MASTER NEGA TIVE NO. 92-80711 MICROFILMED 1993 COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY LIBRARIES/NEW YORK as part of the "Foundations of Western Civilization Preservation Project" Funded by the NATIONAL ENDOWMENT FOR THE HUMANITIES Reproductions may not be made without permission from Columbia University Library COPYRIGHT STATEMENT The copyright law of the United States - Title 17, United States Code - concerns the making of photocopies or other reproductions of copyrighted material. Under certain conditions specified In the law, libraries and archives are authorized to furnish a photocopy or other reproduction. One of these specified conditions is that the photocopy or other reproduction is not to be "used for any purpose other than private study, scholarship, or research." If a user makes a request for, or later uses, a photocopy or reproduction for purposes in excess of "fair use," that user may be liable for copyright infringement. This institution reserves the right to refuse to accept a copy order if, in its judgement, fulfillment of the order would involve violation of the copyright law. AUTHOR: CHRETIEN, CHARLES TITLE: ESSAY ON LOGICAL METHOD PL A CE : OXFORD DA TE : 1848 COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY LIBRARIES PRESERVATION DEPARTMENT BIBLIOGRAPHIC MICROFORM TARGET Master Negative # Restrictions on Use: Original Material as Filmed - Existing Bibliographic Record C<^Q) I 'fssBv on looical ma+hod' n^ as. Oxford IS<^S. '/ . 11. 7 J ' 0. l+.U + £20p. 753.97 TECHNICAL MICROFORM DATA FILM SIZE: jr REDUCTION RATIO: JiJi. IMAGE PLACEMENT: lA ^ IB IIB DATE FILMED: _^_^^il'^^ INITIALS , •J^'T^^^ HLMEDBY: RESEARCffpi^BLICATIONS. INC WOODBRIDGE. CT »^i7#*yv ~-iJ-' >i> I > 6»4r'«' /'V^I• mu v*^ Y' i^;.. \Q.O^ C^£ in tijc (Citit of |lciu l}ox*h» ^jjffial fxwul OVixtn auoutfmou$lu. •* AN ESSAY ON LOGICAL METHOD. BY CHARLES P. CHRETIEN, M.A FELLOW AND TUTOR OF ORIEL COLLEGE. OXFORD, JOHN HENRY PARKER; AND 377, STRAND, LONDON. 1848. 1^0 c4t BAXTEU, PKiNTER, OXFORD. ^ O TO THOSE FROM WHOM THE AUTHOR HAS LEARNED MUCH WHEN HE SEEMED TO BE TEACHING CO -: . vt — / 180183 PREFACE. In the following pages I have endeavoured to consult principally the wants of those, whose taste for Logic has carried them beyond its simpler technicalities. Such persons will naturally desire to learn how it may be useful in practice. Havincr studied the nature of its machinery, they will gladly see it in operation. It is almost beyond my hope that what I have written may also be of service to some, whose distaste for Logic amounts to a prejudice. Ordinary rea- soning can scarcely remove the irrational opinion, that the legitimate study of the way to knowledge acts mainly as an encouragement to ignorance. That the few examples I have employed are intentionally popular, will hardly be considered a defect by those who know how apt an abstruse illustration is to rival, if not to surpass, its subject in obscurity. VI PREFACE. The very simple division of Sciences wliich I have adopted will excite a smile in some who have approached the same subject from another quarter. But it is perfectly defensible, if the principles of this work be in other respects true. Without being the best or the only scheme, it may yet be valid and Logical. To confess myself conscious of many faults in this Essay, is a poor apology for leaving them un- corrected. They would have been more numerous, but for a reason which I have great pleasure in being permitted to mention. Both the Essay and its Author are under more obligations than can be particularised, to his dear friends and brother-fellows, the Reverend George Buckle, and Mr. John William Burgon. Oriel, June 17, 1848. CONTENTS. INTRODUCTION [ CHAP. I. THE ANCIENT VIEW OF THE RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE. ....... 13 II. THE MEDLEVAL VIEW OF THE RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE QQ III. NOMINALISM AND REALISM 52 IV. THE MODERN VIEW OF THE RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE 79 V. ON THE DIFFERENT MODERN SCHOOLS OF I^OGIC 94 VL ON LOGICAL METHOD IN GENERAI 1-28 VII. ON THE METHOD OF SCIENCE \S2 Vni. ON SCIENTIFIC IDEAS 138 IX, ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. . . 150 X. ON THE GRADATIONS OF SCIENCE. ... 177 XI. ON METHOD IN ART 1^8 XII. ON METHOD IN MORALITV I90 Xni. ON ANALYSIS AND SYNTHESIS 197 XIV. ON THE CONNECTION OF METHOD WITH FORMAL LOGIC t>IO CONCLISION i>|(5 INTRODUCTION. The student of Logic, who takes in hand any of the old compendia which still survive in partial use among us, will observe, that, towards their con- clusion, they all engage upon one common subject, which is, as they differently phrase it. Method, or the use of Logic. To this, all that has preceded is meant to minister. It impHes the earlier parts of Logic, as a building imphes the foundation. Its existence assumes that Apprehension, and Judg- ment, and Discourse, have made some considerable progress, and accumulated a sufficient body of knowledge to require methodical disposition. Thus syllogism is considered as the unit, or, so to speak, the atom of reasoning ; and with its combinations method is concerned. To stop short at the con- sideration of this most concise and simple form of argument, without dwelHng on its methodical arrangement, would be to neglect that application of it, which mainly renders it worth consideration at all. Yet to this part of the subject incipient logicians still want a guide. The able treatise of Archbishop Whately terminates, for this purpose, just too early. He teaches the recruits how each dialectical B 2 INTRODUCTION. weapon may be wielded to advantage ; not how the whole armoury may be employed in concert with good effect. And without any disparagement to later labourers in this field, it may be said, that such other guides to the knowledge of method as are not palpably superficial, start from first premises too unlike those which we semi-scholastics of Oxford still retain to be naturally adopted as instructors in our school. Instead of extending the old line of enquiry, they turn to one which is altogether new, and, where we are expecting explanation, give us contrast. Or their turn is physical rather than logical : they insist more on the facts which method embodies, than on the formal process of their embodiment. It would be wide of our purpose to discuss any schemes of method, which are built on other than a logical groundwork. However true and ex- cellent they may be. Logic is not the porch through which to approach them. And yet it is most unlikely that no entrance lies to method through this vestibule. When we owe to the schoolmen and their successors so much of our scientific phrase- ology, so many of the terms which hang loose between exact and popular usage, and serve to bridge over (for good or for evil, as the causeway so formed is employed) the gap which separates sciolism and science ; when we take so commonly as our material the frasjiuents of their mosaic-work. INTRODUCTION. it seems unnatural and unwise, not to say ungrate- ful, to pay no attention to the plan according to which they arranged them. Doubtless they were fitted for their original use ; and we may learn much from considering the nature of this use, although we may not think proper to adopt it. Possibly, then, the domain of logical speculation is not so fully occupied, as to leave no room for the following Essay. Our object is, to view Logic at once by the light of the past and the present ; to enquire, in the first place, what ideas respecting its nature were formerly entertained, and what questions originated fi'om their adoption : how one race of thinkers profited both by the knowledge and the mistakes of those preceding them, and handed down the results of their labours to their successors, not without a still abiding mixture of error; — and, this done, to show, how truths ad- vancing fi'om different quarters meet at last, and unite peaceably, where we might have feared a collision ; how, as Logic has always of her own free will testified to the truth of Science, Science in her turn bears unintentional but not involuntary witness to the truth and utility of Logic. The former part of this Essay, therefore, is mainly historical; the latter regards rather the present state of knowledge, and aims at illustrating the close connection between logical and scientific method. The general fact of their connection one consideration alone would serve to establish. b2 INTRODUCTION. It cannot be by a mere accidental coincidence that Logic and Science both point to a deductive system as the perfect type of metliod. This they do on grounds perfectly distinct. The logician asserts the supremacy of Deduction, because it exhibits most naturally the powers of his favourite instru- ment, the syllogism ; because it assigns with the greatest definiteness and precision to the pro- position and the term their respective places and importance. The man of science also takes Deduc- tion as the type of excellence, because he finds that, as matter of fact, the deductive sciences are the most perfect. It would not at first strike the logician that Mathematics exhibited the full power of the syllogism, or the mathematician, that his pursuits illustrated the chief exercise of Logic. But a little thought shows either party that there is a real conformity, not only in the results, but in the process by which they attain them. Each is attracted by the same feature in a deductive system, that is, as we shall see hereafter, the perfect manner in w^iich it unites in itself subordination and consequentiality. Where then there is on the whole such general agreement, we should expect to find it pervading the details also. Here, however, it does not at first appear. Science says little of universals and particulars, of distribution and non-distribution, of judgment and discourse. While on the peculiar features and arrangements of each particular INTRODUCTION. science Logic is of course equally silent. But, on reflection, another class of terms occur, which Logic and Science use in common. Such are, conception and idea, genus and species, analysis and synthesis. The vague use of words like these is an evil wliich we ought not unnecessarily to tolerate. Metaphorical in some sense they must be ; but the nature and extent of the metaphor deserves to be considered. And the further ques- tion naturally arises, not only from what they have been transferred, but to whom. Their use in- differently by logicians and men of science suggests the supposition, that Science has taken them improperly from Logic, or Logic from Science. But it is satisfactory to discover, that some knowledge of the nature of method renders either hypothesis unnecessary ; that it is with regard to method that the terms have gained their meaning, and pre- serving that meaning, are derived, with equal propriety, to Science on the one hand, and Logic on the other. The idea of method, indeed, is prior to that of either Science or Logic. It is simpler, w^here they are more complex. It enters into every thing which admits of arrangement and order. There is method in placing in a row a number of mine- ralogical specimens according to their external resemblance : though this is not a science. There is method in grouping together a number of apho- risms, or proverbs, or practical maxims, which refer -'JlS-.-JBSBW ..r)a\ trpdrov pr)TopiKr)v K€KivT)K€vaL. ^s avTiCTTpoc^ov flvai Trjv 8ia\€KTiKT)v, rovTfVrti/, laoirrpotpov, hia to nepl Trfv avTTjv vXrjv . 416. Ovkow fVl tovtois dpKov^€Pois Kara- ttava-TioVj s ei/t /zoXtora, Koi ra np6s rSav v €7rip ndpvos fitpovs p Koi iiaip€T]K€P, h6(P Ka\ 6 TipKpdrqp TroXXotf paBr]p.acnp. *• Metaphys. xii. 4. Avo ydp iaTip, d tis dp dnodtor, 2coKpdT,i SiKaitos, ToCs T enaKTiKoi/s Xoyov^y Kal to dpi(((T6ai Ka6oKov. • See Dioi(. Laert. Prooein. Segm. 18. c2 20 THK ANCIENT VIEW ol THE RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE. 21 division, yet in practice adopts it ^ Epicurus recognised it also, though he gave to the logical section the name of '' canonic ^" The Stoics accepted it without any such alteration of termi- nology. So generally admitted was it, that it was forced in some sense, by popular opinion, on those who would not otherwise acknowledge it. Sects, which denied its validity, or were ignorant of its existence, were tried by its standard. Thus we are informed, (of which more hereafter) that the Cynics confined their attention to Ethic, and neglected Physic and Logic'. It is to our purpose to see, what prominence, what place and office, the different schools assigned to the logical limb of this division. A few pre- paratory remarks will enable us the better to see the real nature of the question on which they ' Top. i. 12. §. 5. 8 Diog. Laert. lib. x. Seg. 29, 30. *" Diog. Laert. vii. 40. ' Diog. Lat'if. vi. 103. Far more out of place, and for that very reason mon* strikingly illustraiive of the prevalence of this division, is the statement of Philo Judiuus, (Quod omnis probus liber) that the Essenes cultivated Ethic to the exclusion of Logic and far the greater portion of Physic. It is startling to find 8t. Jerome applying it to Holy Scripture in the following passage. " Quomodo Philosophi solent disputationes suas in Physicam, Ethicam, Logicamquo partiri, ita et eloquia divina aut de natura disputare, ut in Genesi et in Ecclesiaste : aut de moribus, ut in Proverbiis et in omnibus sparsim libris : aut de Logica, pro qua nostri theoricen sibi vindicant, ut in Cantico Canticorum, et Evangeliis." Epist. ad Paulimi Urbicum de interpretatione Al- phabeii Hebraici, ad init. parted company, and the reasons which rendered it incapable of a satisfactory solution. The ancients used the term Logic in a much wider sense than we do. As physical Philosophy included all the phenomena of the outward world, and, if we can allow a soul to brutes, those of the "irrational soul" also; as Ethic considered all questions of directly practical import, so the whole world of mind came under Logic. It dealt with mental laws, whether these laws were considered as the means of investigation, or its object. If the application of reasoning could solve a ques- tion without appeal to observation or experiment, its solution belonged to this branch of Philosophy. If the nature of the rational soul was considered. Logic claimed it as its province. If a system of rules was to be constructed, fitted to aid in the ordinary investigation of truth, here too Logic was at home. The word then was taken in too broad a sense to be distinct in its meaning. Metaphysic, or the science of thought as belonging to the rational soul, in the first place fell within it. Then it included Logic proper, or the system of rules for reasoning grounded on the laws of thought. Lastly, it included Logic applied — the concrete of these rules, and the matter of any particular question which they enabled the enquirer to determine. The clear mind of Aristotle did not fail to discern this equivocation. He saw the difference oo THE ANCIUNT VIKW OF THE between the metaphysical truths on which the rules of reasoning are grounded, and the rules of reasoning themselves. His usage of language on this point is not however that to which we are now accustomed. Logic is with him the more general term; Analytic, the more restricted**. Our Logic corresponds to the latter rather than to the former. Thus, on the one liand, he calls it a logical ques- tion, whether there be one science of contraries, or not; on the other hand, he describes Rhetoric, which we should characterize as the union ' of the science of human nature, and Logic, as a com- bination of PoHtic and Analytic"". The opposition therefore between logical and analytical, in his mind, would answer to that between metaphysical and logical, in ours. There is of course nothing implied in this antithesis, which could hinder him from viewing Logic generical, including Analytic and much more, as one great section of Philosophy, in contrast both with Ethic and Physic. Plato, on the other hand, it is well known, courted of set purpose the fusion of these two ideas — of the law, and the rule, of thought; of the basis on which Logic is built, and the logical building itself. Though a variety of authorities attribute to him the threefold division of Philosophy, he does not himself explicitly state it. And Dia- lectic, rather than Logic, is the name by which he ' Ton. I ^ Posi. Anal. I. xxii. 21,2. "* Rhet. I. iv. xii. f). I RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE. 23 distinguishes the third number of the division. We know too, that his making those universals, which were generally regarded as the creatures of Logic, real existences, and identifying them with his ideas, led him to include under one name the formal and the real science °. His Dialectic was not a mere intellectual discipline, or a bare organon of truth, but a summary of the highest, and, in some sense, the only real knowledge. It will be seen, then, that these two great authorities, however much they differ on other points, agree in one. They both exalt Logic above Physic and Ethic. Plato's reason was obvious : Dialectic was the one great science to which, in his opinion, other sciences owed not only their apparatus, but their very aim and purpose. And Aristotle, taking, as we have seen. Logic in its broadest sense, made it include far too much, to be at all tempted to vmderrate it. The two great schools which succeeded in Greek philosophy assigned Logic a far low^er importance. The Canonic of the Epicureans was restricted within very narrow bounds, and sometimes con- fused with their Physic**. And the Stoics, who also subordinated it to Physic, introduced also Rhetoric and other extraneous matters into the province which it seemed of itself no longer equal to Hll P. " Metaplivs. xii. 4. ** Dioj;. Larrt. vii. 41. " Diog. Laert. x. 30. 24 THE ANCIENT VIEW OF THE But, as two schools of Philosophy arose before Logic had its origin, so also two, which were almost contemporaneous with its most flourishing days, shut their eyes and refused to acknowledge it. One of these was that of the Cynics. We have seen above'', that the rejection of Logic was formerly laid to their charge. The accusation which is so directly made might have been inferred from their known opinions. Antisthenes and his disciples denied the possibility of definition ' and of contradiction ^ The one position is incon- sistent with a behef in the accuracy of knowledge ; the other even denies that it is attainable. For, if there be no contradiction, there can be no antithesis between truth and falsehood; if there be no definition, truth may exist indeed, but with such indistinctness and uncertainty of outline as to defy a sure recognition. Li each opinion the same tone of mind appears. To regard Truth as something which the mind cannot really grasp, is a long stage on the road towards disbelieving its existence. The Cynics indeed seem to have been a pitiable sect of philosophers — pitiable too, perhaps, in the sense of deserving our pity. First of all, they turned their thoughts to virtue, which they thought both attainable and necessary. On the ethical branch of Philosophy they therefore cast no slight. But this absorbed their wliole attention. On the cold un- 'i r 20. ' Mcl;i|)hys. vii. 3. ' Top. I. ix. f). RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE. 25 impassioned covmtenance of their ideal Virtue they fixed their eyes, and forgot all besides. The laws of the souls, and the phenomena of nature, they alike despised. Beyond Virtue, all seemed un- certain ; the sophists had overthrown their faith in human knowledge, and Heraclitus had sapped their trust in the outer world. Plato invented his theory of ideas, that, by reposing all that was precious upon them, he might preserve the con- fidence of men both in knowledge and goodness. The Cynics thought that their doctrine of im- passibility saved Virtue from the general crash, and calmly allowed the sea of doubt to sweep all else away. Very unlike paths lead different men to the same conclusions. The Cyrenaics also were said to resolve all Philosophy into Ethic'. Aristotle him- self" tells us of the contempt with which Aristippus regarded Mathematics as teaching us nothing of the good and the beautiful. Morals were at any rate the principal study of the Cyrenaics, whether they entirely neglected the other branches of Philo- sophy, or, as is more likely from their treatises on " causes" and " proofs," only placed them in com- plete subordination. Perhaps indeed there was little in their whole system to claim the title of philosophy. They were bound no more to any severity of thought than of conduct. No strict Dioi-. Lat'it. ii. 1)2. " IVIelaplivs. ii. 2. 26 THE ANCIENT VIEW OF THE theory was needed to justify ease and sell-indulgence to those who loved them. As time passed on, the Schools, which at first occupied independent ground, came into contact. Questions, originated by each separately, were discussed in common. And we find, at a period long after the inventors of the respective systems had ceased to write and live, their descendants once more discussing points which seemed to have been settled, and ruhng them anew. In the time of Ammonius^the Stoics, Peripatetics, and Platonists had long, he tells us, held their distinct view as to the relation of Logic to Philo- sophy. The Stoics, true to their old position, made it a part of Philosophy. One of their argu- ments is sufficiently terse and concise to deserve mention. No Art, they said, made its own instru- ment ; Logic therefore, which is the creation of Philosophy, is not its instrument, but a part of it. The title of Aristotle's logical works was the watch- word of the Peripatetics, who held Logic to be only an instrument. The argument which Ammonius puts in their mouth, has certainly a tinge of a phi- losophy foreign to that of their master. They argued, he tells us, that every part must have the same matter, and the same end, with the whole ; but there was no such identity of subject and pur- pose in Logic and Philosophy. For Philosophy, ' The soil of Heniicas, who flourished circ. A.D. 470. Sec his Treatise on the Cate^^ories, pp. 6—8. Ed. Vend. 151)5. RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE. 27 they proceeded, had things for its matter, and asswiilatio7i to God for its end; while the subject of Logic was Language, and its aid. Demonstration. The conclusion at which they arrived was true ; the way of attaining it, if it was really theirs, proves how the school of Aristotle had degenerated in those bad times. The Platonic view, we are informed by the same authority, was, that Logic was both a part and an instrument of Philosophy. These Platonists, too, argued rather childishly. A hand, they urged by way of example, is an instrument of giving and taking, a part of the whole body. Of course there is nothing wonderful in the same thing's being a part of one thing and an instrument of another. There is something more philosophical in a dis- tinction which they drew, with a like object, between Logic when viewed as an independent system of rules, and when actually applied to some particular subject. Regarded abstractedly, as in the former case, it seemed to them an instrument of Philo- sophy ; taken in the concrete, as in the latter case, it became a part. Thus, while they sided theo- retically with the Stoics, their mode of expression tended practically to that confusion of Logic and Science, which afterwards prevailed among the Schoolmen. Thus much of the views which the principal schools of ancient Philosophy held regarding Logic. Their want of distinctness and consistency 28 THE ANCIENT VIEW OF THE is obvious. The reason of this deficiency has been hinted at more than once. Falling short of a definite conception of Logic itself, they could attain no distinct statement of its relation to other subjects. Human reason at large, and reasoning, or the exercise of the inferential faculty par- ticularly, and language, in which reason finds its expression, may all be investigated like any other subject, and therefore brought under one or more sciences. Such science or sciences would of course be a part of Philosophy. And the Greeks, employ- ing a single word to express at once thought and language, would naturally call such a science. Logical, This combination then of Metaphysic and uni- versal Grammar, though scarcely deserving to give a name to the most important division of Philo- sophy, would nevertheless rank under it. Aristotle and Plato were right in insisting on its claim to this honour; the Stoics and Epicureans trod on the verge of error, when they lowered the laws of thought in their esteem to the level of the rules which are gi'ounded on them, and the Cynics and Cyrenaics were undoubtedly wrong when they despised this branch of knowledge altogether. But Logic, in the sense which we give to the term, is not a Science, but an Art. Not directly adding to our stock of abstract truths, but serving to extend in all directions the domain of general knowledge, it is not a part of Philosophy, but the RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE. 29 organon of Philosophy at large. And it was to Logic proper, as an art, that the enquiries of the later Schools which have been mentioned above referred. The Peripatetic position, that it is an instrument, is in this way perfectly correct. It was an anticipation of the modern idea of the subject, and was only too early to bear fruit. The Platonic statement has the air of a verbal com- promise, but agrees essentially with the Peri- patetic. The Stoical opinion is indefensible. That School held fast to its ancient dogma without understanding it. Though it might be rash to assert with Hooker, that they " accounted stupidity the highest top of wisdom V' they certainly showed for the most part more obstinacy in retaining a position than skill in defending it. The view of the later Peripatetics, we have said, was alone correct. But it was planted among the fragments of a ruined philosophy, and failed to take root. The ancients, on the whole, sub- scribed to the formula, that Logic is a part of Philosophy. Turn we now to the Schoolmen, and see, how through their researches we have journeyed by a tortuous road to Truth. y Eccl. Pol. VI, vi. §.6. CHAP. IL THE MEDIEVAL VIEW OF THE RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE. The stream of knowledge, though it always flows, never flows evenly for long together. It often seems to divide, and its portions to take dif- ferent courses. But the separation is seldom final. The severed streamlets form an island, beyond which they unite. The smaller body of water flows perhaps straight onward, through a confined and artificial channel. The main stream makes a longer circuit, but both join at last. We may apply our metaphor, and say, that ancient Philosophy ran in a comparatively narrow course after Aristotle. The late Peripatetics, we have seen, kept and carried on, with regard to Logic, the true doctrine of their master. But Philosophy in general took a diflerent turiL Ari- stotle himself, and not the opinions of his school after him, formed the text which exercised the commentatorial spirit of the middle ages. The Schoolmen set a very different value on Logic from the Peripatetics. It was fated to rise to a still THE RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE. 81 greater height in the world's estimation, before it sunk to its proper level. Aristotle and Plato had made Logic a part; it is not too much to say that the Schoolmen made it the whole, of Philosophy. Aristotle, like many other great men, left behind him a mighty idea, for the future, if possible, to evolve. That idea was the great ruling science of Wisdom, Towards this he pointed the aspirations of all who would be good and happy. He thought it unattainable, certainly to the majority of man- kind, perhaps to all. Yet, in spite of his love of the practical, he could not refrain from dwelling on it. If ever he is enthusiastic, it is on this subject ; some portions of the Metaphysics, read, in consequence, like fragments of a philosophical romance. The Schoolmen caught from him the same idea, and were enraptured with it. We shall not wonder at this, if we consider how great were the promises it held out, to those who thought it practicable. Aristotle's Wisdom is nothing less than a deduc- tive theory of the universe. The mind which has attained it is represented as in some sense sovereign over all that it surveys. The truly wise men, unlike the mass of mankind, who are slaves to sense, and see but consequents without the ante- cedents, and touch only the last and lowest link of the chain which connects heaven and earth, stands at the source of all knowledge, and sees things in their causes. His reason follows the order of the 32 THE MEDIAEVAL VIEW OF THE creative Mind. Whatever is first in nature, is first also to him. And the mental act which this Wisdom implies is of the most perfect kind. All is calm contem- plation. The turmoil of inference is over, and pure intuition has succeeded. The mind's eye does not wander here and there in quest of some worthy object, but is fixed for ever in intellectual serenity on the face of Truth. Viewed only as a habit of the mind, it rose so high in dignity and perfection. Nor were the subjects with which it dealt unworthy of its own elevated nature. It is depicted in a threefold aspect, answering to the division of that which it contemplates. Its highest phase is Theology, — which dwells on the thought of the self-existing Substance, a pure intellectual Being, ever active ; the first Cause ; itself unmoved, yet the source of all motion ; eternal, indivisible, omnipresent ; in a word, the Aristotelian God. Its two other divisions are Mathematic and Physic. These words, to a great degi'ee, explain themselves. Of the latter, however, we should observe, that it took a much wider range with Aristotle than with us, including, to a great extent, the laws of mind as well as of matter, — the laws of all phenomena, in short, which are not reducible to the formulae of space and number. Under this broad sense of Physic falls the Philosophy both of Morals and Art. The wise man does not indeed descend from his I RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE. 33 theoretic elevation to give rules for guiding con- duct, and forming taste. To the lower parts of Philosophy it belongs to train men to the love of goodness and the perception of beauty. But when art and education have not only brought forth fruit in practice, but have also developed character, and elicited Ideas which had else lain dormant in the mind. Wisdom can then, without loss of caste, regard them. She adds to her contemplation of Absolute Being, and, in subordination to this, of the laws which move the framework of the Uni- verse, a knowledge of those principles also, on which depend the Good and the Beautiful. Such was Aristotle's wisdom, perfect in its subject, which is co-extensive with law and order ; perfect in its method, which is that of the cre- ative Mind, starting with the simple idea of Being, and descending thence in regular sequence through the whole array of including and included universals ; perfect in the nature of its contemplation, which sums up in a single term the whole series of causation, and grasps by a simple intellectual act what has been called " the Mundane Idea," or the '' Summary Law of Nature'." The author of this mighty plan did not, of References in detail are impossible, where so abstruse and wide a subject is treated so summarily. But a fuller expansion would have been out of place here. The following Chapters of the Metaphysics contain manv of the nio.st ini])ortant passages. Lib. I. 1.2. V. l.XI. 7— 10. D S4 THE MEDLEVAL VILW OF THE course, witness its completion. It cannot he fairly said that he ever really attempted to carry it out. We have indeed lahorious collections of facts, difficult prohlems, subtle theories, handed down to us in abundance from Aristotle. But thougli he investigated almost every branch of knowledge, there was no great system to which he endeavoured to harmonize the whole. His separate treatises have their own perfection, and generally need no definite place in a more extensive arrangement. Having put before the world a scheme for the consistent organization of all knowledge, and col- lected large materials for tlie work, he left tliem as a legacy to posterity, to be arranged and con- solidated, if it so might be, by others. Nor did the idea fail to bear fruit in its season. The Schoolmen found tlie design, and thought it too striking to be neglected. Their theological stores were a large addition to the material be- queathed by Aristotle. So, with full confidence in their resources, and a per[)etual reference to the original sketch before them, they attempted to rear the tem})le of Universal Knowledge. Where Aristotle had laid the foundation, tluy built; his facts, ready hewn to their hands, they incorporated with the building : his Metaphysic supplied them with the plan; and they took his Logic for their scaffold. To mention the Schoolmen seems at once to trespass on the province of the unintelligible. The RELATION OF LOOIC TO SCIENCE. 35 term is vague enough ; can it be otherwise, when we sum up under the title of scholastic philosophy the whole mass of thought, vast in its extent if not in its value, which occupied the minds of the learned in its elaboration between the tenth and the sixteenth centuries ? If it brings up any image at all before most minds, it is a very incongruous one, in which John Scotus and Dun Scotus are in danger of losing their individuality, Roscelin and Ockham, the nominalists early and late, blend confusedly together, and Anselm and Lanfranc come into contact with Albertus Magnus and Thomas Aquinas. We are apt to think, that during the long period of scholastic dominion there was no true growth and progress ; ' that books increased beyond number, and writer superseded writer, with- out any corresponding, not to say proportionate, increase of knowledge, or revolution of opinion ; but that Aristotle was a uucleus round which hard words innumerable attached themselves by accre- tion like so much inorganic matter. But such a tone of thought is an unnecessary wrong to an extinct philosophy. Its unity of form, though by no means so great as is generally supposed, serves nevertheless to disguise from the care- less observer very wide differences in substance. The opinion that the thinkers of those days must have been all very much like each other, is too rapid an inference from the undoubted fact, that they were all very unlike ourselves. If d2 36 THK MEDLEVAL VIEW OF THE we identify, as is usual, the Scholastic and Me- diaeval Philosophy, we must not forget, that there were as truly within it subordinate schools, as there had been in ancient, and are in modern times, in spite of the greater resemblance of form which they acquired, as, treating all subjects in a single view and in a conventional language, they expanded with difficulty, and often with danger to their advocates, under the watcliful eye and stern admonition of Church-authority. The great point of similarity among the School- men is indeed that feature of their writings with which we are most concerned — the uniform j)re- sence of a dialectical spirit. Some of the traits which we should be most apt at first to select as characteristic are by no means universally present. Their devotion to Aristotle, for instance, is not invariable. The master of sentences himself, Peter Lombard, has been observed never to quote him ; and with several of the early Schoolmen, the Neo- platonic element preponderates over the Peripa- tetic. The commentatorial spirit, again, prevailed not so generally among them as it is said to do now among the literati of China. It does not distinguish, for instance, the scholastic works of St. Anselm; and the master-pieces of school- labour, the Book of Sentences, and the Sums of Theology, are in the form of questions and distinc- tions, not of comment. Some would make realistic opinions a test of the Schoolmen; yet Roscehn RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE. 37 and Abelard are often reckoned in their number, and no one denies Ockham that doubtful honour. They are characterised more surely, as we have said above, by their absorbing devotion to Dialectic. This it is which keeps them poised in the region of intellectual abstraction, equally removed from the pleasing illusions of imagination on the one hand, and the stern realities of observation and experiment on the other. This is the principle of unity, which assimilates to itself all the subjects of which they treat, and reduces to a dreary same- ness the widest and most varied range of discus- sions. But our object is not to delineate the scholastic Philosophy generally. The connection it formed with the Aristotelian idea of Wisdom, and its consequent identification with Logic, alone concern us at present. Peculiarities such as these, though they may be stated in the abstract, cannot be described and rendered intelligible, without some aid of example. And to none of the Schoolmen should we so naturally turn, as to Thomas Aquinas. Several reasons prove him particularly adapted for this purpose. He is perhaps, of all his tribe, the most complete and systematic : and the fact, that when the day of his full power was over, he con- tinued, and still continues, to exercise a real in- fluence over students of a certain portion of Philosophy, fits him still more for our object, when we are treating of the scholastic doctrines mainly with regard to the view which they forwarded on 38 THE MKDl.EVAL VIEW OF THE a single important question — the relation of Logic to Science. Though, were we attempting a portrait of the perfect Schoolman, we should still do best to refer to him. He is, in many ways, the best specimen of his class. He wrote at the time when the School-philosophy seemed to have com{)letely recovered from the attack which tln*eatened it with destruction in its infancy, and which Ockham afterwards renewed to its ultimate downfal. He unites in himself to a remarkable degree the theo- logical and philosophical traditions of former days; Augustine was his acknowledged authority in matters of religion, and Averrcies, to an extent of which he was not himself aware, his leader in the interpretation of Aristotle. The earlier Schoolmen wrote in fear, often well-grounded, of the inter- ference of the Church ; the later are thought to have pressed the system to its utmost boundaries, and to have seen glimpses of the coming reform- ation. Aquinas, more than any of his fellow- labourers, was fortunate in the reception of his speculations : they were never deemed of unlawful tendency, and gained for him the rare praise of uniting orthodoxy and philosojihical acuteness. We may add, that his writings, at the present day, are still spoken of, if not consulted, and referred to, if not read; and alone, of all the scholastic volumes, show traces of a dubious vitality. It will then be worth while, keei)ing Thomas Aquinas steadily l)ef()re us as the type of the RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE. 39 scholastic Philosophy, to show briefly from his writings the place which logical method held in his system. Our position, be it remembered, is this — that the Schoolmen took their ideal of Science from Aristotle's Wisdom ; that, m the endeavour to construct it, they began by ad- mitting his Metaphysic ; that they adopted his facts without enquiry, and placed them for pur- poses of argument on a par with truths derived from more sacred sources ; and that thus, with premises ready to their hand, and a logical system under which to combine them, they reared a fabric of which the form was comparatively every thing, and the matter comparatively nothing ; so that the truth could not be distinguished from the medium in which they exhibited it, and their method became identical with their philosophy. 7^o proceed then to the first point — the co- incidence of the Scholastic view of perfect Science with the Aristotehan idea of Wisdom. The great work of Aquinas is, as every one knows, his '^ Sum of All Theology." Theology, too, was, as we have seen, the title of the highest division of Aristotle's Wisdom. This agreement of language, even if unintentional at first, could not remain unperceived ; and, when once perceived, could not be passed over in silence. Either the Theology of Aquinas was to be, like Aristotle's, the highest wisdom, or it was not ; and a writer so given to definition and distinction could not 40 THE MEDIEVAL VIEW OK THE leave a point of this nature luuleterniined. Ac- cordingly, he meets the question, and answers it in the affirmative. At the very opening of his great work he declares, that the Sacred Doctrine is '* one single science," ''speculative rather than practi- cal," " transcending all other sciences whatsoever," in a word, "absolutely and simply wisdom \" The Christian Theology then w^ould, according to Aquinas, approach very nearly in the terms of its definition to that of the heathen philosopher. This would indeed still leave room for a very wide distinction between them. But it would lead us to expect at least thus much, tliat the Schoolmen would be very careful in drawing a line of de- marcation between the Divine Wisdom and Aris- totle's crowning Virtue. This, however, is not the case. Thus in his connnent on Aristotle's Meta- physics, he begins by assigning to his author's first science the very title by which he distinguishes his own. It bears, he tells us, the three names of the Divine Science, or Theology ; Metaphysic ; and the First Philosophy ^ And how thoroughly he blends in his method of treatment the human and the Divine Wisdom, how he considers them to con- ' See Prima Priinae, Art. I. Qq. 2—6. where he predicates of •* Doctriiia sacra" successively that it is " scientia," " una scientia," " magis speculativa quum practica," " omnes alias scientias traii- scendens turn speculativas quum practicas," " maxime sapient ia inter omnes sapientias humanas, non quiilcm in aliquo generr lantum, sed simpliciter." ^ Comment, in Mctaphys. ad init. RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE. 41 nect themselves with the same subjects in the same manner, may be seen in the following very characteristic passage". "Those arts," he ob- serves, " w^hich govern other arts are called archi- tectonic or ruling arts ; and those who exercise them are called architects, and claim the name of wise. These artificers, however, as aiming only at particular ends, reach not the universal end of all things. They are therefore only called wise on this or that particular subject. In this sense it is said, ' as a wise master-builder I have laid the foundation ^* But the name of absolutely wise is reserved for him alone, whose speculations turn on the end of the universe, which is also the principle of all things. Wherefore, as the Philo- sopher *" says, the wise man must consider the highest causes. But the ultimate end of every thing is that which is intended by its first author and mover. But the first author and mover of the universe is Intellect. Therefore the ultimate end of the universe must be the good of Intellect ; which is Truth. Truth must then be the ultimate end of the whole universe ; and with the con- sideration of this end must Wisdom be principally occupied. Therefore, the Divine Wisdom cl^id in flesh declares that He came into the world to '' Proopm. ad Sum. contr. Gent. •* I Cor. iii. 10. Aquinas quotes the Vulgate, " ut sapiens archifecfus fundamentum posui." ' Melaphvs. i. 2. 42 THK MEDLtVAL VIEW OF THE RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE. 43 manifest the Truth, saying, ' To this end was I born, and for this cause came I into the world, that I'should bear witness unto the Truth? And so the Philosopher^ determines, that the First Philosophy is the Science of Truth, not however of any Truth, but of that which is the origin of all Truth." Further proof cannot be necessary of the close connection, not to say identity, which Thomas Aquinas held to exist between Aristotle's First Philosophy and the Christian Theology. We must next show the importance he attached to the principles of the Aristotelian Metaphysic. Though Aristotle and the Schoolmen each founded their great science on the same idea, that of Being, it by no means necessarily followed that their respective sciences should be identical. They need not ever have been to any great extent similar. The conceptions which they employed to express and bring out at length the meaning and force of that idea, might have been entirely different. They might have endeavoured to por- tion out the world of thought on some novel principle, and have spent their chief labour in discovering a range of metaphysical abstractions, which should give their speculation an individual and original air. In a word, as Aristotle had divided being in one way, they might have divided it in another. Had they undertaken to do so, the ' John xviii. 37. « Mctapliys. ii. 1. ' most characteristic feature of their philosophy would have disappeared, or rather, would never have been called into existence. The endeavour to decide for themselves, what was the best and most natural division of Being, would have called observation into play, and, by giving Induction fair scope, liave destroyed the exclusive power of Deduction. The course of Science might have been more rapid than it has been, had the minds of men been thus early turned to investigating new universals, instead of drawing continually new conclusions fi*om those wiiich w^ere old. But the Schoolmen show^ed no tendency in this direction. As they had taken the idea of their science from Aristotle, they took from him the conceptions which were to illustrate it also. Without any exercise of the critical faculty, they followed him unhesitatingly in his primary division. At the very beginning of Aristotle's Organon stand the Categories, or, in Latin guise, the Pre- dicaments. They are the first broad philosophical division which meets the student of the Aristotelian method. Of what they are a division, is not so clear. Aristotle himself is generally supposed to have attained them by considerations half-logical and half-grammatical; and then to have applied them as heads under which to group thhigs. Thus the question naturally arose — are the Categories to be ' regarded as a scheme for the division of nature, or of language ? Eitlier opinion had its advocates 44 THE MEDIEVAL VIEW OF THE among the ancients. Others preferred an inter- mediate view, and considered them as referring to the conception, which hes midway between the name and the thing. Ammonias ^ who records these different opinions, himself subscribes to a misty formuhi, probably of Neo-platonic origin, which blends them all, and asserts, that " the Categories have to do with words, whicli signify things, through the medium of conceptions." The Schoolmen would have adopted this view, had they exclusively followed tradition. It is contained in their principal authority on the subject, a commentary on the ten Predicaments, erroneously attributed by them to St. Augustine \ But they rejected as superficial and insufficient the belief, that the Categories were mainly a scheme for the division of words. It pleased them rather to hold, that they met with their counter- parts in the outward world. On them they would willingly have constructed, if they could, the classification of an universal science. So Aquinas *• De Categ. p. 14, 15. ' That Alcuiii had no doubt either of the aulhenticitv of this work, or of the value of its contents, appears from the following verses, in which he rc^commended it to the perusal of Charlemagne. Continet iste decem naturie verba libellus Quae jam verba tenent reruni, ratione stiipentld Omne quod in nostrum poterit decurrere sensum. • •••«•••• Hunc Augustino placuit transfcne magislro Do velcrum gazis Griucorum clave Latin^. \ RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE. 45 tells us, that " perfect Being is that which exists, external to the mind, through the ten Predica- ments^;" and again, that '' Being must be portioned out into different kinds according to the different modes of predication; for different modes of pre- dication are attendant on different modes of Beuij^''." Or, as he elsewhere states his doctrine, " modes of Being are proportional to modes of predication \'' And far from making the Categories heads under which to arrange conceptions, he expressly excludes all such mental creatures from them ; for " nothinir IS placed in any predicament, except what exists external to the mind "\" Accordingly, he attempts, with very indifferent success, to show, from con- sidering the nature of existence, that these ten heads amount to an exhaustive division of things'". So high indeed did he raise their dignity, that he sometimes ranges God under the Category of Substance. Though here he speaks more doubt- fully than usual, at one time denying that the Predicaments at all relate to Him", at another time allowing that tliey do % though in a different manner from that in which they apply to other existences^. ^ in Metaphys. v. Leciio ix. * In Phys. iii. Lectio v. •" De Pot. Dei. Qu. vii. Art. ix. Rosp. " Prima Summte, Qn, iii. Art. v. " De Pot. Dei, Qu. vii. Art. iii. ad 7™. ^ De Pot. Dei, Qu. ii. Art. ii. ]•". ad 1'". Ii 46 THE MEDLflVAL VIKW OF THE It is clear, that were the Categories thus state- ments of the real classes of things, a universal science would be at once possible. Under such a classification every thing might be duly ranked and ordered, and a natural system, so to speak, of the whole universe be constructed. And this was the work which the Schoolmen thought they had the power to accomplish. The Categories them- selves indeed do not hold a very prominent place in their general writings. Like other abstract principles, when once enunciated and clearly laid down as true, they are traceable mainly in their consequences. They stand like so many land- marks, seen from a distance indeed, but of most continual use in guiding the mind to its decision on questions which are very remotely and indirectly connected with them. The bearings of truths derived from very different sources, from Holy Writ and the writings of the Fathers, were deter- mined by them. This was a great misfortune to the Schoolmen, that they never suspected the existence of any discrepancy in their heterogeneous material, or at least, if the suspicion unavoidably occurred, never ventured to entertain it. Theo- logians at the first, they began in the school of faith, and carried their l)elieftoo far. Inspiration itself could not receive more reverence than Aris- totle. Where he evidently contradicts the revealed Word, they shut their eyes to the real state of things, and look about for some other exi)lanation. Thus i UELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE. 47 Aquinas wishes to persuade himself, that the Philo- sopher did not actually hold the world to be eternal, but was rather, like a subtle disputant of his own times, urging in a dialectical spirit plausible argu- ments against the position of an adversary*^. The Schoolmen had never heard of destroying, with a view to re-construct. Unhappy in the absence of doubt, they fell short of the philosophic mind in one respect at least — that they never learned to reject. Logic then, as the Schoolmen thought, had a noble task before it. With so much inherited from their predecessors, all new ap])eal to the world of observation seemed on their part superfluous. From certain given truths they hoped by a long circumduction to infer all truth. For this purpose, logical instruments were to suffice. But the in- struments of Logic differ from those of most other arts in a very marked manner. There is, in Art, generally little similarity between the tool and that on which it operates. And further, most arts confine themselves in practice strictly to singulars. The sculptor applies an individual tool to an indi- vidual block of marble : it is a given portion of a compound substance which a chemist analyses, and that by means of tests themselves of a limited and definite quantity. It is not so with the Logician. His subject, and his manner of dealing with it, are ^ Prima Suuiina^ Qu. xlvi. Art. 1. De Pot. Dii. Qu. iii. Art. xvii. 48 THE MEDLEVAL VIEW OF THE alike general. He applies universals as the criterion of other universals. This is his work — to test, arrange, and, it may be, infer, general truths by means of general formulae. So thought the Schoolmen— and to a great measure rightly. How then were they to discri- minate, where there seemed so much risk of con- fusion, between their method, and that on which they employed it ? The conceptions, whether of things or classes, which their enquiries presupposed, and the apparatus of Logic itself, were alike modes of intellect. Without some especial provision, error and perplexity must ensue from their running into each other. This danger was obviated by drawing a distinction between First and Second Intentions. '^ A first intention V' they taught, '^ was the likeness of something existing external to the mind; as, for instance, the conception which follows on hearing the word man — a conception which is founded immediately on the thing." Whereas a second intention is '^not a likeness of any thing existing external to the mind, but a conception following on our mode of understanding such things. These are invented by the intellect itself ; as, for instance, the conception which is signified by the word genus. Intentions of this kind have their immediate foundation not in the things but in the understanding : though the remote foundation is in the thing itself." So that, to express the same •^ Aquinas on i"". Lib. Sent. Dist. ii. Qu. i. Art. iii. UliLATlON Ol LOGIC TO SCIKNCK. 49 truth still more clearly in the form of a distinction not of things but of words, " nouns of the first intention are those which are imposed upon things as such, that conception alone intervening, by which the mind is carried immediately to the thing itself. Such are man, and stone. But nouns of the second intention are those which are imposed upon things, not in virtue of what they are in themselves, but in virtue of their being subject to the intention which the mind makes concerning them : as when we say that man is a species, and animal a genus\" The scholastic apparatus was now complete. They had, as they thought, a primary classification, external to the mind, in the ten Predicaments; they had first intentions, or conceptions drawn directly from things, to range under them; they had, among other second intentions, the Pre- dicables, which enabled them to show, how, under the light of the natural classification, the first intentions were related to each other. In other words, they had, or supposed they had, both the objective and subjective requisites of a perfect system— a valid diWsion of existing things, and a method according to which to group all notions under this division. So, without any further delay, they betook themselves to syllogizing; to determining, that is, by means of their supposed knowledge of the nature and force of terms, the various relations which they might be supposed to • Opusc. xlii. Art. xii. ad init. dO THE MEDIEVAL VIEW OF THE occupy to each other in propositions. Here they were not likely soon to come to a stand: the possible permutations of words are endless ; and they did not think that they were dealing only with words, and falling far short of things. Each distinction which they drew brought forward new questions; and the solution of each question ehcited fresh distinctions. Philosophy separated from a central trunk into numerous branches, which again divided and subdivided till their ulti- mate sections were as fine as hairs, or finer — invisible even to the eyes of those who spun them out. And, through the whole of the prolonged system. Logic every where extended itself; drew each distinction, stated each objection, answered it when stated, summed up when it gave its de- cision, crushed each enquiry into the same uni- form shape, appealed over and over again to the same universal premises, employed unnumbered artifices to extract from these premises conclusions they were never meant to give, cut into shreds the scanty sheet of knowledge, as Dido did the hide, that it might encircle the province which it could not cover, governed absolutely all Philosophy, and as in despotic governments there is no distinction between the monarch and the constitution, was all Philosophy itself. No wonder then that the highest praises were heaped upon it; that though it was confessedly only " reductivelv" or '' indirectly" a part of specu- RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE. 51 lative Science, as supplying it with syllogisms, definitions, and other instruments of like kindS it was yet allowed to bear in common parlance the title of " the Rational Science"," that as directing the act of reason, from which all arts proceed, it was called " the Art of Arts " ;" and that it was held% '' all learning must begin from Logic, not as being more easy than other sciences, (for having to deal with second intentions it involves the greatest diflSculty) but because it teaches the method of procedure in all sciences, and therefore all other sciences dejiend upon it^." « Super Boet. de Triii. Qii. V. Art. 1. " In Post. Analyt. ad init. • Super Boet. de Triii. Qu. Vf . Art. 1. ^ Old John of Salisbury gives an account of the proceedings in a certain Dialectical school with which he was acquainted, which will apply, in a less degree, to the scholastic use of Logic in general. At any rate, we may better see the tendency of the evil, by contemplating its more aggravated form. " It was the fashion to talk of nothing but consistency (convenientia) and reason. Argument was ringing in every one's mouth. To name an ass, or a man, or any other work of nature, counted as a crime; at least was out of place, and unpolished, and unworthy a philosopher. It was thought impossible to act or speak consistently and reasonably, unless express mention were made of consistency and reason. Argument was quite out of the question, without the use of the word argument. No distinction was made, between proceeding according to an art, and treating of it. (Ex arte, et de arte agere, idem erat.)*' Metalogicus, Lib. I. Ch. iii. E 2 NOMINALISM AND REALISM. 53 CHAP. III. NOMINALISM AND REALISM. Before taking our farewell of the scholastic view of Logic, it is natural to make some remarks on the great question as to the nature of Universals, which connected itself so closely with it. Though the battle has long been fought, there is a great historical charm, and even so^ne living interest, associated with the once-prominent party-names of Nominalist and Realist. We may easily see the reason of the importance attached to this question, and the zeal with which it was contested. Logic, we have said, was in fact the sum of scholastic Science. And this great Science professed to deal with Universals. On these depended the whole array of questions and ob- jections, consequences and conclusions. Their modahty, so to speak, determined that of the whole system. And those who were not too busily engaged in adding to it and elaborating it, to find time ibr looking back, and seeing what had been accomplished, and on what foundation it rested, naturally came at last to the enquiry, what these Universals were. Of course, the originators of this question among the Schoolmen were neither the first to ask it, nor the last. Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoics, not to mention other authorities, had each their distinctive theory of Universals. None of these were entirely satisfactory : and modern Philosophy feels the old difficulty to be still unsolved, to be lying at the basis of almost every important doubt, and to l)resent the great clieck to its rapid and confident progress. In all probability, indeed, a compa- ratively ancient source suggested the enquiry to the Schoolmen. Porphyry, in his treatise on the Predicables, states the problem, though he declines attempting to solve it^ "' Whether," he says, '' genus and species are substances, or exist in bare thought alone; or, supposing thein to be substances, whether they are material or im- material ; and again, whether they exist separately, or in composition with sensible objects, I must dechne discussing. The subject is profound, and needs a separate and more detailed enquiry." Its due quantity of enquiry, at least, in after-times it gained. It is well known that Europe derived its know- ledge of Aristotle from the Arabians ; and that, among these, their principal authority Averroes tinctured the Peripatetic philosophy with a strong spice of a spurious Neo-platonism. Under his hands, the doctrine of Universals assumed a form * Fsagogo, clia])- i. 54 NOMINALISM AND REALISM. something like that of Ideas. Genus and species were held to be substances, not mere attributes, much less words. Whether they existed abstract- edly from matter, or were rather to be described as always present in the concrete, was a subject left for after-discussion. The theory of Averroes himself was in fact an ill-disguised Pantheism ; which, when apphed to certain subjects, led to results which so displeased the Schoolmen, as to prevent, even when such objections did not occur, its formal and expHcit reception. Here their theology came in as a safeguard to their philo- sophy; they shrank as Christians from the view which he held, that one common human intellect existed, of which each individual intellect was a part\ But they followed him so far as to conceive, that the Universal was an actual thing; and thus, before Nominalism was heard of, ReaUsm, or a belief in the existence of Universals as sub- stances, and not merely as attributes of the mind of man, was the current belief of the early School- men and their immediate predecessors. It suited the feehngs of those, who, like Scotus Erigena, •• "A view," Thomas Aquinas argued justly, (Opusc. xvi. contra Averroistas,) ** which is repugnant to the truth of the Christian Faith. For intellect appears to be alone, of all the parts of the soul, incorruptible and immortal. Now supposing diversity of intellect to be removed from all men, it follows, that, alter death, nothing of human souls would remain except their intellectual unity, and thus all retribution of reward and punishment would hi? removed." NOMINALISM AND REALISM. 55 were mystically inclined; it could not be dis- agreeable to those argumentative spirits, who were anxious to maintain the honour of Dialectic. But, though thus in possession of the scholastic mind at the first, it did not establish its supremacy without a struggle. The Nominalist attack showed at once its strength and its weakness. It called forth the hidden strength of Reahsm, by proving that it was entwined with the very roots of the School- philosophy, which could not ultimately but stand or ftiU with it : it also betrayed its weakness, by showing that it lacked the distinctness of a true and consistent theory, and assumed very different shapes in the minds of its different supporters. The history of Nominalism divides itself into two very marked periods. During the former of /these, it was forcing by its attacks the scholastic philosophy to assume a more definite form than it had hitherto taken, and was so hurrying on its own temporary defeat; during the latter, it was sapping the strength of that mighty system, by introducing into its inmost heart an element of doubt. In both periods, it connected itself with theological questions, in feeling and tendency, if not by the links of strict consequence. Nominalism has often been called, and justly, the precursor of the Reformation. And as those who first aimed unsuc- cessfully at a reformation were more violent in their opinions than those who took up the work afterwards, and succeeded ; so the earlier Nomi- 66 NOMINALISM AND REALISM. nalists, doomed from the first to fail, were more extravagant and far less philosophical in their teaching, than the happier band whom Ockham led on to victory. Roscelin of Compeigne was confessedly the founder of the sect of the Nominalists. The term at first was meant to indicate that its adherents bestowed their attention on language, and held Universal to consist in na?Nes. Though it was natural that the Realists should endeavour to give it still further force, in applying it as an allusion to what they thought the merely verhaf knowledge of their antagonists. And so Aventinus, even when looking back upon the past, explains it. " Roscelin," he says, '' the founder of the new Lyceum, first cultivated the science of words and phrases, and discovered a new way of philosophizing. To him we owe it, that the Peripatetics, or followers of Aristotle, divided into two classes— the older, rich in invention, and claiming for itself the science of things, and therefore called the Real school ; and the later, disturbers of this science, and called Nominalists, because, niggardly of things, but prodigal of names and notions, they appear to be the partisans of words \" This is neither a very »' Aniiales Boioiuin, lib. vi. p. 406. cd. Basil. 1580. Avoniimis (lied about 1533. A reproach gi-ouuded on a name is of course little to be trusted. " Who can confute a sneer ?" And praise on like grounds is equally deceptive. Luther commends the later Nominalists, on the strength «»f anoiher muw thev here, with NOMINALISM AND REALISM. 57 profound nor a very fair account of Nominahsm in general. But it serves to show the feehngs with which its advocates were regarded down to a comparatively late date, as sceptics who would lower the dignity of Dialectic, curtail the region of Science, and suck out the very marrow of Philo- sophy. Roscehn himself, indeed, appears to have de- served the name of Nominalist in its fullest and most unfavourable signification. He advocated the position that Universals were nothing but names— a position which, as we shall see here- after, has little to be said in its favour, and if consistently maintained, is fatal to all true philo- sophy. The error did not remain unrebuked : for he drew upon himself the powerful opposition of St. Anselm. This distinguished theologian and dialectician had another hold upon his adversary. Roscelin had been also guilty of heretical doctrine concerning the Holy Trinity". St. Anselm in- about as much reason as Aventinus condemns the earlier. " The Terminisls, among whom I was, are sectaries in the high schools ; they oppose the Thomists, the Scotists, and the Albertists ; they are also called Occamists, from Ockham their founder. They are of the newest sect, and are now strongest in Paris Thev are called Terminisls, because they speak ol a thing in its own proper words, and do not a])ply them after a strange sort Ockham was an able and sensible man." Table Talk, pp. 540 — 2. * Roscelin taujjht, " tres personas esse tres realitates di/Terentes." Anselm's remarks are indignant enough. '* All," he says, " should he warned to touch most cautiously on questions of Holy WriL But these dialecticians of onr time, and heielics even in their ' 58 NOMINALISM AND REALISM. I NOMINALISM AND REALISM. 59 geniously couples the two mistakes together as cause and effect. The bad dialectic accounts for the false theology : and the false theology is proof certain of the badness of the dialectic. The issue of the contest was not long doubtful : Roscelin was forced to retract his errors at the Council of Soissons^ The victorious Anselm became next year Archbishop of Canterbury. The defeated innovator was banished both from England and France*. In a few years, John of Salis- bury informs us, his opinions were almost ex- tinct ^ Another ill-starred name, that of Abelard, follows Roscelin in the history of dialectical innovation. Whether Roscelin was his instructor in their com- mon art is doubtful. On the one hand, there is old authority for such a supposition; on the other, Abelard is silent on the point in his account of his own Ufe, in which he displays no disposition to reserve. But perhaps a reason for the omission may be found in his circumstances. He had .dialeciic, men who take universal substances to be nothing but word of mouth, should be altogether excluded from disputing on spiritual things He who does understand in what way several men are yet in species but one man, can such a one com- prehend how, hi the secret depths of the Divine Nature, of seveial persons each shall be perfect God, yet all be one (Jod ?" Dc Incamatione Verbi, (otherwise, De Fide,) ch. ii. " A. D. 109-2. • Abelard, Epist. xxi. ' His words are, ** alius consisiit in vocibus ; licet hacc opinio cum Roscelinosuo fere omnino jam evanuerit." iMetalogicus, ii. 17. himself to bear the imputation of heterodoxy, and would naturally shrink from the weight of obloquy which attached to another. Indeed he goes out of his way to condemn in strong terms both the logic and the theology of Roscelin^. There was the more need for caution here, because their opinions might by the careless or unskilful be confounded. For Abelard, though not in the strictest sense of the word a Nominalist, was at least an Anti-realist. John of Salisbury thus records the distinction between them^. '' The one (meaning Roscelin) takes his stand on words ; the other on propositions :" and he expressly ascribes the latter view to Abelard. It is hard to affix a very definite meaning to this statement. The most probable interpretation is that of Degerando \ that he believed Universals, without having a strict independent and objective reality, to be conceptions — conceptions, however, which, to be formed and retained in the mind, must rest upon the signs of language ; and that « Epist. 21. "Hie sicut pseudo-Dialecticus, ita et pseudo- Chrisiianus, cum in Dialectica sua nullum rem partes habere aestimat, ita divinam paginam impudenter pervertit, ut eo loco, quo dicitur Dominus partem piscis assi comcdisse, partem hujus vocis, quai est piscis assi, non partem rei intelligere cogatur." Fairness in dispute was no characteristic of those days. •• Metalogicus, ii. 17. I have Englished " sermones" by '* pro- positions," believing John of Salisbury to have had the Greek Aoyouff in his mind. ' Hist. Comp. de Philosophic. Vol. iv. p. 403. 60 NOMINALISM AND REALISM. therefore he made them turn, not, like RosceUn, on the simple term, but on the proposition, which expresses the relation of subject and attribute, as they are apprehended by the understanding. Scarcely any other position indeed in the scale of thought upon this subject remains for him to occupy ; for while he dissented from the pure Nominahsm of Roscelin, he fell short of pure Con- ceptualism; those who placed Universals among the creatures of the understanding, as the Con- ceptualists do, being mentioned by John of Salis- bury as a distinct sect : and his own writings would prove, even in the absence of external authority, his decided aversion to Realism ''. But Abelard, with all his niceness of distinction, did not escape from the dialectical field unwounded. Like Roscelin, he had the honour of being defeated ^ He relates with great gusto his contests with his old instnicior, William of Compeigiie, and their successiul termination. " 1 forced him by most conclusive arguments to modify, or lather to sunender, his old opinion concerning Universals. He had been of thai mind with regard to their general nature, that he asserted the same nature to be present at the same time essentiallv in each of the individuals. It followed that among these individuals there was no diversity of essence, but only a variety in the multitude of their accidents. But afterwards he so reformed his opinion as to say, that the same nature was present in them not essentially but indifferently. " (i. e. as much in one hidividual, as in another.) Abelardi Vita, cap. ii. A decision which leaves the question open after all. Though the distinction meant to be drawn would seem to be like that made afterwards in the disputes between Scotisis and Thomisls between real and formal presence. NOMINALISM AND UEALISM. 61 by a great antagonist. In this their lot differed, that Roscelin fell by the hands of one who wielded weapons like his own : while the brand of theo- logical unsoundness was fixed upon Abelard by one, whose mind, occupied by its own beautiful mysticism, hated the philosophizing spirit of the day. It is more an honour to him in our eyes, than it was a consolation in his own, that he owed his overthrow to St. Bernard. But if in those days the imputation of Nominalism was fatal. Realism was not always a protection from error. A contemporary of Abelard, Gilbert de la Poree, is an example of this. He was a Realist, but a bold one. The extent of his boldness in Dialectic has indeed been much overstated. His treatise on the Six Principles has been described as an endeavour to cut down Aristotle's Categories to six. But he was guilty of no such presumption. He only endeavoured to expand the six later Predicaments, which Aristotle had passed cursorily over, after the plan on which the Philosopher had treated the first four. In introducing these in their new shape, he goes so far as to hazard a definition of form. " Form," he says, ^' is con- tingent on matter, consisting of simple and in- variable essence V and flatters himself that this ' Fonna est comj)ositioni conlingens, simplici et invariabili essentia coiisistens. — Erit ilaque terminus foiinaB dicta definitio, iieque enim superflua neque dimiuuta, si quis subtiliter investi- gaverit, reperietur." 62 NOMINALISM AND REALISM. formula will endure a searching criticism. It would have been happy for him if he had confined himself to such harmless innovations. But the same spirit led him wrong elsewhere ; he too was condemned for departing from the doctrine of the Trinity. It was resei-ved for a pupil of Abelard to effect what his master in common with others had so unsuccessftilly attempted — the union of Philosophy and Theology. Peter Lombard effected this end, by reversing the procedure of previous scholastics. They had first formed their dialectical notions, and then applied them to things divine. He, taking his ground on the received Theology of the time, accommodated Dialectic to it, and so freed it from suspicion. His cautious Book of Sentences became in after times the basis of comments much bolder than the text on which they were founded. Or- thodox in faith and philosophy, he completed for the time the victory of Realism. And, like all other principles that are not sound at heart, though a good watchword in a battle, it becomes un- interesting and unprofitable, immediately on its success. We will proceed at once to some con- siderations, which will bear upon the history of its fall. Realism, though now, as it seemed, firmly and finally established, was not really safe. There were enemies within the camp from the first. John of Salisbury, who died as early as A. D. 11 82, NOMINALISM AND REALISM. 63 recognises no less than six different sects of Realists. These may be, however, fairly reduced to four ; — those who adopted the Platonic doctrine of ideas, and held that the names of genera and species belonged properly only to those objectively ex- isting Universals ; — those who considered that the individual contained the whole essence of the class, and was in fact, when viewed from a certain point, itself the Universal, as when it is said that Plato is, as to his manhood, a species;— those who asserted that the whole aggregate of individuals was identical with the Universal ; — and those who regarded the Universal as a substance in some way existing in the singular. These sects, it will be seen, agree in nothing, except in all calling Universals, ili'nigs. The three former views, however, ultimately gave way to the last, of which Aquinas was the great advocate. It became a received doctrine, that the one Universal existed in the many indi- viduals. But this basis of agreement did not shut out all dispute; the meaning of the formula was not so clear, but that enquirers would ask, how the Universal existed in the individuals ? On this point, there was an ominous schism of the Schoolmen. Dominican and Franciscan could not agree even on the abstract questions of Phi- losophy. Their differences extended from ques- tions of free will and predestination to Logic. The school of Scotists arose, and called into existence 64 NOMINALISM AND UEALISM. the rival school of Thomists as defenders of the great Dominican authority. The followers of Aquinas held, that the Universal existed really in the individuals; the disciples of Duns Scotus maintained that it existed only formally'^. The latter went so far, as to abandon the old title of Realists, and assume that of FormaUsts : in order that their very title might protest against the doctrine of their antagonists. And, without endea- vouring to explain the subtle distinction between Reahsm and Formalism, we may assume that the innovators, in rejecting the old watchword, vir- tually, though unconsciously, relinquished tlie cause which it had symbolized so long. The Scotists themselves wxtc, or thought they were, still opposed to Nominalism. But the next generation of thought showed the actual tendency of their views. Out of their school rose Ockham, and with him the opposition to Realism revived once more. In impugning the doctrine of the ex- istence of Universals as substances, he directed his attacks especially against Scotus, under whom he had studied. We must not confound his opinions with those of Roscelin and his disciples. Ockham, •" It should be obsened, ihat the two doctors did not themselves come into contact. Thomas Aquinas died A. D. 1274. The chronology of Duns Scotus is doubtful; hut taking the most probable date of his death A. D. 1308, and following the account which gives him ihe short life of 34 years, we should fix his birth in the very year in which Aquinas died. NOMINALISM AND REALISM. 65 in asserting that Universals existed, but existed only in the mind, answers exactly to a modern Conceptualist. His teaching was on this point clear, distinct, and sound, though expressed and defended with a quaint and technical minuteness of accuracy, which proves him every way a match for any of his scholastic brotherhood. '' " Every Universal," he taught, '' is really a Sin- gular in itself, and therefore is only a Universal in virtue of its signification, which is a sign of many things. This is the doctrine of Avicenna, who teaches, that a single form in the understanding is related to a nmltitude of things, and is therefore a Universal, because it is an intention in the intel- lect whose operation does not vary to whatsoever you apply it. It follows that this form, though in relation to the individuals it is a Universal, yet in relation to the mind on which it is impressed is itself only an Individual, for it is one of the forms which are in the understanding." This is a spe- cimen of his positive reasoning : his negative goes to prove generally that '' no Universal is any thing external to the mind." It may be worth while to show how he fought his adversaries with their own weapons. '' ° No Universal," he urges, '' is a singular substance, for, this granted, it would follow that Socrates is a Universal : for there is no more reason why one singular substance should " Sumnia totius Logicfc, ch. xiv. lb. ch. XV. m NOMINALISM AiND REALISM. NOMINALISM AND REALISM. 67 be a Universal than another." This is rather an endeavour to throw the weight of the proof upon the adversary : the following is a more direct and at the same time more complete argument. " If any substance be, as is supposed, more things than one, it must be either several Singulars or several Universals. If the former be allowed, it follows that a certain substance will be, e. g. several men ; and then although the Universal will be distinct from any one particular man, it will necessarily be the same with all the particulars together. But if we take the other alternative, that one substance is several Universals, we must then ask the ques- tion — is this Universal several things, or only one ? If the answer be that it is only one, it follows that it is really a Singular ; if the answer be that it is several things, I enquire again whether it is several Universals or several Singulars; and so on to infinity." Theology too was l)rought to bear on the point at issue. *' If the Realist opinion were true, God could not annihilate one individual with- out destroying all ; for to annihilate any individual He must destroy all that is of its essence. Con- sequently, He must destroy the Universal which exists both in it and in other individuals ; and these could not continue to exist, when deprived of a part of their substance, such as the Universal is supposed to be." We will not endeavour to follow him, where, in discussing the Scotist opinion of H ■ ^ ♦ -» the formal presence of the Universal in the in- dividual, he refines on a refinement ^\ Opinions like these, not long after the opening of the fomteenth century, were pubHshed by Ockham from the Theological chair of Paris. They pro- duced as much excitement as either friend or enemy could have desired. And argument was not the only means of discussing them employed. Ockham himself, for the ready support which he gave Phihp the Fair against the Pope, by vindicating the rights of the temporal power, and other like acts of insubordination, was rewarded with the pontifical anathema. In more than one University the new doctrines were contested with blows and bloodshed. When we remember that the opinions both of Scotus and Ockham were probably formed within the walls of Merton, we should be surprised if Oxford had been backward in the dispute. Direct persecution was brought to bear in Ockham's other University of Paris, and P Another specimen of his theological reasoning, though curious and characteristic, may be better thrown into a note, and preserved in the Latin. " Item sequitnr quod aliquid de essentia Chrisii erit miserum et danmatum: quia ilia natura communis existens realiter in Christo et in damnato erit damnata,quia in Jud^. Hoc autem est absurdum." Ockham here uses just the same kind of argument against the Thomist supposition of a common human nature, as Aquinas himself had employed against the Averroistic lenetof a common human intellect. How hardily, and apparently without any sense of their hardihood, did these men venture to bring objective truths, and subjective convictions, into the most direct collision. f2 «8 NOMINALISM AND REALISM. NOMINALISM AND IIRALISM. 69 elsewhere. Louis the Eleventh, by an edict whicfi did not prove ultimately successful, condemned the Nominalist teaching, and forbade the study of the works of Ockham and his most famous disciples. So the University of Leipsic ow^es its origin to the expulsion of the Nominalists fi'om Prague. It is said that the Universities of Vienna and Heidel- berg '* were Nominalist from their foundation. Aventinus, who flourished at the beginning of the sixteenth century, mentions that the schools of Paris, Erdfurt, Ingoldstat, and Vienna, were then in Nominalist hands. The opinions of Ockham, when for the time silenced in France, had thus, after taking root deeply in their native home of England, extended themselves to Germany. Luther, Melancthon, and other reformers, pro- fessed their allegiance to them. It would seem the old Theolog)^ could scarcely have been assailed, except with Nominalist arms. It would have stood impregnable against any foes but such as were acquainted with its form and devices, while they had detached themselves from its spirit. Enough has now been said on the history of this great question of the mediaeval philosophy. We have seen how Realism triumphed in the first great contest of opinion ; and how, in the security which followed on this triumph, diversities once more crept in, till Nominahsm at last revived. Revive it '^ The University of Vienna was founded A.D. 1365; that of Heidelberi? A.D. 1346. ( I I \ needs must, after the speculations of Duns Scotus. The belief had not strength and foundation enough to exist without the symbol. When the Scotists took the name of formalists, they virtually gave up the cause to which they professed to adhere. Ockham's claim to distinction lies in the skill and perseverance with which he urged his opinions. The course of things nmst have led many men sinmltaneously with him to entertain them. And now it may be asked — who were in the right, NominaHsts or Realists ? The query deserves an answer, for the question about the nature of Universals is not merely one of words. More importance, indeed, was attached to it in the middle ages than it deserved. But men were wrong in this matter, only because they were con- sistent. They considered the question as a logical one, and their Logic identified itself with their Philosophy, and their Pliilosophy ran up into Theology; and Theology was in those days a subject of very direct and personal import. We are indifferent to Universals now, because the ruling of the point either way would not im- mediately affect daily life, or the opinions of prac- tical men. It is this, and not any superiority to the difficulty, or successful solution of it, which has allowed the cries of Nominalist and Realist to die away. We will endeavour therefore to bring the dis- pute to an issue ; and, that we may tlie better do so, will first define our terms. Here Etymology 70 NOMINALISM AND REALISM. Iff ' i NOMINALISM AND REALISM. 71 comes to our aid. Nominalism, in its strict sense, indicates a belief, that Universals are only names. Realism asserts that they are things. Convenience suggests that we should adopt a third term of later origin, Conceptualism, as expressing the opinion of those, who hold Universals to be conceptions. Nominalism then, in its strict sense of a belief that Universals are only names, is indefensible. Roscelin, who held it, deserved the censures which were heaped upon him as the virtual destroyer of Philosophy. More will be said upon this point, when we come to the logicians of the verbal school, the legitimate successors of the Nominalists. Suffice it for the present to say, that they make, of necessity, the operation of thought merely mecha- nical, and invert the obvious facts of the case by making reason a function of language, instead of seeing in language a consequence of reasoning. Formal argument against them is unnecessary. Their own speculations sufficiently confute them, which they would refuse to admit to have no other subject than words. Like the dogmatical sceptics who asserted positively that nothing could be known, they are silenced, or should be, by their own protestations. It must be remembered, however, that other opinions beside those of Roscelin bore the title of Nominalism. It would be unjust to fix it in its original meaning, in spite of his protest against the doctrine, on Abclard. It became indeed syno- nymous with anti-Realist, and descended toOckham and his school as their natural heritage. But Ock- ham was really what we should call a Conceptual- alist. We have seen that he held Universals to exist, and that really, in the mind ; to be, in fact, mental forms, singular in themselves, but universal in their apphcation. Thus every common term would represent some individual conception in the mind of the conceiver, which should be apphcable indifferently, and without variation, to many exist- ing things. This opinion, if it be not all the truth, is true as far as it goes, and was, at the time, anta- gonist to a mischievous error. For Ockham taught also, as we have seen, negatively, that a Universal is not a substance existing external to the mind. This was the opinion of the Reahsts of his day. Though realism in some of its modified forms had not always necessarily imphed so much. At first it was merely a protest against those who assigned to Universals only a nominal existence. It was con- cluded that they existed real/i/ ; — whether in the mind or external to it, by themselves or in composi- tion, was left as yet undecided. So if we refer to the sects of Reahsts mentioned by John of Salisbury, we find one division holding that the whole aggre- gate of individuals was the Universal. There is nothing extravagant, fanciful, mystical, or irrational in this view ; it has been held very commonly by hard-headed men in our own day ; it differs from that of Ockham only by the omission of a step which may easily be supplied. The two opinions 72 NOMINALISM AND RKALlSM. meet in the following formula — the common noun represents an individual conception which is derived from some known individuals of the class, and is applicable to them all, known and unknown. Against this form of ReaHsm, Ockham did not put in a protest. Neither do his arguments apply directly to the second class of ReaHsts mentioned by John of SaHsbury, who held, as he informs us, that the Individual, as containing the whole essence of the class, was, in a certain point of view, itself the Universal. This opinion was declared to be obsolete by the authority who has recorded it. It was very probably the teaching of William of Compeigne, whom Abelard prided himself on having subdued. We cannot assign it any definite value, when detached from the other opinions of those who entertained it. Thus much only we can be sure of, that it destroyed the strong and natural antithesis between Individual and Universal, by a form of speech in which they were represented as nearly, if not quite, identical. The tendency of the error would depend on circumstances. More than one authority has endeavoured to connect with the scholastic Realism the doctrine of Spinosa, that God is the one substance of which all things are modes. This is probably a mistake, but it suggests an example to our present purpose. That doctrine, always mischievous to the last degree, becomes practically either Atheism or Pantheism, according NOMINALISM AND REALISM. 73 as he who adopts it, taking his notion of substance from the world around him, degrades his conception of God to suit it : or, on the other hand, starting with some high theory of the First Being, interprets all else by it, and raises all forms of existence which meet his eye to a level which is inconsistent with sense and reason. In like manner, he who should assert that Individuals and Universals are the same, would be a most unintelhgible mystic, if he took the common view of a Universal ; an equally unintelligible sensualist, if he adopted the ordinary notion of an Individual. The dominant Reahsm of the Schools was, as we have seen, of another kind, and regarded the Uni- versal as a substance in some way existing in the Individual. The manner of its existence therein was, it will be remembered, the point of dispute between the Thomists and Scotists. Against either shape of the doctrine Ockham has left us little to urge. His arguments are to the point, and conclusive; and have moreover this great advantage, that he from education and familiarity most likely understood, to a degree impossible to us, the meaning of the position he aimed at over- throwing. The remaining kind of ReaUsm is that to which nobler minds are naturally prone, and which owes its origin to the divine Plato. That method of stating his doctrine of Ideas, in which they are regarded as existing in the mind of God, seems to admit of 74 NOMINALISM AND REALISM. an easy defence. Surely, it may be argued, if the creation was, as we know it was, orderly and regular; if the clash of circumstances did not develope the different gradations of Being out of a primitive chaos, but class after class came into existence at the bidding of the Divine Word ; there can be no error in looking to that Eternal Word as the seat of Universals. These are not merely the aggregate of individuals, much less the conceptions which we have derived from them, still less that language which so imperfectly ex- presses thoughts imperfect in themselves ; but abide rather in that unchangeable Word, from whom things, and conceptions, and language, alike pro- ceed. A few words on this view of the subject may be said by way of conclusion. We may observe, in the first place, that a state- ment like this, however pious and true, does not amount to Realism, unless coupled with some further hypothesis. Realism requires that the Universal shall exist as a substance, in the highest category, and not merely as an attribute. So that according to the Scholastic method of treating such subjects, we must enter into the (juestion how Ideas exist in the Divine Mind, and deteiTriine that they inhere as substances in a higher Sub- stance, before we can be Realists indeed. And this was the opinion of most authorities, from Boethius downward. But at present we shall NOMINALISM AND REALISM. 75 probably be of opinion, that such a question cannot be answered one way or the other, without considerable danger of carrying speculation beyond the legitimate sphere of reason. But, waiving this objection, a further caution is necessary to those who think Realism thus con- genial with their Theology. Granting that all true and genuine Universals have their seat in the Divine Mind, a further question arises — what are true and genuine Universals ? Surely we cannot boldly assume, that every common term, in the present state of language, is true to its original purpose. With all our ignorance of the nature of things, all our mistaken speculations, all our con- ventionalities of thought and language, can we venture to think, that we have always exercised the powers of abstraction and generalization aright ? And, in default of such rightful exercise, who can answer that the Universals on which we have fixed are true? Who shall say, that the classes which we have formed are in all cases grounded on the nature of things, and correspond to the in- tention of the Divine Author of the gradations of the universe ? We take for granted, and justly, the correctness of our own involuntary and spontaneous clas- sification. What we do insensibly, we generally do rightly. We need not fear that we are wrong, in classing all men, or all animals, or all virtues, or all colours, or all sounds together. But when, by I 76 NOMINALISM AND REALISM. NOMINALISM AND REALISM. 77 a laborious effort of the mind, we endeavour to arrange these classes, which we gained without such effort, in subordination to each other ; when, for instance, we would ascertain the precise relation in which the class man stands to the class animal, we cannot answer for our success. Viewed as a statement of abstract truth, if the zoological ar- rangement of Linnaeus was right, that of Cuvier is wrong. Only when we are assured on the best evidence, that we have attained to the real order of things, and understand their relative position in the scale of creation, can we assert positively that our class terms are valid, and represent any natural Universal. To make the assumption at an eariier stage, would be, in all probability, to fix ourselves irrevocably in error. We should begin, therefore, at any rate, in our enquiries by adopting the Conceptualist, or, as we might fairly call it, the Occamist hypothesis. We should first of all ascertain that our terms are definite, as representing some distinct mental image, and if they be so, thus far be content with them. But, this point ascertained, we come, if we prosecute our enquiry, to another doubt. How far do these conceptions, definite though they be, find their correlatives in the nature of things? What proof is there, that, when we arrange these under some wider conception, or, on the other hand, group lower classes and individuals under them, our arrangement can claim the title of t natural? Unless we can claim this dignity for it, we cannot set a high value on our class-terms. They will stand at best as symbols of a provisional classification, which greater research, or more skil- ful analysis, may at any moment supersede. To begin therefore by assuming that even the most modified form of Realism is true on the exist- ing state of things would be to begin with a mistake. It stands in this respect on a par with the scho- lastic system as a whole ; it is a great aspiration which has never yet been verified. We may cherish it as an ideal, but as nothing more. Our knowledge is far too imperfect to allow us to assert that we class the phenomena of the world at large uniformly according to their natural classes. In some provinces of science, the work has been readily and satisfactorily accomplished. We have no hesitation in aflSrming that, in Mathematics, the divisions of figures according to the number of their dimensions, of lines into curved and straight, of angles into right, acute, and obtuse, of quantities in general into equal and unequal, are really natural, and give us the knowledge of natural kinds. On other subjects, as in Botany, we seem to have approximated to a true classification, though the fine of demarcation between the several classes is far from being, in all cases, accurately drawn at present. Sometimes, as in the case with Zoology, it seems doubtful if the problem has been solved ; sometimes, as with Mineralogy, the work still re- 78 NOMIiNALiSM AND REALISM. mains to be accomplished ; if the chrystallographic Idea be true, the arrangement of conceptions under it is quite incomplete. On the whole, we must be content to allow that the Conceptualistic view of Universals is true at present : the Realistic view, with some limitations and cautions, may be true hereafter. CHAP. IV. THE MODERN VIEW OF THE RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE. The deductive method of investigation, though theoretically the most perfect, has, when applied to most subjects, important practical defects. Its very ideal perfection destroys its actual utihty. That it may be valid, there must be perfect coherence among its parts, perfect dependence on first premises. One probabihty, admitted, destroys the certainty of the whole ; one falsehood anni- hilates its value. No compensating apparatus can make up for the presence of a doubt, or remedy the consequences of a single error. Even omissions, which are not positive errors, are equally fatal to its pretensions : an element of calculation, left out at the beginning, cannot be introduced afterwards. There is no provision for accommodating fresh principles when the reasoning has once begun. There may be no doubt, no retraction ; all must be unhesitating progress onwards. The scholastic system, then, might naturally be expected to fail. It was a mould far too fine and exquisite for the material to be shaped in it. Had all its premises been necessary truths, the scheme \ 80 THE MODERN VIEW OF THE RELATION OF UXJIC TO SCIENCE. 81 would have been unexceptionable. Proof might have hung on proof in continual succession. But neither Aristotle nor the Fathers were infaUible, either in principles or facts. Nor can the words of Scripture be taken always as expressing the literal truth on subjects not religious. We allow, for instance, the fallaciousness of the argument from Holy Writ against Gahleo. The Schoolmen would have asserted its validity, as their admirers did. They over-rated in fact altogether the mo- dality of their premises. They argued from data, which were general rules at the best, and often only probable in a low degree, and sometimes capable of being proved false by very little enquiry, as if they were absolutely true, and immutable laws of the universe. We know how rapidly the value of probabilities decreases when they are combined deductively. One fraction multiplies into another, and the thread of hkelihood spreads out into the merest possibility. We soon become incapable of affixing to conclusions thus gained any practical value. The argument may serve as a clue to guide us, but not as a chain on which we can depend. If they relate to matters of experience, we call in observation or experiment to confirm them ; if they cannot be so verified, we corroborate them by analogy, or example, or some other such compendious aid to proof. If these fail us, we must leave them without assigning them any im- portance, till they are proved or disproved by some process of reasoning less high in its character than the deductive, but better suited to the matter in hand. The fate of the scholastic Philosophy may serve to illustrate these remarks. Boldly did it proceed at first, ramifying in all directions in dependence on its central trunk. Descending by degrees from broad Universals and elevated speculations, it came at length to the region of practical truth. And here the great mental defect of the Schoolmen betrayed itself. Their perceptive powers were quite sacrificed to the reflective. They neither used observation on the creatures of the world without, nor employed imagination in creating a new world within. Therefore they seem to have reasoned and written mechanically, and without any object external to the process of reasoning or writing itself. It would be hard to say at what their Philosophy aims, except its own complete- ness. When consequently in their course they came to the line which marked the sphere of actual life and conduct, no instinct bade them stop. They traversed the level of ordinary thought without heed or remark, only to descend below it. A few steps sufficed for the passage from a question as to the nature of the Divine understanding, or the laws which limit the operations of God, to a discussion of some minute metaphysical question, or the discovery in some ordinary word of some half dozen senses, which none but a master-schoolman G ^ 8-2 THE MODERN VIEM OF THE RELATION OK UHilC TO SCIENCE. 88 could then devise, and which now, without some pupillage, it is very difficult to follow. Accordingly, the predominant feeling of the Schoolmen turned them away from the region of Physic, which leaves least room for mere dwelling upon terms, without affixing to them a meaning. Aristotle's works on this subject as on others met indeed with their share of comment. But deduc- tions from his principles would have been apt to bring a speculator full tilt against some obvious and opposing fact, which would have pierced his thin and airy system, and caused it in a moment to colhipse. Hence arose the necessity of avoiding this delicate ground, and either neglecting Physic altogether, or running it up into metaphysical questions about the nature, for instance, of the principles of motion or causation, or the distinction of matter and form. Those Schoolmen who had the strongest physical turn seem aliens from their brethren. Roger Bacon ranks with them in little beside date. And the vast learning of Albertus Magnus has had small hifluence on the world, when compared with the acute and systematic deductions of his great pupil Aquinas. Thus the ultimate fortune of scholasticism differed according to its subject. It naturally failed first, when the independent observation of facts caused its truth to be tested. Such dis- coveries as those of Galileo with regard to the falsity of the once-received laws of motion involved ( H f I I the system in disgrace. Consequences could not be trusted where premises were so false ; and when one set of premises had signally given way, httle confidence could be placed on any other which rested on like authority. Botany again, which, as connected with Medicine, was all along of great practical importance, and which, to be cultivated with any reasonable hope of success, evidently demands the attention of the student not only to descriptions of plants but to the plants themselves, was one of the first subjects on which enquirers, laying aside useless comments on Theophrastus and other authorities, betook themselves, first of all, to the study of facts, and those gained, to their classification and arrange- ment. So on a third and more important topic ; the Schoolmen had fashioned Theology after their own mind, and incorporated with it their own views of Church authority, and a characteristic doctrine of the Sacraments. These were something more than speculative opinions; and these too received a heavy blow at the Reformation. ' But, in Morals and Metaphysic, and Method in general, as distinct from its application, their system long lasted on, to a great degree unques- tionable. Ultimately it sank into neglect only on account of its evident unprofitableness. It ex- patiated at its own pleasure, and sufficiently widely to prove itself migatory. Or, like a force expend- ed 2 84 THE MODERN VIEW OV Till ing itself in a vacuum, it met with nothing on which to act, and was therefore of no calcuhible vahie. The walls and bulwarks stood entire, but they were also undefended; the city was deserted by its old inhabitants, and the enemy thought demolition unn.ecessary labour''. The endeavour then to work out the Aristotelian idea of Wisdom had failed. Philosophy had made the eff'ort, and, now^ that its ill success w^as evident, seemed dispirited and remiss, unable to be satisfied with the result of its labours, and yet with no heart to I)egin them anew. She needed some novel Idea to stimulate her exertions, to give a fresh interest to her old field of S])eculation, and serve ns a clue in her resumed researches. Such an Idea was given by the virtual fatlun' of modern philosophy, Lord Bacon. His work was in many respects closely like that of Aristotle. Neither the author of the old or of ■^ Jt i^ cjinoiis to see, how, in luanv cases, the old lorni reiiiahied vvhe)i tlic substance was dej)arled — how, for instance, Sanderson, having treated at length of the Predicanjents in the earlier parts of his Logic, crtvfs, toward^ i close, as examples of a poj)ular arrar.gcnipnt ■ i cunnnon -places, the distribution of facts under oitli " '^' ' ' ^^n»efjori»'<, oi ilie ten Comnumdnients. (Append. Pos . in. 11. ' ): 1m»\v (iwillini, hcialdically faithiul to ihe past, porliiuis o\u i, " throw arguments in actual dis- putation, and not in mere school exercisej^, into the strict di;dectit tbnn. (Cardwell, Hist. otCun ference-, p. MM.) UELATION OF LuulC TO SCIENCK. 85 the new Organon elaborated the system of which lie was to bear the honours hereafter. Each pro- posed an Idea, which was left for others to adopt and perfect. The collections of each in the way of facts and materials were comparatively worth- less. They were great generals, the labour of whose hands w^as of little importance when com- pared to the weight of their conmiands-. Each displayed that boldness which is one of the surest auguries of success; and, in his day, called the attention of all, with a confidence which created confidence in its turn, to his own Idea of Perfect Science. Nor was the form which this Idea assumed on the respective minds of these great thinkers so difi'erent as we are ai)t at first to hnagine. Lord Bacon does not seem to have thought less highly of the possible results of scientific research than Aristotle. They both looked to the absolute unity of all knowledge as its state of ideal perfection, without declaring positively whether they thought such state attainable or not. Thev both thouo'ht that Philosophy would find its fidfilment in the subordination and arrangement of many truths under one. They differed mainly in the method by which they thought this subordination and arrangement was to be attained. They adopted each his own mode and order of investigation, while they looked to the c lul of investigation as ojie itnd the same. 86 THK MODKRN VIEW OF THE The Aristotelians (perhaps it is safer and fairer here to speak of the pupils than of the master) made, as we have seen, the Many depend upon the One. They took that order of Science, which, though it be that of the Divine Mind, is one which requires more perfect discernment and accuracy in its application to general subjects than we can command. One metaphor seems to have been con- tinually before their minds, most suitable to the whole aspect of their system, and recommended to Christians still more by its use in Holy Writ — that of the Tree of Knowledge. All the ramifications of Truth were sui)ported actually by its single trunk, as they had been contained virtually in the idea of Being, its seed. Descartes (a man of such genius that we the more regret the accusations of plagiarism from the Schoolmen, and from every other acces- sible source, which are continually l)rought against him) draws out the figure rather happily. " The whole of Philosophy," he tells us, "is as a tree whose roots are Metaphysic, whose trunk is Physic, whose boughs shooting forth therefrom are all the other sciences, which reduce on the whole to the three principal heads of Medicine, Mechanic, and Ethic— I mean that most exalted and perfect Discipline of Manners, which presupposes the perfect knowledge of other sciences, and is therefore the last and highest grade of Wisdom. Just then as fruits are gatliered neither from tlie roots of trees nor from the trunk, but only from the end of the boughs; so the chief RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCK. 87 use of Philosophy hes in those parts of it which are necessarily the last to be learned \" Appropriate as this figure is, expressing not only the form and configuration, but the natural deve- lopment and inward growth of a philosophical system, the fiict could not at last be denied, that the scholastic tree was withered, if not dead; stretching forth bare boughs through the heavens, and fixed, not by roots, but by its sheer bulk and ponderosity. Lord Bacon at once inverted the method, and supplanted the metaphor. Just as Copernicus, when he perceived the endless complexity in- volved in the supposition that the sun moved round the earth, tried, and successfully, to attain a simpler expression of the facts of Astronomy by supposing the earth to move round the sun : just as, in later times, and with far more doubtful success, Kant, acting on this earlier example, endeavoured to reduce Metaphysic to a simi- lar basis, by making our conceptions determine phenomena, and not, as had been previously assumed, phenomena determine our concep- tions; so Lord Bacon, standing between the two thinkers both in time and in intellectual position, with a keen perception of either kind of truth, curious both in facts and laws, in Physic and in Metaphysic, ventured on tlie experiment, from which so much good has resulted, of in- '' Fridiil. ad Prificipia Philo!hysic and the eternal and immutable 90 THE MODERN VIEW OF THE truths of nature, withdrawing his mind for a time from the flux of things, without at the same time touching on Natural Theology ; so ready and natural is the passage from the vertex of the pyramid to things divine V This was the new turn which Lord Bacon gave to Philosophy. Science appeared to him more material, and less formal, than it had seemed to his predecessors. They had regarded their method as something like a principle of life, which super- seded the ordinary conditions of inanimate nature, and enabled them to widen out their knowledge, as it were, from the basis upwards. Just as organization brings about results which cannot chemically be accounted for; just as the hiw of crystallization seems for a time to suspend the operation of the laws of gravity ; so it appeared to them that the conditions of thought could control and regulate the conditions of Being. Reasoning was something more than the scaffold by means of which the building was erected : it was part of the building itself. The fabric of knowledge presented itself to Lord Bacon in a different light. He thought that the tendency of former times had been to over- rate the powers of reason. His apprehension was, that the lawful construction of a Science might be sacrificed to the love of method and consistency. He reminds his reader that " it is natural for the ■■ Do Aiifijin. Scicntianiii), lil). ii. ad. iiiit. RELATION OF LOGIC TO SCIENCE. 91 mind of man readily to imagine greater order and equality in nature than it finds there '^;" that it " needs not the addition of wings, but rather a burden as of lead, to bar all leaping and flying ^" He allowed no power to the intellect of antici- pating observation and experiment. The instru- ments of Science, he thought, had hitherto cor- rupted Science itself. Plato had spoiled it with Theology, Aristotle with Logic, Proclus with Mathematics^. So he proposed to make know- ledge a congeries of facts, which hke a pyramid would hold together by the natural force of cohesion. None of the apparatus employed in raising it was ultimately to be incorporated with it. Induction was to become a great engine, which all could work, and all with equal success. His method of investigation was to equalize all intellects^, and this on every subject : for, he tells us, "as vulgar Logic, which governs its subjects by syllogism, pertains to all Sciences, and not to physical Science only ; so likewise our Logic, which proceeds by induction, embraces alP." There is always a danger of riding a metaphor to death, especially when it is so natural and true, as to combine itself with the direct argument, and become undistinguishable from it. Perhaps Lord Bacon has been guilty of this mistake, not an uncommon one with rapid and powerful minds, to " Nov. Org. lib. i. §. 45. '^ lb. §. 122. " lb. §. 127. lb. §. 104. ' lb. §. 96. 1 1 92 THE MODERN VIEW OF Til! whom it does not occur that their own energy of thought may have found but an insufficient ex- ponent, and that the tired Pegasus may cease to answer to the spur. The thorough adoption of this pyramidal theory of knowledge implies a great assumption — nothing less than this, that while the order and arrangement, which the facts of Science fall into, is really essential ; that de- pendence and consequence, that necessary con- nection among them, which the mind can in some cases trace, and is eager to trace in all, is not essential. It implies, what, to say the least, has never yet been established, that the Idea of a Science, the nucleus around which all its facts cluster, the principle of that unity wliich Lord Bacon himself insisted upon, is itself merely a generalized fact, true in no other and in no higher sense than the phenomena which fall under it. Thus reason is hnvered unnecessarily, and deposed from the throne which observation is unfit to occupy. The Schoolmen had thought to move the world without a fulcrum for their intellectual lever: Lord Bacon doubted the levei > >tiviigLh, even were the fulcrum given. We need scarcely remark, that neither idea ol Science has prevailed exclusively since his time. Men have not been every where hibouring like Egyptian slaves at perfecting the pyramid of Truth by the mechanical application of the engine called Induction. Deduction is still extant in the world. KKLATIOX or LO(iIC TO SCIENCE. 9:^ I and shows signs of vigorous life. Intellect, in spite of all its idols, is still in request. There is no innnediate probability that any organon will succeed in obliterating the practical distinction between ordinary and extraordinary minds. Mo- dern Science is content to aim at that unity which both the Schoolmen and Lord Bacon sought, by the method of either indifferently. The subject on which it is engaged determines whether it shall follow^ out the idea to its consequences, or arrange phenomena under an idea. In one respect, we are less hopeful now% than the sage of Verulam was. We do not hesitate to pronounce the absolute unity of all knowledge impossible to the human mind. Far less is it thought, that the formal imity of Logic is at all equivalent to a real unity of Science. Logic, as we shall presently see, is held indeed to stand in a shghtly different relation to induction and deduction ; but in neither case is it supposed to give both matter and form, or so to extend form, as to enable us to dispense with matter. Its monarchy is now more sure, because limited. From being, in turn, a part of Philosophy, and the whole, it has descended to the leV'cl of an instrument. / ON THE DIFFERENT MODERN SCHOOLS OF LOGIC. 95 CHAP. V. ON THE DIFFERENT MODERN SCHOOLS OF LOGIC. Logic, then, it is now generally allowed, is only an instrument of Philosophy — an instrument as contrasted with a part; not involved in the idea, or necessarily hound up in its existence ; not even an universal preliminary of Science, though it may be indispensable to some minds, and highly useful to all. Enough will be granted to show its im- portance, if it be admitted, that scientific research, and scientific statement, become more easy by its means; enough also to attach interest to the question, which we will now proceed to discuss — how does Logic prove itself to be thus instrumental to Philosophy ? The correct answer to this enquiry is also the obvious one. Philosophy, it is answered, is elabo- rated by the mind of man; and correctness of process is an ordinary though not an invariable condition of correctness of result. It is by regu- lating thought, or the act of the rational mind, that Logic is instrumental to its end. It gives neither facts, nor ideas under which to combine them ; but by its analysis of the mental operations. it enables us to test the correctness of the com- binations of phenomena, the conclusiveness of the consequences from an idea. There is however more than one school of thinkers, who regard Metaphysic (using that word in the sense of a science of thought) as impossible ; or at least as doubtful, and deceptive, and a fair object of suspicion. These, while they allow the utility of Logic, prefer accounting for it in another way than that mentioned above. Un- willing to speak of it as couversant with thought, or conceptions, or inference, or mental operations in general, they assert broadly that Logic deals either with words, or with things. Thus Logicians, at the very entry of their sub- ject, begin to differ. They cannot agree in stating with what they have to deal. The difference among them is sometimes real, sometimes only verbal ; but, even where it is verbal, it is sufficient to prove a broad separation of tone in the contend- ing parties. The point at controversy needs some explanation; and, for convenience sake, a name which involves no reproach may be given to the advocates of the several opinions. We will then divide Logicians into three schools, according as they hold words, things, or conceptions, to be the subject of Logic; and entitle them respectively, the verbal, the phenomenal, and the conceptional. These divisions find no exact counterpart in ancient or mediaeval Logic. The connection of f 96 ON THE DIFFERENT MODERN SCHOnrs oi I.OUIC. thing, conception, and word, was at first much more dwelt on than their antithesis. The disputes as to the origin of language did not materially affect the question. Even those who, like Aristotle, derived it from convention, admitted this funda- mental parallelism. They assumed, as perhaps it were wiser for us to assume, that our mental impressions adequately represent the outward world ; that our language does sufficient justice to these mental impressions. To decide in which the province of Logic properly lay, was not a point of practical importance. The regulation of either portion of the realm would involve also the proportionate adjustment of the other. Neither again can the question slide back, as it sometimes seems inclined to do, with that of Nominalism, Reahsm, and Conceptualism. Though some of the verbal school are, as we shall see, the legitimate successors of the ancient Nominalists, they should not be confounded with them. Mem- bers of the three schools may be perfectly agreed in their view of Universals. Besides, the dispute is not, like that of old, really extra-logical. How Logic furthers Science, is a question which may be entertained without trenching on Metapiiysic ; not so the other query — what it is that common nouns signify. Proceed we then to consider the respective claims of these rival views to our regard. That the conceptional opinion is on the whole correct. } ON THE DIFFERENT MODERN SCHOOLS OF LOGIC. 97 will be best shown by our notice of the errors with which it is contrasted. Our first remarks shall be devoted to the verbal School. Those who assert, that the regulation of Language is the province of Logic, may be guilty only of an awkward method of stating a truth. They may not intend more than to insist on the intimate connection between Language and Thought. Every act of thought, they urge, and truly, is accompanied, and figured to the mind, by some word, external or internal. Thinking, as naturally seeks its expression in language, as feeling does in inarticulate sound. The relation of the sign to the thing signified is in each case the same ; though the one is the expo- nent of the act of the rational soul, the other of the irrational. Just as brutes express pain spon- taneously, by uneasy motion, or their natural cries, so men spontaneously invest their con- ceptions with an outward clothing. That the word is not always articulated, matters not ; enough, if it be understood, Li all probability, however, were nature left to run wild, we should think aloud for the most part, and make no more secret of our thoughts, than children, before the time of definite reflection, do of their feelings. It is different in society : an instinct, easily developed, teaches us, that to utter all that is conceived would be unwise, as to give vent to all that is felt, would be umnanly. All this is true : but it does not nearly amount H 98 ON TIIK DIFFERENT MODERN SCHOOLS OF LOGIC. to a proof that Logic must subserve to Science only by regulating language. Such regulation is the work not of Logic, but of Grammar. Grammar looks to clearness of expression, as Logic to clear- ness of conception. We may have logical accuracy without grammatical. This is often the case with reflective persons who have lived much alone. They tliink methodically and correctly, but fail in the attempt to communicate their meaning. And if the endeavour to express one's thoughts often shows their indistinctness, it does not follow that the means which expose the defect, will also serve as the remedv. But, it may be urged in reply, though accuracy of thought be really the aim of Logic, this is practically identical with accuracy of language. For it is only through language that thoughts can be transmitted from one mind to another. Thus, it is argued, the necessary medium becomes, for ordinary uses, identical with that which it conveys. Here, however, there is twofold fallacy. Li the first place, though language be essential to thought, it does not follow that accuracy of thought will always be attended with grammatical accuracy of lan2:uaN THE METHOD OF SCIENCE. 133 fall at once under certain elementary and received principles of classification suitable to the science : thus space itself divides according as it is simply hnear, or bounded by lines or surfiices : and geometrical figures in general divide according to the nature of these lines and surfaces, as they are straight or curved ; or again, according to the uniformity or relative proportions of their parts, as when we speak of certain triangles as equilateral, and certain solids as regular. Further, when these conceptions are arranged in order of formal proof, there is of course a consequentiality existing among them ; this dependence of part upon part, and of the whole upon the Idea, being one of the most remarkable features of Geometry. And this consequentiality implies a certain subordination ; for the different ))ropositions do not depend for proof directly on the Idea, but admit among them- selves of greater and less degrees of generahty. Thus the Axioms, Postulates, and Definitions cover very frequently a wider ground than the particular Theorems and Problems ; and of these, some are evidently wider in extent tlian others. Whatever is proved true of triangles in general, for instance, applies to equilateral triangles; while the converse does not hold. In the next place. Botany may stand as a specimen of the ClasslJicaiorij Sciences. Here the Idea may be differently stated, as being in the abstract. Vegetable Life: or in the concrete, the ' ■■r^.: 134 1 ON THE METHOD OF SCIENCE. Vegetable Kingdom. The spontaneous observation of mankind, even prior to scientific enquiry, had supplied a vast number of conceptions to be grouped under this Idea. The names of individual trees, and shrubs, of different portions and organs of the plant, exist prior to scientific arrangement. These are duly grouped imder the Idea, by means of certain intermediate conceptions, which belong properly to the science of Botany, and may or may not be distinctive of the different botanical systems. And in this arrangement a Principle of Classification is involved — the difference of this principle, and not any diversity in the detailed view of species, for instance, distinguishing a natural from an artificial arrangement. And to show that the principle adopted enables us to arrange the conceptions in due relation and sub- ordination to the Idea, is the task which each advocate of a peculiar system undertakes. Of another class of sciences, the applied sciences, we may take Mechanics as an example. Here we have one Idea, viz. that oi force. There are certain principles, further, according to which we can subdivide this idea. Thus the Idea of force com- bined with the conception of Rest or Counterpoise limits itself to S/atics, when combined with that of motion, limits itself to Th/// amirs. In each of these divisions there are other conceptions which enable us to subdivide them ; such are implied, in Statics, \n ttie laws of solid and fluid (Hpiilibrium, and, I ON THE METHOD OF SCIENCE. 135 in Dynamics, in the three great laws of motion. These, when traced into their consequences, give us certain combinations of conceptions, which are su])ordinated to the main Idea, and connected with it through them by a necessary dependence. Lastly, a perplexed and complicated science, like that of Asfronomij, in which Deduction and Observation find place together: where different parts of the results are gained by different pro- cesses, and in the vast array of laws, and inferences, and general facts, and details, the unity seems almost broken; forms no real exception to the notion of a science which we have adopted. The only uncertainty is, in which of two w^ays it shall be made to conform to our requisitions. In one point of view, it must surrender its claims to the dignity of a distinct science ; and rank only as the application, on an enlarged scale, of an independ- ent science to the explanation, or, it may be, pre- diction, of a vast mass of previously arranged and classified phenomena. Astronomy thus becomes the Mechanics of the Heavens. And this is the explanation of its nature which a Mathematician would be likely to give. Or, again, the Physical Philosopher might ask — what is it which enables us to associate so readily in our minds phenomena so different as an eclipse, and the com'se of the planets, and the nature of nebulae, and the form of the earth, and the distance and density of the sun, but the presence of onc^ Idea — that of the Universe, 136 ON THE METHOD OF SCIENCE. or, in other words, of tlie interdepeiHlciice of all material Nature ? May not Astronomy be regarded as the science of the Universe, using, for different purposes, the apparatus both of the classificatory and applied sciences; and so aiming at the re- duction to order and unity, under this Idea, of a multitude of conceptions drawn from phenomena, which seem at first likely to perplex as much from their unhkeness as their multiplicity ? If the foregoing be, as far as it goes, a true account of the nature of Science, it is evident that any view of Scientific Method will be in the highest degree imperfect, which does not treat of Scientific Ideas, of the conceptions which range under them, and of the laws which regulate this ar- rangement. To the first of these subjects we now proceed. CHAP. VIII. ON SCIENTIFIC IDEAS. A SCIENCE then, however much more it may be, is at least thus much ; the union and grouping of conceptions under an Idea. Hence arises a ques- tion evidently deserving our consideration— what the nature of such Scientific Ideas may be. The difference between an Idea and a Conception has often been drawn, by those who insist on the distinction, with great care and deliberation. A Conception, it has been said, is something derived from observation ; not so Ideas, which meet with nothing exactly answering to them within the range of our experience. Thus Ideas are a priori. Conceptions a posteriori ; and it is only by means of the former that the latter are really possible. For the bare fact, taken by itself, falls short of the Conception, which may be described as the syn- thesis of the fact and the Idea. Thus we have an Idea of the Universe, under which its different phenomena fall into place, and from which they take their meaning ; we have an Idea of Goo as a Creator, from wliich we dcM'ive the power of con- 138 ON SCIENTIFIC IDEAS. ceiving that the niipressions produced upon our minds throiigli the senses result from really exist- ing things ; we have an Idea of the Soul, which enables us to realize our own personal identity, by suggesting that a feehng, conceiving, thinking subject exists as the substratum of every sensation, conception, and thought. Others go further in the same direction, and argue, that Space and Time, which they call conceptions, shadow forth dimly the ruling Ideas of Infinity and Eternity; that the Divine Attributes are Ideas, under which fall even the highest conceptions ; that from Onmipotence comes the conception of Power, from Omniscience that of Knowledge, from the independent Essence of God that of dependent Being, and so on. And this brings us to another grade of opinion, adopted by some; namely, that Equality, for instance, and Similarity, nuist be Ideas, the pre-existence of which enables the mind to recognise things as like and equal; these too, it is said, having no exact counterpart in experience, for we have never met with phenomena which are absolutely like or abso- lutely equal. And now we are evidently trembling on the verge of the Platonic doctrine, according to which each visible and perishable Phenomenon corresponds to some intellectual and eternal Idea. Although there niay be much truth in the general impression which these views convey, they cannot, with any distinctness, all bo held together. In- deed, however true any, or, were it possible, all of ON SCn-NTlFlC IDKAS. 139 ^. them might be, they would nevertheless not be to our purpose. For we are seeking a practical rather than a metaphysical distinction; and are investigating the nature, not of Ideas in general, but of Scientific Ideas only. Sometimes, indeed, that which a metaphysician would recognise as an Idea, lies at the basis of a science ; thus Psycho- logy (if that be at present a real science) refers itself to the Idea of the Soul, and Theology to that of God. In other cases, however, what is called on the above theories a Conception, is really a Scientific Idea. It is, for instance, on the Concep- tion of Space, not on the Idea of Infinity, that the science of Geometry has been raised. It will be better, for our present purpose, to take a different course from that which speculations like those above suggest; and passing by all such questions as concern the abstract nature of Scien- tific Ideas, the manner in which they are attained, their necessary connection with the human mind, and the like, to regard them simply as a species of conceptions— that is, definitely, as conceptions on which sciences can be founded. Our question then assumes a more practical shape, and may be stated as follows— what attributes fit a Conception to become the foundation of a Science ? We shall escape one great danger by throwing our enquiry into this form. The human mind is, as we have l)efore observed, naturally disposed to trust too mucli to method, to venture on this 110 ON SCIENTIFIC IDEAS. presumption beyond tlie bounds of experience and lawful proof, and, not content with ascertaining what is, to detennine, as it thinks, what must be. There have been a priori enumerations on almost every subject from the planets downward; reasons have been given why they, and the senses, and the Categories, and the main divisions of the world, and the primitive substances of Chemistry, should be neither more nor less numerous than they were supposed to be ; till further research has proved the falsity of the suppositions for whicli these reasonings were to account, in some cases; and has rendered their truth uncertain in others. It is well to avoid any risk of falling into this delusive and untrustworthy mode of enquiry : and this end will be effected by keeping the above question steadily before us — by the presence of what at- tributes do we distinguish Scientific Ideas from other Conceptions ? There is the more reason for taking this view of the question, because there seems to be, on the face of things, an absolute impossibility of con- fining these Ideas, in our present state of know- ledge, to any definite number. Sometimes con- ceptions, which have been fated to become the basis of sciences, have been long altogether un- known, as was the case witli the Ideas of Galvanism, Electricitv, and Mat^netism. Sometimes fresh dis- coveries with regard to a Conception, wln'ch has been long familiar, elevate it to the dignity of an ON SCIENTIFIC IDEAS. IH Idea. Tims the conception of Heat long preceded the dawn of a science of Thermotics. Sometimes the Idea, though it retains the same name, becomes, from the association of new phenomena with it, practically so far different, that it may be fairly doubted whether it be really the same Idea as before. Thus Optics assumed a new form when the ray of colourless light was discovered to be com- pound ; and Harmonics underwent a still greater metamorphosis, when the properties of musical notes came to be considered as dependent not on the length of string, but on the number of vibrations. Indeed it would seem, that Science follows as surely upon Practice in matter of fact as it pre- cedes it in theory. Let ai^y set of phenomena once be shewn to be of practical importance to a large pait of society ; and human industry com- bines with curiosity in the endeavour to show their relation to each other. Science will soon be at work to discover the principle which shall reduce the mass of perceptions to order. Thus Medicine, and Theology, win'ch appeal directly to the strong- est and deepest cravings of human nature, have been again and again systematized. On the other hand, where the importance of a subject is of late discovery, the corresponding science is of late origin also. The science of Catallactic has only arisen since the world has been comparatively peaceful, and whole nations and continents have 14-2 ON SriFNTIFir TDKAs. felt their permanent welfare to depend on the principles which regulate exchange. As the world then grows wiser and busier, as men expand the sphere of their operations. Sciences will increase in number, and, with them, Scientific Ideas. It does not follow, however, that, though this be true in the long run, each advance of human Science involves a corresponding increase in the number of Ideas. On the contrary, their number may diminish, when two or three ap- parently distinct branches of knowledge are traced back to a common stock, and are henceforth treated as one. So a point of union has been dis- covered in Galvanism, Electricity, and Magnetism. And Cuvier has given some hints towards a Zoo- logy, or Science of Life, of which Botany and animal Zoology may prove ultimately to be mere subdivisions. And attempts have been made to ac- count for vital action in a manner, which, were it correct, would bring it, according to the different theories, under either Chemistry or Electricity. Least of all, however, can we hope to have all Sciences reduced to that unity, which is implied in the Scholastic type of Deduction, or the Baconian type of Induction. The thought of one vast Science grounded on the Idea of Being, furnished with its due array of subordinate principles, whether we call them Categories, or by some other name, including in itself all possible knowledge, assigning its place to every producible phenomenon, may ON SCI I- NTH IC I OKAS. 143 stand before us as a great Ideal, but one which we must confess is unattainable. Though some con- nected Sciences may show a disposition to fall into each other, yet the lines of scientific enquiry must in general be treated as parallel and independent. If there be, as there seems to be in the Divine Mind, a perfect pyramid of knowledge, yet the apex is so far distant from us, that not only is it itself invisible, but the sides of the pyramid have no sensible inclination towards it. Like the vast majority of the fixed stars, it has no ascertainable parallax. What attributes, then, we proceed to enquire, fit a Conception to become an Idea, and be re- garded as the basis of a Science ? It is evident that every Scientific Idea must be distinct, and that this distinctness should, if pos- sible, be put beyond doubt by definition. But, for reasons which shall be given hereafter. Scientific Ideas can very rarely be defined. Distinctness, however, though requisite to Sci- entific Ideas, is by no means confined to them. It is necessary in every Conception which we employ, for whatever purpose, in Science, or Art, or the conduct of life. Indistinctness is that defect of conceptions in general, which Logic professes to remedy. If it remain uncured, there can be no trusting the second and third operations of the mind, while there is such imperfection in the first. 1J4 ON SCIKNTIFIC IDKAS. ON SCIKNTIFIC IDEAS. 145 Obviousness is another feature, which, though essential to Scientific Ideas, is by no means con- fined to them. But it is not, like distinctness, to be sought in all Conceptions. We have a right to expect it only in the Idea, and in those lowest scientific Conceptions, which, in the classificatory sciences (which perhaps exhibit this principle most clearly) coincide with the phenomenon. Common- sense, though not equal to forming Sciences, exercises over them a kind of dominion when formed. Thus the Deductive Method of investi- gation requires that some obvious Idea, with its attendant principles, wiiether gained intuitively or empirically it matters not, should be assumed first, and then traced into its consequences. During this process, it may be allowed to disappear from the surface of the speculation, to become abstruse and complicated in the forms which it assumes, so as to escape the ken of every mind but that which is truly scientific; but it must issue again at last into the light of day, and show the result of its proceedings. Not the most abstruse Sciences are exempt from this law ; they must l)e capable of being made popular at either extreme. In Geometry, for instance, the Idea of Space, the Axioms and Definitions, on the one hand, and the enunciations of the particular propositions, on the other, are at once intelligible to many who find the greatest difiiculty in perceiving how these pro- positions depend for proof on their ultimate data. The Idea of tliat most compHcated of all Sciences, Astronomy, is perhaps the most obvious of all ; and the results to which it leads are the most generally interesting. And how many persons have just the general Idea of Botany and Zoology, and a keen sense of the beauty and wondrousness of individual instances of animal and vegetable life, who on these subjects find exceeding diflSculty in passing the bounds of the merest empiricism, and entering into the spirit even of the outlines of a really natural system. It was said above, again, that the practical importance of a Conception is necessary in order that it may become an Idea. This, however, seems not quite the kind of test to suit our present purpose. In this practical importance, indeed, the reason lies, which leads the mind of the investigator to dwell more upon the Conception, and found a Science upon it. Still, it does not indicate a feature which belongs to the Idea as such, but rather an antecedent fitness in the Conception for its after- wards becoming an Idea. A more important mark of Scientific Ideas, and one which belongs to them more properly as such, may be found in what we may call their generality. Every Science professes a certain breadth of range. As there cannot be a Science of an individual, so neither can there be of a narrow class. This is evidently natural. We attribute such importance to the unity of Science, simply because it enables k 14(i ON SCIENTIFIC IDEAS. UN SCIKNI'IFIC IDEAS. 147 US to collect together much which would otlier- wise be separate. Were its field so narrow, that observation could thoroughly cover it, or memory exhaust its details, or common sense decide upon all its questions by the process of weighing each particular case, we could much more easily dis- pense with it. So we are always disposed to adopt as an Idea that conception which gives the greatest Generality, the widest possible Unity. So, as we have seen, the early endeavours after systematic Truth hit on the magnificent vision of a single all-embracing Science. And, as knowledge pro- ceeds, men are, as we observed, very ready to diminish the number of Sciences by melting several into one. Conjecture on this as on other points even outstrips enquiry : as at present some enter- tain the hope of discovering a single science of all *' imponderables." The union of Statics and Dynamics under the common name of Mechanics illustrates the same tendency. And perhaps it is to the same cause that we must refer the very common, and, it must be allowed, justifiable inclination for viewing Astronomy as a single Science. This generality, however, by itself does not satisfy oiu' requisitions ; we must also have in a Scientific Idea a quahty which we may be allowed, by way of contrast, to call particnlarittj. Or, to use a phrase more usual and striking, though perhaps for our present purpose less correct. Unity .:• \ in Science is not enough, unless there is also Plurality. Science, we have said, must have a certain breadth : but in that breadth it must not be too uniform. No Universals will serve its purpose, however wide they may be, unless they are capable of division and subdivision, and so can descend to details. Any system, which is deficient either in Generality or Particularity, can only half satisfy our preconceived notion of scientific perfection. A-priori principles of Physics, like those which Kant has given, illustrate generally the former of these defects. They are true enough, but, when ad- mitted, they are too indefinite in their application to be useful, and cannot be so combined as, by hmiting each other, to descend to particulars. The Idea of Being is thus shut out from the number of Scientific Ideas. For we can invent few propositions of which this can be the subject. Scholastic ingenuity could not discover more than three predicates which were suitable to it— Unity, Goodness, and Truth. And, after its first division into Substance and Attribute, the distinctions be- came either empirical or arbitrary. Causality is another conception, which has abundant breadth for a Scientific Idea, but which yet is not the foundation of a Science. Why is this? because the number of propositions as to the relation of cause to effect is exceedingly Hmited ; neither does the Idea naturally subdivide, and so descend l2 k 148 ON SCIENTIFIC IDKAS. to lower conceptions, which the mind can readily embrace, and in which we feel a practical interest. But a Conception may have both Generality and Particularity, may associate itself with broad Universals, and allow a nudtitude of Singulars to be combined under it, and yet be unfitted for a Scientific Idea, if it be incapable of consequen- tiaUtij, Unless it be such, that the subordinate conceptions and propositions seem somehow to be connected with it as P'.ffect with Cause, unless it be a kind of nucleus of which the whole Science is a development, we cannot allow it to be really an Idea. Hence, it would seem, certain Ideas hav^ been supposed to be necessarily intuitive; because, when they are once fully understood, the main principles of the Sciences over which they preside, thougli gained at first empirically, assume the appearance of consequences tiom them. Be this as it may ; thus nuich seems clear, that every Science, and therefore every Scientific Idea, implies some consequentiality. This is evident in the ]nu*e deductive Science of Geometry, which would fall to the ground, were it not for the Definitions, Axioms, and Postulates flow- ing naturally from the Idea of Space ; and the several propositions which follow being only the legitimate consequences of these data. The truth is least obvious in the purely classKicatory Sciences. Botany, for instance, or Gt3ology, appears at first sight to be only the arrangement of phenomena ON SCIENTIFIC IDKAS. 149 known by observation, according to a fixed plan, and not to involve any notion of consequence. It might be thought that any introduction here of Antecedent and Consequent, Cause and Effect, was quite out of place. Yet .it is not really so. A purely artificial arrangement, in which the phe- nomena are grouped according to an arbitrary principle, has no claim to the name of a Science : and we shall see hereafter, that in proportion as a classificatory Science becomes natural, it approxi- mates to the consequential Type. All the Conceptions, then, of Science, the highest, or Idea, as well as the intermediate and lowest, must be distinct. The highest and lowest must both possess a certain Obviousness which is not required in the intermediate conceptions which are employed to connect them. And further, the Idea, which will always be a Conception of practical importance, must possess the attributes of Generality, Parti- cularity, and Consequentiality. And under this the other Conceptions must fall according to a certain system of classification. Into the nature of that system we may now proceed to enquire ; and this consideration will naturally lead us to speak of Definition, which, besides being, as was remarked above, highly conducive to Distinctness, is of the greatest importance in connection with several aspects of Science. CHAP. IX. ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. In considering the subject of Classification, it will be of importance to keep constantly in view the distinction between the principles on which we classify, and the method which we employ in the process. The most prominent point of difference is, that the Principles are material, while the Method is formal ; the former vary with the dif- ferent Sciences, being the main Conceptions which come to om* aid in establishing a connection be- tween the lowest Conceptions and the Idea ; the latter, when these principles are given, enables us to estimate, and as it were to measure, the relation of the various Conceptions included in the Science, to the Idea and to each other. Thus the absence, presence, and number of cotyledons point to the principles of Classification in a natural system of Botany; and absorption, assimilation, exhalation, growth, and generation, occupy a corresponding place in Zoology. The Method of Classification, on the other hand, is the same for all the Sciences. And of this we now proceed to treat. The scheme of Predicables contains the Method of Classification which Aristotle in |)art invented, in ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. 151 part found ready to his hand, and which has descended to us through the Schoolmen with alterations which affect its form more than its substance. Its most received terms have, how- ever, escaped from the Schools, and become the property of the world. Every one who pretends to knowledge talks of Genus and Species, Property and Accident, if not with logical accuracy, at least in a sense of his own. And this renders it the more desirable that we should retain its termi- nology, and adopt its spirit, so far as we properly can. The objections against innovations on received systems apply here with more than usual force. And it will appear, that, with some cautions and modifications, we need not seek a new method of Classification, but may let the Predicables stand. It has been customary to attain the five heads of Predicables in one of two ways — the one, more generally known in consequence of its adoption by modern logicians, according to which Species expresses the whole essence, while Genus indicates the common. Differentia the distinguishing part of the same Essence ; and Property, something joined necessarily. Accident, something joined contingently to it ; — the other, more agreeable to Aristotle, and more commonly employed by the Schoolmen, which begins by separating Genus and Species, as coming under the predicament of Substance, from the other Predicables, which are predicated in QuaHty. 162 ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. Now perhaps it would be unfair to object to the term Essence, when taken barely and without ex- planation, that it implies of necessity, as it certainly does by association, an assent to the realistic doctrine of inherent forms. At any rate, the formula, which leads us to describe Genus by its being predicated of things differing in species, as Species is in its turn of things different in number, is free from this imputation. But they are both liable to another objection, which lies deeper — namely, that they assume our possession of the power to decide generally what attributes are really part of the Essence or Substance of any given thing, and what are not. In other words, they assume, perhaps unwittingly on the part of those who adopt them, the possibihty of a science of Being. If we could, for instance, satisfactorily answer the question, — what is the essence of Man ; we should in so doing enumerate fully all those attributes, in virtue of which the name of Man is appHed to him. Granting that he is according to his essence a rational animal, all other attributes, beside those of animality and rationality, must fall under one of the lower predi- cables. We could not raise above the level of Property or Accident his outward form, his position in the animal and in the intellectual world, his condition as a moral being, his capability of govern- ment or other social relations. The erroneous consequences which flow from ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. 153 ' this view are obvious. If we follow it, we must allow, that, his definition once attained, no re- searches, metaphysical, moral, religious, social, physiological, of which Man is the subject, can have a valid claim to the name of Science. They are the investigations, not of the real nature of Man, but only of certain secondary qualities belong- ing to him. They misplace Man for the time, throw him out of his proper rank in the scale of things, and raise those features of his being which are subordinate or collateral, to the place of the highest dignity. Thus the unity of knowledge would seem to be disturbed, and the natural arrange- ment of Truth broken into, by a misplaced and importunate ingenuity. Such inferences of course cannot be correct. It is impossible that any one view of Man's nature can have such right to exclude every other. His phy- sical organization is not to be neglected, because we attach importance to his reason : his individual being has no right to overpower his social ; and so on. If the system of the Predicables is to stand, it must be placed in a light which will admit of its application to Sciences in general. If we show by their aid the relation of a Conception to a given Idea, this must not disparage our investigating, as a separate question, its relation to another also. In order then that the Predicables may occupy their right position, we must be content to regard the whole (juestion as one of relation ; and to 154 ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. admit, that any given individual cannot, on logical grounds, be ascribed absolutely to any species ; but in order to fix its species, and by consequence to assign to its other attributes their proper place as properties or accidents, we must view it in reference to some Scientific Idea. Our old example will not be the worse for being the most obvious and most common. Suppose an individual human being put before us, and the demand made that we should fix his species, genus, differentia, and so on. The problem is one, which, with the individual alone given, even sup- posing our knowledge of all the circumstances concerning him to be most accurate and perfect, will defy all attempts at solution. Let, for instance, the given man be Nicholas, the Emperor of all the Russias. The difficultv will be to ascertain his ft- species : if this is accomplished, all that follows will be easy enough. But how is this first step to be taken ? Of course, if we are considering Zoology, or are content to assume, that the class to which our first natural impulse would lead us to refer him is really his species, there will be no diflSculty in answering at once, Nicholas is by species a Man. But supposing that we are dwelling rather on some Idea which does not extend beyond the human race ; that, to take a particular case, we are con- structing a Science of Civil Government. We shall then divide men, it may be, according as they are governed or governors: and subdivide the latter ON CLASSII K ATION AND DEFINITION. 155 according as they govern in common with others, or are governors sole ; and this subdivision may be further subdivided, as they rule absolutely, or under certain limits of law or constitution. In a scheme of this kind, Nicholas will belong to the species Despot, or sole governor without limitation of law. So, under the Catallactic science, his species will be Capitalist. And the moralist must investigate the affair of the Nuns of Minsk, and other deaUngs of the father of his people, before he decides under which of his two exhaustive species, the good and the bad, he must place the Czar of Russia. A popular instance like this will serve our im- mediate puri)ose, which is, as we have said, not to construct a new theory of the predicables, but to show, under what provisos we may acquiesce in the old one. And, it now appears, that we are at liberty to retain both the received scheme, and the method of attaining it ; on the condition, however, either of rejecting the word Essence, or interpreting it as the union of those attributes which are con- sidered to constitute a Class in relation to a given Idea, Adopting, then, this manner of regarding Essence, our view of the Predicables follows as a matter of course. Species will evidently be the expression of all those attributes, which are considered as constituting the Class relatively to the given Idea. And the notion of Classification implies that of order and arrangement. A Class necessarily 156 ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. 157 suggests to the mind the existence of collateral Classes — standing by its side, that is, as members of the same division. With these, it will have certain attributes in common. These will be re- presented by the Genus, which may be defined, as the Expression of those attributes which a Class has in common with its collateral Classes. The expression of those attributes in which the Class differs from its collateral Classes will, in like manner, be the Differentia. But, supposing certain attributes to be con- sidered as constituting a Class relatively to a given Idea, it is evident that certain other attributes might possibly be considered to constitute the same Class, when viewed in relation to another Idea. Thus the word Man indicates the same Class, whether it comes from the lips of the zoologist or the psychologist; though the one looks to the form which animal life assumes in his fellow-creatures, the other regards the peculiarity of their intellectual constitution. A question might indeed be raised, whether the Class was in either case strictly speaking the same, or whether we should not rather speak of two different Classes including exactly the same individuals.* But this doubt is quite foreign to our present enquiry ; and the two Classes, if they are theoretically distinct, must be allowed to be prnclicallfj the samp. And the point which we have to decide is, in what light we are to regard those attributes which are B observed uniformly to accompany a Class ; although, when it was formed in reference to a given Idea, they were quite foreign to that Idea, and therefore were not taken into account in forming it. The answer of the Logician here corresponds with the common phraseology of educated men : both would agree in calling them Properties ; and the predicable " proprium" may accordingly be defined, as the Expression of those attributes which are observed uniformly to accompany a Class, though they were not taken into consideration in form- ing it. Of the remaining predicable. Accident, little need be said. Certain attributes are observed to be associated with the Individual. The question naturally arises, — are they also associated with the Class? If this be determined in the aflfirmative, further questions remain. Do they by themselves constitute the Class ? If so, they find their ex- pression in the Species, Should this not be so — do they go to constitute the Class ? If so, they are either shared by the collateral Classes, and so fall under the Genus, ox distinguish the Class in question from the collateral Classes, and are therefore ex- pressed by the Differentia. If, though associated with the Class, they neither in whole nor in part constitute it, we have already seen that their ex- pression is the predicable Properti/. If, on the other hand, they neither, in whole or in part, con- stitute the Class, nor are observed uniformly to 158 ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITIDN. ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. 159 accompany it, they fall under the head of Accident : and that predicable may be defined, as the Expres- sion of such attributes as neither are taken into consideration in forming the Class, nor are observed uniformly to accompany it. We are now in a position to enter on the subject of Logical Definition. For, in common phrase, we define the Species, by means of its Genus and Differentia. On an accurate use of these terms must depend the distinctness of our notion of Definition. And, by a natural and common re- action, we shall gain a clearer view of the nature and importance of the Predicables, by viewing them in this connection. They are part of the apparatus and instruments of Logic, and cannot be appreciated, unless we consider their use. We shall learn much of them, by seeing them em- ployed. In the first place, then, a Corollary with refer- ence to Definition naturally follows from the above remarks. It is, that all Definition is necessarily relative; and therefore that all attempts at absolute Definition are from their very nature failures, and may be rejected without individual examination. To any one who assents to the previous theory of the predicables, this is an evident consequence. For if all correct Definition be, as it is commonly granted to be, by means of Genus and Differentia, and the predicables be in their very nature relative, it will follow of course that Definition is entirely I r r relative also. But we may attain the same con- clusion by a less technical method, and one better adapted to convince the general reader. What is Definition ? Most authorities would agree in answering, that it is the statement in its fulness of the meaning of a conception, or, as some would prefer, of a term. Were then absolute Definition possible, it would exhaust the meaning of the thing defined. To take our old example, Man. If he were capable of absolute Definition, every conception that is necessarily associated with the conception of Man, in the mind of the most enlightened thinker and most extended enquirer, must enter into it. He could not be defined under a folio volume. Those attributes which are observed in him by the Physician and the Moralist have as good a prima facie right to enter into his Definition, as those observed by the Meta- physician and the NaturaUst. If one insists on his possession of reason, another may dwell on his possession of two hands, or his place in the scale of moral beings, or the length of his intestinal canal. So the Definition would needs prove in this case an assemblage of most promiscuous and ill- assorted matter. Or, to take another example, that of atmospheric Air ; how shall this be defined ? By the proportions of oxygen and azote which enter into its composition ? or by its relation to animal life ? or by its elasticity viewed as a fluid ? or by its properties of refraction as an optical medium ? 160 ON CLASSI I [CATION ANh DKFIMTIOS. Those who hold that Definition is absohite, nnist say, — By all of these. All of these conceptions, and many more, enter into the notion which an educated man entertains of Air. And to enumerate any thing short of the whole, would be, on this hypothesis, to define imperfectly. An absolute Definition therefore is impossible, on account of the prolixity and confusion of ideas which it necessarily involves. It would resolve itself at best into a long string of unconnected epithets. However complete it might be as a general summary of our knowledge on the subject, it would be utterly wanting in clearness, and would prove no remedy for indistinctness. This being granted, an important consequence follows. We must be content with relative De- finition ; and therefore, a Conception will be capable of at least as many Definitions as there are Sciences, or, which is the same. Scientific Ideas, under which it falls. This, again, the Logician who has followed the previous reasoning will not be slow to admit. If all the Predicables imply a reference to a certain Scientific Idea, the Definition, which is composed of two of them, will imply such reference also ; and as the Ideas nuiltiply, the Predicables increase, and, with them, the Definitions also. But this position, like the former, admits of being put into a more practical form ; into which w^e proceed to throw it. ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. 161 All Definition implies Classification. In defining a Class-conception, (and Class-conceptions alone are definable,) we undertake to show the boundaries which separate it from other Classes, with which it might possibly be confused. But as each Science has its own peculiar Classification, it necessitates also a peculiar Definition, by which the Class in question may be separated from all other Classes which the said Science recognises. The same formula which answers the purpose of distinction in one case, will not serve in another. To keep to our old example, — can any form of w^ords, suf- ficiently concise to be recognised by common- sense as a Definition, be devised, which shall at once show how^ Man is to be distinguished from Spirits, good and bad, and from other incorporeal agencies; and the point at w^hich he parts com- pany with the brute creation ? or, regarding that physical structure which he has in common with brutes, will sum up the features of resemblance and those of difference, which he exhibits when compared with such collateral Classes as the lion and the hare ; and his relation to such more distant Classes as the eagle and the ostrich; or, further still, to the oyster and the crab ? What an entire confusion would necessarily result from the at- tempt to bring before the mind at once all these various points of contrast! By one course only can we avoid it. Man must be defined in one way, if we would see his place in the Spiritual M 16-2 ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. ON CLASS! FK^ATION AND DEFINITION. 1()3 world; in another, if we would regard him in his relation to Good and Evil ; in a third, if he is viewed relatively to the Idea of Life. In many other cases a like difficulty is evident, which must be met in the same manner. We should feel a misgiving if called upon suddenly to define feldspar, for in- stance, or the diamond. The reason probably is, that we should be doubting how to attempt the Definition ; whether we should view them as Minerals, or bring them under Chemistry — consult their crystallography, or their analysis. And the mind seems quite at a loss, and set afloat on a wide sea of speculation, when called on to define some Conception which does not fall naturally under any formed Science. In the absence of a true Science of ^Esthetics, we feel that it is vain to attempt a true Definition of the Subhme, or the Beautiful. One remark remains to be made on this part of the subject. It has been said above, that a Conception may have as many Definitions as there are Ideas under which it falls. We will now observe, that it may have more. The same Idea may be developed by means of different subordinate Conceptions, which will lead of course to dif- ferent Classifications, and therefore to different Definitions. Linnaeus and Cuvier both bring Man under the genus Mammalia ; though the one finds his Differentia in the number of his incisor and molar teeth, the other in his possession I. -f/.:,* ill 'W: of hands. Aristotle, who makes his genus Biped, completes the Definition by distinguishing him from birds either by the absence of wings, or, which comes to nearly the same thing, the restric- tion of his motions to this vile earth we tread on. If each of these accounts of Man distinguishes him with suflScient accuracy from other animals, none of them can well be called an incorrect Definition. Yet one of them will of course be superior to the others. This superiority depends on the respective merits of the Classification employed. And that Classification is to be pre- ferred, in which the Idea, and the lowest Con- ceptions, are connected by the most appropriate intermediate generalisations. What constitutes such appropriateness, it is not hard, in a general manner, to see. Those have the advantage, which, while they apply with sufficient obviousness to the lowest Conceptions, flow at the same time most naturally from the Idea. By their flowing natu- rally from the Idea is meant, that either reason shows a priori their connection with it, or observa- tion and experiment abundantly establish the same fact a posteriori. Thus in Geometry the division of geometrical magnitudes into those of one, two, and three dimensions is natural on the former account: finite space implying possible measure- ment; and length, breadth, and thickness being obviously the three aspects of space which admit of measurement. And Cuvier's arrange- M 2 1()4 UN CLASSIFICATION ANIJ hKHNlllUN ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. l(>5 nient of animals according to the nature of their respiratory and circulating apparatus is an ex- ample of the latter kind; it being amply proved by observation, that according to the perfection of the organs of respiration and circulation, the various functions of animal life are more or less perfectly performed. It is evident that a Deiinition may in this man- ner be reduced to those dimensions which custom and reason have allowed it, and very frequently to its ideal perfection of form, in which it consists only of two words, one of which is the Genus, and the other the Differentia. For, supposing a Class to be viewed thus relatively to an Idea, it is not necessary, in order to distinguish it from other Classes which refer to the same Idea, to enumerate all the attributes with which we know it is invested. We only need to draw the line of demarcation clearly between it and those other Classes. And this will be done, if we show, first of all, how it is related to them in the way of resemblance ; which is expressed by Genus: and then, how it is dis- tinguished from them by certain peculiarities; which is expressed by Differentia. All its other constant attributes come in as Properties ; its inconstant as Accidents ; and those only, which are prominent in the scheme of Classification, enter into the Definition. If, for instance, to the received Definition of Man as a bimanous manmuil, it be objected, that many other attributes, besides those of being viviparous and possessing hands, are necessary to our Conception of Man, such as reason, imagination, the erect posture, the face divine ; the answer is simply, that, so far as the functions of life are concerned, these attributes are not essential, and that the Zoologist views Man with regard to life, and to no other Idea whatsoever. Linnaeus once went so far as to describe the ourang-outang as Homo Simius ; and the practical inconvenience of such a Definition would not have been sufficient to overthrow it, if the physical structure of the brute had borne out, as it did not, the correctness of the Classifica- tion. Indeed,^t present it may be doubted with some plausibility, whether the word Man, as employed in different Sciences, always indicates precisely the same individuals. Thus an Idiot is to the moralist no Man ; and one theory of capital punishment assumes, that the culprit by the com- mission of atrocious crime ceases to possess social rights, in other words, to be a Man in the sense of the Political Science. If this be true, the body of the criminal who has been executed would never- theless be that of a Man for every purpose of the Naturalist. But there is still room for objection left. It may be argued, that, supposing the Definition to be restricted to one Idea, it may still be a very long affair indeed. The above Definition of Man, for instance, does not express all his attributes which 166 ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. 167 have reference to life. Why should his prehensile organs be held to have such reference, if those of locomotion are excluded ? The fact of his having two hands either has no connection with the Idea of Life, or, if it has, must impart a share of that honour to the fact of his having feet also. In spite of this objection, our definition of Man may stand. It is valid, if it marks him off from every other class of animal whatsoever ; if we are prepared to say, as we are, that every animal which is viviparous, and lias two hands and two only, is entitled to the name of Man. This seems the place to consider another ob- jection to which this plan of concise Definition is liable. It has been argued, that a Definition, which does not enumerate all the attributes of a Class, but only such as are assumed lo be distinctive, though long accepted and approved, may fail at last, and be convicted of falsehood. A bimanous mammal, it is urged, may hereafter be discovered, which shall be formed, in some respects, on quite a different type from Man, and to which we should refuse the name, though consistency would urge us to grant it. Neither is it sufficient, taking another point of view, to define him as a Rational animal ; because, it is said, we should not grant the name of a man to a fish or a quadruped, which was found to possess reason. Wc might reply to such instances as these, tliat Definition is grounded on Classification, which con- r templates only existing things ; and that it is hard therefore to object to it, that it neglects the creatures of imagination, and makes no grave provision for non-entities. But this would be only to evade the difficulty. Cases something like the imaginary examples given above, actually occur. Existing systems of Classification are occa- sionally broken into by apparent anomalies, which are stubborn facts nevertheless, and must, ulti- mately, have a place found them. The answer which fairly meets the case, will also bring for- ward another view of our subject. Definition does not, with whatever it deals, actually give Knowledge. It provides for the dis- tinctness, not the discovery, of Truth. It has no alchemical power of turning dross into gold ; but serves as a touch-stone, by applying which to the individual, we may ascertain the extent of our general information on the matter in hand. We shall soon discover this, if we make a few attempts, which are by no means unprofitable as intellectual exercises, at defining. We shall find, that, if we fail, it is often not so much from ignorance of the Conception we wish to define, as from our insuf- ficient acquaintance with the Classes from which we would distinguish it. A man possessing the most thorough acquaintance with the ingredients, and properties, and uses of Coal, could not there- fore define it. He might describe it at length, but this, we have seen, would be no logical Definition. " ; ' ) \ V, 168 ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. 169 If he attempted to select one or two distinguishing attributes, he would most likely fail in the attempt ; because he was ignorant, not of the substance itself, but of the other substances from which it is to be distinguished. To be successful, he must know, not only the mineral in question, but other mine- rals also, and a science of Mineralogy as well. As then we can only classify phenomena which we know, so we can only define on the supposition that such Classification is correct, and based on a sufficient observation of phenomena. The Defini- tion of Man can only distinguish him from all other known animals, or all other known rational beings. According to the probabihty that other rational beings, or other animals, in many respects resembhng him, have, or have not, escaped our observation, will be the probability that a Defini- tion, which is certainly valid in the existing state of our knowledge, will, or will not, continue valid hereafter. We are now close upon the great point of difference between the ancient and modern views of Definition. We have seen that it is a conse- quence of regarding Definition as relative to an Idea, to hold that, though it implies knowledge, it does not give it. He who can define well must be master of his subject : and to one who had not at least a general acquaintance with it, his words would convey no meaning. Only the proficient can give a Definition : only the adviinced pupil can follow it. Suppose, for instance, a hearer to have no system of Classification under which the diamond falls, or a different one from that employed by him who defines it. The Definition will be unmeaning to him in the former case ; it will seem inelegant, irregular, or possibly even wrong, in the latter. This would not be the case, if Definition were, as it was supposed to be, absolute. To define a Conception, would not be in that case to assign it a place in relation to a particular Science, but to state its gradation in the great scale of things. Definition would not appeal to a Classification with which students only were supposed to be acquainted ; but would regard all things by the common light of human nature. On this hypothesis, it would be intelligible to one who had no antecedent ac- quaintance with the subject. Thus Definition was formerly considered as one actual source of know- ledge. Fresh information was to be extracted from it by means of the syllogistic apparatus. By its aid, the imperfections of sense were to be remedied, and Science carried beyond the sphere of observation. And hence the importance formerly attached to the rule, which commanded that every Definition should be composed of two parts, each in itself '' better known than the thing defined." There was a very intelligible sense attached to the phrase in question. Those things were better known in themselves, though probably less known 170 ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. 171 to US, which were more universal. They held a higher place in the deductive scheme, and ap- proached nearer to those summary laws of Nature, on which lower laws were founded. Thus they were more cognisable by reason, just as things less universal were more cognisable by sense. And therefore the rule above given might be put in other words as follows — the Genus and Differentia must each of them be more Universal than the Species to be defined. This rule is evidently binding in the case of Genus, if, as we have said above, it expresses the attributes common to the group of collateral Classes, of which the Species is one. Nor is it hard to see the reason of Aristotle and the School- men after him, for making the same demand with regard to Differentia. They intended, as it has been observed, that the Definition should give knowledge. This it was to do, by enabling the mind to combine two Conceptions, which it had entertained previously, into a new Conception ; just as in syllogism from the two premises we draw a conclusion, which while it requires both, is distinct from either. It would not be difficult to shew, that this view assigns a power to the human mind which it does not really possess, of combining its Conceptions according to some certain and in- variable law. Two Conceptions may indeed be added mechanically one to another; but we can no more^ predict, in Metaphysic, what will result f from their intimate union, than we can foretel, in Chemistry, how the appearance and properties of a protoxide will be altered, by its combination with another volume of oxygen. In either case we may make happy guesses, but we have no guide to which we can trust implicitly ; nothing beyond that tact in perceiving analogies and so anticipating consequences, which experience developes if it does not give, and the conclusions of which, in their most perfect form, cannot, if unsupported from without, rank very high in the scale of pro- bability. But, putting considerations of this kind aside, it is clear, that if a Definition is, in accordance with this hypothesis, to give knowledge, it must be made up of Conceptions, each wider than the Class to be defined. For, if either of its parts be only co-extensive with the Class, no new range will be gained by the mind, which must still be fettered by the limits of observation. On this theory, for instance, it would be unsatisfactory to define Man by his having two hands. Whence, it may be asked, has the mind derived this Concep- tion of bimanous ? Since nothing except man is two-handed, it can only be from man himself. So the Definition is not really explicative, because, in order to understand it, we must be acquainted with man, who is its subject. We may define him as an animal with two feet and without plumage, and escape this objection. For though no other 172 ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. animal be both two-footed and destitute of plumage, we may derive each of these notions, animal, biped, and featherless, from other sources than Man. In modern enquiries, where Definition stands not as the source but as the registry of our knowledge, no such restriction is required. We are content that the Genus shall be often co- extensive with the Species. Unambitious of exer- cising the dangerous privilege of combining Con- ceptions independently of experience, we only claim that the Differentia be as clear and as universal as the Class defined, and seek neither greater clearness, nor a wider universality. We have confined our considerations, hitherto, to purely Logical Definition. We have seen, tliat, in order to sustain its pretensions at all, it must allow them to be considerably narrowed. In no suflficient sense does it state the nature of the thing defined. It implies no attempt at exhausting the attributes of its subject. This it views, not as it is in itself, but only in its relation to a certain Idea. Neither do all the attributes which can be shown to refer to the Idea enter into the Definition. Those only are there admitted, on which the place of the Conception with reference to the Idea turns— those only, in other words, which enter into the scheme of Classification. Thus it is not quite correct to say, that a Logical Division expresses the analysis of a Conception. It is grounded on such an analysis, but does not wholly express it. We ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. 173 ' take an individual, and reject those attributes which belong to it as such. Being thus rid of the Accidents, we have gained the Conception of the Species. Of this, the Attributes divide into those which have direct reference to the Idea under which it falls, as entering into the scheme of Classification, and those which have not. Of these, the former, portioned out into Genus and Differentia, compose the Definition; the latter take their place under the stricter or looser senses of Property. It would be foreign to our present purpose to speak of Definitions other than Logical. SuflSce it to say, that from Logical Definition they derive their name, in virtue of a likeness and analogy more or less cogent. But they are wholly un- scientific, and are useful only as suggestive, or as affording raw material, so to speak, for further speculation. Thus Physical Definition is a con- junction of words which has almost, if not quite, disappeared from our ordinary phraseology. It signifies only an enumeration of all the attributes of the Class defined so far as they are known ; without any selection, or scientific arrangement, or grouping under an Idea. It is therefore prior to Classification, as Logical Definition is posterior to it ; and from its indiscriminate mass the Natu- rahst selects what is fitted for his purpose. To use a distinction of Lord Bacon's, it belongs, not to Physic, but to Natural History. Thus it 174 ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. follows the analogy of Logical Definition, in being grounded on an analysis ; but here it is the thing which we analyse, and not the Conception. Nominal Definition has held its place, but by a very doubtful title. Its exact nature. Logical writers find it hard to state. The most consistent view of it is also the simplest, and that which rests on the most ancient authorities. We define a thing nominally, when we show, or rather attempt to show, its nature, by examining the etymological formation of the word by which we commonly express it. This also is evidently named from the analogy of Logical Definition, being founded on an analysis, not, however, of the Conception, but of the Word. Though often highly suggestive, it can seldom be trusted, unless we are prepared to allow, that, in forming compound words, men have always regarded the most fimdamental and permanent features of the objects to which they apphed them, to the exclusion of those which are fleeting and superficial. Of all the spurious species of Definition, that which is called Accidental, or, in one word. De- scription, is at once of most common use, and least nearly related to its Logical prototype. Without any attempt at analysis, it merely takes those attributes of the Class which appear most salient and characteristic, and calls attention to them as marks by which it may be recognised, quite inde- pendently of its relation to other Classes. I 1/ ON CLASSIFrCATION AND DEFINITION. 175 These few remarks on tlie secondary kinds of Definition are a digression from our main subject : but they may be useful in showing, that one Species only is recognised by Science ; that of this, all others are, more or less, imitations ; and that, in every case. Scientific and Logical Definition coincide. One possible diflSculty attendant on the previous views, still remains to be obviated. It may be objected to the practical working of this scheme of Relative Definition, that it reduces all Sciences to a dead level, and destroys their real distinctions as to dignity and importance. Has Man, as such, it may be asked, no Definition? Is it of no consequence, whether we view him as mortal or immortal, in his relation to the animal kingdom, or to the spiritual world? Logic will do little' service, if it thus violates Common-sense, and overleaps a difference which we observe in every- day life. A little care in drawing a necessary distinction will serve to meet this difficulty. Suppose the same thing to be defined in reference to several Ideas. It follows, that each Definition may be equally con-ect, but not, of course, equally im- portant. As the Ideas themselves rise and fall in dignity, so will the Classifications and Definitions which are founded on them. Thus the value to be attached to the several Definitions will depend, not on the degree of their correctness, (for all may be 174 ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. follows the analogy of Logical Definition, in being grounded on an analysis ; but here it is the thing which we analyse, and not the Conception. Nominal Definition has held its place, but by a very doubtful title. Its exact nature. Logical writers find it hard to state. The most consistent view of it is also the simplest, and that which rests on the most ancient authorities. We define a thing nominally, when we show, or rather attempt to show, its nature, by examining the etymological formation of the word by which we commonly express it. This also is evidently named from the analogy of Logical Definition, being founded on an analysis, not, however, of the Conception, but of the Word. Though often highly suggestive, it can seldom be trusted, unless we are prepared to allow, that, in forming compound words, men have always regarded the most fimdamental and permanent features of the objects to which they apphed them, to the exclusion of those which are fleeting and superficial. Of all the spurious species of Definition, that which is called Accidental, or, in one word. De- scription, is at once of most common use, and least nearly related to its Logical prototype. Without any attempt at analysis, it merely takes those attributes of the Class which appear most salient and characteristic, and calls attention to them as marks by which it may be recognised, quite inde- pendently of its relation to other Classes. 1/ ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. 175 These few remarks on the secondary kinds of Definition are a digression from our main subject : but they may be useful in showing, that one Species only is recognised by Science ; that of this, all others are, more or less, imitations ; and that, in every case. Scientific and Logical Definition coincide. One possible diflficulty attendant on the previous views, still remains to be obviated. It may be objected to the practical working of this scheme of Relative Definition, that it reduces all Sciences to a dead level, and destroys their real distinctions as to dignity and imijortance. Has Man, as such, it may be asked, no Definition? Is it of no consequence, whether we view him as mortal or immortal, in his relation to the animal kingdom, or to the spiritual world? Logic will do Httle service, if it thus violates Common-sense, and overleaps a difference which we observe in every- day life, A little care in drawing a necessary distinction will serve to meet this difficulty. Suppose the same thing to be defined in reference to several Ideas. It follows, that each Definition may be equally con-ect, but not, of course, equally im- portant. As the Ideas themselves rise and fall in dignity, so will the Classifications and Definitions which are founded on them. Thus the value to be attached to the several Definitions will depend, not on the degree of their correctness, (for all may be 1 176 ON CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION. equally correct) but on the comparative promi- nence of the Ideas — a subject which shall be mentioned, though not discussed, at the conclusion of this Essay. I CHAP. X. ON THE GRAUATIONS OF SCIENCE. We will now once more recapitulate the com- mon features which are possessed by all the Sciences. In the first place, each of them is grounded on an Idea. Next, under this Idea is ranked a multitude of Conceptions. Thirdly, these Conceptions have, amongst each other, an Order and Arrangement, in which constant re- ference is had to the Idea. Fourthly, beside this Order and Arrangement, which either tends to, or amounts to. Classification, there is some aim at, and appearance of, Deductiveness, and consequentiahty, wherever fonnal Deduction, and strict Conse- quence, are, from the nature of the case, impossible. Thus much for the common features of Sciences in general. They will be indirectly illustrated yet further in the following remarks, which are in- tended, however, to answer directly a different pui-pose, and to mark, not the Similarity, but the Distinction of Sciences ; not their Uniformity, but their Gradations. The highest place in the scale is of course as- signed to Pure Science. Of this we take Geometry N 178 ON Tin: CiUADATIONS OF SCIENCE. as the type. Its peculiar and characteristic excel- lency is, its entire dependence on its Idea. The Idea, in this case, once given, all the Science necessarily follows. It is the nucleus round which all that is homogeneous with it clusters by a natural law. When once Space is conceived by the mind, mere cogitation, without the aid of experience, would be able to draw fi*om this Idea the Conceptions of Lines, Surfaces, and Solids, and all the various species of these which the Science of Geometry recognises. The prin- ciples of Classification, also, are here exemplified. They only escape attracting our attention, by appearing in so natural and obvious a form. It has been said above, that on Classification follows Definition. Here, accordingly, a good Classifica- tion lies at the very base of the Science, and a corresponding series of accurate Definitions follows it. We begin Pure Science by defining. In other words, we commence by positing bur Species, and stating their Genus and Difference. That result, at which, as we shall see presently, lower ibrms of Science aim, is attained before the main labour of pure Science begins. Being thus furnished with an Idea, and the subordinate Conceptions, and the system of Clas- sification, we apply oiu'selves to our new work, that of drawing Consequences. And the con- sequentiality is here Jis perfect as all that has preceded it. There is no gap between our Data ON THK (iHADAIlUNS OF SCIKNCE. 179 and our ultimate conclusions. The necessary laws of inference, when applied to the Definitions, Axioms, and Postulates, enable us to invest our Species with Properties before unknown. Squares, Triangles, Circles, become no clearer as we ad- vance; for they were accurately defined before we began our researches. But they do become fuller Conceptions, as they are associated in our minds with fresh Attributes. And all these Attributes are Properties : they are proved to be inseparably connected with the several Classes, though not taken into consideration in forming them. In this most perfect sphere of speculation. Accidents have no place. Such then are the distinctive excellencies of Pure Science. It possesses the highest Unity, being simply the development of a single Idea. It begins with a perfect Classification, and following on this, with accurate and perfect Definitions. But these merits are comparatively eclipsed by its most distinguishing excellency, an exact and per- fect Consequentiality. From first to last, it flows in one direction, from the Idea downwards. There is no appeal to Experience, — no desire of confirm- ation from without, — no endeavour, when the fact has been derived from one quarter, to find the reason in another. Every link of the chain of knowledge holds : and, wherever the process stops short, it is, as far as it goes, perfect; having perhaps an unfinished air, but still enduring even in this n2 180 ON THi: GRADATIONS OF SCIENCK intermediate Ibnii, aii^l capable of addition withont alteration. Next in place of dignity to Pure Science come the Applied Sciences. Of these, we have before taken Mechanics as an example. Here, too, we have an Idea, and a number of conclusions flowing from certain data according to a necessary con- sequence. But the Applied Sciences are in- ferior to the preceding Class in one important particular. They have not the same absolute Unity. Their main Principles, though closely connected with the Idea, need not be deductions from it, mere phases and aspects in which it exhibits itself anew. They often need independ- ent proof, and rest upon the testimony of Ex- perience. Thought alone could not have extracted them from the Idea. No one, by only pondering the nature of Force, could arrive at the knowledge of the laws of Motion. Thus therc^ is an interval, so to speak, in the Applied Sciences, between the Idea and the subordinate Principles, which ex- cludes them from perfect Unity, lowers the student from the sphere of pure Abstraction, brings him to the border-land of the Intellectual and Sensible, and introduces the contrast, though not in its hardest outline, between Form and Matter. Thus tlie province of Reason is somewhat narrowed, and that of Experience expands. In this respect their practical appHcation answers to their theory. Though, the further they are ON TUli GRADATIONS OF S(TKNCE. 181 pressed, the more power they display ; though they admit, in ])ractice, of a minute elaboration to an extent which beforehand would be simply in- credible; though they transcend the limits of observation, and become i)rophetic at the time, to derive afterwards fresh credit from the verification of their predictions; yet one important part of their office is to account for the past. This is seldom the case with Pure Science. That, for the most part, gives at once the fact and the reason. It does not usually derive the knowledge of a truth from some extraneous source, and then account for it in virtue of certain known laws; but, ft'om these laws, reaches out to new propositions, which, but for it, would have remained unknown. Not so the Applied Sciences, which have generally, in all their provinces, to account for facts which are known from Observation and other independent sources, before they are trusted in the field where Reason supersedes Sense, and takes a free flight beyond the regions of Experiment. But if the Applied Sciences be thus deficient in Unity, a more serious objection Hes against the next Class of Sciences, which we call Classificalorij. Of these, we may take Botany as an example. They have indeed a sufficiently perfect Unity of Idea. P^very fact of BotcUiy, for instance, bears naturally on the Idea of Vegetable Life. The mind is never in suspense, never seems wandering from its subject. All the C'onceptions group themselves. 182 ON THE GUADATlOiNS OF SCIKNCE. whether readily or not, at least with obvious reference to a single purpose. And therefore the Classificatory Sciences exhibit, in their fullest perfection, the system of Classification, and the practical use of the Predicables. Accidents are not excluded from their cognisance, as in the higher forms of Science. Varieties, for instance, or those modifications of the s])ecies which are not necessarily permanent, though they seem prac- tically to be so; the habitat of a plant, or its ceconomic uses, though confessedly Accidents, find their place in a Botanical treatise. Definition also is perfectly exhibited, though its position here is very different from that which it occupies in Pure Science. There, as we have seen, the Species are first defined, and then certain Attributes, which we at once recognise as Properties, either in the stricter or looser sense of the term, are affixed to them by the process of inference. In the Classificatory Sciences we begin at the other extreme. A mass of Attributes is phiced before us ; we have to arrange them in such a manner, as to determine what constitute the Class (in other words, enter into its Definition), and what do not. And those Attributes which fall under the latter head, according as they are permanent or not, are distributed into the remaining classes of Property and Accident. But the great deficiency of thc.>L' Sciences, in spite of their combining correct Classification and ON THE (iUADATlONS OF SCIENCE. 183 Division with a sufiKcient Unity, lies in their lack of Consequentiality. Let the facts be arranged in the best possible manner ; the principle of cohesion is still wanted. The facts must be taken on trust; they bear Httle or no evidence to their own truth; they resemble, when combined, some piece of Mosaic work, which must be held together by a frame, or it would fall to pieces ; they require the check of evidence, and the support of observa- tion. In Geometry, no position of Euclid can be ignored or doubted by one who has paid due attention to the treatise, without his exposing him- self to the charge of folly or wilfulness. In the Applied Sciences, when certain premises are granted, all doubt as to the sequel is put out of the question. But in Mineralogy or Botany, each separate asser- tion admits of dispute ; the proof of any one will not serve to estabhsh any other : all the internal evidence of the truth of a system lies in the natural air of its details, and the consistency of its general features. Is there then, it may be asked, no Consequen- tiality in the Classificatory Sciences ? May we not say here, as well as in Mathematics, that the Properties are traceable to the nature of the Species, as effect to cause ? When, for instance, monocoty- ledonous i)lants are found to be endogens, while dicotyledonous plants are exogens, may we not say that these modes of growth are consequences, respectively, of the single and double cotyledon ? 184 ON THE GRADATIONS OF SCIENCt. We answer, in the first place, that while it would be rash to deny all consequentiality to the Classifi- catory Sciences, we may safely assert, that, when compared to the previous kinds of Sciences, they prove in this respect greatly deficient. It is certain that we have here no such knowledge of the laws of consequence as to enable us to predict results. No one could have told a priori, that mono- cotyledonous plants are endogens; no one can venture safely on hke predictions hereafter. All attempts at anticipation on such subjects must depend on Analogies, which often fail, and can never be more than probable evidence. So that, at best, Consequentiahty shows itself here in its lowest form. We must be abundantly content, if, having traced our facts first, we can discover the reasons afterwards. We should further observe, that it is by no means the same thing to be sure that consequence exists, that two phenomena are connected as cause and effect : and to be able to investigate the stages of the consequence, to have the history, so to speak, of the causahty. One phenomenon may invariably, so far as our observation goes, follow and attend upon another; and yet we may perceive such a gap in the nature of things between them, as may serve to convince us that there must bJ some remote law, as yet perhaps undiscovered, on which their connection depends. To take our former example: thus much seems clear, that ON THE GRADATIONS OF SCIENCE. 185 endogenous growth is the consequence of the pre- sence of but one cotyledon : but the fact of the consequence does not explain its mystery; its law is still unknown. Admitting that the phenomena do accompany each other, we enquire zvliy ; and at present, in vain. We may now briefly state the sum of the previous remarks on the gradations of Science. Pure Science, we have seen, is the type which unites perfections elsewhere separate, and in which Unity of structure and complete Classification meet with perfect Consequence. In the Applied Sciences, the Consequence, when the premises are once given, may be as perfect, but the Unity is of a lower kind, and depends less entirely on the Idea. The Clas- sificatory Sciences have a Unity nearly as perfect as that of Pure Science, with a Classification as perfect, and of yet wider range. But here the parts are bound together by a loose tie, and the scientific mind regrets the absence of Consequen- tiality. One observation remains to be made at this part of our subject. Sciences are sometimes compli- cated. Observation and Reason go together to make up the whole. An inductive process, which is mainly one of Classification, is to be gone through before the premises are gained from which the deduction begins. And this process is not always, in the less exact Sciences, considered as antecedent to the Science, but sometimes as a part of it. Thus in ISCy ON THK GRADATIONS OF SCIKNCK. ON THE GRADATIONS OF SCIENCE. 187 Harmonics the relation of theiniinber of vibrations to sound, though a matter of experiment, is recognised as part of the Science ; though it serves mainly as the preHminary to other i)arts, which deduce hence the laws of harmony and discord as dependent on numl)er. Sciences Hke these take their place according to their predominant element. We nuist analyse them, and rank them higher or lower, as the Em- pirical or the Rational preponderates. There is another Class of Compound Sciences, such as Geology, and, especially of late. Astronomy, which assume another form. First of all, a certain set of phenomena are collected and arranged : a number of truths are gained by inference, observ- ation, or both. So far the ordinary procedure of Science is observed. We state, after due consider- ation, what is true at present. But another Class of questions soon comes in. We ask, wliat condi- tions of things in past time these present truths presuppose. These are some of the most interest- ing problems connected with Science. Who is not anxious to know, what we can lawfully infer as to the state of the earth in past ages, from the present facts of its stratification and organic remains; — how far celestial phenomena make the nebular hypo- thesis probable ;— and whether the optical ])r()j)erties of the diamond oblige us to assign it a vegetable origm ) nomena that Science, in the strict sense, deals. In attaining or arranging these, it occupies itself. The further queries resulting hence, in deciding which we must infer what has been formerly from what is now, do not belong properly to Scientific Method. There is here no subordination and arrangement, but only a question, as to the practical connection of fact with fact. We can only ask— does the existing state of things necessitate the belief, that another economy, differing in certain given respects, existed at a certain given time ? Our facts are as so many witnesses in a court of justice. To decide whether they prove their point, appertains not to Scientific Method, but to the ordinary laws of Evidence. In cases of this kind, it is with the present phe- ON METHOD IN ART. 189 J CHAP. XL ON METHOD IN ART We should wander far from the direct hne of our enquiry, were we to allow ourselves to enter fully on the place of Method in Art. It would be no trifling undertaking to attempt an Analysis of the rapid glance of Invention, or the cooler exertion of the critical faculty. The comparative inexactness of Method in this province gives a wider scope for speculation concerning it. The two great divisions of Art, the mechanical and the aesthetical, might put in separate claims for dis- cussion. We should have to assign due place and proportion to the skill which adapts means to ends, the fine taste which discriminates results, the broad general theories of beauty and fitness, which the Artist is supposed, often unconsciously, to obey. We might wander freely on the enchanted ground : but should soon find ourselves far from the do- minion of Logic. Our task, with regard both to Art, and to Morality, which in this point of view is closely connected with it, is of a much simpler nature. We are to avoid entering unnecessarily on their i , » peculiarities, and content ourselves with consider- ing those features in which their procedure is identical with, or stands in intimate relation to, the Logical Method of Science. Art, then, like Science, has to consider the relations of certain Conceptions to an Idea. There can be no true Art when an Idea is altogether absent. There may be much empirical skill, great accuracy in imitation, close observation of detail, but no genius, invention, or originality. Yet, on the other hand, there seems to be truth in the position, that Art does not deal with Ideas. Its work is the production of actual individual Things. It seems to wander beyond its province, and confound itself as the case may be, with Mechanics, or ^Esthetics, or some narrower Science, when it quits individuals, and meddles with prin- ciples at all. These two sides of truth may thus be reconciled. Art has, indeed, to do with individual things. But each of these will fall not under one Idea only, but under several, will bear a definite relation to them, and be capable of receiving illustration from them. In other words, the subject of a single Art lies within the sphere of several Sciences. And it cannot be expedient to neglect the light which methodized knowledge may thus cast upon it. These Sciences can be made practically useful, if knowledge is really power. And how are they to be brouglit to bear ? Not surely in an irregular w fi": 190 ON METHOD IN ART. 0\ MKTIIOI) IN ART. 191 and desultory manner. This would be a con- tradiction of their nature. The several Sciences, which claim so nnich order and arrangement in their respective provinces, cannot be in a state of anarchy among themselves. One Science will be dominant above the rest; and the Idea of that Science will be the Idea of the Art. Must, then, the Idea on which an Art is founded be necessarily a Scientific Idea ? It would seem not. After all the attention that has been devoted to the Philosophy of Fine Arts, a real Science of ^Esthetic has never been attained. We have not been able to state satisfactorily in a deductive form the nature of the Beautiful. But, though the Science has been absent, the Art has gone on. It is sufficient that there is no antecedent impossibility of such an expansion of the/Esthetical Idea. Mean- while, Art has lost little of its dignity and nothing of its vmity ; though it has continued deficient in certainty. Comparatively little fiiith has been shown in general rules, and more reliance neces- sarily placed in the individual sense of the Beauti- ful. Art, then, being like Science, conversant both with Conceptions and Ideas, it is natural to enquire, to what kind of Science it is most closely analogous. In its perfect form it approaches closely to the Apphed Sciences. To the type of Pure Science it cannot at all approximate. Its constant appeal to the outward world and experience, its endeavours to m(*et particular wants and gratify particular senses, separate it clearly from the range of i\ priori truth. The empirical element, though not always equally prominent, must be always present. And if we can trace in Art, as we can in Apphed Science, not only the subordination of the Con- ceptions to the Idea, but the reason of that sub- ordination, our approximation to scientific con- sistency is so much the closer. Yet such syste- matic completeness is quite unnecessary for prac- tical purposes. And it is only when we can brin^- the laws of number to bear on our subject, that it can be really obtained. In other cases, we may well rest content with the same comparatively vague notions of consequence which we have observed to exist in the Classificatory Sciences. It will suffice us to infer from the unity of sequence that it takes place in virtue of a law of causation, without pretending to discover how that law operates. We shall soon have occasion, in treating of Analysis and Synthesis, to mention some points in which Art and Science are differently related to Logic. Meanwhile, tliere seems a necessity for a few remarks on the relation, with regard to Method, of Morality to Science. i II '1/ h UN MKTHOn IN MORALITY. 193 CHAP. XII. ON METHOD IN MORALITY Morality may stand to Method in two different relations, between which it is important for our present purpose to distinguish. In the first place, it may be viewed as a Science — that great Science of Human Conduct in general, which enters into the springs of action, and the intellect and feeHngs so far as they concern action. In this sense, it forms the basis of Politics and Rhetoric, and to some extent even of Poetry and the Fine Arts, as well as of Morality in that second sense, which shall be mentioned presently. But, important though it be, it needs no separate discussion of its Method, being in fact a Classificatory Science; more ele- vated in its character indeed than any other of its Class, and, as it deals with internal rather than external phenomena, proportionably more difficult of attainment ; but still, conforming to the same laws, and arriving at its results by a similar process. Morality, in its second and lower aspect, is subject to the same conditions of Logical Method as Art. It might indeed be defined as the Art of Right Action, did not common usage restrict Art to a narrower range, and assign to it some definite end, short of the perfection of human conduct in general. Assuming then that its Method is broadly the same as that of other Arts, we will mention a few peculiarities, which are intimately connected with its nature. It is, then, closely allied to those Arts, which are grounded on some elevated Idea, not as yet made the subject of a perfect Science. There is no commonly recognised and admitted Science of Goodness ; no system of arranging those phe- nomena of human conduct which we call Good, on which Philosophers in general agree. At such a system we have seen many elaborate attempts, but none successful. Thus the Art of Morality is dignified rather than perfect; and, where it most succeeds in accuracy of detail and practical co- gency, is deficient in theoretic dependence on its first principles. We allow the connection of the phenomena in fact, rather than perceive the reason. In this respect it is closely analogous to the Fine Arts. Nor can we be surprised at any extent to which the parallelism runs, when we remember the close connection between the Ideas of Goodness and Beauty. But this Art, however complete, could scarcely be of great practical utility to those who would become good. Its advantageous exercise implies the full recognition of the Idea of Goodness. And, in such recognition. Moral Excellence is presupposed. Again, we are o 194 ON METHOD IN MORALITY. ON METHOD IN MORALITY 195 incapable of using an Art aright, unless we are familiar, not only with its rules, but with the purposes for which it is employed. But the Art of Morality aims at producing good action ; and good action, pliilosophically viewed, is an internal phenomenon, which can be known only by our.own experience, and not by observation of others. Therefore to apply the Moral Art advantageously, we must be good already. This seems a paradox, but it is not far from the truth. The Art of Morality is practically identical with that of Education. He who is acquainted with it applies it not to his own case, but to that of others. They are, if possible, to benefit by his experience; and attain the same end, but by a shorter and more direct process. There is the more occasion for this remark, because the misapplication of the Art in question involves considerable danger. The object of its rules is to enable those, for whose benefit they are meant, to realise more vividly the Moral Idea in general, and to attain clearer Moral perceptions in detail. But the knowledge of a rule whicli they think they can obey without hesitation and doubt, may lead them to neglect the exercise of those perceptive and reflective powers, by which alone they can really apprehend tiie Moral Conceptions, and combine them under the Idea. In a case of this nature, the endeavour after systematic culti- vation may thwart the very tendencies which it I seemed likely to forward. Thus a loose and imperfect casuistry, or any casuistry out of its place, does harm. In the former case, it degrades the Moral sense which adapts itself to its standard; in the latter case, it hinders its operation by seem- ing to render it unnecessary. We should have little hope of excellence in a painter, who followed some general law of Beauty which he thought he had discovered, in spite of the evidence of his eye given to the contrary side. In like manner we cannot hold him to be really good, who sacrifices to some formula of Right and Wrong which he thinks to contain the truth, the unbiassed verdict of a reflective and uncorrupted Conscience. What, then, are the points of resemblance and difference, with regard to Method, between Art and Morality on the one hand, and Science on the other ? We have, it has been seen, in each an Idea, and Conceptions ranged under it. We have in each as much Subordination and Consequen- tiality as the nature of the subject admits. But in purpose and practical application, as well as in form, there is a strong contrast between them. All Science, as such, aims mainly at the illustration or expansion of its original Idea. In this. De- ductive and Inductive Sciences agree. Thus far, the same impression is made by the successive Deductions which follow in Geometry from the Idea of Space, and the multiplied phenomena n 2 196 ON METHOD IN MORALITY. which we group under the Idea of Lite in Botany or Zoology. The central unity is brought more vividly before the mind by being traced and followed through the plurality of detail. Not so with Art. Its every-day work of pro- duction keeps it from this continual tendency towards an ideal centre. When the Idea can be traced in the lower mechanical arts, it seems often to be merely instrumental, and to discharge the office, so to speak, of an intellectual fulcrum, which may enable us to bring our Conceptions to bear the better upon practice. The Critic may trace the Idea in the Conception ; the Artist is only careful to illustrate the Conception by the Idea. This seems to be true even in the Fine Arts and in Morals. How little need the Artist be conscious of that theory of Beauty, which, were he a philosopher, he would in strict consistency adopt. And how wholly ignorant are many who act in the spirit of the institutions under which they live, or are pledged to the moral precepts of the school in which they are educated, of the really distinctive features of the system, which they every day exhibit with sufficient success in practice ! One other point of difference, and that not un- important, between the Method of Art and Science, remains to be mentioned. It will find its place in the following remarks on the nature and applica- tion of Analysis and Synthesis. spondm- divisions in Method, and show a peculiar fitness to be its organs. Similar coincidences are traceable in other and minor parts of the Lo-ical apparatus. These, however, it is not now neces- sary to mention. They will occur naturally to the Student of Logic, though they could not be exhibited in this work without entering on minute technicalities to a degree quite foreign to its purpose. CONCLUSION. We have now concluded, so far as the phm of these pages allows, our consideration of Logical Method. Had they been far more perfect in their design and more exact in their execution, this would not have hindered that unsatisfied feeling, that craving after further Truth, which strengthens with the accession of Knowledge, and is one of the strongest though not of the most pleasant motives for })ursuing it. It has been well said, that the quest, and not the possession, of Knowledge, is the entertainment of the mind. Truth indeed is the one object of our search; but the pleasures of seeking it are present and real ; the pleasures of finding it lie in the future, and prove too often imaginary. Even when no failure intervenes between us and our end, the road is almost always longer and more difficult than we expected. We think ourselves near the top of the mountain ; and, as we make a vigorous effort to scale what seems its highest crag, perceive that we are but just making our CONCLUSION. 217 way over its first shoulder, and that its misty ridges still rise before us in uncertain grandeur, and retreat as we gaze on them. The reader of these pages cannot be more painfully sensible than their writer, that, after all which has been said of Method, its culminating point is not reached. That highest Unity which would give a meaning to the whole is wanting. Granting that all Knowledge which deserves the name of Science naturally arranges itself, accord- ing to certain rules, under definite Ideas, the question yet remains — how are these Ideas them- selves arranged? Have not they too their due disposition and gradation? Can we suppose that there is no standard by which we can decide their relative dignity and importance ? Centres of unity and sources of order as they are, are they in disorder among themselves ? It is hard to suppose that they are wanting in this arrangement and subordination. And yet how can we discover it ? We have surrendered as a vain imagination that Science of Being, of which the Ancients loved to speak. It seems that power- ful minds were permitted by Providence to rest on the thought of the absolute Unity of Knowledge, till some parts of Science were so elaborated, that they could bear, in contemplating their separate perfection, to dispense with the thorough con- solidation of the whole. We are almost reminded of Alexander's attempt at universal empire, which, Q •218 CONCLUSION. as such, failed ; but left, nevertheless, real and per- manent power in the hands of his Generals, to be exercised over their fragmentary Kingdoms. Many Sciences we know^ there can be: we now know, almost with equal certainty, that, while the human mind retains its present constitution, they can never all meet in one. May there not however be, in the absence of this Ideal Unity, some one Science, to direct the rest, though it does not combine them ? As, in Practice, Prudence, which is not an Art, much less the union of all, applies and regulates all those arts which tend, when rightly used, to our connnon well-being; may there not be in Theory also, some great Science, or something above a Science, to assign our speculations their place, their im- portance, their proportion, their relative bearing; and make them, if not in fact, at least in tendency, a Whole ? One branch of Study there is, which, in virtue of its very name, points to the Highest of all subjects, which yet, in its application, reaches to the most delicate thoughts and finest sympathies of the heart of man; w^hich tells of Infinity and Eternity, and yet exhibits truths of Infinite and Eternal moment under forms which have reference to Space and Time ; which distinguishes betw een the Permanent and the Fleeting, — the Principle, and the Economies or dispensations which are founded on it; which teaches the importance of CONCLUSION. 219 all truths, the supreme necessity of some ; to which a Heathen paid involuntary homage, when he gave its name to what he deemed the highest reach of human thought; and which Christians have delighted to honour with the title of the Mother of Sciences. Much she can teach us directly of the relative importance of truths; nuich more by the temper of mind and frame of thought she inculcates. She rules over Knowledge, if by no other right, by that of conquest: she subdued it first, to protect it ever after. And liow far is this fair Mother of Sciences like her children ? Do the same formal conditions, which bind them, bind her also? If they do not — has she another Method of her own ; her own laws of investigation, and standards of truth and false- dood ? If they do—how does the nature of the high and mysterious subjects with which she deals affect and modify their application ? If, again, she neither conforms to the ordinary rules of specula- tion, nor has extraordiuciry canons of her ow^n, how can the body of truth which she presents be fairly studied at all ? How^ can the human mind, prone, not by its perverseness and obliquity, but by a right instinct and a deep principle of nature, to seek for order and system, find its highest occupa- tion in resting on details which may not be com- bined, statements which may not be compared, examples from which no principles may be extracted. M F 2*20 CONCLUSION. facts which refuse to incorporate themselves with doctrines ? He will do a good service to Truth, and Chris- tianity, and the Church, who shall face these questions fairly; and, in grave earnest, and after all due preparation, venture, in a strength not his own, to treat of a subject which I have not ventured to handle — the application of Method to Theology. THE END. BAXTER, PRINTER, OXIOilD. ^ 11 "^ 'j.°';""B;« uwivEHsiry librar.es "- 0021089108 160 C46 BOUNC JAN •> i957 § mk . :it''' •. ( ■-17 -V' ' ■ ' . J ■ . /-, ■ i , A -^ tim^mumii'.!!'. h mm.. 1 SM'^ \mwirmtmEaiMl mm mmmi... (•I Uli: "itmfs . 1! : ■M'f 'J77J w ^v//;m. i« ' t ^ 1. / . * /-> , . ; . / . < « ' I ' < 1 . ( \w(rMM \m 'm ; t ) \rt\ 1 : ■ -I ■ ' 1 • » , -^ 'I ■4/ ■A it ..;/ ,:)! rT/ IT/