MASTER
NEGA TIVE
NO. 92-80711
MICROFILMED 1993
COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY LIBRARIES/NEW YORK
as part of the
"Foundations of Western Civilization Preservation Project"
Funded by the
NATIONAL ENDOWMENT FOR THE HUMANITIES
Reproductions may not be made without permission from
Columbia University Library
COPYRIGHT STATEMENT
The copyright law of the United States - Title 17, United
States Code - concerns the making of photocopies or
other reproductions of copyrighted material.
Under certain conditions specified In the law, libraries and
archives are authorized to furnish a photocopy or other
reproduction. One of these specified conditions is that the
photocopy or other reproduction is not to be "used for any
purpose other than private study, scholarship, or
research." If a user makes a request for, or later uses, a
photocopy or reproduction for purposes in excess of "fair
use," that user may be liable for copyright infringement.
This institution reserves the right to refuse to accept a
copy order if, in its judgement, fulfillment of the order
would involve violation of the copyright law.
AUTHOR:
CHRETIEN, CHARLES
TITLE:
ESSAY ON LOGICAL
METHOD
PL A CE :
OXFORD
DA TE :
1848
COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY LIBRARIES
PRESERVATION DEPARTMENT
BIBLIOGRAPHIC MICROFORM TARGET
Master Negative #
Restrictions on Use:
Original Material as Filmed - Existing Bibliographic Record
C<^Q) I 'fssBv on looical ma+hod'
n^
as.
Oxford IS<^S.
'/
. 11. 7 J '
0. l+.U + £20p.
753.97
TECHNICAL MICROFORM DATA
FILM SIZE: jr REDUCTION RATIO: JiJi.
IMAGE PLACEMENT: lA ^ IB IIB
DATE FILMED: _^_^^il'^^ INITIALS , •J^'T^^^
HLMEDBY: RESEARCffpi^BLICATIONS. INC WOODBRIDGE. CT
»^i
7#*yv
~-iJ-' >i> I > 6»4r'«' /'V^I•
mu
v*^ Y'
i^;..
\Q.O^
C^£
in tijc (Citit of |lciu l}ox*h»
^jjffial fxwul
OVixtn auoutfmou$lu.
•*
AN ESSAY
ON
LOGICAL METHOD.
BY
CHARLES P. CHRETIEN, M.A
FELLOW AND TUTOR OF ORIEL COLLEGE.
OXFORD,
JOHN HENRY PARKER;
AND 377, STRAND, LONDON.
1848.
1^0
c4t
BAXTEU, PKiNTER, OXFORD.
^
O
TO THOSE
FROM WHOM THE AUTHOR HAS LEARNED MUCH
WHEN HE SEEMED TO BE
TEACHING
CO
-:
. vt
— /
180183
PREFACE.
In the following pages I have endeavoured to
consult principally the wants of those, whose taste
for Logic has carried them beyond its simpler
technicalities. Such persons will naturally desire to
learn how it may be useful in practice. Havincr
studied the nature of its machinery, they will gladly
see it in operation.
It is almost beyond my hope that what I have
written may also be of service to some, whose distaste
for Logic amounts to a prejudice. Ordinary rea-
soning can scarcely remove the irrational opinion,
that the legitimate study of the way to knowledge
acts mainly as an encouragement to ignorance.
That the few examples I have employed are
intentionally popular, will hardly be considered a
defect by those who know how apt an abstruse
illustration is to rival, if not to surpass, its subject
in obscurity.
VI
PREFACE.
The very simple division of Sciences wliich I have
adopted will excite a smile in some who have
approached the same subject from another quarter.
But it is perfectly defensible, if the principles of
this work be in other respects true. Without
being the best or the only scheme, it may yet be
valid and Logical.
To confess myself conscious of many faults in
this Essay, is a poor apology for leaving them un-
corrected. They would have been more numerous,
but for a reason which I have great pleasure in
being permitted to mention. Both the Essay and
its Author are under more obligations than can be
particularised, to his dear friends and brother-fellows,
the Reverend George Buckle, and Mr. John
William Burgon.
Oriel,
June 17, 1848.
CONTENTS.
INTRODUCTION [
CHAP. I. THE ANCIENT VIEW OF THE RELATION OF
LOGIC TO SCIENCE. ....... 13
II. THE MEDLEVAL VIEW OF THE RELATION OF
LOGIC TO SCIENCE QQ
III. NOMINALISM AND REALISM 52
IV. THE MODERN VIEW OF THE RELATION OF
LOGIC TO SCIENCE 79
V. ON THE DIFFERENT MODERN SCHOOLS OF
I^OGIC 94
VL ON LOGICAL METHOD IN GENERAI 1-28
VII. ON THE METHOD OF SCIENCE \S2
Vni. ON SCIENTIFIC IDEAS 138
IX, ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. . . 150
X. ON THE GRADATIONS OF SCIENCE. ... 177
XI. ON METHOD IN ART 1^8
XII. ON METHOD IN MORALITV I90
Xni. ON ANALYSIS AND SYNTHESIS 197
XIV. ON THE CONNECTION OF METHOD WITH
FORMAL LOGIC t>IO
CONCLISION i>|(5
INTRODUCTION.
The student of Logic, who takes in hand any
of the old compendia which still survive in partial
use among us, will observe, that, towards their con-
clusion, they all engage upon one common subject,
which is, as they differently phrase it. Method, or
the use of Logic. To this, all that has preceded
is meant to minister. It impHes the earlier parts
of Logic, as a building imphes the foundation. Its
existence assumes that Apprehension, and Judg-
ment, and Discourse, have made some considerable
progress, and accumulated a sufficient body of
knowledge to require methodical disposition. Thus
syllogism is considered as the unit, or, so to speak,
the atom of reasoning ; and with its combinations
method is concerned. To stop short at the con-
sideration of this most concise and simple form of
argument, without dwelHng on its methodical
arrangement, would be to neglect that application
of it, which mainly renders it worth consideration
at all.
Yet to this part of the subject incipient logicians
still want a guide. The able treatise of Archbishop
Whately terminates, for this purpose, just too
early. He teaches the recruits how each dialectical
B
2 INTRODUCTION.
weapon may be wielded to advantage ; not how
the whole armoury may be employed in concert
with good effect.
And without any disparagement to later labourers
in this field, it may be said, that such other
guides to the knowledge of method as are not
palpably superficial, start from first premises too
unlike those which we semi-scholastics of Oxford
still retain to be naturally adopted as instructors
in our school. Instead of extending the old line
of enquiry, they turn to one which is altogether
new, and, where we are expecting explanation,
give us contrast. Or their turn is physical rather
than logical : they insist more on the facts which
method embodies, than on the formal process of
their embodiment.
It would be wide of our purpose to discuss any
schemes of method, which are built on other than
a logical groundwork. However true and ex-
cellent they may be. Logic is not the porch through
which to approach them. And yet it is most
unlikely that no entrance lies to method through
this vestibule. When we owe to the schoolmen and
their successors so much of our scientific phrase-
ology, so many of the terms which hang loose
between exact and popular usage, and serve to
bridge over (for good or for evil, as the causeway
so formed is employed) the gap which separates
sciolism and science ; when we take so commonly
as our material the frasjiuents of their mosaic-work.
INTRODUCTION.
it seems unnatural and unwise, not to say ungrate-
ful, to pay no attention to the plan according to
which they arranged them. Doubtless they were
fitted for their original use ; and we may learn
much from considering the nature of this use,
although we may not think proper to adopt it.
Possibly, then, the domain of logical speculation
is not so fully occupied, as to leave no room for
the following Essay. Our object is, to view Logic
at once by the light of the past and the present ;
to enquire, in the first place, what ideas respecting
its nature were formerly entertained, and what
questions originated fi'om their adoption : how one
race of thinkers profited both by the knowledge
and the mistakes of those preceding them, and
handed down the results of their labours to their
successors, not without a still abiding mixture of
error; — and, this done, to show, how truths ad-
vancing fi'om different quarters meet at last, and
unite peaceably, where we might have feared a
collision ; how, as Logic has always of her own
free will testified to the truth of Science, Science
in her turn bears unintentional but not involuntary
witness to the truth and utility of Logic.
The former part of this Essay, therefore, is
mainly historical; the latter regards rather the
present state of knowledge, and aims at illustrating
the close connection between logical and scientific
method. The general fact of their connection
one consideration alone would serve to establish.
b2
INTRODUCTION.
It cannot be by a mere accidental coincidence that
Logic and Science both point to a deductive system
as the perfect type of metliod. This they do on
grounds perfectly distinct. The logician asserts
the supremacy of Deduction, because it exhibits
most naturally the powers of his favourite instru-
ment, the syllogism ; because it assigns with the
greatest definiteness and precision to the pro-
position and the term their respective places and
importance. The man of science also takes Deduc-
tion as the type of excellence, because he finds that,
as matter of fact, the deductive sciences are the most
perfect. It would not at first strike the logician
that Mathematics exhibited the full power of the
syllogism, or the mathematician, that his pursuits
illustrated the chief exercise of Logic. But a little
thought shows either party that there is a real
conformity, not only in the results, but in the
process by which they attain them. Each is
attracted by the same feature in a deductive system,
that is, as we shall see hereafter, the perfect
manner in w^iich it unites in itself subordination
and consequentiality.
Where then there is on the whole such general
agreement, we should expect to find it pervading
the details also. Here, however, it does not at
first appear. Science says little of universals and
particulars, of distribution and non-distribution, of
judgment and discourse. While on the peculiar
features and arrangements of each particular
INTRODUCTION.
science Logic is of course equally silent. But, on
reflection, another class of terms occur, which
Logic and Science use in common. Such are,
conception and idea, genus and species, analysis
and synthesis. The vague use of words like these
is an evil wliich we ought not unnecessarily to
tolerate. Metaphorical in some sense they must
be ; but the nature and extent of the metaphor
deserves to be considered. And the further ques-
tion naturally arises, not only from what they have
been transferred, but to whom. Their use in-
differently by logicians and men of science suggests
the supposition, that Science has taken them
improperly from Logic, or Logic from Science. But
it is satisfactory to discover, that some knowledge
of the nature of method renders either hypothesis
unnecessary ; that it is with regard to method that
the terms have gained their meaning, and pre-
serving that meaning, are derived, with equal
propriety, to Science on the one hand, and Logic
on the other.
The idea of method, indeed, is prior to that of
either Science or Logic. It is simpler, w^here they
are more complex. It enters into every thing
which admits of arrangement and order. There
is method in placing in a row a number of mine-
ralogical specimens according to their external
resemblance : though this is not a science. There
is method in grouping together a number of apho-
risms, or proverbs, or practical maxims, which refer
-'JlS-.-JBSBW ..r)a\ trpdrov pr)TopiKr)v K€KivT)K€vaL. ^s
avTiCTTpoc^ov flvai Trjv 8ia\€KTiKT)v, rovTfVrti/, laoirrpotpov, hia to nepl
Trfv avTTjv vXrjv . 416. Ovkow fVl tovtois dpKov^€Pois Kara-
ttava-TioVj s ei/t /zoXtora, Koi ra np6s rSav v
€7rip ndpvos
fitpovs p Koi iiaip€T]K€P, h6(P Ka\ 6 TipKpdrqp TroXXotf paBr]p.acnp.
*• Metaphys. xii. 4. Avo ydp iaTip, d tis dp dnodtor, 2coKpdT,i
SiKaitos, ToCs T enaKTiKoi/s Xoyov^y Kal to dpi(((T6ai Ka6oKov.
• See Dioi(. Laert. Prooein. Segm. 18.
c2
20
THK ANCIENT VIEW ol THE
RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE.
21
division, yet in practice adopts it ^ Epicurus
recognised it also, though he gave to the logical
section the name of '' canonic ^" The Stoics
accepted it without any such alteration of termi-
nology. So generally admitted was it, that it was
forced in some sense, by popular opinion, on those
who would not otherwise acknowledge it. Sects,
which denied its validity, or were ignorant of its
existence, were tried by its standard. Thus we
are informed, (of which more hereafter) that the
Cynics confined their attention to Ethic, and
neglected Physic and Logic'.
It is to our purpose to see, what prominence,
what place and office, the different schools assigned
to the logical limb of this division. A few pre-
paratory remarks will enable us the better to see
the real nature of the question on which they
' Top. i. 12. §. 5.
8 Diog. Laert. lib. x. Seg. 29, 30.
*" Diog. Laert. vii. 40.
' Diog. Lat'if. vi. 103. Far more out of place, and for that
very reason mon* strikingly illustraiive of the prevalence of this
division, is the statement of Philo Judiuus, (Quod omnis probus
liber) that the Essenes cultivated Ethic to the exclusion of Logic
and far the greater portion of Physic. It is startling to find
8t. Jerome applying it to Holy Scripture in the following passage.
" Quomodo Philosophi solent disputationes suas in Physicam,
Ethicam, Logicamquo partiri, ita et eloquia divina aut de natura
disputare, ut in Genesi et in Ecclesiaste : aut de moribus, ut in
Proverbiis et in omnibus sparsim libris : aut de Logica, pro qua
nostri theoricen sibi vindicant, ut in Cantico Canticorum, et
Evangeliis." Epist. ad Paulimi Urbicum de interpretatione Al-
phabeii Hebraici, ad init.
parted company, and the reasons which rendered
it incapable of a satisfactory solution.
The ancients used the term Logic in a much
wider sense than we do. As physical Philosophy
included all the phenomena of the outward world,
and, if we can allow a soul to brutes, those of the
"irrational soul" also; as Ethic considered all
questions of directly practical import, so the whole
world of mind came under Logic. It dealt with
mental laws, whether these laws were considered
as the means of investigation, or its object. If
the application of reasoning could solve a ques-
tion without appeal to observation or experiment,
its solution belonged to this branch of Philosophy.
If the nature of the rational soul was considered.
Logic claimed it as its province. If a system of
rules was to be constructed, fitted to aid in the
ordinary investigation of truth, here too Logic was
at home.
The word then was taken in too broad a sense
to be distinct in its meaning. Metaphysic, or the
science of thought as belonging to the rational
soul, in the first place fell within it. Then it
included Logic proper, or the system of rules for
reasoning grounded on the laws of thought. Lastly,
it included Logic applied — the concrete of these
rules, and the matter of any particular question
which they enabled the enquirer to determine.
The clear mind of Aristotle did not fail to
discern this equivocation. He saw the difference
oo
THE ANCIUNT VIKW OF THE
between the metaphysical truths on which the
rules of reasoning are grounded, and the rules of
reasoning themselves. His usage of language on
this point is not however that to which we are now
accustomed. Logic is with him the more general
term; Analytic, the more restricted**. Our Logic
corresponds to the latter rather than to the former.
Thus, on the one liand, he calls it a logical ques-
tion, whether there be one science of contraries,
or not; on the other hand, he describes Rhetoric,
which we should characterize as the union ' of the
science of human nature, and Logic, as a com-
bination of PoHtic and Analytic"". The opposition
therefore between logical and analytical, in his
mind, would answer to that between metaphysical
and logical, in ours. There is of course nothing
implied in this antithesis, which could hinder him
from viewing Logic generical, including Analytic
and much more, as one great section of Philosophy,
in contrast both with Ethic and Physic.
Plato, on the other hand, it is well known,
courted of set purpose the fusion of these two
ideas — of the law, and the rule, of thought; of the
basis on which Logic is built, and the logical
building itself. Though a variety of authorities
attribute to him the threefold division of Philosophy,
he does not himself explicitly state it. And Dia-
lectic, rather than Logic, is the name by which he
' Ton. I
^ Posi. Anal. I. xxii. 21,2.
"* Rhet. I. iv.
xii. f).
I
RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE.
23
distinguishes the third number of the division. We
know too, that his making those universals, which
were generally regarded as the creatures of Logic,
real existences, and identifying them with his
ideas, led him to include under one name the
formal and the real science °. His Dialectic was
not a mere intellectual discipline, or a bare organon
of truth, but a summary of the highest, and, in
some sense, the only real knowledge.
It will be seen, then, that these two great
authorities, however much they differ on other
points, agree in one. They both exalt Logic
above Physic and Ethic. Plato's reason was
obvious : Dialectic was the one great science to
which, in his opinion, other sciences owed not
only their apparatus, but their very aim and
purpose. And Aristotle, taking, as we have seen.
Logic in its broadest sense, made it include far too
much, to be at all tempted to vmderrate it.
The two great schools which succeeded in Greek
philosophy assigned Logic a far low^er importance.
The Canonic of the Epicureans was restricted
within very narrow bounds, and sometimes con-
fused with their Physic**. And the Stoics, who
also subordinated it to Physic, introduced also
Rhetoric and other extraneous matters into the
province which it seemed of itself no longer equal
to Hll P.
" Metaplivs. xii. 4.
** Dioj;. Larrt. vii. 41.
" Diog. Laert. x. 30.
24
THE ANCIENT VIEW OF THE
But, as two schools of Philosophy arose before
Logic had its origin, so also two, which were
almost contemporaneous with its most flourishing
days, shut their eyes and refused to acknowledge
it. One of these was that of the Cynics. We
have seen above'', that the rejection of Logic was
formerly laid to their charge. The accusation
which is so directly made might have been inferred
from their known opinions. Antisthenes and his
disciples denied the possibility of definition ' and
of contradiction ^ The one position is incon-
sistent with a behef in the accuracy of knowledge ;
the other even denies that it is attainable. For,
if there be no contradiction, there can be no
antithesis between truth and falsehood; if there
be no definition, truth may exist indeed, but with
such indistinctness and uncertainty of outline as
to defy a sure recognition. Li each opinion the
same tone of mind appears. To regard Truth as
something which the mind cannot really grasp, is
a long stage on the road towards disbelieving its
existence.
The Cynics indeed seem to have been a pitiable
sect of philosophers — pitiable too, perhaps, in the
sense of deserving our pity. First of all, they turned
their thoughts to virtue, which they thought both
attainable and necessary. On the ethical branch of
Philosophy they therefore cast no slight. But this
absorbed their wliole attention. On the cold un-
'i r 20.
' Mcl;i|)hys. vii. 3.
' Top. I. ix. f).
RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE.
25
impassioned covmtenance of their ideal Virtue they
fixed their eyes, and forgot all besides. The laws
of the souls, and the phenomena of nature, they
alike despised. Beyond Virtue, all seemed un-
certain ; the sophists had overthrown their faith
in human knowledge, and Heraclitus had sapped
their trust in the outer world. Plato invented his
theory of ideas, that, by reposing all that was
precious upon them, he might preserve the con-
fidence of men both in knowledge and goodness.
The Cynics thought that their doctrine of im-
passibility saved Virtue from the general crash, and
calmly allowed the sea of doubt to sweep all else
away.
Very unlike paths lead different men to the same
conclusions. The Cyrenaics also were said to
resolve all Philosophy into Ethic'. Aristotle him-
self" tells us of the contempt with which Aristippus
regarded Mathematics as teaching us nothing of
the good and the beautiful. Morals were at any
rate the principal study of the Cyrenaics, whether
they entirely neglected the other branches of Philo-
sophy, or, as is more likely from their treatises on
" causes" and " proofs," only placed them in com-
plete subordination. Perhaps indeed there was
little in their whole system to claim the title of
philosophy. They were bound no more to any
severity of thought than of conduct. No strict
Dioi-. Lat'it. ii. 1)2.
" IVIelaplivs. ii. 2.
26
THE ANCIENT VIEW OF THE
theory was needed to justify ease and sell-indulgence
to those who loved them.
As time passed on, the Schools, which at first
occupied independent ground, came into contact.
Questions, originated by each separately, were
discussed in common. And we find, at a period
long after the inventors of the respective systems
had ceased to write and live, their descendants
once more discussing points which seemed to have
been settled, and ruhng them anew.
In the time of Ammonius^the Stoics, Peripatetics,
and Platonists had long, he tells us, held their
distinct view as to the relation of Logic to Philo-
sophy. The Stoics, true to their old position,
made it a part of Philosophy. One of their argu-
ments is sufficiently terse and concise to deserve
mention. No Art, they said, made its own instru-
ment ; Logic therefore, which is the creation of
Philosophy, is not its instrument, but a part of it.
The title of Aristotle's logical works was the watch-
word of the Peripatetics, who held Logic to be only
an instrument. The argument which Ammonius
puts in their mouth, has certainly a tinge of a phi-
losophy foreign to that of their master. They
argued, he tells us, that every part must have the
same matter, and the same end, with the whole ;
but there was no such identity of subject and pur-
pose in Logic and Philosophy. For Philosophy,
' The soil of Heniicas, who flourished circ. A.D. 470. Sec
his Treatise on the Cate^^ories, pp. 6—8. Ed. Vend. 151)5.
RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE.
27
they proceeded, had things for its matter, and
asswiilatio7i to God for its end; while the subject
of Logic was Language, and its aid. Demonstration.
The conclusion at which they arrived was true ;
the way of attaining it, if it was really theirs, proves
how the school of Aristotle had degenerated in
those bad times.
The Platonic view, we are informed by the same
authority, was, that Logic was both a part and an
instrument of Philosophy. These Platonists, too,
argued rather childishly. A hand, they urged by
way of example, is an instrument of giving and
taking, a part of the whole body. Of course there
is nothing wonderful in the same thing's being
a part of one thing and an instrument of another.
There is something more philosophical in a dis-
tinction which they drew, with a like object, between
Logic when viewed as an independent system of
rules, and when actually applied to some particular
subject. Regarded abstractedly, as in the former
case, it seemed to them an instrument of Philo-
sophy ; taken in the concrete, as in the latter case,
it became a part. Thus, while they sided theo-
retically with the Stoics, their mode of expression
tended practically to that confusion of Logic and
Science, which afterwards prevailed among the
Schoolmen.
Thus much of the views which the principal
schools of ancient Philosophy held regarding
Logic. Their want of distinctness and consistency
28
THE ANCIENT VIEW OF THE
is obvious. The reason of this deficiency has been
hinted at more than once. Falling short of a
definite conception of Logic itself, they could
attain no distinct statement of its relation to other
subjects. Human reason at large, and reasoning,
or the exercise of the inferential faculty par-
ticularly, and language, in which reason finds its
expression, may all be investigated like any other
subject, and therefore brought under one or more
sciences. Such science or sciences would of course
be a part of Philosophy. And the Greeks, employ-
ing a single word to express at once thought and
language, would naturally call such a science.
Logical,
This combination then of Metaphysic and uni-
versal Grammar, though scarcely deserving to give
a name to the most important division of Philo-
sophy, would nevertheless rank under it. Aristotle
and Plato were right in insisting on its claim to
this honour; the Stoics and Epicureans trod on
the verge of error, when they lowered the laws of
thought in their esteem to the level of the rules
which are gi'ounded on them, and the Cynics and
Cyrenaics were undoubtedly wrong when they
despised this branch of knowledge altogether.
But Logic, in the sense which we give to the
term, is not a Science, but an Art. Not directly
adding to our stock of abstract truths, but serving
to extend in all directions the domain of general
knowledge, it is not a part of Philosophy, but the
RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE.
29
organon of Philosophy at large. And it was to
Logic proper, as an art, that the enquiries of the
later Schools which have been mentioned above
referred. The Peripatetic position, that it is an
instrument, is in this way perfectly correct. It
was an anticipation of the modern idea of the
subject, and was only too early to bear fruit. The
Platonic statement has the air of a verbal com-
promise, but agrees essentially with the Peri-
patetic. The Stoical opinion is indefensible. That
School held fast to its ancient dogma without
understanding it. Though it might be rash to
assert with Hooker, that they " accounted stupidity
the highest top of wisdom V' they certainly showed
for the most part more obstinacy in retaining a
position than skill in defending it.
The view of the later Peripatetics, we have said,
was alone correct. But it was planted among the
fragments of a ruined philosophy, and failed to
take root. The ancients, on the whole, sub-
scribed to the formula, that Logic is a part of
Philosophy. Turn we now to the Schoolmen,
and see, how through their researches we have
journeyed by a tortuous road to Truth.
y Eccl. Pol. VI, vi. §.6.
CHAP. IL
THE MEDIEVAL VIEW OF THE RELATION OF LOGIC
TO SCIENCE.
The stream of knowledge, though it always
flows, never flows evenly for long together. It
often seems to divide, and its portions to take dif-
ferent courses. But the separation is seldom final.
The severed streamlets form an island, beyond
which they unite. The smaller body of water
flows perhaps straight onward, through a confined
and artificial channel. The main stream makes a
longer circuit, but both join at last.
We may apply our metaphor, and say, that
ancient Philosophy ran in a comparatively narrow
course after Aristotle. The late Peripatetics, we
have seen, kept and carried on, with regard to
Logic, the true doctrine of their master. But
Philosophy in general took a diflerent turiL Ari-
stotle himself, and not the opinions of his school
after him, formed the text which exercised the
commentatorial spirit of the middle ages. The
Schoolmen set a very different value on Logic from
the Peripatetics. It was fated to rise to a still
THE RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE.
81
greater height in the world's estimation, before it
sunk to its proper level. Aristotle and Plato had
made Logic a part; it is not too much to say that
the Schoolmen made it the whole, of Philosophy.
Aristotle, like many other great men, left behind
him a mighty idea, for the future, if possible, to
evolve. That idea was the great ruling science of
Wisdom, Towards this he pointed the aspirations
of all who would be good and happy. He thought
it unattainable, certainly to the majority of man-
kind, perhaps to all. Yet, in spite of his love of
the practical, he could not refrain from dwelling
on it. If ever he is enthusiastic, it is on this
subject ; some portions of the Metaphysics, read,
in consequence, like fragments of a philosophical
romance.
The Schoolmen caught from him the same idea,
and were enraptured with it. We shall not wonder
at this, if we consider how great were the promises
it held out, to those who thought it practicable.
Aristotle's Wisdom is nothing less than a deduc-
tive theory of the universe. The mind which has
attained it is represented as in some sense sovereign
over all that it surveys. The truly wise men,
unlike the mass of mankind, who are slaves to
sense, and see but consequents without the ante-
cedents, and touch only the last and lowest link of
the chain which connects heaven and earth, stands
at the source of all knowledge, and sees things in
their causes. His reason follows the order of the
32
THE MEDIAEVAL VIEW OF THE
creative Mind. Whatever is first in nature, is first
also to him.
And the mental act which this Wisdom implies
is of the most perfect kind. All is calm contem-
plation. The turmoil of inference is over, and pure
intuition has succeeded. The mind's eye does not
wander here and there in quest of some worthy
object, but is fixed for ever in intellectual serenity
on the face of Truth.
Viewed only as a habit of the mind, it rose so
high in dignity and perfection. Nor were the
subjects with which it dealt unworthy of its own
elevated nature. It is depicted in a threefold
aspect, answering to the division of that which it
contemplates. Its highest phase is Theology, —
which dwells on the thought of the self-existing
Substance, a pure intellectual Being, ever active ;
the first Cause ; itself unmoved, yet the source of
all motion ; eternal, indivisible, omnipresent ; in a
word, the Aristotelian God.
Its two other divisions are Mathematic and Physic.
These words, to a great degi'ee, explain themselves.
Of the latter, however, we should observe, that it
took a much wider range with Aristotle than with
us, including, to a great extent, the laws of mind
as well as of matter, — the laws of all phenomena, in
short, which are not reducible to the formulae of
space and number. Under this broad sense of
Physic falls the Philosophy both of Morals and Art.
The wise man does not indeed descend from his
I
RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE.
33
theoretic elevation to give rules for guiding con-
duct, and forming taste. To the lower parts of
Philosophy it belongs to train men to the love of
goodness and the perception of beauty. But when
art and education have not only brought forth
fruit in practice, but have also developed character,
and elicited Ideas which had else lain dormant in
the mind. Wisdom can then, without loss of caste,
regard them. She adds to her contemplation of
Absolute Being, and, in subordination to this, of
the laws which move the framework of the Uni-
verse, a knowledge of those principles also, on which
depend the Good and the Beautiful.
Such was Aristotle's wisdom, perfect in its
subject, which is co-extensive with law and order ;
perfect in its method, which is that of the cre-
ative Mind, starting with the simple idea of Being,
and descending thence in regular sequence through
the whole array of including and included universals ;
perfect in the nature of its contemplation, which
sums up in a single term the whole series of
causation, and grasps by a simple intellectual act
what has been called " the Mundane Idea," or the
'' Summary Law of Nature'."
The author of this mighty plan did not, of
References in detail are impossible, where so abstruse and
wide a subject is treated so summarily. But a fuller expansion
would have been out of place here. The following Chapters
of the Metaphysics contain manv of the nio.st ini])ortant passages.
Lib. I. 1.2. V. l.XI. 7— 10.
D
S4
THE MEDLEVAL VILW OF THE
course, witness its completion. It cannot he fairly
said that he ever really attempted to carry it out.
We have indeed lahorious collections of facts,
difficult prohlems, subtle theories, handed down to
us in abundance from Aristotle. But thougli he
investigated almost every branch of knowledge,
there was no great system to which he endeavoured
to harmonize the whole. His separate treatises
have their own perfection, and generally need no
definite place in a more extensive arrangement.
Having put before the world a scheme for the
consistent organization of all knowledge, and col-
lected large materials for tlie work, he left tliem as
a legacy to posterity, to be arranged and con-
solidated, if it so might be, by others.
Nor did the idea fail to bear fruit in its season.
The Schoolmen found tlie design, and thought it
too striking to be neglected. Their theological
stores were a large addition to the material be-
queathed by Aristotle. So, with full confidence
in their resources, and a per[)etual reference to the
original sketch before them, they attempted to
rear the tem})le of Universal Knowledge. Where
Aristotle had laid the foundation, tluy built; his
facts, ready hewn to their hands, they incorporated
with the building : his Metaphysic supplied them
with the plan; and they took his Logic for their
scaffold.
To mention the Schoolmen seems at once to
trespass on the province of the unintelligible. The
RELATION OF LOOIC TO SCIENCE.
35
term is vague enough ; can it be otherwise, when
we sum up under the title of scholastic philosophy
the whole mass of thought, vast in its extent if not
in its value, which occupied the minds of the
learned in its elaboration between the tenth and
the sixteenth centuries ? If it brings up any image
at all before most minds, it is a very incongruous
one, in which John Scotus and Dun Scotus are in
danger of losing their individuality, Roscelin and
Ockham, the nominalists early and late, blend
confusedly together, and Anselm and Lanfranc
come into contact with Albertus Magnus and
Thomas Aquinas. We are apt to think, that during
the long period of scholastic dominion there was
no true growth and progress ; ' that books increased
beyond number, and writer superseded writer, with-
out any corresponding, not to say proportionate,
increase of knowledge, or revolution of opinion ;
but that Aristotle was a uucleus round which hard
words innumerable attached themselves by accre-
tion like so much inorganic matter. But such a
tone of thought is an unnecessary wrong to an
extinct philosophy. Its unity of form, though
by no means so great as is generally supposed,
serves nevertheless to disguise from the care-
less observer very wide differences in substance.
The opinion that the thinkers of those days
must have been all very much like each other,
is too rapid an inference from the undoubted
fact, that they were all very unlike ourselves. If
d2
36
THK MEDLEVAL VIEW OF THE
we identify, as is usual, the Scholastic and Me-
diaeval Philosophy, we must not forget, that
there were as truly within it subordinate schools,
as there had been in ancient, and are in modern
times, in spite of the greater resemblance of form
which they acquired, as, treating all subjects in a
single view and in a conventional language, they
expanded with difficulty, and often with danger
to their advocates, under the watcliful eye and
stern admonition of Church-authority.
The great point of similarity among the School-
men is indeed that feature of their writings with
which we are most concerned — the uniform j)re-
sence of a dialectical spirit. Some of the traits
which we should be most apt at first to select as
characteristic are by no means universally present.
Their devotion to Aristotle, for instance, is not
invariable. The master of sentences himself, Peter
Lombard, has been observed never to quote him ;
and with several of the early Schoolmen, the Neo-
platonic element preponderates over the Peripa-
tetic. The commentatorial spirit, again, prevailed
not so generally among them as it is said to do
now among the literati of China. It does not
distinguish, for instance, the scholastic works of
St. Anselm; and the master-pieces of school-
labour, the Book of Sentences, and the Sums of
Theology, are in the form of questions and distinc-
tions, not of comment. Some would make realistic
opinions a test of the Schoolmen; yet Roscehn
RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE.
37
and Abelard are often reckoned in their number,
and no one denies Ockham that doubtful honour.
They are characterised more surely, as we have
said above, by their absorbing devotion to Dialectic.
This it is which keeps them poised in the region
of intellectual abstraction, equally removed from
the pleasing illusions of imagination on the one
hand, and the stern realities of observation and
experiment on the other. This is the principle of
unity, which assimilates to itself all the subjects of
which they treat, and reduces to a dreary same-
ness the widest and most varied range of discus-
sions. But our object is not to delineate the
scholastic Philosophy generally. The connection
it formed with the Aristotelian idea of Wisdom,
and its consequent identification with Logic, alone
concern us at present. Peculiarities such as these,
though they may be stated in the abstract, cannot
be described and rendered intelligible, without some
aid of example. And to none of the Schoolmen
should we so naturally turn, as to Thomas Aquinas.
Several reasons prove him particularly adapted for
this purpose. He is perhaps, of all his tribe, the
most complete and systematic : and the fact, that
when the day of his full power was over, he con-
tinued, and still continues, to exercise a real in-
fluence over students of a certain portion of
Philosophy, fits him still more for our object, when
we are treating of the scholastic doctrines mainly
with regard to the view which they forwarded on
38
THE MKDl.EVAL VIEW OF THE
a single important question — the relation of Logic
to Science. Though, were we attempting a portrait
of the perfect Schoolman, we should still do best
to refer to him. He is, in many ways, the best
specimen of his class. He wrote at the time when
the School-philosophy seemed to have com{)letely
recovered from the attack which tln*eatened it with
destruction in its infancy, and which Ockham
afterwards renewed to its ultimate downfal. He
unites in himself to a remarkable degree the theo-
logical and philosophical traditions of former days;
Augustine was his acknowledged authority in
matters of religion, and Averrcies, to an extent of
which he was not himself aware, his leader in the
interpretation of Aristotle. The earlier Schoolmen
wrote in fear, often well-grounded, of the inter-
ference of the Church ; the later are thought to
have pressed the system to its utmost boundaries,
and to have seen glimpses of the coming reform-
ation. Aquinas, more than any of his fellow-
labourers, was fortunate in the reception of his
speculations : they were never deemed of unlawful
tendency, and gained for him the rare praise of
uniting orthodoxy and philosojihical acuteness.
We may add, that his writings, at the present day,
are still spoken of, if not consulted, and referred
to, if not read; and alone, of all the scholastic
volumes, show traces of a dubious vitality.
It will then be worth while, keei)ing Thomas
Aquinas steadily l)ef()re us as the type of the
RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE.
39
scholastic Philosophy, to show briefly from his
writings the place which logical method held in
his system. Our position, be it remembered, is
this — that the Schoolmen took their ideal of
Science from Aristotle's Wisdom ; that, m the
endeavour to construct it, they began by ad-
mitting his Metaphysic ; that they adopted his
facts without enquiry, and placed them for pur-
poses of argument on a par with truths derived
from more sacred sources ; and that thus, with
premises ready to their hand, and a logical system
under which to combine them, they reared a
fabric of which the form was comparatively every
thing, and the matter comparatively nothing ; so
that the truth could not be distinguished from the
medium in which they exhibited it, and their
method became identical with their philosophy.
7^o proceed then to the first point — the co-
incidence of the Scholastic view of perfect Science
with the Aristotehan idea of Wisdom.
The great work of Aquinas is, as every one
knows, his '^ Sum of All Theology." Theology,
too, was, as we have seen, the title of the highest
division of Aristotle's Wisdom. This agreement of
language, even if unintentional at first, could not
remain unperceived ; and, when once perceived,
could not be passed over in silence. Either the
Theology of Aquinas was to be, like Aristotle's,
the highest wisdom, or it was not ; and a writer
so given to definition and distinction could not
40
THE MEDIEVAL VIEW OK THE
leave a point of this nature luuleterniined. Ac-
cordingly, he meets the question, and answers it in
the affirmative. At the very opening of his great
work he declares, that the Sacred Doctrine is '* one
single science," ''speculative rather than practi-
cal," " transcending all other sciences whatsoever,"
in a word, "absolutely and simply wisdom \"
The Christian Theology then w^ould, according
to Aquinas, approach very nearly in the terms of
its definition to that of the heathen philosopher.
This would indeed still leave room for a very wide
distinction between them. But it would lead us
to expect at least thus much, tliat the Schoolmen
would be very careful in drawing a line of de-
marcation between the Divine Wisdom and Aris-
totle's crowning Virtue. This, however, is not the
case. Thus in his connnent on Aristotle's Meta-
physics, he begins by assigning to his author's first
science the very title by which he distinguishes
his own. It bears, he tells us, the three names of
the Divine Science, or Theology ; Metaphysic ; and
the First Philosophy ^ And how thoroughly he
blends in his method of treatment the human and
the Divine Wisdom, how he considers them to con-
' See Prima Priinae, Art. I. Qq. 2—6. where he predicates of
•* Doctriiia sacra" successively that it is " scientia," " una scientia,"
" magis speculativa quum practica," " omnes alias scientias traii-
scendens turn speculativas quum practicas," " maxime sapient ia
inter omnes sapientias humanas, non quiilcm in aliquo generr
lantum, sed simpliciter."
^ Comment, in Mctaphys. ad init.
RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE.
41
nect themselves with the same subjects in the
same manner, may be seen in the following very
characteristic passage". "Those arts," he ob-
serves, " w^hich govern other arts are called archi-
tectonic or ruling arts ; and those who exercise
them are called architects, and claim the name of
wise. These artificers, however, as aiming only
at particular ends, reach not the universal end of
all things. They are therefore only called wise
on this or that particular subject. In this sense it
is said, ' as a wise master-builder I have laid the
foundation ^* But the name of absolutely wise
is reserved for him alone, whose speculations turn
on the end of the universe, which is also the
principle of all things. Wherefore, as the Philo-
sopher *" says, the wise man must consider the
highest causes. But the ultimate end of every
thing is that which is intended by its first author
and mover. But the first author and mover of
the universe is Intellect. Therefore the ultimate
end of the universe must be the good of Intellect ;
which is Truth. Truth must then be the ultimate
end of the whole universe ; and with the con-
sideration of this end must Wisdom be principally
occupied. Therefore, the Divine Wisdom cl^id in
flesh declares that He came into the world to
'' Proopm. ad Sum. contr. Gent.
•* I Cor. iii. 10. Aquinas quotes the Vulgate, " ut sapiens
archifecfus fundamentum posui."
' Melaphvs. i. 2.
42
THK MEDLtVAL VIEW OF THE
RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE.
43
manifest the Truth, saying, ' To this end was
I born, and for this cause came I into the world,
that I'should bear witness unto the Truth? And
so the Philosopher^ determines, that the First
Philosophy is the Science of Truth, not however
of any Truth, but of that which is the origin of all
Truth."
Further proof cannot be necessary of the close
connection, not to say identity, which Thomas
Aquinas held to exist between Aristotle's First
Philosophy and the Christian Theology. We
must next show the importance he attached to
the principles of the Aristotelian Metaphysic.
Though Aristotle and the Schoolmen each
founded their great science on the same idea, that
of Being, it by no means necessarily followed that
their respective sciences should be identical. They
need not ever have been to any great extent
similar. The conceptions which they employed
to express and bring out at length the meaning
and force of that idea, might have been entirely
different. They might have endeavoured to por-
tion out the world of thought on some novel
principle, and have spent their chief labour in
discovering a range of metaphysical abstractions,
which should give their speculation an individual
and original air. In a word, as Aristotle had
divided being in one way, they might have divided
it in another. Had they undertaken to do so, the
' John xviii. 37. « Mctapliys. ii. 1.
'
most characteristic feature of their philosophy
would have disappeared, or rather, would never
have been called into existence. The endeavour
to decide for themselves, what was the best and
most natural division of Being, would have called
observation into play, and, by giving Induction
fair scope, liave destroyed the exclusive power of
Deduction. The course of Science might have been
more rapid than it has been, had the minds of men
been thus early turned to investigating new
universals, instead of drawing continually new
conclusions fi*om those wiiich w^ere old. But the
Schoolmen show^ed no tendency in this direction.
As they had taken the idea of their science from
Aristotle, they took from him the conceptions
which were to illustrate it also. Without any
exercise of the critical faculty, they followed him
unhesitatingly in his primary division.
At the very beginning of Aristotle's Organon
stand the Categories, or, in Latin guise, the Pre-
dicaments. They are the first broad philosophical
division which meets the student of the Aristotelian
method. Of what they are a division, is not so clear.
Aristotle himself is generally supposed to have
attained them by considerations half-logical and
half-grammatical; and then to have applied them
as heads under which to group thhigs. Thus the
question naturally arose — are the Categories to be '
regarded as a scheme for the division of nature, or
of language ? Eitlier opinion had its advocates
44
THE MEDIEVAL VIEW OF THE
among the ancients. Others preferred an inter-
mediate view, and considered them as referring to
the conception, which hes midway between the
name and the thing. Ammonias ^ who records
these different opinions, himself subscribes to a
misty formuhi, probably of Neo-platonic origin,
which blends them all, and asserts, that " the
Categories have to do with words, whicli signify
things, through the medium of conceptions."
The Schoolmen would have adopted this view,
had they exclusively followed tradition. It is
contained in their principal authority on the
subject, a commentary on the ten Predicaments,
erroneously attributed by them to St. Augustine \
But they rejected as superficial and insufficient
the belief, that the Categories were mainly a
scheme for the division of words. It pleased them
rather to hold, that they met with their counter-
parts in the outward world. On them they would
willingly have constructed, if they could, the
classification of an universal science. So Aquinas
*• De Categ. p. 14, 15.
' That Alcuiii had no doubt either of the aulhenticitv of this
work, or of the value of its contents, appears from the following
verses, in which he rc^commended it to the perusal of Charlemagne.
Continet iste decem naturie verba libellus
Quae jam verba tenent reruni, ratione stiipentld
Omne quod in nostrum poterit decurrere sensum.
• •••«••••
Hunc Augustino placuit transfcne magislro
Do velcrum gazis Griucorum clave Latin^.
\
RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE.
45
tells us, that " perfect Being is that which exists,
external to the mind, through the ten Predica-
ments^;" and again, that '' Being must be portioned
out into different kinds according to the different
modes of predication; for different modes of pre-
dication are attendant on different modes of Beuij^''."
Or, as he elsewhere states his doctrine, " modes of
Being are proportional to modes of predication \''
And far from making the Categories heads under
which to arrange conceptions, he expressly excludes
all such mental creatures from them ; for " nothinir
IS placed in any predicament, except what exists
external to the mind "\" Accordingly, he attempts,
with very indifferent success, to show, from con-
sidering the nature of existence, that these ten
heads amount to an exhaustive division of things'".
So high indeed did he raise their dignity, that he
sometimes ranges God under the Category of
Substance. Though here he speaks more doubt-
fully than usual, at one time denying that the
Predicaments at all relate to Him", at another
time allowing that tliey do % though in a different
manner from that in which they apply to other
existences^.
^ in Metaphys. v. Leciio ix.
* In Phys. iii. Lectio v.
•" De Pot. Dei. Qu. vii. Art. ix. Rosp.
" Prima Summte, Qn, iii. Art. v.
" De Pot. Dei, Qu. vii. Art. iii. ad 7™.
^ De Pot. Dei, Qu. ii. Art. ii. ]•". ad 1'".
Ii
46
THE MEDLflVAL VIKW OF THE
It is clear, that were the Categories thus state-
ments of the real classes of things, a universal
science would be at once possible. Under such
a classification every thing might be duly ranked
and ordered, and a natural system, so to speak, of
the whole universe be constructed. And this was
the work which the Schoolmen thought they had
the power to accomplish. The Categories them-
selves indeed do not hold a very prominent place
in their general writings. Like other abstract
principles, when once enunciated and clearly laid
down as true, they are traceable mainly in their
consequences. They stand like so many land-
marks, seen from a distance indeed, but of most
continual use in guiding the mind to its decision on
questions which are very remotely and indirectly
connected with them. The bearings of truths
derived from very different sources, from Holy
Writ and the writings of the Fathers, were deter-
mined by them. This was a great misfortune to
the Schoolmen, that they never suspected the
existence of any discrepancy in their heterogeneous
material, or at least, if the suspicion unavoidably
occurred, never ventured to entertain it. Theo-
logians at the first, they began in the school of
faith, and carried their l)elieftoo far. Inspiration
itself could not receive more reverence than Aris-
totle. Where he evidently contradicts the revealed
Word, they shut their eyes to the real state of things,
and look about for some other exi)lanation. Thus
i
UELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE.
47
Aquinas wishes to persuade himself, that the Philo-
sopher did not actually hold the world to be eternal,
but was rather, like a subtle disputant of his own
times, urging in a dialectical spirit plausible argu-
ments against the position of an adversary*^. The
Schoolmen had never heard of destroying, with a
view to re-construct. Unhappy in the absence of
doubt, they fell short of the philosophic mind in
one respect at least — that they never learned to
reject.
Logic then, as the Schoolmen thought, had a
noble task before it. With so much inherited from
their predecessors, all new ap])eal to the world of
observation seemed on their part superfluous.
From certain given truths they hoped by a long
circumduction to infer all truth. For this purpose,
logical instruments were to suffice. But the in-
struments of Logic differ from those of most other
arts in a very marked manner. There is, in Art,
generally little similarity between the tool and that
on which it operates. And further, most arts
confine themselves in practice strictly to singulars.
The sculptor applies an individual tool to an indi-
vidual block of marble : it is a given portion of a
compound substance which a chemist analyses, and
that by means of tests themselves of a limited and
definite quantity. It is not so with the Logician.
His subject, and his manner of dealing with it, are
^ Prima Suuiina^ Qu. xlvi. Art. 1. De Pot. Dii. Qu. iii.
Art. xvii.
48
THE MEDLEVAL VIEW OF THE
alike general. He applies universals as the criterion
of other universals. This is his work — to test,
arrange, and, it may be, infer, general truths by
means of general formulae.
So thought the Schoolmen— and to a great
measure rightly. How then were they to discri-
minate, where there seemed so much risk of con-
fusion, between their method, and that on which
they employed it ? The conceptions, whether of
things or classes, which their enquiries presupposed,
and the apparatus of Logic itself, were alike modes
of intellect. Without some especial provision,
error and perplexity must ensue from their running
into each other. This danger was obviated by
drawing a distinction between First and Second
Intentions. '^ A first intention V' they taught, '^ was
the likeness of something existing external to the
mind; as, for instance, the conception which follows
on hearing the word man — a conception which is
founded immediately on the thing." Whereas a
second intention is '^not a likeness of any thing
existing external to the mind, but a conception
following on our mode of understanding such
things. These are invented by the intellect itself ;
as, for instance, the conception which is signified by
the word genus. Intentions of this kind have their
immediate foundation not in the things but in the
understanding : though the remote foundation is in
the thing itself." So that, to express the same
•^ Aquinas on i"". Lib. Sent. Dist. ii. Qu. i. Art. iii.
UliLATlON Ol LOGIC TO SCIKNCK.
49
truth still more clearly in the form of a distinction
not of things but of words, " nouns of the first
intention are those which are imposed upon things
as such, that conception alone intervening, by
which the mind is carried immediately to the thing
itself. Such are man, and stone. But nouns of the
second intention are those which are imposed upon
things, not in virtue of what they are in themselves,
but in virtue of their being subject to the intention
which the mind makes concerning them : as when
we say that man is a species, and animal a genus\"
The scholastic apparatus was now complete.
They had, as they thought, a primary classification,
external to the mind, in the ten Predicaments;
they had first intentions, or conceptions drawn
directly from things, to range under them; they
had, among other second intentions, the Pre-
dicables, which enabled them to show, how, under
the light of the natural classification, the first
intentions were related to each other. In other
words, they had, or supposed they had, both the
objective and subjective requisites of a perfect
system— a valid diWsion of existing things, and a
method according to which to group all notions
under this division. So, without any further
delay, they betook themselves to syllogizing; to
determining, that is, by means of their supposed
knowledge of the nature and force of terms, the
various relations which they might be supposed to
• Opusc. xlii. Art. xii. ad init.
dO
THE MEDIEVAL VIEW OF THE
occupy to each other in propositions. Here they
were not likely soon to come to a stand: the
possible permutations of words are endless ; and
they did not think that they were dealing only
with words, and falling far short of things. Each
distinction which they drew brought forward new
questions; and the solution of each question
ehcited fresh distinctions. Philosophy separated
from a central trunk into numerous branches,
which again divided and subdivided till their ulti-
mate sections were as fine as hairs, or finer —
invisible even to the eyes of those who spun them
out. And, through the whole of the prolonged
system. Logic every where extended itself; drew
each distinction, stated each objection, answered
it when stated, summed up when it gave its de-
cision, crushed each enquiry into the same uni-
form shape, appealed over and over again to the
same universal premises, employed unnumbered
artifices to extract from these premises conclusions
they were never meant to give, cut into shreds the
scanty sheet of knowledge, as Dido did the hide,
that it might encircle the province which it could
not cover, governed absolutely all Philosophy, and
as in despotic governments there is no distinction
between the monarch and the constitution, was all
Philosophy itself.
No wonder then that the highest praises were
heaped upon it; that though it was confessedly
only " reductivelv" or '' indirectly" a part of specu-
RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE.
51
lative Science, as supplying it with syllogisms,
definitions, and other instruments of like kindS it
was yet allowed to bear in common parlance the
title of " the Rational Science"," that as directing
the act of reason, from which all arts proceed, it
was called " the Art of Arts " ;" and that it was
held% '' all learning must begin from Logic, not as
being more easy than other sciences, (for having to
deal with second intentions it involves the greatest
diflSculty) but because it teaches the method of
procedure in all sciences, and therefore all other
sciences dejiend upon it^."
« Super Boet. de Triii. Qii. V. Art. 1.
" In Post. Analyt. ad init.
• Super Boet. de Triii. Qu. Vf . Art. 1.
^ Old John of Salisbury gives an account of the proceedings in
a certain Dialectical school with which he was acquainted, which
will apply, in a less degree, to the scholastic use of Logic in
general. At any rate, we may better see the tendency of the evil,
by contemplating its more aggravated form. " It was the fashion
to talk of nothing but consistency (convenientia) and reason.
Argument was ringing in every one's mouth. To name an ass, or
a man, or any other work of nature, counted as a crime; at least
was out of place, and unpolished, and unworthy a philosopher. It
was thought impossible to act or speak consistently and reasonably,
unless express mention were made of consistency and reason.
Argument was quite out of the question, without the use of the
word argument. No distinction was made, between proceeding
according to an art, and treating of it. (Ex arte, et de arte agere,
idem erat.)*' Metalogicus, Lib. I. Ch. iii.
E 2
NOMINALISM AND REALISM.
53
CHAP. III.
NOMINALISM AND REALISM.
Before taking our farewell of the scholastic view
of Logic, it is natural to make some remarks on the
great question as to the nature of Universals, which
connected itself so closely with it. Though the
battle has long been fought, there is a great
historical charm, and even so^ne living interest,
associated with the once-prominent party-names of
Nominalist and Realist.
We may easily see the reason of the importance
attached to this question, and the zeal with which
it was contested. Logic, we have said, was in fact
the sum of scholastic Science. And this great
Science professed to deal with Universals. On these
depended the whole array of questions and ob-
jections, consequences and conclusions. Their
modahty, so to speak, determined that of the
whole system. And those who were not too
busily engaged in adding to it and elaborating it,
to find time ibr looking back, and seeing what had
been accomplished, and on what foundation it
rested, naturally came at last to the enquiry, what
these Universals were.
Of course, the originators of this question among
the Schoolmen were neither the first to ask it, nor
the last. Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoics, not to
mention other authorities, had each their distinctive
theory of Universals. None of these were entirely
satisfactory : and modern Philosophy feels the old
difficulty to be still unsolved, to be lying at the
basis of almost every important doubt, and to
l)resent the great clieck to its rapid and confident
progress. In all probability, indeed, a compa-
ratively ancient source suggested the enquiry to
the Schoolmen. Porphyry, in his treatise on the
Predicables, states the problem, though he declines
attempting to solve it^ "' Whether," he says,
'' genus and species are substances, or exist in
bare thought alone; or, supposing thein to be
substances, whether they are material or im-
material ; and again, whether they exist separately,
or in composition with sensible objects, I must
dechne discussing. The subject is profound, and
needs a separate and more detailed enquiry." Its
due quantity of enquiry, at least, in after-times it
gained.
It is well known that Europe derived its know-
ledge of Aristotle from the Arabians ; and that,
among these, their principal authority Averroes
tinctured the Peripatetic philosophy with a strong
spice of a spurious Neo-platonism. Under his
hands, the doctrine of Universals assumed a form
* Fsagogo, clia])- i.
54
NOMINALISM AND REALISM.
something like that of Ideas. Genus and species
were held to be substances, not mere attributes,
much less words. Whether they existed abstract-
edly from matter, or were rather to be described
as always present in the concrete, was a subject
left for after-discussion. The theory of Averroes
himself was in fact an ill-disguised Pantheism ;
which, when apphed to certain subjects, led to
results which so displeased the Schoolmen, as to
prevent, even when such objections did not occur,
its formal and expHcit reception. Here their
theology came in as a safeguard to their philo-
sophy; they shrank as Christians from the view
which he held, that one common human intellect
existed, of which each individual intellect was
a part\ But they followed him so far as to
conceive, that the Universal was an actual thing;
and thus, before Nominalism was heard of, ReaUsm,
or a belief in the existence of Universals as sub-
stances, and not merely as attributes of the mind
of man, was the current belief of the early School-
men and their immediate predecessors. It suited
the feehngs of those, who, like Scotus Erigena,
•• "A view," Thomas Aquinas argued justly, (Opusc. xvi. contra
Averroistas,) ** which is repugnant to the truth of the Christian
Faith. For intellect appears to be alone, of all the parts of the
soul, incorruptible and immortal. Now supposing diversity of
intellect to be removed from all men, it follows, that, alter death,
nothing of human souls would remain except their intellectual
unity, and thus all retribution of reward and punishment would hi?
removed."
NOMINALISM AND REALISM.
55
were mystically inclined; it could not be dis-
agreeable to those argumentative spirits, who were
anxious to maintain the honour of Dialectic. But,
though thus in possession of the scholastic mind at
the first, it did not establish its supremacy without
a struggle. The Nominalist attack showed at
once its strength and its weakness. It called forth
the hidden strength of Reahsm, by proving that it
was entwined with the very roots of the School-
philosophy, which could not ultimately but stand
or ftiU with it : it also betrayed its weakness, by
showing that it lacked the distinctness of a true
and consistent theory, and assumed very different
shapes in the minds of its different supporters.
The history of Nominalism divides itself into
two very marked periods. During the former of
/these, it was forcing by its attacks the scholastic
philosophy to assume a more definite form than it
had hitherto taken, and was so hurrying on its own
temporary defeat; during the latter, it was sapping
the strength of that mighty system, by introducing
into its inmost heart an element of doubt. In
both periods, it connected itself with theological
questions, in feeling and tendency, if not by the
links of strict consequence. Nominalism has often
been called, and justly, the precursor of the
Reformation. And as those who first aimed unsuc-
cessfully at a reformation were more violent in
their opinions than those who took up the work
afterwards, and succeeded ; so the earlier Nomi-
66
NOMINALISM AND REALISM.
nalists, doomed from the first to fail, were more
extravagant and far less philosophical in their
teaching, than the happier band whom Ockham
led on to victory.
Roscelin of Compeigne was confessedly the
founder of the sect of the Nominalists. The term
at first was meant to indicate that its adherents
bestowed their attention on language, and held
Universal to consist in na?Nes. Though it was
natural that the Realists should endeavour to give
it still further force, in applying it as an allusion to
what they thought the merely verhaf knowledge of
their antagonists. And so Aventinus, even when
looking back upon the past, explains it. " Roscelin,"
he says, '' the founder of the new Lyceum, first
cultivated the science of words and phrases, and
discovered a new way of philosophizing. To him
we owe it, that the Peripatetics, or followers of
Aristotle, divided into two classes— the older, rich
in invention, and claiming for itself the science of
things, and therefore called the Real school ; and
the later, disturbers of this science, and called
Nominalists, because, niggardly of things, but
prodigal of names and notions, they appear to be
the partisans of words \" This is neither a very
»' Aniiales Boioiuin, lib. vi. p. 406. cd. Basil. 1580. Avoniimis
(lied about 1533. A reproach gi-ouuded on a name is of course
little to be trusted. " Who can confute a sneer ?" And praise on
like grounds is equally deceptive. Luther commends the later
Nominalists, on the strength «»f anoiher muw thev here, with
NOMINALISM AND REALISM. 57
profound nor a very fair account of Nominahsm
in general. But it serves to show the feehngs
with which its advocates were regarded down to a
comparatively late date, as sceptics who would
lower the dignity of Dialectic, curtail the region of
Science, and suck out the very marrow of Philo-
sophy.
Roscehn himself, indeed, appears to have de-
served the name of Nominalist in its fullest and
most unfavourable signification. He advocated
the position that Universals were nothing but
names— a position which, as we shall see here-
after, has little to be said in its favour, and if
consistently maintained, is fatal to all true philo-
sophy. The error did not remain unrebuked : for
he drew upon himself the powerful opposition of
St. Anselm. This distinguished theologian and
dialectician had another hold upon his adversary.
Roscelin had been also guilty of heretical doctrine
concerning the Holy Trinity". St. Anselm in-
about as much reason as Aventinus condemns the earlier. " The
Terminisls, among whom I was, are sectaries in the high schools ;
they oppose the Thomists, the Scotists, and the Albertists ; they
are also called Occamists, from Ockham their founder. They are
of the newest sect, and are now strongest in Paris Thev are
called Terminisls, because they speak ol a thing in its own proper
words, and do not a])ply them after a strange sort Ockham
was an able and sensible man." Table Talk, pp. 540 — 2.
* Roscelin taujjht, " tres personas esse tres realitates di/Terentes."
Anselm's remarks are indignant enough. '* All," he says, " should
he warned to touch most cautiously on questions of Holy WriL
But these dialecticians of onr time, and heielics even in their
'
58
NOMINALISM AND REALISM.
I
NOMINALISM AND REALISM.
59
geniously couples the two mistakes together as
cause and effect. The bad dialectic accounts for
the false theology : and the false theology is proof
certain of the badness of the dialectic. The issue
of the contest was not long doubtful : Roscelin
was forced to retract his errors at the Council of
Soissons^ The victorious Anselm became next
year Archbishop of Canterbury. The defeated
innovator was banished both from England
and France*. In a few years, John of Salis-
bury informs us, his opinions were almost ex-
tinct ^
Another ill-starred name, that of Abelard, follows
Roscelin in the history of dialectical innovation.
Whether Roscelin was his instructor in their com-
mon art is doubtful. On the one hand, there is
old authority for such a supposition; on the other,
Abelard is silent on the point in his account of his
own Ufe, in which he displays no disposition to
reserve. But perhaps a reason for the omission
may be found in his circumstances. He had
.dialeciic, men who take universal substances to be nothing but
word of mouth, should be altogether excluded from disputing
on spiritual things He who does understand in what way
several men are yet in species but one man, can such a one com-
prehend how, hi the secret depths of the Divine Nature, of seveial
persons each shall be perfect God, yet all be one (Jod ?" Dc
Incamatione Verbi, (otherwise, De Fide,) ch. ii.
" A. D. 109-2.
• Abelard, Epist. xxi.
' His words are, ** alius consisiit in vocibus ; licet hacc opinio
cum Roscelinosuo fere omnino jam evanuerit." iMetalogicus, ii. 17.
himself to bear the imputation of heterodoxy, and
would naturally shrink from the weight of obloquy
which attached to another. Indeed he goes out
of his way to condemn in strong terms both the
logic and the theology of Roscelin^. There was
the more need for caution here, because their
opinions might by the careless or unskilful be
confounded. For Abelard, though not in the
strictest sense of the word a Nominalist, was at
least an Anti-realist. John of Salisbury thus
records the distinction between them^. '' The one
(meaning Roscelin) takes his stand on words ; the
other on propositions :" and he expressly ascribes
the latter view to Abelard.
It is hard to affix a very definite meaning to
this statement. The most probable interpretation
is that of Degerando \ that he believed Universals,
without having a strict independent and objective
reality, to be conceptions — conceptions, however,
which, to be formed and retained in the mind,
must rest upon the signs of language ; and that
« Epist. 21. "Hie sicut pseudo-Dialecticus, ita et pseudo-
Chrisiianus, cum in Dialectica sua nullum rem partes habere
aestimat, ita divinam paginam impudenter pervertit, ut eo loco,
quo dicitur Dominus partem piscis assi comcdisse, partem hujus
vocis, quai est piscis assi, non partem rei intelligere cogatur."
Fairness in dispute was no characteristic of those days.
•• Metalogicus, ii. 17. I have Englished " sermones" by '* pro-
positions," believing John of Salisbury to have had the Greek
Aoyouff in his mind.
' Hist. Comp. de Philosophic. Vol. iv. p. 403.
60
NOMINALISM AND REALISM.
therefore he made them turn, not, like RosceUn,
on the simple term, but on the proposition, which
expresses the relation of subject and attribute,
as they are apprehended by the understanding.
Scarcely any other position indeed in the scale of
thought upon this subject remains for him to
occupy ; for while he dissented from the pure
Nominahsm of Roscelin, he fell short of pure Con-
ceptualism; those who placed Universals among
the creatures of the understanding, as the Con-
ceptualists do, being mentioned by John of Salis-
bury as a distinct sect : and his own writings
would prove, even in the absence of external
authority, his decided aversion to Realism ''. But
Abelard, with all his niceness of distinction, did
not escape from the dialectical field unwounded.
Like Roscelin, he had the honour of being defeated
^ He relates with great gusto his contests with his old instnicior,
William of Compeigiie, and their successiul termination. " 1
forced him by most conclusive arguments to modify, or lather to
sunender, his old opinion concerning Universals. He had been of
thai mind with regard to their general nature, that he asserted the
same nature to be present at the same time essentiallv in each of
the individuals. It followed that among these individuals there
was no diversity of essence, but only a variety in the multitude of
their accidents. But afterwards he so reformed his opinion as to
say, that the same nature was present in them not essentially but
indifferently. " (i. e. as much in one hidividual, as in another.)
Abelardi Vita, cap. ii. A decision which leaves the question open
after all. Though the distinction meant to be drawn would seem
to be like that made afterwards in the disputes between Scotisis
and Thomisls between real and formal presence.
NOMINALISM AND UEALISM.
61
by a great antagonist. In this their lot differed,
that Roscelin fell by the hands of one who wielded
weapons like his own : while the brand of theo-
logical unsoundness was fixed upon Abelard by
one, whose mind, occupied by its own beautiful
mysticism, hated the philosophizing spirit of the
day. It is more an honour to him in our eyes,
than it was a consolation in his own, that he owed
his overthrow to St. Bernard.
But if in those days the imputation of Nominalism
was fatal. Realism was not always a protection from
error. A contemporary of Abelard, Gilbert de la
Poree, is an example of this. He was a Realist,
but a bold one. The extent of his boldness in
Dialectic has indeed been much overstated. His
treatise on the Six Principles has been described as
an endeavour to cut down Aristotle's Categories
to six. But he was guilty of no such presumption.
He only endeavoured to expand the six later
Predicaments, which Aristotle had passed cursorily
over, after the plan on which the Philosopher had
treated the first four. In introducing these in
their new shape, he goes so far as to hazard a
definition of form. " Form," he says, ^' is con-
tingent on matter, consisting of simple and in-
variable essence V and flatters himself that this
' Fonna est comj)ositioni conlingens, simplici et invariabili
essentia coiisistens. — Erit ilaque terminus foiinaB dicta definitio,
iieque enim superflua neque dimiuuta, si quis subtiliter investi-
gaverit, reperietur."
62
NOMINALISM AND REALISM.
formula will endure a searching criticism. It
would have been happy for him if he had confined
himself to such harmless innovations. But the
same spirit led him wrong elsewhere ; he too was
condemned for departing from the doctrine of the
Trinity.
It was resei-ved for a pupil of Abelard to effect
what his master in common with others had so
unsuccessftilly attempted — the union of Philosophy
and Theology. Peter Lombard effected this end,
by reversing the procedure of previous scholastics.
They had first formed their dialectical notions, and
then applied them to things divine. He, taking
his ground on the received Theology of the time,
accommodated Dialectic to it, and so freed it from
suspicion. His cautious Book of Sentences became
in after times the basis of comments much bolder
than the text on which they were founded. Or-
thodox in faith and philosophy, he completed for
the time the victory of Realism. And, like all other
principles that are not sound at heart, though a
good watchword in a battle, it becomes un-
interesting and unprofitable, immediately on its
success. We will proceed at once to some con-
siderations, which will bear upon the history of its
fall.
Realism, though now, as it seemed, firmly and
finally established, was not really safe. There
were enemies within the camp from the first.
John of Salisbury, who died as early as A. D. 11 82,
NOMINALISM AND REALISM.
63
recognises no less than six different sects of Realists.
These may be, however, fairly reduced to four ; —
those who adopted the Platonic doctrine of ideas,
and held that the names of genera and species
belonged properly only to those objectively ex-
isting Universals ; — those who considered that the
individual contained the whole essence of the class,
and was in fact, when viewed from a certain point,
itself the Universal, as when it is said that Plato
is, as to his manhood, a species;— those who
asserted that the whole aggregate of individuals
was identical with the Universal ; — and those who
regarded the Universal as a substance in some
way existing in the singular. These sects, it will
be seen, agree in nothing, except in all calling
Universals, ili'nigs.
The three former views, however, ultimately
gave way to the last, of which Aquinas was the
great advocate. It became a received doctrine,
that the one Universal existed in the many indi-
viduals. But this basis of agreement did not shut
out all dispute; the meaning of the formula was
not so clear, but that enquirers would ask, how the
Universal existed in the individuals ?
On this point, there was an ominous schism of
the Schoolmen. Dominican and Franciscan could
not agree even on the abstract questions of Phi-
losophy. Their differences extended from ques-
tions of free will and predestination to Logic. The
school of Scotists arose, and called into existence
64
NOMINALISM AND UEALISM.
the rival school of Thomists as defenders of the
great Dominican authority. The followers of
Aquinas held, that the Universal existed really
in the individuals; the disciples of Duns Scotus
maintained that it existed only formally'^. The
latter went so far, as to abandon the old title of
Realists, and assume that of FormaUsts : in order
that their very title might protest against the
doctrine of their antagonists. And, without endea-
vouring to explain the subtle distinction between
Reahsm and Formalism, we may assume that the
innovators, in rejecting the old watchword, vir-
tually, though unconsciously, relinquished tlie cause
which it had symbolized so long.
The Scotists themselves wxtc, or thought they
were, still opposed to Nominalism. But the next
generation of thought showed the actual tendency
of their views. Out of their school rose Ockham,
and with him the opposition to Realism revived
once more. In impugning the doctrine of the ex-
istence of Universals as substances, he directed his
attacks especially against Scotus, under whom he
had studied. We must not confound his opinions
with those of Roscelin and his disciples. Ockham,
•" It should be obsened, ihat the two doctors did not themselves
come into contact. Thomas Aquinas died A. D. 1274. The
chronology of Duns Scotus is doubtful; hut taking the most
probable date of his death A. D. 1308, and following the account
which gives him ihe short life of 34 years, we should fix his
birth in the very year in which Aquinas died.
NOMINALISM AND REALISM.
65
in asserting that Universals existed, but existed
only in the mind, answers exactly to a modern
Conceptualist. His teaching was on this point
clear, distinct, and sound, though expressed and
defended with a quaint and technical minuteness of
accuracy, which proves him every way a match for
any of his scholastic brotherhood.
'' " Every Universal," he taught, '' is really a Sin-
gular in itself, and therefore is only a Universal in
virtue of its signification, which is a sign of many
things. This is the doctrine of Avicenna, who
teaches, that a single form in the understanding is
related to a nmltitude of things, and is therefore a
Universal, because it is an intention in the intel-
lect whose operation does not vary to whatsoever
you apply it. It follows that this form, though in
relation to the individuals it is a Universal, yet in
relation to the mind on which it is impressed is
itself only an Individual, for it is one of the forms
which are in the understanding." This is a spe-
cimen of his positive reasoning : his negative goes
to prove generally that '' no Universal is any thing
external to the mind." It may be worth while to
show how he fought his adversaries with their
own weapons. '' ° No Universal," he urges, '' is a
singular substance, for, this granted, it would
follow that Socrates is a Universal : for there is no
more reason why one singular substance should
" Sumnia totius Logicfc, ch. xiv.
lb. ch. XV.
m
NOMINALISM AiND REALISM.
NOMINALISM AND REALISM.
67
be a Universal than another." This is rather an
endeavour to throw the weight of the proof upon
the adversary : the following is a more direct and
at the same time more complete argument. " If
any substance be, as is supposed, more things than
one, it must be either several Singulars or several
Universals. If the former be allowed, it follows
that a certain substance will be, e. g. several men ;
and then although the Universal will be distinct
from any one particular man, it will necessarily be
the same with all the particulars together. But if
we take the other alternative, that one substance
is several Universals, we must then ask the ques-
tion — is this Universal several things, or only one ?
If the answer be that it is only one, it follows that
it is really a Singular ; if the answer be that it is
several things, I enquire again whether it is several
Universals or several Singulars; and so on to
infinity." Theology too was l)rought to bear on
the point at issue. *' If the Realist opinion were
true, God could not annihilate one individual with-
out destroying all ; for to annihilate any individual
He must destroy all that is of its essence. Con-
sequently, He must destroy the Universal which
exists both in it and in other individuals ; and these
could not continue to exist, when deprived of
a part of their substance, such as the Universal is
supposed to be." We will not endeavour to follow
him, where, in discussing the Scotist opinion of
H ■
^
♦
-»
the formal presence of the Universal in the in-
dividual, he refines on a refinement ^\
Opinions like these, not long after the opening of
the fomteenth century, were pubHshed by Ockham
from the Theological chair of Paris. They pro-
duced as much excitement as either friend or
enemy could have desired. And argument was
not the only means of discussing them employed.
Ockham himself, for the ready support which
he gave Phihp the Fair against the Pope, by
vindicating the rights of the temporal power, and
other like acts of insubordination, was rewarded
with the pontifical anathema. In more than one
University the new doctrines were contested with
blows and bloodshed. When we remember that
the opinions both of Scotus and Ockham were
probably formed within the walls of Merton, we
should be surprised if Oxford had been backward
in the dispute. Direct persecution was brought to
bear in Ockham's other University of Paris, and
P Another specimen of his theological reasoning, though curious
and characteristic, may be better thrown into a note, and preserved
in the Latin. " Item sequitnr quod aliquid de essentia Chrisii
erit miserum et danmatum: quia ilia natura communis existens
realiter in Christo et in damnato erit damnata,quia in Jud^. Hoc
autem est absurdum." Ockham here uses just the same kind of
argument against the Thomist supposition of a common human
nature, as Aquinas himself had employed against the Averroistic
lenetof a common human intellect. How hardily, and apparently
without any sense of their hardihood, did these men venture to
bring objective truths, and subjective convictions, into the most
direct collision.
f2
«8
NOMINALISM AND REALISM.
NOMINALISM AND IIRALISM.
69
elsewhere. Louis the Eleventh, by an edict whicfi
did not prove ultimately successful, condemned the
Nominalist teaching, and forbade the study of the
works of Ockham and his most famous disciples.
So the University of Leipsic ow^es its origin to the
expulsion of the Nominalists fi'om Prague. It is
said that the Universities of Vienna and Heidel-
berg '* were Nominalist from their foundation.
Aventinus, who flourished at the beginning of the
sixteenth century, mentions that the schools of
Paris, Erdfurt, Ingoldstat, and Vienna, were then
in Nominalist hands. The opinions of Ockham,
when for the time silenced in France, had thus,
after taking root deeply in their native home of
England, extended themselves to Germany.
Luther, Melancthon, and other reformers, pro-
fessed their allegiance to them. It would seem
the old Theolog)^ could scarcely have been assailed,
except with Nominalist arms. It would have stood
impregnable against any foes but such as were
acquainted with its form and devices, while they
had detached themselves from its spirit.
Enough has now been said on the history of this
great question of the mediaeval philosophy. We
have seen how Realism triumphed in the first great
contest of opinion ; and how, in the security which
followed on this triumph, diversities once more
crept in, till Nominahsm at last revived. Revive it
'^ The University of Vienna was founded A.D. 1365; that of
Heidelberi? A.D. 1346.
(
I
I
\
needs must, after the speculations of Duns Scotus.
The belief had not strength and foundation enough
to exist without the symbol. When the Scotists
took the name of formalists, they virtually gave
up the cause to which they professed to adhere.
Ockham's claim to distinction lies in the skill and
perseverance with which he urged his opinions.
The course of things nmst have led many men
sinmltaneously with him to entertain them.
And now it may be asked — who were in the
right, NominaHsts or Realists ? The query deserves
an answer, for the question about the nature of
Universals is not merely one of words. More
importance, indeed, was attached to it in the
middle ages than it deserved. But men were
wrong in this matter, only because they were con-
sistent. They considered the question as a logical
one, and their Logic identified itself with their
Philosophy, and their Pliilosophy ran up into
Theology; and Theology was in those days a
subject of very direct and personal import. We
are indifferent to Universals now, because the
ruling of the point either way would not im-
mediately affect daily life, or the opinions of prac-
tical men. It is this, and not any superiority to
the difficulty, or successful solution of it, which
has allowed the cries of Nominalist and Realist to
die away.
We will endeavour therefore to bring the dis-
pute to an issue ; and, that we may tlie better do
so, will first define our terms. Here Etymology
70
NOMINALISM AND REALISM.
Iff '
i
NOMINALISM AND REALISM.
71
comes to our aid. Nominalism, in its strict sense,
indicates a belief, that Universals are only names.
Realism asserts that they are things. Convenience
suggests that we should adopt a third term of later
origin, Conceptualism, as expressing the opinion
of those, who hold Universals to be conceptions.
Nominalism then, in its strict sense of a belief
that Universals are only names, is indefensible.
Roscelin, who held it, deserved the censures which
were heaped upon him as the virtual destroyer of
Philosophy. More will be said upon this point,
when we come to the logicians of the verbal
school, the legitimate successors of the Nominalists.
Suffice it for the present to say, that they make, of
necessity, the operation of thought merely mecha-
nical, and invert the obvious facts of the case by
making reason a function of language, instead of
seeing in language a consequence of reasoning.
Formal argument against them is unnecessary.
Their own speculations sufficiently confute them,
which they would refuse to admit to have no other
subject than words. Like the dogmatical sceptics
who asserted positively that nothing could be
known, they are silenced, or should be, by their
own protestations.
It must be remembered, however, that other
opinions beside those of Roscelin bore the title of
Nominalism. It would be unjust to fix it in its
original meaning, in spite of his protest against
the doctrine, on Abclard. It became indeed syno-
nymous with anti-Realist, and descended toOckham
and his school as their natural heritage. But Ock-
ham was really what we should call a Conceptual-
alist. We have seen that he held Universals to
exist, and that really, in the mind ; to be, in fact,
mental forms, singular in themselves, but universal
in their apphcation. Thus every common term
would represent some individual conception in the
mind of the conceiver, which should be apphcable
indifferently, and without variation, to many exist-
ing things. This opinion, if it be not all the truth,
is true as far as it goes, and was, at the time, anta-
gonist to a mischievous error. For Ockham taught
also, as we have seen, negatively, that a Universal
is not a substance existing external to the mind.
This was the opinion of the Reahsts of his day.
Though realism in some of its modified forms had
not always necessarily imphed so much. At first
it was merely a protest against those who assigned
to Universals only a nominal existence. It was con-
cluded that they existed real/i/ ; — whether in the
mind or external to it, by themselves or in composi-
tion, was left as yet undecided. So if we refer to
the sects of Reahsts mentioned by John of Salisbury,
we find one division holding that the whole aggre-
gate of individuals was the Universal. There is
nothing extravagant, fanciful, mystical, or irrational
in this view ; it has been held very commonly by
hard-headed men in our own day ; it differs from
that of Ockham only by the omission of a step
which may easily be supplied. The two opinions
72
NOMINALISM AND RKALlSM.
meet in the following formula — the common noun
represents an individual conception which is derived
from some known individuals of the class, and is
applicable to them all, known and unknown.
Against this form of ReaHsm, Ockham did not put
in a protest.
Neither do his arguments apply directly to the
second class of ReaHsts mentioned by John of
SaHsbury, who held, as he informs us, that the
Individual, as containing the whole essence of the
class, was, in a certain point of view, itself the
Universal. This opinion was declared to be obsolete
by the authority who has recorded it. It was very
probably the teaching of William of Compeigne,
whom Abelard prided himself on having subdued.
We cannot assign it any definite value, when
detached from the other opinions of those who
entertained it. Thus much only we can be sure of,
that it destroyed the strong and natural antithesis
between Individual and Universal, by a form of
speech in which they were represented as nearly,
if not quite, identical. The tendency of the error
would depend on circumstances. More than one
authority has endeavoured to connect with the
scholastic Realism the doctrine of Spinosa, that
God is the one substance of which all things are
modes. This is probably a mistake, but it suggests
an example to our present purpose. That doctrine,
always mischievous to the last degree, becomes
practically either Atheism or Pantheism, according
NOMINALISM AND REALISM.
73
as he who adopts it, taking his notion of substance
from the world around him, degrades his conception
of God to suit it : or, on the other hand, starting
with some high theory of the First Being, interprets
all else by it, and raises all forms of existence which
meet his eye to a level which is inconsistent with
sense and reason. In like manner, he who should
assert that Individuals and Universals are the same,
would be a most unintelhgible mystic, if he took
the common view of a Universal ; an equally
unintelligible sensualist, if he adopted the ordinary
notion of an Individual.
The dominant Reahsm of the Schools was, as we
have seen, of another kind, and regarded the Uni-
versal as a substance in some way existing in the
Individual. The manner of its existence therein
was, it will be remembered, the point of dispute
between the Thomists and Scotists. Against
either shape of the doctrine Ockham has left us
little to urge. His arguments are to the point,
and conclusive; and have moreover this great
advantage, that he from education and familiarity
most likely understood, to a degree impossible to
us, the meaning of the position he aimed at over-
throwing.
The remaining kind of ReaUsm is that to which
nobler minds are naturally prone, and which owes its
origin to the divine Plato. That method of stating
his doctrine of Ideas, in which they are regarded as
existing in the mind of God, seems to admit of
74
NOMINALISM AND REALISM.
an easy defence. Surely, it may be argued, if the
creation was, as we know it was, orderly and
regular; if the clash of circumstances did not
develope the different gradations of Being out of
a primitive chaos, but class after class came into
existence at the bidding of the Divine Word ;
there can be no error in looking to that Eternal
Word as the seat of Universals. These are not
merely the aggregate of individuals, much less the
conceptions which we have derived from them,
still less that language which so imperfectly ex-
presses thoughts imperfect in themselves ; but abide
rather in that unchangeable Word, from whom
things, and conceptions, and language, alike pro-
ceed.
A few words on this view of the subject may be
said by way of conclusion.
We may observe, in the first place, that a state-
ment like this, however pious and true, does not
amount to Realism, unless coupled with some
further hypothesis. Realism requires that the
Universal shall exist as a substance, in the highest
category, and not merely as an attribute. So that
according to the Scholastic method of treating
such subjects, we must enter into the (juestion
how Ideas exist in the Divine Mind, and deteiTriine
that they inhere as substances in a higher Sub-
stance, before we can be Realists indeed. And
this was the opinion of most authorities, from
Boethius downward. But at present we shall
NOMINALISM AND REALISM.
75
probably be of opinion, that such a question
cannot be answered one way or the other, without
considerable danger of carrying speculation beyond
the legitimate sphere of reason.
But, waiving this objection, a further caution is
necessary to those who think Realism thus con-
genial with their Theology. Granting that all true
and genuine Universals have their seat in the
Divine Mind, a further question arises — what are
true and genuine Universals ? Surely we cannot
boldly assume, that every common term, in the
present state of language, is true to its original
purpose. With all our ignorance of the nature of
things, all our mistaken speculations, all our con-
ventionalities of thought and language, can we
venture to think, that we have always exercised
the powers of abstraction and generalization aright ?
And, in default of such rightful exercise, who can
answer that the Universals on which we have
fixed are true? Who shall say, that the classes
which we have formed are in all cases grounded on
the nature of things, and correspond to the in-
tention of the Divine Author of the gradations of
the universe ?
We take for granted, and justly, the correctness
of our own involuntary and spontaneous clas-
sification. What we do insensibly, we generally
do rightly. We need not fear that we are wrong,
in classing all men, or all animals, or all virtues, or
all colours, or all sounds together. But when, by
I
76
NOMINALISM AND REALISM.
NOMINALISM AND REALISM.
77
a laborious effort of the mind, we endeavour to
arrange these classes, which we gained without
such effort, in subordination to each other ; when,
for instance, we would ascertain the precise relation
in which the class man stands to the class animal,
we cannot answer for our success. Viewed as a
statement of abstract truth, if the zoological ar-
rangement of Linnaeus was right, that of Cuvier is
wrong. Only when we are assured on the best
evidence, that we have attained to the real order
of things, and understand their relative position in
the scale of creation, can we assert positively that
our class terms are valid, and represent any natural
Universal. To make the assumption at an eariier
stage, would be, in all probability, to fix ourselves
irrevocably in error.
We should begin, therefore, at any rate, in our
enquiries by adopting the Conceptualist, or, as we
might fairly call it, the Occamist hypothesis. We
should first of all ascertain that our terms are
definite, as representing some distinct mental
image, and if they be so, thus far be content with
them. But, this point ascertained, we come, if we
prosecute our enquiry, to another doubt. How
far do these conceptions, definite though they be,
find their correlatives in the nature of things?
What proof is there, that, when we arrange these
under some wider conception, or, on the other
hand, group lower classes and individuals under
them, our arrangement can claim the title of
t
natural? Unless we can claim this dignity for it,
we cannot set a high value on our class-terms.
They will stand at best as symbols of a provisional
classification, which greater research, or more skil-
ful analysis, may at any moment supersede.
To begin therefore by assuming that even the
most modified form of Realism is true on the exist-
ing state of things would be to begin with a mistake.
It stands in this respect on a par with the scho-
lastic system as a whole ; it is a great aspiration
which has never yet been verified. We may
cherish it as an ideal, but as nothing more. Our
knowledge is far too imperfect to allow us to assert
that we class the phenomena of the world at large
uniformly according to their natural classes. In
some provinces of science, the work has been
readily and satisfactorily accomplished. We have
no hesitation in aflSrming that, in Mathematics, the
divisions of figures according to the number of their
dimensions, of lines into curved and straight, of
angles into right, acute, and obtuse, of quantities in
general into equal and unequal, are really natural,
and give us the knowledge of natural kinds. On
other subjects, as in Botany, we seem to have
approximated to a true classification, though the
fine of demarcation between the several classes is
far from being, in all cases, accurately drawn at
present. Sometimes, as in the case with Zoology,
it seems doubtful if the problem has been solved ;
sometimes, as with Mineralogy, the work still re-
78
NOMIiNALiSM AND REALISM.
mains to be accomplished ; if the chrystallographic
Idea be true, the arrangement of conceptions under
it is quite incomplete. On the whole, we must be
content to allow that the Conceptualistic view of
Universals is true at present : the Realistic view,
with some limitations and cautions, may be true
hereafter.
CHAP. IV.
THE MODERN VIEW OF THE RELATION OF LOGIC
TO SCIENCE.
The deductive method of investigation, though
theoretically the most perfect, has, when applied
to most subjects, important practical defects. Its
very ideal perfection destroys its actual utihty.
That it may be valid, there must be perfect
coherence among its parts, perfect dependence on
first premises. One probabihty, admitted, destroys
the certainty of the whole ; one falsehood anni-
hilates its value. No compensating apparatus can
make up for the presence of a doubt, or remedy
the consequences of a single error. Even omissions,
which are not positive errors, are equally fatal to
its pretensions : an element of calculation, left out
at the beginning, cannot be introduced afterwards.
There is no provision for accommodating fresh
principles when the reasoning has once begun.
There may be no doubt, no retraction ; all must
be unhesitating progress onwards.
The scholastic system, then, might naturally be
expected to fail. It was a mould far too fine and
exquisite for the material to be shaped in it. Had
all its premises been necessary truths, the scheme
\
80
THE MODERN VIEW OF THE
RELATION OF UXJIC TO SCIENCE.
81
would have been unexceptionable. Proof might
have hung on proof in continual succession. But
neither Aristotle nor the Fathers were infaUible,
either in principles or facts. Nor can the words
of Scripture be taken always as expressing the
literal truth on subjects not religious. We allow,
for instance, the fallaciousness of the argument
from Holy Writ against Gahleo. The Schoolmen
would have asserted its validity, as their admirers
did. They over-rated in fact altogether the mo-
dality of their premises. They argued from data,
which were general rules at the best, and often
only probable in a low degree, and sometimes
capable of being proved false by very little enquiry,
as if they were absolutely true, and immutable laws
of the universe. We know how rapidly the value
of probabilities decreases when they are combined
deductively. One fraction multiplies into another,
and the thread of hkelihood spreads out into the
merest possibility. We soon become incapable
of affixing to conclusions thus gained any practical
value. The argument may serve as a clue to
guide us, but not as a chain on which we can
depend. If they relate to matters of experience,
we call in observation or experiment to confirm
them ; if they cannot be so verified, we corroborate
them by analogy, or example, or some other such
compendious aid to proof. If these fail us, we
must leave them without assigning them any im-
portance, till they are proved or disproved by some
process of reasoning less high in its character than
the deductive, but better suited to the matter in
hand.
The fate of the scholastic Philosophy may serve
to illustrate these remarks. Boldly did it proceed
at first, ramifying in all directions in dependence
on its central trunk. Descending by degrees from
broad Universals and elevated speculations, it
came at length to the region of practical truth.
And here the great mental defect of the Schoolmen
betrayed itself. Their perceptive powers were
quite sacrificed to the reflective. They neither
used observation on the creatures of the world
without, nor employed imagination in creating a
new world within. Therefore they seem to have
reasoned and written mechanically, and without
any object external to the process of reasoning or
writing itself. It would be hard to say at what
their Philosophy aims, except its own complete-
ness. When consequently in their course they
came to the line which marked the sphere of
actual life and conduct, no instinct bade them stop.
They traversed the level of ordinary thought
without heed or remark, only to descend below it.
A few steps sufficed for the passage from a question
as to the nature of the Divine understanding, or
the laws which limit the operations of God, to a
discussion of some minute metaphysical question, or
the discovery in some ordinary word of some half
dozen senses, which none but a master-schoolman
G
^
8-2
THE MODERN VIEM OF THE
RELATION OK UHilC TO SCIENCE.
88
could then devise, and which now, without some
pupillage, it is very difficult to follow.
Accordingly, the predominant feeling of the
Schoolmen turned them away from the region of
Physic, which leaves least room for mere dwelling
upon terms, without affixing to them a meaning.
Aristotle's works on this subject as on others met
indeed with their share of comment. But deduc-
tions from his principles would have been apt to
bring a speculator full tilt against some obvious
and opposing fact, which would have pierced his
thin and airy system, and caused it in a moment
to colhipse. Hence arose the necessity of avoiding
this delicate ground, and either neglecting Physic
altogether, or running it up into metaphysical
questions about the nature, for instance, of the
principles of motion or causation, or the distinction
of matter and form. Those Schoolmen who had
the strongest physical turn seem aliens from their
brethren. Roger Bacon ranks with them in little
beside date. And the vast learning of Albertus
Magnus has had small hifluence on the world,
when compared with the acute and systematic
deductions of his great pupil Aquinas.
Thus the ultimate fortune of scholasticism
differed according to its subject. It naturally
failed first, when the independent observation of
facts caused its truth to be tested. Such dis-
coveries as those of Galileo with regard to the
falsity of the once-received laws of motion involved
(
H
f
I
I
the system in disgrace. Consequences could not
be trusted where premises were so false ; and when
one set of premises had signally given way, httle
confidence could be placed on any other which
rested on like authority.
Botany again, which, as connected with Medicine,
was all along of great practical importance, and
which, to be cultivated with any reasonable hope
of success, evidently demands the attention of the
student not only to descriptions of plants but to the
plants themselves, was one of the first subjects on
which enquirers, laying aside useless comments
on Theophrastus and other authorities, betook
themselves, first of all, to the study of facts, and
those gained, to their classification and arrange-
ment.
So on a third and more important topic ; the
Schoolmen had fashioned Theology after their own
mind, and incorporated with it their own views of
Church authority, and a characteristic doctrine of
the Sacraments. These were something more than
speculative opinions; and these too received a
heavy blow at the Reformation. '
But, in Morals and Metaphysic, and Method in
general, as distinct from its application, their
system long lasted on, to a great degree unques-
tionable. Ultimately it sank into neglect only on
account of its evident unprofitableness. It ex-
patiated at its own pleasure, and sufficiently widely
to prove itself migatory. Or, like a force expend-
ed 2
84
THE MODERN VIEW OV Till
ing itself in a vacuum, it met with nothing on
which to act, and was therefore of no calcuhible
vahie. The walls and bulwarks stood entire, but
they were also undefended; the city was deserted
by its old inhabitants, and the enemy thought
demolition unn.ecessary labour''.
The endeavour then to work out the Aristotelian
idea of Wisdom had failed. Philosophy had made
the eff'ort, and, now^ that its ill success w^as evident,
seemed dispirited and remiss, unable to be satisfied
with the result of its labours, and yet with no
heart to I)egin them anew. She needed some
novel Idea to stimulate her exertions, to give a
fresh interest to her old field of S])eculation, and
serve ns a clue in her resumed researches. Such
an Idea was given by the virtual fatlun' of modern
philosophy, Lord Bacon.
His work was in many respects closely like that
of Aristotle. Neither the author of the old or of
■^ Jt i^ cjinoiis to see, how, in luanv cases, the old lorni reiiiahied
vvhe)i tlic substance was dej)arled — how, for instance, Sanderson,
having treated at length of the Predicanjents in the earlier parts of
his Logic, crtvfs, toward^ i close, as examples of a poj)ular
arrar.gcnipnt ■ i cunnnon -places, the distribution of facts under
oitli " '^' ' ' ^^n»efjori»'<, oi ilie ten Comnumdnients. (Append.
Pos . in. 11. ' ): 1m»\v (iwillini, hcialdically faithiul to ihe
past, porliiuis o\u i, " throw arguments in actual dis-
putation, and not in mere school exercisej^, into the strict di;dectit
tbnn. (Cardwell, Hist. otCun ference-, p. MM.)
UELATION OF LuulC TO SCIENCK.
85
the new Organon elaborated the system of which
lie was to bear the honours hereafter. Each pro-
posed an Idea, which was left for others to adopt
and perfect. The collections of each in the way
of facts and materials were comparatively worth-
less. They were great generals, the labour of
whose hands w^as of little importance when com-
pared to the weight of their conmiands-. Each
displayed that boldness which is one of the surest
auguries of success; and, in his day, called the
attention of all, with a confidence which created
confidence in its turn, to his own Idea of Perfect
Science.
Nor was the form which this Idea assumed on
the respective minds of these great thinkers so
difi'erent as we are ai)t at first to hnagine. Lord
Bacon does not seem to have thought less highly
of the possible results of scientific research than
Aristotle. They both looked to the absolute unity
of all knowledge as its state of ideal perfection,
without declaring positively whether they thought
such state attainable or not. Thev both thouo'ht
that Philosophy would find its fidfilment in the
subordination and arrangement of many truths
under one. They differed mainly in the method
by which they thought this subordination and
arrangement was to be attained. They adopted
each his own mode and order of investigation,
while they looked to the c lul of investigation as
ojie itnd the same.
86
THK MODKRN VIEW OF THE
The Aristotelians (perhaps it is safer and fairer
here to speak of the pupils than of the master)
made, as we have seen, the Many depend upon the
One. They took that order of Science, which,
though it be that of the Divine Mind, is one which
requires more perfect discernment and accuracy
in its application to general subjects than we can
command. One metaphor seems to have been con-
tinually before their minds, most suitable to the
whole aspect of their system, and recommended to
Christians still more by its use in Holy Writ — that
of the Tree of Knowledge. All the ramifications of
Truth were sui)ported actually by its single trunk,
as they had been contained virtually in the idea
of Being, its seed. Descartes (a man of such genius
that we the more regret the accusations of plagiarism
from the Schoolmen, and from every other acces-
sible source, which are continually l)rought against
him) draws out the figure rather happily. " The
whole of Philosophy," he tells us, "is as a tree whose
roots are Metaphysic, whose trunk is Physic, whose
boughs shooting forth therefrom are all the other
sciences, which reduce on the whole to the three
principal heads of Medicine, Mechanic, and Ethic—
I mean that most exalted and perfect Discipline of
Manners, which presupposes the perfect knowledge
of other sciences, and is therefore the last and highest
grade of Wisdom. Just then as fruits are gatliered
neither from tlie roots of trees nor from the trunk,
but only from the end of the boughs; so the chief
RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCK.
87
use of Philosophy hes in those parts of it which are
necessarily the last to be learned \"
Appropriate as this figure is, expressing not only
the form and configuration, but the natural deve-
lopment and inward growth of a philosophical
system, the fiict could not at last be denied, that
the scholastic tree was withered, if not dead;
stretching forth bare boughs through the heavens,
and fixed, not by roots, but by its sheer bulk and
ponderosity.
Lord Bacon at once inverted the method, and
supplanted the metaphor. Just as Copernicus,
when he perceived the endless complexity in-
volved in the supposition that the sun moved
round the earth, tried, and successfully, to attain
a simpler expression of the facts of Astronomy
by supposing the earth to move round the sun :
just as, in later times, and with far more doubtful
success, Kant, acting on this earlier example,
endeavoured to reduce Metaphysic to a simi-
lar basis, by making our conceptions determine
phenomena, and not, as had been previously
assumed, phenomena determine our concep-
tions; so Lord Bacon, standing between the
two thinkers both in time and in intellectual
position, with a keen perception of either kind of
truth, curious both in facts and laws, in Physic
and in Metaphysic, ventured on tlie experiment,
from which so much good has resulted, of in-
'' Fridiil. ad Prificipia Philo!hysic and the eternal and immutable
90
THE MODERN VIEW OF THE
truths of nature, withdrawing his mind for a time
from the flux of things, without at the same time
touching on Natural Theology ; so ready and
natural is the passage from the vertex of the
pyramid to things divine V
This was the new turn which Lord Bacon gave
to Philosophy. Science appeared to him more
material, and less formal, than it had seemed to
his predecessors. They had regarded their method
as something like a principle of life, which super-
seded the ordinary conditions of inanimate nature,
and enabled them to widen out their knowledge,
as it were, from the basis upwards. Just as
organization brings about results which cannot
chemically be accounted for; just as the hiw of
crystallization seems for a time to suspend the
operation of the laws of gravity ; so it appeared
to them that the conditions of thought could
control and regulate the conditions of Being.
Reasoning was something more than the scaffold
by means of which the building was erected : it
was part of the building itself.
The fabric of knowledge presented itself to
Lord Bacon in a different light. He thought that
the tendency of former times had been to over-
rate the powers of reason. His apprehension was,
that the lawful construction of a Science might be
sacrificed to the love of method and consistency.
He reminds his reader that " it is natural for the
■■ Do Aiifijin. Scicntianiii), lil). ii. ad. iiiit.
RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE.
91
mind of man readily to imagine greater order and
equality in nature than it finds there '^;" that it
" needs not the addition of wings, but rather a
burden as of lead, to bar all leaping and flying ^"
He allowed no power to the intellect of antici-
pating observation and experiment. The instru-
ments of Science, he thought, had hitherto cor-
rupted Science itself. Plato had spoiled it with
Theology, Aristotle with Logic, Proclus with
Mathematics^. So he proposed to make know-
ledge a congeries of facts, which hke a pyramid
would hold together by the natural force of
cohesion. None of the apparatus employed in
raising it was ultimately to be incorporated with
it. Induction was to become a great engine,
which all could work, and all with equal success.
His method of investigation was to equalize all
intellects^, and this on every subject : for, he tells
us, "as vulgar Logic, which governs its subjects
by syllogism, pertains to all Sciences, and not to
physical Science only ; so likewise our Logic,
which proceeds by induction, embraces alP."
There is always a danger of riding a metaphor
to death, especially when it is so natural and true,
as to combine itself with the direct argument, and
become undistinguishable from it. Perhaps Lord
Bacon has been guilty of this mistake, not an
uncommon one with rapid and powerful minds, to
" Nov. Org. lib. i. §. 45.
'^ lb. §. 122. " lb. §. 127.
lb. §. 104.
' lb. §. 96.
1
1
92
THE MODERN VIEW OF Til!
whom it does not occur that their own energy of
thought may have found but an insufficient ex-
ponent, and that the tired Pegasus may cease to
answer to the spur. The thorough adoption of
this pyramidal theory of knowledge implies a
great assumption — nothing less than this, that
while the order and arrangement, which the facts
of Science fall into, is really essential ; that de-
pendence and consequence, that necessary con-
nection among them, which the mind can in some
cases trace, and is eager to trace in all, is not
essential. It implies, what, to say the least, has
never yet been established, that the Idea of a
Science, the nucleus around which all its facts
cluster, the principle of that unity wliich Lord
Bacon himself insisted upon, is itself merely a
generalized fact, true in no other and in no higher
sense than the phenomena which fall under it.
Thus reason is hnvered unnecessarily, and deposed
from the throne which observation is unfit to
occupy. The Schoolmen had thought to move
the world without a fulcrum for their intellectual
lever: Lord Bacon doubted the levei > >tiviigLh,
even were the fulcrum given.
We need scarcely remark, that neither idea ol
Science has prevailed exclusively since his time.
Men have not been every where hibouring like
Egyptian slaves at perfecting the pyramid of Truth
by the mechanical application of the engine called
Induction. Deduction is still extant in the world.
KKLATIOX or LO(iIC TO SCIENCE.
9:^
I
and shows signs of vigorous life. Intellect, in
spite of all its idols, is still in request. There is
no innnediate probability that any organon will
succeed in obliterating the practical distinction
between ordinary and extraordinary minds. Mo-
dern Science is content to aim at that unity which
both the Schoolmen and Lord Bacon sought, by
the method of either indifferently. The subject
on which it is engaged determines whether it
shall follow^ out the idea to its consequences, or
arrange phenomena under an idea. In one
respect, we are less hopeful now% than the sage of
Verulam was. We do not hesitate to pronounce
the absolute unity of all knowledge impossible to
the human mind. Far less is it thought, that the
formal imity of Logic is at all equivalent to a real
unity of Science. Logic, as we shall presently
see, is held indeed to stand in a shghtly different
relation to induction and deduction ; but in neither
case is it supposed to give both matter and form,
or so to extend form, as to enable us to dispense
with matter. Its monarchy is now more sure,
because limited. From being, in turn, a part of
Philosophy, and the whole, it has descended to
the leV'cl of an instrument.
/
ON THE DIFFERENT MODERN SCHOOLS OF LOGIC.
95
CHAP. V.
ON THE DIFFERENT MODERN SCHOOLS OF LOGIC.
Logic, then, it is now generally allowed, is only
an instrument of Philosophy — an instrument as
contrasted with a part; not involved in the idea,
or necessarily hound up in its existence ; not even
an universal preliminary of Science, though it may
be indispensable to some minds, and highly useful
to all. Enough will be granted to show its im-
portance, if it be admitted, that scientific research,
and scientific statement, become more easy by its
means; enough also to attach interest to the
question, which we will now proceed to discuss —
how does Logic prove itself to be thus instrumental
to Philosophy ?
The correct answer to this enquiry is also the
obvious one. Philosophy, it is answered, is elabo-
rated by the mind of man; and correctness of
process is an ordinary though not an invariable
condition of correctness of result. It is by regu-
lating thought, or the act of the rational mind,
that Logic is instrumental to its end. It gives
neither facts, nor ideas under which to combine
them ; but by its analysis of the mental operations.
it enables us to test the correctness of the com-
binations of phenomena, the conclusiveness of the
consequences from an idea.
There is however more than one school of
thinkers, who regard Metaphysic (using that word
in the sense of a science of thought) as impossible ;
or at least as doubtful, and deceptive, and a fair
object of suspicion. These, while they allow
the utility of Logic, prefer accounting for it in
another way than that mentioned above. Un-
willing to speak of it as couversant with thought,
or conceptions, or inference, or mental operations
in general, they assert broadly that Logic deals
either with words, or with things.
Thus Logicians, at the very entry of their sub-
ject, begin to differ. They cannot agree in stating
with what they have to deal. The difference
among them is sometimes real, sometimes only
verbal ; but, even where it is verbal, it is sufficient
to prove a broad separation of tone in the contend-
ing parties. The point at controversy needs some
explanation; and, for convenience sake, a name
which involves no reproach may be given to the
advocates of the several opinions. We will then
divide Logicians into three schools, according as
they hold words, things, or conceptions, to be the
subject of Logic; and entitle them respectively,
the verbal, the phenomenal, and the conceptional.
These divisions find no exact counterpart in
ancient or mediaeval Logic. The connection of
f
96
ON THE DIFFERENT MODERN SCHOnrs oi I.OUIC.
thing, conception, and word, was at first much
more dwelt on than their antithesis. The disputes
as to the origin of language did not materially
affect the question. Even those who, like Aristotle,
derived it from convention, admitted this funda-
mental parallelism. They assumed, as perhaps
it were wiser for us to assume, that our mental
impressions adequately represent the outward
world ; that our language does sufficient justice to
these mental impressions. To decide in which
the province of Logic properly lay, was not a
point of practical importance. The regulation of
either portion of the realm would involve also the
proportionate adjustment of the other.
Neither again can the question slide back, as it
sometimes seems inclined to do, with that of
Nominalism, Reahsm, and Conceptualism. Though
some of the verbal school are, as we shall see, the
legitimate successors of the ancient Nominalists,
they should not be confounded with them. Mem-
bers of the three schools may be perfectly agreed
in their view of Universals. Besides, the dispute
is not, like that of old, really extra-logical. How
Logic furthers Science, is a question which may
be entertained without trenching on Metapiiysic ;
not so the other query — what it is that common
nouns signify.
Proceed we then to consider the respective
claims of these rival views to our regard. That
the conceptional opinion is on the whole correct.
}
ON THE DIFFERENT MODERN SCHOOLS OF LOGIC.
97
will be best shown by our notice of the errors with
which it is contrasted. Our first remarks shall be
devoted to the verbal School.
Those who assert, that the regulation of Language
is the province of Logic, may be guilty only of an
awkward method of stating a truth. They may
not intend more than to insist on the intimate
connection between Language and Thought. Every
act of thought, they urge, and truly, is accompanied,
and figured to the mind, by some word, external or
internal. Thinking, as naturally seeks its expression
in language, as feeling does in inarticulate sound.
The relation of the sign to the thing signified is in
each case the same ; though the one is the expo-
nent of the act of the rational soul, the other of
the irrational. Just as brutes express pain spon-
taneously, by uneasy motion, or their natural
cries, so men spontaneously invest their con-
ceptions with an outward clothing. That the
word is not always articulated, matters not ;
enough, if it be understood, Li all probability,
however, were nature left to run wild, we should
think aloud for the most part, and make no more
secret of our thoughts, than children, before the
time of definite reflection, do of their feelings. It
is different in society : an instinct, easily developed,
teaches us, that to utter all that is conceived would
be unwise, as to give vent to all that is felt, would
be umnanly.
All this is true : but it does not nearly amount
H
98 ON TIIK DIFFERENT MODERN SCHOOLS OF LOGIC.
to a proof that Logic must subserve to Science only
by regulating language. Such regulation is the
work not of Logic, but of Grammar. Grammar
looks to clearness of expression, as Logic to clear-
ness of conception. We may have logical accuracy
without grammatical. This is often the case with
reflective persons who have lived much alone.
They tliink methodically and correctly, but fail
in the attempt to communicate their meaning.
And if the endeavour to express one's thoughts
often shows their indistinctness, it does not follow
that the means which expose the defect, will also
serve as the remedv.
But, it may be urged in reply, though accuracy
of thought be really the aim of Logic, this is
practically identical with accuracy of language.
For it is only through language that thoughts
can be transmitted from one mind to another.
Thus, it is argued, the necessary medium becomes,
for ordinary uses, identical with that which it
conveys.
Here, however, there is twofold fallacy. Li the
first place, though language be essential to thought,
it does not follow that accuracy of thought will
always be attended with grammatical accuracy of
lan2:uaN THE METHOD OF SCIENCE.
133
fall at once under certain elementary and received
principles of classification suitable to the science :
thus space itself divides according as it is simply
hnear, or bounded by lines or surfiices : and
geometrical figures in general divide according to
the nature of these lines and surfaces, as they
are straight or curved ; or again, according to the
uniformity or relative proportions of their parts,
as when we speak of certain triangles as equilateral,
and certain solids as regular. Further, when these
conceptions are arranged in order of formal proof,
there is of course a consequentiality existing
among them ; this dependence of part upon part,
and of the whole upon the Idea, being one of the
most remarkable features of Geometry. And this
consequentiality implies a certain subordination ;
for the different ))ropositions do not depend for
proof directly on the Idea, but admit among them-
selves of greater and less degrees of generahty.
Thus the Axioms, Postulates, and Definitions cover
very frequently a wider ground than the particular
Theorems and Problems ; and of these, some are
evidently wider in extent tlian others. Whatever
is proved true of triangles in general, for instance,
applies to equilateral triangles; while the converse
does not hold.
In the next place. Botany may stand as a
specimen of the ClasslJicaiorij Sciences. Here the
Idea may be differently stated, as being in the
abstract. Vegetable Life: or in the concrete, the
' ■■r^.:
134
1
ON THE METHOD OF SCIENCE.
Vegetable Kingdom. The spontaneous observation
of mankind, even prior to scientific enquiry, had
supplied a vast number of conceptions to be
grouped under this Idea. The names of individual
trees, and shrubs, of different portions and organs
of the plant, exist prior to scientific arrangement.
These are duly grouped imder the Idea, by means
of certain intermediate conceptions, which belong
properly to the science of Botany, and may or
may not be distinctive of the different botanical
systems. And in this arrangement a Principle of
Classification is involved — the difference of this
principle, and not any diversity in the detailed
view of species, for instance, distinguishing a
natural from an artificial arrangement. And to
show that the principle adopted enables us to
arrange the conceptions in due relation and sub-
ordination to the Idea, is the task which each
advocate of a peculiar system undertakes.
Of another class of sciences, the applied sciences,
we may take Mechanics as an example. Here we
have one Idea, viz. that oi force. There are certain
principles, further, according to which we can
subdivide this idea. Thus the Idea of force com-
bined with the conception of Rest or Counterpoise
limits itself to S/atics, when combined with that of
motion, limits itself to Th/// amirs. In each of these
divisions there are other conceptions which enable
us to subdivide them ; such are implied, in Statics,
\n ttie laws of solid and fluid (Hpiilibrium, and,
I
ON THE METHOD OF SCIENCE.
135
in Dynamics, in the three great laws of motion.
These, when traced into their consequences, give
us certain combinations of conceptions, which are
su])ordinated to the main Idea, and connected with
it through them by a necessary dependence.
Lastly, a perplexed and complicated science,
like that of Asfronomij, in which Deduction and
Observation find place together: where different
parts of the results are gained by different pro-
cesses, and in the vast array of laws, and inferences,
and general facts, and details, the unity seems
almost broken; forms no real exception to the
notion of a science which we have adopted. The
only uncertainty is, in which of two w^ays it shall
be made to conform to our requisitions. In one
point of view, it must surrender its claims to the
dignity of a distinct science ; and rank only as the
application, on an enlarged scale, of an independ-
ent science to the explanation, or, it may be, pre-
diction, of a vast mass of previously arranged and
classified phenomena. Astronomy thus becomes
the Mechanics of the Heavens. And this is the
explanation of its nature which a Mathematician
would be likely to give. Or, again, the Physical
Philosopher might ask — what is it which enables
us to associate so readily in our minds phenomena
so different as an eclipse, and the com'se of the
planets, and the nature of nebulae, and the form of
the earth, and the distance and density of the sun,
but the presence of onc^ Idea — that of the Universe,
136
ON THE METHOD OF SCIENCE.
or, in other words, of tlie interdepeiHlciice of all
material Nature ? May not Astronomy be regarded
as the science of the Universe, using, for different
purposes, the apparatus both of the classificatory
and applied sciences; and so aiming at the re-
duction to order and unity, under this Idea, of a
multitude of conceptions drawn from phenomena,
which seem at first likely to perplex as much from
their unhkeness as their multiplicity ?
If the foregoing be, as far as it goes, a true
account of the nature of Science, it is evident that
any view of Scientific Method will be in the highest
degree imperfect, which does not treat of Scientific
Ideas, of the conceptions which range under
them, and of the laws which regulate this ar-
rangement. To the first of these subjects we now
proceed.
CHAP. VIII.
ON SCIENTIFIC IDEAS.
A SCIENCE then, however much more it may be,
is at least thus much ; the union and grouping of
conceptions under an Idea. Hence arises a ques-
tion evidently deserving our consideration— what
the nature of such Scientific Ideas may be.
The difference between an Idea and a Conception
has often been drawn, by those who insist on the
distinction, with great care and deliberation. A
Conception, it has been said, is something derived
from observation ; not so Ideas, which meet with
nothing exactly answering to them within the
range of our experience. Thus Ideas are a priori.
Conceptions a posteriori ; and it is only by means
of the former that the latter are really possible.
For the bare fact, taken by itself, falls short of the
Conception, which may be described as the syn-
thesis of the fact and the Idea. Thus we have an
Idea of the Universe, under which its different
phenomena fall into place, and from which they
take their meaning ; we have an Idea of Goo as a
Creator, from wliich we dcM'ive the power of con-
138
ON SCIENTIFIC IDEAS.
ceiving that the niipressions produced upon our
minds throiigli the senses result from really exist-
ing things ; we have an Idea of the Soul, which
enables us to realize our own personal identity, by
suggesting that a feehng, conceiving, thinking
subject exists as the substratum of every sensation,
conception, and thought. Others go further in
the same direction, and argue, that Space and Time,
which they call conceptions, shadow forth dimly
the ruling Ideas of Infinity and Eternity; that the
Divine Attributes are Ideas, under which fall even
the highest conceptions ; that from Onmipotence
comes the conception of Power, from Omniscience
that of Knowledge, from the independent Essence
of God that of dependent Being, and so on. And
this brings us to another grade of opinion, adopted
by some; namely, that Equality, for instance, and
Similarity, nuist be Ideas, the pre-existence of
which enables the mind to recognise things as like
and equal; these too, it is said, having no exact
counterpart in experience, for we have never met
with phenomena which are absolutely like or abso-
lutely equal. And now we are evidently trembling
on the verge of the Platonic doctrine, according
to which each visible and perishable Phenomenon
corresponds to some intellectual and eternal Idea.
Although there niay be much truth in the general
impression which these views convey, they cannot,
with any distinctness, all bo held together. In-
deed, however true any, or, were it possible, all of
ON SCn-NTlFlC IDKAS.
139
^.
them might be, they would nevertheless not be to
our purpose. For we are seeking a practical
rather than a metaphysical distinction; and are
investigating the nature, not of Ideas in general,
but of Scientific Ideas only. Sometimes, indeed,
that which a metaphysician would recognise as an
Idea, lies at the basis of a science ; thus Psycho-
logy (if that be at present a real science) refers
itself to the Idea of the Soul, and Theology to that
of God. In other cases, however, what is called
on the above theories a Conception, is really a
Scientific Idea. It is, for instance, on the Concep-
tion of Space, not on the Idea of Infinity, that the
science of Geometry has been raised.
It will be better, for our present purpose, to take
a different course from that which speculations
like those above suggest; and passing by all such
questions as concern the abstract nature of Scien-
tific Ideas, the manner in which they are attained,
their necessary connection with the human mind,
and the like, to regard them simply as a species of
conceptions— that is, definitely, as conceptions on
which sciences can be founded. Our question
then assumes a more practical shape, and may be
stated as follows— what attributes fit a Conception
to become the foundation of a Science ?
We shall escape one great danger by throwing
our enquiry into this form. The human mind is,
as we have l)efore observed, naturally disposed to
trust too mucli to method, to venture on this
110
ON SCIENTIFIC IDEAS.
presumption beyond tlie bounds of experience and
lawful proof, and, not content with ascertaining
what is, to detennine, as it thinks, what must be.
There have been a priori enumerations on almost
every subject from the planets downward; reasons
have been given why they, and the senses, and the
Categories, and the main divisions of the world,
and the primitive substances of Chemistry, should
be neither more nor less numerous than they were
supposed to be ; till further research has proved
the falsity of the suppositions for whicli these
reasonings were to account, in some cases; and has
rendered their truth uncertain in others. It is
well to avoid any risk of falling into this delusive
and untrustworthy mode of enquiry : and this end
will be effected by keeping the above question
steadily before us — by the presence of what at-
tributes do we distinguish Scientific Ideas from
other Conceptions ?
There is the more reason for taking this view of
the question, because there seems to be, on the
face of things, an absolute impossibility of con-
fining these Ideas, in our present state of know-
ledge, to any definite number. Sometimes con-
ceptions, which have been fated to become the
basis of sciences, have been long altogether un-
known, as was the case witli the Ideas of Galvanism,
Electricitv, and Mat^netism. Sometimes fresh dis-
coveries with regard to a Conception, wln'ch has
been long familiar, elevate it to the dignity of an
ON SCIENTIFIC IDEAS.
IH
Idea. Tims the conception of Heat long preceded
the dawn of a science of Thermotics. Sometimes
the Idea, though it retains the same name, becomes,
from the association of new phenomena with it,
practically so far different, that it may be fairly
doubted whether it be really the same Idea as
before. Thus Optics assumed a new form when
the ray of colourless light was discovered to be com-
pound ; and Harmonics underwent a still greater
metamorphosis, when the properties of musical
notes came to be considered as dependent not
on the length of string, but on the number of
vibrations.
Indeed it would seem, that Science follows as
surely upon Practice in matter of fact as it pre-
cedes it in theory. Let ai^y set of phenomena
once be shewn to be of practical importance to
a large pait of society ; and human industry com-
bines with curiosity in the endeavour to show their
relation to each other. Science will soon be at
work to discover the principle which shall reduce
the mass of perceptions to order. Thus Medicine,
and Theology, win'ch appeal directly to the strong-
est and deepest cravings of human nature, have
been again and again systematized. On the other
hand, where the importance of a subject is of late
discovery, the corresponding science is of late
origin also. The science of Catallactic has only
arisen since the world has been comparatively
peaceful, and whole nations and continents have
14-2
ON SriFNTIFir TDKAs.
felt their permanent welfare to depend on the
principles which regulate exchange.
As the world then grows wiser and busier, as
men expand the sphere of their operations. Sciences
will increase in number, and, with them, Scientific
Ideas. It does not follow, however, that, though
this be true in the long run, each advance of
human Science involves a corresponding increase
in the number of Ideas. On the contrary, their
number may diminish, when two or three ap-
parently distinct branches of knowledge are traced
back to a common stock, and are henceforth
treated as one. So a point of union has been dis-
covered in Galvanism, Electricity, and Magnetism.
And Cuvier has given some hints towards a Zoo-
logy, or Science of Life, of which Botany and
animal Zoology may prove ultimately to be mere
subdivisions. And attempts have been made to ac-
count for vital action in a manner, which, were it
correct, would bring it, according to the different
theories, under either Chemistry or Electricity.
Least of all, however, can we hope to have all
Sciences reduced to that unity, which is implied in
the Scholastic type of Deduction, or the Baconian
type of Induction. The thought of one vast
Science grounded on the Idea of Being, furnished
with its due array of subordinate principles, whether
we call them Categories, or by some other name,
including in itself all possible knowledge, assigning
its place to every producible phenomenon, may
ON SCI I- NTH IC I OKAS.
143
stand before us as a great Ideal, but one which we
must confess is unattainable. Though some con-
nected Sciences may show a disposition to fall into
each other, yet the lines of scientific enquiry must
in general be treated as parallel and independent.
If there be, as there seems to be in the Divine
Mind, a perfect pyramid of knowledge, yet the
apex is so far distant from us, that not only is it
itself invisible, but the sides of the pyramid have
no sensible inclination towards it. Like the vast
majority of the fixed stars, it has no ascertainable
parallax.
What attributes, then, we proceed to enquire,
fit a Conception to become an Idea, and be re-
garded as the basis of a Science ?
It is evident that every Scientific Idea must be
distinct, and that this distinctness should, if pos-
sible, be put beyond doubt by definition. But,
for reasons which shall be given hereafter. Scientific
Ideas can very rarely be defined.
Distinctness, however, though requisite to Sci-
entific Ideas, is by no means confined to them.
It is necessary in every Conception which we
employ, for whatever purpose, in Science, or Art,
or the conduct of life. Indistinctness is that defect
of conceptions in general, which Logic professes to
remedy. If it remain uncured, there can be no
trusting the second and third operations of the
mind, while there is such imperfection in the
first.
1J4
ON SCIKNTIFIC IDKAS.
ON SCIKNTIFIC IDEAS.
145
Obviousness is another feature, which, though
essential to Scientific Ideas, is by no means con-
fined to them. But it is not, like distinctness, to
be sought in all Conceptions. We have a right to
expect it only in the Idea, and in those lowest
scientific Conceptions, which, in the classificatory
sciences (which perhaps exhibit this principle most
clearly) coincide with the phenomenon. Common-
sense, though not equal to forming Sciences,
exercises over them a kind of dominion when
formed. Thus the Deductive Method of investi-
gation requires that some obvious Idea, with its
attendant principles, wiiether gained intuitively or
empirically it matters not, should be assumed first,
and then traced into its consequences. During
this process, it may be allowed to disappear from
the surface of the speculation, to become abstruse
and complicated in the forms which it assumes,
so as to escape the ken of every mind but that
which is truly scientific; but it must issue again
at last into the light of day, and show the result
of its proceedings. Not the most abstruse Sciences
are exempt from this law ; they must l)e capable
of being made popular at either extreme. In
Geometry, for instance, the Idea of Space, the
Axioms and Definitions, on the one hand, and the
enunciations of the particular propositions, on the
other, are at once intelligible to many who find
the greatest difiiculty in perceiving how these pro-
positions depend for proof on their ultimate data.
The Idea of tliat most compHcated of all Sciences,
Astronomy, is perhaps the most obvious of all ; and
the results to which it leads are the most generally
interesting. And how many persons have just the
general Idea of Botany and Zoology, and a keen
sense of the beauty and wondrousness of individual
instances of animal and vegetable life, who on
these subjects find exceeding diflSculty in passing
the bounds of the merest empiricism, and entering
into the spirit even of the outlines of a really
natural system.
It was said above, again, that the practical
importance of a Conception is necessary in order
that it may become an Idea. This, however,
seems not quite the kind of test to suit our present
purpose. In this practical importance, indeed, the
reason lies, which leads the mind of the investigator
to dwell more upon the Conception, and found a
Science upon it. Still, it does not indicate a feature
which belongs to the Idea as such, but rather an
antecedent fitness in the Conception for its after-
wards becoming an Idea.
A more important mark of Scientific Ideas, and
one which belongs to them more properly as such,
may be found in what we may call their generality.
Every Science professes a certain breadth of range.
As there cannot be a Science of an individual, so
neither can there be of a narrow class. This is
evidently natural. We attribute such importance
to the unity of Science, simply because it enables
k
14(i
ON SCIENTIFIC IDEAS.
UN SCIKNI'IFIC IDEAS.
147
US to collect together much which would otlier-
wise be separate. Were its field so narrow, that
observation could thoroughly cover it, or memory
exhaust its details, or common sense decide upon
all its questions by the process of weighing each
particular case, we could much more easily dis-
pense with it. So we are always disposed to adopt
as an Idea that conception which gives the greatest
Generality, the widest possible Unity. So, as we
have seen, the early endeavours after systematic
Truth hit on the magnificent vision of a single
all-embracing Science. And, as knowledge pro-
ceeds, men are, as we observed, very ready to
diminish the number of Sciences by melting several
into one. Conjecture on this as on other points
even outstrips enquiry : as at present some enter-
tain the hope of discovering a single science of
all *' imponderables." The union of Statics and
Dynamics under the common name of Mechanics
illustrates the same tendency. And perhaps it is
to the same cause that we must refer the very
common, and, it must be allowed, justifiable
inclination for viewing Astronomy as a single
Science.
This generality, however, by itself does not
satisfy oiu' requisitions ; we must also have in a
Scientific Idea a quahty which we may be allowed,
by way of contrast, to call particnlarittj. Or, to
use a phrase more usual and striking, though
perhaps for our present purpose less correct. Unity
.:•
\
in Science is not enough, unless there is also
Plurality.
Science, we have said, must have a certain
breadth : but in that breadth it must not be too
uniform. No Universals will serve its purpose,
however wide they may be, unless they are capable
of division and subdivision, and so can descend to
details. Any system, which is deficient either in
Generality or Particularity, can only half satisfy
our preconceived notion of scientific perfection.
A-priori principles of Physics, like those which Kant
has given, illustrate generally the former of these
defects. They are true enough, but, when ad-
mitted, they are too indefinite in their application
to be useful, and cannot be so combined as, by
hmiting each other, to descend to particulars.
The Idea of Being is thus shut out from the
number of Scientific Ideas. For we can invent
few propositions of which this can be the subject.
Scholastic ingenuity could not discover more than
three predicates which were suitable to it— Unity,
Goodness, and Truth. And, after its first division
into Substance and Attribute, the distinctions be-
came either empirical or arbitrary. Causality is
another conception, which has abundant breadth
for a Scientific Idea, but which yet is not the
foundation of a Science. Why is this? because
the number of propositions as to the relation of
cause to effect is exceedingly Hmited ; neither
does the Idea naturally subdivide, and so descend
l2
k
148
ON SCIENTIFIC IDKAS.
to lower conceptions, which the mind can readily
embrace, and in which we feel a practical interest.
But a Conception may have both Generality
and Particularity, may associate itself with broad
Universals, and allow a nudtitude of Singulars to
be combined under it, and yet be unfitted for a
Scientific Idea, if it be incapable of consequen-
tiaUtij, Unless it be such, that the subordinate
conceptions and propositions seem somehow to
be connected with it as P'.ffect with Cause, unless
it be a kind of nucleus of which the whole Science
is a development, we cannot allow it to be really
an Idea. Hence, it would seem, certain Ideas
hav^ been supposed to be necessarily intuitive;
because, when they are once fully understood,
the main principles of the Sciences over which
they preside, thougli gained at first empirically,
assume the appearance of consequences tiom
them. Be this as it may ; thus nuich seems clear,
that every Science, and therefore every Scientific
Idea, implies some consequentiality.
This is evident in the ]nu*e deductive Science of
Geometry, which would fall to the ground, were it
not for the Definitions, Axioms, and Postulates flow-
ing naturally from the Idea of Space ; and the several
propositions which follow being only the legitimate
consequences of these data. The truth is least
obvious in the purely classKicatory Sciences.
Botany, for instance, or Gt3ology, appears at first
sight to be only the arrangement of phenomena
ON SCIENTIFIC IDKAS.
149
known by observation, according to a fixed plan,
and not to involve any notion of consequence.
It might be thought that any introduction here of
Antecedent and Consequent, Cause and Effect, was
quite out of place. Yet .it is not really so. A
purely artificial arrangement, in which the phe-
nomena are grouped according to an arbitrary
principle, has no claim to the name of a Science :
and we shall see hereafter, that in proportion as a
classificatory Science becomes natural, it approxi-
mates to the consequential Type.
All the Conceptions, then, of Science, the highest,
or Idea, as well as the intermediate and lowest, must
be distinct. The highest and lowest must both
possess a certain Obviousness which is not required
in the intermediate conceptions which are employed
to connect them. And further, the Idea, which will
always be a Conception of practical importance,
must possess the attributes of Generality, Parti-
cularity, and Consequentiality. And under this
the other Conceptions must fall according to a
certain system of classification. Into the nature
of that system we may now proceed to enquire ;
and this consideration will naturally lead us to
speak of Definition, which, besides being, as was
remarked above, highly conducive to Distinctness,
is of the greatest importance in connection with
several aspects of Science.
CHAP. IX.
ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION.
In considering the subject of Classification, it
will be of importance to keep constantly in view
the distinction between the principles on which we
classify, and the method which we employ in the
process. The most prominent point of difference
is, that the Principles are material, while the
Method is formal ; the former vary with the dif-
ferent Sciences, being the main Conceptions which
come to om* aid in establishing a connection be-
tween the lowest Conceptions and the Idea ; the
latter, when these principles are given, enables us
to estimate, and as it were to measure, the relation
of the various Conceptions included in the Science,
to the Idea and to each other. Thus the absence,
presence, and number of cotyledons point to the
principles of Classification in a natural system of
Botany; and absorption, assimilation, exhalation,
growth, and generation, occupy a corresponding
place in Zoology. The Method of Classification,
on the other hand, is the same for all the Sciences.
And of this we now proceed to treat.
The scheme of Predicables contains the Method
of Classification which Aristotle in |)art invented, in
ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION.
151
part found ready to his hand, and which has
descended to us through the Schoolmen with
alterations which affect its form more than its
substance. Its most received terms have, how-
ever, escaped from the Schools, and become the
property of the world. Every one who pretends
to knowledge talks of Genus and Species, Property
and Accident, if not with logical accuracy, at least
in a sense of his own. And this renders it the
more desirable that we should retain its termi-
nology, and adopt its spirit, so far as we properly
can. The objections against innovations on received
systems apply here with more than usual force.
And it will appear, that, with some cautions and
modifications, we need not seek a new method of
Classification, but may let the Predicables stand.
It has been customary to attain the five heads
of Predicables in one of two ways — the one, more
generally known in consequence of its adoption
by modern logicians, according to which Species
expresses the whole essence, while Genus indicates
the common. Differentia the distinguishing part of
the same Essence ; and Property, something joined
necessarily. Accident, something joined contingently
to it ; — the other, more agreeable to Aristotle, and
more commonly employed by the Schoolmen,
which begins by separating Genus and Species, as
coming under the predicament of Substance, from
the other Predicables, which are predicated in
QuaHty.
162
ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION.
Now perhaps it would be unfair to object to the
term Essence, when taken barely and without ex-
planation, that it implies of necessity, as it certainly
does by association, an assent to the realistic
doctrine of inherent forms. At any rate, the
formula, which leads us to describe Genus by its
being predicated of things differing in species, as
Species is in its turn of things different in number,
is free from this imputation. But they are both
liable to another objection, which lies deeper —
namely, that they assume our possession of the
power to decide generally what attributes are really
part of the Essence or Substance of any given thing,
and what are not.
In other words, they assume, perhaps unwittingly
on the part of those who adopt them, the possibihty
of a science of Being. If we could, for instance,
satisfactorily answer the question, — what is the
essence of Man ; we should in so doing enumerate
fully all those attributes, in virtue of which the
name of Man is appHed to him. Granting that
he is according to his essence a rational animal,
all other attributes, beside those of animality and
rationality, must fall under one of the lower predi-
cables. We could not raise above the level of
Property or Accident his outward form, his position
in the animal and in the intellectual world, his
condition as a moral being, his capability of govern-
ment or other social relations.
The erroneous consequences which flow from
ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION.
153
'
this view are obvious. If we follow it, we must
allow, that, his definition once attained, no re-
searches, metaphysical, moral, religious, social,
physiological, of which Man is the subject, can
have a valid claim to the name of Science. They
are the investigations, not of the real nature of
Man, but only of certain secondary qualities belong-
ing to him. They misplace Man for the time,
throw him out of his proper rank in the scale of
things, and raise those features of his being which
are subordinate or collateral, to the place of the
highest dignity. Thus the unity of knowledge
would seem to be disturbed, and the natural arrange-
ment of Truth broken into, by a misplaced and
importunate ingenuity.
Such inferences of course cannot be correct. It
is impossible that any one view of Man's nature can
have such right to exclude every other. His phy-
sical organization is not to be neglected, because
we attach importance to his reason : his individual
being has no right to overpower his social ; and so
on. If the system of the Predicables is to stand, it
must be placed in a light which will admit of its
application to Sciences in general. If we show by
their aid the relation of a Conception to a given
Idea, this must not disparage our investigating, as
a separate question, its relation to another also.
In order then that the Predicables may occupy
their right position, we must be content to regard
the whole (juestion as one of relation ; and to
154
ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION.
admit, that any given individual cannot, on logical
grounds, be ascribed absolutely to any species ; but
in order to fix its species, and by consequence to
assign to its other attributes their proper place as
properties or accidents, we must view it in reference
to some Scientific Idea.
Our old example will not be the worse for being
the most obvious and most common. Suppose an
individual human being put before us, and the
demand made that we should fix his species,
genus, differentia, and so on. The problem is one,
which, with the individual alone given, even sup-
posing our knowledge of all the circumstances
concerning him to be most accurate and perfect,
will defy all attempts at solution. Let, for instance,
the given man be Nicholas, the Emperor of all the
Russias. The difficultv will be to ascertain his
ft-
species : if this is accomplished, all that follows
will be easy enough. But how is this first step to
be taken ? Of course, if we are considering Zoology,
or are content to assume, that the class to which
our first natural impulse would lead us to refer
him is really his species, there will be no diflSculty
in answering at once, Nicholas is by species a Man.
But supposing that we are dwelling rather on some
Idea which does not extend beyond the human
race ; that, to take a particular case, we are con-
structing a Science of Civil Government. We shall
then divide men, it may be, according as they are
governed or governors: and subdivide the latter
ON CLASSII K ATION AND DEFINITION.
155
according as they govern in common with others,
or are governors sole ; and this subdivision may be
further subdivided, as they rule absolutely, or under
certain limits of law or constitution. In a scheme
of this kind, Nicholas will belong to the species
Despot, or sole governor without limitation of law.
So, under the Catallactic science, his species will
be Capitalist. And the moralist must investigate
the affair of the Nuns of Minsk, and other deaUngs
of the father of his people, before he decides under
which of his two exhaustive species, the good and
the bad, he must place the Czar of Russia.
A popular instance like this will serve our im-
mediate puri)ose, which is, as we have said, not to
construct a new theory of the predicables, but to
show, under what provisos we may acquiesce in
the old one. And, it now appears, that we are at
liberty to retain both the received scheme, and the
method of attaining it ; on the condition, however,
either of rejecting the word Essence, or interpreting
it as the union of those attributes which are con-
sidered to constitute a Class in relation to a given
Idea,
Adopting, then, this manner of regarding Essence,
our view of the Predicables follows as a matter of
course. Species will evidently be the expression
of all those attributes, which are considered as
constituting the Class relatively to the given Idea.
And the notion of Classification implies that of
order and arrangement. A Class necessarily
156
ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION.
ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION.
157
suggests to the mind the existence of collateral
Classes — standing by its side, that is, as members
of the same division. With these, it will have
certain attributes in common. These will be re-
presented by the Genus, which may be defined, as
the Expression of those attributes which a Class
has in common with its collateral Classes. The
expression of those attributes in which the Class
differs from its collateral Classes will, in like
manner, be the Differentia.
But, supposing certain attributes to be con-
sidered as constituting a Class relatively to a given
Idea, it is evident that certain other attributes
might possibly be considered to constitute the
same Class, when viewed in relation to another
Idea. Thus the word Man indicates the same
Class, whether it comes from the lips of the
zoologist or the psychologist; though the one
looks to the form which animal life assumes in his
fellow-creatures, the other regards the peculiarity
of their intellectual constitution. A question
might indeed be raised, whether the Class was in
either case strictly speaking the same, or whether
we should not rather speak of two different Classes
including exactly the same individuals.* But this
doubt is quite foreign to our present enquiry ; and
the two Classes, if they are theoretically distinct,
must be allowed to be prnclicallfj the samp. And
the point which we have to decide is, in what
light we are to regard those attributes which are
B
observed uniformly to accompany a Class ; although,
when it was formed in reference to a given Idea,
they were quite foreign to that Idea, and therefore
were not taken into account in forming it. The
answer of the Logician here corresponds with the
common phraseology of educated men : both
would agree in calling them Properties ; and the
predicable " proprium" may accordingly be defined,
as the Expression of those attributes which are
observed uniformly to accompany a Class, though
they were not taken into consideration in form-
ing it.
Of the remaining predicable. Accident, little
need be said. Certain attributes are observed to
be associated with the Individual. The question
naturally arises, — are they also associated with the
Class? If this be determined in the aflfirmative,
further questions remain. Do they by themselves
constitute the Class ? If so, they find their ex-
pression in the Species, Should this not be so —
do they go to constitute the Class ? If so, they are
either shared by the collateral Classes, and so fall
under the Genus, ox distinguish the Class in question
from the collateral Classes, and are therefore ex-
pressed by the Differentia. If, though associated
with the Class, they neither in whole nor in part
constitute it, we have already seen that their ex-
pression is the predicable Properti/. If, on the
other hand, they neither, in whole or in part, con-
stitute the Class, nor are observed uniformly to
158
ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITIDN.
ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION.
159
accompany it, they fall under the head of Accident :
and that predicable may be defined, as the Expres-
sion of such attributes as neither are taken into
consideration in forming the Class, nor are observed
uniformly to accompany it.
We are now in a position to enter on the subject
of Logical Definition. For, in common phrase, we
define the Species, by means of its Genus and
Differentia. On an accurate use of these terms
must depend the distinctness of our notion of
Definition. And, by a natural and common re-
action, we shall gain a clearer view of the nature
and importance of the Predicables, by viewing
them in this connection. They are part of the
apparatus and instruments of Logic, and cannot
be appreciated, unless we consider their use. We
shall learn much of them, by seeing them em-
ployed.
In the first place, then, a Corollary with refer-
ence to Definition naturally follows from the above
remarks. It is, that all Definition is necessarily
relative; and therefore that all attempts at absolute
Definition are from their very nature failures, and
may be rejected without individual examination.
To any one who assents to the previous theory of
the predicables, this is an evident consequence.
For if all correct Definition be, as it is commonly
granted to be, by means of Genus and Differentia,
and the predicables be in their very nature relative,
it will follow of course that Definition is entirely
I
r
r
relative also. But we may attain the same con-
clusion by a less technical method, and one better
adapted to convince the general reader.
What is Definition ? Most authorities would agree
in answering, that it is the statement in its fulness
of the meaning of a conception, or, as some would
prefer, of a term. Were then absolute Definition
possible, it would exhaust the meaning of the
thing defined. To take our old example, Man.
If he were capable of absolute Definition, every
conception that is necessarily associated with the
conception of Man, in the mind of the most
enlightened thinker and most extended enquirer,
must enter into it. He could not be defined
under a folio volume. Those attributes which
are observed in him by the Physician and the
Moralist have as good a prima facie right to enter
into his Definition, as those observed by the Meta-
physician and the NaturaUst. If one insists on his
possession of reason, another may dwell on his
possession of two hands, or his place in the scale
of moral beings, or the length of his intestinal
canal. So the Definition would needs prove in this
case an assemblage of most promiscuous and ill-
assorted matter. Or, to take another example,
that of atmospheric Air ; how shall this be defined ?
By the proportions of oxygen and azote which
enter into its composition ? or by its relation to
animal life ? or by its elasticity viewed as a fluid ? or
by its properties of refraction as an optical medium ?
160
ON CLASSI I [CATION ANh DKFIMTIOS.
Those who hold that Definition is absohite, nnist
say, — By all of these. All of these conceptions,
and many more, enter into the notion which an
educated man entertains of Air. And to enumerate
any thing short of the whole, would be, on this
hypothesis, to define imperfectly.
An absolute Definition therefore is impossible, on
account of the prolixity and confusion of ideas
which it necessarily involves. It would resolve
itself at best into a long string of unconnected
epithets. However complete it might be as a
general summary of our knowledge on the subject,
it would be utterly wanting in clearness, and would
prove no remedy for indistinctness.
This being granted, an important consequence
follows. We must be content with relative De-
finition ; and therefore, a Conception will be
capable of at least as many Definitions as there
are Sciences, or, which is the same. Scientific Ideas,
under which it falls.
This, again, the Logician who has followed the
previous reasoning will not be slow to admit. If
all the Predicables imply a reference to a certain
Scientific Idea, the Definition, which is composed
of two of them, will imply such reference also ; and
as the Ideas nuiltiply, the Predicables increase,
and, with them, the Definitions also. But this
position, like the former, admits of being put
into a more practical form ; into which w^e proceed
to throw it.
ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION.
161
All Definition implies Classification. In defining
a Class-conception, (and Class-conceptions alone are
definable,) we undertake to show the boundaries
which separate it from other Classes, with which
it might possibly be confused. But as each Science
has its own peculiar Classification, it necessitates
also a peculiar Definition, by which the Class in
question may be separated from all other Classes
which the said Science recognises. The same
formula which answers the purpose of distinction
in one case, will not serve in another. To keep to
our old example, — can any form of w^ords, suf-
ficiently concise to be recognised by common-
sense as a Definition, be devised, which shall at
once show how^ Man is to be distinguished from
Spirits, good and bad, and from other incorporeal
agencies; and the point at w^hich he parts com-
pany with the brute creation ? or, regarding that
physical structure which he has in common with
brutes, will sum up the features of resemblance
and those of difference, which he exhibits when
compared with such collateral Classes as the lion
and the hare ; and his relation to such more distant
Classes as the eagle and the ostrich; or, further
still, to the oyster and the crab ? What an entire
confusion would necessarily result from the at-
tempt to bring before the mind at once all these
various points of contrast! By one course only
can we avoid it. Man must be defined in one
way, if we would see his place in the Spiritual
M
16-2
ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION.
ON CLASS! FK^ATION AND DEFINITION.
1()3
world; in another, if we would regard him in his
relation to Good and Evil ; in a third, if he is viewed
relatively to the Idea of Life. In many other cases
a like difficulty is evident, which must be met in
the same manner. We should feel a misgiving if
called upon suddenly to define feldspar, for in-
stance, or the diamond. The reason probably is,
that we should be doubting how to attempt the
Definition ; whether we should view them as
Minerals, or bring them under Chemistry — consult
their crystallography, or their analysis. And the
mind seems quite at a loss, and set afloat on a wide
sea of speculation, when called on to define some
Conception which does not fall naturally under
any formed Science. In the absence of a true
Science of ^Esthetics, we feel that it is vain to
attempt a true Definition of the Subhme, or the
Beautiful.
One remark remains to be made on this part
of the subject. It has been said above, that a
Conception may have as many Definitions as there
are Ideas under which it falls. We will now
observe, that it may have more. The same Idea
may be developed by means of different subordinate
Conceptions, which will lead of course to dif-
ferent Classifications, and therefore to different
Definitions. Linnaeus and Cuvier both bring
Man under the genus Mammalia ; though the
one finds his Differentia in the number of his
incisor and molar teeth, the other in his possession
I. -f/.:,*
ill
'W:
of hands. Aristotle, who makes his genus Biped,
completes the Definition by distinguishing him
from birds either by the absence of wings, or,
which comes to nearly the same thing, the restric-
tion of his motions to this vile earth we tread on.
If each of these accounts of Man distinguishes
him with suflScient accuracy from other animals,
none of them can well be called an incorrect
Definition. Yet one of them will of course be
superior to the others. This superiority depends
on the respective merits of the Classification
employed. And that Classification is to be pre-
ferred, in which the Idea, and the lowest Con-
ceptions, are connected by the most appropriate
intermediate generalisations. What constitutes
such appropriateness, it is not hard, in a general
manner, to see. Those have the advantage, which,
while they apply with sufficient obviousness to the
lowest Conceptions, flow at the same time most
naturally from the Idea. By their flowing natu-
rally from the Idea is meant, that either reason
shows a priori their connection with it, or observa-
tion and experiment abundantly establish the same
fact a posteriori. Thus in Geometry the division
of geometrical magnitudes into those of one, two,
and three dimensions is natural on the former
account: finite space implying possible measure-
ment; and length, breadth, and thickness being
obviously the three aspects of space which
admit of measurement. And Cuvier's arrange-
M 2
1()4
UN CLASSIFICATION ANIJ hKHNlllUN
ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION.
l(>5
nient of animals according to the nature of their
respiratory and circulating apparatus is an ex-
ample of the latter kind; it being amply proved
by observation, that according to the perfection of
the organs of respiration and circulation, the
various functions of animal life are more or less
perfectly performed.
It is evident that a Deiinition may in this man-
ner be reduced to those dimensions which custom
and reason have allowed it, and very frequently
to its ideal perfection of form, in which it consists
only of two words, one of which is the Genus, and
the other the Differentia. For, supposing a Class
to be viewed thus relatively to an Idea, it is not
necessary, in order to distinguish it from other
Classes which refer to the same Idea, to enumerate
all the attributes with which we know it is invested.
We only need to draw the line of demarcation
clearly between it and those other Classes. And
this will be done, if we show, first of all, how it is
related to them in the way of resemblance ; which
is expressed by Genus: and then, how it is dis-
tinguished from them by certain peculiarities;
which is expressed by Differentia. All its other
constant attributes come in as Properties ; its
inconstant as Accidents ; and those only, which
are prominent in the scheme of Classification,
enter into the Definition. If, for instance, to the
received Definition of Man as a bimanous manmuil,
it be objected, that many other attributes,
besides those of being viviparous and possessing
hands, are necessary to our Conception of Man,
such as reason, imagination, the erect posture, the
face divine ; the answer is simply, that, so far as
the functions of life are concerned, these attributes
are not essential, and that the Zoologist views
Man with regard to life, and to no other Idea
whatsoever. Linnaeus once went so far as to
describe the ourang-outang as Homo Simius ; and
the practical inconvenience of such a Definition
would not have been sufficient to overthrow it,
if the physical structure of the brute had borne
out, as it did not, the correctness of the Classifica-
tion. Indeed,^t present it may be doubted with
some plausibility, whether the word Man, as
employed in different Sciences, always indicates
precisely the same individuals. Thus an Idiot is
to the moralist no Man ; and one theory of capital
punishment assumes, that the culprit by the com-
mission of atrocious crime ceases to possess social
rights, in other words, to be a Man in the sense of
the Political Science. If this be true, the body of
the criminal who has been executed would never-
theless be that of a Man for every purpose of the
Naturalist.
But there is still room for objection left. It
may be argued, that, supposing the Definition to be
restricted to one Idea, it may still be a very long
affair indeed. The above Definition of Man, for
instance, does not express all his attributes which
166
ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION.
ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION.
167
have reference to life. Why should his prehensile
organs be held to have such reference, if those of
locomotion are excluded ? The fact of his having
two hands either has no connection with the Idea
of Life, or, if it has, must impart a share of that
honour to the fact of his having feet also.
In spite of this objection, our definition of Man
may stand. It is valid, if it marks him off from
every other class of animal whatsoever ; if we are
prepared to say, as we are, that every animal
which is viviparous, and lias two hands and two
only, is entitled to the name of Man.
This seems the place to consider another ob-
jection to which this plan of concise Definition is
liable. It has been argued, that a Definition, which
does not enumerate all the attributes of a Class,
but only such as are assumed lo be distinctive,
though long accepted and approved, may fail at
last, and be convicted of falsehood. A bimanous
mammal, it is urged, may hereafter be discovered,
which shall be formed, in some respects, on quite
a different type from Man, and to which we should
refuse the name, though consistency would urge
us to grant it. Neither is it sufficient, taking
another point of view, to define him as a Rational
animal ; because, it is said, we should not grant the
name of a man to a fish or a quadruped, which
was found to possess reason.
Wc might reply to such instances as these, tliat
Definition is grounded on Classification, which con-
r
templates only existing things ; and that it is hard
therefore to object to it, that it neglects the
creatures of imagination, and makes no grave
provision for non-entities. But this would be
only to evade the difficulty. Cases something
like the imaginary examples given above, actually
occur. Existing systems of Classification are occa-
sionally broken into by apparent anomalies, which
are stubborn facts nevertheless, and must, ulti-
mately, have a place found them. The answer
which fairly meets the case, will also bring for-
ward another view of our subject.
Definition does not, with whatever it deals,
actually give Knowledge. It provides for the dis-
tinctness, not the discovery, of Truth. It has no
alchemical power of turning dross into gold ; but
serves as a touch-stone, by applying which to the
individual, we may ascertain the extent of our
general information on the matter in hand. We
shall soon discover this, if we make a few attempts,
which are by no means unprofitable as intellectual
exercises, at defining. We shall find, that, if we
fail, it is often not so much from ignorance of the
Conception we wish to define, as from our insuf-
ficient acquaintance with the Classes from which
we would distinguish it. A man possessing the
most thorough acquaintance with the ingredients,
and properties, and uses of Coal, could not there-
fore define it. He might describe it at length, but
this, we have seen, would be no logical Definition.
" ; ' )
\
V,
168
ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION.
ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION.
169
If he attempted to select one or two distinguishing
attributes, he would most likely fail in the attempt ;
because he was ignorant, not of the substance
itself, but of the other substances from which it is to
be distinguished. To be successful, he must know,
not only the mineral in question, but other mine-
rals also, and a science of Mineralogy as well.
As then we can only classify phenomena which
we know, so we can only define on the supposition
that such Classification is correct, and based on a
sufficient observation of phenomena. The Defini-
tion of Man can only distinguish him from all
other known animals, or all other known rational
beings. According to the probabihty that other
rational beings, or other animals, in many respects
resembhng him, have, or have not, escaped our
observation, will be the probability that a Defini-
tion, which is certainly valid in the existing state
of our knowledge, will, or will not, continue valid
hereafter.
We are now close upon the great point of
difference between the ancient and modern views
of Definition. We have seen that it is a conse-
quence of regarding Definition as relative to an
Idea, to hold that, though it implies knowledge, it
does not give it. He who can define well must be
master of his subject : and to one who had not at
least a general acquaintance with it, his words
would convey no meaning. Only the proficient
can give a Definition : only the adviinced pupil
can follow it. Suppose, for instance, a hearer to
have no system of Classification under which the
diamond falls, or a different one from that employed
by him who defines it. The Definition will be
unmeaning to him in the former case ; it will seem
inelegant, irregular, or possibly even wrong, in the
latter.
This would not be the case, if Definition were,
as it was supposed to be, absolute. To define a
Conception, would not be in that case to assign it
a place in relation to a particular Science, but to
state its gradation in the great scale of things.
Definition would not appeal to a Classification with
which students only were supposed to be acquainted ;
but would regard all things by the common light
of human nature. On this hypothesis, it would be
intelligible to one who had no antecedent ac-
quaintance with the subject. Thus Definition was
formerly considered as one actual source of know-
ledge. Fresh information was to be extracted
from it by means of the syllogistic apparatus. By
its aid, the imperfections of sense were to be
remedied, and Science carried beyond the sphere
of observation. And hence the importance formerly
attached to the rule, which commanded that every
Definition should be composed of two parts, each
in itself '' better known than the thing defined."
There was a very intelligible sense attached to
the phrase in question. Those things were better
known in themselves, though probably less known
170
ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION.
ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION.
171
to US, which were more universal. They held a
higher place in the deductive scheme, and ap-
proached nearer to those summary laws of Nature,
on which lower laws were founded. Thus they
were more cognisable by reason, just as things less
universal were more cognisable by sense. And
therefore the rule above given might be put in
other words as follows — the Genus and Differentia
must each of them be more Universal than the
Species to be defined.
This rule is evidently binding in the case of
Genus, if, as we have said above, it expresses the
attributes common to the group of collateral
Classes, of which the Species is one. Nor is it hard
to see the reason of Aristotle and the School-
men after him, for making the same demand with
regard to Differentia. They intended, as it has
been observed, that the Definition should give
knowledge. This it was to do, by enabling the
mind to combine two Conceptions, which it had
entertained previously, into a new Conception ; just
as in syllogism from the two premises we draw a
conclusion, which while it requires both, is distinct
from either. It would not be difficult to shew,
that this view assigns a power to the human mind
which it does not really possess, of combining its
Conceptions according to some certain and in-
variable law. Two Conceptions may indeed be
added mechanically one to another; but we can
no more^ predict, in Metaphysic, what will result
f
from their intimate union, than we can foretel, in
Chemistry, how the appearance and properties of
a protoxide will be altered, by its combination
with another volume of oxygen. In either case
we may make happy guesses, but we have no guide
to which we can trust implicitly ; nothing beyond
that tact in perceiving analogies and so anticipating
consequences, which experience developes if it
does not give, and the conclusions of which, in
their most perfect form, cannot, if unsupported
from without, rank very high in the scale of pro-
bability.
But, putting considerations of this kind aside, it
is clear, that if a Definition is, in accordance with
this hypothesis, to give knowledge, it must be
made up of Conceptions, each wider than the
Class to be defined. For, if either of its parts be
only co-extensive with the Class, no new range
will be gained by the mind, which must still be
fettered by the limits of observation. On this
theory, for instance, it would be unsatisfactory to
define Man by his having two hands. Whence, it
may be asked, has the mind derived this Concep-
tion of bimanous ? Since nothing except man is
two-handed, it can only be from man himself. So
the Definition is not really explicative, because, in
order to understand it, we must be acquainted
with man, who is its subject. We may define him
as an animal with two feet and without plumage,
and escape this objection. For though no other
172
ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION.
animal be both two-footed and destitute of plumage,
we may derive each of these notions, animal, biped,
and featherless, from other sources than Man.
In modern enquiries, where Definition stands
not as the source but as the registry of our
knowledge, no such restriction is required. We
are content that the Genus shall be often co-
extensive with the Species. Unambitious of exer-
cising the dangerous privilege of combining Con-
ceptions independently of experience, we only
claim that the Differentia be as clear and as
universal as the Class defined, and seek neither
greater clearness, nor a wider universality.
We have confined our considerations, hitherto, to
purely Logical Definition. We have seen, tliat, in
order to sustain its pretensions at all, it must allow
them to be considerably narrowed. In no suflficient
sense does it state the nature of the thing defined.
It implies no attempt at exhausting the attributes
of its subject. This it views, not as it is in itself,
but only in its relation to a certain Idea. Neither
do all the attributes which can be shown to refer
to the Idea enter into the Definition. Those only
are there admitted, on which the place of the
Conception with reference to the Idea turns—
those only, in other words, which enter into the
scheme of Classification. Thus it is not quite
correct to say, that a Logical Division expresses the
analysis of a Conception. It is grounded on such
an analysis, but does not wholly express it. We
ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION.
173
'
take an individual, and reject those attributes
which belong to it as such. Being thus rid of
the Accidents, we have gained the Conception of
the Species. Of this, the Attributes divide into
those which have direct reference to the Idea
under which it falls, as entering into the scheme
of Classification, and those which have not. Of
these, the former, portioned out into Genus and
Differentia, compose the Definition; the latter
take their place under the stricter or looser senses
of Property.
It would be foreign to our present purpose to
speak of Definitions other than Logical. SuflSce
it to say, that from Logical Definition they derive
their name, in virtue of a likeness and analogy
more or less cogent. But they are wholly un-
scientific, and are useful only as suggestive, or as
affording raw material, so to speak, for further
speculation. Thus Physical Definition is a con-
junction of words which has almost, if not quite,
disappeared from our ordinary phraseology. It
signifies only an enumeration of all the attributes
of the Class defined so far as they are known ;
without any selection, or scientific arrangement,
or grouping under an Idea. It is therefore prior
to Classification, as Logical Definition is posterior
to it ; and from its indiscriminate mass the Natu-
rahst selects what is fitted for his purpose. To
use a distinction of Lord Bacon's, it belongs, not
to Physic, but to Natural History. Thus it
174
ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION.
follows the analogy of Logical Definition, in being
grounded on an analysis ; but here it is the thing
which we analyse, and not the Conception.
Nominal Definition has held its place, but by
a very doubtful title. Its exact nature. Logical
writers find it hard to state. The most consistent
view of it is also the simplest, and that which rests
on the most ancient authorities. We define a
thing nominally, when we show, or rather attempt
to show, its nature, by examining the etymological
formation of the word by which we commonly
express it. This also is evidently named from the
analogy of Logical Definition, being founded on an
analysis, not, however, of the Conception, but of
the Word. Though often highly suggestive, it can
seldom be trusted, unless we are prepared to allow,
that, in forming compound words, men have always
regarded the most fimdamental and permanent
features of the objects to which they apphed them,
to the exclusion of those which are fleeting and
superficial.
Of all the spurious species of Definition, that
which is called Accidental, or, in one word. De-
scription, is at once of most common use, and least
nearly related to its Logical prototype. Without
any attempt at analysis, it merely takes those
attributes of the Class which appear most salient
and characteristic, and calls attention to them as
marks by which it may be recognised, quite inde-
pendently of its relation to other Classes.
I
1/
ON CLASSIFrCATION AND DEFINITION. 175
These few remarks on tlie secondary kinds of
Definition are a digression from our main subject :
but they may be useful in showing, that one
Species only is recognised by Science ; that of this,
all others are, more or less, imitations ; and that,
in every case. Scientific and Logical Definition
coincide.
One possible diflSculty attendant on the previous
views, still remains to be obviated. It may be
objected to the practical working of this scheme
of Relative Definition, that it reduces all Sciences
to a dead level, and destroys their real distinctions
as to dignity and importance. Has Man, as such,
it may be asked, no Definition? Is it of no
consequence, whether we view him as mortal or
immortal, in his relation to the animal kingdom,
or to the spiritual world? Logic will do little'
service, if it thus violates Common-sense, and
overleaps a difference which we observe in every-
day life.
A little care in drawing a necessary distinction
will serve to meet this difficulty. Suppose the
same thing to be defined in reference to several
Ideas. It follows, that each Definition may be
equally con-ect, but not, of course, equally im-
portant. As the Ideas themselves rise and fall in
dignity, so will the Classifications and Definitions
which are founded on them. Thus the value to be
attached to the several Definitions will depend, not
on the degree of their correctness, (for all may be
174
ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION.
follows the analogy of Logical Definition, in being
grounded on an analysis ; but here it is the thing
which we analyse, and not the Conception.
Nominal Definition has held its place, but by
a very doubtful title. Its exact nature. Logical
writers find it hard to state. The most consistent
view of it is also the simplest, and that which rests
on the most ancient authorities. We define a
thing nominally, when we show, or rather attempt
to show, its nature, by examining the etymological
formation of the word by which we commonly
express it. This also is evidently named from the
analogy of Logical Definition, being founded on an
analysis, not, however, of the Conception, but of
the Word. Though often highly suggestive, it can
seldom be trusted, unless we are prepared to allow,
that, in forming compound words, men have always
regarded the most fimdamental and permanent
features of the objects to which they apphed them,
to the exclusion of those which are fleeting and
superficial.
Of all the spurious species of Definition, that
which is called Accidental, or, in one word. De-
scription, is at once of most common use, and least
nearly related to its Logical prototype. Without
any attempt at analysis, it merely takes those
attributes of the Class which appear most salient
and characteristic, and calls attention to them as
marks by which it may be recognised, quite inde-
pendently of its relation to other Classes.
1/
ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. 175
These few remarks on the secondary kinds of
Definition are a digression from our main subject :
but they may be useful in showing, that one
Species only is recognised by Science ; that of this,
all others are, more or less, imitations ; and that,
in every case. Scientific and Logical Definition
coincide.
One possible diflficulty attendant on the previous
views, still remains to be obviated. It may be
objected to the practical working of this scheme
of Relative Definition, that it reduces all Sciences
to a dead level, and destroys their real distinctions
as to dignity and imijortance. Has Man, as such,
it may be asked, no Definition? Is it of no
consequence, whether we view him as mortal or
immortal, in his relation to the animal kingdom,
or to the spiritual world? Logic will do Httle
service, if it thus violates Common-sense, and
overleaps a difference which we observe in every-
day life,
A little care in drawing a necessary distinction
will serve to meet this difficulty. Suppose the
same thing to be defined in reference to several
Ideas. It follows, that each Definition may be
equally con-ect, but not, of course, equally im-
portant. As the Ideas themselves rise and fall in
dignity, so will the Classifications and Definitions
which are founded on them. Thus the value to be
attached to the several Definitions will depend, not
on the degree of their correctness, (for all may be
1
176
ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION.
equally correct) but on the comparative promi-
nence of the Ideas — a subject which shall be
mentioned, though not discussed, at the conclusion
of this Essay.
I
CHAP. X.
ON THE GRAUATIONS OF SCIENCE.
We will now once more recapitulate the com-
mon features which are possessed by all the
Sciences. In the first place, each of them is
grounded on an Idea. Next, under this Idea is
ranked a multitude of Conceptions. Thirdly,
these Conceptions have, amongst each other, an
Order and Arrangement, in which constant re-
ference is had to the Idea. Fourthly, beside this
Order and Arrangement, which either tends to, or
amounts to. Classification, there is some aim at, and
appearance of, Deductiveness, and consequentiahty,
wherever fonnal Deduction, and strict Conse-
quence, are, from the nature of the case, impossible.
Thus much for the common features of Sciences
in general. They will be indirectly illustrated yet
further in the following remarks, which are in-
tended, however, to answer directly a different
pui-pose, and to mark, not the Similarity, but the
Distinction of Sciences ; not their Uniformity, but
their Gradations.
The highest place in the scale is of course as-
signed to Pure Science. Of this we take Geometry
N
178
ON Tin: CiUADATIONS OF SCIENCE.
as the type. Its peculiar and characteristic excel-
lency is, its entire dependence on its Idea.
The Idea, in this case, once given, all the
Science necessarily follows. It is the nucleus
round which all that is homogeneous with it
clusters by a natural law. When once Space is
conceived by the mind, mere cogitation, without
the aid of experience, would be able to draw fi*om
this Idea the Conceptions of Lines, Surfaces, and
Solids, and all the various species of these which
the Science of Geometry recognises. The prin-
ciples of Classification, also, are here exemplified.
They only escape attracting our attention, by
appearing in so natural and obvious a form. It
has been said above, that on Classification follows
Definition. Here, accordingly, a good Classifica-
tion lies at the very base of the Science, and a
corresponding series of accurate Definitions follows
it. We begin Pure Science by defining. In other
words, we commence by positing bur Species, and
stating their Genus and Difference. That result,
at which, as we shall see presently, lower ibrms of
Science aim, is attained before the main labour of
pure Science begins.
Being thus furnished with an Idea, and the
subordinate Conceptions, and the system of Clas-
sification, we apply oiu'selves to our new work,
that of drawing Consequences. And the con-
sequentiality is here Jis perfect as all that has
preceded it. There is no gap between our Data
ON THK (iHADAIlUNS OF SCIKNCE.
179
and our ultimate conclusions. The necessary
laws of inference, when applied to the Definitions,
Axioms, and Postulates, enable us to invest our
Species with Properties before unknown. Squares,
Triangles, Circles, become no clearer as we ad-
vance; for they were accurately defined before we
began our researches. But they do become fuller
Conceptions, as they are associated in our minds
with fresh Attributes. And all these Attributes are
Properties : they are proved to be inseparably
connected with the several Classes, though not
taken into consideration in forming them. In
this most perfect sphere of speculation. Accidents
have no place.
Such then are the distinctive excellencies of
Pure Science. It possesses the highest Unity,
being simply the development of a single Idea.
It begins with a perfect Classification, and following
on this, with accurate and perfect Definitions.
But these merits are comparatively eclipsed by its
most distinguishing excellency, an exact and per-
fect Consequentiality. From first to last, it flows
in one direction, from the Idea downwards. There
is no appeal to Experience, — no desire of confirm-
ation from without, — no endeavour, when the fact
has been derived from one quarter, to find the
reason in another. Every link of the chain of
knowledge holds : and, wherever the process stops
short, it is, as far as it goes, perfect; having perhaps
an unfinished air, but still enduring even in this
n2
180
ON THi: GRADATIONS OF SCIENCK
intermediate Ibnii, aii^l capable of addition withont
alteration.
Next in place of dignity to Pure Science come
the Applied Sciences. Of these, we have before
taken Mechanics as an example. Here, too, we
have an Idea, and a number of conclusions flowing
from certain data according to a necessary con-
sequence. But the Applied Sciences are in-
ferior to the preceding Class in one important
particular. They have not the same absolute
Unity. Their main Principles, though closely
connected with the Idea, need not be deductions
from it, mere phases and aspects in which it
exhibits itself anew. They often need independ-
ent proof, and rest upon the testimony of Ex-
perience. Thought alone could not have extracted
them from the Idea. No one, by only pondering
the nature of Force, could arrive at the knowledge
of the laws of Motion. Thus therc^ is an interval,
so to speak, in the Applied Sciences, between the
Idea and the subordinate Principles, which ex-
cludes them from perfect Unity, lowers the student
from the sphere of pure Abstraction, brings him to
the border-land of the Intellectual and Sensible,
and introduces the contrast, though not in its
hardest outline, between Form and Matter. Thus
tlie province of Reason is somewhat narrowed,
and that of Experience expands.
In this respect their practical appHcation answers
to their theory. Though, the further they are
ON TUli GRADATIONS OF S(TKNCE.
181
pressed, the more power they display ; though they
admit, in ])ractice, of a minute elaboration to an
extent which beforehand would be simply in-
credible; though they transcend the limits of
observation, and become i)rophetic at the time, to
derive afterwards fresh credit from the verification
of their predictions; yet one important part of
their office is to account for the past. This is
seldom the case with Pure Science. That, for the
most part, gives at once the fact and the reason.
It does not usually derive the knowledge of a truth
from some extraneous source, and then account
for it in virtue of certain known laws; but, ft'om
these laws, reaches out to new propositions, which,
but for it, would have remained unknown. Not
so the Applied Sciences, which have generally, in
all their provinces, to account for facts which are
known from Observation and other independent
sources, before they are trusted in the field where
Reason supersedes Sense, and takes a free flight
beyond the regions of Experiment.
But if the Applied Sciences be thus deficient in
Unity, a more serious objection Hes against the
next Class of Sciences, which we call Classificalorij.
Of these, we may take Botany as an example.
They have indeed a sufficiently perfect Unity of
Idea. P^very fact of BotcUiy, for instance, bears
naturally on the Idea of Vegetable Life. The mind
is never in suspense, never seems wandering from
its subject. All the C'onceptions group themselves.
182
ON THE GUADATlOiNS OF SCIKNCE.
whether readily or not, at least with obvious
reference to a single purpose. And therefore the
Classificatory Sciences exhibit, in their fullest
perfection, the system of Classification, and the
practical use of the Predicables. Accidents are
not excluded from their cognisance, as in the
higher forms of Science. Varieties, for instance,
or those modifications of the s])ecies which are not
necessarily permanent, though they seem prac-
tically to be so; the habitat of a plant, or its
ceconomic uses, though confessedly Accidents, find
their place in a Botanical treatise. Definition
also is perfectly exhibited, though its position here
is very different from that which it occupies in
Pure Science. There, as we have seen, the Species
are first defined, and then certain Attributes, which
we at once recognise as Properties, either in
the stricter or looser sense of the term, are affixed
to them by the process of inference. In the
Classificatory Sciences we begin at the other
extreme. A mass of Attributes is phiced before
us ; we have to arrange them in such a manner,
as to determine what constitute the Class (in other
words, enter into its Definition), and what do not.
And those Attributes which fall under the latter
head, according as they are permanent or not,
are distributed into the remaining classes of
Property and Accident.
But the great deficiency of thc.>L' Sciences, in
spite of their combining correct Classification and
ON THE (iUADATlONS OF SCIENCE.
183
Division with a sufiKcient Unity, lies in their lack of
Consequentiality. Let the facts be arranged in
the best possible manner ; the principle of cohesion
is still wanted. The facts must be taken on trust;
they bear Httle or no evidence to their own truth;
they resemble, when combined, some piece of
Mosaic work, which must be held together by a
frame, or it would fall to pieces ; they require
the check of evidence, and the support of observa-
tion. In Geometry, no position of Euclid can be
ignored or doubted by one who has paid due
attention to the treatise, without his exposing him-
self to the charge of folly or wilfulness. In the
Applied Sciences, when certain premises are granted,
all doubt as to the sequel is put out of the question.
But in Mineralogy or Botany, each separate asser-
tion admits of dispute ; the proof of any one will
not serve to estabhsh any other : all the internal
evidence of the truth of a system lies in the
natural air of its details, and the consistency of its
general features.
Is there then, it may be asked, no Consequen-
tiality in the Classificatory Sciences ? May we
not say here, as well as in Mathematics, that the
Properties are traceable to the nature of the Species,
as effect to cause ? When, for instance, monocoty-
ledonous i)lants are found to be endogens, while
dicotyledonous plants are exogens, may we not
say that these modes of growth are consequences,
respectively, of the single and double cotyledon ?
184
ON THE GRADATIONS OF SCIENCt.
We answer, in the first place, that while it would
be rash to deny all consequentiality to the Classifi-
catory Sciences, we may safely assert, that, when
compared to the previous kinds of Sciences, they
prove in this respect greatly deficient. It is certain
that we have here no such knowledge of the laws
of consequence as to enable us to predict results.
No one could have told a priori, that mono-
cotyledonous plants are endogens; no one can
venture safely on hke predictions hereafter. All
attempts at anticipation on such subjects must
depend on Analogies, which often fail, and can
never be more than probable evidence. So that,
at best, Consequentiahty shows itself here in its
lowest form. We must be abundantly content, if,
having traced our facts first, we can discover the
reasons afterwards.
We should further observe, that it is by no
means the same thing to be sure that consequence
exists, that two phenomena are connected as cause
and effect : and to be able to investigate the stages
of the consequence, to have the history, so to
speak, of the causahty. One phenomenon may
invariably, so far as our observation goes, follow
and attend upon another; and yet we may perceive
such a gap in the nature of things between them,
as may serve to convince us that there must bJ
some remote law, as yet perhaps undiscovered, on
which their connection depends. To take our
former example: thus much seems clear, that
ON THE GRADATIONS OF SCIENCE.
185
endogenous growth is the consequence of the pre-
sence of but one cotyledon : but the fact of the
consequence does not explain its mystery; its law
is still unknown. Admitting that the phenomena
do accompany each other, we enquire zvliy ; and at
present, in vain.
We may now briefly state the sum of the previous
remarks on the gradations of Science. Pure
Science, we have seen, is the type which unites
perfections elsewhere separate, and in which Unity
of structure and complete Classification meet with
perfect Consequence. In the Applied Sciences, the
Consequence, when the premises are once given,
may be as perfect, but the Unity is of a lower kind,
and depends less entirely on the Idea. The Clas-
sificatory Sciences have a Unity nearly as perfect
as that of Pure Science, with a Classification as
perfect, and of yet wider range. But here the
parts are bound together by a loose tie, and the
scientific mind regrets the absence of Consequen-
tiality.
One observation remains to be made at this part
of our subject. Sciences are sometimes compli-
cated. Observation and Reason go together to
make up the whole. An inductive process, which
is mainly one of Classification, is to be gone through
before the premises are gained from which the
deduction begins. And this process is not always,
in the less exact Sciences, considered as antecedent
to the Science, but sometimes as a part of it. Thus in
ISCy
ON THK GRADATIONS OF SCIKNCK.
ON THE GRADATIONS OF SCIENCE.
187
Harmonics the relation of theiniinber of vibrations to
sound, though a matter of experiment, is recognised
as part of the Science ; though it serves mainly as
the preHminary to other i)arts, which deduce hence
the laws of harmony and discord as dependent on
numl)er.
Sciences Hke these take their place according to
their predominant element. We nuist analyse
them, and rank them higher or lower, as the Em-
pirical or the Rational preponderates.
There is another Class of Compound Sciences,
such as Geology, and, especially of late. Astronomy,
which assume another form. First of all, a certain
set of phenomena are collected and arranged : a
number of truths are gained by inference, observ-
ation, or both. So far the ordinary procedure of
Science is observed. We state, after due consider-
ation, what is true at present. But another Class
of questions soon comes in. We ask, wliat condi-
tions of things in past time these present truths
presuppose. These are some of the most interest-
ing problems connected with Science. Who is not
anxious to know, what we can lawfully infer as to
the state of the earth in past ages, from the present
facts of its stratification and organic remains; — how
far celestial phenomena make the nebular hypo-
thesis probable ;— and whether the optical ])r()j)erties
of the diamond oblige us to assign it a vegetable
origm
)
nomena that Science, in the strict sense, deals. In
attaining or arranging these, it occupies itself. The
further queries resulting hence, in deciding which
we must infer what has been formerly from what
is now, do not belong properly to Scientific Method.
There is here no subordination and arrangement,
but only a question, as to the practical connection
of fact with fact. We can only ask— does the
existing state of things necessitate the belief, that
another economy, differing in certain given respects,
existed at a certain given time ? Our facts are as
so many witnesses in a court of justice. To decide
whether they prove their point, appertains not to
Scientific Method, but to the ordinary laws of
Evidence.
In cases of this kind, it is with the present phe-
ON METHOD IN ART.
189
J
CHAP. XL
ON METHOD IN ART
We should wander far from the direct hne of
our enquiry, were we to allow ourselves to enter
fully on the place of Method in Art. It would be
no trifling undertaking to attempt an Analysis
of the rapid glance of Invention, or the cooler
exertion of the critical faculty. The comparative
inexactness of Method in this province gives a
wider scope for speculation concerning it. The
two great divisions of Art, the mechanical and the
aesthetical, might put in separate claims for dis-
cussion. We should have to assign due place and
proportion to the skill which adapts means to ends,
the fine taste which discriminates results, the
broad general theories of beauty and fitness, which
the Artist is supposed, often unconsciously, to obey.
We might wander freely on the enchanted ground :
but should soon find ourselves far from the do-
minion of Logic.
Our task, with regard both to Art, and to
Morality, which in this point of view is closely
connected with it, is of a much simpler nature.
We are to avoid entering unnecessarily on their
i
, »
peculiarities, and content ourselves with consider-
ing those features in which their procedure is
identical with, or stands in intimate relation to, the
Logical Method of Science.
Art, then, like Science, has to consider the
relations of certain Conceptions to an Idea. There
can be no true Art when an Idea is altogether
absent. There may be much empirical skill, great
accuracy in imitation, close observation of detail,
but no genius, invention, or originality.
Yet, on the other hand, there seems to be truth
in the position, that Art does not deal with Ideas.
Its work is the production of actual individual
Things. It seems to wander beyond its province,
and confound itself as the case may be, with
Mechanics, or ^Esthetics, or some narrower Science,
when it quits individuals, and meddles with prin-
ciples at all.
These two sides of truth may thus be reconciled.
Art has, indeed, to do with individual things. But
each of these will fall not under one Idea only,
but under several, will bear a definite relation to
them, and be capable of receiving illustration from
them. In other words, the subject of a single
Art lies within the sphere of several Sciences.
And it cannot be expedient to neglect the light
which methodized knowledge may thus cast upon
it. These Sciences can be made practically useful,
if knowledge is really power. And how are they
to be brouglit to bear ? Not surely in an irregular
w
fi":
190
ON METHOD IN ART.
0\ MKTIIOI) IN ART.
191
and desultory manner. This would be a con-
tradiction of their nature. The several Sciences,
which claim so nnich order and arrangement in
their respective provinces, cannot be in a state of
anarchy among themselves. One Science will be
dominant above the rest; and the Idea of that
Science will be the Idea of the Art.
Must, then, the Idea on which an Art is founded
be necessarily a Scientific Idea ? It would seem
not. After all the attention that has been devoted
to the Philosophy of Fine Arts, a real Science of
^Esthetic has never been attained. We have not
been able to state satisfactorily in a deductive form
the nature of the Beautiful. But, though the
Science has been absent, the Art has gone on. It
is sufficient that there is no antecedent impossibility
of such an expansion of the/Esthetical Idea. Mean-
while, Art has lost little of its dignity and nothing
of its vmity ; though it has continued deficient in
certainty. Comparatively little fiiith has been
shown in general rules, and more reliance neces-
sarily placed in the individual sense of the Beauti-
ful.
Art, then, being like Science, conversant both
with Conceptions and Ideas, it is natural to enquire,
to what kind of Science it is most closely analogous.
In its perfect form it approaches closely to the
Apphed Sciences. To the type of Pure Science it
cannot at all approximate. Its constant appeal to
the outward world and experience, its endeavours
to m(*et particular wants and gratify particular
senses, separate it clearly from the range of i\
priori truth. The empirical element, though not
always equally prominent, must be always present.
And if we can trace in Art, as we can in Apphed
Science, not only the subordination of the Con-
ceptions to the Idea, but the reason of that sub-
ordination, our approximation to scientific con-
sistency is so much the closer. Yet such syste-
matic completeness is quite unnecessary for prac-
tical purposes. And it is only when we can brin^-
the laws of number to bear on our subject, that it
can be really obtained. In other cases, we may
well rest content with the same comparatively
vague notions of consequence which we have
observed to exist in the Classificatory Sciences. It
will suffice us to infer from the unity of sequence
that it takes place in virtue of a law of causation,
without pretending to discover how that law
operates.
We shall soon have occasion, in treating of
Analysis and Synthesis, to mention some points in
which Art and Science are differently related to
Logic. Meanwhile, tliere seems a necessity for a
few remarks on the relation, with regard to Method,
of Morality to Science.
i
II
'1/
h
UN MKTHOn IN MORALITY.
193
CHAP. XII.
ON METHOD IN MORALITY
Morality may stand to Method in two different
relations, between which it is important for our
present purpose to distinguish. In the first place,
it may be viewed as a Science — that great Science
of Human Conduct in general, which enters into
the springs of action, and the intellect and feeHngs
so far as they concern action. In this sense, it
forms the basis of Politics and Rhetoric, and to some
extent even of Poetry and the Fine Arts, as well as
of Morality in that second sense, which shall be
mentioned presently. But, important though it
be, it needs no separate discussion of its Method,
being in fact a Classificatory Science; more ele-
vated in its character indeed than any other of its
Class, and, as it deals with internal rather than
external phenomena, proportionably more difficult
of attainment ; but still, conforming to the same
laws, and arriving at its results by a similar
process. Morality, in its second and lower aspect,
is subject to the same conditions of Logical Method
as Art. It might indeed be defined as the Art
of Right Action, did not common usage restrict Art
to a narrower range, and assign to it some definite
end, short of the perfection of human conduct in
general. Assuming then that its Method is broadly
the same as that of other Arts, we will mention a
few peculiarities, which are intimately connected
with its nature.
It is, then, closely allied to those Arts, which are
grounded on some elevated Idea, not as yet made
the subject of a perfect Science. There is no
commonly recognised and admitted Science of
Goodness ; no system of arranging those phe-
nomena of human conduct which we call Good,
on which Philosophers in general agree. At such
a system we have seen many elaborate attempts,
but none successful. Thus the Art of Morality is
dignified rather than perfect; and, where it most
succeeds in accuracy of detail and practical co-
gency, is deficient in theoretic dependence on its
first principles. We allow the connection of the
phenomena in fact, rather than perceive the
reason. In this respect it is closely analogous
to the Fine Arts. Nor can we be surprised at any
extent to which the parallelism runs, when we
remember the close connection between the Ideas
of Goodness and Beauty. But this Art, however
complete, could scarcely be of great practical
utility to those who would become good. Its
advantageous exercise implies the full recognition
of the Idea of Goodness. And, in such recognition.
Moral Excellence is presupposed. Again, we are
o
194
ON METHOD IN MORALITY.
ON METHOD IN MORALITY
195
incapable of using an Art aright, unless we are
familiar, not only with its rules, but with the
purposes for which it is employed. But the Art
of Morality aims at producing good action ; and
good action, pliilosophically viewed, is an internal
phenomenon, which can be known only by our.own
experience, and not by observation of others.
Therefore to apply the Moral Art advantageously,
we must be good already.
This seems a paradox, but it is not far from the
truth. The Art of Morality is practically identical
with that of Education. He who is acquainted
with it applies it not to his own case, but to that
of others. They are, if possible, to benefit by his
experience; and attain the same end, but by a
shorter and more direct process.
There is the more occasion for this remark,
because the misapplication of the Art in question
involves considerable danger. The object of its
rules is to enable those, for whose benefit they are
meant, to realise more vividly the Moral Idea in
general, and to attain clearer Moral perceptions in
detail. But the knowledge of a rule whicli they
think they can obey without hesitation and doubt,
may lead them to neglect the exercise of those
perceptive and reflective powers, by which alone
they can really apprehend tiie Moral Conceptions,
and combine them under the Idea. In a case of
this nature, the endeavour after systematic culti-
vation may thwart the very tendencies which it
I
seemed likely to forward. Thus a loose and
imperfect casuistry, or any casuistry out of its
place, does harm. In the former case, it degrades
the Moral sense which adapts itself to its standard;
in the latter case, it hinders its operation by seem-
ing to render it unnecessary. We should have
little hope of excellence in a painter, who followed
some general law of Beauty which he thought he
had discovered, in spite of the evidence of his eye
given to the contrary side. In like manner we
cannot hold him to be really good, who sacrifices
to some formula of Right and Wrong which he
thinks to contain the truth, the unbiassed verdict
of a reflective and uncorrupted Conscience.
What, then, are the points of resemblance and
difference, with regard to Method, between Art
and Morality on the one hand, and Science on the
other ? We have, it has been seen, in each an
Idea, and Conceptions ranged under it. We have
in each as much Subordination and Consequen-
tiality as the nature of the subject admits. But
in purpose and practical application, as well as in
form, there is a strong contrast between them.
All Science, as such, aims mainly at the illustration
or expansion of its original Idea. In this. De-
ductive and Inductive Sciences agree. Thus far,
the same impression is made by the successive
Deductions which follow in Geometry from the
Idea of Space, and the multiplied phenomena
n 2
196
ON METHOD IN MORALITY.
which we group under the Idea of Lite in Botany
or Zoology. The central unity is brought more
vividly before the mind by being traced and followed
through the plurality of detail.
Not so with Art. Its every-day work of pro-
duction keeps it from this continual tendency
towards an ideal centre. When the Idea can be
traced in the lower mechanical arts, it seems often
to be merely instrumental, and to discharge the
office, so to speak, of an intellectual fulcrum,
which may enable us to bring our Conceptions to
bear the better upon practice. The Critic may
trace the Idea in the Conception ; the Artist is
only careful to illustrate the Conception by the
Idea. This seems to be true even in the Fine
Arts and in Morals. How little need the Artist
be conscious of that theory of Beauty, which, were
he a philosopher, he would in strict consistency
adopt. And how wholly ignorant are many who
act in the spirit of the institutions under which
they live, or are pledged to the moral precepts of
the school in which they are educated, of the
really distinctive features of the system, which
they every day exhibit with sufficient success in
practice !
One other point of difference, and that not un-
important, between the Method of Art and Science,
remains to be mentioned. It will find its place in
the following remarks on the nature and applica-
tion of Analysis and Synthesis.
spondm- divisions in Method, and show a peculiar
fitness to be its organs. Similar coincidences are
traceable in other and minor parts of the Lo-ical
apparatus. These, however, it is not now neces-
sary to mention. They will occur naturally to the
Student of Logic, though they could not be
exhibited in this work without entering on minute
technicalities to a degree quite foreign to its
purpose.
CONCLUSION.
We have now concluded, so far as the phm of
these pages allows, our consideration of Logical
Method. Had they been far more perfect in their
design and more exact in their execution, this
would not have hindered that unsatisfied feeling,
that craving after further Truth, which strengthens
with the accession of Knowledge, and is one of the
strongest though not of the most pleasant motives
for })ursuing it.
It has been well said, that the quest, and not
the possession, of Knowledge, is the entertainment
of the mind. Truth indeed is the one object of
our search; but the pleasures of seeking it are
present and real ; the pleasures of finding it lie in
the future, and prove too often imaginary. Even
when no failure intervenes between us and our
end, the road is almost always longer and more
difficult than we expected. We think ourselves
near the top of the mountain ; and, as we make a
vigorous effort to scale what seems its highest
crag, perceive that we are but just making our
CONCLUSION.
217
way over its first shoulder, and that its misty
ridges still rise before us in uncertain grandeur,
and retreat as we gaze on them.
The reader of these pages cannot be more
painfully sensible than their writer, that, after all
which has been said of Method, its culminating
point is not reached. That highest Unity which
would give a meaning to the whole is wanting.
Granting that all Knowledge which deserves the
name of Science naturally arranges itself, accord-
ing to certain rules, under definite Ideas, the
question yet remains — how are these Ideas them-
selves arranged? Have not they too their due
disposition and gradation? Can we suppose that
there is no standard by which we can decide their
relative dignity and importance ? Centres of unity
and sources of order as they are, are they in
disorder among themselves ?
It is hard to suppose that they are wanting in
this arrangement and subordination. And yet
how can we discover it ? We have surrendered as
a vain imagination that Science of Being, of which
the Ancients loved to speak. It seems that power-
ful minds were permitted by Providence to rest on
the thought of the absolute Unity of Knowledge,
till some parts of Science were so elaborated, that
they could bear, in contemplating their separate
perfection, to dispense with the thorough con-
solidation of the whole. We are almost reminded
of Alexander's attempt at universal empire, which,
Q
•218
CONCLUSION.
as such, failed ; but left, nevertheless, real and per-
manent power in the hands of his Generals, to be
exercised over their fragmentary Kingdoms. Many
Sciences we know^ there can be: we now know,
almost with equal certainty, that, while the human
mind retains its present constitution, they can
never all meet in one.
May there not however be, in the absence of
this Ideal Unity, some one Science, to direct the
rest, though it does not combine them ? As, in
Practice, Prudence, which is not an Art, much less
the union of all, applies and regulates all those
arts which tend, when rightly used, to our connnon
well-being; may there not be in Theory also,
some great Science, or something above a Science,
to assign our speculations their place, their im-
portance, their proportion, their relative bearing;
and make them, if not in fact, at least in tendency,
a Whole ?
One branch of Study there is, which, in virtue
of its very name, points to the Highest of all
subjects, which yet, in its application, reaches to
the most delicate thoughts and finest sympathies
of the heart of man; w^hich tells of Infinity and
Eternity, and yet exhibits truths of Infinite and
Eternal moment under forms which have reference
to Space and Time ; which distinguishes betw een
the Permanent and the Fleeting, — the Principle,
and the Economies or dispensations which are
founded on it; which teaches the importance of
CONCLUSION.
219
all truths, the supreme necessity of some ; to which
a Heathen paid involuntary homage, when he
gave its name to what he deemed the highest
reach of human thought; and which Christians
have delighted to honour with the title of the
Mother of Sciences.
Much she can teach us directly of the relative
importance of truths; nuich more by the temper of
mind and frame of thought she inculcates. She
rules over Knowledge, if by no other right, by that
of conquest: she subdued it first, to protect it
ever after.
And liow far is this fair Mother of Sciences
like her children ? Do the same formal conditions,
which bind them, bind her also? If they do not —
has she another Method of her own ; her own laws
of investigation, and standards of truth and false-
dood ? If they do—how does the nature of the
high and mysterious subjects with which she deals
affect and modify their application ? If, again, she
neither conforms to the ordinary rules of specula-
tion, nor has extraordiuciry canons of her ow^n,
how can the body of truth which she presents be
fairly studied at all ? How^ can the human mind,
prone, not by its perverseness and obliquity, but by
a right instinct and a deep principle of nature, to
seek for order and system, find its highest occupa-
tion in resting on details which may not be com-
bined, statements which may not be compared,
examples from which no principles may be extracted.
M F
2*20
CONCLUSION.
facts which refuse to incorporate themselves with
doctrines ?
He will do a good service to Truth, and Chris-
tianity, and the Church, who shall face these
questions fairly; and, in grave earnest, and after
all due preparation, venture, in a strength not
his own, to treat of a subject which I have not
ventured to handle — the application of Method
to Theology.
THE END.
BAXTER, PRINTER, OXIOilD.
^
11 "^
'j.°';""B;« uwivEHsiry librar.es "-
0021089108
160
C46
BOUNC
JAN •> i957
§
mk
. :it'''
•. (
■-17 -V' ' ■ '
. J ■ . /-,
■ i , A -^
tim^mumii'.!!'.
h mm..
1
SM'^
\mwirmtmEaiMl
mm
mmmi...
(•I Uli:
"itmfs
. 1! :
■M'f
'J77J
w ^v//;m.
i« ' t ^ 1. / .
* /-> , . ; . / .
< « ' I ' < 1 . (
\w(rMM
\m
'm
; t
)
\rt\
1 : ■ -I ■
' 1 • » , -^ 'I
■4/
■A
it
..;/ ,:)!
rT/ IT/