure of mental acti- vity and not the possession of truth is the motive vfhich stimulates activity. III. Hence we conclude that Philosophy, being the best gymnastic of the mind, is the best entitled to be called useful. >• Objective, as it supplies the mind with know- ledge = the knowledge of the human mind is the most important and noble of all kinds of know- ledge -p the phenomena of mind alone afford the basis of an argument for God’s existence. 1. Idea of God=that of a First Cause + Intelli- gence -f Virtue=a First Cause without intelli- gence and virtue is blind Fate -f- an Intelligent and virtuous Being without original and infin- ite power is dependent and limited = the pecu- liar attributes of Deity are Intelligence and Virtue. 4 SPECIAL ANALYSIS OF PARTS. II, That intelligence stands first in the absolute order of existence -p that the universe is govern- ed by moral laws, rest exclusively on the phenomena of mind = phenomena of matter governed by immutable laws + the phenomena of mind which are independent of the ph3^sical organization are free = in man, as a free intelli- gence, we can see the possibility and the ground of believing in a God. A. Intelligince first in the order of existence = if in man intelligence be a free power independent of the physical organism we ma^" conclude by analogy that intelligence is first and independent in the universe. B. The universe is governed not merely by physical but by moral laws=this depends upon the existence of a moral world -f- this upon our own moral agency + this upon human liberty + this is established in three ways : — I. A careful study of mind is necessary to attain a clear consiousness of the fact of freedom. II. A profound philosophy is necessary to obviate the diffi- culties in the way of explaining the possibility of this fact = by showing that freedom though inconceivable may not therefore be impossible. III. The study of mind counteracts the influence of the study of matter, which last (1) diverts us from all notice of the phenomena of moral liberty and (2) habituates us to the contempletion of blind necessity. C. These uses of philosophy not superseded under the Christian dispensation since revelation supposes a genuine philosophy of mind as the condition of its truth. PHILOSOPHY IN GENERAL. 5 PAET IT. Philosophy in General. A. Nature and Comprehension of Philosophy = Lee. Iii. can now be not completely but only provisionally explained as a guide to study = may be described from two points of view : — I. With reference to the nmne philosophy is etymologically a love of wisdom = the term philosopher supposed to have been first as- sumed by Pythagoras, but probably first rendered familiar by Socrates in opposition to the Sophists. II. With reference to the thing ^ — A. Philosophy has been variously defined according to the view taken by differ- ent philosophers of its nature + in Greek antiquity there were six famous definitions. I. The knowledge of things existent as exist- ent’’ = Pythagoras. II. “ The knowledge of thing divine and hu- man” = Pythagoras. III. A meditation of death” = Plato. IV. A resembling of the Deity in so far as that is competent to man” = Plato. V. “ The art of arts, and science of sciences” = Aristotle. VI. The love of wisdom” = Pythagoras. B. Philosophy is a kind of knowledge distin- guished from empirical knowledge = em- pirical or historical knowledge is the knoTY- 6 PHILOSOPHY IN GENERAL. ledge that something is, while philosophi- cal knowledge is the knowledge why or how it is = a knowledge of things in their causes = it aims at the discovery of a first cause, but vainly in consequence of the limitation of our faculties. I. Thus in a wide sense all sciences occupied in the search after causes are philosophical. II. In a special sense the study of mind is pro- perly called philosophy. A. Because all kuowledge depends, for its possibility, upon certain conditions found only in the mind. B. Because, philosophy being concerned about causes and the mind giving the principal constituents of every act of knowledge, it demands special study. Lee. IV. B, The causes of philosophy are implied in man's very capacity for knowledge and are of two kinds : — I. Essential and necessary causes. A. Principle of cause and effect = the felt necessity to connect objects of knowledge with others which may explain them = it is impossible to believe in the absolute commencement of anything. B. The love of unity = a desire to perceive unity or harmony amidst variety of ob- jects = exhibited in perception, imagina- tion, generalization, judgment and rea- soning. I. This desire to discover unity, leading us to expect uniformity in nature, is the efficient PHILOSOPHY IN GENERAL. cause and guiding principle of scientific dis- covery. II. It is also a source of error = leads to the supposition of unity where it does not exist = has led to the majority of false theories -f is identical with pre-conceived opinion or pre- judice. II. Auxilary cause = Wonder or Curiosity = does not account for the rise of philosopy but explains why one class of objects is studied in preference to another = e. g. in early times external objects excited wonder and study before the human mind. A The subjective conditions of the successful study Lee. Y. of philosophy. I. The renunciation of prejudice = the mind must be free from prepossession and open to conviction = the power of prejudice and cus- tom prepetuates error and leads to sceptical conclusions regarding the existence of truth and goodness. II. Doubt is necessary = if people do not doubt their previous opinions they will not search for truth. A. Philosophical doubt is indulged as a mean to the discovery of truth. B. Scepticism is doubt which rests in itself and seeks not for truth = shallow and week. HI. The subjugation of the passions, especially, — A. Sloth. B* Pride. B PHILOSOPHY IN GENERAL. Lee, VI. B. The method of philosophy = the procedure by which the ends of philosophy may be reached. I. Method explained in relation to the ends_^of philosophy. A. First end of philosophy, — the discovery of causes — can be attained, I. by decomposing the effects into their causes or elements. II. by reconstructing these into their products or effects -f- these two processes, called analysis and synthesis, are the correlative parts of the one method and each is imperfect without the other. B. The second end of philosophy, — the re- duction of our knowledge to unity — is reached by the same two-fold method, e. g. I. In perception we comprehend great or multi- form objects by first attending to the parts (analysis), and then taking a comprehensive view of the whole (synthesis). II. In classification and induction we proceed first to compare resemblances (analysis), and then to bring together resembling pheno- mena under some class or law (synthesis). II. Method illustrated by the history of philo- sophy. A. Ancient philosophy began by applying analysis and synthesis to the objects of their knowledge, but in a very uncriti- cal and imperfect manner. PHILOSOPHY IN GENERAL. 9 I. Thales and the Ionic school studied external nature to find the first principle or cause of all thiuors -L found it in some material element * as water, air, or fire. II. Pythagoras and the Italic school discovered the cause of things in their form or harmony or number, as distinguished from the matter or substance. III. The Eleatic school referred all things to The One or Pure Being, as therir principle or cause. IV. Socrates diverted the attention of men from the universe to the mind, but did not change the method. V. Plato and Aristotle studied, — the former — the higher faculties of intelliirence, — the latter — the ordinary understanding, laying the basis respectively of transcendental idealism and phenomenal psychology, but both employ- inor the same method. O VI. The Alexandrian school of Heo-Platonists was eclectic and comprehensive. Vil. Bacon and Descartes used the same method of analysis and synthesis but insisted upon a more careful and thorough analysis and a more cautious synthesis. The Divisions of philosophy. I. The most ancient division, instituted by Aris- totle and adopted by the Stoics, Epicureans and others, is into Theoretical and Practical = Theoretical philosophy is knowledge for the sake of knowing H- practical philosophy is knowledge for the sake of its practical appli- cation. Lee. 2 PHILOSOPHY IN GENEKAL. A. Since all philosophy is properly theoretical or speculative it is illogical' to divide it by a principle foreign to its nature. B. Since all philosophy, with reference to its final end, is practical, this principle does not accurately divide the different branches of philosophy. I. Among the ancients great differences of opinion existed regarding the position of Logic in relation to philosopy in general. II. The distinction between Arts and Sciences does , not correspond to that between sciences practU cal and sciences speculative = this explained by Aristotle’s use of the ierm^ praxis andpm^- tihos. Praxis in a generic sense was opposed to speculation -f praxis in a specific sense was co-ordinate with poiesis or production, both comprehended by the generic praxis, thus : — praxis j57i6ona= speculative ( ■ ,t.i - philosophy praxis or poiesis, or science practical science productive, as Ethics, Politics. as Logic, Rhetoric. = an art, being defined as a science productive, may not be identical with a practical science. II Bacon divides philosophy with reference to its object-matter as concerned about Diety, Nature, and Man. II. The Cartesians and Kant divide into theore- tical and practical with various sudivisions. INTRODUCTION TO PSYCHOLOGY. II IV. Hamilton proposes the following division : — Cognitions, Feeling, Co- nativePowers (will and De- sire.) Cognitions, — Logic. Feeling, — AaBsthetics. Conation, — Ethics, Poli- tics. Results, — Ontology 'I Being of God. Inferential Psy- Immortality of chology J soul. Matter. Note. Sir W, Hamilton has nowhere sys- tematically followed this division. PART III. INTRODUCTION TO PSYCHOLOGY r being an explication of the most important terms : — Lee. VIIL A, General Definition =; Psychology is the science conversant about the phenomena or modifications or states of the mind or conscious-subject, or soul or spirit, or self or ego. I. Use of Psychology vindicated againstthe objec- tion that it is an exotic or technical name. A. Philosophy itself and the most of itsbrarfeh- es have received Greek technical names. B. Psychology is now naturalized in Europe. C. Its use avoids frequent periphrases. I Facts, — phenomeno- | logy. Empirical } Psychology j M i n d o r the object of perception is in immediate contact with organ. B. Reid and other philosophers hold that an organic action must precede the intellec- tual action in perception -{- Hamilton = if this were so the immediate perception of an extra' organic object would be im- possible + corporeal movement and mental perception simultaneous -f mind connected with the whole nervous system. c. Reid^ and Stewart = sensation proper al- ways precedes perception proper = if soj. 44 THE COGNITIVE FACULTIES. Lee. XXIX. perception is only an instinctive belief, consequent on sensation, that there is some unknown quality, the cause of the sensa- tion -k Hamilton = perception proper and sensation proper coexist, B. Self-Consciousness. I. Its character and forms, A. Contrasted with perception = perception embraces the phenomena of external world 4- its forms are space and time ; Self-cons- ciousness comprehends the phenomena of internal world -k its forms are time and self, B. Forms = the frame or the a priori condi- tions apart from which no objects can be known = necessary and native to the mind = time, space and self = the fact of space being a form of perception does not involve the extension of the mind. II. Modes of studying self-consciousness. A. Described. I. Induction alone = comparison and classifica- tion of mental phenomena = results in the general not the necessary. II. Induction + analysis = besides comparing and classifying phenomena, analyses them into necessary and contingent elements = this necessity governs thought only not things. B, Illustrated from the history of philosophy. I, Doctrines of philosophers. THE COGNITIVE FACULTIES. 45 A. Locke used induction alone = discovered nothing necessary = all axioms are generalisations from experience. B. Leibnitz = there is necessary truth not obtained by empirical induction but in- volved in the structure of the mind. c. Kant = first clearly showed the character of necessary truth. II. Has Locke been misrepresented ? A. Stewart = Gassendi, Condillac, Diderot and Horne Tooke held all our knowledge to be derived from sense + Locke held reflection also to be an original source of ideas = Locke misrepresented by his French followers. B. Hamilton = Locke’s reflection concerned only about contingent objects of sense = similar to doctrine of Gassendi who assigned to reflection a higher function than Locke giving it more spiritual objects = Locke not misrepresented II. The Conservative Faculty. A. Introduction = conservation necessary to the possession of knowledge + conserva- tion of knowledge would be useless with- out the power of reproducing and repre- senting it in consciousness = these faculties though mutually dependent are distinct = in the language of philosophers the conservative faculty proper is called Mew^ory, the reproductive faculty, EecoU lection or Reminiscence, B. The fact of retention explained. I-. Illustrative similes. Lee. 46 THE COGNITIVE FACULTIES. A. Cicero call memory a storehouse provided with cells. B. Gassendi compares it to the folds in a peice of paper or cloth. II. Psychological explanation = memory the necessary result of the self-activity of the mind. A. Real problem = not how a mental activity endures but how it ever vanishes. B. Forgetfulness explained by distribution of men- tal force = the greater the number of mental activities, the less the proportion of force in each = some activities thus become delitescent or latent c. Distraction and attention explained by same principle = the want of attention causes different degrees of obscuration. D. Results of preceding theory. I. Memory extends to cognitions, feelings cona- tions and all mental states or activities. II. Physiological hypotheses useless = betray ignor- ance of true nature of thinking principle c» self-activity of mind independent of bodily re- lations, C. Concluding remarks. I. Conditions of a good memory = capacity of retention + faculty of reproduction. II. Two incorrect opinions. A. Great memory incompatible with great intelli- gence = proved false by history = Scaliger and others had great memory and great philosophical power. B. Great intelligence incompatible with great me- mory =?= refuted by common sense, Lee. XXXI. Ill- The Eeproductive Faculty. THE COGNITIVE FACULTIES. 47 A. Historical introduction = all admit that mental phenomena are reproduced accord- ing to the laws of Association = thoughts retained in memory are excited by their connection with other thoughts according to certain laws. I. The Laws of Association are seven in all : — A. Thoughts originally coexistent or immediately suc- cessive suggest one another. B. Things contiguons in space suggest one another. C. The cause suggests the effect, the whole the part. D. Things contrasted or similar become associated. E. Operations of the same power or of different powers about the same object are associated. F. The sign suggests the things signified. o. Things denoted by the same sound are mutually suggestive. II. Aristotle reduced all laws to three = conti- quity in time and space 4-resemblance+ con- trariety. III. St. Augustine reduced all to one = thoughts which have coexisted in the mind are after- wards associated, IV. Hume admitted three = resemblance -f conti- quity in time and space -f cause and effect. V. Stewart classified the laws into : — A. Relations perfectly obvious = resemblance and analogy, contrariety, and vicinity in time and place. B. Relations not obvious = cause and effect, means and end, premisses and conclusion. VI. Brown distinguished. 48 THE COGNITIVE FACULTIES. A. Primary laws of suggestion = resemblance, con- trast aud contiquity. B. Secondary laws = vicinity, recentness &c. B. Reduction of all laws to one. I. All laws reducible to simultaneity and affi- nity. A. Simutlancity = coexistence or immediate succes- sion. B. Affinity is a compreliensive expression for all the others. I. Resembling or analogous objects have a natu- ral affinity. II. Contrasted objects have affinity because the knowledge of contraries is one. III. Local contiquity gives unity to unconnected objects. IV. In the case of whole and parts, sign and thing signified, a thing and its properties there is a connection both of affinity and simultaneity. V. Cause and effect stand in the closest affinity. II. Simultaneity and affinity both reducible to one grand law of Redingtegration,= Those thought suggest one another which had previously constituted parts of the same entire or total act of cognition = the parts of a total act of thought consist of simul- taneous thoughts and those having mutul affinity. Ill, Apparent exception 'to laws = thoughts apparently unconnected sometimes succeed one another = explained by mental latency + canot be explained by forgetfulness of intermediate link. THE COGNITIVE FACCLTIES. 49 C. Reminiscence = laws of reproduction + Lee. XXXII. voluntary effort = implies that the mind recognise the identity of the repro- duced immediate and the original pheno- menon + that the mind be conscious of the second being something different from the first = the common explanation of reminiscence recognises only the conse- cutive order of thought + the following points constitute the true explanation. I. The mind goes backward and forward over a great variety of thoughts in every order. II. Conditions of reminiscence, A. Momentary circumstances are the causes which awaken our activity. B. The determining circumstances as constituting a want tend to awaken associated thoughts which may satisfy that want. III. Consciousness of a want awakens the idea of its object together with many accessory notions + accessory ideas not so vivid as that of object sought and therefore soon disappear from consciousness, IV. These accessory notions whether conscious or not call up others and so help to bring before consciousness the object wanted. V. Relations of our thoughts as suggesting one another. A. Some thoughts reciprocally connected by mutual relations and therefore excite one another. 7 60 THE COGNITIVE FACULTIES. B. Some are connected with a greater number of determining circumstances than others = these are more frequently called up. c. Thoughts connected with circumstances which most vividly affect us predominate over the others. Lee. XXXIII. IV. The Eepresentative Faculty^ — Imagination. A. It character and conditions. I, Erroneous view = imagination divided into the reproductive and productive. A. Reproductive = called conception -i- simply re- presentative of objects of perception = term con- ception improperly applied + the faculty not simple, comprehending representation proper and reproduction. B. Productive = ordinary imagination or Fancy = produces nothing new, — only rearranges and modifies the old. II. Correct view = imagination a complex pro- cess, comprehending representation 4- its determining powers. A. Representation == energy of mind in holding up to its own contemplation mental phenomena. B. Determing powers = reproductive faculty,— the immediate source of materials + faculty of rela- tions, — analysis and synthesis of phenomena Hence . — c. Representation = condition of the possibility of an act of comparison + realizes or holds up results of comparison. THE COGNITIVE FACULTIES. 51 B. Its objects = imagination is concerned not: merely with objects of sense but also with the objects of abstraction, of wit, of judg- ment, of reason, of feeling, of volitions and of the passions. C. Its order, — is three-fold. I. Natural order = that in which objects spon- taneously present themselves. II. Logical order = order of scientific study = from universal to particular or vice versa = deductive or inductive. III. Poetical order = grouping with a view to effect. D. Its modes. I. Ordinary modes = the mode of imagination determined by different associations in differ- ent circumstances = education, habits, reli- gion, age, and sex determine the kind and order of imagination. II. Extraordinary modes. A. Dreaming == exercise of imagination during sleep = can sometimes scarcely be distinguished from sensible perceptions or waking thoughts. B. Somnambulism = extraordinary exaltation of powers during sleep + subsequent forgetfulness of what was done. C. Reverie = waking dreams governed by the involuntary associations of imagination. E. Its effects = it is the principal source of the happiness and misery of human life. UBRAirr UHlVERSlPf OF ILLINOf? 52 THE COGISITIVE FACULTIES. F. Its organs = the different organs of sense or muscular activity are employed by imagination. Lee. XXXIv. V. The Elaborative Faculty. This faculty proceeds exclusively by the method of com- parison as may be seen by examining its principal processes. A. Primary acts of comparison. I. Comparison of ego or non-ego with notion of existence. II. Discrimination of eofo from non-eofo* III. Observing the resemblance or difference of phenomena. IV. Comparison of phenomena with native notion of substance. V. Comparison of phenomena with notion of cau- sality. B. Classification or Generalization = grouping together resembling phenomena as the result of comparison. I. Products of classification. A. Complex notions = repetition of the constituent notion so as to form a group as army, forest = aided by language which gives unity to the col- lections of objects. B. Notions formed by decomposition. I. A Poetical analysis and synthesis = separation and recomposition of integral parts for the sake of pleasure. THE COGNITIVE FACULTIES. 53 ii. Scientific analysis and synthesis = abstraction and combination of constituent qualities for the sake of accurate knowledge. A. Abstraction c= withdrawal of attention from some qualities to fix it upon others = may be performed by the senses upon physical qualities or by the mind upon reproduced cognitions. B. Abstract individual ideas = particular qualities of individual objects separated from tbe others. c. Abstract general notions = produced by attending to and naming points of resemblance in a number of objects, and thus forming a class, and successively higher classes. I. Quantity of general notions two-fold = exten- sion, — the classes or objects contained under them + comprehension, — the atributes involv- ed in them = extension and comprehension are in the inverse ratio of one another. II. Resolution of quantity is two-fold = generaliza- tion or rejection of differentiae and attention to resemblances, the process rising from indivi- duals to higher and higher classes + determi- nation^ or attention to differences and abstrac- tion from resemblances, the process descending from higher classes to lower or to individuals. II. Wherein does g^enerality consist ? =the ans- Lee' XXXV. wer to this question involves an account of the nominalist controversy. A. Nominalism = every act and object of thought singular + the name only is general = held by Hobbes, Berkeley, Hume, Adam Smith, Campbell and Stewart = mind can abstract from 'particular qualities of objects + cannot conceive a general notion apart from particular qualities. B. Conceptualism held by I. Locke =x the general notion of an object with- out special peculiarities may be formed, but it is imperfect. 54 THE COGNITIVE FACULTIES. II. Brown == generalizing process consists of (1) perception or conception of two or more objects + (2) relative feeling *of their resemblance + (3) naming these circumstances of resemblance => nominalism excludes the relative feeling of resemblance. Brown incorrect, for, A. Nominalists do not exclude resemblance in generalization, as e. g. t. Hobbes = name .imposed for Bimilitnde in some quality or accident. II. Berkeley = words become general by being applied to particular ideas which resemble one another. III. Hume =: perceived resemblance is the foundation of classification. IV. Adam [Smith2=^ resemblance the reason of giving a common name. B. Notion of similitude not general. I. Axioms. a. Resemblance is a relation = inconceivable apart from resembling objects. b. Resemblance] exists 'in some particular mode or accident. c. Resemlance not nsoessarily universal = not morn general tlian resembling objects. II. Brown’s theory tested by axioms. a. Universality of feeling cannot arise from univer- sality of resembling objects. b. >'or can it arise from the universality of the notion of the common quality. c. Hence it must be supposed by Brown to rest in tho feeling of resemblance itself in opposition to the third axiom -i* there are four conceivable reasons in support of this 2. The feeling of resemblance may be general because it is a relation = not asserted by Brown. 2. The particular relation called similarity may be more general than other relations = it is the same as that of difference which is not general. THE COGNITIVE FACULTIES. 55 3. The feeling of Eimilarity may be g?neral because we have a capacity of feeling similarity =then every act of every power weuki be general. 4 . If universality be not in sensible representations it may be found in the intellectual notion which connects two particular qualities by the bond of similarity = the only supposition which accounts for Browms doctrine [but which he was not war- ranted in assuming. Wliat kind of idea and terms first arise ? Lee. XXXVI, = the question of the Primnm Co^nitiim, A. That first ideas and names are of • particular things is held by — I. Vives = the order of learning is from simple to complex, from particulars to universals. II. Adam Smith = assignation of particular names to particular objects is the commence- ment of language + these names are after- wards extended to other resembling objects and thus become general. B. That general ideas and terms first arise is held by— I. Leibnitz = it would be impossible to speak without appellatives, ^. e. names which may be applied to eeveral objects + general name usually most easily formed + proper name originally appellative or general. II. M. Turgot = our first ideas are general and afterwards become more particular. C. That first ideas and terms are vague and confused is held by I. Hamilton = language at first expresses the the vague and confused + out of this the universal and particular are elaborated = par- ception commences with masses, and proceeds by analyses from the vague to the definite + general attributes are formed by comparison 66 THE COGNITIVE FACULTIES. and attention + individuals distinguished by discrimination of differences. II. Degerando = a child first uses nouns , and verbs absolutely and afterwards compares and distinguishes. HI. Aristotle = we proceed from the better known to the less known = from the complex or confused to the singular and clear. Lee, XXXVIL C. Judgment and Reasoning = rendered necessary by tlie imperfection of our na- ture ; higher intelligences know by in- tuition. I. Judgment = an act of comparison = of a total conception with a partial -f- recognition that the latter constitutes part of the former = consists of subject, predicate and copula + expressed in words is called a proposition. II. Reasoning = complex or mediate judgment = recognition of the relation of one notion to another through a third = proceeds either from the whole to its parts, or from all the parts to the whole collectively = deductive and inductive. A. Deductive reasoning = depends upon the axiom, — Whatever is the part of a part is a part of the whole = the subject may be the whole and predicate part, or predicate whole and sub- ject part = comprehension + extension. I. Reasoning in comprehension = subject whole and predicate part = subject may be either a physical or a mathematical whole = depends upon principle that, — all that belongs to the predicate must belong to the subject. THE COGNITIVE FACULTIES. 67 II. Reasoning in extension = predicate whole and subject part = what was subject in compre- hensive reasoning becomes predicate in exten- sive. III. In both deductive and inductive reasoning the inference is necessary = usual account of induction as probable reasoning erroneous + in deduction and induction, the analysis of comprehension is exactly the reverse of the analysis of extension = in deduction the analysis of comprehension corresponds to the synthesis of extension and vice versa -1- inductive synthesis on a comprehensive whole the reverse of that on an extensiv whole. VI. The Eegulative Faculty. A. Introductory discussion. I. General character of the faculty = it is the Lecture XXXVTTT power possessed by the mind of modifying or regulating the knowledge it receives = the complement of a priori principles belong- ing to the mind. IL Its nomenclature = it corresponds to the Greek, nous or Reason -f- has been called common sense by many authorities which is ambiguous = it usually means a sound un- derstanding. A. The faculty may be called the noetic to distinguish it from the Elaborative faculty or dianoetic. B. The cognitions are called first principles, prin- ciples of common sense, intuitive truths &c. III. Its criteria enounced by : — A. Descartes and Spinoza = Descartes distinguished 8 58 THE COGNITIVE FACULTIES. universal from particular notions 4- Spinoza pointed out that our clear and dLtinct ideas fol- low from the sole necessity of our nature = these philosophers were not explicit. c. Leibnitz = native distinguished from adventi- tious knowledge by the circumstance that wo cannot but think the one, but may easily annihi- late the other in thought f the intellect is the source of necessary truths while contingent truths come from experience + experience apart from reason never leads to absolute universality. ,C. Reid illustrates his doctrine by the principle of causality which cannot be acquired or proved by experience because I . The cansal judgment expresses not a contingent but a necessary truth. II. Maxims grounded on experience have a pro- bability only proportioned to the extent of our experience. III. Limited experience inadequate to the establish- ment of a universal principle. IV. The number of primary truths = still sub- ject of dispute -h B,eid and Stewart charged with admitting too many 4- metaphysics like chemistry, — apparently simple elements may be analyzed. B. Systematic deduction of necessary prin 2. I. The quality of necessity distinguishes native from adventitious elements of knowledge -f necessity may arise from two causes = may be the result of a power or of a power- THE COGNITIVE FACULTIES. 59 lessness of thinking principle = positive or negative. II. Positive necessity = an act power = e.g, affirmation of existence, personal identity, the laws of contradiction, excluded middle &c. III. Negative necessity = result of a powerless- ness of mind. A. Principles on which it depends. I. Law of contradiction = a thing cannot be and not-be at the same time. II. Law of excluded middle = a thing either is or is not. B. Law of the Conditioned = all that is conceiv- able in thought lies between two inconceivable extremes which, as contradictory of each other, cannot both be true, but of which, as mutual contradictories, one must. C. Illustrations of this law. I. Space as a maximum = space must be either finite or infinite -t- we cannot conceive space as positively limited since this would be con- tradictory of our idea of space + we cannot conceive space as without limits, since this surpasses our power of conception + therefore our power of conception lies between the two unconditioned extremes. II. Space as a minimum = we can neither con- ceive an absolute minimum of spase nor its infinite divisibility. III. Time as a maximum = past or future time is bounded by the present= a bounded infinite is a contradiction + we cannot conceive past time as either infinitely not-beginning or absolutely beginning, nor future time as either infinitely not-ending or absolutely ending. 60 THE COGNITIVE FACULTIES. Lec.XXXIX. IV. Time as a minimum = we can neither con- ceive an absoute minimum of time nor its infiinite divisibility. D. General Summary = the conditioned is the mean between two exclusive extremes neither of which can be conceived as possible, but of which, on the principles of contradiction and excluded middle, one must be admitted as necessary = the two extremes are the abso- lutely unconditioned or absolute + the infi- nitely unconditioned or infinite = the condi- tionally limited is the only possible object of knowledge or of positive thought + this law consistent with the orthodox doctrine that we cannot know God. C. Application of the Law of the Conditioned to the explanation of the principle of cau- sality. I. The phenomenon of causality. A. General account of it — we cannot conceive any new existence to commence -I- all that now exists had a previous existence under a prior form + the causes contain all that is contained in the effect + effect contains nothing which was not contained in the causes. B. Brown’s account of it = the causal judgment asserts present immediate priority + past and future invariable sequence of one event upon another. To this account Prof. Wilson objects that it omits two ideas ; — one of necessity and the other of a constitution of things in which that necessity is established. THE COGNITIVE FACULTIES. 61 II. Theories in explanation of the causal judg- ment. A. A posteriori tlieories = those which consider this principle to be derived from experience. I. Original or primitive. a. We have a direct perception of causai agency in exter nal phenomena. To this it is objected ; — 1. We have no perception of the connection of cause and effect in the external world = this objection first urged by Algazel in the 12th cent, and now generally accepted. 2. If we had this could not account for the qualities of necessity and universality. b. We have a direct perception oi causai efficiency in the consciousness of our physical operations as in fluenced by the will = in effort there is , — (IJ the cons- ciousness of an act of will (2) the consciousness of a motion produced (3) a reiation of the motion to the volition = Locke and M.de Biran objected that we have no consciousness of the connection between the voli~ tion and the limb moving, as proved by paralysis where there may be a volition without movement •}* empirical consciousness would still fail to account for necessity. II. Derivative or secondary. c. The causal judgment the result of induction and gener- alization = this would never engender the irresistable belief that every event must have a cause. d. The causal judgment derived from subjective custom or association == the customary can never become the necessary. B. A priori theories = those which consider the causal judgment a condition of intelligence it- self. I. Original or primitive. 62 THE COGNITIVE FACULTIES. e. The causal judgment is a simple primary datum,- =*a positive revelation of intelligence = Descartes, Lei~ bnitz, Reid, Stewart, Kant, Fichte, Cousin &c. = can not be held it the causal judgment may be explained”’ without postulating a special principle, f. The causal judgment may be reso Ived into the the ins- tinctive inclination to believe in the constancy of nature = held by brown but does not account for element of necessity. II. Derivative or secondary. g. The Causal judgment proved by the principle of contradiction = whatever is produced without a cause is produced by nothing; but nothing can no more be a cause than it can be something; there fore everything must have a real cause for its exis- tence = held by the Leibuityo— Wolflan school but guilty of the fallacy petltio principu == if all causes are excluded ‘nothing’ should be excluded also. Lee. XL. The causal judgment evolved from the law of :h© conditioned. 3, Manner of evolution explained— all thought Implies — the thought of existence + the thought of time + that of existence conditioned in time — we must think an object which exists now as having existed in past time and as continuing to exist ic future time = we cannot conceive either abso'ute creation or absolute annihilation = the inability of annihiiat ng in thought an existence in t'me past expliins the whole phenomenon of of ciusiiity + the judgment is simply the assertion ih it ev=‘ry thing must have existed previously in a fferent forms. 2. Reasons for preferring this explanation, i. It postulates no new principle. ii. It averts scepticism = avoids the contradictory assertions, that existence cannot absolutely com_ meiice and cannot intlnicely not-eommence by showing thu both of these assertions are the result of the liiiiitxtion of cur faculties, iii. It avoides fata ism or inconsistency = the denial of free causation in volition leads to fatalism or atheism + tho admission of free consation in volii tion is inconsistent with the casual judgment + THE FEELINGS. 63 the law of the conditioned obviates this contradic- tion by showing that both positions are unthink- able while in favour of fteedom we may ihen ap- peal to consciousness. PAET VI. THE FEELINGS. A. Preliminary questions. I. Are the Feelings really distinct from the other phenomena of the mind ? A. Historical notice of question. I. Ill ancient pliilosojdiy mental phenomena were divided into Gnostic or Cognitive -p Orectic or Appetent = the modem division into understanding and will. II. Previous to Kant, German psychologists had distinguished the Feelings as a separate class but Kant first established the distinction, B, Determination of question. I. Preliminary difficulty = language applied to mental phenomena not so clear and distinct as that applied to external objects this led to confusion in the analysis of mental pheno- mena = the word feeling in many languages means first tactual sensations and afterwards pleasure and pain -{- this ambiquity leads to the secondary meaning of the word being supposed the same as the primary. . II. By an appeal to experience we can easily dis- tinguish the feelings of pleasure and pain from any cognition or conation. Lee. XLI, 64 THE FEELING. C. Krug s objection. I. Stated = all activity of mind is directed either inward or outward -f- if feeling be distinct from these two activities it mast have cither both directions at once or none at all — • must have either be a combination of the other two powers or nothing at all, II. Answered. A. There may be three mental energies = ineunfc or cognitions + immanent or feelings + tran- seunt or conations. B. It is not proper to ascribe any direction to purely mental powers, direction and position being attributes of external objects. C. The objection rests on the analogy between the mental and material worlds which does not ajfford ground for the argument. II. What is the position of the Feelings in a scientific classification of the faculties? A. The Feelings are to be placed after the cognitions = without cognition no feeling is possible. B. The Feelings precede and determine the conations = if cognition alone were suffi- cient to arouse conation, then : — I. We should strive after all objects alike with- out distinction. II. All persons would seek with equal eagerness after the same objects = the distinction which each person and several persons make THE FEELINGS. (5 in seeking after objects of desire is explained by the feelings, III. Into what classes should the Feelings be distributed ? A. Kant divides the Feelings into two great classes. I. The sensuous feelings = through the senses + through the imagination. II. The intellectual feelings = connected with notions of the understanding -f ideas of the reason. B. Schulze, into corporeal, spiritual, and mixed. C. Hildebrand, into feelings of states, condi- tions, and appetency. D. Herbert, into objective, subjective, and mixed in origin. E. Carus, into intellectual, aesthetic, moral and religious. F. Hamilton, into sentiments and sensations. B, Theory of Pleasure and Pain, I. Feelings distinguished from other pheno- mena. A. Cognition =»■ object known distinguished in consciousness from subject knowing + object may be different from ego,— object- object, or a modification of ego, — sub- 9 Lee. XLII THE FEELINGS. ject-object = objectification is the essen- tial pecularity of cognition. B. Feeling = does not objectify mental modi- fication or state = is nothing but what is subjectively subjective. C. Conation = related to an external object like cognition + relation implies a want and a tendency resulting in an endeavour + conation has reference to the future, feeling to the present. II, Law by which the Feelings are governed. A. Stated in detail. I. The life of man corresponds to his conscious energy. Ii. Conscious energy is determined through spe- cial modes without which it cannot be exerted. III. Pleasure and pain accompany exertion in these modes. IV. Since pleasure or pain cannot arise except as the concomitant of some conscious energy the question arises as to the law of their connection. V. The Law is, — The more perfect, the more pleasurable the energy ; the more imperfect the more painful. VI. The perfection of an energy is. A. A relation to the power. ‘ B. A relation to the object. THE FEELINGS. 67 vll. In relation to the power. A. A perfect energy = the full and not more than full complement of free and spontaneous energy of the power in regard to degree and duration. B. An imperfect energy = the restrained or the; over-stimulated exertion of a power. VIII. In relation to the object. A. A perfect energy = object elicits the full and not more than full amount of energy. B. An imperfect energy = object stimulates'energy unduly in degree or time + unduly restrains it. IX. Pleasure is a reflex of the spontaneous and unimpeded exertion of a power of whose * energy we are conscious + pain is a reflex of the over-strained or repressed exertion of Such a poweiv B. Explained. I. Pleasure as reflex of energy = distinguished from energy which may not be pleasurable -{- from perfection of energy. II. Spontaneous = every power should put forth freely and naturally its proper amount of energy -f unimpeded — all obstacles should be removed. Ill, Consciousness a condition of feelinor = no o feeling out of consciousness -f- pleasure and pain may be either negative or positive. History of Theories of Pleasure and Pain. Lee. I. Plato was the first to generalize a theory of the Feelings = a state of pleasure always €8 THE FEELINGS. preceded by a state of pain + pain arises from a breacli in the harmony of our consti- tution + pleasure follows when the harmony is restored = pleasure is a thing always in generation never actually existing, — a mere relation to and negation of pain + pain is the root the antecedent of pleasure. II. Aristotle refutes the Platonic theory of plea- sure being a mere negation by showing that this theory explains only bodily wants and pleasures + intellectual pleasures are posi- tive and not accompanied by pain = pleasure is the concomitant of a perfect energy of health or intellect exercised upon an object suited to call forth the power into unim- peded activity + pleasure is not some- thing that arises from moment to moment but is a real positive existence. Hamil- ton in comparing the above theories ob- serves Plato is right in holding that every state of pleasure and free energy is the escape from an alternative state of pain and compulsory inaction + Aristotle is right in holding that pleasure is more than freedom from pain = pleasure and pain are both absolute in being both posi- THE FEELINGS. 69 tive + both relative in being increased by contrast with one another. Ill Cardan = All changes proceed from one countrary to another, from good to bad or from bad to good = the latter pleasurable = a state of pain must always precede one of pleasure = this theory excludes intermedi- ate gradations of feeling. IV. Descartes = Pleasure is the consciousness of some one of our perfections = supposed by his followers to have been original but really a vague version of Aristotle’s theory. V. Wolf = Pleasure is the intuitive cognition of any perfection whatever either true or ap- parent = this theory is erroneous because ; — A. Pleasure is a subjective state not a cogni- tion of an attribute. B. Pleasure belongs not only to the intuitive faculty but also to the understanding or faculty of relations. VI. Du Bos and Pouilly = Pleasure subjectively is the result of the gratification of a want + the chief want is mental occupation + men- tal activity when over stimualted or res- trained is painful + the stronger and easier the activity the more agreeable. 70 THE FEELINGS'. VII. Sulzer = The feelings aie grounded in the natural activity of the soul + this activity is pleasurable when called forth by objects in which diversity may be reduced to unity + bea uty consists in the unity of the manifold = to this theory it may be ob- jected. A, This theory excludes the pleasure of recep- tivity or passivity. B. Pleasure is not a consciousness of unim- peted activity but a consciusness of feel- ing. VII. Kant = Pleasure is the feeling of the fur- therance, pain of the hinderance of life + former must pre-suppose the latter + man is always dissatisfied with the present and seeks to better his condition = man is always seeking to escape from a state of* pain to one of pleasure + pleasure is nothing posi- tive, only a negation of pain, and nothing enduring, only a transition. Lee. XLIV. Do Application of Theory to phenomena. I. As causes states of feeling may be either pleasures or pains = pleasure is felt in pro- portion as our powers are exercised but not over-exercised + pain, in proportion as they THE FEELINGS. 71 ^re compelled either not to operate or to operate too much. A. Testimony showing that activity is plea- surable. I. The love of idleness or learned leisure is nofc idleness, but bodily inactivity accompanied by mental activity -H ennui is painful. II. Many writers — as Johnson Ferguson, Paley have shown the pleasure of activity + all young animals delight in the activity of their powers wiiile the old are pleased with ease. III. Even the affections which are of a painful kind are accompained with a certain amount of pleasure, as e. g, grief, fear, pity. B. General causes determining the degree of pleasure and pain. I. JSTovelty is a cause of a higher feeling of plea- sure. A. Subjectively, as it determines the mind to a new mode of action eithei from inactivity or from ano- ther state of energy. B. Objectively, as it affords gratification to our de- sire of knowledge. II. Contrast enhances the real as well as the apparent intensity of a feeling. A. Unkindness from a person from whom we expect kindness increases the real pain. B. Recollection of past suffering or past happiness increases present feelings + comparison of our condition with that of others increases our feeling of pleasure or pain. 72 THE FEELINGS. III. Harmony = when different feelings are Iiar- monions. they enhance i^ileasiire + when they are discordant they produce pain. IV. Association pre-supposes, does not create feel- ing -f by connecting ideas with objects makes them appear pleasurable or painful although they would not otherwise be so. Lee. XLV. II. As effects states of feeling may be connected with every kind of activity. A. Sensations have certain feelings connected with them. I. The five senses or sensus Jixus^we must dis- tinguish the organic pleasure or pain con- nected with these senses from the higher pleasures resulting from the imagination working upon the objects of the senses = the degree of organic feeling determined by the general law of perception and sensation. — Pleasure or pain varies directly as the sensa- tion and inversely as the perception = in sight and hearing there is little suscepti- bility of organic feeling, in taste and smell - great +no law can explain the causes of par- ticular feelings. II. The vital sense sensus vagus = Hamilton thinks the general law applies to it but does not enter into details. B. Sentiments, connected with the higher fa- culties. I. Contemplative = concomitants of our cogni- tive powers. THE FEELINGS. V3 A. Sentiments attending self-consciousness = plea- surable when there is vigorous and unimpeded energy + painful when there is no cause for one present state of activity to pass into another, as in tedium or ennui = a repressed tendency to ac- tion felt chiefly by the educated + cured by pastimes or occupation + too rapid change of our activity is accompanied by dizziness or nausea. B. Sentiments connected with imagination. I. Reproductive imagination, when its object is clearly and vividly brought before consciousness gives pleasure, and vice versa + an external ob- ject which gives full play to imagination by pre- senting variety ' combined with unity is beautiful and gives pleasure. ir. Creative imagination = reconstructs old materials into new forms either in one or a series of re- presentations = pleasure arises from a varied and harmonious image -t- from the logical depend- ance of representations upon one another = plea- sure comes from extending our knowledge + from clearness and distinctness in our cognitions + from the conviction of the truth of our opi- nions 4 - from ease in detecting unity in variety of objects from induction of general laws and deduction from first principles + from the per- ception of the adaptation of means to ends. C. Sentiments arising from the union of the under- standing and imagination. I. The Beautiful *= Kant distinguishes beauty into absolute and relative = that which is beautiful in itself, as a flower + that which is judged beau- tiful by reference to a certain end =a relative beauty is nothing but utility,— a beautiful utili- ty or a utilized beauty. A. Absolute beauty gives pleasure in proportion as it affords to the imaginatoinand the under- Lee. XLVI. 74 THE FEELINGS. standing the opportunity of exerting fully and freely their respective energies =» the understanding gathers up into a unity the ob - jects of the imagination =» pleasure is in proportion to the ease with which the under- standing performs its functions + there is no pleasure in sundering a whole into its parts + there is pleasure in dividing a whole into its lesser wholes. B. Relative beauty gives a double pleasure =* that which arises from the absolute beauty of the object + that which arises from the notion of conformity to an end = the heauti- ful is that which occupies the imagination and understanding in a free, full and agreeable activity. II. The Sublime =s rouses strong emotion + partly repels =■ is mingled pleasure and pain + re- quires magnitude as its condition. a. Of extension and protension, or of space and time = comprises so great a multitude of parts that the imagination sinks under the attempt to represent it in an image, and the understanding, to estimate it. b. Of intension = power so great that’imagina- tion cannot represent and understanding can- not measure it. III. The Picturesque = variety which allows the mind to expatiate freely aiid easily without at- tempting painfully to reduce it to unity. 11. Practical Sentiment relate to A. Self-preservation. B. Enjoyment of existence. C. Preservation of the species. D. Tendency to developement or perfection. E. The moral law. NOTES EXPOSITORY AND CRITICAL NOTE A. THE RELATIVITY OF KNOWLEDGE. Tpie doctrine of the Kelativity of knowledge, or more properly the relativity of the objects of our knowledge, holds a prominent position in Sir William Hamilton'’s Lectures upon Metaphysics. In this Note three things are proposed : — 1st, To examine the subject of relativity, not- ing a certain impropriety of the language generally em- ployed to describe it, and indicating what is properly meant by the doctrine ; 2nd, To discuss Sir William Hamilton's statement of the doctrine ; and 3rd, To compare his doc- trine of relativity with another of his doctrines alleged to be inconsistent with it. I. All the objects of our conscious knowledge exist iu certain relations, and a study of these relations is needful for a clear understanding of the doctrine of relativity. From the sphere of consciousness we must manifestly ex- clude the Distant and the Past or Future. It is only men- tal phenomena Now and Here which consciousness com- prehends. This principle follows immediately from the na- ture of consciousness. The inner light by which the work- ings of our mind are revealed to us comprehends nothing but its own constituent elements, of whatever nature these elements may be ; but the Distant and the Past or Future cannot, except by proxy, be included in these elements. We do, however think of the distant in space and time, and therefore by proxy, it must be present in our con- scious life. The contents of consciousness appear therefore to divide themselves into two classes those which are 11 78 THE KELATIVITY OF KNOWLEDGE. primitively now and here ; and those whicli are the proxies of the distant either in space or time. These two classes we shall cdX\ Presentations 2i,ndL Representations, These two classes of mental phenomena are sometimes not easily dis- ting'uishable, and are frequently quite inseparable in their union the one with the q^her. Presentations however may, generally, be thus characterised : they are accompanied or preceded by some organic or objective conditions, and have not a necessary reference to any other phenomenon past or present or future. Hepresentations, on the other hand, involve of necessity a reference to some presentation either past or future, or usually some presentation actual in the past and possible in the future. All the contents of con- sciousness must necessarily belong to one or the other of these two classes, as every phenomenon must either be absolute and complete in itself, or must involve a reference to some other possible phenomenon. The presentations and representations of our conscious life appear in consciousness in a state of great complexity, arising from their great number and variety, as well as from the intricate manner in which they are united together. But there are four great Relations in which all the objects of consciousness must stand to one another. These relations are Pifference and Resemhlance, Coexistence and Succession, If objects of consciousness do not differ we cannot discri- minate the one from the other, that is, cannot know them at all. If a representation do not resemble its original pre- sentation and also differ from it, we cannot recognise it as a representation and consequently can have no founda- tion for the belief in the continuity of our own conscious life. The necessary condition of comparing resembling or differing objects is Coexistence ; if they do not coexist with one another they cannot be compared. The Succession of phenomena is necessary as the condition of our own continuous existence and as the basis of the relation be- tween presentations and representations. Thus all pre- sentative and representative phenomena must be related THE RELATIVITY OF KNOWLEDGE. 7 ^ to one another in one or more of these four ways, — Differ- ence, Resemblance, Coexistence and Succession. And the existence of these relations may be considered as one of the a priori conditions of our being* permanent cognitive beings. With reference to these relations, although it may be said that the objects of our knowledge must be mutually relative, it is not correct to say that knowledge itself is relative. Knowledge may be described as a relation ; but to say that that relation is itself relative appears to be unmeaning. Our knowledge of any presentation is surely absolute and complete, provided that presentation is duly distinguished from other phenomena. Our knowledge of any representation, the same condition being fulfilled, appears equally absolute and complete, provided in addi- tion that we clearly recognise the representative character of the phenomenon and clearly conceive the presentation which it represents. As far therefore as simple presenta- tions and representations are concerned, it appears to be incorrect to say that knowledge is relative, although it is quite true that knowledge is a relation and that the pheno- mena of knowledge must be mutually related in order to be known. There is another kind of relativity to which we must turn our attention. Representations are relative to some previous actual or some future possible presentation, and it has been said that our knowledge of that presentation is relative. The chief objection to this statement is that the term relative does not here seem appropriate or suitable to describe what is meant. Our knowledge of the represen- tation is, as we have said already, absolute ; but, in the pro- per sense of the term, we cannot be said to know the origi- nal presentation at all. We believe that it was actually presented in the past, or we believe that it may possi- bly or will certainly be presented in the future, but we do not noio and here know it. If the term knowledge is to be iised in describing our intellectual relation to the past ac- 80 THE RELATIVITY OF KNOWLEDGK tual or future possible presentations represented in consci- ousness, we should say that that knowledge is mediate or representative not relative. Still another question of greater difficulty has to be considered in connection with this subject. The presen- tations of consciousness are undoubtedly related to one another and to representations ia our conscious life. But it is held by many that they are related also to something else not phenomenal ^ that is, which has never been and can never be presented in consciousness. This non-phenomenal thing is sometimes called the thing -in-it self , and is be- lieved to have an existence independent of our minds, and to be the objective cause of those presentations of which we are conscious. Being inferred for the purpose of ac- counting ‘for the presentations which appear in conscious- ness independently of any voluntary effort of our own, it can never be directly known by us. And, since in this discussion, we ought to understand by knowledge imme- diate direct knowledge, we must exclude this non-pheno- menal inferred entity from the sphere of knowledge alto- gether. We believe in its existence as an inference from the presentations of our consciousness, we may hold differ- ent views regarding its nature and relations to phenomena, but we certainly cannot say that we know it and conse- qu^'iitly cannot say that our knowledge of it is relative. What we appear now to have made out is; — that know- ledge itself is a relation, which however requires further examination; that the objects of knowledge are related to one another in terms of difference, resemblance, co-existence and succession, but that our knowledge of them cannot be properly called relative , that those phenomena which are representations are related not only to other phenomena presently in consciousness but also to other past actual or future possible presentations which are believed in but not known and of which they are the proxies ; and that pre- sentations also are related not only to other contiguous phenomena, but also to certain inferred or hypothetical THE RELATIVITY OF KNOWLEDGE. 81 realities believed in, it may be, but not known, and there- fore not known relatively. II. We now proceed to the examination of Sir W. Hamilton’s statement of the doctrine, which is contained in his eighth lecture. According to him knowledge is relative, lst,^‘ Because existence is not cognizable absolutely and- in itself, but only in special modes; 2ud, Because these modes can be known only if they stand in a certain relation to our faculties ; and 3rd, Because the modes, thus relative to our faculties, are presented to and known by the mind only under modifications determined by these faculties themselves.’^ There is much in the phraseology of this statement open to unfavourable criticism. When Hamilton speaks of ab- solute and in-itself existence it does not appear very clear what he means. Existence is an abstract idea taken from things or phenomena which exist. And, according to the laws of representation, it is impossible to conceive existence apart from particular existing things, just as it is impossible to represent extension apart from something extended. Moreover existence apart from existing things is not only unrepresentable but also, as an actual fact, unbelievable. Existence is only an idea abstracted from particular existing objects, and which has no reality apart from these objects. If this is what Hamilton means by absolute existence it appears superfluous to tell us that it cannot be known. But there is reason to believe that by absolute existence Hamilton does not mean the abstract idea above described, but that he means the inferred objective causes of pheno- mena. In summing up his review of philosophers’ doc- trines regarding the relativity of knowledge he says We know mind and matter not in themselves, but in their accidents or phenomena.” And here mind and matter, the unknown bases of phenomena, are evidently synony- mous with absolute existence. By absolute existence then he means the objective cause or causes which co-operate with our activity in giving rise to the phenomena of our S2 THE RELATIVITY OF KNOWLEDGE. knowledge. But these objective inferred causes are not known to us at all ; we infer we are compelled to infer that some objective causes exist, but the nature of these causes is only a matter of uncertain speculation. And it is not correct to say even that these objective causes are known modes, as Hamilton appears to say in his second proposition. The modes of existence, Hamilton appears to consider different from the 'phenomena of our 'knowledge, as well as from alsoluie existence. Now, we know nothing but phenomena ; modes of existence which are not phenomena we do not know. Perhaps, however, by modes of existence, Hamilton means the particular objective causes, such as vibration, heat, light, and so on, which along with our activity, produce phenomena. But these causes are only inferred and speculated about, they are not known. If this be Hamilton’s meaning, then his doctrine that the modes of existence may he greater than the number of our facul- ties of apprehension appears to amount to this, — that if we were endowed with other senses we might have other sensations. There may be objective causes in existence which would give rise to hitherto unknown phenomena if we had only faculties of apprehension adapted to them. This is a statement which cannot be denied. The third point of Hamilton’s statement is, — that the modes thus relative to our faculties are presented to and known by the mind only under modifications determined by these fa- culties themselves.” In examining this we shall take for granted that by “ modes” Hamilton means the inferred ob- jective causes of particular phenomena. And it appears quite plain that these are not presented to and known by the mind” at all ; they are inferred merely to account for the phenomena which are known. Still it may he truly said that these phenomena are the result partly of the ob- jective modes” and partly of the subjective modifica- tions” of which Hamilton speaks. The character of our sensive organism undoubtedly determines the character of the phenomena of which we are conscious. If we had not ! I ) • 1 THE RELATIVITY OF KNOWLEDGE. 83 j eyes and optic nerves of a particular construction we could not be conscious of colours as we now are. If we bad not \ a system of nerves radiating' outwards from tbe centre at the extremities of which sensations are located we could ; not have a knowledge of these sensations as at a particular place or extended over a part of our bodies. The organic A structure of our sense -apparatus is adapted to the objec- Btive modes'’^ or forces so that when the latter come into ■ contact with the former certain phenomena such as colours, ^■sounds, smells, touches and so on arise in consciousness. ^BBut it must be borne in mind that the sensive organism of ^»ur bodies is itself objective with reference to consciousness. ^■Vnd the relation between our organic system and the extra- ^Wrganic forces of nature has for its result the presentation of phenomena such as the above in consciousness. Hence when Hamilton speaks of modifications determined by these faculties themselves^^ we can scarcely interpret him as referring to the part which the sensive organism plays in the production of phenomena. Fie would be the last per- son to predicate any modifying power of the organic senses ; and he doubtless refers to something purely mental. From other parts of his writings we know that he holds that there are certain principles in the mind itself which regulate and determine the character of our knowledge. These principles are called a 'priori or regulating prin^ ciples and, taken together, constitute what he calls the Regulative Faculty. They are not derived from sensa- tions or phenomena ; they are the subjective elements introduced by the mind into phenomena. There can be little doubt but that, by the modifications determined by the faculties/^ Hamilton means the a priori elements of knowledge contributed by the mind. But as he does not here explain himself fully regarding this matter we shall defer the discussion of it to a subsequent Note. Meantime we may sum up in our own language HamiltoiFs doctrine of relativity, and, in doing so, we prefer to invert the order in which he has stated it. 12 84 THE RELATIVITY OF KNOWLEDGE. All that we can directly know is phenomenal ; to suppose that we can know things as they exist anterior to and independent of our knowledge is contradictory and absurd. But the phenomena which we immediately know are not purely objective; they comprehend also subjective elements contributed by our own minds. These subjective elements are inherent in our intellectual nature as cognitive beings, and they unite themselves to the objective elements furnished by the organism and th extra-organic forces, this union constituting thephenoraer of consciousness. These phenomena are what we hm but we are constrained to infer from them certain object] modes^^ which existed in the outside universe anterioi the rise of the phenomena ; and there may be mod . now in existence which are not adapted to our organism and which therefore do not give rise to conscious pheno- mena. From the various inferred modes of existence, and from other possible modes which we have not been led to infer, we can generalize existence itself, abstract or abso- lute existence. But since the special modes of existence, the particular kinds of objective agents or causes, cannot be directly known, but are only inferred, it follows a for- tiori that abstract existence must also be unknown. Hence we may say generally,— all that we immediately know consists of phenomena^ and that these phenomena are not purely objective^ hut consist of certain elements contributed from our cognitive nature and certain elements contributed by our sensive organism in co-operation with the extra- organic agents of nature. III. The third point to which we shall turn our atten- tion refers to the consistency or inconsistency of HamiltoiFs doctrine of relativity with his doctrine of the immediate knowledge of the non-ego. It is alleged by Mr. J. S. Mill that the two doctrines are inconsistent, and there can be no doubt but that Hamilton’s phraseology sometimes lays him open to the charge. In his account of Natural Realism he tells us over and over again that we are immediately con- THE RELATIVITY OF KNOWLEDGE. 85 scious of the thing itself , the material reality, the material non-ego. And Mr. Mill charges him with asserting in his exposition of Natural Realism, an immediate knowledge of that which, in his statement of the doctrine of relativity, he had said we cannot know. In making this charge Mr. Mill has of course to assume that the absolute existence, the thing -in-itself of the doctrine of relativity, is identical with the thing -in^itself, the material reality of the doctrine of natural realism. If we were to judge simply from the phraseology which Sir W. Hamilton employs we might ad- mit the correctness of Mr. MilFs charge. But it is surely inconceivable that Sir W. Hamilton should be so obtuse as not to see and avoid such an obvious contradiction. And a generous critic ought to seek to reconcile apparent in- consistencies rather than to press upon them the character of absolute contradictions. Moreover we think that the apparently inconsistent statements of Sir W. Hamilton may be accounted for by considering the different objects which he had in view in the exposition of the two doctrines. In his exposition of the doctrine of relativity he was oppos- ing himself to these transcendental philosophers who held that the Absolute, or the Thing-in-itself can be known ; in his exposition of natural realism he was opposing the re- presentationists who held that we do not immediately know the objects of the material universe, but only through a representation. Against the former he maintained that we can know only phenomena; against the latter, that the phenomena which we do know are not representatives of other and more real objects, but that they have themselves a real objective existence, that they constitute the real world of our knowledge. Thus he uses the term thing-in^ itself in two different senses; in the one case it is opposed, as unknown, to the phenomenon which we know ; in the other case, it is opposed, as a reality known to us, to the representative idea, a hypothetical fiction which does not exist ; in both cases it may be maintained that Hamilton's object of knowledge is a phenomenon only, but composed 12 2 86 THE RELATIVITY OF KNOWLEDGE. of the subjective and objective elements which we before pointed out. Hence we conclude that Hamilton's doctrine of relativity is not really inconsistent with his doctrine of our immediate knowledge of the material non-ego. NOTE B. SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON'S DOCTRINE OF CON. SCIOUSNESS. Sir William Hamilton’s doctrine of consciousness will be almost exhaustively examined by studying what he teach- es regarding (1) the character and elements of conscious- ness, (2) the sphere of consciousness, and (3) the interpre- tation of consciousness. I.— THE CHARACTER AND ELEMENTS OF CON- SCIOUSNESS. According to Sir William Hamilton, and indeed every other psychologist, consciousness is the most general phe- nomena of the human mind, and all particular phenomena are but its states or modifications. No mental phenome- non can take place which is not, as it were, a link in the general train of our conscious life, a particular form of consciousness. Hence it is impossible to define conscious- ness in the proper sense of the term, that is, to refer it to a higher class of phenomena of which it is a species. Every particular mental phenomenon involves consciousness ; and, on the other hand, there can be no general consciousness which is not some particular phenomenon. Consciousness may be compared to an inner light which reveals to us all that takes place in our minds, and is considered by Ha- milton to be synonymous with immediate knowledge. There are three elements into which Hamilton analyzes OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 87 consciousness^ viz. ; — A recognising or knowing subject ; a recognised or known modification; and a recognition or knowledge by the subject of the modification. Thus con- sciousness, or immediate knowledge is, in reality, a rela- tion between two things, — the knowing subject and the known modification or phenomenon. This relation and the terms of it are worthy of very close examination. The first term of this relation is the knowing subject, the self or ego ; the second term consists of the presenta- tions and representations which are known. With refer- ence to the first of these terms it is manifest that it can- not be itself a phenomenon ; we could never say that one sensation knows another, or that a thought is aware of a volition, or that any single mental phenomenon cognises any other. It would seem equally absurd to say that the whole collection of phenomena which constitutes our consciousness at any one time knows any particular phe- nomenon of the series ; or that the whole of our past and present conscious life consisting of all past and all present phenomena cognises any phenomenon now in con- sciousness. Every single phenomenon is knowi^ is an object of knowledge ; and it is impossible to invest the whole ag- gregate of phenomena with a power the elements of which are not possessed by them separately. Still further we cannot, by generalization, from all the past and pre- sent aggregate of mental phenomena, obtain an element whicb^^e^ji be considered identical with the first term of the relation we are examining. Suppose that, from all past and present mental phenomena, we abstract and genera- lize Feeling itself, we^ may have here the highest mental abstraction we can reach, but it is not the self. Thus we set aside three doctrines which may be held regarding the character of the first term of the relation of knowledofe, the knowing subject : — ( 1 ) That the subject of conscious- ness is some particular phenomenon of consciousness ; (2) that it is the whole aggregate of mental phenomena past as well as present j (3) that it is some element or charac- 88 SIR \V. HAMILTON’S DOCTRINE teristic of the mental phenomena, abstracted from particu- lars, such as Thought or Feeling. All of these proposi- tions we reject because it is inherently absurd that a single phenomenon or an aggregate of phenomena or an abstraction from phenomena should exercise the function of knowing which we are conscious of possessing. There is an element in the relation of immediate knowledge which makes it impossible to explain that relation as existing between mental phenomena simply, or between any com- binations of mental phenomena or any abstractions from them. A common man speaking of his mind or feelings would say my mindj^ or my feelings^ He would say I thought so-and-so,^^ or felt such a sensa- tion/^ or I was conscious of this smell or that sound.^^ In short every one thinks and speaks of himself as a person not to be identified with his body, or the series of phenomena which make up what he calls his mind. This reference of all one^s feelings and thoughts to self is called self-consciousness. The idea of self-hood in- volves the, belief that who am conscious of feelings at the present moment am the same identical being who was conscious at a past time of those feelings which F’ remember. This permanence of self in the midst of successive and diverse sensations is the essential element of personality. The idea of self is not of the sum of the series of feelings which constitute our general con- sciousness, because it is absurd to speak of the aggregate of a series of feelings being conscious of any one of them- selves. Nor is it that of Feeling in general abstracted from particular feelings, because it is absurd to attribute to this or any other abstraction the function of conscious knowledge. In the relation of knowledge there is implied a kind of opposition between self and the sensations of which self is conscious. Sensations past, present and ex- pected are all referred to self as their possessor and subject Self is thought to be the unity in the midst of diverse OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 89 kinds of sensations, the permanent element in the midst of transient and successive sensations, the one conscious subject in the midst of many known objects. In ‘‘selP therefore we have the subjective term of the relation of knowledge, but this term of the relation is so peculiar and remarkable that we must bestow some more attention upon it. We have said that it is not a pheno- menon, and it cannot, in any way, be phenomenized so as to become known. The function of self is to know, and although, in the very act of knowing, a phenomenon arises, yet it is impossible for that which knoivs to set itself over against itself as object and thus become known. Self is the universal relative of all objects, — a something separat- ing itself, as it were, from the phenomena of general con- sciousness and converting them into objects, but incapable itself of becoming an object. This peculiarity of self makes it the most intractable and puzzling element of our con- scious existence. Unknown, but all-knowing, it emerges, as it were, from the midst of the endless variety of phe- nomenal consciousness, asserting its freedom from phe- nomenal law, and offering the great miracle of the life with which we are endowed. It is absurd to attempt a scientific definition or exposition of the unknown ; but we have the power of studying its function conscious activity, and through the study of this function alone can we learn anything about the nature of that which is conscious. About the beginning of this Note it was said that knowledge was the relation between the knowing subject and the known modification. In the former Note we ex- amined the a priori relations existing between the known modifications and we have now turned our attention to the first term of the relation. It remains to examine the relation itself which Hamilton describes as the recognU iion by the subject of the modification j’ and which is de- scribed above as conscious activity directed towards ob- jects. For the function of the subject is really the same SIR W. HAMILTON’S DOCTRINE Dt) as the relation between the subject and the objects of knowledge. And it is manifest tha1»this relation must be different from other relations with which we are acquaint- ed, since the subjective term of it is different from any ob- ject of our knowledge. Moreover the terms of the rela- tion, under present conditions, are inseparable, because the phenomena which we know are themselves comprehended in and to a certain extent identical with the act of know- ing. When we feel a smell, the act of feeling and the smell itself appear to be, as it were, different sides of the same phenomenon. When we attempt, therefore, an examination of conscious activity as seen in cognition we cannot very well separate that activity from its objects. We describe the function of self in cognition as conscious activity in order to distinguish it from the ohjectwe or passive element in phenomena. Knowledge is not the reception of images or impressions from without ; it is essentially an activity of self in relation to things which are not self. This activity is perhaps best described or rather indicated by such terms as assertion, judgment, or predication. We are conscious of a loud noise j in the act of consciousness there is involved the asse rtion of the' existence of the sound. We are conscious of two varying sensations; assert that they differ from one another. We are conscious of a particular smell, colour, figure, and taste ; we assert — this is a rose. Now without this men- tal assertion there is no knowledge ; the mere appearance in consciousness of some phenomenon which does not call forth a responsive activity is t^ot knowledge. We have therefore in this assertion — this conscious activity indi- cated by the term assertion — the essential element of that relation existing between subject and object in cognition. ‘ There is a particular feature of this relation of great importance which we may indicate by the term objeciifica- iion. It is essential to knowledge that the object should be put over against the subject, — that the phenomenal activity should be discriminated into subjective and ob- OF CONSCIOUSNESS. n jective elements. This creation of an opposition or anti- thesis between subject and object, called objectification, is perhaps a result of the conscious activity before described as assertion, or is perhaps identical with it ; but it is at least essential to every act of cognition. Conscious activity is, as we saw before, further dis- criminated into the assertion, in general, of the four great relations between objects, — diflPerence, resemblance co- existence and succession, and the various combinations of these which make up our phenomenal knowledge. But this we do not now need to discuss. We shall proceed to the consideration of our second point — the sphere of con- sciousness. II.— THE SPHERE OP CONSCIOUSNESS. The doctrine which Hamilton maintains regarding the sphere of consciousness is that consciousness is co-extensive with all our knowledge — with all our faculties of knowing as well as with the objects of those faculties. And he sup- ports this proposition in detail by showing that in imagina- tion, in memory, and in perception, the objects of these mental acts are objects of consciousness also. But it is manifest that consciousness is cognisant only of what is now and here present to the mind ; and hence if conscious- ness is to comprehend the objects of imagination, memory, and perception, these objects must be shown to be now and here present. This is what Hamilton does. He does not extend the sphere of consciousness to the past or the distant ; but he contracts the spheres of imagination, memory and perception to that which is present in time and space. The object of imagination, for instance, is not the distant or the past or the future thing or event which is thought about j it is the present mental representation of that thing or event, and that is plainly the object of consciousness. So the object of memory is not the past event which occurred, but the present representation of it. 13 02 SIR W. HAMILTON’S DOCTRINE And, in perception, the thing which we see or hear is not the distant object from which the light or sound proceeds, but the organic impression of which we are conscious. Thus Hamilton makes consciousness co-extensive with all knowledge, by restricting the particular forms of know- ledge so as to bring their objects into immediate relations y/ith the conscious-subject. Notwithstanding the importance which Hamilton attri- butes to this doctrine and his laborious eflPorts to support it, we cannot admit its accuracy. Memory, imagination, and perception have certain universally recognised and appropriate meanings, which the psychologist has no right to alter. When the psychologist adopts a term in common use into his system he ought to employ it in its common and understood meaning. And certainly the common and universally understood meaning of memory, imagination and perception is not that which Hamilton gives to them. When we speak of remembering an event, as, for example, the visit of the Prince of Wales to Calcutta, the object of memory is not a present idea or representation but the past occur- rence. It is unavailing to say that the past event does not now exist and therefore cannot be an object of memory. The act of memory in reality reproduces the past event, by projecting backwards into past time our present mental re- presentation of it, and asserting a belief that it actually occurred as we represent it. In this act the object of con- sciousness .is only the mental representation ; the object of memory is the mental representation projected backwards in time and invested with that reality of objective exis- tence which v»re assert when we say that we believe it actu- ally occurred. Thus the object of consciousness is only partially identical with the object of memory ; the latter involves elements which are not contained in the former. Similar remarks might be made with reference to imagi- nation. In perception it may be made equally manifest that Hamilton's identification of the sphere of consciousness and OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 93 perception cannot be held. Accordin;^ to the universal use of the term perception, we are said to perceive distant objects ; and when we adopt this term into psychology we have no right to change its meaning. We may quite properly analyze the act or the process of perception into its elements, but in doing so we must take care and nob destroy it. According to Hamilton, perception, as far as sight is concerned, is the consciousness of the impi'ession of light upon the retina of the eye. And it is perfectly certain that this is not the ordinary and proper meaning of sight. The ordinary man sees distant objects. His seeing of distant objects is a phenomenon which he cannot explain ; the psychologist undertakes to explain the pheno- menon; but in doing so he has no right to mutilate or destroy it. This Hamilton does by bringing the object of perception into immediate contact with the organism. The object of consciousness is, no doubt, partially identical with the object of perception ; but, as in memory, the latter involves elements which are not contained in the former. The analysis of the process and the object of perception would be out of place here; and, having stated our objec- tions to Hamilton's doctrine regarding the sphere of con- sciousness, we shall now proceed to our third point, the in- terpretation of consciousness. III.— THE INTERPRETATION OF CONSCIOUS- NESS. According to Sir William Hamilton there are two methods of interpreting consciousness, which he calls the inductive and the critical methods respectively. By the former method particular phenomena of consciousness are subject- ed to study and classified according to their resemblances or differences, and from them general laws of thought are reached by induction. Many cases of caudal connection, for example, are observed, and from them there is general- ized the great principle that every event has a cause. Simi- 13 2 94 SIR W. HAMILTON’S DOCTRINE larly, many material objects are perceived to be extended, and it is concluded by induction that all material things are extended, or are perceived as occupying space. But Sir William Hamilton objects to this method that it is in- capable of explaining the element of necessity which is in- volved in many mental products or laws. Induction alone can only lead to a principle which is generally and probably true ; but there are principles in the human mind which are universally and necessarily true. For example all men not only believe, but must believe that every event has a cause ; all men not only perceive but must perceive phenomena under the relations of time and space. Now this element of necessity, it is alleged, does not and cannot arise from an induction from experience. And hence Hamilton rejects the inductive method as inadequate, and makes use of an- other method which he calls the Critical, In studying the phenomena of consciousness, he employs criticism^ that is, he discriminates the phenomena of consciousness into two classes : — those which are contingent, the results of mere experience ; and those which are necessary, and therefore not the results of experience but rather the a priori conditions of experience. By this critical examina- tion of the simple facts of consciousness he is able to ac- count for the elements of necessity and universality in the more complex products of conscious life ; and he is able also to make use of the method of induction wherever it may be applicable. Mr. J. S. Mill, in his examination of Sir William Hamilton's method, chooses to call it the Introspective Method, instead of adopting the name which Hamilton himself applies to it. Whatever may have been his motive for changing the name, we do not think that the one which he has chosen is so suitable as the proper one. All methods of interpreting consciousness must employ intros- pection, since introspection is the only possible means by which we can become acquainted with the contents of our minds. In fact introspection appears to be almost synony- OF CONSCIOUSNESS, 95 mous with consciousness itself. The term introspective therefore does not distinguish Hamilton's method from others, and we prefer to employ the term which Hamilton himself used, and call his method the Critical. The term Inductive by which Hamilton designates the method which he rejects, is rejected by Mr. Mill also, al- though the method itself is essentially that which he em- ploys. He calls it by a new name, the Psychological Method, and although this name is not without objections, yet we shall employ it, since it is that by which Mill de- signates his own method. We have then, to be examined, two important methods of studying the phenomena of con- sciousness, viz. the Critical and the Psychological. We have seen that the first of these discriminates between two classes of conscious phenomena, the contingent and the necessary. These facts which are necessary and simple and universal are held to be the primary and original elements of our conscious existence and to be the « priori conditions of all experience. All contingent phenomena of experience are based upon them and have them as es- sential constituent elements. The objection urged by Mr. Mill against this method is that necessity and universality do not of themselves render it certain that a mental fact is original; complex and derived facts or phenomena may also be characterized by necessity. Hence, according to him, before we accept any fact or phenomenon as an original and simple datum of consciousness we must examine into the character and source of its necessity. There is a necessity which re- sults from experience, and which consists simply of an in- separable association ; and in fact all necessity may result from the application of the laws of association to pheno- mena. Mr. Mill holds in particular that extension and space are the results of experience and association. And the proposed object of all those who make use of the psy- chological method is to show that all mental products are the results of experience and association. 96 SIR W. HAMILTON’S DOCTRINE Now there can be no doubt but the laws of association play a most important part in the formation of the complex contents of our consciousness. Phenomena do not appear in consciousness in an accidental or random order, but there is a mutual connection between them of such a nature that they serve to bring* one another before consciousness. When two mental phenomena have been experienced at or about the same time^ a bond of connection is formed between them, so that afterwards if one of them is repeated the other is likely to be represented. This link of association between mental phenomena appears to be altogether inde- pendent of volition ; the associated idea of any particular phenomenon appears in consciousness without any effort of ours, or even in spite of efforts to avoid thinking about it. Illustrations of this association of mental phenomena will readily occur to any one. W^e have once visited a house, and at the time of our visit something of particular interest to us has occurred. If we ever again visit the house or even have our thoughts directed to it, the idea of the interesting fact obtrudes itself upon our attention. The various laws by which phenomena are associated to- gether have been sufficiently investigated and are well- known. We need not therefore refer to them, but shall proceed to point out a distinction of importance with re- ference to our present study. We have to distinguish between what is properly a mental association and an objective connection. When two or more phenomena have been once or frequently presented together in consciousness, they become connected in representation. But there are two different cases to be considered. Two different phenomena may be, upon one or more occa- sions, connected together in presentation, but may afterwards become objects of consciousness separately. This we may call the case of the association of separable phenomena. On the other hand two or more phenomena may be so connected together ^ that the one is never pre- sented except in connection with the other, and the as- OF CONSCIOUSNESS, 97 pociation in this case is an association of inseparahJe phenomena. And we must be careful to discriminate between the distinction which we have here drawn be- tween separable and inseparable phenomena and another distinction which is considered of great importance by psychologists, — the distinction, viz. between separable and inseparable associations. There may be an inseparable association of separable phenomena ; but as a matter of course, when the phenomena are inseparable in presenta- tion, the association of the representations is inseparable also. There are many familiar instances of an inseparable association of separable phenomena; a book, a watch, a trinket of any kind, which has been presented to us by a dear friend becomes, in our mind, inseparably associated with the idea of that friend. But quite different from this is the inseparable association of phenomena which are in- separable. Let us study a case. In our experience we have never been conscious of colour except in connection with extension. No matter how far back in our lives we attempt to reach by the aid of memory we are incapable of discovering the slightest trace of the possibility of a separation between the two phenomena. We do not remember ever to have seen a colour which was not extended or an extended figure which was not, in some way coloured. Nor is there any indication in history or in language of the existence of any race of human beings in whose minds there was ever conceived the possi- bility of such a separation. And since the presentation of colour is always combined in our experience with that of extension it follows as a matter of course that the re- presentations also are always combined. This distinction between an inseparable subjective as- sociation and an association of objectively inseparable phe- nomena is one of great importance. When phenomena which are only occasionally presented together have an affinity for one another sp as to cling together in repre- sentation, the association is truly and only mental. The 98 SIB W. HAMILTON’S DOCTRINL possibility of tbeir being separated in presentation shows that their synthesis in association is only a mental one_, or at least that the objective union is only accidental. But, on the other hand, when phenomena are always united in presentation and can never by any means be separated, their synthesis is not only or even chiefly mental. The ob- jective inseparable connection is that upon which the sub- jective association depends. It constitutes a different kind of connection from that which is simply subjective. There is such a decided difference both in degree and in kind be- tween the mental synthesis which we form between two phenomena which have accidentally been brought into contiguity, and that synthesis which exists between two such inseparable phenomena as extension and colour, that no person who has not a particular theory to support, would ever place them in the same category. The in- separability of phenomena in presentation leads no doubt to their inseparability in representation ; but it also leads to something else, and that is, to the conclusion that the synthesis which binds them together is not a subjective one at all. Another phase of the same distinction is found in the distinction between associations which are peculiar to in- dividuals and those which are common to all mankind. All mental associations depend upon the experience of the individual in whose mind they have been formed. Peculiar experiences will therefore produce peculiar associations. Experiences common to all will result in associations com- mon to all. In different zones of the earth^s surface and in difiPerent countries there are many differences of climate, landscape, means of living, habits and customs which give rise to very varied mental associations. The character of the seasons in India, in Britain, and in Canada presents strikinsT differences, and, in the minds of the inhabitants of these countries respectively, there are consequently very different ideas connected with each of them. The word “ water/^ for example, in the torrid zone, is always asso- OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 99 dated with fluidity as one of the characteristic qualities constituting the denoted object. But in the temperate and frigid zones, where water frequently assumes a solid form, fluidity is not uniformly associated with the word. Many other examples of variable associations might be given. On the other hand, with the word air^^ there are always, associated the peculiar sensations or ideas connected with respiration. The air which we breathe^'' is a phrase which may be universally employed to express the ex- perience of mankind, the reason of course being that, in our present state of existence and with our present physi- cal constitution, the breathing of air is an essential con- dition of life. This association of the word air^^ with the idea of breathing is just as inseparable as any asso- ciation which we could name. It is moreover an asso- ciation formed in the minds of all men without excep- tion ; but there are important difierences which we shall note between this and other inseparable associations. We have just considered two associations, one of them variable and the other invariable and universal, but both being associations connected with particular objects of our knowledge. The qualities or ideas associated are relative to or representative of particular complex sensa- tions depending upon our present physical constitution. But if we consider the connection between extension and colour we shall be able to note an important difference. The quali- ties to which we referred as associated with air and water were simply a combination of complex sensations objectified ; but here we have a sensation “ colour’^ associated with some- thing which is not a sensation. Extension is neither a sensation nor any combination of sensations, but a certain relation which is seen to exist between objectified sensa- tions, or a form which is perceived in connection with a single sensation. And although the mental association between air and hreatJiing may be just as inseparable and universal to the human mind as that between colour and extension^ yet we would never place the objective con- U 100 SIR W. HAMILTON’S DOCTRINE nection between the first pair in the same category as that between the second pair. The connection between air and breathing is determined to our minds hy the peculiar cir- cumstances in which we are placed as physical heings^ and we can easily imagine other circumstances in which this gonnection would not exist. But the relation between extension and colour, although neither more objective nor more necessary than the former is determined hj the consti- tution of our minds with reference to external objects^ or the constitution of external objects loith reference to our minds. Hence, since we are unacquainted with any other forms or laws of knowledge except our own, it is impossible for us to conceive that any intelligence could be cognisant of colour without extension ; or to state the same thing more abstractly, it is impossible for us to conceive that any intelligence could be cognisant of phenomena except in the relation of difference and co-existence. Thus the connection between extension and colour is characterized by an absolute Universality with reference to all intelligence as far as intelligence can be understood by us ; while that between air and breathing has only a contingent universa- lity with reference to beings who may possess bodies con- stituted as ours are. We have endeavoured to show that the connection be- tween extension and colour is not a case of mental asso- ciation and cannot be resolved into association. Objectively the two things are absolutely inseparable ; and subjectively the relation of extension depends upon the primary relation of co-existence which we have seen is an a priori condition of our constitution as capable of knowing. But if this doctrine be correct we have here an original fact of our consciousness which the psychological method of Mr. Mill fails to interpret. And until this method explains satis- factorily the inseparability of colour and extension both objectively and subjectively we cannot admit that it is adequate to the interpretation of all the facts of our con- ciousness. This case of inseparability is only one of those OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 101 wbicli miglit be adduced as being insoluble by tbe psycbo- logical metbod. We have cbosen to examine it thus fully because it is perhaps tbe most important. And as, until tbe above doctrines are overthrown, tbe psychological metbod must be considered unsatisfactory, we shall now proceed to tbe consideration of other methods. Tbe critical metbod of Sir W. Hamilton, which however is to be assigned to Kant as its author, has already been referred to, but before examining it further we desire to point out and describe another metbod, which has arisen out of tbe psychological, and which may be considered a kind of compromise between the psychological and the critical. We allude to that which has been called the Fsychogeneiical Method. Those who adopt this method admit that there are men- tal facts and products which cannot be explained by the principles of association. Neither the form nor the matter of our knowledge is the result of our individual experience merel}^ We are born with a certain constitution, mental and physical, and the nature and extent of our subsequent acquirements in knowledge and practical ability depend upon our inherited constitution. In other words it is ad- mitted that individuals possess certain « jorim principles and tendencies by which the phenomena of their conscious- ness are determined and governed. This admission, made by such psychologists as Herbert Spencer and G. H, Lewes, is a tacit acknowledgment of the essential truthful- ness of the position held by those who have adopted the critical method. But, while admitting this, the Psycho- genetical method attempts to trace the origin of the a priori conditions and principles of our nature to a very remote source. The accumulated experience of the past ages of human history, as well as of the past ages, count- less in length and impenetrable to human knowledge, of brute history, is called upon for an explanation of the ori- gin of that physical, intellectual, and social nature with which we are born into the world. It is assumed that lower 14 2 102 SIR W. HAMILTON’S DOCTRINE living forms develop themselves into higher, tliat the ex- perience of individuals and races gradually produces organic changes which are transmitted to successors, and that thus, by the natural transmission of organic structures produced or modified by incessant experience all the higher forms of life and mind have been produced. An adequate examina- tion of this ambitious method would carry us far be 3 mnd our allotted space and our object; but we oflTer the follow- ing observations with reference to it. 1. The problem attempted by this method is practically an - impossible one. We are not able to trace the series of changes asserted to have taken place. It cannot be esta- blished that experience gives rise to the structural changes in the organism said to be the result of it. The pheno- mena requiring to be studied in a satisfactory employment of the method are too remote from possible observation to be used as the foundation of a science. Even if we at- tempt to study the organic changes produced by experi- ence in human beings now living we cannot succeed ; and any dogmatic assertions made regarding them must be rash and vain. Much more must this be the case with re- ference to races of men and animals which existed in a remote past antiquity. Consequently the researches car- ried on in accordance with this method are nothing better than ambitious and perfectly uncertain speculations. 2. Against the fundamental assumptions of this method it may be alleged that mental phenomena do not, in some cases at least, correspond to organic structure. It is now universally admitted that the brain and nervous system of the anthropoid ape is exceedingly similar to that of man, whereas the mental functions of the latter are almost infi- nitely in advance of those of the former. This fact is quite inconsistent with the fundamental assumption of the psy- chogenetical method. 3. If experience in past ages has given rise to necessary truths and a priori conditions of thought and knowledge, we might reasonably expect that these a priori principles should OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 103 continue to be produced in our own age. While it may- be admitted that some particular tendencies and abilities may be acquired and transmitted, it has not been shown that the essential and universal laws of human intelligence have suffered the slightest change since man came into being. From these considerations we should be inclined to re- ject the psychogenetical method as impracticable, possibly false, and quite incompatible with that desire to attain certain conclusions which ought to characterize men of science. And we are now driven back to the critical me- thod of Kant and Hamilton which we adopt as correct and adequate, with the following reservations : 1. The adoption of this method does not commit us to all the results of criticism which those who have hitherto employed the method have reached. It may be that mis- takes have been made in discriminating between facts of consciousness as original and acquired, simple and com- plex, that some phenomena have been regarded as origi- nal and simple which are really derived and complex. But this admission does not detract from the value of the me- thod. 2. The adoption of the critical method does not pre- vent us from making use of the principles of association as far as they are applicable. It is not an essential princi- ple of this method that anything which is now found to be necessary must be an original necessity of intelligence. And if any necessity of thought or knowledge can be ex- plained by the laws of association or any other principles of experience it ought unquestionably so to be explained. But the critical method insists upon distinguishing be- tween such explicable necessities of thought, and an inex- plicable residue of necessities which, from their nature, must be taken as a priori and founded in the constitution of our intelligence. 3. The critical method, while it looks principally to the phenomena of consciousness as the materials with 104 SIR W. HAMILTON’S DOCTRINE OF CONSCIOUSNESS. which it has to deal, is not inconsistent with a careful study of the organism and cosmic forces and laws in so far as these way throw light upon the problems to be solved. NOTE C. SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON’S CLASSIFICATION OF MENTAL FACULTIES. Sir William Hamilton divides the operations of the mind into six classes which he calls Faculties. These are — the Presentative, the Retentive, the Reproductive, the Re- presentative, the Elaborative, and the Regulative. We might criticise unfavourably the use of the term faculty to express a class of mental operations, were it not that Hamilton himself guards against an improper use of it. Faculty, with him is not a part or organ of the mind, but simply a class of similar mental activities. But the parti- cular classification of operations which he adopts is open to serious objections. We must bear in mind that one of Hamilton's most important doctrines is that all particular mental operations are but particular modes of conscious- ness, and that consciousness comprehends or is co-exten- sive with all its own particular modes or activities. Now the second and third of Hamilton's Faculties are admit- tedly exercised out of consciousness. The so-called Reten- tive Faculty or memory is the retention, somewhere or in some way not very well understood but certainly out of or beneath consciousness, of knowledge once presented so that it may afterwards be represented. This retention may be explained as resulting from a certain constitution of the mind, as Hamilton explains it ; or it may be explained as resulting from a certain constitution of the nervous sys- tern as certain physiologists explain it. But however it may be explained, it certainly is not mental activity ; it is CLASSIFICATION OF MENTAL FACULTIES. 105 not exercised in consciousness ; it is not a mode of con- scious life ; and therefore it should not be called a mental faculty, if by faculty we mean a conscious mental opera- tion, as Hamilton does. As for the Reproductive Faculty, it also is exercised beneath consciousness. The act of re- production has been finished as soon as the phenomenon appears in consciousness, and therefore it cannot be called a conscious mental activity. Still further the so-called Reproductive Faculty is simply a name given to the laws of association which express the order in which phenomena usually appear in consciousness. The laws which deter- mine the order in which one mental phenomenon follows another are certainly of importance but they are not pro- perly called a faculty, they are not a conscious mental activity. The sixth of Hamilton's Faculties — the Regulative— he himself admits to be improperly called a Faculty. It is simply a name given to the sum of a priori principles which govern our mental operations. We are so consti- tuted that we must know and think in certain ways and according to certain principles. And it is of great impor- tance for us to be able to analyze this original constitution of our nature so as to ascertain the general laws which must govern our conscious mental life. But these laws are certainly not classes of mental activities or phenomena, are not properly in consciousness, and should not therefore be collected into a class called by the name of Faculty. The result of our criticism is that we reject three of Hamil- ton’s list of Faculties. The remaining three, — the Presentative, Representative, and Elaborative must be retained. Knowledge is present- ed, represented, and elaborated, all these acts taking place in consciousness. The preceding criticism of Hamilton’s classification is founded upon the principle which Hamilton maintains, that consciousness is co-extensive with all mental activities, the latter being but particular modes of consciousness. It lOG CLASSIFICATION OF MENTAL FACULTIES. is however open to the psychologist to maintain that there is a kind of mental activity going on beneath the sphere of consciousness ; but if we admit this we must give up the doctrine of the co-extensiveness of consciousness and mental activity. There are certain obscure problems con- nected with what goes on beneath the sphere of conscious- ness which should not be hastily solved. Knowledge is somehow retained so that it may be subsequently repre- sented in consciousness, but whether the conditions of its retention are mental or cerebral it is not very easy to de- termine. Thought are sometimes suggested to the mind in such very extraordinary ways that we find it difficult to explain their origin. Sometimes a strange sympathy is excited between one mind and another so that the one can control the other without any apparent physical com- munication. There are many obscure phenomena which appear to indicate that there is a sphere of spiritual acti- vity and life unilluminated by the light of consciousness and beyond the region of direct study. While therefore, if we admit Hamilton‘’s own great principle of conscious- ness, we must reject his classification of mental faculties, it is perhaps better to leave the character of sub-conscious life and activity undetermined until more of the obscurities connected with it are cleared up. NOTE D. REID’S DOCTRINE OE PERCEPTION. It is an unfortunate thing that Sir W. Hamilton, in his Lectures, has made it a matter of so great importance to show that Reid held the doctrine of Natural Realism. The truth or falsehood of Natural Realism does not, in the slightest degree, depend upon the doctrine of perception held by Reid ; and although the character of Reid^s philo- REID’S DOCTRINE OF PERCEPTION. 107 sopby niay Lave been of importance to those who listened to his lectures it does not seem now to be of the slightest consec[uence whether he was a Natural Realist or not. It seems therefore extraordiuaiy that Hamilton should have devoted three lectures to the examination of Reid's historical review of theories of perception and of his own theory. And it is quite bewildering to follow Hamilton in his examination of the errors of the philosophers whom Reid criticises, Reid's errors in criticising them and Rrown's errors in criticising Reid's criticism. Without attempting to follow Hamilton through this bewildering maze, we shall turn our attention to the principal point which he endeavours to maintain, — that Reid was a Natural Realist. In his twenty- third lecture, Hamilton sums up his examination of Reid's doctrine 'by pointing out four suppositions upon which Reid must be held to bie a Natural Realist. These are : — (1) If he maintain that his immediate perception of external things is convertible with their reality; (2) if he assert that^ in his doctrine of perception, the external reality stands to the percipient mind face to face, in the same immediacy of relation which the idea holds in the representative theory of the philor sophers ; (3) if he declare the identity of his own opinion with the vulgar belief, as thus expounded by himself and the philosophers ; or (4) if he declare that his perception affords us equal evidence of the existence of external phe- nomena, as his consciousness affords us of the existence of internal. And Hamilton adduces quotations, which we shall examine, to show that all these suppositions are ful- filled in Reid's doctrine. In support of the first and second he adduces the following; — "We have before examined the reasons given by philosophers to prove that ideas, and not external objects, are the immediate objects of perception. We shall only here observe, that if exter- nal objects be perceived immediately we have the same reason to believe their existence as philosophers have to believe the existence of ideas, while they hold them 15 108 REID’S DOCTRINE OF PERCEPTION. to be the immediate objects of perception/^ (Works, p. 446), From this quotation, according* to Hamilton, we are to conclude that Reid holds that to be perceived means the same as to exist, and that, in perception, the external rea- lity stands face to face to the percipient mind in the same immediacy of relation as the ideas of the philosophers stand to consciousness, . A fair reading of the quotation should lead us, we think, to this conclusion that the immediate perception of ex- ternal objects is as sure a guarantee of their existence as the consciousness of ideas is of their existence. It is one thing to say that perception is a guarantee of existence or reality ; it is another thing to say that perception is con~ nertible with existence or reality. The latter was said by Berkeley, but Reid did not understand the doctrine and never expressed it. All that Reid meant to say was that we should place as implicit confidence in our perception of external objects as philosophers do in their conscious- ness of ideas. And none but madmen or fools have ever doubted this. But in saying this he asserts nothing whatever regarding the character of perception. He tells us, however, that external objects are the immediate objects of perception, and here we appear to have something said regarding the nature of perception. But the question arises, — what does Reid mean by immediate? There are two meanings of this term which it is of importance for us to discriminate. The first of these may be called the psychological meaning, and in this sense the term is used by Hamilton. In this sense immediate knowledge means knowledge in which the object is present to consciousness itself and not through the medium of any representation. The second of these may be called the logical meaning, and in this sense immediate know- ledge means knowledge which is obtained directly without the intervention of a process of proof or inference. Now when Read says that the objects of the external world are REID’S DOCTRINE OF PERCEPTION. 109 tbe immediate objects of perception, we cannot decide whether he is a Natural Realist, until we have determined whether be uses the term in its psychological or in its logi- cal significance. He might use the term in its latter sense without having the most remote idea of the meaning of that immediate knowledge which is asserted in Natural Realism. A few quotations from his writings will show in what sense be uses it. In the meantime, I beg leave to think with the vulgar, that when I remember the smell of the tuberose, that very sensation which I had yesterday and which has now no more any existence, is the immediate object of my memory.” (Works, p. 106.) It is simply impossible that immediate can be used here in the 'psychological sense, since the so-called immediate object now no longer exists. And immediately below this passage he explains himself in such a way that we must conclude that he had the logical meaning of the word in his mind. If you ask me,” he says, “ why I believe that the smell exists, I can give no other reason, nor shall ever be able to give any other than that I smell it. If you ask me why I believe that it existed yesterday, I can give no other reason but that I remember it.” Manifestly immediate^ of the first quotation, is identical in meaning with I can give no other reason^ of the second. That is, it is used in its logical sense. Again, in his essays upon the Intellectual Powers, Reid says — If, therefore, we attend to that act of our mind which we call the perception of an external object of sense, we shall find in it these three things : — First, some con- ception or notion of the object perceived ; Secondly, a strong and irresistible conviction and belief of its present existence ; and, Thirdly, that this conviction and belief are immediate and not the effect of reasoning P (Works, p. 258). Here Reid himself indicates as clearly as possible that the term imm.ediate is used in its logical sense. And in explaining the third of the above points he en- larges upon the fact that no process of reasoning is in» 15 2 no REID’S DOCTRINE OF PERCEPTION. volved in perception. But throughout his flfitlngs we have ‘ nowhere been able to discover the idea of psychologi- cal immediacy which is involved in the doctrine of Natural Kealism. Hamilton’s third point is that Reid declares the identi- ty of his own opinion with the vulgar belief. What can be established by this it is difficult to see. Berkeley de- clared the identity of his opinion with the vulgar belief; and yet Reid is very far way from the position of Berke- ley. Reid declared the identity of his opinion with the vulgar belief, and yet he maintained, contrary to vulgar belief, that the appearance or idea of colour is in the eye (Works, p. 137) and that the colour of an external object something unseen and unknown (W'orks, p. 138). Hamil- ton declared the identity of his opinion with the vulgar belief, and yet he held that the immediate object of per- ception is in all cases in immediate contact with the or- ganism, a proposition which the vulgar can neither un- derstand nor believe. An appeal to uncritical unenlight- ened vulgar belief is surely unworthy of a philosopher. In the fourth place, Hamilton tells us that if Reid de- clare that his Perception affords us equal evidence of the existence of external phenomena, as his consciousness affords us of the existence of internal” he must be a na- tural realist. But surely it is possible to hold that we can place implicit confidence in the truth of perception without holding that the object of perception is imme- diately present to the mind. The essential point of natural realism is that the non- ego is immediately present to and Jcnoivn by the ego ; but this point is not involved in the assertion that perception gives us certain evidence of the existence of its object. The longest train of ma- thematical reasoning gives us certain evidence of the truth of its conclusion, but this fact vouches nothing as to the character of the reasoning process. Neither does the certainty of perception vouch anything as to the character perception. The fact is that Reid knew no more about REID'S DOCTRINE OF PERCEPTION. Ill tRe doctrine of natural realism than Berkeley knew about Kaiit^s doctrine of the subjectivity of space. Although Berkeley came very close to the doctrine of natural realism, Beid did not even understand him, and it appears to be a foolish anachronism to attribute to Read a doctrine which bad then scarcely dawned upon the minds of psychologists. Reid^s doctrine of perception was a slight advance upon that of preceding representationists. He held that sensa- iionsy hy a natural and irresistible principle of our consti- tution, suggest to our minds the conception and create the belief of external objects, and that this suggestion is imme- diate and not the effect of reasoning. How this can possi- bly be interpreted as a form of natural realism, and why the attempt should be made thus to interpret it, transcend the present writer’s power of imagination to conceive. NOTE E. NATURAL REALISiM. This is the name which Sir W. Hamilton gives to the doctrine which may be considered the most important that has been enunciated by him. We shall first quote, from bis sixteenth lecture, Hamilton’s statement of the doctrine. We may therefore lay it down as an undisputed truth, that consciousness gives, as an ultimate fact, a primitive duality ; — a knowledge of the ego in relation and contrast to the non-ego ; and a knowledge of the non-ego in rela- •tion and contrast to the ego. The ego and non-ego are, thus, given in an original synthesis, as conjoined in the unity of knowledge, and, in an original antithesis, as op- posed in the contrariety of existence. In other words, we are conscious of them in an indivisible act of knowledge together and at once,- — but we are conscious of them as, in themselves, different and exclusive of each other. Again, 112 NATURAL REALIS.VI. consciousness not only gives us a duality, but it gives its elements in equal counterpoise and independence. The ego and non-ego, — mind and matter — are not only given together, but in absolute co-equality. The one does not precede, the other does not follow ; and, in their mutual relations, each is equally dependent, equally independent. Such is the fact as given in and by consciousness.’^ The grand psychological doctrine here enunciated is probably the most valuable contribution which Sir W. Hamilton has given to the philosophy of his country and the world. And this doctrine has already been incorporated into the systems of eminent psychologists who are not always ready to acknowledge whence it comes. Before proceeding to the examination of Natural Realism we propose first to criticise what appears to be an inaccuracy in the above ex- pression of it. Hamilton says that consciousness gives a knowledge of the ego in relation and contrast to the non-ego ; and a knowledge of the non-ego in relation and contrast to the ego.’^ In Note B above, when examining the character and elements of consciousness’^ we pointed out that the ego is not a phenomenon, and cannot in any way be phenomenized so as to become known. The function of self is to know, and although in the very act of knowing, a phenomenon arises, yet it is impossible for that which knows to set itself over against itself as object and thus become known."’^ From this point of view the reader will at once see that the expression ^‘a knowledge of the ego'' cannot be considered correct. The ego is the subject of consciousness, — that which is conscious — but cannot be known. The objects of consciousness are known. There is a relation between the ego and the non* ego; from the subjective side the relation is one of knowing ; from the objective side, it is one of being known. Hence it would be more correct to say that an examination of conscious- ness gives as an ultimate fact a relation between the ego as the permanent and universally-present conscious-subject, NATURAL REALISM. 113 on the one hand, and a multiplicity of different and tran- sient objects constituting the non-ego on the other. The subjective term of this relation is itself unknown, but our knowledge of its character and reality is the result of the analysis of consciousness which leads necessarily to a belief in the existence of something which is conscious. The objective term — the non- ego — is known, not as an activity or modification of the ego, but as a real object appearing in consciousness independent of subjective determination and having an existence and laws quite uncontrolled by the conscious-subject. Thus we appear to have, as the most essential principle of natural realism, the fact that the ego is immediately cou'^ scions of the non-ego^ or that consciousness is the relation between the ego and the non-ego^ or the illuminating tight which mahes hiotvn the non- ego to the ego. A fact of such great psj^ch'blogieal importance as this is perhaps not to be fully expressed by any single mode of statement, but we hope that the above explanation will make clear its mean- ing. The doctrine which is directly opposite to this principle of natural realism is that in consciousness there is no knowledge of the non-ego, but only of the states or acti- vities of the ego. This doctrine is usually known as ideal- ism, and of it there are many forms. The one grand objection to conjidering the objects of consciousness mere states or activities of the ego is that they are manifestly not so 'they appear in consciousness independent of and frequently in spite of voluntary subjective effort ; the order in which they appear is, as a rule, entirely independent of subjective control ^ they are collected into groups consti- tuting complex objects quite independent of any subjective synthesis. Hence to speak of these objects as states or activities of the ego is entirely to ignore their manifest character. Perhaps the prevalent errors regarding them have arisen from their being called ideas of the mind ; if so, the sooner the terms ideas and mind^ in such a loose in- 114 NATURAL REALISM. accurate application, are banished from psychology, the better. We return then to Hamilton's fundamental and, we think, unassailable, position, that in consciousness the ego stands in the relation of immediate knowledge to a great variety of objects constituting the non-ego. And we must now enquire regarding the character and conditions of this non-ego. In answering the third objection to natural realism in lecture twenty-fifth, Hamilton explains what is the total and real object of perception or rather, as it should be, of consciousness. Perceiving the material rea- lity, he tells us, does not mean that we perceive the material reality absolutely and in itself, that is, out of relation to our organs and faculties ; on the contrary the total and real object of perception is the external object under relation to our sense and faculty of cognition. We perceive, through no sense, aught external but what is in immediate relation and in immediate contact with its organ ; and that is true which Democritus of old asserted, that ail our senses are only modifications of touch. Through the eye we perceive nothing but the rays of light in relation to, and in contact with, the retina.-’"’ The determination of the particular character and con- ditions of the non-ego of consciousness is not of so great consequence as the establishment of the fundamental posi- tion of natural realism that a non-ego of some kind is the object of consciousness. But, this fundamental position having been established, the point next in importance is to determine something more definite regarding the imme- diate and primary objects of consciousness. In the above quotation Hamilton tells us that the objects of perception are certain external realities in immediate contact with our bodily organs at the different points of sense. We have already criticised the use by Hamilton of the term perception as synonymous with consciousness or immediate knowledge ; and in examining this doctrine regarding the immediately-known non-ego we shall adopt a phraseology NATURAL REALISM. 115 which we think correct. The question then is, — does the primary non -ego of consciousness consist of external reali- ties in immediate contact with our organs of sense ? This question must be answered in the negative if it can be shown (1) that a knowledge of our bodily organs in- cluding the organs of sense is itself not primary but ac- quired, and (2) that it takes a certain determinate time for an impression made upon an organ of sense to be followed by an act of conscious knowledge. 1. If we are not primarily acquainted with our bodily organism, it cannot be said that we are conscious of the external reality in contact with our bodily organism. No matter what theory we hold as to the relation between consciousness and the organism, a knowledge of an exter- nal reality as in contact with the organism implies a knowledge of the organism as in contact with the external reality. And if we have not a primary knowledge of the organism, neither can we have a primary knowledge of the extra-organic reality. And we think that any one who watches the progress of the acquisition of knowledge in the case of a child must conclude that the child is not born with any definite knowledge of its own physical system. A considerable experience has to be passed through before the infant intelligence obtains any tolerable acquaintance with its own organic abode, and the same experience is ne- cessary to enable it to become acquainted with external realities as in relation to its organism. Hence we should say that tbe knowledge of these external realities is not prima- rily given in consciousness. 2. But further the most distinguished modern physio- logists tell us that a certain appreciable time elapses be- tween contact of an external reality^^ with the organ and the conscious sensation or perception. The existence of this interval appears to indicate that a nervous process must take place between the organic contact and the act of consciousness. And this is fatal to the supposition that 16 m NATURAL REALISM. we are primarily and immediately conscious of the exter- nal reality at the point of sense. What then are the primary contents of consciousness ? We have seen that consciousness is the illuminating* lio-ht in which the ego becomes aware of the non-ego, and in a previous Note we indicated the relations which must pri- marily exist between the constituent elements of the non- ego. These relations are Difference, Resemblance, Co- existence and Succession. The crude phenomense which appear in consciousness in these relations may be designat- ed by the general term Feelings, In the course of ex- perience, by an objective law, a law of the organism, these Reelings locate themselves in different parts of the or- ganism. This location of the Feelings, we know, depends upon the nervous and muscular structure of the organism. And it is a most important step in the acquisition of the child^s knowledge of his abode. Thus the immediate primary non-ego of consciousness consists of crude Feelings known in certain relations to one another; and the first step in the acquisition of knowledge consists in the location of these Feelings — the assigning to them of the position determined for them by their objective conditions. This location of the Feelings is the foundation of our knowledge both of the organism and of extra-organic rea- lities. The knowledge of external things may indeed be supposed to advance with the knowledge of the organism itself. Both are objective with reference to the ego ; and it is their mutual contact and interaction, in an infinity of ways, which give rise to the phenomena of con- sciousness. The progress of the knowledge of the organism and of extra- organic realities is the acquisition of the power of Ferception, The knowledge given in perception is very complex and is made up of many simple elements which it has taken a considerable time to bring together. We shall describe briefly the process by which our acquired power of perception is built up. The most primitive act of thought consists in the intui- NATURAL REALISM. 117 tion of one of the relations of difference^ resemblance, si- multaneity or succession which we have described. And next in rank is the synthetic act by which objects or ele- ments thus related are connected together into unity. These primitive acts of thought, carried on involuntarily, result in certain products which constitute the simple ob- j'ects of common knowledge ; and we now propose to study these products. We consider first the perception of differ- ence and simultaneity. We have already seen that there can be no cognition of simultaneous objects without a perception of difference. That which enables the child to distinguish between colours and sounds, and tastes, and smells is a certain difference in the manner in which his senses are affected. But along with this difference of sensation there is a co-existence of them. Sensations differing from one another in quality are frequently experienced in regularly combined groups. A connection is thus formed between them, so that when one of the sensations is experienced the others are expected. This combination of a real with expected sensations con- stitutes an object. The formation of natural objects is therefore one of the most primitive products of thought. All objects of knowledge are composed of a certain uni- form group of sensations and expected sensations. But it takes a considerable amount of experience to determine accurately the exact constituents of objects. A child, for example, has been accustomed to take some disagreeable medicine from a spoon ; this experience has been repeated so frequently that a firm connection has been formed be- tween the appearance of the spoon in the hand of the nurse and the disagreeable taste of the medicine. To the mind of the child the hand of the nurse holding the spoon and the expected taste constitute an object ; and the child^s mistake is corrected only when some pleasant food is given to it by the spoon ; then it learns that the taste of the medicine is not an invariable element of that cluster of sensations introduced by the sight of the spoon, 16 2 118 NATURAL REALISM. The most important of the sensations connected to- gether in the formation of objects are those of sight and touch. The sense of sight gives only colours differing from one another in quality and occupying a certain hounded space. The sense of touch combined with the muscular sense of effort leads to the inference of hard or soft, rough or smooth resisting bodies existing outside of us. The motion of our limbs in contact with ex- ternal bodies gives us the idea of distance. But it takes a considerable time for the child to connect the figured colour which it sees with the resisting body which it touches. The same sensations of colour and the same sensations of touch and muscular effort havinsr been fre- quently experienced together the child learns to believe that the object which it sees^ is the same as the object which it touches. Other sensations, as of smell, taste or sound are soon added to the group, and thus is produced the full conception of a natural object. The distance of an object from the body is first measur- ed by the motion of the hand towards it ; the greater time and effort required to reach an object the farther it ps believed to be away from us. But it is observed also that the greater time and effort taken by the hand to reach an object, the dimmer does the colour of the object appear to the eye ; and the difference between clear- ness of colouring is still more observable when the process of walking is combined with the stretch of the arm. Other differences of appearance also are observed by the eye, as a greater or less size, a greater or less clearness in the ap- pearance of the minute parts of objects and so on. These differences of appearance become gradually connected with the longer or shorter time and the greater or less effort required to reach objects with the hand, and thus we learn to see the distance of objects, or, properly speaking, to in- fer from visible appearances, what are the distances from us of the objects of touch. Hence we see that the percep- tion of the objects of the external world is a combination NATURAL REALISM. 119 of iotuition and inference. We perceive intuitively actual sensations ; we expect, by an involuntary inference the other sensations of the group. We intuite sensations of muscular resistance ; we infer some resisting external ob- ject. We intuite particular sensations of colour ; we infer the distance to be passed over before particular sensations of touch can be reached. The products of thought just described are founded mainly but not exclusively upon the relations of difference and simultaneity ; other products of a primitive kind are founded mainly but not exclusively upon the relations of resemblance and succession. The child is conscious of the same sensation or the same group of sensations at succes- sive times; the regular recurrence of the group of sensa- tions leads to a belief in the identity of the object. Thus our belief in the permanence and independence of natural objects is the result of seeing that a present group of sen- sations resembles a group of sensations which we remem- ber to have experienced some time ago. This recognition of similarity between present experienced sensations and past represented sensations is of the greatest importance as it is the foundation of our belief not only in the perma- nence of objects but also in the permanence and identity of ourselves. We have in this also the only means we possess of comparing all kinds of relations as well as ob- jects with one another. Past periods of time, figures and dimensions of space, forthputtings of energy, experiences of pleasure and pain, are recalled and compared with pre- sent experiences ; and thus our lives are enriched by being able to bring together the past and the present. When the present group of sensations do not exactly re- semble the representation of a past group we get the idea of sameness of kind but difference of individual object. The child at first is unable to distinguish between its mother and other ladies ; but, soon differences are recog- nized and individuals distinguished. The ability to per- ceive minute differences in the midst of a general resem- 120 NATURAL REALISM. blance is necessary in order to enable us to distinguish one object from another; as the ability to assert with confi- dence the exact resemblance of a present object and a re- presentation is necessary to enable us to identify an indivi- dual. The uniform connection between succeeding events con- stitutes what we know of the causal relation. When a certain phenomenon is uniformly followed by another phe- nomenon^ the two become so connected that when the one appears the other is expected. Uniformity of succession is thus an essential, though not the only essential element in the causal relation. We thus see that the objects and relations of our com- mon knowledge are produced by the exercise of involun- tary and to a great extent unconscious thought. When we first waken up to conscious life we find ourselves in tlie midst of a world of objects regarding which we know a good deal. This primitive knowledge is the result, no doubt, of an almost unconscious process which has gone on during the dreaming sleep of infancy, as our bodies and minds were being gradually adapted to our surroundings. Having discussed at length the doctrine of natural real- ism and the process of perception based upon it, we shall now refer to what we think an important mistake in Ha- milton's elassification of theories of perception. Natural realism as we take it, is a psychological doctrine which asserts phenomenal duality of consciousness. But there is asserted by Hamilton an ontological duality or duality of siibstance, not as actually given in consciousness, but as testified to by consciousness. Hamilton appears to assume that the phenomenal duality of consciousness cannot be and has never been denied, whereas the ontological duality testified to, as he thinks, by consciousness, has very ge- nerally been denied. And bis classification of theories is based partly upon a psychological and partly upon an onto- logical principle. The result of this is considerable con- fusion and inaccuracy. For example, Berkeley is put down NATURAL REALISM. 121 as a Cosmothetic Idealist of the cruder form ^ wbereas lie was undoubtedly a presentationist^ and, according to our view, a natural realist. It is greatly to be regretted that Sir W. Hamilton’s great learning is so often accompanied by a want of simplicity and accuracy. We shall conclude our Note upon Natural Realism by proposing a classification of the elements into which objects of perception may be resolved. All Objects of Perception consist of : — A. Quantity founded upon co-existence and succession ; such as Trinal Extension, Figure, Position, Distance, &c. B. Quality founded upon the difference and association of sensations, and divided into particular qualities accord- ing as I. They require for their percep- tion tactual contact or resistance. 1. Sardness, roughness, ^c. known by the tactual sensation and mus- cular effort in pressure or motion. 2. Taste, known by the tactual sensation and a chemical solution of particles in the mouth. II. They do not involve contact with the object. 1. Colour, in which the sensation is perfectly projected so that there is no conscious inference connect- ing it with the object. 2. Sound, in which the sensation is imperfectly projected requiring a conscious inference to connect it with the object. 3. Smell, in which the sensation is scarcely if at all projected re- quiring the assistance of other senses to lead to the inference of its connection with the object. NOTE F. CLASSIFICATION. The reason wby we classify objects and relations is that we may thereby systematize our knowledge. The know- ledge of an infinite number of individual things, without bringing together resembling things and separating differ- ing things, would simply be confusion — a class of images without order. We arrange the objects of our knowledge into classes in order the more clearly to understand them. The most general principle of classification may be thus 122 CLxVSSIFIC.mON. expressed ; — Things which resemhle one another are to le united into one class ; things which differ from one another are to he arranged in separate classes. For example, if we have before us on a black-board a large number of differ- ent mathematical figures, we should select from them figures having three sides and put them into one class ; figures having four sides or more we should arrange in other classes. The class of three-sided figures being con- stituted by their general resemblance we should denomi- nate triangles. But a study of these triangles would re- veal that there are differences amongst them, some have all their sides equal ; some have two of their sides equal ; some have all their sides unequal. Why is it then that we arrange these differing figures in the one class, triangle ? Manifestly because the general resemblance in having three sides and three angles is of greater importance than the minor differences in the lengths of the sides or the sizes of the angles. Hence we arrive at a modification of our general principle : — Points of resemblance should he m- ffloyed to constitute a class when they are more general and more important than points of difference between individuals. And when we have constituted a class by means of certain general resembling qualities, we may make use of minor points of difference for the purpose of constituting sub- classes or varieties. As e. g. triangles may be equilateral isosceles, scalene and so on. The name by which we designate a class is called a com- mon term; although there are certain modified forms of classification whose names we do not call common terms. We frequently classify objects for the purpose of counting them without reference to other important principles of classification ; and we get the classes of numeration, — tens, hundreds and so on. We classify objects from some su- perficial or arbitrary point of view ; as trees into ^forest, soldiers into a regiment y geese into flock and so on. Here the classification is founded upon the principle of general resemblance and contiguity in space, and we call the terra CLASSIFICATION. 123 by which such classes are distinguished a collective term. Again when we study inorganic substances as gold, silver, lead, we observe that the character of these metals does not depend upon the size or figure of the pieces. A mi- nute particle of gold possesses the same qualities as a large nugget, and thus the mechanical or chemical properties of metals are taken into account in their classification, other points of resemblance or difference being neglected. The names by which we indicate these inorganic substances are called substantial terms. And as these substances are. not divided into individual objects, but simply into greater or smaller pieces, the term cannot be said to denote indivi- duals, but only an object of indefinite shape and size pos- sessing certain qualities. Ascending higher in the scale of existence, we reach organic objects, in which we have a certain unity produced by nature which we cannot divide without destroying the object. This impossibility of phy- sical separation without the destruction of life has caused these objects to be called individuals. And it is with re- ference to them that the most important problems of classi- fication arise. If we wish to examine, for the purpose of accurate knowledge, all the organized individuals discoverable, we must first adopt some criterion by which we can distinguish them from inorganic elements. This criterion must be found in all the individuals ; and it must form a clear dis- tinguishing line separating them from things inorganic. An accurate description of what is common to all organic beings constitutes a definition of the class. And the name, organized beings, organized individuals, or whatever it may be is said to connote these common qualities. Examining more minutely into the character of organic beings, we observe some of them possessed of powers of locomotion while others are not. Four-footed animals, birds, fishes, insects and so on wander about in search of food ; while trees and smaller plants are rooted to the soil. This and other differences serve to distinguish organized beings into 17 124 CLASSIFICATION. two great classes ; those which we call animal ; and those called vegetable. The connotation of animal organized leings and vegetable organized beings comprehends both the qualities common to them all, and the qualities in the one case, possessed by all animals, and, in the other case, pos- sessed by all vegetables. Thus, as we sub-divide a class, the concept becomes richer, but the number of individual to w'bich the name is applicable is smaller. If now we confine our attention to animal organized beings we observe important differences amongst the individuals in- cluded in the whole class. Some of them possess a back- bone or vertebra which serves as the foundation or support of the other parts of the body ; some of them have hard rings going round the body and protecting the softer parts within ; some of them have solid shells within which they live ; while some attach themselves after the manner of plants to some more solid foreign body. Thus we have four sub-divisions of the animal kingdom : — vertebrated animals^ articulated animals ^ mollusca, and zoophytes. Now, as be- fore, if we add to the concept of organized animal beings the qualities indicated by the names vertebrated^ articidaU ed, mollusc^ and zoophyte we enrich the concept with a fuller meaning ; but we restrict the application of the name. We might again take the class vertebrated animals, and observe the distinctions belonging to individuals of it ; and by adding these distinctions to the general concept, we would at the same time enrich the concept and constitute a number of smaller classes. In this way we might go on enriching the concept and sub-dividing the classes until we reached a class which could not be farther divided. The concept of this lowest species would comprehend all the qualities of the concepts of the larger classes to which it belonged ; but it would exclude many qualities belonging to individuals of the species. Thus no matter how far we go in the process of sub-division we never reach a class so small that its concept comprehends all the qualities of an images It is absolutely essential to classification that some CLASSIFICATION. 125 of the peculiarities of individuals should be struck olf in forming the concept, unless indeed we can realize the impossible supposition that there might be a number of organized individuals found exactly alike in every quali- ty. Moreover the determination of the lowest species is, to a certain extent, arbitrary, as there may often be a doubt whether a quality common to a number of indivi- duals is to be considered a mark of a species, or merely of a subordinate variety. Now, it must be remembered that this process of classifi- cation is purely a mental arrangement of individual objects of knowledge, although it is founded upon actual distinc- tions and resemblances observed amongst them. And hence the concept of any class is only a mental object composed of represented qualities separated from the images of the individuals belonging to the class. This concept as repre- sented in the mind is an indwidual object of consciousness; but its peculiarity is that a presentation of it may be ob- tained from a great number of objects. And hence some have said, although erroneousnessly, that the concept of a class is general. It is bat a single object of consciousness, hut it symbolizes a large number of objects, just as a com- mon name is applicable to a large number of objects. The only difference between a concept and a name is, that the former is a collection of qualities abstracted from indivi- duals, according to some principle, while the latter is a sound more or less arbitrarily associated with the indivi- duals .which agree in the possession of the qualities of the concept. In considering the doctrine of classification we must study it also as applied to actions^ or modes of action, or complex relations of things. In the phenomena of the mind, for example, there are important difference. All mental phenomena agree in this, that we are conscious of them. But some of our mental phenomena have no external ob- ject corresponding to them and revealed by them, — they are purely subjective in their character ; these are feelings. 17 2 126 CLASSIFICATION. Some agaia have a special object either present or past these are cognitions. While others have an object expect- ed and lead to some action ; these are volitions. Thus we can classify mental actions ; but the principal difficulty here, which we do not meet with in the case of organic individuals, is that we do not actually find these mental actions distinct and separate from one another. There is a complexity and intermingling of them which renders their classification difficult. Again we distinguish differ- ent men from one another by their different modes of ac- tion, One man is very energetic and regular in the per- formance of his duties ; we classify him with energetic or industrious men. Another man is noted for his want of sympathy with suffering or for the cruel actions which he performs ; we name and classify him a cruel man. Thus every adjective which we apply to an individual implies a conscious or possible classification, because it denotes a quality which may be found in other individuals and may therefore be the basis of forming them into a class. There are also complex united systems of things which are to be classified. Such are a steam-engine, a threshing- machine, a family, a tribe, a government, a system of planets, a combination of forces, and so on. The same prin- ciples of classification as we have already explained apply to these complex unities, the only difference being that the relations constituting the unity are frequently not ob- jects of sense-knowledge, but are apprehended only by the intellect. The relations of persons, for example, constitut- ing a government cannot be perceived by the senses j they are so complex and remote from sense that we think of them as entirely different from ordinary things known through sense. And yet they are all ultimately reducible to objects of sense-perception. The essential feature of government consists in the relation between one person who issues a command and a number of other persons who, for fear of punishment, are led to obey the command. But this simple relation is usually combined along with CLASSIFICATION. 127 many others into a system of great complexity constituting what we understand by the word government. Having explained and illustrated the general principles of classification we now proceed to study the process of assigning any particular object of our knowledge or thought to its appropriate class. To be able to do this correctly is a matter of great importance^ as we do not know an object accurately until we know what classes it belongs to. Be- fore we can classify any individual it is manifestly necessary for us to know that it possesses the essential qualities of some class ; having ascertained this we immediately assign it to that class. We see, for example, an object rooted to the soil, evidently organic, and having a stem, branches, and leaves. Knowing that these qualities are possessed by many vegetables we assign our individual to that class. A further examination reveals the fact that the object has flowers growing upon it, that the leaves are netted instead of parallel veined, that it has a woody stem composed of a number of circular layers around a central pith. Knowing something of botanical classification w^.call our plant an exogenous fiowering plant. Pursuing our examination into minute characteristics of the flower and the leaves and the seeds we succeed in determining the Order, the Genus, and the Species of the plant. Thus it appears that all that is necessary in classifying an object is a knowledge of the characteristics of the class to which it is problematically to be referred, and a know- ledge derived from examination that the object in hand presents these characteristic qualities. Having discovered the important qualities of an object we look about, unless we already know, for some class whose concept compre- hends these qualities ; and having found it we unite by a synthetic act the individual with the other individuals of the class. As long as we are dealing with inorganic elements or organic material bodies there are no great difficulties in the w^ay of classifying individuals. We are now able to 128 CLASSIFICATION. apply cLemlcal tests with definite* and precise results to all inorganic elements ; and the microscope and dissecting knife enable us to examine the minute parts of organized objects with great accuracy. And consequently it only requires a certain amount of practical training and skill to refer any object with precision to its proper class. But when we come to the more complex relations of human life and action much greater difficulties present themselves. These difficulties arise from the greater complexity of the phenomena with which we are dealing, from the want of such a precise system of classification as we have with re- ference to material objects, from the impossibility of ob- serving such clear distinctions as are seen between organic things, and from other causes. The following are some of the objects of thought in connection with human life and action which present themselves for study and classifica- tion : — The phenomena of consciousness ; mental modes of action constituting character ; bodily habits ; languages ; general forms of body and countenance ; national customs and superstitions ; family institutions ; tribal habits and laws ; forms and characteristics of governments ; and other features connected with social life which will readily sug- gest themselves. A few illustrations will show the diffi- culty of reducing these things to scientific system. When we observe an action done by some person, we often experience a feeling of pleasure or displeasure, of approbation or disapprobation, and we judge that the ac- tion is either right or wrong. Now students of the human mind cannot ag-ree as to what is the true nature of this moral feeling or judgment, as to whether it is primarily a feeling or primarily a cognition, as to whether it is a simple and original phenomenon of human consciousness, or a complex and derived phenomenon found only in human minds which have attained a certain degree of advancement. Again when we try to estimate the character of the men whom we meet there is room for great doubt and uncer- tainty, We sometimes observe men giving large sums in CLASSIFICATION. 129 cLarity to the poor or otherwise trying to ameliorate their condition ; and we should probably think that these were benevolent men. But it is possible^ and many times true, that men perform apparently benevolent actions from some selfish motive, and the discovery of this fact makes it im- possible for us to classify them as benevolent. The motive by which an action is inspired constitutes the most essential element of the action, and the difficulty of ascertaining its character renders it difficult to characterize the action. Suppose again that we wish to determine whether a certain writer is a poet, or a philosopher it is not in all cases easy to do so. There are versifiers who are not poets ; and there are many who write about philosophy but are not philoso- phers. And critics are not by any means agreed as to what it is that constitutes a man a poet or a philosopher. Thus we have here a two-fold difficulty; the essential qualities of the classes are not determined with precision; and even if they were determined it is no easy matter to say in any particular case whether a person possesses them. It requires a certain amount of poetical or philosophical genius to estimate the quality of poetical or philosophical writings. Students of language also find great difficulty in classify- ing the diffPerent languages of mankind. Leading distinc- tions have no doubt been observed and form the basis of a provisional classification, but the science is yet in its in- fancy and much has to be done in the way of determining the characteristics of diflPerent languages and arranging them into a system. Similar remarks might be made with reference to most of the problems of classification which arise in connection with the intellectual, moral, and social life of man. And we may now point out a few leading er- rors which we are apt to make in our study of the pheno- mena in question. (1) Errors are often made in failing to distinguish the essential or predominating character of that which we are examining. A man may conceal under a harsh and forbidding exterior a really kind and generous heart j the manner of a man is most frequently that by 130 CLASSIFICATION. which he is at first judged ; and thus people frequently form an erroneous judgment by not looking through the manner at the more essential qualities of mind and conscience. (2) Errors in classification arise from supposing things to differ which in reality are the same or similar. For example Sir W. Hamilton supposed that Dr. Heidi’s theory of perception was quite different from and inconsistent with the representative theory held by Dr. Thos. Brown and others of Heidis predecessors. In truth, although there were minor differences, the essential doctrines of Reid^s theory are not what Hamilton supposed and are not so dif- ferent from the doctrines of Brown as to entitle them to be put into a different class. Real resemblances are often concealed under a difference of phraseology, and it is an important function of thought to penetrate beneath the verbal expression of doctrines to the ideas taught. (3) Errors in classification arise from supposing things to resemble one another which are in reality different. Things indicated by the same word, for example, especially if the things indicated are mental in their character, are at first sight supposed to be the same, but in reality they are frequently found to be very different. Names, in the course of time, often change their meaning, and it is frequently very difficult to observe and discriminate the different meanings which, at successive times and as used by different persons, they carry with them. The philosophical name idea presents us with a good example of a word which means very different things as used by different writers or even by the same writer. Not only may single words mean different things but also similar forms of expression may be very ambiguous in meaning ; of this good speci- mens are given in many of the ancient oracles which were usually susceptible of quite different interpretations. And tlie writings of sophistical reasoners are usual 1}^ filled with forms of expression which convey one meaning to the mind of the reader, but are used to express quite a different idea of the writer’s mind. CLASSIFICATION. 131 TLe above are the principal sources of error in classifica- tion ; and thus it appears that there are three important conditions of making an accurate classification. These are ; — to be able to distinguish, for the purpose of com- parison, the essential from the subordinate qualities of the things with which we are dealing ; to be able to detect resemblances even when concealed under manifest differ- ences ; and to be able to detect differences although con- cealed by apparent resemblances. Having selected essen- tial qualities of things and observed resemblances and differences the process of classification is obvious, — things which resemble one another are to be classified together, and things which differ from one another are to be arranged in different classes. Thus the most important and the most difficult part of the process of classification consists in the analysis and comparison v/hich must precede the synthetic act in order that it may be of any value. The synthetic act of classifying is obvious and necessary as soon as the preceding analysis and comparison are completed. NOTE G. THE LOGICAL DOCTRINE OP THE PROPOSI- TION. In a preceding Note we pointed out that there are four great relations in which the phenomena of our conscious- ness must stand to one another, — the relations vijn* of Difference, Resemblance, Simultaneity and Succession. If now, we consider the objects of our knowledge we shall reach another division of relations subordinate to the above. All objects which are related to one another may be distinguished into quantities and qualities^ The latter correspond to the sensations of which we are or may be conscious ; the former consist of the Form of sensations or objects, namely, the space, time, motion and so on, by 18 132 THE LOGICAL DOCTRINE OF THE PROPOSITION. which sense objects are conditioned. Ag-ain the relations of all objects or classes which ma)^ be predicated are either internal or external ; the former being* the relations of ob- jects or classes to internal constituent qualities or parts, the latter to other external objects or classes. Internal and external relations may be both quantitative and quali- tative, and thus we have a four-fold division of relations into: — I., Internal Quantitative ; II., Internal Qualitative ; III., External Quantitative ; IV., External Qualitative. This classification is founded upon and not exclusive of our former division of the four primary relations, as will be seen from the following table : — I. Internal Quantitative Re- lations compre- hend : — Relations of fi* gure, size, shape, motion, number, and so on, of the constituent parts or elements of objects, classes or systems. These relations may be any of the four primary relations or any combina- tions of them. II. Internal Qualitative Re- lations compre- hend : — Relations be- tween the qua- lities of objects of our know- ledge, or classes of objects, these qualities being made known to us by the sen- sations or ideas which they pro- duce in our minds. III. External Quan titative Relations comprehend : — Relations of any of the four pri- mary kinds orany combinations of them between the figure, size, shape, motion, duration, number, and so on, of objects, clas.='es or systems which are external to one another. I IV. External Qua- litative Relations comprehend : — R.dations be- tsveen external objects or systems with reference to qualities made known by sense, moral or aestheti- oal qualities, char- acters, habits, con- ditions and any other character- istics of objects of knowledge which may be appropri- ately called quali- tative. We shall give illustrations of these great classes of re- lations. I. Internal Quantitative Relations. When we construct a geometrical figure, as that- of the fifth or the forty- seventh proposition of the first book of Euclid, we constitute a unity, and the subsequent demon- stration is a comparison of the different internal i^arts in respect of their magnitude, and the inferences which result from that comparison. Similarly, many of the proposi- tions of geometry consist of a combination of predications regarding the internal quantitative relations of different kinds of figures. THE LOGICAL DOCTRINE OF THE PROPOSITION. 133 The astroDomer who studies the motions of the different bodies beloni^ing' to the solar system is engaged with in- ternal quantitative relations. The solar system as a whole constitutes a unity^ the elements of which are the sizes, masses, distances, orbits, velocities, and so on, of the vari- ous bodies which revolve around the sun or the primary planets, and of the central luminary. The mechanical engineer is similarly occupied when he arranges the figure, strength, motion, position, and so on, of mechanical structures, as houses, bridges, or machines. Comparative anatomists are able to complete the skeletons of animals, having given them certain of the bones. This ability is the result of careful study of the internal quanti- tative relations of the bodies of animals, II. Internal (Qualitative Relations. The qualities of single objects of sense often require to be studied and compared in the interests of science. The chemist in his analysis of the various organic and inorganic substances which come under his notice is engaged in the study of internal qualitative relations. The process of classification involves a careful examination and compari- son of the internal qualities of bodies or things classified. The composition and criticism of the productions of the poet, musici ill, statuary, and painter, consist chiefly of the arrangement and examination of internal qualitative rela- tions. The same relations are the objects of study when we examine the characteristics of a man, of a nation, of a government, of a religious system, of a systematic body of doctrine of any kind, of an oration, in short of any of the vast variety of things known to us which are cha- racterised by internal differences of quality or powers of exciting ideas. III. External (Quantitative Relations. In classification, when the extension or quantity of one class is compared with that of another, we are dealing with external quantitative relations. Many geometrical propositions are concerned with these relations. Compari- 18 2 134 THE LOGICAL DOCTRINE OF THE PROPOSITION. sons of the weights, masses, figures, proportions, velocities, numbers, and so on, of distinct bodies not forming parts of a connected system, have for their objects external quantitative relations. IV . External Qualiiaiice Relations. The botanist, zoologist, and chemist, in comparing the different specimens of objects which comes within their respective spheres to study are concerned about external qualitative relations. So is the ethnologist in comparing the characteristics of different races of men, the philologist in comparing the principles of different languages, the mythologist in bringing together the myths, legends, and folk-lore of different countries, and the comparative econo- mist in studying together the different social and political institutions which have sprung up in different countries at different times. This study of the qualitative relations of things and systems has sprung into importance chiefly in modern times and is a very powerful method of scientific discovery. In the comparative study of physical charac- teristics, of moral and social habits, of myths, of religious beliefs, of languages, of institutions, of laws, and of his- torical events, consists the only available effectual method of discovering the beginnings and the principles of human progress. Now all thought is concerned about some, or all or various combinations of the relations which we have just now classified ; and the result of every comparison as well as the expression of every relation, is 2 l predication ox 2^ 'pro • position. In the exposition of our own views, we shall use the former term ; in the criticism of current logical doctrine we shall use the latter. Predication^ we may thus define as the assertion that one object or element of our knowledge or conception stands, or does not stand, in some relation to one or more other objects or elements of knowledge or concep- tion, In order that we may clearly understand the nature and forms of predication we shall study a few examples of THE LOGICAL DOCTRINE OF THE PROPOSITION. 135 it. Aud we shall begin with the study of examples of the predication of internal relations. When we sa}^, this rose is red, we affirm an internal rela- tion of simultaneity or co-existenee. The redness is a quality found co-existing with all the other qualities which make up our knotvledge of the flower. The uniform and inseparable co-existence of these qualities causes us to think of them ail as making one object ; and when we say this rose, we mean by it the one object made up of all the qua- lities. The first term of the above predication calls up an image before consciousness ; the second term is one of the elements of the image singled out for the moment for particular attention ; the predication affirms that the ele- ment forms a part of the whole object, or co-exists with the other element of it uniformly and inseparably. The horse has four legs. This predication also affirms a certain internal relation of the object horse. The first term of the relation denotes a particular object composed of many parts and ^qualities. The second term of the relation expresses particular elements or parts of the whole object. The predication affirms a relation of co»existence of that regular and inseparable kind which constitutes the co- existing qualities an individual. All predications which we make regarding the internal constitution of objects are of the same nature as the above, and have about the same significance. The form of the predication is a matter of comparative indifference, as we are now engaged in the study of thoughts not of words. The same relation is expressed by all the following forms : — The rose is red ; the horse has four legs ; the house consists of six rooms ; England contains Middlesex ; the lion is possessed of a shaggy mane ; the solar system comprehends the sun, planets and satellites, iknd in all these cases the first term of the predication denotes a whole object, and the second term expresses some quality, part, or element of the object. Not only may we predicate internal relations of material 136 THE LOGICAL DOCTRIKE OF THE PROPOSITION. objects and systems of objects, but also oj mental and social pbenomeua. The following’ are examples of such predica- tions : — A moral judgment consists of intellectual and sentimental elements ; the family is composed of a husband, wife, and children ; the Government of England includes the Sovereign, the House of Lords,* and the House of Commons. The meaning of the predication in ail these cases is the same as before. There are other predications of relations which may, perhaps, be called internal, but which should be distin- guished from the above. These are predications of sUive actions. We may give as examples of these : — The dog barks; fire burns; the sun shines ; the river runs; the wheel turns, and so on. In all these predications, and such as these, there is involved the idea of some thing pro^ eeeding from the first term of the relation. The dog barks, means a certain sound proceeds from the dog. Fire burns, means that a certain sensation is experienced after contact with fire. The river runs, means that a body of water occupies different places at successive times. The ivlieel turns, means that the different parts of the wheel succes- sively occupy different positions. The first term of each of these predications denotes some object ; the second term implies some sensation or action ; and the predication affirms a relation of succession between the co-existing qualities of the object and the sensation or action predicat- ed. We now proceed to the examination of external relations of objects as affirmed or denied in predications, and, for the sake of convenience, shall consider indiscriminately quantitative and qualitative relations. And first amongst these we have relations of difference. A relation of differ- ence, we have seen, is absolutely necessary to enable us to distinguish one object from another. If two objects are exactly alike in quality they must, at least, have different spatial positions to be distinguishable. Relations of differ- ence are usually expressed by the comparative degree of THE LOGICAL DOCTRINE OF THE PROPOSITION. 137 the adjective which expresses the quality with reference to which two objects are compared. The following* are ex- amples : — Red is brighter than green. Lead is heavier than wood. The sun is larger than any of its planets. The conceptions of Paradise LosP^ are more sublime than those of The Deserted Village.'’^ A child is not so strong as a man. A greyhound can run faster than a bull- dog. The scenes of heaven are more glorious than can be ex- pressed by language. The fruit of the pine-apple is not the same as that of the orange tree. In all these cases, .and in others which might be adduced, we see that the two terms of the predication are the two objects compared ; and the predication asserts that a relation of difference, in some particular respect, exists between them. The words which we have italicised in the above examples ex^ press the relation predicated between the two terms \ and it is manifest that it is of no consequence which term of the relation comes first in the predication. The substitution of the second term for the first would simply involve a slight change in the expression, but no change in the thought. Red is brighter than green, is in thought the same as green is not so bright as red. And so of all the others. Frequently we have to express a difference be- tween two objects which consists in the fact that, along with a certain resemblance, the one possess(;s qualities W'hich the other does not. For example, the bat differs from the mouse in that the former has membranous appendages answering the purpose of wings, while the latter has not. The zebra differs from the horse in having a regularly striped shin. The whale differs from the most of the mammals in being an aquatic animal. In such compari- sons as these it is not easy to adopt such an expression as will show the difference predicated so clearly as in the for- mer cases ; but the thought is equally simple. There are two objects compared ; they are found to differ in a cer- tain respect ; and the predication affirms that they do thus differ. And, as before, it is of no consequence which term 138 THE LOGICAL DOCTRINE OF THE PROPOSITION. of tbe relation comes first in tlie predication ; the thought is the same whatever he the particular mode of expression. Amongst the external relations of objects, both in res- pect of quantity and quality^ that of resemblance is of great importance. It is in consequence of resemblance in certain respects that we classify objects together and con- stitute them a unity. It is in consequence of resemblance between objects that we draw inferences regarding them. We are not now concerned^ however, with these uses of re- semblance, but only with the nature and expression of the predication of resemblance. Let us study some examples: — This line is of the same length as that. These triangles are all equal-sided. This piece of lead weighs two pounds. In the first and third of these examples there is a compa- rison of two objects, and a predication that they resemble one another ; in the second the predication of resemblance has reference to several objects. When the terms related to one another in a predication of resemblance are common names, there is always involved a comparison of several objects. For example, horses have four feet ^ we mean that all objects known by the term horse resem- ble one another in having four feet ; here we predicate a relation of resemblance between all known or conceived in- dividuals. And, as we said before, we imply that each horse has four feet — an internal relation of co-existence. We often predicate resemblance between things which are not exactly alike, but yet sufficiently alike to be classi- fied together. When we say crimson is like scarlet., we mean not that they are exactly alike, but that they are the same hind of colour, and thus distinguishable from blue or green. When we say that the sheep resembles the deer^ we mean to predicate resemblance only in certain respects, and if we state our meaning fully we will particularise the points of resemblance. The most of the resemblances which are affirmed in predication are only partial ; when we affirm a complete resemblance we call it an identity, an equality or some such name. THE LOGICAL DOCTRINE OP THE PROPOSITION. 139 Although mental phenomena and material phenomena are thought to be entirely different in kind, yet they are frequently employed to illustrate one another. We speak of a lofty thought^ thus implying a resemblance between the excellence of the thought and the altitude of some ma- terial object. We use light as a symbol of truth, or we say that light resembles truths although there is in reality no resemblance whatever between them in themselves ; but in their results there is a resemblance since the appearance of light and the imparting of truth are both productive of knowledge in the mind. The relation between a symbol and that which is symbolized, between a sign and that which is signified, is usually either a direct resemblance between the two things, or is .accompanied by a resem- blance amongst some of the circumstances or results con- nected with the two things. Sometimes, of course, this is not so, as in the case of the relation of a word to that which is denoted by it, where there is now often no re- semblance, although there is reason to believe that origi- nally the application of names was founded upon resem- blance. The relations of simultaneity and succession between mutually external objects are often the subjects of predica- tion. As when we say: — Milton was a contemporary of Cromwell ; John and James were class-fellows ; soldiers on parade keep step with one another. Or when we say : — • Chaucher preceded Spenser ; after the ffash of lightning a loud peal of thunder was heard ; a cause is always followed by its effect. It will be observed that the same relation of simultaneity or succession may be expressed in many dif- ferent waj^s ; and so far as thought is concerned, it is of no consequence by what words the relation is indicated, pro- vided only it be indicated clearly. It will be observed, too, that the order in which the objects said to be related occur in the predication is immaterial. The sentence, Chaucer preceded Spenser is the same as Spenser followed Chaucer, The predication consists in asserting that a relation of 19 140 THE LOGICAL DOCTRINE OF THE PROPOSITION. succession exists between the two individuals^ specifying which comes first. And, with reference to all the other examples, it will be admitted that the form of predication is unimportant, provided only that it be clearly expressed what objects are related to one another and what is the relation between them. We have hitherto confined ourselves as closely as possible to simple relations of difference, resemblance, simultaneity and succession ; but in the great majority of predications the relations predicated are more or less complex ; and often the relations implied in a predication are more numerous than those which are expressed. We may give examples of such complex relations. The judges in session, having tried the prisoner, agreed to find him guilty. In this complex predication many re- lations are expressed and implied. The judges sit simul- taneously upon the bench, — a double relation of simultaneity (1) amongst the judges (2) between the judges and the bench. Having tried the prisoner, expresses a continuous process and implies a multitude of relations it also indi- /Cates that the action next asserted followed the trial. Agreed lo find him guilty ; here is expressed a relation of agreement amongst the legal opinions of the judges, and a relation of difference between the action of the prisoner and some law. John struck the table. In this short sentence there are implied several relations. John and the table are in point of time simultaneous, in point of space contiguous ; and contiguity is itself the result of the combination of several relations. The stroke of John is an action, and therefore involves succession, viz., first the arm is raised; then it is gradually lowered, occupying successively different posi- tions ; and then it comes into contact with the table pro- ducing, probably, a sensation of sound and certainly one of touch. Thus this simple sentence predicates a complex series of relations between two objects, John and the table. Many other examples might be given of complex rela- THE LOGICAL DOCTRINE OF THE PROPOSITION. 1^1 tious being* predicated between two or more objects ; and it would be a useful exercise in the analysis of thought for the student to examine and separate the relations express- ed or implied in the sentences which he reads. We think it will be found that all relations may ultimately be re- duced to the four simple ones which we have described ; and that all predications may be shown to consist of an assertion or denial^ that one or more of these relations ex- ists between two or more objects or elements of knowledge or conception. We have now given and illustrated what we believe is a correct exposition of that most important act of thought which we call predication. It now remains for us, from the stand'point which we have endeavoured to establish^ to take a view of the current logical doctrines regarding the proposition. These doctrines are found in all the smaller text-books of logic j and they find a place also in many of the more elaborate expositions of logical science. Not, however in all, for we observe decided tendencies towards a departure from the traditional doctrine of the proposition in some modern writers of distinction. The leading fea- tures of the traditional doctrine are the following : — Every proposition consists of two terms and the copula. The terms represent either concepts classes or individual things ; and the copula serves as the connecting link be- tween them. The words which constitute the copula are is and is 7iot, according as the one term is to be affirmed or denied of the other. The first of the two terms, that about which the assertion is made, is called the subject ; the second, that which is asserted or denied of the first, is called the predicate. The subject of universal propositions is said to be distributed, or applied to all the things de- noted by it; that of particular propositions is not. The predicate of negative propositions, being altogether denied of all the individuals denoted by the subject, is distributed ; that of affirmative propositions is not. The copula is sim- ply the sign of the relation of the two terms to one another ; Id 2 14 ^ THE LOGICAL DOCTRINE OF THE PROPOSITION. it must not indicate the actual objective existence of the relation or the things related, nor the time when the rela- tion existed, nor the degree of certainty with which the assertion is made. All these accidental things must be included in the predicate. It is always possible, after limi- tations and changes in the predicate or copula, to convert propositions, that is, to put the predicate in place of the subject, and the subject in place of the predicate ; and this conversion, being rendered necessary by the laws of the syllogism^ is an essential part of the doctrine of the propo- sition. These are the principal points in the doctrine of the proposition regarding which writers upon logic are agreed ; but there are some points about which they are not agreed. They are not agreed as to the character of the predicate, some maintaining that it may be either deno- tative or connotative, others that it is connotative only. Those who believe that it may be denotative are not agreed as to its quantification y some holding that its extent should be explicitly stated in the proposition, others that its quantity should be determined by the ordinary rules. They are not agreed as to the meaning of the predication y some holding that the subject and predicate are simply asserted to be two different names of the same thing ; some that the pre- dicate consists of attributes asserted of the subject; and some that a relation of mutual co-existence or mutual in- clusion or exclusion or congruence or confliction between the two terms is asserted. These differing views may be referred to in the following criticism ; but we shall give the most of our attention to the foregoing doctrines which are generally agreed upon. For the sake of clearness we divide the subject of our criticism into the following parts : — 1, The terms of the proposition ; 2. The relation between these terms as expressed by the copula; 3. The doctrine of distribution ; 4. The doctrine of conversion. (1). In examining the terms of the proposition our principal aim will be to ascertain whether they correspond with the terms of predication, All predications; we have THE LOGICAL LOCTBINE OF THE PROPOSITION. 143 already shown, consist of the assertion or denial that one or more objects or elements of knowledge or conception holds some specified relation to one or more other objects or elements of knowledge or conception. All predications have, therefore, two terms related to one another, and the assertion of some relation existing between them. And we have to enquire whether the terms of the proposition, as described by logicians, are the same as the terms of the predications which we consciously make. In every propo- sition, put into logical form, the predicate must com- prehend all the elements of time, mode and action, which are usually expressed by verbs and adjectives or ad- verbs. A few examples of propositions may form a good basis for our criticism. Horses are vertehrated. In this predication we affirm that each of a class of individual things possesses a certain quality or rather a certain part called a vertebra. Two objects of thought are before consciousness, the image of a horse or horses and that of a vertebra ; and we affirm that the latter constitutes a part of the former. Thus we here assert an internal relation between the two terms ; and this internal relation is correctly expressed by the word are. Neither can there be any doubt that the terms of the proposition correspond to the terms of the conscious predication. But, suppose we modify the proposition, and assert that* horses belo^ig to the class of vertebrata^ it ap- pears manifest that the predication which we make is quite different from the former one. Instead of predicat- ing an internal relation we now predicate an external one; we assert that the class of horses are included in a much larger class of vertebrated animals. In the former propo- sition we do not think of any other animals except horses ; in this proposition we must think of other animals consti- tuting a large class which includes horses. Now the scholastic doctrine of the proposition teaches that the pre- dicate vertebrated is either connotative or denotative, and thus fails to distinguish between the two important kinds 144 THE LOGICAL DOCTRINE OF THE PROPOSITION. of predications above illustrated. This arabig^uity in tlie meaning* of the predicate in such propositions should not be recognised either in psychology or logic ; a predicate ' should mean either one thing or another, and the mode of expressing it should indicate which meaning is intended to be conveyed. Again, the sun illnminates the earth. In this predica- tion we have in thought tv^ro objects which are the terms of the predication, and a certain relation existing between them, namely, that light proceeds from the first to the second and thus makes its surface visible to our eyes. This proposition when put into logical form becomes, the sun is a-hody which-illuminates-the^earth. There the sub- ject is the sun, and the predicate is a-hody-which-ilhmi- nates- the- earth, i. e., the sun again, along with its relation to the earth. Now we think that an appeal to conscious- ness will show clearly that the terms of this proposition, after being put into the logical mould, do not correspond to the terms of the predication which we consciously make. The two objects which we think of as related are, plainly, the sun and the earth, not the sun and a-body-which-illu- minates-the-earth. And it should, therefore, appear that the so-called logical form of this proposition has no founda- tion in the facts of consciousness. Gold is heavier than iron. Here we have the image of two substances before consciousness, and we assert a certain relation between them, namely, that the one substance is heavier than the other. But according to scholastic doctrine, the predi- cate of the proposition is not iron, but heavier~than-iron. In this case also an appeal to consciousness will show that the second term of the predication, said to be in a certain relation to the first, does not correspond to the predicate of the logical proposition. Many other propositions might be adduced which would show that in the majority of cases the terms of the logi- cally-formed proposition do not correspond to the terms of predication which are thought of in consciousness as related THE LOGICAL DOCTRINE OF THE PROPOSITION. 145 to one another. We have seen and admitted that, when a proposition expresses an internal relation of an object or class to some of its constituent parts or elements, the scho- lastic proposition may be correct and adequate. But, when external relations are predicated between objects, the logi- cal proposition is quite inadequate to their expression ; the terms of the proposition do not correspond to the terms of the predicated relation. (2.) We now consider the relation itself predicated be- tween the objects or elements compared. Is this relation accurately expressed by the logical copula ? According to logical doctrine the relations expressed by the copula are those of genus, species, difference, property, and ac- cident ; the predicate of a proposition may stand to the subject in any one of these relations. The two first of these are external relations ; the remaining three are in- ternal. Now it is manifest that these relations have all reference to the process of classification ; and it appears equally manifest that there are a multitude of other rela- tions which form the subjects of predication that have no reference to classification whatever. When we say, for example, lightning precedes thtmder, we do not mean to classify either lightning or thunder with any other pheno- mena whatever, nor have we in our mind any fact or pro- cess involved in classification. We do not mean that the fact of preceding thunder is a differentia or a property or an accident of lightning, or that that fact distinguishes lightning from any other phenomenon. We mean simply to assert that a certain phenomenon, lightning, usually or always, is observed, before another phenomenon, thunder, is heard. And this relation of antecedence or succession is certainly not expressed by the copula. Again, when we say, elephants are quadrupeds^ these words properly express an internal relation between the animals spoken of, and the quality indicated by the predicate, the possession of four feet. But if this proposition is made to mean, ele^ phants belong to the class of four-footed animals^ we have 146 THE LOGICAL DOCTRINE OF THE PROPOSITION. an external relation asserted^ and the copula is not adequate to its nnanabig'uous expression. In the same wav it might he shown that all the other external relations of difference, resemblance, co-existence and succession, and their various combinations, cannot be expressed by the copula. In fact, logicians do not pretend that they can, because they al- ways consign the expression of these relations to the pre- dicate, thus playing false with the phenomena of conscious- ness and producing monstrous forms of language. It ap- pears then, that psychology offers no foundation for the doctrine that the copula is the only proper expression of the relation between the terms of predication ; and it might also be shown that there is no foundation in language. In many languages which are unquestionably expressive of thought there is found no such abstract verb as our is. And, even in our language, the substantive verb requires to be divested of all its meaning before it is fitted for logical use. Thus, it comes to be but an empty symbol, which differs from the symbols of mathematics, in that while each one of them has a definite meaning and represents a rela- tion in thought, it is introduced for the purpose of putting aside the relations thought of which it cannot express. (3.) The doctrine of distribution is manifestly founded upon facts connected with classification. In the classes which we construct of organized individuals there are some qualities which are found in all the individuals denoted by the class-name; there are other qualities, called accidental, found in some individuals but not in others. We are able, then, to predicate that all the individuals of the class possess the former kind of qualities, but only that some of them possess the latter kind of qualities. Again, when we predicate an external relation of certain objects, as when we say “ birds belong to the class of oviparous animals,"’^ it is evident that we speak of all birds, but only of some ovi- parous animals ; and in this case the first term of the pre- dication is distributed, the second not. But if we say birds do not belong to the class of quadrupeds/^ we speak THE LOGICAL DOCTRINE OF THE PROPOSITION. 147 of all birds and all quadrupeds, and assert that the one class is altogether excluded from the other. In this ease both the terms of predication are distributed. Thus, when the first term of the relation denotes a class, we indicate its distribution by prefixing the words all or some. When the second term denotes a class of greater extent than the first, we naturally indicate by the form of the predication whether we speak of all or some of the individuals belong- ing to it ; and at least the accurate expression of thought demands that the distribution of both the terms of the re- lation should be unambiguously expressed. These principles of distribution, properly applicable only to terms which denote classes, are applied by logicians to all kinds of terms and all kinds of propositions. All uni- versal propositions distribute their subject, while particu- lars do not. All negative propositions distribute their predicate, while affirmatives do not. Now, if we had not a particular system to maintain, it might appear plain to us that the principles of distribution cannot be, without absurdity, applied to anything which does not admit of distribution or non distribution. If we say, for example, *^the Duke of Wellington is a man,^^ neither the first nor the second term of the predication is a class name as here used ; and were it not that we import from the process of classification, ideas foreign to the subject in hand, we should never think of the distribution either of the Duke of Wellington^^ or a man.^^ Logicians, however, must reduce every proposition to the normal form, and so they make this a universal affirmation and write it all of the Duke of Wellington is one of the class — man.^^ Again, if we take a proposition expressive of an internal relation, we shall see that the rules of distribution are not applicable. In the proposition roses are sweet- smelling,” the first term of the predication may denote either all or some roses according to our opinion of their odour. But the second term sweet-smelling” expresses a quality pos- essed by roses, and when we speak of a quality, we surely 20 148 THE LOGICAL DOCTKINE OF THE PROPOSITIOIs; mean the whole of the quality, and it seems absurd to say that the name of the quality is either distributed or not distributed ; if we do so we apply a distinction to it which is plainly not applicable. This objection, however, is got over by changing the predicate and thus forming another proposition, thus : — Hoses are sweet-smelling flowers,^'’ meaning “ roses belong to the class of sweet-smelling powers.” But it is surely objectionable, in order to get' a proposition into such a form that the rules of distribution may be applied to it, to change the relation predicated in it. This proposition in its first form asserts an internal relation to the second term of which the principles of distribution do not apply ; and in order to bring it into such a form that the second term may be tested by the laws of distribution, it is changed so as to express an external relation. Surely a correct psychology offers no foundation for such a procedure. It could be easily shown that the laws of distribution are inapplicable to many other kinds of propositions, of which \ve may give the following as examples : — The line A is equal to B ; the sun is brighter than the moon ; the dawn precedes the day ; silver is not so valuable as gold ; the Prince of Wales shot an elephant ; stars bespangle the sky. In all these propositions relations are predicated between two or more objects, the relation being expressed with perfect clearness, and in none of them can we say, with any degree of appropriateness, that either term of'the relation is distributed or non-distributed ; the distinction is inapplicable and foreign to the subject. Our conclusion, founded upon an examination of the meaning of propositions, may be thus stated. Only those terms which denote classes of things can be properly spoken of as being totally or partially distributed ; the names of single qualities or objects should not be quanti- fied ; but wherever a class-name, admitting of quantifica- tion, should, for the sake of clearness have its quantity made knowH; we have a right to insist that its quantity THE LOGICAL DOCTRINE OF THE PROPOSITION. 149 should be explicitly stated. This conclusion is founded upon the great law of expression, — whatever is contained in thought should be accurately expressed in words ; whatever is not contained in though should not be express- ed in words. We do not thinh of the quality affirmed in the predicate of a proposition as being applicable to many or few objects; we should not therefore quantify it. But where the subject or predicate is a class-name, wholly or partially distributed in thought^ its distribution should be expressed in language. (4.) We now come to the doctrine of conversion. For the sake of the transposition of terms required by the syllogism, it is considered by logicians of importance, that all propositions should be convertible ; and there are cer- tain well-known laws laid down for their conversion. The laws of distribution receive their full importance only in connection with conversion ; as the importance of the laws of conversion is seen only in relation to the syllogism. The great law of conversion is, — that no term should be distributed in the converted proposition, which was un- distributed in the original one. And by the application of this law it is found that universal negative and parti- cular negative propositions may be converted without any change of quantity or quality, that the universal affirma- tive can be converted by limiting the quantity of the pre- dicate, and that the particular negative may be simply converted after changing its quality, that is, changing it into a particular affirmative by transferring the sign of negation from the copula to the predicate. Now, if we examine predications as they are naturally expressed, there does not seem to be any objection to the order of the term being changed provided there is a suffi- cient reason for the change. If we say whales are in- cluded in the class mammals,^^ we mean the same as the class mammals includes whales.-’^ If we say ^Hhunder succeeds lightning,^^ we are understood no better than if we say lightning precedes thunder.^^ The predication gold 20 2 150 THE LOGICAL DOCTRINE OF THE PROPOSITION. is heavier than silver,” expresses the same relations as silver is lighter than gold.” The sentence “ John strikes the table,” is, as far as thought is concerned, exactly the same as the table is struck by John.” In short, if we express any relation in a predication, the laws of thought and language require nothing more than clearness and ac- curacy in the expression ; and it is a matter of indifference which term of the relation comes first. But, if we examine the conversions of logically formed propositions 3 we cannot so easily admit their legitimacy. The proposition roses are red,” becomes, in the hands of logicians, when converted, some red things are roses.” The simple sentence thunder succeeds lightning” is me- tamorphosed into a* class of things succeeding lightning is thunder.” The monstrous forms of language which re- quire to he introduced for the purpose or converting the majority of logically moulded propositions appear to afford a strong reason for doubting the legitimacy of the process. But, as we have seen, the principal objection does not lie against transposing the terms of a predication, but rather against the changes to which naturally expressed predica- tions must be subjected, in order to bring them into the so-called logical form. Having examined the principal features of the scholastic doctrine of the proposition, we may sum up our results. Propositions concerned about classification, are wrongly taken to he the type of all propositions ; and all other kinds of propositions are forced into the form naturally assumed by them. The terms of the logical proposition do not, in the majority of cases, correspond with the objects whose relation is predicated in thought. The copula is incapable of expressing the most of relations, and consequently the words expressive of relations are usually relegated to the predicate, this being inconsistent with the facts of thought. The laws of distribution, founded upon facts of classifica- tion, are applied where there is no reference to classifica- tion, and where they are consequently inapplicable. And THE LOGICAL DOCTRINE OF THE PROPOSITION. 151 finally the simple process of changing the order of the terms of a relation, when applied to the terms of a propo- sition forced into the logical form, produces results quite opposed to the facts of thought and the forms of language. In the preceding exposition and criticism, we have taken our stand upon the position that the psychologist and the logician ought to occupy themselves with the analysis and study of thought rather than of expression. The scholastic logicians concerned themselves too much with words, mere words \ hence the word quibbling, the logomachies of me- diaeval times. We have inherited their logical system and still teach it in our colleges ; and a useless system it is, interesting chiefly as a specimen of the ingenuity of men, who had nothing better to do than to'invent puzzles. We hope that the time may soon come when a logic will be generally taught which will attempt to be a real and ac- curate analysis of thought worthy of the study of men, who wish to understand the working of their own minds in its higher operations, and who desire a method by which their practical researches after truth may be systematically guided. NOTE H. IMPLIED PREDICATIONS. There is such a connection and complication between truths that, generally speaking, when we know and ex- press one truth there are many other truths implicitly known and ready to be expressed. In the predications which we make regarding the objects of our knowledge we give prominence to some particular feature which it suits our purpose to express, but there may be many other rela- tions connected with the same objects which we know, which we imply in our predications, but which we do not care to state explicitly. Almost every explicit predication 152 IMPLIED PREDICATIONS. is connected with other implicit predications ; in beini» distinctly conscious of the former we know the latter also, although they may not be so distinctly before conscious- ness. The explicit predication stands out clearly from amidst the surrounding implicit ones, but they are in the immediate neighbourhood and simply require the atten- tion to be directed to them in order to make them as dis- tinct as that which we have chosen to express. And it is frequently as important to know what is implied in our predications as to have a clear apprehension of what we distinctly state. A few illustrations will bring the subject more clearly before us. When we make 'the general predication. — All men are mortal, we have in our mind the class of men as a whole wherever they are to be found, and we predicate regarding them that they are, without exception, liable to death. But in the very act of making this assertion there is in- volved the knowledge or belief that some particular men will die. In asserting a universal predication we imply its truth with reference to any particular number. The same kind of implication is involved of course in negative predications. The Law of Contradiction is the expression of another fact regarding the relations of predications. An explicit predication not only implies other predication, but may also exclude other predications. The proposition above referred to excludes the corresponding negative. — All men, or some men, are not mortal. And in the same way the predication of a universal or particular negative excludes the corresponding affirmatives. To know what a particular predication implies and what it excludes is the most im- portant condition of consistency in our knowledge. An important class of implicit predications is involved in the predication of the internal relations of an object or class of objects and its constituent qualities. Whenever we predicate a quality of any object we thereby implicitly classify that object with others possessing the same quality. IMPLIED PREDICATIONS. 165 When we say for example that birds are oviparous we do not say anything* about other oviparous things and we do not even mean anything about them, but if we examine the thoughts which cluster about the explicit predication We shall find amongst them that birds may be classified with other oviparous beings, if such exist. Were we to examine all other cases of internal predication we should find that each of them implies an external predication ; whenever we predicate a quality of any object or class of objects we implicitly predicate that that object or class of objects may be included in a larger class p-ll of whose members are marked by the possession of that quality. This implied predication has also its corresponding exclude ed predication. If we can assert that objects, in conse- quence of possessing a certain quality, may be classified with all other objects possessing the same quality, we are precluded from making this predication with reference to objects which do not possess the quality. And, generally speaking, where two predications are inconsistent with one another, if the one is either explicitly stated or im- plied the other is thereby excluded. For the sake of illustration we offer the following ex- amples of explicit, implied, and excluded predications : — EXPLICIT Predication. All fishes oxL dize their blood from water. All planets move in elliptic orbits. IMPLIED Predications. Some fishes, or these fishes, oxidize &c. Fishes belong to the class of animals oxidizing &c. Any particular planet moves in an elliptic orbit. The class of bodies moving in elliptic orbits comprehends planets. EXCLUDED Predications. No fishes oxidize &c. Animals which do not oxi- dize &e. are fishes. All or some planets move in an orbit not elliptic. Bodies moving in a pa- rabolic or other non-ellip- tic orbit are planets. Whales belong to the class mam- mats. Some mammals are whales. Some of the qualities pos*- sessed by all mammals are possessed by whales. N o mammals are whales. Mammals possess no qualities in common with whales. Alfred Tenny- son is a poet. Alfred Tennyson possesses Alfred Tennyson is the genius and other qualities wanting in poetical genh which constitute a poet. ' us, 154 IMPLIED PIIEDICATIONS. EXPLICIT Predication. The angles of a plane triangle are either equal to two right an- gles or unequal. IMPLIED Predications. If they are equal to two I right angles they cannot be unequal, and vice versd. John Smith is a drunkard. J ohn Smith cannot control his appetite for strong drink. The line A is double of B. The line B is half of A . The sun illumi* The sun is luminous. The nates the earth. sun and earth are so related in space that light from the former can fall upon the lat- ter. EXCLUDED Predications. They may be both equal and unequal. John Smith can choose either to drink or not to dring strong liquor when he pleases. The lines A and B are equal. The line B is greater than half of A. The sun is neither a self- luminous nor a light-re- flecting body. The earth is so situated that rays of light from the sun cannot fall upon it. Having illustrated the relations between explicit and implied and excluded predications we may sum up our re- sults in the following canons 1. Whatever relation is predicated of a class of objects may be predicated of any individuals belonging to the class ; the denial of this relation with reference to any or all of these individuals is excluded. 2. The predication of an internal relation of any class of objects implies an external relation, viz. that these ob- jects belong to a larger class of things possessing the qua- lity predicated. The denial of this and the assertion that objects not possessing the quality belong to the class are excluded. 3. The predication that an individual belongs to a class implies the possession of the qualities constituting the class. The contrary is excluded. 4. The predication of any external relation between two or more objects implies the existence of all the condi- tions which renders that relation possible. The denial of these conditions is excluded. 5. Generally, the predication of any relation excludes the predication of all other relations which are inconsistent IMPLIED PREDICATIONS. 155 witli it, and implies the predication of all relations which are its necessary conditions or consequences. Notwithstanding the fact that these principles regulat- ing the implication and exclusion of predications are clear and certain, there are actually found many inconsistencies and inaccuracies amongst the thoughts of men. Predica- tions are frequently thought to be implied which are not really implied, and thought to be exclude which are not really inconsistent with admitted truth. And it is the great duty of the instructors of mankind to spread abroad accurate and consistent knowledge, that is, knowledge in which established principles and facts are accompanied by everything implied in them and from which all inconsis- tent opinions are excluded. We may refer, by way of illus- tration, to -some mistakes which are frequently made or have been made in determining the implication or exclu- sion of predications. In judging of the national characteristics of foreign peoples, striking features are often erroneously supposed to be universal, and false judgments are consequently pro- nounced in particular cases. Englishmen are of the opi- nion that the Germans are a musical people, and it might be supposed that every particular German is a musician either actually or potentially. But such would be doubt- less a mistake. Europeans are of opinion that Bengalis are an untruthful people, and many of them in Bengal act upon the belief that the word of no Bengali is to be trusted. This is un- questionably an error. Bengalis on the other hand are of opinion that Englishmen are harsh and overbearing, and frequently apply this judgment indiscriminately. This is equally erroneous. Defenders of the Jewish and Christian Scriptures main- tain their accuracy and truth, and many of them think that it is implied that every statement must be accepted as li terally true, and they will not admit any hostile criticism 21 156 IMPLIED PREDICATIONS. •which results in disclosing- any inaccuracies or inconsis- tencies. Believing that the Scriptures are true they thinli that if anything in them is shown to be inaccurate there is nothing worth preserving. They do not see that the presence of most important religious truth in the Scriptures is quite consistent with the presence of many scientific and historical inaccuracies and many inconsistencies amongst details. Consequently when they learn that inaccuracies or inconsistencies have been pointed out they fear that the citadel of their faith has been taken and that they can have no confidence in any religious truth whatever. The same foolish position is frequently assumed by the enemies of Christianity. Some of them appear to think that, if they have shown statements in the Scriptures to be scientifical- ly or historically inaccurate or mutually inconsistent, they have demonstrated the falsity of Christianity, whereas in reality they have not approached the foundations of the Christian faith in their attacks. Similarly, in former times, it was usual for the followers of rival creeds to attack with virulence subordinate details in the religious systems or Scriptures of their antagonists, thinking that by so doing they were aiding their over- throw. And generally speaking sectarians are those who are unable to see that there may be possessed great and important religious truth quite consistently along with many minor points of form or doctrine which they cannot agree with. In philosophical doctrines there may often be an ap- pearance of inconsistence between two predications when in reality they are quite consistent. For example Mr. J. S. Mill has endeavoured to show that Sir W. Hamilton’s Doctrine of the Relativity of Knowledge is inconsistent with his Doctrine of Immediate Perception. In the former doctrine Hamilton maintains that we do not know things- in-themselves ; in the latter doctrine, that we have an immediate knowledge of real things. Mr, Mill assumes IMPLIED PREDICATIONS. 157 that the thinors spoken of in the former doctrine are the same as the things said to be known in the latter, and upon that assumption rig*ht]y concludes that the one statement is inconsistent with the other. Now it appears to us that a careful examination of Hamilton's writings will show that Mr. Mill is incorrect in his criticism, and that Ha- milton in the two doctrines is speaking of two quite dif- ferent things in the Doctrine of the Relativity of Know- ledge he teaches that the cause or substratum which under, lies the objects of our senses is unknown ; in the Doctrine of Immediate Perception he teaches that the objects of our senses are directly known ; and between these statements there is certainly no inconsistency. Again, there are many in the world who believe that God^s will is sovereign, or that all events in their lives are controlled by Fate ; and frequently they think that this implies that their own efforts in adverse circumstances are unavailing. They cannot reconcile the sovereignty of God with the importance of exercising all their own power and wisdom at all times as if they were sovereigns of their own lives. In consequence of permitting the idea of an over-ruling sovereignty to fill their minds to the exclusion of the idea of their own personal responsibility, when temptation or adverse circumstances come upon them they 5ield without an effort and prove how helpless and worth- less man is if he have not a lively sense of his own dignity and responsibility. Sophistical reasoners in their attempts to mislead the people usually etideavour to show that opposing statements are quite consistent or that really consistent statements are incongruous. And generally speaking it is of the greatest importance for seekers after truth to watch care- fully appearances of consistency and appearances of incon- gruity ; falsehood frequently comes .veiled under the one and truth is frequently concealed by the other. Doctrines apparently conflicting may frequently be comprehended 21 2 158 IMPLIED PREDICATIONS. harmoniously under a higher truth ; and doctrines joined together in some human system may be as inconsistent as light and darkness. NOTE I. A PRIORI REGULATIVE PRINCIPLES. That there are a priori principles which regulate our intel- lectual activity is admitted by all psychologists. We say all psychologists, because even the most extreme advocates of the experiential school must and do admit that the charac- ter of our knowledge and our thought depends, at least to some extent, upon the constitution of the nature with which we are born into the world. And in so far as the nature which we inherit from our parents determines our experience in so far we are under the government of a priori principles. There are some who hold that our men- tal experience depends upon the character of the physical organism with w^hich we are born. Even in this case our mental activity is governed by a priori laws. It is main- tained also that the physical organism which we inherit is itself the result of the indefinite past experience of our ancestors ; but manifestly the past experience of our ances- tors at every stage must have been regulated by something a priori, something in the condition of things immediately preceding. So that, even upon this theory, all past ex- perience must have been under the government of a priori principles, and the accumulated results of that experience admittedly involve the a priori principles which govern present experience. Whether therefore the a priori prin- ciples which regulate our mental activity are established in connection with our physical organism or our mental na- ture it must necessarily be admitted that there are such A PRIORI REGULATIVE PRINCIPLES. 159 a priori principles, both in tbe present condition of human nature, and at every past stai^e of prog'ress by which human and inferior races have advanced. We shall therefore assume the existence of a priori reg’ulative prin- ciples as indisputable, and proceed to discuss the account which Hamilton gives of them. After dividing necessity or necessary principles into two kinds — Positive and Negative, — and briefly describing the former, Hamilton proceeds to the exposition of the doctrine, peculiar to himself, of Negative necessity. This doctrine he denominates the Law of the Conditioned, which he enun- ciates in the following terms : — All that is conceivable in thought lies between two inconceivable extremes which, as contradictory of each other, cannot both be true, but of which, as mutual contradictories, one must.^^ The two inconceivable extremes are called respectively the Abso- lutely Unconditioned or the Absolute, and the Infinitely Unconditioned or the Infinite, and the conceivable middle sphere is called the Conditioned. Thus the Conditioned is the mean between two exclusive extremes neither of which can be conceived as possible, but of which on the principles of Contradiction and Excluded Middle, one must be ad- mitted as neccessary. This Law of the Conditioned is illustrated by being applied to Space and Time. Space must be either Absolutely Limited or Infinitelv Unlimit- ed ; upon the principle of Excluded Middle space can have no intermediate predicate applied to it ; but it is im- possible for us to think of "pace as either Absolutely Limited or Infinitely Unlimited, — we can think of Space only as Conditioned or Conditionally Limited. Such is Hamilton's famous Law of the Conditioned. Without entering into an exhaustive examination of this Law we offer the following critical remarks : — 1. One of the inconceivable extremes, — the Absolutely Limited — appears to involve contradictory elements. That which is limited cannot be absolute in any sense of that 160 A PRIORI REGULATIVE PRINCIPLES. term. The idea of limitation necessarily implies two things — something’ which is limited and something which limits — and these two things are mutually relative. The ideas of the Absolute and the Limited are mutually incon- sistent. On the other hand the ideas of the Infinite and the Unlimited are not inconsistent, and there is no difficul- ty in conceiving the Infinite except that which arises from the weakness of the human mind. Again, when we apply this Law to space, for example, the two extremes do not present the same difficulty. Absolute space, that is space absolutely limited is inconceivable, not from the weakness of OUT minds hut because the attributing of a limit to space is inconsistent with our idea of ivhat space is. Infinite space is inconceivable from the weakness of our minds. Thus we see that the two apparently contradictory extremes do not arise naturally in our thoughts ; they have an appearance of being manufactured for the purpose of satisfying the re- quirements of the Law, and one of them is inconceivable because it is so constructed by its author as to be incon- ceivable. 2. What is the meaning of saying that all that is conceivable lies between two inconceivable extremes?’^ Ac- cording to the conditions of the case there is no middle sphere between the two contradictory extremes , all that is between them is excluded by the well-known Law of Excluded Middle; how then can thought be concerned about that which, by one of the necessary Laws of Thought, cannot be thought about ? Thus the Law of the Condi- tioned appears to be inconsistent with the Law of Excluded Middle ; both of them are Laws governing our thoughts ; and that which is made the sole object of our thought by the former is absolutely excluded by the latter. 3. The object which Hamilton had in view in institut- ing this Law— the limitation of thought to its proper sphere — may be equally well accomplished by an appeal to the universally recognised conditions of thought. All A PRIORI REGULATIVE PRINCIPLES. 161 human thought is concerned about phenomena under the relations of Difference, Kesemhlance, Simultaneity and Succession and is governed by the great Laws of Identity, Contradiction, and Excluded Middle j or if thought endea- vours to reach beyond phenomena, the nou-phenomenal objects must be draped in phenomenal clothing. These restrictions imposed upon thought, if observed, are quite sufficient to keep us from the transcendental metaphysics against which Hamilton directed his Law of the Condition. Tiia END. Printed by B. M. Sen, “ Tomohur” Press, Serampore. , . •' -X^ *v' ■; , ' ' ■j:,.v.;..:'Jll^r. ' A- h f '•'f- ' 'J?'' '’ ::m ' ... .. ■^^^. ’■ '■• . ■■t -: • ‘i 5SS: r... ^-Vi. ■?•«■: • «-= ’ ... .. . i', .A';**-- V. :V: v'-- /i*’i'.' A . * ^A.’- •4. .?■■*■ •• ■' . ' 'x P \ ' 4 ' y S i „4 V sj; i>- rV- i- / (