MASTER NEGA TIVE NO. 92 f^?^^!!T 0496 MICROFILMED 1 992 COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY LIBRARIES/NEW YORK as part of the ^ "Foundations of Western Civilization Preservation Project Funded by the NATIONAL ENDOWMENT FOR THE HUMANITIES Reproductions may not be made without permission from Columbia University Library COPYRIGHT STATEMENT The copyright law of the United States ~ Title 17, United S '^«4»» %* %»'■ s Code ~ concerns the making of photocopies or other reproductions of copyrighted mEiterial... E ,^'"\ r-^ /-^ Www Library reserves the right to refuse to pi a copy order if, in its judgement, fulfilhnent of the order would involve violation of the copyright law. v^ AUTHOR: OWER, CARL VERNON TITLE RELAT OF BERKELEY'S LATER TO r1 1 w tZ/i IDEA n PLACE: ANNA DA TE : 1899 Restrictions o..\ Use: COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY LIBRARIES PRESERVATION DEPARTMENT Master Negative # BIBLIOGRAPHIC MICROFORM TARGET Original Material as Filmed - Existing Bibliographic Record lp91B4-5".TovTer, C^rlYernon. Ini5 earlier, idesilfsvnn. •' ' ^ 1 A^r\ Arb or -^ *' kw / .- -' 1699. 0. 71 P univer^i H loc+or^s dis.' >5er+*,fion 5,f Corvnell TECHNICAL MICROFORM DATA REDUCTION RATIO:__ii.J^ FILM SIZE- ZS_^_iO^ IMAGE PLACEMENT: lA (JL^ IB IIB DATE FILMED:_,3._-_5_-ijvl INITIALS_7)li£.^_ HLMEDBY: RESEARCH PUBLICATIONS. INC WOODBRIDGE. CT c Association for information and image iManagement 1100 Wayne Avenue, Suite 1100 Silver Spring, Maryland 20910 301/587-8202 4- . Centimeter 1 2 3 IM llllilllllllllilllllllllllllMllllilllllllllilllllllll 4 5 iliiiiliiiili 7 8 9 10 11 llllllllllllluilllllllllllllillllllllllllll 12 13 14 J 15 mm IMIIIIillUMIIIillllMlllilllMIIII I TT Inches I I I I I 1.0 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 4 4.5 5.0 5.6 6,3 2.8 3.2 2.5 I.I ■ so 1.25 1.4 2.2 2.0 1.8 1.6 TTT T MnNUFfiCTURED TO flllM STPNOnRDS BY flPPLIEID IMRGEp INC. mB^5- FT in mc ©Its ot W^cw movV. %xhxvixi^ 5- -i",^i \ < , /■ \v t- The Relation of Berkeley's Later to His Earlier Idealism BY CARL V. TOWER, A. M., Ph.D., INSTRUCTOR IN PHILOSOPHY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF MICHIGAN. PRESENTED TO THE FACULTY OF CORNELL UNIVERSITY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY. w ANN ARBOR: 1899. The Relation of Berkeley's Later to His Earlier Idealism BY CARL V. TOWER, A.M., Ph.D., INSTRUCTOR IN PHILOSOPHY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF MICHIGAN. PRESENTED TO THE FACULTY OF CORNELL UNIVERSITY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY. ANN ARBOR 1899. THE INLAND PRESS, ANN ARBOR, MICH. Page 7. Page 12. Page 13. Page 20. Page 55. Page 66. ERRATA. Note I, read p. 176. Note 5, read note 3, p. 47- Note I, read note 3, page 47. Line 10, read muscle instead of muscular. Line 29, read mists instead of midst. Line 24, read Humian instead of human. t ^ ^ CD CD CD 00 CD 292826 i CONTENTS. CHAPTER I. CHAPTER II. CHAPTER III. 1. Introduction. 2. Abstract Ideas. (a) Abstract Images. (b) Universals. Ideas and Things. 1. Idea as Mere Sensation. 2. Idea as Percept. 3. Spirit, Phenomenon and Idea. Constitution of Experience. 1. Relations. (a) Arbitrary Connection. (b) Necessary Connection. 2. Notions and Their Objects. (a) Notion of Relations. (b) Notion of Spirit. CHAPTER IV. Conclusion. CHAPTER I, § I . INTRODUCTION. On one of the pages of Berkeley's Commonplace Book, the author notes that ''nothing can be a proof against one side of a contradiction that bears equally hard upon the other." One might be inclined to admit that a just estimate of the Berkeleian philos- ophy resolves itself into this reflection, if it were not that historical evidence decidedly favors a more positive interpretation. Unfor- tunately, the true appreciation of the attitude adopted toward Reality by a philosopher who, like Berkeley, is not a system-maker — scarcely a systematizer of philosophic conceptions — is often partially obscured by the fact that the positive construction placed upon his work by subsequent thinking sometimes emphasizes the negative element of his philosophy, and so isolates it from the course of later philosophical development. This is a truism, but its explanation simply is that the spirit of philosophy respects the system by which its course of development is for a time api)arently arrested. When theory succeeds theory in rapid suc- cession, the progress of thought is in single file. A feature, an aspect, is sufficient to constitute a farther step in advance. The value of the theory is merely extensive, while that of the system is also intensive. The system serves always to recall the personality of the system maker, the theory is merged in its later outgrowths, apart from which it is abstract and featureless. Berkeley was not the creator of a system. Rather was he a man with a theory of life, of morals, of Reality. Thus it is not surprising if, in his philosophy, the many definite tendencies in the direction of Empiricism have come to be regarded as almost the only positive elements in his conception of the world.' The his- tory of philosophy makes evident the value of Berkeley as a link in the empirical succession from Locke to Mill, though with regard to his philosophy as a whole, it may likewise be said that Empiricism forms a negative rather than a positive element. The lines of thought followed by him in his earlier metaphysical under- taking are undoubtedly those which make most clearly and defi- nitely toward the empirical views adopted by his successors. It ^*'In its best known form, as a factor in the history of philosophy, only an empirical idealism." Burt: "A History of Modern Philosophy ''( iSg2). — 6 — was, perhaps, unfortunate for the later acceptance of the Berke- leian theory of immaterialism, in a form more acceptable to its originator, that the ' new doctrine ' found so ready an acceptance as to what have since been regarded as its essential features: The Cartesian dualism of thought and existence, so haltingly maintained by Locke^ in his doctrine of substance, added to Berkeley's own nominalistic tendency and further sustained by his relii:^ious ' re- pugnance ' to an atheistical, unthinking ' matter', were the forces at work in the life of Berkeley, which early culminated in his view that, upon the existence or non-existence of abstract matter, there lay at stake the consistency of human reason with itself, and our only warrant for the objectivity of the ideals which human reason sets for itself. It may indeed be objected that these ideals, being so apparently of a theological cast, were the rocks and stubble which prevented the successful spading up of false notions und pre- judices so vigorously begun. But as Berkeley does not lay claim to a philosophy without presuppositions, so neither does he regard the prepossessions of his opponents as in themselves obstacles to truth, provided only the motives underlying them be not inherently self -contradictory. Whatever may have been the motive which determined Berke- ley to become the promulgator of immaterialism, the discoverer himself seemed scarcely aware that the world was already ripe for his views. In the enthusiasm which formed the necessarv accom- paniment of the awakening consciousness of his mission in the world of philosophy, Berkeley was in piirt led to misconstrue the task which he had set for himself. Aware that he was to inau- gurate a revolution in the current modes of metaphysical thinking, and mindful of the "mighty sect of men" which was to oppose him, the single problem of the existence or non-existence of mat- ter assumed for him a size disproportionate to its true significance, in view of the other questions which an idealistic philosophy is called upon to solve. Immaterialism- is far removed from idealism in any positive and definite sense, though the former meant for Berkeley the latter, and accordingly upon the doctrine of the im- materiality of matter — the first step in the idealistic progression which ensued, his early efforts are chiefly directed. The success which he attained in the clear and forcible series of arguments em- bodied in the Principles of Human Knowledge, was at the time grudgingly attested in comments, which, however, may best be ex- pressed in the words of the more favorably disposed critic, Hume: 1 Cf. T. H. Webb: "Veil of Isis," p. 12. 2 " It is the negative side of his philosophy to which — unfortunately, but naturally — he was led in his early works to give the greatest relative considera- tion." Morris: "British Thought and Thinkers", p. 221. — 7 — Berkeley's arguments says he, "admit of no answer and produce no conviction.'" " But the lessons in scepticism which Hume drew from them were foreign, not only to the spirit and intention of Berkeley, but in not a few instances, even in his earlier philosophy seemed directly opposed to the mould in which it was cast. Berkeley certainly over- shot his mark in his too vigorous insistence upon the sensuous character of all that we know; and in consequence the objectivity of thought relations, which any idealism of value must in some sense lay claim to discover, appear, indeed, in his philosophy as a background, but highly colored with theological notions. His idealism, being a theory rather than a system, the various aspects which it assumes are external to one another; yet one form of ideal- ism drops out of sight, rather than is premeditatedly abandoned for another. He runs the whole gamut of idealisms from phe- nomenalism to what is in the end very like Platonic Realism. There is something kaleidescopic about this progression, one can- not say that there is any true line of demarcation between the earlier and the later, although the fundamental difference is appa- rent. Berkeley never deepens his conceptions to the extent of fully ascertaining if they are in agreement or non-agreement with the propositions which form the starting point of his early posi- tion.^ Thus there results a number of seemingly heterogeneous lines of thought which are, in great part, rather suggestions and beginnings in thought than steps in a course of logical development. If, then, our interpretation shall endeavor to determine the resultant of these lines of thought it ought to effect this, not by a process of subjectively balancing the evidence for or against the earlier or the later theory as representative of Berkeley, but by taking such ex- plicit utterances as he offers us in his general attitude toward phil- osophy other than his own. Berkeley has most frequently been regarded as an extreme Nominalist, and upon this basis largely rests the claim of Empiricism upon him as its representative. This Nominalism, whether of an extreme or, as some would have it, of a modified type, is best set forth in his discussion of Abstract 1 Works; Hume IV, p. i8r. 'i 4'\Ve may be "inclined to wonder," says Balfour in his biographical introduc- tion to Berkeley's works, that a man who had done so much before he was thirty, had not done much more by the time he was sixty. * * * That he produced so little in his maturer years is doubtless due in part to temperament, and to the dis- traction of an unsettled and fvandering life, but it must also be largely attributed to the almost total absence of intelligent criticism, either from friends or foes, under which Berkeley suffered throughout the whole period during which criticism might have aroused him to make some serious effort to develop or to defend the work of his youth." "The Works of George Berkeley,' edited by George Sampson, 1898. I V — 8 — Ideas, which constitutes his Introduction to the Principles of Mu man Knowledge, and it is accordingly with this work as a basis that we shall introduce the first of the topics in tnis discussion. ABSTRACT IDEAS. [a) Abstract Images. The philosophical discussions and dialogues of Berkeley every- where abound in figures, and the effect of his metaphors is sometimes to make one think that the Platonism of his later years was indeed the undercurrent of his life, for a time obscured by the new discovery which attracted him in his youth. The predominating figure which, m his early philosophy, serves to clothe his conception of the world is that of the analogy of human language to a divine lan- ) Universals. It would be in a great measure to anticipate a discussion of the notion and its objects if we were at this point to dwell at length upon Berkeley's positive conception of universals. Yet a few 1 Locke's Essay, Bk. II, Ch. XL 9. 2 " Philonous", 3d dialogue. 3Cf. also, "Siris," note 2 of Eraser's "Selection's," p. 343. * Intro, to "Principles," J^ li- — 12— ■ words may be sufficient to show that with the abstract idea, in any other sense than that of abstract inia,<'' '^stly, that I have a notion not Dercdve ,tlV A ""'' T"'^^ ^P^aking, an idea of it. I do disproo/'oVabsTra^t irer"°\hr'j "l^^^"^^'^ ^^^""'^ ^"'^ ?-"'- grounded on the f?A?if ! .~ "' ^""^ negative disproof being grounaea on ttie fact that its existence s not supported bv the Pvi We may put the case briefly thus: We can have no idea of ' "Third Dialogue between Hylas and Philonous." — 54 — spirit, but only a notion or conception of it. We have neither an idea of abstract matter nor can we conceive its existence. The notion of matter is self-contradictory because, being conceived as passive, we may demand that the notion of it shall be realized in the form of passive existence, or ideas, and this demand it cannot fulfill — or if it does, it at once becomes idea, and then Berkeley asks: why reduplicate existence and attempt to think matter other- wise than as it is revealed to us in the percipient consciousness ? The notion of matter is thus inadequate to its objective existence. If it be replied that matter is active, produces, brings about effects, Berkeley would say that the notion of activity is indentical with the notion of spirit; for as soon as you attempt to conceive it as matter, you make it passive, i. e., idea, and thus destroy activity. If then you attempt to conceive matter in itself, as an absolute ex- istence apart from spirit, you must admit that it must stand on its own merit, i. e., as passivity, and thus, again, it is idea. The notion of spirit, however, though ' inadequate' in so far as we attempt to characterize it by conceptions borrowed from passive ideas, is not inconsistent; for the conception of spirit does not demand that it shall be, iti its absolute nature, expressed in terms of ideas, but that these shall only signify or represent spirit- ual activity, which is by hypothesis different from ideas. Thus we must, from the very notion of matter, demand a complete knowl- edge of what it is, and it is thus inadequate to the form of repre- sentation which its conception requires; while, on the other hand, the notion of spirit is less inadequate inasmuch as it only requires a medium for the expression of itself, viz, notions or representa- tions. We may accordingly be forced to content ourselves with a relative knowledge of mind or spirit, a 'probability,' as Berkeley expresses it, but of matter we can have no knowledge, except as a mind-dependent existence. The passages which I have transcribed from Berkeley's dia- logue do not seem to me to indicate a sole reliance upon the em- pirical self in support of his idealistic hypothesis. In the self or * thinking principle ' which ' I evidently know by reflection ' there is implied the thought of an activity of relation of which we are made aware not only by its empirical manifestations but, also by the universals of reason or 'notions.' Berkeley, as we have before said, does not think of instituting a Kantian inquiry into the prin- ciples which must be presupposed in the constitution of experience in order to render it possible. Before Kant's question could arise there was needed Hume's misinterpretation of Berkeley's 'spirit substance ' and the subsequent disintegration of the self into ab- stract sensations. By Kant the self was to be rediscovered, although the foreign ' Somewhat ' against which Berkeley so vigor- ously contended reappeared in the guise of a dins^-an-sich, thus oc- — 55 — casioning the transformation of the self from an ontological into hfs fe'" ;'T"'i ""^•^^- ^''^''''^ ^^ ^^^ ^^her hand! who bj his less critical and easier method, had seized upon Locke's com^ from?hr'"1r ' """'' '^ ^^^^"^^"S ^^^ -^P^ -' its act vity from the small sphere to which the latter had confined it, viz ideas of reflection, gradually transforms it into the self, which by par ticipation in the Infinite Self, or God, is constitutive o the rela- tions that are througout implied in all phenomenal objects I' At the first thought it seems altogether incongruous ard un- SsUhv"'"'' ""'"' '^'^^ ^^^^^^^^^^^ with Berkeley a^fd his pniiosopny . and yet the two are more nearly con nected than at first sight would seem to be possible, not merdv by" their historic connection through Hume under the law of acdon and reaction but by the problem with which both grappted so earnestly, although their solutions vary so widely, w! fin It e^ m certain particulars nearer than we should at first have suspected J he matter which Berkeley so passionately rejects while he mis the sensations which are all we know, is, as he conceives t, no greatly unlike the Ding-an-sich which Kant so pertinacioush. gnores while he accepts the phenomena, which somehow he holds TdL. .1 l'^''/'"''^''^^- ^he time and space which Kant acknowl- edges as the forms and only as the forms of our direct knowledge af^rmed or presumed-of sense experiences by an a priori neces sity are accepted by Berkeley as a priori relations, because neces- sarily involved in the continued activity of God. Kant's cate4- nes of our generalized thinking are matched by Berkeley's original notions of relations between ideas which are discerned Ind bSd as r'^"-'^ 'u' "^"'- ^^^^ ^^^-' ^^— ' which Kant beheld as shivering ghosts through the midst of his timid scepti- cism, and which he was forced to recognize as real by a faith which cosmo ThJ ''' — -ake-believe-of God, the'soul, and he cosmos, -these were to Berkeley the pillars and foundation of his t'obS^nr'^H ,^^^^^^^,-^fi-^^ -^ conscience the command to believe in God, because God is needed as a chief of police for and enforcer of duty, because duty is the voice of reason and goodness, which are but other names for the thoughts and actings We have endeavored to show that the self of Berkeley is but as "nl'atfvr'r.' ''. ^"^ '^^^^"^ "^^^ ^^^ ^^^^-^ ^^ -^stance as indicative of his deeper thought or last word about the matter ™'SXr'h'' '??^^ ''' T'^'^'y "^ ^ substance, ^ and his Zes!TeZ^f -^ 'V inadequate concept by which to ex- Th.rVv, ' ^P-^f '"^ ^ ^^'"^ passages in his Commonplace Book, sense ".Z^"' "^!^\^^^^^^^ '^ ^^e objective source of ideas of sense, 'there is a being which wills these perceptions in us," to — oQ — which he adds: " It should be said, nothing but a Will — a dang which wills being unintelligible."^ T.ikewise he seems to disallow the hypostalization of Will or Understanding, either as modes of a substance, or as faculties in abstraction from the self of which they are different forms of manifestation: "I must not say that will or understanding is all one, but that they are both abstract ideas, i. e., none at all — they not being even ratione different from the spirit, qua faculties, or active." ^ Again: Thought itself, or thinking, is no idea. '^'Tis an act, i. e., volition, as contradistin- guished to effects — the Will." '^ Further in his account of the per ception of objects, Berkeley says, in a passage already noted in another connection: '^when I speak of objects as existing in the mind, or imprinted on the senses, I would not be understood in the gross literal sense — as when bodies are said to exist in a place, or a seal to make an impression on wax. My meaning is only that the minds comprehends or perceives them.""^ On the whole it does not seem that he has much thought of pressing the analogy of material substance upon his ' active prin- ciple.' Although ideas, in so far as they are regarded apart from the relating mind, are passive, and although as coming from a source foreign to the finite mind, the latter is receptive with regard to them; yet ideas in themselves, having no connexion or identity with one another, have a meaning for the finite mind only in so far as the latter possesses the relating activity which is necessary for the interpretation of these significant signs into a rational lan- guage. Thus the mind is not a mere tabula rasa, a substance- vehi- cle for conveying into the empirical consciousness a world of ready made perceptions; on the contrary, in so far as empirical perception is present, there is implied the work of rational activ- ity, without which experience would be impossible. The finite mind can interpret the language of the Author of Nature only so far as it possesses the capability of interpretation, i. e., as it shares the rational activity which is at the heart of experience. With respect to the identity of the finite mind or self, Berke- ley is eminently unsuccessful, at least in his early philosophy. The question thus appears to him in the '* Commonplace Book": ''Wherein consists the identity of persons? Not in actual con- sciousness, for then I'm not the same person I was this day twelve- months but while I think of what I did then. Not in potential, for then all persons may be the same for aught I know." ^ Here * "Life Letters and Unpublished Writings of Berkeley," p. 430. 'Fraser; ''Commonplace Book " in "Life, letters, etc.," p. 466. ' Ibid, p. 460. *" Third Dialogue between Hylas and Philonious." ^Fraser; "Commonplace Book," in "Life, letters, etc.," p. 481. « — 57 — he seems to rely solely upon memory as the bond of connection between past and present states of consciousness; and °"s inlde quacy as an explanation of any other than empir cal ident kv he could have seen if he had but applied the principle of a socia tional psychology which he himself set afoot In the third dialogue between Hylas and Philonous he seems VZ'T """f ^"''l^q"'^"' P'-o«dure with regard to the seTf Hyla. says m reply to the long speech of Philonous which we have quoted: ''Notwithstanding all you have said and in conse aTste^m o/Zr" ^r'^'l '' ^'"""^ ^°"°^ *-' you are only WorfsTre not tn h! 7 ^'1,''°"' ^"^ '"''^'^"^^ '« ^'Wort them^ words are not to be used without a meaning in sp/H/uJ/ su/>s/a«r^ aTthVoth^r'-.r^tll ""^h""; '"" °"^ '^ ^° be^explTde^u/:: as the other for "the murder of matter is the suicide of the mind " L kder:a:s"',raf ""tT "' ''' Commonplace fU.ok, ir^whfch Soul '-Ihfrh ii < ""^ existence of idea constitutes the fo°"ows- < rtnow ,?"' '^°"g"'«^ of perceptions,' is answered as lOiiows. 1 know or am conscious of my own bein.' and th^t r myself am not my ideas, but somewhat else, a thinkin" actte principle which perceives, knows, wills and operates aboli't id as oundl-^h' 1 ' °T '"*' "^^ ^^""^ ""''' P"^-- both colors and and s^3unda'n'd r,r "'"'''"^' P^'"'^'^'^' ^-'inct from color and nert ideJl R . /""' '""'''"' ^""'' "" ""^"^^ ^^"^'^e things and ineit ideas. But, I am not in like manner conscious of the existence or essence of Matter.- Now from this statement that the self IS an individual principle, distinct from ideas, an'T he pre seems'thaTpi'r, '''' ' '''"i'^ '^ ^ '^""^"'^ °' perceptions,' t seems hat Blakeley contemplated a distinction between an em oiri :inc.^i; po\-n°tTci <:;?: ''''°"^' ^'^ ^'^^'— ^^ ^- ^- ^-g whilJ"h^'' H^n"'"™°"P'''" v°°'' ^' '"'sards the persm as immortal, means'heself'7n'>"'°''!,''"r '? ''^ ^°"'' '^^ "'^ch he evi.lenti; means the self in ts individual or empirical aspect. Berkeley's heory of personality is a later development of his philosoohv in the progress of which he has come to place increasing "SaLce upon the notion, rather than upon mere intuition. But i in his TjKT7'Lr:if' '° '^'"'"^"'^^ clearly between fh^'ei'iric wh U ren^ ^ongeries of perceptions, and the rational activity which lenders possible an interpretation of the sign lan<.ua-e of th'e ide'mitv of T "u'^'^y °' ^'"^ "'"^ '^ ^ tendency to ose the Identity of the self m Universal Mind. He now verges upon ' "Third dialogne between Hylas and Philonous " Z'rt"!.'','^?"""™'"'''" ^""^^ " L'*'^' '^"'='-''. «'<=•." p. 438. Third dialogue between Hilas and Philonous " — 58 — mysticism, and draws largely from Neo-Platonic sources for his conceptions. Jamblichus, he says, furnishes a doctrine that ''there is a principle of the soul higher than nature, whereby we may be raised to a union with the gods, and exempt ourselves from fate."^ " According to the Platonic philosophy, ens and untivi are the same. And consequently our minds participate so far of existence as they do of unity. But it should seem that personality is the indivisible center of the soul or mind, which is a monad so far forth as she is a person. Therefore Person is really that which exists, inasmuch as it participates in the Divine unity:"''^ Again, he says: '' Upon mature reflection, the person or mind, of all created being, seemeth alone indivisible and to partake most of unity. Rut sensible things are rather considered as one than truly so, they being in a perpetual flux or succession ever differing and various. Nevertheless, all things together must be considered as one uni- verse, one by the connexion and order of its parts, which is the work of mind, whose unit is, by Platonics, supposed a participa- tion of the first r^ji'v."'^ "Aristotle himself, in his third book of the Soul, saith it is the mind that maketh each thing to be one. . . . How this is done Themistius is more particular, observing that as being conferreth essence, the mind, by virtue of her sim- plicity, conferreth simplicity upon compound beings. And, indeed, it seemeth that the mind, so far forth as person, is individual. Therein resembling the divine one by participation, and imparting to other things what itself participates from above. This is agree- able to the doctrine of the ancients; however the contrary opinion of supposing number to be an original primary quality in things, independent of the mind, may obtain among the moderns. ''* Here Berkeley in his theory of personality relies upon the concept of unity not only to exhibit the necessary dependence of the finite upon the infinite mind, but also to differentiate the former from the latter. "Number," he now says, in entire agreement with his earlier philosophy, " is no object of sense :" " it is an act of the mind. The same thing in a different conception is one or many."' Unity he still regards as a creature of the mind, and not something existing in things independent of the mind; yet it is no longer as formerly an abstract idea, but a notion. And the notions, as vve have seen, are in Siris identified with the archetpyes or ideas of Reason, immanent in the phenomena of sense. The latter, as Berkeley insists, are not to be regarded in one aspect 1*' Siris," § 272. ^Ibid, §346. ^I^id, § 350. *Idid, § 356 and 357. ^ Ibid, §288. % -59-- *^°"t' ^""'u^ phenomenon is not merely the complex of sensations which has been marked by one name, and so reputed as a Thine The Ihing IS, in another aspect, as (he presenied object of con- sciousness, an irreducible fact; it must finally be referred to its causal source and receive its ultimate explanation in objective Universal Mind. The identity of the thing is not a meri ficti- lous identity, for the unity «-hich the mind introduces into sensa- tions has Its counterpart in an objective unity whose source is Universal Mind. As the finite mind, in its explanation of phe- nomena, precedes from synthesis to higher synthesis, by the redis- covery m Iinje of the archetypal ideas or notions, it becomes aware of the 'Divine unity ' in which it participates But while /r;w« is really that which exists, inasmuch as it participates in the Divine Unity, difference is not lost; for it is also true that "the mind so far forth as person is individual" lersonality is for Berkeley the most adequate category for the complete explanation of experience, since the self not onlv ex- presses the highest synthesis but, true to the empirical aspect of things, ,t also expresses difference, as self distinguished from self My experiences, he seems to say, must be referred to a hi-her source than myself, and there is a cosmical order independent of me; yet, in a very real sense also, these experiences are mine, and I am not the mere theatre for the play of passing iihenomena since in my ability to discern the unphenomenal character which attaches to my experiences, in the significance which the arche- typal Ideas have for me, my empirical self becomes, like my other phenomenal experiences, the symbol of a higher personality But there is another reason why Berkeley, in his final account Honof?h K • w-'f '° ^^°'^' '■^J^='^=' cov^^Mx^ identifica- tion of the self wHh (.od. We have seen that in his early philos- ophy Berkeley s conception of God seems unmistakably to be of the de.sfc cast. The arbitrariness of the divime nature language IS chiefly put forward; (Jod is seemingly regarded as an extraneous power working effects in us. But the interpretability of this lan- guage rests for us upon the i)resuppositioi, of a necessary unity of he finite wuh the .Absolute Mind or Reason. "Siris" is the explica- tion of this, and the universals of Reason which formerly received such brief recognition are the means whereby we arrive at the knowledge of an objective order of things, which as the deeper meaning IS the completion as well as the ground of Berkeley's ear- lier Idealism. With his increasing gnosticism, his growing confi- dence m the universals of Reason, Herkeley is apparentfv more " WlT'! "^l'^''^ T'"^',' '" ^"■''='"«s cannot be calle.l theistic. U he her the ...o-, be abstracted from the sensible world, and con- sidered by Itself as distinct from and presiding over the created system; or whether the whole Universe, including mind, together — 60 — with the mundane body, is conceived to be God, and the creatures to be partial manifestations of the Divine essence — there is no Atheism in either case, whatever misconception there may be; so long as Mind or Intellect is understood to preside over, govern and conduct the whole frame of things."' As we have elsewhere seen, the immanence of the divine Rea- son in the world of sense is the view which is now favored by Berkeley; but it is not maintained to the exclusion of the theistic view which dominated his early idealism: and in this he avoids the pantheism towards which he seems tending and the complete resolution of the self into an Absolute Reason." It is true that his theistic utterances are no longer dogmatic assertions as for- merly. The limitation of that finite knowledge which would grasp the infinite is now more clearly recognized. The theistic concep- tion of (lod comes as the deeper insight into the ever present cre- ative Reason which informs and maintains the world. It comes as a conviction that as man in his rational activity is made aware of a higher rational self which is the completion of the finite and the presupposition of our knowledge of a world, so may this higher self be more completely known by conceiving it in analogy with the total nature of man. As in Berkeley's idealism, and more expressly in the later form which it takes in " Siris," Reasoii is not to be absolutely divorced from sense, so neither is Will a faculty distinct from Reason. Not Reason alone, but Reason and Will, as different expressions of man's spiritual activity, constitute his inner self. In the third dialogue between Hylas and Philonous we have already seen Berkeley's statement that God is to be known only by reflecting upon the self, ''by heightening its powers and removing its imperfections." In "Alciphron, the Minute Philosoi)her," the question of the legitimacy of this process comes up. The inade- quacy of finite categories is recognized, while predication by means of them is nevertheless defended by reverting to the schol- astic argument that they are applied "by way of eminence and not by way of defect."* The theistic view, which he thus but poorly maintains as against i)antheism, is perhai)s furnished with a more rational basis if one reads it in connection with his later utterances with respect to the notion, and the function which we found must be assigned 1 ' -Siris," § 326. -^Cf. "Siris, ' §276, 287. 3 '' La larj^e tolerance de B,Mkeley n'excommunie pas le pantheism, hien qu'elle affirme que le funds de letre, en Dicu coniine en nous, est I'lndivisible unite de la personnc." L. Carrau: "La phihjsophie reli^icuse en Angleterre; " I'aiis, iSSS, J), 27. *" Divine Visual Language," § 19. I — 61 — to it in the constitution of experience. Viewed in this light, man's knowledge of God is but the farther extension of his knowledge of the phenomenal order. In the phenomenal world of Berkeley we are not cut off from a world of noumenal existence, for in the sense-material which is subjected to the unifying work of finite conceptions there is nothing foreign to Reason. In the generali- zations of science, by means of which is made possible for us an orderly and connected world of experience, nay even in perception Itself, we are already transcending the merely phenomenal. Finally in the highest completed synthesis, the Divine Reason, we have merely the last step which gives meaning to the whole. Man shares in the Universal Reason, and it is only by his participation in this Reason that he is enabled to take cognizance of this Unity which is the truest explanation of himself and of the world in which he lives. But m man Reason and Will are equally fundamental, alike universal expressions of his experience of himself, and together they constitute his personality. In his conception of God Berke- ley refuses to be be content with mere Reason as the final explana- tion of things. Reason, as so conceived, is scarcely differentiated from Fate, while the Reason it is Berkeley's purpose to discover is a purposeful activity, directed toward the Supreme Good; it is as he tells us, Will which is ''conducted and applied by intellect " The Divine arbitrariness is still retained: God is Divine Will di- rected by Divine Reason. Although in that Reason the finite is now seen to participate, the key to the knowledge of God is not only the rational, but the moral implication contained in man's knowledge of himself. ^ Siris, § 254. —63— CHAPTER IV. The relations which obtain either by way of agreement or contrast bet«-een the earlier and later phases of Berkeley" "leaT r^hTfh '','''" ""r '^''hibited somewhat in detaTl wUh e pect" that third class of existences, denominated by Berkeley snirit, may now be briefly summarized ^^erKeiey, spirits, y) tne sensation, (2) the phenomenal object, which is in on^ aspect a mere complex of sensations, and which in another asoert remains an objective datum of consciousness, ultiL^rexplafned SdT?raron°''\f^"f^'}:!,"'^°^^'-^^ (3) thL7c£y"e his in:Lance u;on the bW fvf c TaSr 0I T^''''' '^'^'^'^'^ in the later philosophy of "^ris'-tht, P^*^"°"'^"^' ^^^ile brought to hA by mSsIf tht -'mman: ^ imS: idtT^^h^oi^ existence had n the '' Prinrinlpc ^' o f •. ^^^^^\^^ icieas, whose former possesses the capability of rationally interpretinrthe sens Divine' u'n T'"' ^''T''"^ '''^'''' "P°" ^^^ cau^aTact v y of 1^ r. < n 1 -'^S^'";,'" the " Principles of Human Knowledge" and he t th"t r^h n"""'''? 'r''''''' ^■""■^ acknowledtmen o 'kU'rSerthn ?.''"."' °^^'''' ^°' ''^'''^ ^' prefers the term . h ^ ^ u ^ f" """S' ''^^^ "Ot a merely subjective existence out of %i; ', "^r""" '' '^ meaningless if J attempt to concdvett kno^Wed 'mlToTth^is'^"'^ ''""' consciousness. H^is sufficien; c Kiiowieagment ot this is, however, in this earlv nhase of hi<. iHp.i ism, unsupported otherwise than by citin.. the fact ihL J ; t « ^ established in so simple a way. Accordingly, in "Alciphron/ ' the objective imi)lications of the phenomenal object are made more expressly the subject of study, which results in the discovery that any perception is not merely the sum of particular sensations, but that, on the contrary, in order to the recognition of any perceived object, there is involved the work of unconscious rational infer- ence. ' A few sensations serve as signs by which we are led to expect other unperceived sensations, provided certain conditions be ful- filled. These present sensations are nothing of themselves, but only as they are signs of relations whose permanence and objectivity are due to the constitutive universals of Supreme Mind." Imme- diate perception is thus seen to imply mediation; and ''faith in an established, objective order of association between the two kinds of sense phenomena (visual and tactual) is the basis of the con- structive activity of intellect in all inductive interpretation of sensi- ble things."' Berkeley's association of ideas is, as Fraser points out,* not merely subjective but objective, although his ])osition of objective association is not reached critically; it is, says Phaser, his "religious faith in the constancy of the divine constitution of' the cosmos." "Objective association originates the notions of sensa- tions as significant signs, and belief in the invariableness of the relations of which they are significant." Subjective association, on the other hand, "helps us to recollect the meaning of each partic- ular sensation and connect the signs with their significance in our imagination."^ In the latest phase of his idealism, represented by " Siris," we have seen that the 'judgment of suggestion' ripens into the explicit recognition of universals of Reason, or the constitutive notions, imminent in sense. The legitimacy of Berkeley's final resort to the notion, of which he makes such important use in establishim,^ a more consistent foundation for his early idealism, was found in the fact that his early nominalism was directed merely against the hypostatization of conceptions in abstract separation from mind as percipient, while a more concrete universal was admitted by him even in his early theory, although its function in the constitution of experience was but imperfectly conceived. Finally, our consideration of Berkeley's third class of exist- ences, viz: Spirits, revealed that, corresponding to Berkeley's growing insight into the nature of the phenomenal object, there iCf. Wenley; "British Thought and Modern Speculation," p. 140 of Scot- tish Rev., vol. 19. '^ Fraser; " Philosophy of Berkeley." 3 Ibid, p. 395. * Fraser; "Philosophy of Berkeley" in "Life, Letters and Unpublished Wntins^s," p. 304. * Ibid, p. 404. —64— also emerges a theory of the self and God which is more consistent with the rationalism that is implicitly the basis of his theory of the world. That the world is to be regarded as my individual repre- sentation, had never been maintained by Berkeley, as some would have us believe. Its ultimate dependence upon Divine, rational will had been affirmed at the outset, the guarantee for its indepen- dence of me consisting in the very fact of Berkeley's insistence that perception and conception should not be thought to exist in absolute separation from one another. The particular is indeed the conscious datum to which introspective analysis of the pheno- menal object conducts us; but the conceptual existence of the latter is as much a basal fact of consciousness as the particulars by means of which it translates itself into the concrete perceptual ex- perience of individual minds. Accordingly the early theory,which tells us that particular sensations are merely the signs by which we are enabled to interpret the rational language of a supreme Author of x\ature, becomes, by means of the later development of the notion, the obverse of Berkeley's rationalistic philosophy, in which we are led to see that the relations which subsist between pheno mena, in the organic system of human experience, are not mere subjective fictions, but objective relations, discoverable by us, be- cause of the essential unity which obtains between the finite' and the Universal Mind, upon which these relations ultimately depend. Vet, as we have seen, in this unity of the self with God to which he finally conducts us in Siris, difference is not mei-ed in mere identity. The world is also in a sense the representation of the finite self, not because of the mere fact that man is a percipient organism, but rather because of that very unitv which obtains be- tween the finite and the infinite in virtue 'of which man possesses an 'imperishable personality all his own',' sharing, as he does in the universal constitutive ideas. Through man, by means of these universals, the world is constituted, and is representative alike of an eternal or timeless order of things subsisting in the mind of God, though also of the subjective interpretation which man puts upon his experience. From this subjectivity, man, by voluntary willingness of insight into the eternal order, seeks to free himself and thus reconstitute the world in the likeness of God. Thus the early doctrine that nature is in its totality an interpretable system dependent upon a Power that is not ourselves, seems borne out in Sins by his theory of the personality or 'spiritual individuality''-' of man. ' It must, however, be kept in mind that the separate strands of Berkeley's philosophy were never united in an organic whole. The nVenley; " lintish Thought and Modern Speculation; " Scottish Rev., Vol ^9» P- 154- • ^Fraser; '' Berkeley," p. 207. Uv — Ho— manifold implications of the new point of view, consequent upon his disposal of the fiction of abstract matter, were but imperfectly conceived. The work of establishing an idealistic philosophy which should take the place of i)revious materialistic theories was only partially sketched, never definitely executed. Furthermore, his philosophy was always in a state of transition, and accordingly on^ cannot regard any particular phase of its development as an adequate expression of Berkeley's complete thought about reality Kmpincism, which is by far the dominant principle of his early theorizing, long ago yielded up to more consistent systemati/ers material valuable not alone for psychological method but for o-en- eral scientific enquiry. On the other hand, the final ideaHstic position which he reached in Siris was presented in too fragmentary a form to be of abiding service to subsequent philosophy. " Elle n' ctait yas fausse, mais incomplele " la S/ns n' est qu' un devdoppement plein de grandeur de ce que nous ont rcvele les premieres oeuvres l^erkeley est arrive au seuil de la vieillesse, il a iuilO jusqu' ici cntre ce quil croit le nial et 1 erreur; nul polemiste via eie plus ardent, plus soupple, plus inlati^al.le; il a poursuivi dans tons ses retrenchmenis snccessifs la niaiiere en s<.i: il a "refute Lollins, .\ andeville, Shaftesbury, comhattu 1' elendue-substance de Descartes la nionade de Leibniz, V attraction newtonienne et jusqu' un principe du calcul infinitesimal; c est encore un sohiat de la verite qu' il est parti pour les Hermu.las. Le voila dans sa retraite de Cloyne; sa philosophie, comme sa vie, a cesse d'etre mihtante, il lit et medite, laisse sa pensee poursuivie son ascension de principe en principe, jusqu a 1' Un suprC^ne; pen soucieux des objections et des preuves s enchantant, sans trop s' interroger sur 1' authenticiie des tex-es. des echos de la sagesse antique, ou il coit surprcndre comme le souffle affaibli d'une insniraii.m sacree. C est ainsi que Platon, parvenu au bout de ses jours et au somm.t de son genie, laisse a de plus jeunes les procedes de refutation, les armes de la dispute et, ressuscitant les vieilles doctrines pour leur donner un plus beau sen^, expose p us qu II ne demonire dans ses oeuvres magistrales et serenes, A- 7'ime, les Lois Une critique exigeante pent les trailer de romans philosophiques, comme la Siris- nous croyons qu elle aurait tort. Quand une grande intelligence a perse toute sa vie ce qu elle a pense a le fin, en pleine poss.ssi.m d'elle-meme, et ce qui doit nous inleresser le plus, et qui dans la mesure que les productions humaines en sont capables, doit contenir le plus de ventc." 1 If, however, Berkeley cannot be regarded as a thorough-going empiricist, nor yet as a consistent rationalist, the suggesliveness of his theory as a whole should not on that account be minimized His early theory, in which it is claimed that the existence of sen- sible objects always involves a reference to percipient conscious- ness, "denotes a faithfulness to experience "- that is not without Its value, when corrected by the subsecjuent view that mere com- plexes of sensations, actually present in the individual mind, do not of themselves constitute the substantiality of the object, which is also a conceptual unity. ^ But Berkeley's close identification of perception and concep- tion has, because of the imperfect manner in which he explicates f h iL. Carrau; La philosophie religieuse, pp. iS, 20. 2 Green; Philosophical Works, Vol. I, Intro, § 173. —60— Ihe rationalistic elements of in, j^lulosophy, been the occasion of not a httle nusnnderstanding with 'regard 'to Ws true.t it^de toward the phenomenal object, which he substitntes for the thin, i de pen.lent of conscuusness. Thus Green, while ad.ni ,"»:. tl .t ' P>erkeley knew that pure theisnt (which he wished to es abl h has no foundation nnless it can be shown that there is noU nl eal apart fron, thonght," says that "he faile'- -"ce .ese IZTT > "^^ ^' ''""'"y- ''"" ""'^ '^t° is^l^te the phrasfe, ... IS Avr/A. more particularly if the Avr,// be held to imply ex c lusively the perception of a single in,lividnal through the medium of his senses only [as Creen in the above passages seems to insisO ■ ■ . . '^ to eviscerate lierkeley."^' For "he does not declare ne^s, since mere feeling present in any individual subjective con- cousness apart from the objective con.litions which rende fee'big nterpre.able is, on Berkeley's theorv, an abstraction no les abs , d than abstract matter.* The rssr of things indeed implies A r.//et not alone this but ...,v>, or .V,//,,v. Therefore to isolate the former p rase IS not only to neglect the later realistic development P ace of Eertel '°''''' "' '" ""^^'"'"'^ '-'" ""'•'S'"-' abstraction in or^d nf 1 7 ' '°"""' P'''"-"^"''''^- ''lie substantiality of the «or Id of e.xternal existence, as distinct from the images and fnncies diub,:d"th "" "'-•?'•—-• - f- Berkeley a fact not to be oubte.l. 1 he mere lieing^ and snbstantialitv of things is the least that can be said about them, and the true question o i leallsm s not does matter e.xist? since the materiality of the worhf can^o mat' en'aUvorn'i ""'"':'■'" t "" """" ''^'^y''^ ''^' "-- ' material woild, i, e., what is the truth about matter? 1 he answer is, that from our thought of the existence of the 'Green; I'hihisophical \V.„k.c, V,,I. I, Imro ' nVenley; lintish Thought and .Modern Speculation, p. i.e. "Ibid, p. I j4. ■ '^ "'■' ^ ^.;i'>aser; "Philosoph,. of Berkeley,- in Life, Letters, etc., of Berkeley, r, .\ \ — 67 — material object we cannot abstract that very condition which seems necessary to its being, viz., the condition that it shall be an object for perceptual consciousness. But this does not mean that its existence is entirely comprehended in my perception of the object; that it is nothing apart from me; but only that perception is a universal and necessary condition of the being of an object. The two have, as it were, a kind of organic relation, and cannot be separated. What is not/(?r consciousness, for the passive ex- perience of perception, no less than what is not constituted by thought, is a mere abstraction. The view that the Berkelian idea is equivalent to mere feeling involves a most ludicrous construction of Berkeley's theory of the object not immediately present in perception. Does Berkeley mean that, in turning my back upon the object, I thereby anni- hilate it? In this respect at least, as Mr. Wenley has said, '*he was not the fool his critics would have had him." For, in the first place, even if the object has an existence only under the con- dition of sense-perception; if that condition be not fulfilled, we have yet no right to speak of the object being annihilated, for that would mean that we first take the object apart from perceptual consciousness, and then conceive its destruction. If the object has an existence only in relation to some perceptual consciousness, if it gets its meaning only as it is for a percipient subject, then in the absence of its being perceived, we cannot say that the object is tfes/r(?yetf a.nd again flashed back into existence when the condi- tion of sense-perception is fulfilled; object would simply be rn^a/i- ing/css apart from sense-perception. However, this is to lay exclusive emphasis upon the percipi. Upon Berkeley's principles, Fraser says,^ the thing may be taken to exist, when we are absent from it, in percisely the same way that the thing present to sense exists, i. e., in the one case as in the other, actual sensations signify a conceivable object. The immediate object being rationally constituted, Berkeley does not mean that, in merely thinking of the object not present in my per- ception, I by this means recreate it, but that, in my thought of the object, I again recognize the universal conditions which now, as at the time when the object was present to my perception, consti- tute its independence of me. Does he not mean this in the fol- lowing? ^'The trees are in the park, i. e., whether I will or no. Let me but go thither and open my eyes by day, and I shall not avoid seeing them."^ Or again, '^bodies do exist whether we think of them or no, they being taken in a two-fold sense; (i) Col- lections of thoughts, (2) Collections of powers to cause these thoughts. These latter exist, though perhaps a parti rei it may be 1 Fraser; " Philosophy of Berkeley in Life Letters and Unpublished Writings," p. 332 '•'Commonplace Book, p. 474. 68 — one simple perfect power'''— which, as we afterward learn, is Supreme Mind. Green, however, in considering the philosophical idealism of Berkeley in its bearing upon science, says that ''if physical truths imply permanent relations Berkeley's theory properly excludes them."- Quoting section 58 of the Principles, he explains that this passage meant for Berkeley that the motion of the earth would begin as soon as^we were there to see it; while for us it means that it is now going on as an established law of nature which may be collected from the phenomena. This seems, however, to lay too exclusive emphasis upon the accident of sense-perception. What Berkeley means appears rather to be that the 'established rules of nature' are certain permanent conditions of existence which the mind in its conceptual activity is enabled to discover. Our belief in these primary conditions is ultimately grounded upon our belief in Supreme Rational Will, of which these laws or conditions are the expression. Once discovered, I know that the phenomena, which may be subsumed under these laws, actually occur in ac- cordance with them. The earth moves whether I perceive it or not, for in my thought of the motion of the earth, I recognize that the accident of my individual perception is not involved in the ob- jective conditions underlying my presumption that the earth moves. Still the universal condition, under which the mind arrives at a knowledge of the laws which subsist between phenomena, is that of sense- i)erception. Conception is only an abstraction from the concrete life of mind or spirit; we have only a relative universal as likewise a relative particular; therefore mere relations or abstract conditions of existence are not to be hypostatized and taken in absolute separation from perceptual consciousness. This is the logic of Berkeley's polemic against 'abstract ideas.' Accordingly the motion of the earth, as also any phenomenal object not present to my perception, must be regarded as being in a certain sense per- ceived. Nor does this imply for Berkeley the idea of God as a percipient being in a human and anthropomorphic sense, for 'God,' it is said in "Siris," 'has no sensory.'" Perception is finally translated into a system of rational relations which are intuited rather than perceived. The world is ultimately a rationally con- stituted cosmos, whose intelligible relations are at once the crea- tion and the object of Supreme Rational Will or Person. What- ever difficulties attach to this view,— and they are doubtless many, it at least avoids the extreme of the rationalistic view by refusing to regard the ultimate unity, to which experience must be sub- jected, as a mere system of relations apart from the concrete life of conscious personality. 1 " Commonplace Book " in "Life, Letters," etc., p. 486. "Green; Philosophical Works, Vol. I, Introduction, '"Siris:" § 289. / \ BlBLlOCiRAPHV. Berkeley, Geo.: A Nc7v Theory of Vision (1709), Prineiples u- Human Knowledo;e ( 1710), Dialoi^^ues between Jlylas and Phil, onous (17 13), The T/ieoiy of Vision further Vindicated and Explained (1730), Alcephron or the Minute J'Jiilosopher (1732)/ Siris (1744), The Analyst (1733-34), Concerning Motion (1721). Fraser: Berkeley's IVorks (4 7'ols. Clarendon Press, London). Sampson, Geo.: Berkeley's IVorks (3 vols., Geo. Bell and Sons, London; vols. L and LL, 1898). Bailey: A I^evieiv of Berkeley's 'Theory of Vision, designed to show the Unsoundness of that Celebrated Sfeculatien {Westmin- ster Review, Oct. 1842). Baumaun, J. J. : Die Lehre von Raum, Zeit und Mathematik, 1869. Baxter, Andrew: Lnc/uiry into the Nature of the Human Soul {2d cd., Sec. entitled Dean Berkeley's Scheme against the existence of Matter and a Material World examined and slunun incon- clusive), pp. 256-344, V. Kraut h, Princ. of Human Kmm'lcdge. Beasley: A Search of Truth, v. Kraut h, I^rinc. if LLuman Knond- edire. Be at tie, James: Essay on the Nature and Lm mutability cf Truth (1770). Boii'cn, Francis: Berkeley and his Philosophy {Cambrid^^e, Mass., 1838). Bradley, W. : Berkeley's Ldealism {Journal of Spec. Philos., voh\ XV-XVL, 18S1-1882). Brockhaus: Real Encychp., Elfte. Aufl. Vol. LL, 1S64. Bnmni, Thos. : Lectures on the Philos. of the Human Mind {4 vols. Fdinh., 1820, Lectures XXVL and XXVIJ). Bukle: Geschichte der neuern L^hilosophie, 1803 v. Kraut h Princ. of LLuman Knowledi^e. " Butherogge: Essay upon Reason and the Nature of Spirits (?'. Krauth: Purine). Butt, J. : Afternoon L.ectures on English Literature (1866). Carrau, Ludovic: La philosophic rcligieuse en Augleterre (1888, Paris, Art., Berkeley). Collyns, Simon: Berkeley's Doctrine on the Nature of Matter, {Journal cf Spec. Philos., 3-4, 1869-70), Berkeley, the New Materialism, and the Diminution cf Light by Distance {Jour. Spec. J^ hi I OS., vol. 15, 1881). — 70 — Simon- Collyns: On the Nature and Elements of the Materia/ Worlds,'' Hamilton versus Mile,'' Edinburgh, 1866), Is Thouo/it the 7 hinkcr {Jour. Spec. Philos., Dec., \^(i()). Cournry, IV. L.: Studies in Philosophy (1882 ). Erdmann: Leibnitz und d. Entivickel d. Idealismus vor Kant (1842 in Gcs chic lite d. Philos). Ee trier: Lectures and Philosophic Remains, JuiLkenberg: History of Philosophy (trans, by A. C. Armstrong. Jr., 1893). Erederichs, Eriedrich: Der Phaenomcnale Ldealismus Berkelefs und Kant's, cin kritisch-philosophische Abhaudlung {Berlin, 1 8 7 I ), Ueben Berkelefs L deal isms, Berlin, 1870). Eraser, Alex. Campbell: Selections from Berkeley {Oxford, 1891), Berkeley a Subjectivist {North British Rev., vol. XXXLV, i86r). Ifuxley, T. If.: Collected Essays VI, 1894. Eaiceett, Ediaard Douglas: Berkeley to Hegel, Monist, Oct. 1896, vol. VI f, pp. 41-81. Hegel. Gesch. d. Philosophic {Michelit, Berlin, 1844). Ifildcbrand: Propaedeutic der Philosophic { Lfcidclberg, 1819). *■" Ifome, Henry: Elements of Criticism {ch. XXV), 1762. Hume, David: Essays, etc., 1748. Krug, Wilt. Traug.: Handwortcrbuch der philos. Wissenschaften. Loeu'g, Th.: Der Idealismus Berkelefs {Sitsungberich der konig- liche Akadanin der IViss., IVim). McCosh, J.; Criteria of Truth {Locke's Theory of Knowledge ivith a notice of Berkeley). Meyer, Eugen: JJume's and Berkelefs Philosophic der Mathe- m atik {/Idlle, \Svf^). Mill, J. S.: Dissertations and Discussions {vol. J I, 1882). Mrrris, G. S.: British Thought and Thinkers (iSSo). Orange, H. IV. : Berkeley as a Moral Philosopher. Porter, Noah: The Two Hundredth Birthday of Bishop Berkeley {March 12, 18S5). Reid, Thos.: Works {Hamilton, Edinb., 1^2-]), Intellectual Pow- ers of Man. Ritter: Geschichte der neuern Philosophic, 1853, vol. IV. Robertson, Geo. Croom: Erase?-' s Berkeley, a criticism by Robert- son ed. of Mind in vol. VI, 1881, p. 421. Hazard, Rowland G.: Will, 1864, Causation, 1869. • Green, T II. : Philos Works, vol. I. Kraut h, Chas. P.: A Treatise concerning the Principles of Human Knoiv ledge, with Prolegomena and collected opinions (1874). Simion: Principles of Human Knoivledge, (1878). Sell wegler : History of Ph ilosopli v. f — 71 — Spieker Gideon: Kant, Hume und Berkeley, eine Kritik der Er- kentuiss theone {Berlin, 1875). '"'''"' w' K/f • \ ^''f""'- ^'■'''"■'^ Berkeley {Jour. Spec. Philos. i'ot. vlfjan. 1873). Stewart, Dugald: Elements of the Philosophy of the Human Mind ( 1792-1S27, ch. /), Works {Hamilton V, oo; // i8 in) v Krauth, Princ. of Hum. Know. ' 9 • ^A i^ 19) - ^''"^Trauth SS '^' '^''''^''^'''' Philosophie (1797 vol. VI, v. Pvler: Three Men of Letters (1895) Ueberweg: Philosophische Bibliothek, 12, {Abhandluu^ren uber dit Pruicipien der menschlichen erkentniss; ins Deutsche uberset-e unci mit Amierkungen versehen von E. Ueberwc-r^s -> And Leipzig 1879)^ . Trans, of Ueberweg^s notes into En^. Iv Chas. /m ^-^T'- 'f^'"'^'' Knozv ledge), Gesch d' Philosoph- len d Neuzeit Dritte Aufl., i8j2. Vogel: Philosoph. Repetitorium, 1872 Webb, T E. : Veil of Isis (1885 )• Windelband: History of Philosophy Zinunermann^ Ueber Hume's Stclling zu Berkeley und Kant (1883). Stirling, /. H: Philosophy and Theology, ^ ^hlls^ Jr., E : Memoir of Geo. Berkeley { The Irish Nation). Z'-'y-'r. ^'''''' ''f ^^^'^'tf'ious Irishmen {vol. V, pt. I, pp i-.n\ i^^enley R^ M.: British Thought and Modern SpeculJtion, Scot- iish Rev. San. iSgz. NoTK.__For detailed reference to Berkeley's comment Krauth s -Principles of Human Knowled-e," throu^rh much of the above bibliography has been obtained tators V. gh which \ I . / -.1 *i I,. I Iff t '^«p I ) COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY LIBRARIti 0023398140 i DUE DATE — . — *" ^5f^MrW^ 1 1 i -^rrfrr- i- r:- ! ! 1 1 - —— ■ * — ■ — - "" Printed in USA I -1* ro LTV CO it- i>