MASTER
NEGA TIVE
NO. 92
f^?^^!!T
0496
MICROFILMED 1 992
COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY LIBRARIES/NEW YORK
as part of the ^
"Foundations of Western Civilization Preservation Project
Funded by the
NATIONAL ENDOWMENT FOR THE HUMANITIES
Reproductions may not be made without permission from
Columbia University Library
COPYRIGHT STATEMENT
The copyright law of the United States ~ Title 17, United
S
'^«4»» %* %»'■
s Code ~ concerns the making of photocopies or other
reproductions of copyrighted mEiterial...
E
,^'"\ r-^ /-^
Www
Library reserves the right to refuse to
pi a copy order if, in its judgement, fulfilhnent of the order
would involve violation of the copyright law.
v^
AUTHOR:
OWER, CARL VERNON
TITLE
RELAT
OF
BERKELEY'S LATER TO
r1 1 w tZ/i
IDEA
n
PLACE:
ANNA
DA TE :
1899
Restrictions o..\ Use:
COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY LIBRARIES
PRESERVATION DEPARTMENT
Master Negative #
BIBLIOGRAPHIC MICROFORM TARGET
Original Material as Filmed - Existing Bibliographic Record
lp91B4-5".TovTer, C^rlYernon.
Ini5 earlier, idesilfsvnn. •' ' ^
1
A^r\ Arb
or
-^ *' kw / .- -'
1699. 0. 71
P
univer^i
H
loc+or^s dis.' >5er+*,fion 5,f Corvnell
TECHNICAL MICROFORM DATA
REDUCTION RATIO:__ii.J^
FILM SIZE- ZS_^_iO^
IMAGE PLACEMENT: lA (JL^ IB IIB
DATE FILMED:_,3._-_5_-ijvl INITIALS_7)li£.^_
HLMEDBY: RESEARCH PUBLICATIONS. INC WOODBRIDGE. CT
c
Association for information and image iManagement
1100 Wayne Avenue, Suite 1100
Silver Spring, Maryland 20910
301/587-8202
4- .
Centimeter
1 2 3
IM
llllilllllllllilllllllllllllMllllilllllllllilllllllll
4 5
iliiiiliiiili
7 8 9 10 11
llllllllllllluilllllllllllllillllllllllllll
12 13 14
J
15 mm
IMIIIIillUMIIIillllMlllilllMIIII
I TT
Inches
I I I I I
1.0
1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1
4
4.5
5.0
5.6
6,3
2.8
3.2
2.5
I.I
■ so
1.25
1.4
2.2
2.0
1.8
1.6
TTT
T
MnNUFfiCTURED TO flllM STPNOnRDS
BY flPPLIEID IMRGEp INC.
mB^5-
FT
in mc ©Its ot W^cw movV.
%xhxvixi^
5-
-i",^i
\
< ,
/■
\v
t-
The Relation of Berkeley's Later
to His Earlier Idealism
BY
CARL V. TOWER, A. M., Ph.D.,
INSTRUCTOR IN PHILOSOPHY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF MICHIGAN.
PRESENTED TO THE
FACULTY OF CORNELL UNIVERSITY FOR THE DEGREE
OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY.
w
ANN ARBOR:
1899.
The Relation of Berkeley's Later
to His Earlier Idealism
BY
CARL V. TOWER, A.M., Ph.D.,
INSTRUCTOR IN PHILOSOPHY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF MICHIGAN.
PRESENTED TO THE
FACULTY OF CORNELL UNIVERSITY FOR THE DEGREE
OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY.
ANN ARBOR
1899.
THE INLAND PRESS, ANN ARBOR, MICH.
Page 7.
Page 12.
Page 13.
Page 20.
Page 55.
Page 66.
ERRATA.
Note I, read p. 176.
Note 5, read note 3, p. 47-
Note I, read note 3, page 47.
Line 10, read muscle instead of muscular.
Line 29, read mists instead of midst.
Line 24, read Humian instead of human.
t
^
^
CD
CD
CD
00
CD
292826
i
CONTENTS.
CHAPTER I.
CHAPTER II.
CHAPTER III.
1. Introduction.
2. Abstract Ideas.
(a) Abstract Images.
(b) Universals.
Ideas and Things.
1. Idea as Mere Sensation.
2. Idea as Percept.
3. Spirit, Phenomenon and Idea.
Constitution of Experience.
1. Relations.
(a) Arbitrary Connection.
(b) Necessary Connection.
2. Notions and Their Objects.
(a) Notion of Relations.
(b) Notion of Spirit.
CHAPTER IV. Conclusion.
CHAPTER I,
§ I . INTRODUCTION.
On one of the pages of Berkeley's Commonplace Book, the
author notes that ''nothing can be a proof against one side of a
contradiction that bears equally hard upon the other." One might
be inclined to admit that a just estimate of the Berkeleian philos-
ophy resolves itself into this reflection, if it were not that historical
evidence decidedly favors a more positive interpretation. Unfor-
tunately, the true appreciation of the attitude adopted toward
Reality by a philosopher who, like Berkeley, is not a system-maker
— scarcely a systematizer of philosophic conceptions — is often
partially obscured by the fact that the positive construction placed
upon his work by subsequent thinking sometimes emphasizes the
negative element of his philosophy, and so isolates it from the
course of later philosophical development. This is a truism,
but its explanation simply is that the spirit of philosophy respects
the system by which its course of development is for a time
api)arently arrested. When theory succeeds theory in rapid suc-
cession, the progress of thought is in single file. A feature, an
aspect, is sufficient to constitute a farther step in advance. The
value of the theory is merely extensive, while that of the system is
also intensive. The system serves always to recall the personality
of the system maker, the theory is merged in its later outgrowths,
apart from which it is abstract and featureless.
Berkeley was not the creator of a system. Rather was he a
man with a theory of life, of morals, of Reality. Thus it is not
surprising if, in his philosophy, the many definite tendencies in the
direction of Empiricism have come to be regarded as almost the
only positive elements in his conception of the world.' The his-
tory of philosophy makes evident the value of Berkeley as a link
in the empirical succession from Locke to Mill, though with
regard to his philosophy as a whole, it may likewise be said that
Empiricism forms a negative rather than a positive element. The
lines of thought followed by him in his earlier metaphysical under-
taking are undoubtedly those which make most clearly and defi-
nitely toward the empirical views adopted by his successors. It
^*'In its best known form, as a factor in the history of philosophy, only an
empirical idealism." Burt: "A History of Modern Philosophy ''( iSg2).
— 6 —
was, perhaps, unfortunate for the later acceptance of the Berke-
leian theory of immaterialism, in a form more acceptable to its
originator, that the ' new doctrine ' found so ready an acceptance
as to what have since been regarded as its essential features: The
Cartesian dualism of thought and existence, so haltingly maintained
by Locke^ in his doctrine of substance, added to Berkeley's own
nominalistic tendency and further sustained by his relii:^ious ' re-
pugnance ' to an atheistical, unthinking ' matter', were the forces
at work in the life of Berkeley, which early culminated in his view
that, upon the existence or non-existence of abstract matter, there
lay at stake the consistency of human reason with itself, and our
only warrant for the objectivity of the ideals which human reason
sets for itself. It may indeed be objected that these ideals, being
so apparently of a theological cast, were the rocks and stubble
which prevented the successful spading up of false notions und pre-
judices so vigorously begun. But as Berkeley does not lay claim
to a philosophy without presuppositions, so neither does he regard
the prepossessions of his opponents as in themselves obstacles to
truth, provided only the motives underlying them be not inherently
self -contradictory.
Whatever may have been the motive which determined Berke-
ley to become the promulgator of immaterialism, the discoverer
himself seemed scarcely aware that the world was already ripe for
his views. In the enthusiasm which formed the necessarv accom-
paniment of the awakening consciousness of his mission in the
world of philosophy, Berkeley was in piirt led to misconstrue
the task which he had set for himself. Aware that he was to inau-
gurate a revolution in the current modes of metaphysical thinking,
and mindful of the "mighty sect of men" which was to oppose
him, the single problem of the existence or non-existence of mat-
ter assumed for him a size disproportionate to its true significance,
in view of the other questions which an idealistic philosophy is
called upon to solve. Immaterialism- is far removed from idealism
in any positive and definite sense, though the former meant for
Berkeley the latter, and accordingly upon the doctrine of the im-
materiality of matter — the first step in the idealistic progression
which ensued, his early efforts are chiefly directed. The success
which he attained in the clear and forcible series of arguments em-
bodied in the Principles of Human Knowledge, was at the time
grudgingly attested in comments, which, however, may best be ex-
pressed in the words of the more favorably disposed critic, Hume:
1 Cf. T. H. Webb: "Veil of Isis," p. 12.
2 " It is the negative side of his philosophy to which — unfortunately, but
naturally — he was led in his early works to give the greatest relative considera-
tion." Morris: "British Thought and Thinkers", p. 221.
— 7 —
Berkeley's arguments says he, "admit of no answer and produce
no conviction.'"
" But the lessons in scepticism which Hume drew from them
were foreign, not only to the spirit and intention of Berkeley, but
in not a few instances, even in his earlier philosophy seemed directly
opposed to the mould in which it was cast. Berkeley certainly over-
shot his mark in his too vigorous insistence upon the sensuous
character of all that we know; and in consequence the objectivity
of thought relations, which any idealism of value must in some
sense lay claim to discover, appear, indeed, in his philosophy as
a background, but highly colored with theological notions. His
idealism, being a theory rather than a system, the various aspects
which it assumes are external to one another; yet one form of ideal-
ism drops out of sight, rather than is premeditatedly abandoned
for another. He runs the whole gamut of idealisms from phe-
nomenalism to what is in the end very like Platonic Realism.
There is something kaleidescopic about this progression, one can-
not say that there is any true line of demarcation between the
earlier and the later, although the fundamental difference is appa-
rent. Berkeley never deepens his conceptions to the extent of
fully ascertaining if they are in agreement or non-agreement with
the propositions which form the starting point of his early posi-
tion.^ Thus there results a number of seemingly heterogeneous
lines of thought which are, in great part, rather suggestions and
beginnings in thought than steps in a course of logical development.
If, then, our interpretation shall endeavor to determine the resultant
of these lines of thought it ought to effect this, not by a process of
subjectively balancing the evidence for or against the earlier or the
later theory as representative of Berkeley, but by taking such ex-
plicit utterances as he offers us in his general attitude toward phil-
osophy other than his own. Berkeley has most frequently been
regarded as an extreme Nominalist, and upon this basis largely
rests the claim of Empiricism upon him as its representative. This
Nominalism, whether of an extreme or, as some would have it, of
a modified type, is best set forth in his discussion of Abstract
1 Works; Hume IV, p. i8r.
'i 4'\Ve may be "inclined to wonder," says Balfour in his biographical introduc-
tion to Berkeley's works, that a man who had done so much before he was thirty, had
not done much more by the time he was sixty. * * * That he produced so
little in his maturer years is doubtless due in part to temperament, and to the dis-
traction of an unsettled and fvandering life, but it must also be largely attributed
to the almost total absence of intelligent criticism, either from friends or foes, under
which Berkeley suffered throughout the whole period during which criticism might
have aroused him to make some serious effort to develop or to defend the work of
his youth." "The Works of George Berkeley,' edited by George Sampson,
1898.
I
V
— 8 —
Ideas, which constitutes his Introduction to the Principles of Mu
man Knowledge, and it is accordingly with this work as a basis
that we shall introduce the first of the topics in tnis discussion.
ABSTRACT IDEAS.
[a) Abstract Images.
The philosophical discussions and dialogues of Berkeley every-
where abound in figures, and the effect of his metaphors is sometimes
to make one think that the Platonism of his later years was indeed the
undercurrent of his life, for a time obscured by the new discovery
which attracted him in his youth. The predominating figure which,
m his early philosophy, serves to clothe his conception of the
world is that of the analogy of human language to a divine lan-
) Universals.
It would be in a great measure to anticipate a discussion of
the notion and its objects if we were at this point to dwell at length
upon Berkeley's positive conception of universals. Yet a few
1 Locke's Essay, Bk. II, Ch. XL 9.
2 " Philonous", 3d dialogue.
3Cf. also, "Siris," note 2 of Eraser's "Selection's," p. 343.
* Intro, to "Principles," J^ li-
— 12— ■
words may be sufficient to show that with the abstract idea, in any
other sense than that of abstract inia,<'' '^stly, that I have a notion
not Dercdve ,tlV A ""'' T"'^^ ^P^aking, an idea of it. I do
disproo/'oVabsTra^t irer"°\hr'j "l^^^"^^'^ ^^^""'^ ^"'^ ?-"'-
grounded on the f?A?if ! .~ "' ^""^ negative disproof being
grounaea on ttie fact that its existence s not supported bv the Pvi
We may put the case briefly thus: We can have no idea of
' "Third Dialogue between Hylas and Philonous."
— 54 —
spirit, but only a notion or conception of it. We have neither an
idea of abstract matter nor can we conceive its existence. The
notion of matter is self-contradictory because, being conceived as
passive, we may demand that the notion of it shall be realized in
the form of passive existence, or ideas, and this demand it cannot
fulfill — or if it does, it at once becomes idea, and then Berkeley
asks: why reduplicate existence and attempt to think matter other-
wise than as it is revealed to us in the percipient consciousness ?
The notion of matter is thus inadequate to its objective existence.
If it be replied that matter is active, produces, brings about effects,
Berkeley would say that the notion of activity is indentical with
the notion of spirit; for as soon as you attempt to conceive it as
matter, you make it passive, i. e., idea, and thus destroy activity.
If then you attempt to conceive matter in itself, as an absolute ex-
istence apart from spirit, you must admit that it must stand on its
own merit, i. e., as passivity, and thus, again, it is idea.
The notion of spirit, however, though ' inadequate' in so far
as we attempt to characterize it by conceptions borrowed from
passive ideas, is not inconsistent; for the conception of spirit does
not demand that it shall be, iti its absolute nature, expressed in
terms of ideas, but that these shall only signify or represent spirit-
ual activity, which is by hypothesis different from ideas. Thus we
must, from the very notion of matter, demand a complete knowl-
edge of what it is, and it is thus inadequate to the form of repre-
sentation which its conception requires; while, on the other hand,
the notion of spirit is less inadequate inasmuch as it only requires
a medium for the expression of itself, viz, notions or representa-
tions. We may accordingly be forced to content ourselves with a
relative knowledge of mind or spirit, a 'probability,' as Berkeley
expresses it, but of matter we can have no knowledge, except as a
mind-dependent existence.
The passages which I have transcribed from Berkeley's dia-
logue do not seem to me to indicate a sole reliance upon the em-
pirical self in support of his idealistic hypothesis. In the self or
* thinking principle ' which ' I evidently know by reflection ' there
is implied the thought of an activity of relation of which we are
made aware not only by its empirical manifestations but, also by
the universals of reason or 'notions.' Berkeley, as we have before
said, does not think of instituting a Kantian inquiry into the prin-
ciples which must be presupposed in the constitution of experience
in order to render it possible. Before Kant's question could arise
there was needed Hume's misinterpretation of Berkeley's 'spirit
substance ' and the subsequent disintegration of the self into ab-
stract sensations. By Kant the self was to be rediscovered,
although the foreign ' Somewhat ' against which Berkeley so vigor-
ously contended reappeared in the guise of a dins^-an-sich, thus oc-
— 55 —
casioning the transformation of the self from an ontological into
hfs fe'" ;'T"'i ""^•^^- ^''^''''^ ^^ ^^^ ^^her hand! who bj
his less critical and easier method, had seized upon Locke's com^
from?hr'"1r ' """'' '^ ^^^^"^^"S ^^^ -^P^ -' its act vity
from the small sphere to which the latter had confined it, viz ideas
of reflection, gradually transforms it into the self, which by par
ticipation in the Infinite Self, or God, is constitutive o the rela-
tions that are througout implied in all phenomenal objects
I' At the first thought it seems altogether incongruous ard un-
SsUhv"'"'' ""'"' '^'^^ ^^^^^^^^^^^ with Berkeley a^fd his
pniiosopny . and yet the two are more nearly con
nected than at first sight would seem to be possible, not merdv by"
their historic connection through Hume under the law of acdon
and reaction but by the problem with which both grappted so
earnestly, although their solutions vary so widely, w! fin It e^
m certain particulars nearer than we should at first have suspected
J he matter which Berkeley so passionately rejects while he mis
the sensations which are all we know, is, as he conceives t, no
greatly unlike the Ding-an-sich which Kant so pertinacioush.
gnores while he accepts the phenomena, which somehow he holds
TdL. .1 l'^''/'"''^''^^- ^he time and space which Kant acknowl-
edges as the forms and only as the forms of our direct knowledge
af^rmed or presumed-of sense experiences by an a priori neces
sity are accepted by Berkeley as a priori relations, because neces-
sarily involved in the continued activity of God. Kant's cate4-
nes of our generalized thinking are matched by Berkeley's original
notions of relations between ideas which are discerned Ind
bSd as r'^"-'^ 'u' "^"'- ^^^^ ^^^-' ^^— ' which Kant
beheld as shivering ghosts through the midst of his timid scepti-
cism, and which he was forced to recognize as real by a faith which
cosmo ThJ ''' — -ake-believe-of God, the'soul, and he
cosmos, -these were to Berkeley the pillars and foundation of his
t'obS^nr'^H ,^^^^^^^,-^fi-^^ -^ conscience the command
to believe in God, because God is needed as a chief of police for
and enforcer of duty, because duty is the voice of reason and
goodness, which are but other names for the thoughts and actings
We have endeavored to show that the self of Berkeley is but
as "nl'atfvr'r.' ''. ^"^ '^^^^"^ "^^^ ^^^ ^^^^-^ ^^ -^stance
as indicative of his deeper thought or last word about the matter
™'SXr'h'' '??^^ ''' T'^'^'y "^ ^ substance, ^ and his
Zes!TeZ^f -^ 'V inadequate concept by which to ex-
Th.rVv, ' ^P-^f '"^ ^ ^^'"^ passages in his Commonplace Book,
sense ".Z^"' "^!^\^^^^^^^ '^ ^^e objective source of ideas of
sense, 'there is a being which wills these perceptions in us," to
— oQ —
which he adds: " It should be said, nothing but a Will — a dang
which wills being unintelligible."^ T.ikewise he seems to disallow
the hypostalization of Will or Understanding, either as modes of
a substance, or as faculties in abstraction from the self of which
they are different forms of manifestation: "I must not say that
will or understanding is all one, but that they are both abstract
ideas, i. e., none at all — they not being even ratione different from
the spirit, qua faculties, or active." ^ Again: Thought itself, or
thinking, is no idea. '^'Tis an act, i. e., volition, as contradistin-
guished to effects — the Will." '^ Further in his account of the per
ception of objects, Berkeley says, in a passage already noted in
another connection: '^when I speak of objects as existing in the
mind, or imprinted on the senses, I would not be understood in
the gross literal sense — as when bodies are said to exist in a place,
or a seal to make an impression on wax. My meaning is only that
the minds comprehends or perceives them.""^
On the whole it does not seem that he has much thought of
pressing the analogy of material substance upon his ' active prin-
ciple.' Although ideas, in so far as they are regarded apart from
the relating mind, are passive, and although as coming from a
source foreign to the finite mind, the latter is receptive with regard
to them; yet ideas in themselves, having no connexion or identity
with one another, have a meaning for the finite mind only in so far
as the latter possesses the relating activity which is necessary for
the interpretation of these significant signs into a rational lan-
guage. Thus the mind is not a mere tabula rasa, a substance- vehi-
cle for conveying into the empirical consciousness a world of
ready made perceptions; on the contrary, in so far as empirical
perception is present, there is implied the work of rational activ-
ity, without which experience would be impossible. The finite
mind can interpret the language of the Author of Nature only so
far as it possesses the capability of interpretation, i. e., as it shares
the rational activity which is at the heart of experience.
With respect to the identity of the finite mind or self, Berke-
ley is eminently unsuccessful, at least in his early philosophy.
The question thus appears to him in the '* Commonplace Book":
''Wherein consists the identity of persons? Not in actual con-
sciousness, for then I'm not the same person I was this day twelve-
months but while I think of what I did then. Not in potential,
for then all persons may be the same for aught I know." ^ Here
* "Life Letters and Unpublished Writings of Berkeley," p. 430.
'Fraser; ''Commonplace Book " in "Life, letters, etc.," p. 466.
' Ibid, p. 460.
*" Third Dialogue between Hylas and Philonious."
^Fraser; "Commonplace Book," in "Life, letters, etc.," p. 481.
«
— 57 —
he seems to rely solely upon memory as the bond of connection
between past and present states of consciousness; and °"s inlde
quacy as an explanation of any other than empir cal ident kv he
could have seen if he had but applied the principle of a socia
tional psychology which he himself set afoot
In the third dialogue between Hylas and Philonous he seems
VZ'T """f ^"''l^q"'^"' P'-o«dure with regard to the seTf
Hyla. says m reply to the long speech of Philonous which we have
quoted: ''Notwithstanding all you have said and in conse
aTste^m o/Zr" ^r'^'l '' ^'"""^ ^°"°^ *-' you are only
WorfsTre not tn h! 7 ^'1,''°"' ^"^ '"''^'^"^^ '« ^'Wort them^
words are not to be used without a meaning in sp/H/uJ/ su/>s/a«r^
aTthVoth^r'-.r^tll ""^h""; '"" °"^ '^ ^° be^explTde^u/::
as the other for "the murder of matter is the suicide of the mind "
L kder:a:s"',raf ""tT "' ''' Commonplace fU.ok, ir^whfch
Soul '-Ihfrh ii < ""^ existence of idea constitutes the
fo°"ows- < rtnow ,?"' '^°"g"'«^ of perceptions,' is answered as
lOiiows. 1 know or am conscious of my own bein.' and th^t r
myself am not my ideas, but somewhat else, a thinkin" actte
principle which perceives, knows, wills and operates aboli't id as
oundl-^h' 1 ' °T '"*' "^^ ^^""^ ""''' P"^-- both colors and
and s^3unda'n'd r,r "'"'''"^' P^'"'^'^'^' ^-'inct from color
and nert ideJl R . /""' '""'''"' ^""'' "" ""^"^^ ^^"^'^e things
and ineit ideas. But, I am not in like manner conscious of the
existence or essence of Matter.- Now from this statement that
the self IS an individual principle, distinct from ideas, an'T he pre
seems'thaTpi'r, '''' ' '''"i'^ '^ ^ '^""^"'^ °' perceptions,' t
seems hat Blakeley contemplated a distinction between an em oiri
:inc.^i; po\-n°tTci <:;?: ''''°"^' ^'^ ^'^^'— ^^ ^- ^- ^-g
whilJ"h^'' H^n"'"™°"P'''" v°°'' ^' '"'sards the persm as immortal,
means'heself'7n'>"'°''!,''"r '? ''^ ^°"'' '^^ "'^ch he evi.lenti;
means the self in ts individual or empirical aspect. Berkeley's
heory of personality is a later development of his philosoohv in
the progress of which he has come to place increasing "SaLce
upon the notion, rather than upon mere intuition. But i in his
TjKT7'Lr:if' '° '^'"'"^"'^^ clearly between fh^'ei'iric
wh U ren^ ^ongeries of perceptions, and the rational activity
which lenders possible an interpretation of the sign lan<.ua-e of
th'e ide'mitv of T "u'^'^y °' ^'"^ "'"^ '^ ^ tendency to ose
the Identity of the self m Universal Mind. He now verges upon
' "Third dialogne between Hylas and Philonous "
Z'rt"!.'','^?"""™'"'''" ^""^^ " L'*'^' '^"'='-''. «'<=•." p. 438.
Third dialogue between Hilas and Philonous "
— 58 —
mysticism, and draws largely from Neo-Platonic sources for his
conceptions. Jamblichus, he says, furnishes a doctrine that ''there
is a principle of the soul higher than nature, whereby we may be
raised to a union with the gods, and exempt ourselves from fate."^
" According to the Platonic philosophy, ens and untivi are the
same. And consequently our minds participate so far of existence
as they do of unity. But it should seem that personality is the
indivisible center of the soul or mind, which is a monad so far
forth as she is a person. Therefore Person is really that which
exists, inasmuch as it participates in the Divine unity:"''^ Again, he
says: '' Upon mature reflection, the person or mind, of all created
being, seemeth alone indivisible and to partake most of unity. Rut
sensible things are rather considered as one than truly so, they
being in a perpetual flux or succession ever differing and various.
Nevertheless, all things together must be considered as one uni-
verse, one by the connexion and order of its parts, which is the
work of mind, whose unit is, by Platonics, supposed a participa-
tion of the first r^ji'v."'^ "Aristotle himself, in his third book
of the Soul, saith it is the mind that maketh each thing to be one.
. . . How this is done Themistius is more particular, observing
that as being conferreth essence, the mind, by virtue of her sim-
plicity, conferreth simplicity upon compound beings. And, indeed,
it seemeth that the mind, so far forth as person, is individual.
Therein resembling the divine one by participation, and imparting
to other things what itself participates from above. This is agree-
able to the doctrine of the ancients; however the contrary opinion
of supposing number to be an original primary quality in things,
independent of the mind, may obtain among the moderns. ''*
Here Berkeley in his theory of personality relies upon the
concept of unity not only to exhibit the necessary dependence of
the finite upon the infinite mind, but also to differentiate the former
from the latter. "Number," he now says, in entire agreement
with his earlier philosophy, " is no object of sense :" " it is an act
of the mind. The same thing in a different conception is one or
many."' Unity he still regards as a creature of the mind, and
not something existing in things independent of the mind; yet it
is no longer as formerly an abstract idea, but a notion. And the
notions, as vve have seen, are in Siris identified with the archetpyes
or ideas of Reason, immanent in the phenomena of sense. The
latter, as Berkeley insists, are not to be regarded in one aspect
1*' Siris," § 272.
^Ibid, §346.
^I^id, § 350.
*Idid, § 356 and 357.
^ Ibid, §288.
%
-59--
*^°"t' ^""'u^ phenomenon is not merely the complex of sensations
which has been marked by one name, and so reputed as a Thine
The Ihing IS, in another aspect, as (he presenied object of con-
sciousness, an irreducible fact; it must finally be referred to its
causal source and receive its ultimate explanation in objective
Universal Mind. The identity of the thing is not a meri ficti-
lous identity, for the unity «-hich the mind introduces into sensa-
tions has Its counterpart in an objective unity whose source is
Universal Mind. As the finite mind, in its explanation of phe-
nomena, precedes from synthesis to higher synthesis, by the redis-
covery m Iinje of the archetypal ideas or notions, it becomes
aware of the 'Divine unity ' in which it participates
But while /r;w« is really that which exists, inasmuch as it
participates in the Divine Unity, difference is not lost; for it is
also true that "the mind so far forth as person is individual"
lersonality is for Berkeley the most adequate category for the
complete explanation of experience, since the self not onlv ex-
presses the highest synthesis but, true to the empirical aspect of
things, ,t also expresses difference, as self distinguished from self
My experiences, he seems to say, must be referred to a hi-her
source than myself, and there is a cosmical order independent of
me; yet, in a very real sense also, these experiences are mine, and
I am not the mere theatre for the play of passing iihenomena
since in my ability to discern the unphenomenal character which
attaches to my experiences, in the significance which the arche-
typal Ideas have for me, my empirical self becomes, like my other
phenomenal experiences, the symbol of a higher personality
But there is another reason why Berkeley, in his final account
Honof?h K • w-'f '° ^^°'^' '■^J^='^=' cov^^Mx^ identifica-
tion of the self wHh (.od. We have seen that in his early philos-
ophy Berkeley s conception of God seems unmistakably to be of
the de.sfc cast. The arbitrariness of the divime nature language
IS chiefly put forward; (Jod is seemingly regarded as an extraneous
power working effects in us. But the interpretability of this lan-
guage rests for us upon the i)resuppositioi, of a necessary unity of
he finite wuh the .Absolute Mind or Reason. "Siris" is the explica-
tion of this, and the universals of Reason which formerly received
such brief recognition are the means whereby we arrive at the
knowledge of an objective order of things, which as the deeper
meaning IS the completion as well as the ground of Berkeley's ear-
lier Idealism. With his increasing gnosticism, his growing confi-
dence m the universals of Reason, Herkeley is apparentfv more
" WlT'! "^l'^''^ T'"^',' '" ^"■''='"«s cannot be calle.l theistic.
U he her the ...o-, be abstracted from the sensible world, and con-
sidered by Itself as distinct from and presiding over the created
system; or whether the whole Universe, including mind, together
— 60 —
with the mundane body, is conceived to be God, and the creatures
to be partial manifestations of the Divine essence — there is no
Atheism in either case, whatever misconception there may be; so
long as Mind or Intellect is understood to preside over, govern
and conduct the whole frame of things."'
As we have elsewhere seen, the immanence of the divine Rea-
son in the world of sense is the view which is now favored by
Berkeley; but it is not maintained to the exclusion of the theistic
view which dominated his early idealism: and in this he avoids
the pantheism towards which he seems tending and the complete
resolution of the self into an Absolute Reason." It is true that
his theistic utterances are no longer dogmatic assertions as for-
merly. The limitation of that finite knowledge which would grasp
the infinite is now more clearly recognized. The theistic concep-
tion of (lod comes as the deeper insight into the ever present cre-
ative Reason which informs and maintains the world. It comes as
a conviction that as man in his rational activity is made aware of
a higher rational self which is the completion of the finite and the
presupposition of our knowledge of a world, so may this higher
self be more completely known by conceiving it in analogy with
the total nature of man. As in Berkeley's idealism, and more
expressly in the later form which it takes in " Siris," Reasoii is not
to be absolutely divorced from sense, so neither is Will a faculty
distinct from Reason. Not Reason alone, but Reason and Will,
as different expressions of man's spiritual activity, constitute his
inner self.
In the third dialogue between Hylas and Philonous we have
already seen Berkeley's statement that God is to be known only by
reflecting upon the self, ''by heightening its powers and removing
its imperfections." In "Alciphron, the Minute Philosoi)her," the
question of the legitimacy of this process comes up. The inade-
quacy of finite categories is recognized, while predication by
means of them is nevertheless defended by reverting to the schol-
astic argument that they are applied "by way of eminence and
not by way of defect."*
The theistic view, which he thus but poorly maintains as
against i)antheism, is perhai)s furnished with a more rational basis
if one reads it in connection with his later utterances with respect
to the notion, and the function which we found must be assigned
1 ' -Siris," § 326.
-^Cf. "Siris, ' §276, 287.
3 '' La larj^e tolerance de B,Mkeley n'excommunie pas le pantheism, hien
qu'elle affirme que le funds de letre, en Dicu coniine en nous, est I'lndivisible
unite de la personnc." L. Carrau: "La phihjsophie reli^icuse en Angleterre; "
I'aiis, iSSS, J), 27.
*" Divine Visual Language," § 19.
I
— 61 —
to it in the constitution of experience. Viewed in this light, man's
knowledge of God is but the farther extension of his knowledge
of the phenomenal order. In the phenomenal world of Berkeley
we are not cut off from a world of noumenal existence, for in the
sense-material which is subjected to the unifying work of finite
conceptions there is nothing foreign to Reason. In the generali-
zations of science, by means of which is made possible for us an
orderly and connected world of experience, nay even in perception
Itself, we are already transcending the merely phenomenal. Finally
in the highest completed synthesis, the Divine Reason, we have
merely the last step which gives meaning to the whole. Man shares
in the Universal Reason, and it is only by his participation in this
Reason that he is enabled to take cognizance of this Unity which
is the truest explanation of himself and of the world in which he
lives. But m man Reason and Will are equally fundamental, alike
universal expressions of his experience of himself, and together
they constitute his personality. In his conception of God Berke-
ley refuses to be be content with mere Reason as the final explana-
tion of things. Reason, as so conceived, is scarcely differentiated
from Fate, while the Reason it is Berkeley's purpose to discover is
a purposeful activity, directed toward the Supreme Good; it is as
he tells us, Will which is ''conducted and applied by intellect "
The Divine arbitrariness is still retained: God is Divine Will di-
rected by Divine Reason. Although in that Reason the finite is
now seen to participate, the key to the knowledge of God is not
only the rational, but the moral implication contained in man's
knowledge of himself.
^ Siris, § 254.
—63—
CHAPTER IV.
The relations which obtain either by way of agreement or
contrast bet«-een the earlier and later phases of Berkeley" "leaT
r^hTfh '','''" ""r '^''hibited somewhat in detaTl wUh e pect"
that third class of existences, denominated by Berkeley snirit,
may now be briefly summarized ^^erKeiey, spirits,
y) tne sensation, (2) the phenomenal object, which is in on^
aspect a mere complex of sensations, and which in another asoert
remains an objective datum of consciousness, ultiL^rexplafned
SdT?raron°''\f^"f^'}:!,"'^°^^'-^^ (3) thL7c£y"e
his in:Lance u;on the bW fvf c TaSr 0I T^''''' '^'^'^'^'^
in the later philosophy of "^ris'-tht, P^*^"°"'^"^' ^^^ile
brought to hA by mSsIf tht -'mman: ^ imS: idtT^^h^oi^
existence had n the '' Prinrinlpc ^' o f •. ^^^^^\^^ icieas, whose
former possesses the capability of rationally interpretinrthe sens
Divine' u'n T'"' ^''T''"^ '''^'''' "P°" ^^^ cau^aTact v y of
1^ r. < n 1 -'^S^'";,'" the " Principles of Human Knowledge" and
he t th"t r^h n"""'''? 'r''''''' ^■""■^ acknowledtmen o
'kU'rSerthn ?.''"."' °^^'''' ^°' ''^'''^ ^' prefers the term
. h ^ ^ u ^ f" """S' ''^^^ "Ot a merely subjective existence
out of %i; ', "^r""" '' '^ meaningless if J attempt to concdvett
kno^Wed 'mlToTth^is'^"'^ ''""' consciousness. H^is sufficien; c
Kiiowieagment ot this is, however, in this earlv nhase of hi<. iHp.i
ism, unsupported otherwise than by citin.. the fact ihL J ;
t
«
^
established in so simple a way. Accordingly, in "Alciphron/ ' the
objective imi)lications of the phenomenal object are made more
expressly the subject of study, which results in the discovery that
any perception is not merely the sum of particular sensations, but
that, on the contrary, in order to the recognition of any perceived
object, there is involved the work of unconscious rational infer-
ence. ' A few sensations serve as signs by which we are led to expect
other unperceived sensations, provided certain conditions be ful-
filled. These present sensations are nothing of themselves, but
only as they are signs of relations whose permanence and objectivity
are due to the constitutive universals of Supreme Mind." Imme-
diate perception is thus seen to imply mediation; and ''faith in
an established, objective order of association between the two kinds
of sense phenomena (visual and tactual) is the basis of the con-
structive activity of intellect in all inductive interpretation of sensi-
ble things."' Berkeley's association of ideas is, as Fraser points
out,* not merely subjective but objective, although his ])osition of
objective association is not reached critically; it is, says Phaser, his
"religious faith in the constancy of the divine constitution of' the
cosmos." "Objective association originates the notions of sensa-
tions as significant signs, and belief in the invariableness of the
relations of which they are significant." Subjective association, on
the other hand, "helps us to recollect the meaning of each partic-
ular sensation and connect the signs with their significance in our
imagination."^
In the latest phase of his idealism, represented by " Siris," we
have seen that the 'judgment of suggestion' ripens into the explicit
recognition of universals of Reason, or the constitutive notions,
imminent in sense. The legitimacy of Berkeley's final resort to
the notion, of which he makes such important use in establishim,^ a
more consistent foundation for his early idealism, was found in the
fact that his early nominalism was directed merely against the
hypostatization of conceptions in abstract separation from mind as
percipient, while a more concrete universal was admitted by him
even in his early theory, although its function in the constitution
of experience was but imperfectly conceived.
Finally, our consideration of Berkeley's third class of exist-
ences, viz: Spirits, revealed that, corresponding to Berkeley's
growing insight into the nature of the phenomenal object, there
iCf. Wenley; "British Thought and Modern Speculation," p. 140 of Scot-
tish Rev., vol. 19.
'^ Fraser; " Philosophy of Berkeley."
3 Ibid, p. 395.
* Fraser; "Philosophy of Berkeley" in "Life, Letters and Unpublished
Wntins^s," p. 304.
* Ibid, p. 404.
—64—
also emerges a theory of the self and God which is more consistent
with the rationalism that is implicitly the basis of his theory of the
world. That the world is to be regarded as my individual repre-
sentation, had never been maintained by Berkeley, as some would
have us believe. Its ultimate dependence upon Divine, rational
will had been affirmed at the outset, the guarantee for its indepen-
dence of me consisting in the very fact of Berkeley's insistence
that perception and conception should not be thought to exist in
absolute separation from one another. The particular is indeed
the conscious datum to which introspective analysis of the pheno-
menal object conducts us; but the conceptual existence of the
latter is as much a basal fact of consciousness as the particulars by
means of which it translates itself into the concrete perceptual ex-
perience of individual minds. Accordingly the early theory,which
tells us that particular sensations are merely the signs by which we
are enabled to interpret the rational language of a supreme Author
of x\ature, becomes, by means of the later development of the
notion, the obverse of Berkeley's rationalistic philosophy, in which
we are led to see that the relations which subsist between pheno
mena, in the organic system of human experience, are not mere
subjective fictions, but objective relations, discoverable by us, be-
cause of the essential unity which obtains between the finite' and
the Universal Mind, upon which these relations ultimately depend.
Vet, as we have seen, in this unity of the self with God to
which he finally conducts us in Siris, difference is not mei-ed in
mere identity. The world is also in a sense the representation of
the finite self, not because of the mere fact that man is a percipient
organism, but rather because of that very unitv which obtains be-
tween the finite and the infinite in virtue 'of which man possesses
an 'imperishable personality all his own',' sharing, as he does in
the universal constitutive ideas. Through man, by means of these
universals, the world is constituted, and is representative alike of
an eternal or timeless order of things subsisting in the mind of
God, though also of the subjective interpretation which man puts
upon his experience. From this subjectivity, man, by voluntary
willingness of insight into the eternal order, seeks to free himself
and thus reconstitute the world in the likeness of God. Thus the
early doctrine that nature is in its totality an interpretable system
dependent upon a Power that is not ourselves, seems borne out in
Sins by his theory of the personality or 'spiritual individuality''-'
of man. '
It must, however, be kept in mind that the separate strands of
Berkeley's philosophy were never united in an organic whole. The
nVenley; " lintish Thought and Modern Speculation; " Scottish Rev., Vol
^9» P- 154-
• ^Fraser; '' Berkeley," p. 207.
Uv
— Ho—
manifold implications of the new point of view, consequent upon
his disposal of the fiction of abstract matter, were but imperfectly
conceived. The work of establishing an idealistic philosophy
which should take the place of i)revious materialistic theories was
only partially sketched, never definitely executed. Furthermore,
his philosophy was always in a state of transition, and accordingly
on^ cannot regard any particular phase of its development as an
adequate expression of Berkeley's complete thought about reality
Kmpincism, which is by far the dominant principle of his early
theorizing, long ago yielded up to more consistent systemati/ers
material valuable not alone for psychological method but for o-en-
eral scientific enquiry. On the other hand, the final ideaHstic
position which he reached in Siris was presented in too fragmentary
a form to be of abiding service to subsequent philosophy.
" Elle n' ctait yas fausse, mais incomplele " la S/ns n' est qu' un
devdoppement plein de grandeur de ce que nous ont rcvele les premieres oeuvres
l^erkeley est arrive au seuil de la vieillesse, il a iuilO jusqu' ici cntre ce quil croit
le nial et 1 erreur; nul polemiste via eie plus ardent, plus soupple, plus inlati^al.le;
il a poursuivi dans tons ses retrenchmenis snccessifs la niaiiere en s<.i: il a "refute
Lollins, .\ andeville, Shaftesbury, comhattu 1' elendue-substance de Descartes la
nionade de Leibniz, V attraction newtonienne et jusqu' un principe du calcul
infinitesimal; c est encore un sohiat de la verite qu' il est parti pour les Hermu.las.
Le voila dans sa retraite de Cloyne; sa philosophie, comme sa vie, a cesse d'etre
mihtante, il lit et medite, laisse sa pensee poursuivie son ascension de principe en
principe, jusqu a 1' Un suprC^ne; pen soucieux des objections et des preuves
s enchantant, sans trop s' interroger sur 1' authenticiie des tex-es. des echos de la
sagesse antique, ou il coit surprcndre comme le souffle affaibli d'une insniraii.m
sacree. C est ainsi que Platon, parvenu au bout de ses jours et au somm.t de son
genie, laisse a de plus jeunes les procedes de refutation, les armes de la dispute
et, ressuscitant les vieilles doctrines pour leur donner un plus beau sen^, expose
p us qu II ne demonire dans ses oeuvres magistrales et serenes, A- 7'ime, les Lois
Une critique exigeante pent les trailer de romans philosophiques, comme la Siris-
nous croyons qu elle aurait tort. Quand une grande intelligence a perse toute sa
vie ce qu elle a pense a le fin, en pleine poss.ssi.m d'elle-meme, et ce qui doit
nous inleresser le plus, et qui dans la mesure que les productions humaines en sont
capables, doit contenir le plus de ventc." 1
If, however, Berkeley cannot be regarded as a thorough-going
empiricist, nor yet as a consistent rationalist, the suggesliveness of
his theory as a whole should not on that account be minimized
His early theory, in which it is claimed that the existence of sen-
sible objects always involves a reference to percipient conscious-
ness, "denotes a faithfulness to experience "- that is not without
Its value, when corrected by the subsecjuent view that mere com-
plexes of sensations, actually present in the individual mind, do not
of themselves constitute the substantiality of the object, which is
also a conceptual unity.
^ But Berkeley's close identification of perception and concep-
tion has, because of the imperfect manner in which he explicates
f
h
iL. Carrau; La philosophie religieuse, pp. iS, 20.
2 Green; Philosophical Works, Vol. I, Intro, § 173.
—60—
Ihe rationalistic elements of in, j^lulosophy, been the occasion of
not a httle nusnnderstanding with 'regard 'to Ws true.t it^de toward
the phenomenal object, which he substitntes for the thin, i de
pen.lent of conscuusness. Thus Green, while ad.ni ,"»:. tl .t
' P>erkeley knew that pure theisnt (which he wished to es abl h
has no foundation nnless it can be shown that there is noU nl eal
apart fron, thonght," says that "he faile'- -"ce .ese
IZTT > "^^ ^' ''""'"y- ''"" ""'^ '^t° is^l^te the phrasfe,
... IS Avr/A. more particularly if the Avr,// be held to imply ex
c lusively the perception of a single in,lividnal through the medium
of his senses only [as Creen in the above passages seems to insisO
■ ■ . . '^ to eviscerate lierkeley."^' For "he does not declare
ne^s, since mere feeling present in any individual subjective con-
cousness apart from the objective con.litions which rende fee'big
nterpre.able is, on Berkeley's theorv, an abstraction no les abs , d
than abstract matter.* The rssr of things indeed implies A r.//et
not alone this but ...,v>, or .V,//,,v. Therefore to isolate the
former p rase IS not only to neglect the later realistic development
P ace of Eertel '°''''' "' '" ""^^'"'"'^ '-'" ""'•'S'"-' abstraction in
or^d nf 1 7 ' '°"""' P'''"-"^"''''^- ''lie substantiality of the
«or Id of e.xternal existence, as distinct from the images and fnncies
diub,:d"th "" "'-•?'•—-• - f- Berkeley a fact not to be
oubte.l. 1 he mere lieing^ and snbstantialitv of things is the least
that can be said about them, and the true question o i leallsm s
not does matter e.xist? since the materiality of the worhf can^o
mat' en'aUvorn'i ""'"':'■'" t "" """" ''^'^y''^ ''^' "-- '
material woild, i, e., what is the truth about matter?
1 he answer is, that from our thought of the existence of the
'Green; I'hihisophical \V.„k.c, V,,I. I, Imro '
nVenley; lintish Thought and .Modern Speculation, p. i.e.
"Ibid, p. I j4. ■ '^ "'■'
^ ^.;i'>aser; "Philosoph,. of Berkeley,- in Life, Letters, etc., of Berkeley,
r,
.\
\
— 67 —
material object we cannot abstract that very condition which
seems necessary to its being, viz., the condition that it shall be an
object for perceptual consciousness. But this does not mean that
its existence is entirely comprehended in my perception of the
object; that it is nothing apart from me; but only that perception
is a universal and necessary condition of the being of an object.
The two have, as it were, a kind of organic relation, and cannot
be separated. What is not/(?r consciousness, for the passive ex-
perience of perception, no less than what is not constituted by
thought, is a mere abstraction.
The view that the Berkelian idea is equivalent to mere feeling
involves a most ludicrous construction of Berkeley's theory of the
object not immediately present in perception. Does Berkeley
mean that, in turning my back upon the object, I thereby anni-
hilate it? In this respect at least, as Mr. Wenley has said, '*he
was not the fool his critics would have had him." For, in the
first place, even if the object has an existence only under the con-
dition of sense-perception; if that condition be not fulfilled, we
have yet no right to speak of the object being annihilated, for that
would mean that we first take the object apart from perceptual
consciousness, and then conceive its destruction. If the object
has an existence only in relation to some perceptual consciousness,
if it gets its meaning only as it is for a percipient subject, then in
the absence of its being perceived, we cannot say that the object
is tfes/r(?yetf a.nd again flashed back into existence when the condi-
tion of sense-perception is fulfilled; object would simply be rn^a/i-
ing/css apart from sense-perception.
However, this is to lay exclusive emphasis upon the percipi.
Upon Berkeley's principles, Fraser says,^ the thing may be taken
to exist, when we are absent from it, in percisely the same way
that the thing present to sense exists, i. e., in the one case as in
the other, actual sensations signify a conceivable object. The
immediate object being rationally constituted, Berkeley does not
mean that, in merely thinking of the object not present in my per-
ception, I by this means recreate it, but that, in my thought of the
object, I again recognize the universal conditions which now, as
at the time when the object was present to my perception, consti-
tute its independence of me. Does he not mean this in the fol-
lowing? ^'The trees are in the park, i. e., whether I will or no.
Let me but go thither and open my eyes by day, and I shall not
avoid seeing them."^ Or again, '^bodies do exist whether we
think of them or no, they being taken in a two-fold sense; (i) Col-
lections of thoughts, (2) Collections of powers to cause these
thoughts. These latter exist, though perhaps a parti rei it may be
1 Fraser; " Philosophy of Berkeley in Life Letters and Unpublished Writings,"
p. 332
'•'Commonplace Book, p. 474.
68 —
one simple perfect power'''— which, as we afterward learn, is
Supreme Mind.
Green, however, in considering the philosophical idealism of
Berkeley in its bearing upon science, says that ''if physical truths
imply permanent relations Berkeley's theory properly excludes
them."- Quoting section 58 of the Principles, he explains that
this passage meant for Berkeley that the motion of the earth would
begin as soon as^we were there to see it; while for us it means that
it is now going on as an established law of nature which may be
collected from the phenomena. This seems, however, to lay too
exclusive emphasis upon the accident of sense-perception. What
Berkeley means appears rather to be that the 'established rules of
nature' are certain permanent conditions of existence which the
mind in its conceptual activity is enabled to discover. Our belief
in these primary conditions is ultimately grounded upon our belief
in Supreme Rational Will, of which these laws or conditions are
the expression. Once discovered, I know that the phenomena,
which may be subsumed under these laws, actually occur in ac-
cordance with them. The earth moves whether I perceive it or
not, for in my thought of the motion of the earth, I recognize that
the accident of my individual perception is not involved in the ob-
jective conditions underlying my presumption that the earth moves.
Still the universal condition, under which the mind arrives at
a knowledge of the laws which subsist between phenomena, is that
of sense- i)erception. Conception is only an abstraction from the
concrete life of mind or spirit; we have only a relative universal as
likewise a relative particular; therefore mere relations or abstract
conditions of existence are not to be hypostatized and taken in
absolute separation from perceptual consciousness. This is the
logic of Berkeley's polemic against 'abstract ideas.' Accordingly
the motion of the earth, as also any phenomenal object not present
to my perception, must be regarded as being in a certain sense per-
ceived. Nor does this imply for Berkeley the idea of God as a
percipient being in a human and anthropomorphic sense, for
'God,' it is said in "Siris," 'has no sensory.'" Perception is finally
translated into a system of rational relations which are intuited
rather than perceived. The world is ultimately a rationally con-
stituted cosmos, whose intelligible relations are at once the crea-
tion and the object of Supreme Rational Will or Person. What-
ever difficulties attach to this view,— and they are doubtless many,
it at least avoids the extreme of the rationalistic view by refusing
to regard the ultimate unity, to which experience must be sub-
jected, as a mere system of relations apart from the concrete life of
conscious personality.
1 " Commonplace Book " in "Life, Letters," etc., p. 486.
"Green; Philosophical Works, Vol. I, Introduction,
'"Siris:" § 289.
/
\
BlBLlOCiRAPHV.
Berkeley, Geo.: A Nc7v Theory of Vision (1709), Prineiples u-
Human Knowledo;e ( 1710), Dialoi^^ues between Jlylas and Phil,
onous (17 13), The T/ieoiy of Vision further Vindicated and
Explained (1730), Alcephron or the Minute J'Jiilosopher (1732)/
Siris (1744), The Analyst (1733-34), Concerning Motion
(1721).
Fraser: Berkeley's IVorks (4 7'ols. Clarendon Press, London).
Sampson, Geo.: Berkeley's IVorks (3 vols., Geo. Bell and Sons,
London; vols. L and LL, 1898).
Bailey: A I^evieiv of Berkeley's 'Theory of Vision, designed to
show the Unsoundness of that Celebrated Sfeculatien {Westmin-
ster Review, Oct. 1842).
Baumaun, J. J. : Die Lehre von Raum, Zeit und Mathematik,
1869.
Baxter, Andrew: Lnc/uiry into the Nature of the Human Soul {2d
cd., Sec. entitled Dean Berkeley's Scheme against the existence
of Matter and a Material World examined and slunun incon-
clusive), pp. 256-344, V. Kraut h, Princ. of Human Kmm'lcdge.
Beasley: A Search of Truth, v. Kraut h, I^rinc. if LLuman Knond-
edire.
Be at tie, James: Essay on the Nature and Lm mutability cf Truth
(1770).
Boii'cn, Francis: Berkeley and his Philosophy {Cambrid^^e, Mass.,
1838).
Bradley, W. : Berkeley's Ldealism {Journal of Spec. Philos., voh\
XV-XVL, 18S1-1882).
Brockhaus: Real Encychp., Elfte. Aufl. Vol. LL, 1S64.
Bnmni, Thos. : Lectures on the Philos. of the Human Mind {4 vols.
Fdinh., 1820, Lectures XXVL and XXVIJ).
Bukle: Geschichte der neuern L^hilosophie, 1803 v. Kraut h Princ.
of LLuman Knowledi^e. "
Butherogge: Essay upon Reason and the Nature of Spirits (?'.
Krauth: Purine).
Butt, J. : Afternoon L.ectures on English Literature (1866).
Carrau, Ludovic: La philosophic rcligieuse en Augleterre (1888,
Paris, Art., Berkeley).
Collyns, Simon: Berkeley's Doctrine on the Nature of Matter,
{Journal cf Spec. Philos., 3-4, 1869-70), Berkeley, the New
Materialism, and the Diminution cf Light by Distance {Jour.
Spec. J^ hi I OS., vol. 15, 1881).
— 70 —
Simon- Collyns: On the Nature and Elements of the Materia/
Worlds,'' Hamilton versus Mile,'' Edinburgh, 1866), Is Thouo/it
the 7 hinkcr {Jour. Spec. Philos., Dec., \^(i()).
Cournry, IV. L.: Studies in Philosophy (1882 ).
Erdmann: Leibnitz und d. Entivickel d. Idealismus vor Kant (1842
in Gcs chic lite d. Philos).
Ee trier: Lectures and Philosophic Remains,
JuiLkenberg: History of Philosophy (trans, by A. C. Armstrong.
Jr., 1893).
Erederichs, Eriedrich: Der Phaenomcnale Ldealismus Berkelefs
und Kant's, cin kritisch-philosophische Abhaudlung {Berlin,
1 8 7 I ), Ueben Berkelefs L deal isms, Berlin, 1870).
Eraser, Alex. Campbell: Selections from Berkeley {Oxford, 1891),
Berkeley a Subjectivist {North British Rev., vol. XXXLV,
i86r).
Ifuxley, T. If.: Collected Essays VI, 1894.
Eaiceett, Ediaard Douglas: Berkeley to Hegel, Monist, Oct. 1896,
vol. VI f, pp. 41-81.
Hegel. Gesch. d. Philosophic {Michelit, Berlin, 1844).
Ifildcbrand: Propaedeutic der Philosophic { Lfcidclberg, 1819). *■"
Ifome, Henry: Elements of Criticism {ch. XXV), 1762.
Hume, David: Essays, etc., 1748.
Krug, Wilt. Traug.: Handwortcrbuch der philos. Wissenschaften.
Loeu'g, Th.: Der Idealismus Berkelefs {Sitsungberich der konig-
liche Akadanin der IViss., IVim).
McCosh, J.; Criteria of Truth {Locke's Theory of Knowledge
ivith a notice of Berkeley).
Meyer, Eugen: JJume's and Berkelefs Philosophic der Mathe-
m atik {/Idlle, \Svf^).
Mill, J. S.: Dissertations and Discussions {vol. J I, 1882).
Mrrris, G. S.: British Thought and Thinkers (iSSo).
Orange, H. IV. : Berkeley as a Moral Philosopher.
Porter, Noah: The Two Hundredth Birthday of Bishop Berkeley
{March 12, 18S5).
Reid, Thos.: Works {Hamilton, Edinb., 1^2-]), Intellectual Pow-
ers of Man.
Ritter: Geschichte der neuern Philosophic, 1853, vol. IV.
Robertson, Geo. Croom: Erase?-' s Berkeley, a criticism by Robert-
son ed. of Mind in vol. VI, 1881, p. 421.
Hazard, Rowland G.: Will, 1864, Causation, 1869. •
Green, T II. : Philos Works, vol. I.
Kraut h, Chas. P.: A Treatise concerning the Principles of Human
Knoiv ledge, with Prolegomena and collected opinions (1874).
Simion: Principles of Human Knoivledge, (1878).
Sell wegler : History of Ph ilosopli v.
f
— 71 —
Spieker Gideon: Kant, Hume und Berkeley, eine Kritik der Er-
kentuiss theone {Berlin, 1875).
'"'''"' w' K/f • \ ^''f""'- ^'■'''"■'^ Berkeley {Jour. Spec. Philos.
i'ot. vlfjan. 1873).
Stewart, Dugald: Elements of the Philosophy of the Human Mind
( 1792-1S27, ch. /), Works {Hamilton V, oo; // i8 in) v
Krauth, Princ. of Hum. Know. ' 9 • ^A i^ 19) -
^''"^Trauth SS '^' '^''''^''^'''' Philosophie (1797 vol. VI, v.
Pvler: Three Men of Letters (1895)
Ueberweg: Philosophische Bibliothek, 12, {Abhandluu^ren uber dit
Pruicipien der menschlichen erkentniss; ins Deutsche uberset-e
unci mit Amierkungen versehen von E. Ueberwc-r^s -> And
Leipzig 1879)^ . Trans, of Ueberweg^s notes into En^. Iv Chas.
/m ^-^T'- 'f^'"'^'' Knozv ledge), Gesch d' Philosoph-
len d Neuzeit Dritte Aufl., i8j2.
Vogel: Philosoph. Repetitorium, 1872
Webb, T E. : Veil of Isis (1885 )•
Windelband: History of Philosophy
Zinunermann^ Ueber Hume's Stclling zu Berkeley und Kant (1883).
Stirling, /. H: Philosophy and Theology, ^
^hlls^ Jr., E : Memoir of Geo. Berkeley { The Irish Nation).
Z'-'y-'r. ^'''''' ''f ^^^'^'tf'ious Irishmen {vol. V, pt. I, pp i-.n\
i^^enley R^ M.: British Thought and Modern SpeculJtion, Scot-
iish Rev. San. iSgz.
NoTK.__For detailed reference to Berkeley's comment
Krauth s -Principles of Human Knowled-e," throu^rh
much of the above bibliography has been obtained
tators V.
gh which
\
I . /
-.1
*i
I,.
I
Iff
t
'^«p
I
)
COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY LIBRARIti
0023398140
i
DUE DATE
— . — *"
^5f^MrW^
1
1
i
-^rrfrr-
i- r:- !
!
1
1
-
—— ■
* — ■ — - ""
Printed
in USA
I
-1*
ro
LTV
CO
it- i>