MA S TER NEGA TIVE NO. 93-81223 MICROFILMED 1993 COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY LIBRARIES/NEW YORK as part of the "Foundations of Western Civilization Preservation Project" Funded by the NATIONAL ENDOWMENT FOR THE HUMANITIES Reproductions may not be made without permission from Columbia University Library COPYRIGHT STATEMENT The copyright law of the United States - Title 17, United States Code - concerns the making of photocopies or other reproductions of copyrighted material. Under certain conditions specified In the law, libraries and archives are authorized to furnish a photocopy or other reproduction. One of these specified conditions is that the photocopy or other reproduction is not to be used for any purpose other than private study, scholarship, or research." If a user makes a request for, or later uses, a photocopy or reproduction for purposes in excess of fair use," that user may be liable for copyright infringement. This institution reserves the right to refuse to accept a copy order if, in its judgement, fulfillment of the order would involve violation of the copyright law. AUTHOR: HEBBERD, STEPHEN S. TITLE: THE NEW PHILOSOPHY PLACE: [NEW YORK?] DA TE : [190- COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY LIBRARIES PRESERVATION DEPARTMENT Master Negative # BIBLIOGRAPHIC MICROFORM TARGET Original Material as Filmed - Existing Bibliographic Record r ;108 |Z3 ■ Restrictions on Use: : T^rff^^frnmrnmrn^mmmmmtmimn lIeb]>ord, otcplien Soutiiric, 1841- »M1, xno non pniIono-.},y ^by^ G. G. Hebbord... York? 100- ? J [Hew 1901."'"'"' ^''°'''' ''^"' '""" P^'^^°-'^°P'^y °^ hictory. Volune of pninnhlots I covor tit]o, p. t--'3]-^'00. 22 cm in 25^ om. ' Addod )nlf tiUo mco: Supplenont to The sci- ence of j)hnos;oi.!iY. TECHNICAL MICROFORM DATA FILM SIZE: 3S~y??^ REDUCTION RATIO:__/_/^ IMAGE PLACEMENT: lA QlP IB IIB DATE FILMED: ^h±1_fS.^ INITIALS HLMEDBY: RESEARCH PUBLICATIONS. INC WOODBRIDGE. cf 1% r Association for information and image Management 1100 Wayne Avenue. Suite 1100 Silver Spring. Maryland 20910 301/587-8202 Centimeter 12 3 4 5 nil lllllllllllllUllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllll T Inches TTT ^ 6 7 8 iiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliii I I I 1 i 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 mm iiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiil TTT 1.0 Lm i2-8 |43 ■Uku 1.4 |2.5 2.2 2.0 1.8 1.6 I.I 1.25 TTT m i \' MfiNUFRCTURED TO RUM STfiNDPRDS BY fiPPLIED IMRGE. INC. . I ^ w / THE NEW PHILOSOPHY ^ S. S. HEBBER.D. CHESTERFIELD. ILL. bt SUPPLEMENT I Pliilo^oply THE SCIENCE OF THOUGHT. f> \ Preliminary Observations. Let it be well understood that I do not here pretend to construct a new system of philosophy. Such a construction will demand th^ work of many thinkers laboring throughout the present century of which I shall see at best but the bare beginning. My task must be confined to a rough sketching of the point of departure and the general direction which this philosophic de- velopment must pursue. And at the outstart let me try to disarm one or two prejudices. A distinguished American writer has set it forth, almost as an axiom that It is a mere waste of time to seek for any really new system of metaphysics. That is certainly an amazing proposition. Thorough agnosticism, if not satisfactory, is at least intelligible. Possi- bly human reason will finally determine to aban- don all search for a science of thought as hope- less. But to a believer in evolution it se^ms only foolishness to say that mankind is doomed to forever pursue paths of thought which have _^..'\y\jL,-0 ^T> a Li? 316 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. THE SCIENCE OF THOUGHT. 317 been proved by the experience of three thousand years to lead only to endless and barren dispute. But there is another kind of prejudice which I am far more anxious to disarm. It is that of g-enuine idealists who will probably scorn any criticism of their unscientific methods as an at- tack upon those eternal verities which idealism lias sought to maintain. Those verities are as sacred to me as to them. The idealistic tendency which has been but a mere undertone for the last four hundred years, is to be the dominant note of human development during the present cen- tury and many others to come. That, it seems to me, is fully proved in the Philosophy of His- tory. Criticism here is directed solely agamst the idealistic method in times past— the method of "Maya," of "transcendental illusions" and -phenomenality." This method seems to sup- pose that certainty is a sort of lump the more of >vhich is subtracted from things seen, the more there will be to add to things unseen. But that is a grave mistake. All experience both m the CJrient and the Occident shows that the f^nal out- come of such a process is purely skeptical and pessimistic. And it is my hope to show here that what is really valid and valuable in idealism can be reached in a better way, by a strict inductive method and without affronting the primary con- victions of mankind. It would be very desirable too to disarm the natural prejudice against the seeming "arro- gance" of the claims here made. But that is probably impossible. Really, no one can be less disposed than myself to pretend to any rivalry with the great masters of thought, who saw so much amidst a darkened and generally pre-sci- entific environment. But, nevertheless, the old metaphysics is dead; in the process of human ev- olution the time has come for a new framing of our fundamental conceptions; and somehow it seems to have devolved upon me to begin the ATork. Assumption not the Basis of Thought. It seems best to begin by considering the chief objections which have already been urged against the fundamental principle underlying my Philosophy of History. And first of all it has been objected by an eminent educator and au- thor that this principle amounts only to the fa- miliar truth that we must assume a rational con- nection of things. How easy it is to misunderstand! One main design of my work was to over-turn this whole theory of necessary assumptions lying at the basis of thought. That theory has played a great part — but an evil one, it seems to me — in all modern speculation. It has appeared in differ- ent shapes, in Descartes' doctrine of "innate ideas," in the Scottish dogma of intuitions, in the Kantian system of a priori forms and categories. 318 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. But in every shape the theory fails to accomplish the task for which it was set. It provides no sol- id basis of certainty. On the contrary, it dis- credits rather than guarantees our primary con- victions. To say as Kant does, for instance, that we are mysteriously compelled by some pe- culiarity of our mental make-up, to believe cer- tain propositions, is to instantly excite th« suspi- cion that these beliefs are only subjectively true. They may be valid for us, and still only delu- sive and false. Reason cannot b€ really com- pelled except by a reason. How vainly Kant himself struggled against this ''subjectivity" is well known, nor has any one since his day suc- ceeded better. This curious wobbling of the mind between "the phenomenally true" and "the ontologically true," between believing and disbe- lieving the same proposition at the same time, seems to be the gist of modern philosophy. For more than forty years this shuffling back and forth between two kinds of truth has seemed to me, not only logically but morally indefensi- ble. All that time I have sought to find and elu- cidate some principle that would do away with these necessary assumptions. Surely there must be some better criterion of truth, some sounder basis of certainty than this motley crowd of intuitions, forms and categories for whose va- lidity no other reason can be rendered than that they are compulsory beliefs. All the more when THE SCIENCE OF THOUGHT. 319 it is confessed that they are not after all compul- sory but can be easily set aside by distinguishing between two kinds of truth. And now it is objected that this principle of mine is really nothing more than one of these fa- miliar assumptions. Let us see. That fundamental principle is that all thinking is a relating of cause and effect. In other words, causality is not merely one among the many cat- egories of reason, but is the one implied in all the rest and from which all are derived. It is the es- sence of thought as distinguished from mere feel- ing. In fine every complete affirmation made by the mind is, either explicitly or implicitly, an af- firmation of causality. Of course this principle remains to be estab- lished. It is the object of this supplement to es- tablish it — not deductively, for that would de- mand some wider principle from which it could be deduced, but inductively, by a strict examina- tion of the various processes into which thinking divides itself. But if it can be thus proved, then it seems to me our present object is easily gained. We shall readily find an indisputable criterion of, not merely subjective, but objective truth. The existence of causal relations between all objects of thought will no longer be a mere assumption hanging in the air but a demonstrat- ed truth supported by a very simple and cogent proof. 320 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. THE SCIENCE OF THOUGHT. 321 For if all thinking is a relating of cause and effect then the denial of causality logically in- volves the complete collapse of the whole think- in- process. No matter in what form you put yo'Lr denial, the same result inevitably follows. Do you say that casuality is subjective and not objective? The answer is that both subject and object involve in essence the idea of casuality and become empty words when that idea is cancelled. Or do you say that causal relations do not really exist? But to exist is, as I hope to show, to be in causal relation with somewhat or other, when that relation is cancelled, the word existence has lost its meaning.. In fine, all propositions con- cerning the true or the false would become ab- surd; for, as will be shown when we come to treat' of judgments, the essence of every affirma- tion is to affirm some causal relation between subject and predicate. Thus the whole fabric of thought would collapse, would fall into a tangled, useless mass like a fabric of cloth from which the woof had been withdrawn. Perhaps this proof will be made clearer by noting its parallelism with that mathematical kind of demonstration called a reductio ad ab- surdum. The geometer sometimes proves his theorem by showing that its denial involved the denial of some universally accepted proposition; for instance, that the whole is greater than any of its parts. The demonstration in the present case is even more thorough: for the denial of causality involves the denial not merely of some one particular proposition but of all possible propositions which the mind can frame. It in- volves the extinction of thought. This proof is as yet hypothetical. It depends upon the establishment of my fundamental prin- ciple that all thinking is a relating of cause and effect. But ^ven now it ought to be evident that my doctrine is not that of some "universal and necessary" assumption. It aims to substitute for that assumption a demonstrated theorem. Note still further that in this argument I have simply made explicit what has always been im- plicit in the human mind. The belief in caus- ality has always been something more llian a mere assumption supported by naught but its al- leged irresistibleness. From the beginning the human mind has been vaguely conscious that the denial of causality involved the collapse and ex- tinction of all thinking. But the fact was not proved; and therefore speculation easily wander- ed off into th€ wilderness of Kantian subjectivity, etc. Nor can it be proved, I think, except- through the recognition of our fundamental prin- ciple, to-wit, that all thinking is unitary, all its processes but more or less developed forms of relating cause and effect. The Nature of Causality. A second objection has been urged by others 322 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. and with especial earnestness by a distinguished American writer who has written several very able works from the idealistic point of view. The objection is that I have confounded different kinds of causality. To this I answer that distinctions are worthless when made at random and without regard to the real unity underlying them. And one chief de- fect of modern metaphysics is that it has blindly borrowed its distinctions of casuality from the philosophv of a pre-scientif^c age. Wonderful indeed is the genius evinced in the Greek philos- ophy ; especialy the idealism of men like Pythag- oras' and Plato, belonging to a race saturated with materialism, seems almost a miracle ot insight and beauty. But the defect of our modern speculation is that it has been little more than a revamping of this pre-scientific Greek philosophv— the ghost of it, so to speak. Hence our philosophy has never been able to really adapt itself to the revolution in thought effected by modern science. Especially in the present case, it has never risen above an ancient division of causes about as meritorious as the ancient di- vision of the plant-world into trees, shrubs and herbs. Hence I have sought to subsume these con- fused distinctions under that one uniform type of causality upon which modern science so strenu- cuslv insists. And the terms best fitted to ex- THE SCIENCE OF THOUGHT. 323 press this common character inherent in all caus- al relations seems to be — a relation of depend- ence. How readily the various distinctions be- tween causes can be assigned their true value by referring them to this relation of dependence, may perhaps be best shown by considering some of the aberrations of idealism and materialistic positivism in regard to casuality. (i) Idealism. One of the pregnant errors of idealism has been its failure to note the complex- ity of effects. Let the reader take this for grant- ed, or otherwise seek for the proof thereof given in the Section of this Supplement dealing with Perception. At present I am interested only in the fact that effects arc exceedingly complex, and that therefore we have manv words with va- rious shades of meaning to denote certain differ- ences between the many causes upon which a given effect depends. Thus w^e speak of one cause as the occasion, as the cause most closely connected in time with the effect. Others w^e en- title conditions, as being more remote although often more significant. And one of these condi- tions which happens to be the most conspicuous, we are apt to designate as the cause. But the effect is dependent upon th-em all, whether called occasion, condition or cause. The shades of dis- tinction denoted by the different terms refer merely to differences in the combination of causes; they do not essentially effect that com- L ! I 11 324 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY, show herealK . tne overlooking and sufficient cause. P..-..,-..-. But .e are also con ron^.d by the positivist who affirms ^^^^^"^s nendence are mere chimeras, that science ^ 1 thL except the uniform succession of Z'^ nothing excq, .^ .^ ^^^^^.^,,^ ^^ phenomena /"^ *°^"^^^^ ^^ ^ave thoroughly roSertlHatrof those phenomena con _ing which th.^ <1^--^^^^ have not seen that every y ., , „, mialitv •;„ n„ effect ■ it is some attribute or quality maintained it can never positiv- dchcvdcnt upon that thing, bo that me r fst cal not Uke the first step in his scientific ob- ^T^t'Ses^h: Stivist insist t- ahlK^gh a .elation of dependence j" some se^e nu^ t per^ Vians be admitted at the start, \ei <* See ,„ ,o <,o ";'>vrr;,s""d:'»ct THE SCIENCE OF THOUGHT. 325 science has consisted in showing Httle by little that every phenomenon is dependent not solely upon the thing from which it has been abstracted but also upon a vast variety of other things. Science is insight into this immense complex of relations of dependence. The charge of ambiguity then, in my con- ception cf causality has been more than dis- proved. Not only has it been shown that there is no such incompatibility between the alleged different kinds of causation, as would make it impossible to comprehend them in one genus. More than that, it has been shown that only through this generic or unitary view can we at- tain to any clear insight into the nature and va- lidity of these distinctions. The real confusion and equivocalness have been on the part of the old philosophy, which leaving these causal distinctions wholly vague and indefinite, has simply flung them all together in a witches' caldron of dispute and paradox. Immanent and Dynamic Casiiality. This es- say is but a tentative — a mere introduction to the Science of Thought; and therefore I shall at- tempt here to interpret only one of these distinc- tions. But it is the most conspicuous and vital one, and the one that will be most glibly urged against my theory of judgment and reasoning. It is the distinction between formal or immanent and efficient or dynamic causality. S26 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY In the Cartesian philosophy, especially as fin- ally developed by the marvelous Spinoza, all the emphasis was laid upon causality as immanent. The type of the causal relations was the relation between a substance and its attributes, qualities, etc That was a distinct advance, so far as it negated the pre-scientific Aristotlean view of qualities as themselves occult causes stowed away in things. But after Newton's great discovery, we see the emphasis shifting to the idea of causality as force. The first stir of the transition is shown in Leib- niz^s Monadology. As it became more and more evident that the gist of science was insight into the motions of things the greater the stress upon this new dynamic view of causality. The type of the causal relation was no more the rela- tion of substance and attribute as with Spinoza, but the relation of force to motion— force not immanent or fixed in things, but transitive or rather transilient, leaping from object to object and thus producing these motions. And as the older view of causality culminated into Spino- za's materialistic pantheism, so the newer view culminated in the ideal or what would more properly be called the abstract pantheism of the Post-Kantian philosophy. The dispute between these two modes of con- ceiving has done much towards bringing the question of causality into its present chaotic THE SCIENCE OF THOUGHT. 327 state. Every tyro in philosophy knows what in- finite confusion prevails. There are no definite and fixed distinctions ; all is fluid, vague and vacuous. And yet from our pre'sent point of view it seems easy to so interpret these two ap- parently conflicting types of causality as to give to each an exactly definite value and at the same time show their generic unity. Here, then, on the one side we have a relation of dependence between qualities and things; on the other side a relation of dependence between motions and things. The average professor of philosophy would remonstrate, off-hand, against confounding two such palpably diverse relations, the one merely ''formal," the other ''efficient" and "dynamic." But we remind him of the Con- servation of Energy — of the scienticfic discovery that all qualities are ultimately reducible to and identical with motions. And then we ask: If attributes and motions are thus identical, how can their relations to things be so essentially dif- ferent? It is demonstrable then that there can be no eLential difference in the two cases, although apparently so diverse. But what, then, makes them appear so diverse? I answer: because we are regarding the same relation from two dif- ferent points of view. In the first case— that of substance and accident— we are regarding the quality mainly as dependent upon the thing from Ii' 328 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. Avhich it has been abstracted, although perfectly aware that is also dependent upon other things. In the second case, we are regarding the motion mainlv as dependent upon the other things, al- though perfectly aware that it is dependent also upon the thing it is abstracted from. We have shown, then, both that the relation is identical and whv it seems so diverse. The proof may be made clearer hereafter. But just as it stands, I think it will be clear and conclusive enough, except to those with whom imagination is so strong and reason so weak that they can think of force only as some sort of muscular pull- ing cr pushing. Reason and Cause. Let me also mention briefly the most pregnant of all such distinc- tions,' that between cause and reason. Nowhere have I been able to find a clear-cut and valid ac- count of the difference between these most sig- nificant terms; on the contrary, the utmost con- fusion and the wildest vagaries seem here to prevail For example, an eminent and very thoughtful representative of the newest monism • defines cause as meaning merely motion, and reason as signifying ^the forces of nature, such as gravity, elasticity, etc. The upshot of tha would seem to be to make reasons the only real causes and to convert causes into mere effects, i. r., motions. Many other examples of equally beclouded .views might be given. THE SCIENCE OF THOUGHT. 329 But one main design of this treatise is to draw a precise and unimpeachable distinction be- tween cause and reason. A deep and exact dif- ference, even opposition, between them — undis- closed in any previous system of speculation — will be demonstrated. And yet even here a uni- tary bond will be found. The Fundamental Law of Knozvledge. That law is simply this: Causes can be known only through their effects, and conversely, ef- fects can be known only through their causes. In other words we know the objects of thought only in their causal relations to each other. This law is an evident corollary from our funda- mental principle that all thinking is a relating of cause and effect. Let it be carefully noted at the outset that this law prescribes solely the method and not the limits of knowledge. Otherwise, the critic may see in it only a reduplicated form of the now prevailing agnosticism: thinking, it may be urged, is thus made to consist in the combining of two unknown quantities. On the contrary, our doctrine clearly understood puts an impass- able barrier before the advance of nescience. For, it shows that all the easy inferences now current concerning ''Relativity" and the ''Un- knowable" are based upon an entire misappre- hension of what knowledge really is. Let us consider this. X 330 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. The Fallacy of Resemblance. Thinking, as I hope to show, is under the law of evolution; it rises from the simplest causal judgments, little by little, by processes of composition and de- composition, to more complex and comprehen- sive judgments. But error also is under the law of evolution ; all its fallacies are but more or less developed forms of the Fallacy of Resemblance. Furthermore, the average intellect naturally inclines to judgments based upon mere resem- blance rather than to causal ones. For, they are easier to construct. Man, like any other ani- mal, is governed largely by the Law of Associa- tion—not, as many philosophers imagine, the association of thoughts but of feelings. Auto- matically, without any effort on our part, pres- ent sensations or feelings cohere with images of the past according to those rules of similarity which the Association philosophers have so la- boriously expounded. This process of linking like to like goes on spontaneously; and thus a life of sentiency and suggestion is formed for us which does not differ essentially from the same life in horses or dogs. Attempts at thinking are so suppressed by association of similarities that our judgments, classifications and reasonings are very largely founded upon mere resem- blances. The first and often the last interroga- tory we propound concerning any object is: What does it look like? THE SCIENCE OF THOUGHT. 331 The fallacy of all such judgments based solely upon resemblance is evident. They have in- herent in themselves their own contradiction. For two objects are never so much alike as not to be unlike in some respects. So that we can say: "This is Hke that," and: "This is )iot like that," with equal truthfulness. Judgment and reasoning from resemblance then, show themselves upon bare inspection as tending to fallacy. And yet they have always formed the main staple of metaphysicsal dispu- tation. In dealing with th'e unseen, elusive phe- nomena of thought the temptation is almost ir- resistible to picture them, to clothe them in the shape and semblance of things, to appeal to the imagination and misleading analogies. Hence the midnight that has enveloped the leading problems of the mental life. Our essay will show how the great questions of Space, Time. Perception, Inductions, Self-Consciousness, and Causality itself have been converted into insolu- ble enigmas by this pictorial philosophy. It will show also that the only w^ay out of this wilder- ness of "Relativity'' and "The Unknowable" is through the recognition that all genuine knowl- edge of any object is a knowledge, not of its re- semblances, but of its causal relations. I 1 'Mi JUDGMENTS. 333 II. JUDGMENTS. To Judge is to Abstract. Prior to judgments there must be presentations of sense common to men and other animals, often given perhaps more distinctly and exactly to the mere animal than to the man. But the presentation is only feeling, not thought. It is possible, even com- mon for us to gaze, to smell, to hear, to touch etc., and for the appropriate re-action to be giv- en, to these stimuli, without any act of thought whatsoever. But the process of thinking or judging begins only with a conscious act of an- alysis whereby we abstract from the object pre- sented, one or more of its attributes. No mat- ter now what that presented object may be. Perchance it is but ":Maya," or a transcendental illusion; that question does not concern us here. Nor let any one cavil that we are here estab- lishing an arbitrary distinction betweeen feeling and thought. That objection comes with an ill- grace from any adherent of the old philosophies which have always hopelessly confounded feel- ing and thought, without a serious attempt to make any more than a purely verbal distinction between them. But here we have a distinction perfectly clear, simple and precise. Further- more, there are implicit in it the two other fun- damental differences between thought and feel- ing: First, feeling is passive, while thought is active. The sensation of the color or the odor of an object is presented to an animal, even to a caterpillar perhaps as vividly as to us and it is instinctively attracted or repelled thereby. But thought is essentially active; it analyzes the ob- ject presented into two factors and observes the relations between them. Secondly, feeling is stationary; there is no possibility of developing what is purely passive and automatic. But thought is progressive ; and it progresses for the very reason that it is abstractive. For, as I hope to show, this simple act of abstraction is the nu- cleus of all possible forms of mental develop- ment — the tie of consanguinity, so to speak, con- necting the first perceptive judgments of the child with the most profound and universal judgments of science. Other items of difference between thought and feeling might be men- tioned to the same effect. But these are enough I think, to show that we have here a clear-cut distinction furnishing a solid basis for a true science of thought. Note now that we have in this primitive act of abstraction the perfect type of what we have de- clared at the outset to be the essence of all 334 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. thinking— to-wit, the establishment of causal re- lations. For, firstly, that which is abstracted upon must alwavs remain absolutely dependent upon the object 'from which it has been abstracted. So patent is this that in all ages logic has issued an emphatic warning against the too common error of disregarding this dependence; of con- ceiving the abstracted element as having an m- dependent, substantial existence apart from the object from which it has been abstracted. Sec- ondly, even those philosophers who seem able to tliink onlv in figures of speech and are there- fore most strenuous concerning the "ei^^ciency or "dynamism" of true, "ontological" causahty must 'see that the object is certainly one of the causes upon which its attributes or properties depend. If not let them read again what was said a few pages back concerning immanent causality. Thirdly, in this primary act of abstraction the demands' of our Law of Knowledge are com- pletely fulfilled: the causes cannot be known or even 'thought unrelated to its effects and con- versely the effect apart from its cause. Mani- festly the object is known only through the at- tributes abstracted from and dependent upon it And conversely no one of these dependent attri- butes can be known or thought apart from the object; to try to think it thus apart— as inde- pendent and isolated— is confessedly one of the JUDGMENTS. 335 most childish of logical errors. Each of the two factors, the object or that which is abstracted, is by itself but a semi-thought, fragmentary, sense- less. Only when they are causally connected does a real and distinct meaning emerge. Note now that the old philosophy has missed this insight through its passion for the fallacy of resemblance. It has seen the abstracted, the at- tribute only as something like a thing "inher- ent" in the object, sticking in it apparently like a pin in a pin-cushion. From that theory of "in- herence" it is but a step to self-contradiction and ultimate skepticism. But from all this we are saved by simply thinking in terms of cause and effect. (2.) To Judge is to Experiment. Philosophy heretofore has taken a very narrow and mislead- ing view of experimentation as a rare and ex- tremely artificial process, for the most part car- ried on only in the laboratories of the learned On the contrary we are always experimenting whenever we are really thinking. For this work Nature has furnished the laboratory in our physical organism. She has provided in the or- gans of sense a wonderfully delicate and com- plex apparatus designed to present before us a particular phenomenon isolated from modifying causes. In vision, for instance, we see only the object; thus one cause of the vision is presented before us, isolated from the other agencies at ''II 336 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. il w \ JUDGMENTS. 337 work, the aether waves, the nerve motions, cere- bral changes, etc. If all these were perceived with the object, infinite confusion would result and knowledge be rendered impossible. Furthermore, the variety of the organs enable us to vary the experiment. Through the sense of touch, for instance, we can experiment to see how the object behaves under one set of condi- tions; through sight, under another set of con- ditions; and similarly through smell, hearing etc. Thus through a continuous process of ex- perimentation we obtain those simple percep- tive judgments with which the evolution of . thought and knowledge begins. Note further that the results thus attained are true inductions. For instance, an object is pre- sented to sight and a particular color appears; the object is removed, the color vanishes. Or the object is touched with the finger, a feeling of resistance is felt; the object is touched no long- er, the feeling disappears. In both cases we have used the '^:Method of Difference," which is universally regarded as the gist of the inductive process. But as conmion speech has confined the term induction to the forming of universal propositions, it is perhaps better to speak of these primary acts of abstraction simply as ex- perimental. (3). To judge is to afiirm existence. In this I agree with some recent logicians who lay much stress upon the "existential" aspect of judgments. But I wholly reject their interpre- tation and proof of this aspect. Here Mr. Brad- ley's strange juggling with such uncouth dis- tinctions as "Thisness" and "This," may be passed over in silence. But a word must be said concerning a more seductive theory which regards the affirmation of existence as a sort of by-product of feeling — "the reality-feeling," "the feeling envelope of the presentation," etc. (i) That is not merely vague and inconclusive; it is a sheer plunge into the pit of mysticism. A. feeling, so far from proving anything, does not even assert anything. It merely feels and re- sponds automatically to the stimulus. A "feel- ing envelope" will no more justify our belief in reality than it will our belief in the equation of the cycloid. To overlook this, to subvert the distinction between feeling and thought, is to open the door to all fanaticism and vagaries. There is a safer and solider ground than that for our belief in reality. The simplest, most primary judgment, as we have seen, affirms a causal relation; and in affirming that it affirms existence. For, whatever is a cause developing an effect, must exist in some shape or other. The nature of this existence is of course a mat- ter to be determined hereafter. (J Baldwin. Fragments of Philosophy, 1902. P. 240. seq. 1/7 .38 THE PHILOSaPHY OF HISTORY. Furthermore, these same logicians have much ^ T- !lh a symbol of causal connexion. copula IS simpU a sjmuui To affirm that "This is, i. e., exists, is then to ate. Has not the difficulty vanished m a mo ment? Qualitative Judgments. Hitherto we have been regarding only the « tv,u evclusive reference of the But we soon see this exciusiv The subject is not the sole cause, but a cause. Qualitative judgments o-f /^^", ^^7;,^;,^ .Ui4. to this advancing know e^ge of ^ ^cau._^ relation connecting the preaicate JUDGMENTS. 339 causes, besides the subject. When we affirm, for instance, that "this is red," we do not think of the predicate as solely an effect of the subject, but as something adjectival, added to and quali- fying the subject. In fine, there is an implicit reference to the wider field of causality. This, I think, is the chief peculiarity in judgments of quality; in other respects they have the same three-fold character as the perceptive judgments already described. Contrast now this theory of judgment with that of the old philosophies which have never been able to see in a quality anything much but its resemblance to other qualities bearing the same name. Firstly, the latter theory shows it- self upon its very face to be vague and self-con- tradictory. Qualities although designated by a common name are rarely precisely alike in dif- ferent things; in the same breath we may say with equal truthfulness that they are alike and they are }iot alike. Secondly, no relation be- tween the predicate and the subject is exhibited except the absurd and impossible one of ''inher- ence." Thirdly and most important of all. Ab- straction—the vital breath of all genuine think- ing — loses its significance and is even put under suspicion as a breeder of vain subtleties. Hegel even wished to create a New Logic wherein **the barren abstract'' should be replaced by ''the concrete," by "the organic"— in fine, by a meta- phor. 340 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. Quantitative Judgments. (i). Quantitative judgments are affirmations concerning abstractions. Therein lies their es- sential difference from the judgments previously considered. In the latter, only the predicate is an abstraction and is directly referred to the subject from which it has been abstracted and upon which it depends. In the qualitative judg- ment, as we have seen, there is indeed an im- plicit reference also to other causes besides the subject which is partially disclosed in the very form of this predicate as an adjective and not a verb; but the paramount reference is to the sub- ject. ' But in the quantitative judgment all this is changed. Therein we reach a more highly developed form of the judgmm possible. Countless examples m.ght be jven to the same eflect. In all cases -'"^-"f ^^j. stractions are, in the largest sense and ult. mately, abstracted from Time; and spat.al ab- Stractions from Space. (3). This insight explains the well-kno^^•n fact that the goal of science is H. transfonmmnof qualitative into quantitative H^^"'^- . J^^^ qualities are abstracted entirely from thmgs and therefore thev partake, to some extent at Last of that infinite variability which attaches to things. There is no quality which does not hold wfthin itself some shade of difference from a fmilar quality in another thing. But quarj. tative abstractions, as we have seen, are ultt mately abstracted from space or time, both of which have absolute uniformity, "-hangeable- ness and continuity. And because quantitative affirmations partake of this invariableness and JUDGMENTS. 343 exactitude, it becomes possible for science to attain through them to universal judgments which are mathematically demonstrable. Take notice likewise of the concomitant truth which has also just been shown. These quanti- tative abstractions are, in a secondary sense, ab- stracted from and dependent upon concrete ob- jects. By remembering this science has been kept from losing itself in the wilderness of mere- ly abstract speculation. It has always insisted upon verifying its splendid abstractions by showing their exact correspondence with the actual state of things in the world of sense. Thus our theory of quantity seems already to foreshadow and to explain that double crown of science — its two-fold capacity for inconceivably abstract speculation and for strictly verifying its conclusions. It may not be amiss to add that our theory of quantity is fortunate in being apparently with- out a rival. The older logicians seem to have early given up the attempt to propound such a theory as hopeless; and Hegel finds it easy enough to show in his Logic that tbeir defini- tions of quantity were but the baldest tautolo- gies. True, Hegel has propounded a theory of his own in which he describes quantity as an early and crude phase of "self-negating negativ- ity." But that fails to comply with a very mod- est demand which we have the right to make / i -.344 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. of every theory : if it does not make clear what was dark, at least it ought not to darken what was clear. Universal Judgments, As yet we have treated only of particular judgments, but we come now to a still more dif- ficult problem. How shall we explain and guar- antee the validity of those universal judgments which form the substance of science, and yet seem to lie beyond the bounds of all possible ex- perience? That problem, despite many earnest endeavors, has never been satisfactorily solved. It is the great scandal of modern logic that while every one is talking about the scientific method, no one seems able to give a precise answer to the question: What is the scientific method? To prove this and at the same time to eluci- date my own theory, let us consider the now most generally accepted exposition of the induc- tive process. It is Mill's theory of the Five Methods. Upon its very face this multipHcity of methods suggests a suspicion of empirical and unscientific explanation. But letting that go, let us examine the first two of these meth- ods, they being confessedly the fundamental ones. The Method of Agreement. This is but the Tulgar method per enumerationem simplieem JUDGMENTS. 345 with a very important proviso annexed. The proviso is that the enumerated instances should "have only one circumstance in common," But that stultifies the whole exposition; for, it is manifestly impossible when we observe many in- stances of an effect or rather of similar effects, to know that their antecedents agree in only one particular. Mill's restriction upon the vulgar method, guards against its abuses by making the method impossible. Does some one urge that only material cir- cumstances ought to be considered, those hav- ing some appreciably adequate power to pro- duce the effect? But that would over-turn the entire method, and substitute for it something quite different and even contrary. The inquiry would hinge, not upon the number of instances, but upon the adequacy of the cause to produce the effect. Note, however, that our quarrel is not with' the method of agreement in itself. Used wisely, under the qualification just given, it leads in many cases to a sufficient degree of certainty. Our only objection is to the attempt to convert it — by foisting upon it an impossible condition — into one of the methods of scientific induc- tion, which it is not. Th^: Method of Diiference. Here we find the same impossible condition annexed as in the previous canon: there must be a "circumstance I li '■ 346 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. in which alone the two instances differ." Let us consider the only example given by Mill in his exposition of the method: A man shot through the heart, dies instantly. Undoubtedly there is in this proof enough that in this partic- ular case the death was caused by the wound. But what warrants us, in converting that partic- ular judgment into a universal one? What en- ables us to infer that death is the invariable con- sequent of gun-shot wounds in the heart? Be- cause, Mill asserts, all other circumstances were the same except the wound; "the man was m the fullness of life immediately before." But that we can never know except as more or less prob- able. Men apparently in the fullness of life, of- ten drop dead without any perceptible cause. Even then in this extreme case, we must search for some other warrant for a universal judgment than that afforded by Mill's method. • The true warrant evidently is in our previous knowledge that such a wound is adequate in all cases to produce death. The injury inflicted up- on the most delicate part of the frail boddy mechanism is so great that nothing could coun- teract the result. But if the wound had been on the finger, would we have framed a universal judgment therefrom? Would we not have said rather that death had been caused by fright^ heart-failure or some other unknown cause? And so in all cases, I think, the real warrant JUDGMENTS. 347 for the induction is in a previous knowledge for which Mill's canon makes no provision. We dismiss then these famous Methods as merely annexing an impossible condition to the old empirical methods. And so we still have be- fore us the problem of determining the essential distinction between scientific and merely empir- ical induction. In the Philosophy of History the secret of the scientific method was stated as being a process of abstracting and accounting for the modifying causes. Some fifty or sixty pages were devoted to setting forth the historical evidence that all the physical sciences have had their origin in a developing comprehension of the complexity of effects — in a continuous discovery of modifying causes before unknown or disregarded. But we have now reached a point of view where it is pos- sible to go still deeper and make an important addition to that statement. We can show pre- cisely what it is that makes possible this scientific analysis of the complexity of effects. This in- most secret of the inductive method is its quanti- tative conception of force. The Conception of Force. The term force, as commonly understood, is as vague as it is famil- iar. It is used as a loose synonym for power, efficiency or causality of any kind. But since the discovery of the first two laws of motion, a new scientific conception of force has gradually 1 I- ! ' It 34S THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. developed which is as definite and exact as any other mathematical term. These discoveries made it possible to establish units of motion in- variable in velocity and direction, and to analyzo all actual motions, inconceivably complex and changeful as they are, into mathematical sums of such units, and the unit of force thus became whatsoever cause was adequate to the production of such a unit of motion. Thus the quantitative conception of force arose— a symbol for caus- ality conceived as absolutely invariable and ana- lysable into a sum of exactly equivalent units. ' Note, now, first, that only through such a quantitative conception does the analysis of Na- ture's complex and ever changing effects be- come possible. The simplest calculations in arithmetic would be impossible, if the units used were variable. How much more impossible un- der the same supposition would the Infinitesimal Calculus become by which the astronomer anal- yzes the earth^s motions, calculates the several 'influences of all the perceptible causes and sums them all up in a result minutely accordant with observation ! Secondly, this conception of force makes it possible to demonstrate the uniformity of causa- tion. To see this it is only necessary to rightly distinguish between effect and cause. The ob- served effects are infinitely changeful; but in all these changes each still remains the product of JUDGMENTS. 349 some definite sum of unvarying, equivalent units of force. The Law of Physical Causation. See now how fully our fundamental Law of Knowledge is here vindicated. First, the cause is known only through its effects. Consider that widest of all scientific inductions — the doctrine of the conser- vation of energy. But what is energy more than an abstract expression for causality conceived as acting with absolute invariability or mathemati- cal uniformity? Beyond that there is no knowl- edge of energy except through its results, to-wit, the motions it produces. True, many physicists like to think of energy or forces as immanent in things; nor is there any objection to that consid- ered as a mere mode of conceiving — an expedi- ent for calculating directions, etc., and an aid to the imagination. But there the true scientific spirit stops. To insist that we have any real knowledge of forces as little entities hidden in things and passing out of them — that is to be victimized by the fallacy of resemblance. Secondly the effects are known only through their causes. The simplest motion conceivable is still a complex effect, dependent upon a mov- ing thing, force, time and space; and how can we know or even think of it independently of these, its causal factors? Or take some more complicated case, the infinitesimal variations of acclerating motion, for instance; these defv even 350 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. JUDGMENTS. 351 imagination ; the fact of their existence even was first discovered only by abstract reasoning from the thought of continuous forces. Or take the still more wonderful changes of motion into heat, color, etc. To humor the imagination we speak of these as transformations; and yet it is more than inconceivable, it is self-contradictory, to speak of the formless as changing its form. We know only that these abstractions are in certain definite causal relations with motions. So alwavs and everywhere, the only knowledge of motion is a knowledge of that upon which motion depends. Deduction. Little need be added here to what was said in the main treatise. The function of the syllogism is simply to unite and apply to par- ticular cases the truths obtained by induction. Its art consists in remembering and using knowledge already gained, and its rigidly me- chanical operations are very much like those whereby in animal sentiency a present sensation is fused with past images. In fine, the exagger- ated importance generally attached to the syllo- gism is a striking proof of how entirely our modern philosophy has been but a revamping of the pre-scientific philosophy of Greece. Note, however, that all long chains of reason- ing naturally assume the syllogistic form; for, the syllogism is the instrum-ent for combining and applying inferences. The inferences thus united, however, are essentially inductive. In geometry, for instance, the main thing is to see at each minute step of th^ reasoning that what is true in the particular case presented in the dia- gram, is universally true; and that is induction. SPACE. 353 III. SPACE. Confessedly, one of the most perplexing of all philosophic problems is that of space. To this problem I wish now to apply my fundamental law of thought, that all thinking is a relating of cause and effect, and that neither of these can be known except in relation with the other. On the one side we have some apprehension of in- finite space; on the other, of the spatial proper- ties of things, sucll as forms, distances, direc- tions, etc. My thesis is that these two factors, space and the spatial attributes of things are re- laated to each other as causae and effect. Space by itself is but a vague, elusive semi-thought which can be truly known or even thought of only through reference to the spatial attributes. And conversely, the attributes can be known or even thought only by relating them to that infin- ite space upon which they depend. And, I fur- ther hope to show that the obscurities and para- doxes enveloping the spatial problem have come from ignoring this fundamental law of thought. Tlie Kantian Theory of Space. Let us consider first the arguments by which this famous theory IS supported by its author. (i). Space, Kant first maintains is not derived by abstraction from particular external experi- ences; on the contrary the perception of objects presupposes the idea of space '*as an intuition a priori, before all experience." The argument here is based upon a narrow and erroneous view of abstraction. We have now discovered and proved that in every abstracting act, the attri- bute abstracted is shown as dependent not only upon the thing or substance, but also upon other causes. In the case of spatial attributes this secondary ground of dependence is space. But how, it may be asked, do we get the idea of space? I answer that we do not get it apart as a distinct, isolated idea, any more than we get the isolated idea of the object or of the attribute. Taken thus apart each is but the fragmentary suggestion of an idea. What is a thing without a form? Or a form without a thing? Or space without spatial properties? But each becomes intelligible- when united with the other in causal relation. Without this insight, Kant finds it impossible to conceive of space except as a wholly magical creation of the perceiving intelleqt. (2). Kant's second argument is that the no- tion of space is a necessary a priori idea, a pre- '/< m I) ti! :354 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. condition of the possibility of all phenomena. As others have noted, this is nothing mre than a new assertin of the thesis which the Critique purports to prove. But it gives me the opportu- nity for showing the exact point of failure in the Kantian solution of the problem — not only of space but of all thought. That point of failure is that Kant made knowledge to begin with a blind, unconscious act. His necessary a priori ideas are mere as- sumptions necessitated by *'our mental make- irp" — compulsory, irresistible beliefs — aflFirma- tions which the mind is somehow mysteriously compelled to make without knowing any more why it makes them than a stone knows why it falls. And knowledge thus starting as a blind, mechanically determined activity, never after- ward gains any other character. In the end, it confesses itself not to be genuine knowledge, but nescience, mere "phenomenality." We read again and again that Kant showed how knowl- edge was possible; he showed rather how knowledge was impossible. And vet Kant was verv near the solution of the great problem. In reducing to a system the mongrel crowd of innate id-eas, necessary truths, intuitions, etc., imagined by dermatic idealism, and in genetically tracing them back to some primary connection with the ideas of space and .time, he was presenting the problem in so mas- SPACE. 355 terly a shape as to make its solution seem not very far away. And it was, I think, this sense of a great problem almost solved, this expectancy of a light about to break forth, which gave to the Critique such a wonderfully fascinating pow- er over human thought. Everybody, at least in German V, thought himself competent to com- plete the master's work. But his ''successors" failed— almost comically. And they failed, I think, because they did not have that full, deaf view of the significance of the problem which Kant had. For the present I content myself with statmg anew this problem. It is to discover some other origin and basis of knowledge than mere as- sumptions which all men, blindly, without knowl- ing why, are compelled to believe just as all stones are compelled to fall. But the Kantian philosophy merely gives us a reason for not be- lieving what— as it asserts in the same breath— we are blindly compelled to believe. (3). The third argument rests upon the supposition that space is a whole divisible into manv parts. But upon this argument we shall not dwell, because we are to consider it later in its more modern form as the theory of space conceived as a sum of relations. Suffice it now that the great German here falls a victim to the fallacy of resemblance. He can conceive of space only under ijie similitude of a divisible Ill 356 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. thing. But the very essence of space is to be in- divisible, inseparable. Parts of space are pure fig- ures of speech; and the only rational way in which we can think of any spatial property of things is simply as dependent upon space. (4). Again space is infinite. But to know it as thus actually existent, one would have to count up, in Kant's opinion, the infinite number of its parts. But that would be plainly impossi ble in an ordinary life-time ; therefore our knowl- edge of infinite space must be derived from some a priori, congenital "form of our sensibility." But there would be no need of so much count- ing in order to discover that space is infinite, if one would discard the fallacy of resemblance and think only in terms of cause and effect. Then he would see instantly that all limitation of the extended depends upon and is made pos- sible only by space. Whatsoever is thus limited, must have space beyond it. Therefore, if space is limited or finite it must have space beyond it ; which is a contradiction in terpis. (5). The Possibility of Mathematics. The four arguments just given form the corner-stone of Kant's system; and yet he has presented them almost as cursorily as I have. But there is an- other argument upon which his heart was plainly set; especially in the Prolegomena he expa- tiates upon it at great length and lovingly. The argument is that only upon his hypothesis can SPACE. 357 philosophic certainty be assured to mathematics. And if there is no other way, it would perhaps be well to give up the spatial world as a tran- cendental illusion in order to save mathematics and a part of morals. But there is another way. It consists in re- signing all hope of reaching real knowledge ex- cept by thinking in terms of cause and effect. Confining ourselves to the question of space, let us remember that the geometer demands only to be assured of the exact uniformity or unchange- ableness of space. What is geometrically proved true here must be true — not, as Mill thinks, in a "a reasonable degree of adjacent cases" — but true everywhere even to infinitude. Nowhere must there be the most infinitesimal lapse in the immovability of space. How, then, is this assurance of spatial con- tinuity gained? I answer that it is implicit in all perceptions of moving things. Motion is a complex effect, dependent upon and inseparable from some moving thing, but also dependent upon the absolute fixedness of points in space. If there were no such unalterableness of the spa- tial points, motion would lack all determination of direction or velocity and therefore could nev- er be known. The fact just stated may be illustrated by means of a queer conclusion reached by Mr. Spencer, the great nineteenth century phophet of 'The 358 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. Unknowable." He instances at great length the case of a man walking on a ship which is sailing in the opposite direction upon a sea which as part of the earth is being carried in still another direction, with several other complications. And he concludes therefrom that **our ideas of mo- tion are illusive:" that even motion is unknow- able. One might as well affirm that algebra was an unknowable, self-contradictory science be- cause it insisted upon adding together plus and minus quantities. For the case given is merely that of a sum of motions which partially cancel each other. And the ultimate motion obtained by adding these plus and minus quantities would plainly be altogether unknowable and also im- possible, if there were no fixed points in space, (i) J There is then no need of affirming the subjec- tivitv of space in order to make mathematics possible. Thus the only argument upon which Kant seems really to have relied is obliterated. It may likewise be added that there is no need of any other a priori machinery of innate ideas or intuitions to assure us that continuous, im- movable space exists. That assurance is given by the logical process of abstraction— that es- sence of all reasoning— which proves to us that SPACE. 351». (1) Spencer. First Pi^nciples. every perceptible motion is an abstract from and dependent upon space. There is, then, no good reason for accepting the Kantian supposition. But, it may still be urged, is there not at least a bare possibility of its being true? If not probable, is it not at least possible that space is but a product of our sub- jectivity? I answer: No! But the full demon- stration thereof must be reserved to the next sec- tion, where we treat of perception. For the present let the following suffice. Kant undeniably made a great advance upon the skepticism of Hume, when he showed that all the objects of thought or the understanding — Space, Time, the World, Substance, Cause, etc., — were so closely interrelated that to deny one was to deny all. But he did not take the final step. He did not see that thought itself was so peculiarly interrelated with the objects of thought that to cancel them was to render all thinking impossible. This insight would have saved him from that pit of "subjectivity" from which he was always evidently striving to escape, but in vain. The Argument from Interaction.. But in addi- tion to these Kantian arguments there are two others of a more showy, superficial kind, and therefore more current in recent philosophy. Both of them, as I hope to show, are products L*ll'il 360 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. of the fallacy of resemblance — that deep-rooted tendency of the human animal to think only in figures of speech. One of these arguments springs from the attempt to picture space in the likeness of things considered as interacting; the other, in the likeness of a thing as made up of a whole and its parts. Let us first examine the argument from interaction. Let me present this argument in the words of an American idealist noted for keenness and vigor of thought: ''Unless we endow space with activity and regard it as a peculiar something in interaction with other things the affirmation of its existence becomes absurd; and its existence would in no way be distinguishable from its non-existence." (i). Such is the argument from interaction. How childish it seems! For, first, what is interaction but the production of motion.. But motion has no meaning except as change of position in space. And so the argument reduces itself to this: Space does not exist because it does not change position in space. Secondly. We are told that because space does not interact, its existence would be indis- tinguishable from its non-existence ; space there- fore is merely phenomenal. But in another place, the author argues that things likewise cannot in- SPACE. 961 (1) Bowne. Metaphysia 129. teract, and therefore they are merely phenom- enal. This is the chief weapon of "critical" ideal- ism — a preposterous hatchet with which it splits sensible reality into impossible parts and then easily shows that each of the dissevered parts is a ghostly illusion. It is of course impossible that either space or spatial properties or things should be perceptible apart from each other. Thirdly. This argument from interaction shows upon its very face its descent from the fal- lacy of resemblance. Space in order to exist must be like things, must move and be moved; and because it is not thus like things, it does not exist. Such is the pictorial philosophy. Space as a Sum of Relations. This argument has the same origin as the one just considered concerning interaction. Space is pictorially rep- resented as an infinite thing divisible into an in- finite number of parts. And as innumerable ab- surdities must inevitably result from such a fan- cy as that, space is once more dismissed as mere- ly subjective, existing only "in and for the mind." Even the cool-headed Kant was led astray at this point and painfully pointed out that it would take too much time to count, all this infinite number of parts and that therefore space must be an a priori form of intuition. The persistent error in all such argumenta- tions is the false assumption of the divisibility of 362 THE PHILOSOiPHY OF HISTORY. space. Space may be mentally analyzed, but it cannot be actually divided. Every one will see the moment he begins to reflect that the very es- sence of space is its absolute continuity. Bisect it and there is still space between the parts. In fact the very idea of division or separation in- volves that of space between the parts separated; for, if there were no space between, there would be no separation. Space may be analyzed; we can measure it by means of things used as units of measurement; we may imagine the space within a room as separated from that outside. But in all these operations space is mentally an- alyzed, not actually divided. But that, it will be urged, is but a trivial dis- tinction, a mere truism. And so it would be in the light of the old philosophy, which sees in mental analysis nothing more than a mental as distinguished from a physical operation. But we have now passed far beyond that naive view. We have gained a new insight into the deep meaning and universal scope of abstraction. We see that abstraction does not consist mere- ly in mentally dividing or separating the attri- bute from its object but that it instantaneously puts them together again — unites them in causal relation to each other. In Hue, to abstract is to re- late. To merely divide mentally leaves the divided halves as urrelated as the halves of a split log SPACE. 363 are physically. And to that process the old phi- losohpy has practically confined itself, in its view of abstraction. Let us apply this insight to the chief idealistic arguments concerning space re- lations. (i). Spatial relations, it is said, have no inde- pendent existence of their own; therefore, they must exist only in and for thought, and so like- wise must space, which is but their sum. Non-scqiiitur. The premise is undeniable: the spatial form, for instance, which we abstract from any given thing has no independent exist- ence. The form without the thing is indeed nothintg. But likew^ise the thing without a form is nothing. Abstraction, however, does not con- sist in splitting a thing asunder into two noth- ings. It is an analysis of the thinig into two fac- tors conjoined with an instantaneous synthesis of these two as cause and effect. The abstract and the object abstracted from still exist indis- solubly together and with the same common right to existence. If the thing is real, the form is real; and if the form is not real, the thing is not real.. Or to put it into a still simpler form, the whole idealistic argument reduces itself to this: Be- cause an effect does not exist independently of its cause, therefore it does not exist at all. Such reasoning would lay waste the whole universe of thought. ' i 364 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. (2). Another argument is, that the spatial re- lations of things are perpetually changing and therefore space, as the sum of these is perpetual- ly becoming something else. The answer is that space is not a piece of patch-work made of an infinite number of parts. We must discard all such foolish imagery and look upon space scien- tifically as that upon which the infinite host of spatial abstractions, forms, places, etc., depend. And then, surely, it will be evident that a cause may remain eternally the same while its effects are incessantly changing because they are also dependent upon other conditions which are in- cessantly changing. (3). Beside the actual, there are countless myriads of ideal and possible space-relations which things might have; these evidently are subjective, therefore so must space be, since it is but the source of them. But how utterly childish this appears when we no longer regard space as a sum of parts, but as that upon which all space properties depend! For, surely, it does not detract from the reality of a cause that there are ' 'myriads of ideal and possible" effects which it might produce under different condi- tions. The Independence of Space. Another argu- ment of Maya idealism is that the reality of space would involve a dualism of first principles SPACE. 365 —two independent and infinite existences. But what compels us to beliieve that space is abso- lutely independent? Nothing but the tacit as- sumption — pervading all idealism — that whatev- er is dependent, is not real. But that assump- tion is not merely baseless, it is absurd. For if the dependent, the effects do not exist, then causes do not exist. X TIME. 367 IV. TIME. Much of what has just been> said concerning space appHes to time, and therefore need not be repeated in this brief survey. I note here only a few neglected facts which put a new light upon the theory of Time. The Pictorial Process. Nineteenth century metaphysics exhibits, even more clearly in its discussions about time than elsewhere, the won- derful vigor of the Fallacy of Resemblance even under conditions that would seem to render it impossible. Space readily lends itself to the uses of the imagination; nothing is easier than to think of space pictorially, as an airy sort of a thing capable of being divided into parts and re- united into a whole just like any other thing. But the surprising peculiarity of Time is that it absolutely refuses to submit to this picturing process. There are no possible images of it that do not manifestly contradict all its properties. But despite this impossibility, imagination does manage to find some semblance of things wherewith to picture time. How? Simply by borrowing, so to speak, second-hand images of space and absurdly trasferring them to time. This attempt to understand time by means of spatial images leads to queer results. For in- stance, we often try to think of time as like a moving thing; it flows like a stream, etc. But time cannot move any more than it can stand on its head; present time is not "before" us for an instant, and it does not suddenly dart behmd us to become past time. Or, seeing the folly of this we change the figure and think of time as stationary, as a straight line divisible into parts. Tliis seems better as being more abstract; but proves to be really more self-con;tradictory and delusive. For the 'parts of a straight line all co- exist. But time is of such a nature that only the present instant exists; the past has become ex- tinct and the future does not yet exist. The quibbles and contradictions resultant from this pictorial view are too familiar to need rehearsal here. But note now the use that mod- ern idealists have made of these puzzles. Seemg the contradictions and absurdities resulting from the attempt to find out what time ''looks like," do they abandon such attempts? Do they sim- ply draw the rational inference that time is oi such a nature to preclude all picturing of it? No! on the contrary, they proudly present these N 368 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. riddles as a demonstration that time does not really exist. Time and Temporal Periods. But let us dis- card all these puerilities. Instead of trying to imagine what time looks like, let us interpret it simply in terms of cause and effect. We have, then, temporal periods — days, hours, instants, etc. — each presented in our conscious experi- ence as a complex effect. Each is dependent partly upon our ever changing experience and partly upon the continuity and oneness of time. To the latter is due the absolute irreversiblenesss of these periods; to the former is due their par- ticularity, their capacity for being analyzed — the days into hours, the hours into moments, etc. — in fine, the possibility of their being measured and recognized by thought. Let us apply this insight now to that chief difficulty, that most formidable problem in the metaphysics of time over which philosophy was vexing its brains as hopelessly two thousand years ago as during the last century. Every thinker knows the problem by heart: the non- existence of the past and the future, the present a merely subjective boundary line no more real- ly existing than the equator. But from our present point of view the problem is readily solved. Temporal periods are analyzable into past, present and future; for, they are abstracted TIME. 369 from, partially dependent upon and always measurable by the motions of things. But the time upon which these temporal periods also de- pend is indivisible. It is not a thing, a com- pound, a whole constructed out of its parts. On \he contrary, it is, even more evidently than in the cognate case of space— absolutely one, con- tinuous, indivisible. We may indeed properiy in familiar speech, speak of time past, present or future, as we speak of the ''rising" and the "set- ting" of the sun. But none the less, time is indivisible, contmuous, without gaps, atomic structure or other semblance of a thing. The problem of time, then, is simply dust, which philosophy has thrown into its own eyes by its attempts to imagine what time looks like. The obscuration disappears when we think ra- tionally— not metaphorically— of time as that upon which temporal periods depend. Time and Interaction. But perhaps the old cavil will still be urged. Time does not interact with things. It is merely a condition, not the real and ''efficient" cause of their motions. But what does science claim to know about this mys- tic ''influence," this "dynamic efficiency" sup- posed to pass from body to body and to thus produce their motions? Absolutely nothing ex- cept the persistence of its quantity through all apparent transformation. And this persistence is 370 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. determined solely by the invariable conditions of Space and Time. So that space and time seem to be the ultimate conditions upon which mov- ing things depend not merely for a place and time to move in, but also for all we really know about those mystic influences which are alleged to be their only true and efficient causes. V. PERCEPTION. Compulsory Beliefs. Let it be fully understood at the out-set that we shall make no appeal to any merely alleged irresistibleness of belief. Reason, as I have said elsewhere, is too divine to be compelled; it will listen only to reasons. In fact, an irresistible belief in this sense— a behef which we are mysteriously compelled to accept by something inherent in our mental structure or constitution— is an impossibility. The very fact that this belief is unaccountably forced upon us, excites the suspicion of its being merely sub- jective We doubt it because we are thus com- pelled to believe it. Kant taught this to the world, although the teacher seemed sometimes hardly conscious of what he was teachmg. Hence thet Scottish philosophy, with its lavish appeals to common-sense, irresistible beliefs, etc., failed utterly to find any real guarantee for ob- jective existence. There is a vein of almost whimsical irrationality running through it. What ;fff* 372 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. could be worse, for instance, than its plea that perception was •'immediate," despite the im- mense and complicated mass of mediation which so evidently intervenes between the object per- ceived and the perceiving intellect. No wonder that Sir Wm. Hamilton was driven to the strange device of imagining the soul as somehow seated in both eyes and there inspecting the pictures painted upon the two retinas. Discarding, then, all appeals to intuition, irre- sistible beliefs, etc., the question of reality nar- rows itself to this: How do we know that an outer, spatial world exists? My ultimate answer to this question will prove to be a very simple one. But before its full force can be appreciated, It is necessary to exhibit the sources of the con-* fusion and perplexity which have so long en- veloped this theme. The Fallacy of Resemblance. That a thought should resemble a thing is an evident absurdity, an utter impossibility; And yet there is hardly any proposition which has come much nearer to being accepted by all philosophers as a ''univer- sal and necessary truth'^ than the proposition that our ideas of things must be like their objects. Especially has modern philosophy made constant use of this preposterous proposition as the enter- ing wedge of skepticism. Locke began the work by discovering that our ideas of secondary quali- PERCEPTION. 373 ties could not be resemblances of what really ex- ists in bodies, although primary qualities possi- bly might be. Berkeley developed this hint into his celebrated idealism. He shows that ihe primary qualitites are in the same plight as the secondary ones; points out the contradictions in- volved "in supposing things like unto our ideas existing without;" and concludes therefrom that corporeal substances do not exist. Hume argues in the same strain. Kant carefully points out as the inmost distinction of his philosophy that he does not regard the space idea as quite ''similar to the object," any more than he believes that "the sensation of red has a similarity to the prop- erty of vermilion which in one excites this sen- sation." (i) And so with Spencer, in fact with all idealistic or agnostic writers — never have I found one who did not sooner or later disclose the true basis of his skepticism as lying in the impossibility of ever finding out whether our per- ceptions really resemble the things perceived. But we have now passed far beyond that ab- original point of view. We see that there is not the slightest need that a thought should be like the object which it makes known to us. Think- ing is not some mystic process of interior pho- tography. A thought is a means, an instrumental condition for the disclosure of an object. But it (1) Kant. ProUoomfna. 13. Remark II. i pip™ II 374 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. is no more requisite that a thought in order to perform its functions, should be Hke the object than that an axe should be like the log which it splits or that a toothache should resemble the tooth that causes it. Up to this point I have presented but a merely negative aspect of the theory of perception. A perception, whatever it may or may not be, is certainly not a picture. And if the reader fully grasps even this purely negative view, he will be surprised to find how much of the bewilderment and contradiction of current epistemology is es- caped. But something more than this merely negative view must, of course, be given. Otherwise we should seem to be accusing the great thinkers of the race of utter imbecility in having thus insist- ed upon what was self-evidently impossible and absurd— viz., that thoughts should resemble their objects But this insistence was due not to pure folly, but to a logical demand for some in- sight into the method of knowledge. How, it was asked, can a thought give us any valid knowledge of a thing, if the one does not corre- spond to or somehow resemble the other? But evidently the required correspondence or resem- blance between the idea and its object could be secured only by stripping the object of every spa- PERCEPTION. 375 tial quality — that is, of all that was essentially characteristic of things. Hence, idealism. A False Viciv of Abstraction. For a typical ex- ample of this let us take the teachings of Berke- ley. Impartial readers can hardly help being puzzled by that author's serene and confident as- surance that things are only "ideas." That to Berkeley seems to be an axiom, self-evident, in- disputable. And if his axiom be conceded the rest of his philosophy naturally becomes very easy. Things being only ideas, of course they do not exist independently of the mind. The es- sence of being is to be perceived ; the world does not exist when no one is looking at it. Even "the vulgar" understand by reality nothing but a regular succession of ideas in their minds. And so on and on, until th'e mystified reader begins to suspect some malformation either in Berkeley's brain or his own. But the trouble is not so serious as that. Berk- eley is simply the victim of a defective and de- lusive view of abstraction. To see that it is necesary to clearly understand what an abstrac- tion is. To abstract, as we have seen, in the section upon judgment, is to relate a cause and an effect. The object and its attribute are not split apart as with a hatchet ; the one is not even subtracted from the other. But there is an analysis con- 376 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. PERCEPTION. 377 joined with a new synthesis; the attribute — mo- tion, for instance— has b^en abstracted from and yet is never to be considered as really separate from or independent of its object. There is also a second essential characteristic of an abstrac- tion, its complexity; it is dependent not only up- on the object from which it has been abstracted, but also upon other causes external to the object; it is indeed this secondary dependence which gives to the abstraction that wonderful wealth of meaning and power whereby it becomes the means of binding things with things in that vast network of causal relations revealed by science. But to avoid confusion, let us provisionally ig- nore this secondary dependence. Let us fix our attention upon its primary indefeasible depen- dence upon the object abstracted from. That at least is indisputable. Any attempt to think of motion or any other abstract as having a really independent existence of its own, would i)e a sure sign of insanity. Now Berkeley, and idealists in general, do not indeed deny this dependence; that would be ab- surd. But they burrow und^r the fact and un- dermine it. They think of these abstracts — attri- butes, motions, qualities — as somehow having a vague, independent existence of their own; the object abstracted from is to them nothing but the sum of these airy abstractions. Thinking thus, it is but a short step to the idealistic conclusion. These abstractions detached from all reality, floating in the void, elusive and evanescent — what more natural than to regard them as merely "ideas?" For do not "ideas" have the same ghostly and ephemeral nature? Thus Berkeley and all other idealists — misled by a defective view which misses the most essen- tial characteristic of the abstracting process- find it easy, even necessary, to believe that things are only "ideas." They are the victims of a mental mirage which presents only abstractions, hanging in mid-air, unsupported and turned up- side down. Substance arid Attribute. Of similar origin are the follies that have gathered around the con- ception of substance and attribute. What can be more grotesque than the idea of attributes "in- hering" or sticking in a substance like pins in a pin-cushion? Or of the substance as a mysteri- ous, imperceptible substrate hidden beneath the attributes? How determined, too, each term in this strange relation seems to be to annihilate its correlate; the substance, we are told, is but the sum of its attributes; and the attributes are but mere abstractions. But if we interpret the two correlates, not in ligures of speech, but in terms of cause and ef- fect, ihe perplexity disappears. When we ab- < ikil: i ^1 378 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. PERCEPTION. 379 stract an attribute from an object we do not di- vide them from each other or spHt them apart. On the contrary we bring them together, we re- late them as cause and effect. Even if 'we ab- si- acted a thousand attributes from a given sub- stance, the substance would remain unimpaired and undinilnished, and the attributes lose noth- nig of their reality in the process of being ab- stracted. In fine, the relation of substance and accident is the complete vindication of our funda- mental law of knowledge; neither cause nor ef- fect can be known or even thought dissevered from its correlate. A substance without attri- butes would indeed be a deep mvstery. And an attribute without a substance would be a still deeper one. But unite the two in causal relation and each instantly illumines the other. Composite Pictures. Some thinkers have found in a recent photographic invention a new means of explaining and making plausible the ancient theory of abstraction as onlv a picturing of re- semblances. General ideas, it is aserted, are pro- duced in some such way as that in which a pho- tographer produces a "composite picture '' Im- ages of different individuals are mechanically blended or fused; their differences are obliterat- ed, a common type appears. But these pictorial philosophers seem to entire- ly overlook the fact that composite pictures are impossible except when the resemblance is very great and the differences almost indiscernible. Portraits vary but slightly in their outlines, and hence are readily fused into a common likeness. But who would attempt a composite picture of all triangles or of all motions? Or of all animals or plants? Or even of the arithmetical digits? Mo! the formation of general ideas does not consist in the mere effacement of differences. Every at- tempt to explain abstraction as solely a tracing of resemblances must end in the confusion and perplexity so characteristic of our modern phi- losophy. The Complexity of Effects. Another superabun- dant source of idealistic error is the neglect of the scientific common-place that effects are com- plex. Discerning that the object perceived is not sufficient by itself to produce the effect, the ideal- ist gravely announces that it is not necessary at all for the production of the effect and does not Because colors, for instance, are dependent not exist! The effect is merely a mental creation, solely upon colored objects, but also upon aether waves, nerve motions, cerebral centres, etc. therefore colored objects are needless. Because the effect is consummated by the abstracting mind, therefore it is independent of everything else. I shall waste no time upon argumentation of 380 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. that type. Let us rather note that insight into the complexity of effects dispells that appear- ance of deceptiveness in perception which has al- ways been the real stronghold of skepticism. The stationary appears to move, for instance, if we fail to take in account that essential factor' in all observation, the position of the spectator. The very large appears very small, if we fail to take mto account that essential factor in all per- ception of magnitudes, the intervening distance And so everywhere scientific insight into the complexity of effects vindicates the truthfulness and exactitude of perception instead of reducing It to such a process of "phenomenality" and illu- sion, as idealism imagines. The Kantian Doctrine of Phenomenality. This doctrine is the elaborate systematization of what has always been a favorite conception of minds of a mystical cast. It conceives of the world as a dream which all men are somehow mysterious- ly compelled to dream throughout their earthly Jives. Here, again, the fallacy of resem- blance is evidently at work; it is an at- tempt to explain reality by likening it to a dream, a hallucination or some other product of involuntary imagination. But what I wish to show is that this Kantian doctrine of phenomenality, plausible as it may seem to the thoughtless, is absolutely inconceivable. It is PERCEPTION. 381 devoid of something without which even dreams would be impossible. It lacks an element of san- ity which is inseparable even from a madman's ravings. For, let it be noted that Kant's doctrine of "phenomenality" makes not the least provision for any genuine causation. No more than Hume, can he find any real bond of connection between either things or ideas. There is nothing more than a subjective necessity of imagining causal relations which, instead of guaranteeing discredits their reality. Note further this fact which, so far as known to me, has been hitherto- fore overlooked: Sense, understanding, reason in Kant's view of them, sink far below the level of the imagination in its craziest moods. No matter how monstrous may be the illusions pre- sented to the dreamer or the madman, yet tha bond of causal connexion between them is, real; they do not come at random; they unfold one from another with as rigid a continuity as do the movements of the stars. But in the Kantian world of phenomenality nothing is real. The in- terdependence of the phenomena is just as illu- sive as the phenomena themselves. Causation is merely a subjective necessity — a dream about dreatns. Order and invariableness are equally illusive, since both Space and Time are non-ex- istent. In fine, each phenomena, each evanes- \^. 882 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. cent idea, is absolutely isolated, comes really at random, is really without any connection with the rest. Compared with this the madman's world is a cosmos. Let then the idealist think intently upon this unassailable distinction. Let him cease to prattle about ''fixed order," "invariable succession," etc., after he has by his hypothesis converted such words into symbols of mere delusion and un- reality. Then he cannot but see instantly that phenomena in his sense of the term are abso- lutely unknowable. They have not even that de- gree of intelligibility which attaches to the products of the imagination. Nor can the idealist escape by throwing Kant overboard like another Jonah. None of Kant's successors have made any better provision for the order and interdependence of phenomena than he did. In Hegel especially, causation was but a provisional, inadequate, "self-annulling" phase of thought— to be left behind as the notion moved on toward the Idea. That, indeed, is the fatal error of all Post-Kantian idealism. As has been abundantly shown in the Philosophy of History, the essence and life of the idealistic im- pulse is its emphasis upon causality. The dogma of "Maya" or "transcendenal illusion" is but an accident, a disease to which idealism is peculiarly susceptible. Post-Kantian idealism has flung PERCEPTION. 383 away the essence, the life, but kept the accident, the disease. Finally, the dogma of "phenomenality" renders all real knowledge impossible by destroying the distinction between truth and falsehood. Its teaching is that an enormously successful lie is a kind of truth, and the only kind of truth of which we have any genuine knowledge. But that is high treason against good morals as well as reason. It puts all human knowledge of existence upon a lower level than the hallucinations of the mad- man. For, first, it exploits the former as being a more universal, gigantic and irresistible impos- ture than the latter; secondly, it denies to our human world-view that element of truthfulness which is to be found, as we have shown in the preceding paragraph, even in the ravings of the insane. The Demand for Unity. The more one exam- ines the grounds on which the doctrine of the world's ideality rests, the more he is surprised at their inadequacy and airiness. Hence we in- stinctively feel that there must be some weightier reason for this long persistence of a paradox that seems to hang upon such a brittle thread of ar- gument. There have been, perhaps, several such reasons, but chief among them is the demand for unity. The human mind demanded that even in the pre-scientific age; and now more than ever. S84 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. PERCEPTION. 88b ' ttii t But philosophy has sought this unity by a wrong method—through the fallacy of resemblance, by ignoring the differences and magnifying the like- ness of the objects. Thus comes materialism cry- iny thoughts are but pale copies of things; and also idealism crying that things are but ^'exter- nalized" pictures of thoughts. But instead of umty we get thus only endless contention over what is really little more than a question of nom- enclature. The only true unity is the unity of dependence. Objects the most diverse—even things and thoughts— may be related as cause and effect • in fact, ihey are thus being related in every moment Of genuine thinking. There is no need of pain- fully paring down either of these contrasted ele- ments into a delusive similitude of the other. There is need of gradually disentangling, by a strict scientific method, the immense complex of causal relations until we reach that Ultimate Unity on which all else depends. This is the -only sane monism. The Ultimate Doubt. We have thus examined —in this section and the two preceding ones up- on Space and Time— the arguments for modem or agnostic idealism, and traced them all back to t few primary errors into which the human intel- lect seems very prone to fall. So far as positive arguments are concerned, agnostic idealism seems to have no standing-ground; any positive proof or even indication of the world's "phenom- enality" appears to be lacking. But there still remains a negative argument, venerable and formidable. Must not all our knowledge, it will be asked, ultimately rest upon some unverifiable assumption? And does not every asumption carr>' with it some suggestion, some probability of its deceptiveness even though there may be no proof or even indication thereof? And does not this ultimate dubiety at- tach itself especially to the senses? May not per- ception after all prove to be merely a universal dream? Could not Infinite Power produce our sensations, each in its order, without the inter- vention of a spatial world and organs of sense? I begin my answer to these questions by point- ing out that no real knowledge is based or can be based solely upon an unverifiable assumption. And under that term must be included all such nondescript phrases as ''self-evident truths," "in- tutions," irresistible beliefs, etc.; for, they differ only in name; no new certainty is gained by the easy process of declaring a given proposition to be "self-evident." No real knowledge, then, can be based upon an assumption. This wide prevalence of a contrary opinion is but a survival from a pre-scientific age, when induc- tion was misunderstood and when reasoning i( rt 386 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. PERCEPTION. 387 .4 meant only a deducing of some proposition from a more universal one, and that from a still wider one, and so on up to "self-evident truths," or un- verifiable asumptions. But we now know that knowledge begins with inductions; and that the starting-point of an induction is not an assump- tion. Precisely in this inductive way we began. The proposition that all thinking was a relating of cause and effect was set forth as something to be proved by an inductive examination of the various processes of thought. And we have found that every form of mental activity — per- ceiving, abstracting, conceiving, judging, the simplest inference, the most universal of scien- tific inductions, the recognition of Space and Time — has for its essence the establishment of some causal relation. Eliminate the causal ele- ment from any act of thinking and it loses forth- with all its meaning, its life. Thus a wonderful interrelation, a common kinship, is proved to ex- i§t between all activities of thought. All, from the simplest and most rudimentary to the high- est and most complex, are found to be but more or less developed forms of a single process. Through this inductively established principle we hope to give a final answer to the question above presented. In other words, it is this soli- darity of thought which renders doubt concern- ing the reality of the spatial world logically im- posible. Let us see. The Final Argument. My thesis is this. Thought is so interrelated that the negation of the spatial world logieally involves the negation — the eollapse and extinetion of all thinking. The dem- onstration thus becomes that known to all mathematicians as the reductio ad absurdum. There is a difference, indeed, but one that serves only to give a greater potency and sweep to our argument. The geometer shows that the negation of his theorem leads to the overthrow of some accepted principle of thought. Here it is to be shown that the negation of the spatial world logically leads to the overthrow not merely of some particular principle, but of all principles of thought — to the collapse of all thinking. (i). To begin my argument, the first fact to be proved is that we have no knowledge of any particular perception apart from our knowledge of the object perceived. Of course, the average psychologist will wave this affirmation aside with a derisive smile. He has always been in the habit of claiming the most transparent knowl- edge of his thoughts apart from everything else. All his teachers and books have been quite unan- imous upon that point. Concerning his knowl- edge of external existence he is modest enough; 38S THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. PERCEPTION. 389 :'1 . but for him no other spot was ever so brightly illumined as that which he calls his "field of con- sciousness." And yet if he will think intently in- stead of blindly following the ruts of tradition, he cannot but see instantly that there is no possible knowledge of perceptive thoughts apart from knowledge of objects perceived. For asuredly to know an object we must know at least some of its attributes. But the peculiar- ity of sensations or perceptions is that they have no distinctive attributes of their own, known to us. We distinguish a particular sensation from all others, not by its own attributes, but by means of the attributes of the object revealed by that sensation. For instance, is the sensation of heat itself hot? Or the sensation of roundness, itself of a round shape? Or when the sensation of red "rises above the threshold of consciousness/' is it painted of a red color? Or does the interior sensation of a mal-odorous substance itself have a bad smell? Such questions seem almost silly iirtheir simplicity. And yet a clear apprehension of the answer to them would work miracles of renovation in our modern psychology. At least it wuld prove to all what is here being contended for: to-wit, that there is no possible knowledge of our particular sensations apart from a knowl- edge of their objects. (2). Even those great groups into which sen- sations are divided can be discrimmated from each other only in the way above described. We distinguish between sensations of sight, sound, smell, etc., through attributes either of their ob- jects or else of the organs of sense definitely lo- cated in space, never through any non-spatial at- tributes of the sensations themselves. The latter remain and must ever remain shrouded in mys- tery. It may be objected that we can discriminate between feelings of pain and of pleasure without reference to any spatial quality. But that excep- tion serves only "to prove the rule." For per- ception proper occupies the neutral ground be- tween pain and pleasure; whenever either of these feelings is very intense, the perceptive func- tions are retarded and impaired. (3). Perceptions and spatial objects perceived are so closely interrelated that without knowl- edge of the latter, there is no posible knowledge of the former ; and that for the simple reason that perceptions have no discernible attributes of their own by which they can be discriminated, known, or even thought. That proved the remainder of our task is easy. For perceptioons, as we have seen, are the primary units out of which reason develops all its other processes. By memory we simply recall what was once perceived; by imag- ination , voluntary or involuntary, our memories !i 390 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. are combined; by abstracting, judging, reason- ing, we analyze and re-unite what was given in perception. So strict is the inter-relation be- tween all our mental activities. Hence we con- clude that if the negation of the spatial object logically involves the negation of the perceptive act, it also involves the negation of all other mental processes. The whole fabric of thought dissolves. (4). Carefully note, however, that our argu- ment refers only to the spatial attributes of ob- jects. Science is now fully convinced that all merely qualitative relations are derivative from and reducible to spatial or quantitative ones, al- though it has not yet completed their reduction. Therefore our task here is much simplified. We have to prove only of the spatial attributes thai their cancellation would make all knowledge im- possible. The splendid genius of Kant divined that the problem of Space was the key to all metaphysics. But perplexed by the obscurities enveloping the space-idea, he worked out the easier, skeptical solution of the problem which led to nothing but nineteenth century agnosticism. But against this view we have now raised an impassable bar- rier. Every attempt to prove the ideality of the spatial world has been shown to stultify itself — from the start. For, it makes thoughts even PERCEPTION. 391 more delusive and unknowable than things. In nullifying the spatiality of the object it takes away the only means of discriminating one thought from another. Thus reason is converted into chaos. Questions concerning existence or non-existence, truth or falsehood become absurd. Thinking has been rendered logically impossible. The Appeal to Cotiseiousness. Do you then re- pudiate, it may be asked, that testimony of con- sciousness which gives so clear an insight into our mental operations? No! but I repudiate that worn-out trick of proving sheer assumptions by alleging that we are conscious of them. Such disingenuous follies do indeed seem to be bringing consciousness into disrepute with many. One of the most eminent of American psycholo- gists wrote a few years ago: (i) **Every one as- sumes "that we have direct introspective ac- quaintance with our thinking activity as such. Yet I must confess that for my part I cannot feel sure of such a conclusion." But there is no need of going to that extreme. In fact, the very thesis we have just been contending for, instead of ig- noring consciousness, rather defines it and de- scribes its real functions. As the fine philological' instinct of the race divined in framing the word, ra;/sciousness is concomitant knowledge. In (J) James. Pychology. (B. C.) p. 467 Also p. 215 216. 392 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. every perceptive act, for instance, knowledge is gained of some object perceived and along with it a collateral knowledge of the mental operation of perceiving. Take away the first and the col- lateral knowledge vanishes of course. And that is largely the gist of our thesis: cancel the spa- tial object and knowledge of thoughts is render- ed impossible. VI. SELF-CONSCIOUSNESS. Nowhere, perhaps, has the fallacy of resem- blance had such scope as in speculations con- cerning self-consciousness. The difference be- tween the two rival theories upon this subject seems to reduce itself entirely to a choice of met- aphors. On the one side we have the party of Hume, who describes consciousness as a series of ideas, a flowing ''stream" of thoughts. That simile throws not one ray of light upon the sub- ject; rather it seems to be devised for the special purpose of concealing everything characteristic of our consciousness. The figure of a flowing stream as we have seen, is misleading even when applied to a succession of events in time; but far more so when the essence of each event is to remember the rest. On the other side, we have the Post-Kantian philosophy teaching another doctrine, but by precisely the same metaphysical method. Thus in Hegel's view, exclusive em- phasis is laid upon the self, that is, the ego, "the Idea" externalizing itself. But when is an idea inside and when outside itself or anything else? 394 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. So self is pictured as opposite to and confronting itself, like a maiden admiring her image in a mir- ror. And then after a while space itself is inter- preted as this opposition between the ''empty subject" and an "empty object." Thus the met- aphor works both ways: first, consciousness is explained by a supposed analogy to space, and then space is interpreted by a supposed analogy to consciousness. But we have now passed beyond this pictorial philosophy. We interpret consciousness not by metaphors, but in terms of cause and effect. To be conscious is to be aware of the causal relation 'between the thinker and his thought. And here our fundamental law of knowledge vindicates itself grandly. First, we can know the cause only through its effects ; the ego by it- self is but a half-thought, elusive, non-descript; in vain we try to see what it looks like, to de- scribe it as a simple substance, to interpret it piclorially; it can be known only by its effects, by what it docs. Ignorance of this fact led to Kant's mistake when he declared the self to \A "the emptiest of all notions," or when he en- tered upon his famous but futile tilt against the soul, conceived by him as ''a simple substance" or thing. Precisely the same mistake is made by hosts of people who doubt because they cannot discover where the soul is and what it looks like. SELF-CONSCIOUSNESS. 395 But conversely effects can be known only when related to their causes; thoughts without a think- er are unintelligible, nonsensical. Ignoring this is the mistake of Hume and his followers, who interpret their thoughts as a "stream." Thoughts without a thinker are abstractions abstracted from nothing; they are like attributes without a substance or notions detached from moving things. By thus reasoning, not in metaphors but in terms of cause and effect, we have certainly made some headway in disentangling the perplexities investing the subject of self-consciousness. But our task is but begun. Thoughts are dependent upon a thinker; but w^e have found them to be also dependent upon the spatial world. And it is needful to know something of the relation be- t^veen these two factors which co-operate to pro- duce human experience. Let us try to thus com- plete our theory. The Antithesis of Feeling and Thought. The pivot of any true theory of consciousness, it seems to me, must be the following distinction: The process of feeling and that of thought are exactly antithetical. Feeling is automatic; its only function is to bind like to like according to the well known laws of Association ; without con- scious effort, by a process as purely mechanical as the growth of an organism, present sensations 396 THE PHILOSOiPHY OF HISTORY. SELF-CONSCIOUSNESS. 397 are fused with past experiences. But thought, cri the contrary, is a conscious eflFort to arrest this automatism, to rise above the mere spontane- ity of suggestion, to abstract, to judge ,to dis- cover causal relations, instead of yielding to the blind, mechanical flow of associated feelings. The tendency among experimental psycholo- gists has been to ignore this antithesis, to see only resemblance between feelings and thoughts. M. Binet especially has shown, with great skill and power, the close parallelism between the structure of a syllogism and the fusion of present sensations with past images which is constantly taking place in all animal life. He wishes to prove the virtual identity of the reasoning pro- cess with this fusion of images; and yet he can- not wholly hide from himself their essential dif- ference. This idle flow of associated images, as we see it in dreams or revery, making the oddest leaps and the queerest conjunctions, is certainly something very different from the steady, unde- viatrng march of reason towards its conclusions. M. Binet confesses it w^ith admirable candor. "How does it happen," he asks, "that these ideal recollections are not reasonings although they have their structure? To tell the truth, I do not know." (i). The truth is that he has throughout his work (1) Binet. The rnyehohtgy of Reasoning. 174. mistaken the nature of logical inference. The syllogism is not, as the ancient Greeks imagined, the type of reasoning. On the contrary it is but a subsidiary process for interpreting and apply- ing the knowledge already gained through in- duction. Its work is so entirely mechanical that machines can do it as unerringly as human minds, (i). There is no need, then, of being sur- prised at the close correspondence between the syllogism and the automatic process which Na- ture has devised for all animal sentiency. Furthermore, this supposed analogy is very vague and far-fetched. But even if it were ten- fold closer, than it really is, it could not hide the opposition between thinking and the mere asso- ciation of feelings. Thought dissolves what asso- • ciation unites : for the blind automatic suggestion of similarities it substitutes the search for causal relations. Almost every page of this essay has shown the opposition between the two processes. The Functions of Consciousness, (i). This antithesis between thought and feeling is further proved by a scrutiny of consciousness. For, first, there would be no need of consciousness if think- ing consisted merely in automatic or mechanical association. More than that it would be a posi- tive impediment, preventing ease and rapidity of performance. Common experience shows that to (i) Jevons, Logic. 199. 398 THE PHILOSO'PHY OF HISTORY. SELF-CONSCIOUSNESS. 399 be true of all movements which at first have to be learned by conscious effort but afterwards be- come automatic or unconscious. But no one learns to think unconsciously. On the contrary^ the more we keep every step of the proces clearly and consciously before us, the better our think- ing. (2). Another most familiar fact is our experi- ence of the immense cifori required to really think. Despite our best endeavors the mind sud- denly shoots off into some by-path of associa- tion. Children are notoriously thoughtless; and the vast majority of men soon give up the at- tempt to think as altogether too laborious. The reason is that to think requires a complete re- versal of the natural tendency which we share with other animals. That tendency is to let our sensations and memories link themselves sponta- neously together according to the mechanical laws of similarity. (3^. For the same reason thinking is never continuous. As finite beings, we are too easily swept off our feet by the under-tow of our animal existence. And therefore in its struggle against the blind automatism of the unconscious, thought requires the aid of language. Those who assert that there can be no thought without words are probably mistaken; at least it seems possible to perform some of the simplest acts of judging or abstracting without the aid of speech. But evidently these acts are too volatile to avail much in the hard struggle of thought to maintain itself against the automatism of feeling. There- fore thought needs the aid of words, not merely for purposes of communication, but as symbols giving fixedness and persistence to our ideas, which are created with difficulty and vanish with ease into the stream of associated sensations and memories. (4). This activity of thought controls, partially at least ,the lower automatic activity, arrests it, reverses, reconstructs and transforms it. Con- stant experience proves this fact of control, and it is needless to enter here into the details of the proof. My design is to show that in this now completed view of the essential distinction — the contrariety, even — between thoughts and the stream of animal sentiency we have the first dawn of a scientific psychology. The Basis of Psychology. For thousands of years the darkest of all dark questions has been that of the relation of the thinker to his thoughts. Even Oriental philosophy, otherwise a marvel of unity, split upon that point. And the chief source of this perplexity, apparently increasing instead of diminishing, seems to be the failure to inquire what thinking really is. That unknown, much knowledge concerning the thinker could hardly 400 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. be expected. Yet philosophy has never seriously propounded to itself the question: What is the nature, the essential function of thinking? The result is that there has never been any precise line of demarcation drawn between the activities of the conscious self and those of the physical organism. Self has been vaguely con- ceived as some recollective force binding togeth- er the disconnected moments of experience. But animals also rem^ember: even the minutest of the micro-organisms do. They seem to have other traces of consciousness also; they are aware of their pleasures and pains, they discriminate be- tween spatial relations, they apparently exercise choice, (i) And if a single cell of protoplasm can accomplish all this, what specific function or rea- son for existence is left for the psychical self as distinguished from the physical organism? But we have now established a precise line of demarcation, even an essential opposition be- tween the activity of the conscious self and the stream of animal sentiencv. This activitv is re- vealed in all human experience as a transforming and, in a certain sense, creative power. It is the effort to control the mechanism of passivity, to convert sensations into reasoned perceptions, to exalt feeling into emotion, to transmute causes (i) Binet. The Psychic Life of Micro-orKanisms, by, 78. 109, et al. SELF-CONSCIOUSNESS. 401 into means and results into final causes, to create a cosmos within out of materials blindly provided from without. Such an activity is unknown to other animals, and of it, therefore, the physical organism cannot furnish even the hint of an ex- planation. The agent of this unique actiyity, this effort to think, is the thinker, the will to know, the con- scious self. / VII. THE CONSCIOUS CAUSE. We have already proved that the essence of modern scientific induction as distinguished from vulgar empiricism, consists in its new conception of force or energy as a causality acting with ab- solute invariability for the production of the mo- tions of the universe. At fir^t this conception was but a mere hypothesis. It was an exceeding- ly doubtful hypothesis also. Some phenomena manifested a certain degree of uniformity- but the most seemed to show nothing but incessant vari- ation. But with the discovery of the first two laws of motion this hypothesis began to be dem- onstrated little by little. And the whole gist of modern scientific progress may be said to lie in the gradual verifying of this hypothesis of inva- riableness and the applying of it to ever widening circles of phenomena, until now it has become that universal law known as the Conservation of Energy. But an enormous error has always dogged the heels of this great scientific movement. That er- ror is the assumption that what has been demon- • . \ THE CONSCIOUS CAUSE. 403 strated concerning force or energy — causality conceived as limited to one unvarying mode of action — must be true concerning all causation; in other words, that such a limitation is somehow necessarily inherent in the very nature of a cause. This assumption pervades modern speculation through and through. It is the root of Kant's celebrated antonomies. It is pervasive in all nine- teenth century idealism which, absorbed in the paradox of "phenomenality," lost all true ideal- istic insight into causality. And yet upon its very face it shows itself as an utterly unverifiable assumption. .Certainly finite experience can nev- er verify so vast a conclusion as that all causes are necessarily limited to one invariable manner of action. Even "intuition" cannot help us here; for that certainly cannot be a universal and nec- essary truth which had never been heard of three hundred years ago. Evidently this assumption is another case of the fallacy of resemblance, of mere analogical reasoning. Just as forces are pictured as things somehow secreted within other things, so caus- ality is pictured as something like these mystical forces and acting accordingly. But discarding all this, let us once more appeal to our Fundamental Law of Knowledge. Instantly two transparent and indubitable facts emerge. The first fact is that there is nothing contradic- 4(M THE PHILOSClPHY OF HISTORY. tory in the idea of a dependent cause, of a thing that is a cause in one relation and an effect in an- other relation. Some philosophers have indeed marvelled over this, but it is hard to understand why. It seems no more mysterious than the fact that a man may be at once a father and a son. The second and equally obvious fact is that every idea of a dependent cause has implicit in it the idea of an independent cause. Otherwise all causal relationship would be subverted. MarV further that this implicitness is not a mere hy- pothesis deduced through some difficult regress to the infinite. On the contrary, it is a fact evi- dent upon bare inspection of inert things as science has taught us to regard them; it is made obscure only by that fallacy of resemblance which leads so many to conceive of forces as act- ual entities, like things and hidden inside of them. The TJicisfic Argument. The above view, I think, shows the validity of the once famous *'on- tological argument" from the Idea of God to His Existence. That argument, insufficiently stated by the pre-scientific philosophy of the Middle Ages and much ridiculed since, is in its essence, profoundly true. Kant's witty criticism of it — that the idea of "a hundred thalers in my pocket" does not prove their actual existence there — has been received with unbounded applause. But, THE CONSCIOUS CAUSE. 40& really, the blinded Samson of modern philosophy was in that only making sport for the Philistines. His reply has no logical force; for, there is an utter disparateness between the two cases which he treats as analogous. The idea of God, of free, unlimited Causality, differs from all other ideas in this one respect, that it is implicit in them all. Therefore, if the idea of God is illusory, every other possible idea is also illusory — a mere shell of words enveloping a delusion. And if all ideas are illusory, nothing exists; all thinking suffers instant collapse. Thus we have again reached the logically impassable barrier which reason throws across the path to skepticism. The ontological argument, therefore, despite all ridicule, will stand. Every thought of things or forces or of dependent causality in any other form, logically involves the thought of some free, uncoerced causality. Every act of true thinking, as distinguished from the merely spon- taneous flow of associated feelings, has implicit in it the idea of God. Every such act of thinking is literally an act of worship. The cosmological argument is but a corollary to the ontological one, rightly understood. The criticism against it may easily be traced back to the error considered in the first part of this sec- tion — the asumption that causality cannot be in- dependent, but must always act with absolute in- 406 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. variability. Physical science has indeed proved that all motions follow, without a shadow of variableness, from their causes. But to assume that their primary cause must produce effects thus and only thus, is utter unreason. It is not only unwaranted, but it subverts the very idea of causality and thus makes all thinking impossible. In fine, it is the ubiquitous fallacy of resemblance again ; merely imagining that causes must bt : like their effects , it argues that because the effects are necessitated, therefore their causes must also be necessitated. And yet upon this wanton as- sumption all pantheism reposes. Analogy of Divine and Human Activity. We have before confessed — even boasted — that our conclusions were but th-e logical setting forth and verifying of what the human mind has always vaguely divined. This is pre-eminently true in regard to that argument from the analogy of di- vine and human activity upon which theistic faith has mainly rested and which even doubters, like Kant and Mill, have received with favor. That argument we fully accept; only we lift it from the level of a mere analogy to that of a true induction. Induction, as we have seen, does not ignore difference and reason from mere resemblance alone. But it accounts for the difference, quanti- tatively if it can ; and thus develops so far as pos- THE CONSCIOUS CAUSE. 407 sible the vague resemblance into sameness or identity. Let us follow this inductive method here. For the dim analogy between the making of a watch, for instance, and the creation of a uni- verse, let us substitute that exact correspondence which science has discovered between divine and human thinking. "O God!" cried Kepler, *'l think Thy thoughts after Thee." In other words there is no essential diversity or opposition be- tween the finite and the infinite Reason. True, the former is interwoven with error; but that is because our human thinking is intermittent, diffi- cult, yielding readily to lower impulses and sug- gestions, and thus ever lapsing into unreason. In fine, the difference is purely quantitative — the difference between the interrupted energ\' of the finite and the continuous, unlimited energy of the Infinite. The Reigfu of Law. But there is a still closer correspondence between the activities of the hu- man and the divine will. Both are the outcome of obedience to self-imposed laws of reason and righteousness. To speak of the Infinite as being compelled from without to yield such obedience, would be manifestly absurd. And that man also is very far from being compelled to yield this obedience, is too painfully evident from all his history. It is hardly needful to add that here also the difference between the divine and the human "T?:'--' ;S;t. 408 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. is purely quantitative. The conformity of the Infinite to moral law is continuous and eternal; that of man is fitful, interrupted by frequent lapses. Note, however, that even these human varia- tions do not in the least interfere with the univer- sal reign of law. If man thinks — in what we have seen to be the only full and true sense of that term — he freely conforms to those higher laws upon which all the lower laws depend. If he ceases to think, if he does not will to control the mechanism of impulse and suggestion, he yields himself to the dominion of their mechanical laws. In either case, the reign of law is not for an in- stant broken. ^. '. *:-.; '-■■-.:i ''^s / f tii I ^* ,! ^i: \ N