MASTER NEGA TIVE NO. 92-81148 MICROFILMED 1993 COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY LIBRARIES/NEW YORK as part of the "Foundations of Western Civilization Preservation Project" Funded by the NATIONAL ENDOWMENT FOR THE HUMANITIES Reproductions may not be made without permission from Columbia University Library COPYRIGHT STATEMENT The copyright law of the United States - Title 17, United States Code - concerns the making of photocopies or other reproductions of copyrighted material. Under certain conditions specified In the law, libraries and archives are authorized to furnish a photocopy or other reproduction. One of these specified conditions Is that the photocopy or other reproduction is not to be "used for any purpose other than private study, scholarship, or research." If a user makes a request for, or later uses, a photocopy or reproduction for purposes In excess of "fair use," that user may be liable for copyright infringement. This institution reserves the right to refuse to accept a copy order If, In Its judgement, fulfillment of the order would involve violation of the copyright law. A UTHOR : ELLIS, ALEXANDER J. TITLE: LOGIC FOR CHILDREN PLACE: LONDON DA TE : 1882 COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY LIBRARIES PRESERVATION DEPARTMENT DIDLIOGRAPHIC MICROrORM TARCKT Master Negative # Original Material as Filmed - Existing Bibliograpliic Record Restrictions on Use: ^. « .Mj f » W» . ■ ■ I I * n ■>.. -- / ■ ■ p t imif p I 9iYid mduic;hV?...lv/o 5iJclY6sse.s''TQ kacne.YSM, L OTH d oiadftTn MVL, Q. 94. 1024(]0 F- » i. m- tmcMii i FILM SIZE: 55^ Z^£it2:^ TECHNICAL MICROFORM DATA REDUCTION RATIO: //^_ IMA^E PLACEMENT: lA ^ IB IIB DAfE FILMED:__3r:>n^_'^ INITIALS n.M FILMED BY: RESEARCH PUBLICATIONS. INC WOODBRinnF CT c Association for information and image iManagement 1100 Wayne Avenue, Suite 1100 Silver Spring. Maryland 20910 301/587-8202 Centimeter 12 3 4 im ITT Inches TTT 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 mm liiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiihiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiL fm T^ I I I ^ I I I I I fl 1.0 Ui 2.8 y. — ^ ||ai ■ 63 ■ 80 in 1^ 1.4 2.5 22 I.I 2.0 1.8 1.6 1.25 rTTTT TTT ■h+i MfiNUFfiCTURED TO fillM STflNDflRDS BY fiPPLIED IMRGE. INC. ?lwt ■' «^m d --^ c?- c/ 1(3 ^:i^^ 4** kir^' ^'.i^'^. fe r-r- ifV ^^ w^ 1 >«|. ^ iSr ^ -.-^•».i ,'^^* v' * V^i tAi bt l^^j ^«s^:> •l^' !*• X*: ,> >•-< .■•*; ">,*' J IS. - ii v^^.:j4;t^ f*,«i ^^^ ,^1 i-wV M ll' iW '3 \U l\5 Coltttnttiit dvcHeae in the (Citii cf |lcw DorU ramV i (A ■ i^ I Y. I COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY LIBRARIES This book is due on the date indicated below or at tho 1™,°,:/,,' 'f ""^ ''""' ^^t- *he date of Cowing as provided by the rules of the Library or by s Dedal af' rangement with the Librarian in charge DATE BORROWED DATE DUE DATE BORROWED DATE DUE ^. .^ "■^ s; C2a(ll40)M100 ^ii^^' \1 LOGIC FOE CHILDREN, DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE. BEING THE SUBSTANCE OF TWO ADDRESSES TO TEACHERS DELIVERED BEEORE THE COLLEGE OF PRECEPTORS. ENTITLED I J. ON A METHOD OF TEACHING DEDUCTIVE OR FORMAL LOGIC TO CHILDREN BY MEANS OF WORDS AND COUNTERS, 8 May, 1872. 2. ON SCHOOL INDUCTIONS, 12 Feb., 1873. -/. ,\ BY ALEXANDEE J. ELLIS, P.R.S., F.S.A., F.C.P.S., F.C.P., PRESIPKNT (for THE SECOND TIME) OF THE PHILOLOGICAL SOCIETY, MEMBER OF THE MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY, FORMERLY A VICE-PRESIDENT OF THE COLLEGE OF PRECEPTORS, AND FORMERLY SCHOLAR OF TRINITY COLLEGE, CAMBRIDGE, B.A. 1837. The Jirst lecture reprinted from the Educational Times for June, July, and August^ 1872 ; the second from the same for March^ April, and May, 1873 ; both with numerous additions. Printed off in 1872 and 1873, and Published in 1882. Ii ' i /( LONDON: C. F. HODGSON & SON, 1, GOUGH SQUARE, ^FLEET STREET. Price Two Shillings,* tit LOGIC FOE CHILDTIEN, . DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE. BEINO THE SUBSTANCE OF TWO ADDRESSES TO TEACHERS DELIVERED BEFORE THE COLLEGE OF PRECEPTORS. ENTITLED I 1. ON A METHOD OF TEACHIN-O DEDUCTIVE OR FORMAL LOGIC TO CHILDREN BY MEANS OF WORDS AND COUNTERS, 8 May, 1872. 2. ON SCHOOL INDUCTIONS, 12 Feb., 1873. BY ALEXANDER J. ELLIS, F.R.S., F.S.A.. F.C.P.S., F.C.P., ' PEKSIPENT (FOR THE SECOVn TIME) OF TITE PniLOLOf^rrCAL SOCIETY. MEMBER OP TUB MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY, FORMERLY A VICE-PRESIDENT OF THE COLLEGE OF PRECEPTORS, AND F 'RMERLY SCHOLAR OF TRINITY COLLLGE, CAMBRIDGE, B.A. 1837. The first lecture reprinted from the Educational Times for June, July, and August, 1872 ; the second from the same for March, April, and May, 1873 j both with numerous additions. Printed off in 1872 ani> 1873, and Published in 1882. LONDON: C. F. HODGSON & SON, 1, GOUGH SQUARE, FLEET STllEET, • • • • • • • ••• •• • • • #, ••• •. • • • • • ••• ••••• • • • • • •• • • •• • •• • • • •.••• • • • •••••• f ^ \ i w ^ « ^ CO CD \ ^ • t ' ' • , , • J » • • o NOTICE. B I 1 ' • ' v. > • * , : ) a » i • • These pages are for Teachers only, or for Adult Students. Ihey should on no account be put into the hands of children Their object is to shew Teachers who have studied other works (as those cited on p. 46, note 6, to which I would now add : W. Stanley Jevons, Studies in Deductive Logic, a Manual tor Students. Macmillan, 1880, pp. 304) how to teach Deduc- tive Logic with the greatest amount of simplicity, combined with scientific accuracy, and to instil the principles of In- ductive Logic into the minds of the youngest children. The notes are for the further guidance of teachers or others who wish to pursae the study for themselves. The Deductive Logic was printed off in 1872, and has re- mained untouched ever since. In 1873 an Appendix on some points of Higher Deductive Logic, applying my methods to' everything in De Morgan's and Boole's works, was written and the delay in publication arose from an intention to revise this Appendix. But so much has since appeared on the sub- ject which ought to be included, that the idea of printing such an Appendix has been definitively abandoned, and the tract IS published as it stood in 1872. It is believed that the exemplifications by the vowels in words, notation, diagrams and working of the syllogism, here explained, are original, while they appear to be the simplest and most complete hitherto proposed. In the abandoned Appendix it was shewn that the same methods were applicable for the solution of the highest logical problems. The Inductive Logic, printed in 1873, was published sepa- rately in that year, with some slight alterations, under the title " On School Inductions, or how to familiarise school children with the principles of Inductive Logic." It now appears as it was originally written. ALEX. J. ELLIS. 25, Argyll Road, Kensington, London, W. ■Aj>n/, 1882. *>• • It •■ a •• fr A • • '\ ERRATA. p. 12, line last, diagram (2), for ay i° the left-hand square, read ^p. p. o3,linel,/or:,(;r.y, x.!/) read t,{x.Y, x.y). p. 91, foot-note, last lines of paragraphs 10, 11, and 12, for p. 26 .cad p. 86 ; and last line of paragraph 14, for p. 24 read p. 84. To prevent trouhle, the Reader is requested to correct these trifling, but very confusing, errors before reading the pages in question. A. J. E. I CONTENTS. Part L— DEDUCTIVE LOGIC. ART. 1. Goethe on Logic, p. 5. 2. Necessity of Logic for Children, p. 5. 3. The Old Logic unsuitable for Children, p. 6. 4. The Problem of Deductive Logic, p. 7. 5. The Value of Deductive Logic, p. 7. 6. The Laws of Attributes, p. 7. 7. Sorting words for one vowel. General condition that the same vowel does not occur in all the words sorted, p. 8. 8. Sorting words for a second vowel, p. 9. 9. The 4 sets resulting from the double sorting, p. 9. 10. Compounds and Counters, p. 9. 11. Effect of one sot being absent. Expression of presence, absence, and doubt, with Counters, p. 10. 12. Expression for the presence, absence, doubt, and limitation of doubt in writing, p. 11. 13. The 7 complete Assertions or possible arrangements of the 4 sets of Art. 8, p. 13. 14. The 8 usual arrangements (or In- complete Assertions), p. 14. 15. Inconsistency, p. 17. 16. The transition to ordinary propo- sitions purposely delayed, p. 18. 17. The 8 sets arising from sorting for 3 vowels, p. 19. 18. Effect of the sorting by two vowels on the sorting by three — or of assertions respecting two vowels on conditions respecting three, p. 19. 19. From the sorting with respect to three vowels to determine the effect of sorting with respect to any two, p. 20. 20. AVlienihe general condition (Art. 7) is not fulfilled. Singu]arity,p. 2 1 . ART. 21. 22. 23. 24 25. 26. 27. 28. 29. 30. 31. 32. 33. 34. 35. 36. 37. 38. Syllogisms, their nature and solu- tion, p. 21. First kind of Syllogism, p. 22. Its eight cases, and skeleton rule for the same, p. 24. Second kind of Syllogism, p. 25. Its eight cases, and skeleton rule for the same, p. 26. Third kind of Syllogism, and the use of Indices in the case of numerous limitates, p, 26. Its sixteen cases, and skeleton rule for the same. p. 27. Syllogisms with doubtful con- clusions, p. 28. Skeleton rules for the thirty- two cases of syllogisms already con- sidered, p. 29. The eleven Syllogisms of the Old Logic explained, with foot-note on the actual 676 possible syllogisms, p. 29. Use of the skeleton rules in solving complex syllogisms, with com- pleteas8ertionsaspremi8ses,p.32. Use of the skeleton rules in solving enthymemes, p. 33. Use of the skeleton rules for finding all the syllogisms with a given conclusion andgivenmean, p. 33. Use of the skeleton rules to deter- mine whether any syllogism is erroneous, p. 33. A conclusion not disproved by shewing that either or both of the premisses is or are false, p. 35. Opponent syllogisms, p. 34. The conclusion combined with one premiss gives a new conclusion consistent with, not the same as, the other premiss, p. 34. Given the resultant, to find pre- misses and the conclusion and other conclusions also, p. 35. IV ART, 39. 40. 41. 42. 43. 44. 45. 46. 47. 48. 49. 60. 61. 62. CONTENTS. Written form for contrasting cases of syllogisms, p. 36. Transition, from dealing with vowels of words, to dealing with attributes of objects, p. 37. Transition to ordinary propositions p. 38. Connotation and Denotation, p. 39. Analysis of assertions, with a note on Sir William Hamilton's, p. 39. Diversity of ordinary expressions for the same assertion, with note on Subject, Copula, and Pre- dicate, p. 43. Definitions, p. 45. Disjunctive Assertions, p. 46. Elementary Text Books to supple- ment this lecture, note, p. 46. Other kinds of assertion, p. 47. Assertions on the consistency of other assertions, p. 48. Notation and Counters for these assertions, p. 49. Inconsistent assertions, p. 49. Unicates, p. 50. ART. 53. 54. 55. 56. 57. 58. 59. 60. 61. 62. 63, 68. 69. 70. Complexes, p. 50. Sets of Complexes, p. 51. Complexes of three truths, p. 51. If one complex is present in a set, all the rest are absent, p. 51. If several complexes form a unicate, all the rest are absent, p. 51. If several complexes are absent, all the rest form a unicate, p. 52. Study of the eflfect of one or more absent complexes from a set of four, p. 52. Ex Absurdo proof, p. 53. Study of eflfect of absent complexes in sets of three or four truths, p. 53. Method of solving problems, p. 54. 64, 65, 66, 67. Examples of di- lemmas from Fowler, pp. 55, 66. Ambiguities, story of Eualthus and Protagoras newly completed, with a Moral, p. 56. Abridgements, p. 58. Conclusion, with note on the character of the Old Logic, p. 58. Part II.— INDUCTIVE LOGIC. ART. ART. 71 . Reasons for adding this Part, p. 61. 72. Inductive Logic deals with the Formation of Assertions which are taken for granted in Deduc- tive Logic, p. 61. 73. Object of this Part, to show Teach- ers how to put children on the right track, p. 62. 74. Limitation to Verifiabilities, pp. 63-66. 75. The Object of Inductive Processes is from the Known Past and Present to predict the Unknown Future, p. 66. 76. Inductive Reasoning is Regulated Guessing, p. 67. 77. Its Basis is the assumed Uniformity of Nature, p. 68. 78. Mode of directing a child to feel that Relations are fixed, and Conditions variable, p. 70. 79. Explanations and Illustrations of the words: — ^i. Law, p. 71; ii. Chance and Averages, p. 73; iii. Restraint, p. 75; iv. Cause and Eflfect, p. 76 ; v. Empirical Laws, p. 77 ; vi. Popular Reason Why, p. 78; vii. Scientific Reason Why, p. 79 ; viii. Nature, p. 81. 80. Phenomena, Noumena, Observa- tion, Experiment, Test of Authority, Classification, pp. 82-85. 81. Canons of Induction, Plurality of Causes, Three General Laws, Analogy, pp. 85-87. 82. Inductive Methods, — i. of Agree- ment, p. 87 ; ii. of Diflference, p. 87 ; iii. of Concomitant Variations, p. 88 ; iv. of Residues, p. 88. 83. The two Main Principles to be taught to children, p. 89, with foot-note on Comte's Fifteen Laws of Primary Philosophy, p. 90. 84. How children are to be led to form Inductions, p. 91. 85. Suggested Scholastic Processes in- vohdng — i.AccurateObservation, p. 92 ; ii. Invariable Sequences, p. 92 ; iii. Accidents, p. 93 ; iv. Inquiries, p. 93 ; v. Induction, pp. 93-^94 ; Conclusion, p. 94. ••• ,•• -• 0-' i ' • . • • i * LOGIC FOE CHILDEEN. 1. Goethe, in that biting satire upon University studies, to which he ffives the shape of advice from Mephistopheles to a btudent, makes his fiend say :-" My dear friend, I advise you, first of all, to attend a course of logic. There your mind will be properly drilled, and laced up in the tightest of boots, so that it may hence- forth slink more circumspectly along the path of thought, and not perchance will-o'-the-wisp-it hither and thither, through thick and thin. Then you'll be taught for many a day, that what you ve been in the habit of doing in a moment, as easy as eating and drink- ing, must have its One ! Two ! Three ! To be sure, the manufacture of thought is like a masterpiece of weaving, where one treadle moves a thousand threads. The shuttles fly hither and thither, the threads flow unseen, a single stroke strikes a thousand combi- nations. Your philosopher comes up, and proves to you that it can't help being so. * The first was so, the second so, and hence the third and fourth were so ; and if the first and second had not been there, the third and fourth would have never come to pass. The students go into ecstacies over his explanation,— but none ot them have become weavers." 2. Now this is very wittily and pungently expressed, and the truth at the bottom of it all is incontestable. Thinking by rule will not make an original thinker. But then, however original a thinker may be, he can only think according to rule, for the rule is merely the register of the processes actually followed by original thinkers. We don't expect, and we don't desire, every human being born into the world to have the insight of a Cxoethe — not to mention an Aristotle, who, himself the towering mind of his day, first bethought himself of the advantage that would accrue trom accurately stating the processes and laws of reasoning. But eveiy one of us, from the grandson to the grandsire, has to go through small processes of reasoning every hour of his life, ^very one of us, every time he speaks, has to make an assertion. He seldom does speak without making several assertions, which m some way modify and limit one another. And in point of fact, many ot us are often apt to make assertions without knowing precisely what B » » * 1 ' * » • • • i^ . i 6 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. [arts. 2, 3. ^^ecch cf theiQ meais separately, and still more often without know- ing how they limit previous assertions, or even how to find out the e'ifent^of liyiita'tibn. Hence we are all prone to make blunders, -,- some^ya^ips simply ridiculous, often mortifying, and not unfre- quently entailing other disagreeable consequences. Now if there aie.a; Vew simple and general considerations which will help us out . of this difficulty, should we grudge the labour of mastering them ? To say that when reasoners have thought out processes of reason- ing, they should not be studied by those who wish to reason, seems about as wise as to say that because people can make themselves understood by picking up so much of a language as strikes their ear, they should not make use of a grammar and a dictionary, or that because all the rules of composition will never make a poet, no simple-minded soul who wishes to convey his thoughts intel- ligibly, and flounders awfully in the attempt, should avail himself of rules of composition. 3. Now, the College of Preceptors seems to have plainly stated its own opinion, by making a certain (albeit very small) amount of logical knowledge indispensable for passing their diploma exami- nations ; and though their main thought was to guide the teacher himself in the application of methods of teaching, yet there must necessarily have been a secondary object in view referring to the matters taught. Clearly, of all others, children should be led to comprehend the expression of thought, and hence teachers should be put into a condition to train them. Of course, no one supposes that the barbarous terminology and unwieldy processes of scholastic logic, which seem very like sledge-hammers for killing flies, should be presented to the mind of a child, already so much overburdened with the pedantry of grammar. But are these necessary ? Do we require more distinctions than objects distinguished ? more classes than things classified ? a dozen sesquipedalian words to express a single simple notion ? difficult and subtle discriminations, in which the difficulty and subtlety mainly arise from viewing but half the battle ? This is what shocks one in the old logic, which school- men have petted into a monster. 'Tis well that in recent times, so recent that they are within the experience of many here present, two s^reat thinkers, whose loss we have had recently to deplore. Dr. Boole and Professor De Morgan, have shown us a way out of this muddle. It is from these two writers principally that 1 have drawn the materials for my own view of the real scope of so-called deductive logic. On working out a system in detail,* it struck me that the method was eminently adapted for school instruction, and that it could really be adapted, in its early stages, as a method of teaching logic to children. Of course it is impossible, during early school work, to do more than scrape the surface of so great a sub- ject; but the soil is naturally so fertile, that I do not despair of a crop with even such shallow cultivation. * In ray paper, entitled " Contributions to Formal Logic," read Royal Society on Thursday, 25th April, 1872. See ' Proceedinas of Society," vol. 20, No. 134, p. 307. before the the Royal ,u< ARTS. 4 — 6.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 4. Let me first confide to you, as a secret which you must strictly keep from youi- pupils, that " the intention of deductive logic IS to determine the precise meaning of any number of given assertions— that is, to determine precisely what they affirmT pre- cisely what they deny, and precisely what they leave in doubt, separately and jointly." This is the whole problem of deductive logic. It has nothing to do with the formation of assertions, i hat IS the special object of induction. It has nothing directly to do with the correctness or incorrectness of the assertions. It takes them as they come, good, bad, and indifferent, and determines precisely what ground they cover, singly and in combination. Hence it must not be imputed as a fault, that logic leads to no new discovery; that the conclusion is involved in the premisses- that It merely teUs us in other words, as a final assertion, what has been already sufficiently told in the preliminary assertions. This IS no fault m logic; this is its aim. It is just because people do not in general know the full force of each assertion they launch the number of cases which it settles, and more especially the number of cases which it leaves entirely unnoticed ; it is just because people do not see the combined effect of their assertions, do not know what the premisses do and do not contain or imply; it is iust for these reasons that it becomes of the last importance to have an easy, straightforward, infallible, and general method of finding all this out. Herein hes the raison d'etre of deductive logic. 5. The value of this method, in indirectly determining the cor- rectness of assertions, cannot be over-estimated. It is only when we see every case which an assertion does and does not cover, that we can confront it with fact. Hence, in every stage of induction, deduction IS imperative. All induction consists in the formation of successive hypotheses, which have to be stated as assertions, and these hypotheses have to be put to the test of observation and ex- periment in the well-known methods. By deduction, and by de- duction alone, can we be sure of conducting this test with the requi- site thoroughness. Of course such applications imply a very much deeper knowledge of the subject than can be presented to children ; \^}l f J^^^^^^^ "Ot, sufficient foundation can be laid in very youthful days for a superstructure which will prove advantageous to the most adventurous investigator of nature. To-night I shall only deal with two kinds of assertion, and I shall not advance far 111 their consideration ; but the method I shall explain is general, and It will be found that most other problems of deduction differ Irom those now adduced in complication only, not in principle. 6. Language has become possible solely because "different at- tributes frequently reside at the same time in the same thing, and the same attribute generally resides at the same time in different things, where the word "things" is used with the utmost gene- rality, for all objects of thought, such as material objects, their qualities and actions, states, conceptions, feelings, relations, in short, whatever can be named. Now, of course, no teacher would be mad enough to present children with such excessively abstract general propositions. But if he wishes to make his pupils think, - B 2 B LOGIC FOE CHILDREN. [arts. 6, 7. he must contrive some method of making them perfectly familiar with this fact, which pervades all language, and is the foundation of the first class of assertions that they will have to analyze, a class which occupies by far the greater part of all treatises on logic. Of course this must be effected by presenting the pupils with con- crete objects of thought ; and the method which occurs to me as most convenient to the teacher, and at the same time as the best introduction to the future expression of abstract logical relations, is the following. It is based on the supposition that a teacher would not be called upon to give lessons on logic to pupils who cannot read and write. 7. The teacher requests each pupil in his class to write down about twenty English words, each on a separate piece of paper. The choice of words should be left to the pupils, but for conveni- ence of writing they should be recommended to choose " short" words. This done, let each pupilsort his words, putting on the left hand all those containing A, and all the rest on the right. Let this right-hand heap be well looked through to ascertain that not one of them contains A. All the words are therefore divided into two heaps, which we will call A-words, and non-A-words, and in writ- ing we will employ a little a in place of the words " non-A'*, so that the second heap contains a-words only. If each pupil has been able to make this division, it will be felt that it can always be made. But perhaps one or two pupils will have no A-words, or no a-words. If this should not happen to be the case, make instances by requesting one pupil to throw away his A-words, and another pupil his a-words. Then an opportunity will be offered for show- mg that this was not a peculiarity of our language, because other pupils have found words of the missing kinds, but that it merely depended upon the choice of words, that is, upon the words thought of, or upon the " range of thought," a most useful and important conception. Then explain that, to get the most common, or the most general case, we ought to lay down as a rule or general con- dition, that when we have to look alter A-words, we should have " at least one" A-word, and at least onea-word word, within the "range of thought," because the exceptional cases are very easily hunted up when the general cases are known (art. 20). Perhaps some word, as " papa, avail, abase," may contain more than one A. If no such words occur, let the teacher supply some on the black board, and ask to which set they belong. Clearly to the A-words, because they contain " at least one" A, and that is all we mean by an A- word. Hence, if we suppose the ** general condition" just stated to be fulfilled, — and ivhatever letters we taJJc about we shall hereafter suppose it to be fulfilled — all the words within the range of thought can be separated into two sets, the first or A-words, containing *' at least one" A, and the second or a-words, containing ** not even one" A. No word can belong to both sets, which are perfectly ex- clusive one of the other. It is worth while bestowing great pains on this elementary conception, which is the basis of all classifica- tion, and which, expressed in the usual abstract language of logic, is intensely perplexing to a child's mind. t ! ^ 1 i ( K ARTS. 8 — 10.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 9 8. We now advance a stage. Take each of the two sets of A- words and a-words, and examine them for E. Observe that vowels are selected by the teacher because all words have some vowel or other. The A-words can then be divided into two heaps, containmg at least one E, and containing not even one E. These will then be E-words and e-words. But in order to show that they have been formed out of the single set of A-words, prefix A to each and call the sets AE-words, (read "A, E, words") and Ae- words (read "A, non-E words"). Do the same with the a-words, and thus find two other sets of aE-words, (read "non-A, E words, ) anda^-words (read "non-A, non-E words"). Of course the general condition has been complied with, so that there is at least one E-word and one e-word. But it will not always happen, even then, that each pupil will have all four sets of AE Ae aE ae words. Having ascertained whether any one has got all four sets, begin with him. ° 9. Then the AE-words and aE-words are two sets which could have been formed out of the one set of E-words, supposing that the list of words had been examined for E first. And the Ae and ae are two sets which could have been formed out of the one set ot e-words. This must not merely be acknowledged, but prac- tically done. Let one pupil that has all the four sets of words read out his list, and let the teacher write it on the black board thus, — ^E Ae aE ae E 1 i got put mutton slit round ale bate seat have amen ail papa cat sham lady feet sieve seize conceive people The continuous lines group together all the A- and all the E- words ; the dotted lines group together all the a- and all the e-words. Ihis being understood, merely writing such Hues with A and E at rlil ^^'."""Tf •' ^-^^ ^""^""l *° '^'^^' ^y overlapping, how the two different subdivisions can be made. Thus a mode of forming logical diagrams is suggested, which will be found of the greatest use. 10. Now observe that, instead of selecting words, it would have been sufficient to have written upon at least one of the slips of paper the letter A, implying that at least that one slip con- tained or represented a word containing A, and to have written on all the rest the letter a, implying that all these represented words without A, and then to have written E upon at least one of all these Slips, and e upon all the rest, implying respectively that the slips represented words containing or not containing E. In this way every one of the slips would bear one or other of the marks AE, Ae, aJli, ae, and these marks would represent the " names" of these 10 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. [aRTS. 10,11 . words considered in relation to their containing or not containing the letters A and E. The names A and a would be " simple" names; but AE, Ae, aE, ae, would be "compound" names, and may be briefly termed compoimcU. This being well understood and tried with various slips of paper,* will form the basis for a mechanical arrangement of great value in teaching. The number of slips of paper containing each ** compound" is evidently unim- portant for ascertaining the fact that there h at least one such compound. Hence four slips of paper — or, for greater convenience of handling, four slips of pasteboard, or " counters" — may be used, marked in bold letters with the names of the compounds AE, Ae, aE, ae, respectively. For class teaching these counters should be six inches long and three high, and the capital letters should be more than two inches high, and very clear and bold. These are readily drawn with a camel-hair pencil dipped in hlach ink. The back of each counter, for a purpose immediately to be explained, should be marked with the same letters in red ink. If four other counters be mai-ked with A, a, E, e, respectively, and little ledges be arranged for resting them on, the double arrangement may be ehown thus, — A a I E 6 AE Ae «E oe I AE aE Ae ae So that, in fact, we have only to transpose Ae, aE, in order to con- vert the first into the second. Be careful that the pupil under- stands that each of these counters stands for a set of words con- sisting of at least one word. Each counter therefore represents a column, Yrith at least one word in it.§ 11. Now suppose, as is most likely, that some of the pupils have not supplied words which can be fitted into every column, so that at least one column is empty. The question then arises (and it is one of primary importance), in how many different ways is it pos- sible to have empty columns, consistent with the fulfilment of the "general condition"? Tliis the pupils must be led to answer for themselves. Take a pupil that has only three sets. Suppose AE to be " absent," that is, that there is not even one word in the AE ♦ Beoin by writing the compound names on the front or back of the actual slips of paper containing words ; as, mate AE, mot aE, &c. § A complete set of counters for the first kind of assertions consists of twenty-six pieces, namely A, a, E, ^, I, t ; AE, A^, aE, ae ; AI, A«, al, ai ; EI, Ej, el, ei ; AEI, AEj, A^I, A^», aEI, aEt", a^I, aei ; all with black letters on one side, and red on the other. Also a set of eleven indices, three inches high and one and a-half inch wide, black on one side only, namely 2i, 2i, %y 22, 23, 23, 24, 24, 3i, 82, 83. For the second set of assertions thirty pieces are "required, namely, twenty-six black on one side and red on the other, X, x, Y, y, Z, 2 ; X. Y, X.y, ir.Y, x.y ; X.Z, X.«, x.Z, x.z ; Y.Z, Y.2, y.Z, y.z ; X.Y.Z, X.Y.z, X.y.Z, X.y.r, a;. Y.Z, x.Y.z, x.y.Z, x.y.z ; and four black on one side only, X', X'', x', xf'. The uses of these forms will be explained in due course. For classes of two or three persons, smaller counters, made on blank address caids, will suffice ; and as these may be laid on a table, no ledges to support them are necessary. TJnlcBs the reader will cmstrnct caunters of some hind, and use them as directed, he cannot pro- perly appreciate the method. { ARTS. 11, 12.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 11 / column. Show this by turning the red side of the AE counter, which will therefore mean an empty column. Now is it quite necessary that when AE is absent, Ae, aE, ae, should be all "pre- sent, ' that IS, that there should be at least one word in each of these columns ? Try this. What does the general condition de- mand f I hat there should be at least one A-word and one a-word But what is implied by there being at least one A-word? Ali A-words, as we have seen, must be AE-words or Ae-words. There ^e no AE-words, there must be, therefore, at least one Ae-word Hence Ae must be present. The Ae counter is therefore ranged with the black side out, beside the red AE. Again, there must be at least one E-word. But all E-words are either AE-words or aE- words. There are no AE-words. There must, therefore, be at least one aE-word. Place a black aE on the ledge. Then observe that, as we have Ae and aE, we have already satisfied the general condition for e-words and a-words, and hence cannot tell whether there are any ae-words or not. There may be, or may not be, any ; there must be at least one, or else not even one ; but when we say there are no AE-words, we say nothing about the ae-words. Their presence is therefore " doubtful." Mark this by putting the ae counter on the ledge, black side out, but inverted, thus ["^ 9D \ This doubtful compound must be well understood. Revert to the general condition. There must be at least one a-word All a-words are aE-words, or ae-words. We know that there is at least one aE-word, and this gives at least one a-word, because we only want a word without A, and whether it contains E or not is quite indifferent. Hence we cannot tell whether there are any ae-words from this consideration. Similarly from knowing that there must be at least one e-word, and that there is at least one Ae-word, we cannot tell whether there is any ae-word or not This is very important for all future applications of reasoning. We see then that absent AE gives present Ae, and present aE, but doubtful ae ; but that in any real case that can be formed, the doubt will be resolved when all the words are known, and 'that there will be either present ae or absent oe. Cases, however, may well be imagined where all the words are not known, but only the fact that none contain both A and E, and these, in the applications are the usual cases. ' 12. Now the counters are very convenient, nay, almost indis- pensable, in teaching, but for registering the results we require other signs. We cannot use the distinction of upright black letters for present, inverted black for doubtful, and red for absent compounds. Hence it is convenient to use abbreviations for these words. In my Complete System of Logical Notation, I have found it most convenient to use — J for present, P for doubtful, and f for absent,— as shown in the following cases, where the exact meaning of each symbol should be rendered quite plain, and no use of " some" for "at least one," or "no" for "not even one," should be allowed, as the words " some, no" have occasioned groat confusion. 12 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. [art. 12. ARTS. 12, 13.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 13 JAB, read " present, A,E," means that " there is at least one word within the range of thought which contains at least one A and at least one E." JAe, read " present, A, non-E," means that " there is at least one word within the range of thought which contains at least one A and not even one E." JaE, read " present, non-A, E," means that " there is at least one word within the range of thought which contains at least one E and not even one A." Joe, read "present, non-A, non-E," means that "there is at least one word within the range of thought which contains not even one A, and also not even one E." fAE, fAe, t^E, t^xe, read respectively "absent, A, E," " absent. A, non-E," " absent, non-A, E," and " absent, non-A, non-E," mean that " there is not even one word within the range of thought which contains, respectively, at least one A and at least one E ; at least one A and not even one E ; at least one E and not even one A; and not even one A and not even one E." While PAE, PAe, PaE, ?ae, would imply a doubt arising from the absence of information as to whether J AE or fAE, whether JAe or fAe, whether JaE or faE, whether Jae or fae respectively. To embrace the cases where the presence or absence of every single one of the four compounds is declared, it is convenient to compound these signs, thus — tj for all present with, or pre-present, Jt for all present hut, or pre-absent, tt for one absent with, or ab-absent, the precise use of which is shown in the next article. We have already seen that the general condition that there should be at least one A-word, obliges us to acknowledge that there must be at least one AE-word, or else at least one Ae-word, and that there may be more than one of either or both sets. That is, at least one of the compounds AE, Ae must be present, and both may be present. That is, we may have JAE and JAe, or JAB and fAe, or fAE and JAe, but cannot have fAE and fAe. This very curious limitation is constantly occurring in logic, and requires a sign. It is expressed by — J' (AE, Ae) read "present at least one of AE and Ae." With the counters it is expressed by inverting both, and placing them close together thus : | gy I ay Observe that the general conditions give four such combina- tions, called limitates, namely, JHAE, Ae), +HAE, aE), t^(Ae, ae), J^(aE, ae,) Combinations of these may be indicated by groupings of the counters. Thus the two first might be (1), and the two last might be (2), while the whole four sets might be (3). (1) (2) (3) ay a» ay ay ay 9V ay 9Y a» 9V if i \ The inversion shows the really doubtful nature of each indi- vidual compound, and the grouping shows the limitation of that doubt. Another method of marking this fact is given in art. 26. The following signs are also useful in writing : II for means, and ( • ) for and, with, together with. These signs must only be introduced gradually as a means of easily writing what the counters indicate, and the pupils must be exercised in passuig from the written forms to the counters, and thence to the sets of words themselves, as the real things under consideration. 13. We may now note all the cases which can possibly happen regarding the separation of vrords into four sets, and each case must be rigorously demonstrated by the pupils themselves, in the manner described in art. 11. The continuous and dotted lines show immediately how the columns would overlap, and what columns would be absent ; but each case should also be illustrated by words, and, if possible, the actual cases which occur among the pupils should be taken first ; if these are not enough, the pupils, rather than the teacher, should be led to furnish the rest. Pupils should also be exercised in constructing diagrams for themselves, giving various lengths to the dotted and continuous lines, interrupting dotted by continuous lines, and so on, till they feel that the length of these lines is of no consequence, (because they merely indicate the breadth of columns containing words ; and as the length of those columns is indefinite, any number of words can be written in any column, however narrow, ) but that the overlapping of the dotted and continuous parts in the two lines is everything, (be- cause each overlapping shows the presence of a certain set of words). The Seven Possible Arrangements (or Complete Assertions). i. JJAB, "all present," also written JJAe, JJaE, or JJoe, means present AE, and present Ae, and present aE, and present ae, or in the abbreviated form, || JAE • JAe • JaE * Jae ;. f A that is, at least one word occurs in ( jj each one of all the four sets. { 'K ii. JfAE, " aU present but AE," || fAE • JAe • JaE • Jae ; A there is not even one word of the B first set, but there is at least one word in each of the other three sets. iii. JfAe, " all present but Ae," || J AE • fAe • JaE • Joe ; A there is not even one word of the J] second set, but there is at least one word in each of the other three sets. iv. JfaE, " all present but aE," || JAE • JAe • faE • Jae ; A there is not even one word of the jg third set, but there is at least one word in each of the other three sets. 14 LOGIC FOR CBILDREN. [ARTS. 13, 14. { V. Ifae, " all present but ae," || {AE • J Ae • JaE • fae ; A there is not even one word of the E — fourth set, but there is at least one word in each of the other three sets. vi. tfAE, "one absent with AE," also written ffae, "one absent with ae" (because AE and ae can be absent together, and neither Ae nor oE can be absent at the same time with either AE or ae, consistently with the "eceneral condition.") (I tAE-JAe-JaE-fae; (A there is not even one word of the i^ first and fourth sets, but there is at . . least one word in the second and also m the third set. This is the arrangement of complete diversity, for (1) no A-words are E-words, (2) no E-words are A-words, (3) no a-words are e-words, and (4) no e-words are a-words. vii. tfAe, "one absent with Ae," also written ffaE, "one absent with aE," (because Ae and aE can be absent together, and neither AE nor ae can be absent at the same time with either Ae or aE, consistently with the "general condition") II JAE-fAe-faE'+ae; ' [ A E there is not even one word of the second and third sets, but there is least one word of the first and also of the fourth set. This is the arrangement of complete identity, for (1) every one of the A-words is an E-word, (2) every one of the E-words is an A-word, (3) every one of the a-words is a e-word, and (4) every one of the e-words is a a-word. Hence, so far as the words thought of are concerned, it would be indifferent whether we said any given word were an A-word or an E-word, a a-word or a e-word. But the possession of an A is a very dif- ferent mark from the possession of an E. Hence ffAe or ffaE points to identical groups formed by means of different marks A and E. This is really a point oi great importance. These seven arrar-T'ements are the only arrangements that can possibly occur consistently with the general condition. This fact should be made perfectly clear to the mind of the pupils, and not a step further should be taken until every pupil is familiar with it, and has tested it in every possible way, because it is the fundamental fact of all deduction. 14. Now make the following observations, leading to — The Eight Usual Arrangements {or Incomplete Assertions). i. t AE (read strictly according to the interpretation given in art. 12) occurs in 5 of the 7 arrangements, namely, 1, 3, 4, 5, 7, and does not occur in 2, 6. That is, if I know that one of the pupils has an AE-set, I know that he must have one of those five arrangements ; but, not knowing which of the five, I can't tell where he has an Ae-set (present in 1, 4, 5, but absent in 3, 7) or an aE-set (present in 1, 3, 5, but absent in 4, 7), or an ae-set (pre- Mifc- i ( ( ART. II.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 16 sent in 1, 3, 4, 7, but absent in 6). The limited knowledge, JAE, consequently leaves the presence or absence of each of the other three sets of words, Ae, aE, ae, in doubt, but not in unlimited doubt. This we gather also from the four limitates given in art. 12. Thus JAE in conjunction with the two JM^E, Ae) and J'(AE, aE), leaves Ae, aE in unlimited doubt. But the two other limitates l^{Ae, ae) and JK^E, ae), limit this doubt, by showing that there are only five possible cases of the presence and absence of Ae, aE, ae, which are easily deduced, and seen to be the same as those pointed out by the seven complete arrangements. This is very easily done with the counters and then registered, and every pupil should be made to do it for himself, and write out his process at length. It is an important and very easy exercise. Hence JAE implies J* (Ae, ae) ' J» (aE, ae). /-^ The diagram will have an incom- ? jj plete line for E, and this line can be filled up so as to make any one of the diagrams 1, 3, 4, 5, 7, and hence satisfy the two limitates, but can not be filled up so as to form either of the diagrams 2, 6. The teacher must see that the pupil actually fills up the diagram in all these ways for himself, and feels that there are no other ways in which it can be filled up, and so on in each of the following cases. ii. JAe occurs in the five arrangements 1, 2, 4, 5, 6, and does not occur in 3, 7. And by the same process as before we see that JAe implies X\A.E, aE) • t^(aE, ae), and may be represented thus : 4 A which may be filled up into the I E diagrams of 1, 2, 4, 6, 6, only. iii. JaE occurs in the five arrangements 1, 2, 3, 5, 6, and does not occur in 4, 7; so that JaE implies J^AE, Ae) * JHAe, ae), and may be represented thus : VA which may be filled up into the i E diagrams of 1, 2, 3, 5, 6, only. iv. Jae occurs in the five arrangements 1, 2, 3, 4, 7, and does not occur in 5, 6 ; so that Jae implies J^AE, Ae) • J^(AE, aE), and may be represented thus : J A which may be filled up into the i E diagrams of 1, 2, 3, 4, 7, only. V. fAE occurs in the two arrangements 2, 6, and does not occur in 1, 3, 4, 5, 7, so that fAE implies JAe • JaE, but gives Poe, where the doubt is absolutely unlimited, and may be represented thus : CA which may be filled up into the J > li i I \ ARTS. 19 — 21.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 21 cause by the general condition there must be at least one com- pound present containing A, and only these four compounds can contain A. This is often very useful. All these cases must be worked out over and over again, with' all varieties, and for any two or three of the 8 larger compounds, and results deduced with ease and certainty, just as in simple arithmetic. Where no doubtful compounds occur, the pupils should give words completely illustrating given cases. Where doubtful com- pounds occur, they should give sets of words answering to each case included in the doubt, not omitting any one included, but not giving any one excluded. 20. But suppose the general condition is not fulfilled, what hap- pens P Suppose there is at least one word containing A, but no a- word, that is no word without A. Then of course all the words are A words, and we have faE and fae and hence t«EI • faEi and ■fael' faei. This occasions no difiiculty. But it will be seen that the only compounds which can be present are AEI, AEi, Ael, Aei, all of which contain A, and are in fact the compounds EI, Ei, el, ei, with A prefixed. Hence there is really no use in mentioning A at all. The range of thought is confined to A- words. But suppose there is 07ily one word containing A, what happens ? One of the two compounds AE, Ae must be present, and only one can he present. In counters show this by grouping | AE | Ae'j not inverted. In writing prefix Ji, with the little 1 below, thus, Ji (AE, Ae), and read " present only one of AE, Ae." We have then also Ji (AEI, AEi, Ael, Aei). In writing, it is often conve- nient to put a little i below the letter which occurs in only one word. Thus JAj E shows that there is only one word containing A, and that that word also contains E, so that fA^e. This is a case of common occurrence in practice, when general propositions are used, and should be carefully studied in every case. A little rider of paper, or a clip, placed across the letter on the counter, or an elastic band strung round it, will sufficiently mark A^, &c., as the case may be. 21. Every preparation has now been made for considering syl- logisms, and indeed much more complicated cases. Considered as problems upon words containing letters, the syllogism is as fol- lows -.—Given the state of a certain group of ivords ivith respect to containing A and E ; and also their state with respect to containing E and I ; to find their state ivith respect to containing A and I. These states are given by one of the complete or incomplete arrangements of Art. 13 or 14. The two first are called the pre- misses, and the last the conclusion. The letters A and I are called the extremes. The letter E, which occurs in both the premisses, but does not occur in the conclusion, is called the mean. The process is as follows, and may bo conducted with counters or on paper, but for children counters are far best. First, state the two premisses, in the abbreviated form of Arts. 13 and 14, forming the upper line of counters, remembering all the implied present, absent, or doubtful parts. C 20 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. [arts. 18, 19. ARTS. 19 — 21.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 21 A and E without I, or containing E without either A or I. That is, if fEi then t(AEi, crEi). But we know that if fEi then JEI •JerPel, hence we know J' (AEI, aEI)' J» (Aei, aei) '?{Ael, ael). All these consequences of fEi) should be very distinctly seized and well exemplified by words. Get the whole class to write down twenty words a-piece, each having 2 or 3 vowels, and none having E without I, taking care that the general condition is fulfilled ; as- certain that the above results are obtained, by actually sorting first with respect to E, e; then each bundle with respect to I, t ; and finally each with respect to A, a. Some may have JAel, others fAfil ; some may have Jael, others fael. None will have JAEi or J«Ei. Some may have JAEI'JaEI, others JAEI-faEI, others fAEI • JaEI, but none fAEI * faEI, and so on. By this means the real meaning of the signs and processes will become evident to them, and they will feel that they are dealing with a law of thought. Any set of words being given, the pupils should be exercised in marking what compounds are present or absent. Thus avail, Italy, debascvient, conceive, seem, give fAEI' JAEi * JAt'I'fA^'i* JaEI 'Xa'Ei'fael'faei. This is best done by writing the compounds on the black board, and writing against them each word as it arises, thus, — AEI aEI AEfc debasement oEi Ael avail, Italy ael Aei conceive seem aei. All the words being used up, the blanks show the absent sets. This exercise is really important. 19. Next suppose we happened to know which of the larger com- pounds were present or absent or doubtful, see if we could find out what is the case with the smaller. ^ It is quite clear that if JAEI, then JAE, JAI, and JEI. Thus increase being an AEI-word, is also an AE-word, and an Al-word, and an El-word; so that if there is at least one such word as the first, th ere is by that means at least one such word as each of the three last. Again, if J^(AEI, AE/), then certainly JAE; because in that case either J AEI, or JAEt, or both, and in either case, as we have seen, there must be JAE. Thus if wo know that either increase or mate, or both, are among the words thought of, we know that there must be at least one AE-word. If JAEI • fAEt, or if JAEI- ?AE/, still there must be JAE on ac- count of JAEI. If fAEI • fAE?', then, and in no other case, fAE, That is, if no word thought of contains both A and E, either with or without I, then no word at all contains both A and E. If PAEI- ?AE^, or if PAEIfAEi, or if fAEI' PAE/', then PAE. For if all the P were f, then fAE, by the last case; but if only one of them were J, then JAE, by the former cases. But we do not know which is the case, hence PAE. If three compounds all containing the same letter are f, then the fourth will be J. Thus if fAE I -fAE i -fA^I, then J Aei. Be- ) cause by the general condition there must be at least one com- pound present containing A, and only these four compounds can contain A. This is often very useful. All these cases must be worked out over and over again, with' all varieties, and for any two or three of the 8 larger compounds, and results deduced with ease and certainty, just as in simple arithmetic. Where no doubtful compounds occur, the pupils should give words completely illustrating given cases. "Where doubtful com- pounds occur, they should give sets of words answering to each case included in the doubt, not omitting any one included, but not giving any one excluded. 20. But suppose the general condition is not fulfilled, what hap- pens P Suppose there is at least one word containing A, but no a- word, that is no word without A. Then of course all the words are A words, and we have f^E and fae and hence faEI • faEi and frtel-faei. This occasions no difficulty. But it will be seen that the only compounds which can be present are AEI, AEi, Kel, Aei, all of which contain A, and are in fact the compounds EI, Ei, el, ei, with A prefixed. Hence there is really no use in mentioning A at all. The range of thought is confined to A- words. But suppose there is only one word containing A, what happens ? One of the two compounds AE, Ae must be present, and only one can he present. In counters show this by grouping | AE | Ae \ not inverted. In writing prefix Ji, with the little 1 below, thus, ti (AE, Ae), and read " present only one of AE, Ae." We have then also Ji (AEI, AEi, Ael, Aei). In writing, it is often conve- nient to put a little i below the letter which occurs in only one word. Thus JAi E shows that there is only one word containing A, and that that word also contains E, so that f^ie. This is a case of common occurrence in practice, when general propositions are used, and should be carefully studied in every case. A little rider of paper, or a clip, placed across the letter on the counter, or an elastic band strung round it, will sufficiently mark Ai, &c., as the case may be. 21. Every preparation has now been made for considering syl- logisms, and indeed much more complicated cases. Considered as problems upon words containing letters, the syllogism is as fol- lows : — Given the state of a certain group of words with respect to containing A and E ; and also their state tvith respect to containing E and I ; to find their state ivith respect to containing A and I. These states are given by one of the complete or incomplete arrangements of Art. 13 or 14. The two first are called the pre- misses, and the last the conclusion. The letters A and I are called the extremes. The letter E, which occurs in both the premisses, but does not occur in the conclusion, is called the mean. The process is as follows, and may be conducted with counters or on paper, but for children counters are far best. First, state the two premisses, in the abbreviated form of Arts. 13 and 14, forming the upper line of counters, remembering all the implied present, absent, or doubtful parts. C 22 LOGIC FOR CTTTLDREK. [aKTS. 21, 22. Secondly, arrange the 8 compounds below. Thirdly, work with one premiss upon those coraponnds, as shown by art. 18, and then with the other upon the- result. The final result is called the resultant. Fourthly, from this resultant, deduce the conclusion as in art. 19. Fifthly, place this conclusion in the top line. The examples will make this quite easy. Every case given should be worked over and over again, to gain ease, rapidity, and certainty. Be sure not to hurry. If properly conducted, the work will be found very amusing. For convenience of printing, only written signs are given. For tAEI the teacher will show black side of counter erect ; for P AEI, black side inverted ; and for f AEI, red side. Before being thus arranged so as to indicate that any one is pre- sent, absent, or doubtful, the eight counters of the larger com- pounds will be all put on their sides, in two rows, thus — HH 1— ( t— 1 i-i ^ «> p&) <» -< <1 e e •<* •«>» "» < <1 e e This may be indicated by writing (AEI) (Ael) (AEi) {Aei) (aEI) (aEi) (ael) {aei) 22. First hind of Syllogism. " No words have A without E or E without I ; then no words have A without I." First premiss. " No words have A without E," or fAc, or "all words having A have E," This implies J AE * Jnc and PaE. Second premiss. "No words have E without I," or fEi, or "all words having E have I." This implies JEI * Jei and Pel. Resultant. First work for f A e, and get f Ael and f Aei. Then work forfEt, and get fAEi and faEt. Hence, in counters, the resultant will stand thus — (AEI) tAel (aET) (ael) tAEi fAei t«Ei (aei) Rule : whenever there are f compounds in the premisses, work with them first. Next go to the implied P compounds, and work first with PaE. This gives only PaEI, for faEi is already determined. Next work with Pel, and get Pael, since fAel is already determined. The resultant now stands in counters — (AEI) tAel PaEI Pael fAEt fAei faEi (aei) Next work for the J compounds of the premisses. Then JAE gives JH AEI, AEi), but we have already got fAEi, hence we must have J AEI, in order that one of the two compounds should be present. Next try tae, giving J'(ael, aei). But here we have rael, and hence also raei, so far as this is concerned. But we have ART. 22.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 23 +i?l ^T t^o"^Po«".^s of the other premiss to try. Now JEI gives + ( AlLl, aEI) and as we have already J A EI, we have PaEI, so that we are not advanced Next lei gives J'(Ae/, aei), and here sinc6 ' m> T ^"/* ^^^® +^^^' so ^^^^^ t^e previous Paei becomes laei. Ihe final form of the resultant is, therefore, I AEI fAei PaEI Pael fAEi fAei faEi Jaei The two J compounds might have been found from the fact that they are the only non-absent compounds containing A and i re- spectively. Now make a diagram of this syllogism, thus — (A !f== ;;:::: and show how it agrees with the resultant. Conclusix)7t. JAEI • fAEi give JAI ; f A Ei • fAei give fAi ; P aEI • 1a- ^at^ ' ^^^^ "^^^^ ' +^'^'' ^^^® +"*'• ^^"c® ^^^ conclusion is fAi. Now place the counter fAi on the upper ledge, widely se- parated from the premisses. In writing put .'., read " therefore," before the conclusion. This conclusion shows that there are no words having A without I. Write the whole syllogism thus : fAc • fEi .*. fAi. Illustrate by words. Get each pupil to do it separately. Pro- bably the P compounds will be differently determined by different pupils, as in the four following instances, J'j^^^^^'^9* '^ecisuring, seeming, sin, fog. This gives JfAe and +fEi as premisses, and JfAi as conclusion. Show that in such a case, instead of PaEI, and Pael, we 7)iust have (as in the particular instance selected) JaEI * Jacl. Compare art. 30, note, 14. ii. ftea^m^. measuring, sin, fog. This gives ffAe and JfEi, with +tiU as conclusion again, but PaEI and Pael are now faEI and Jael. Compare art. 30, note, 16. ni. heating, measuring, seeming, fog. This gives JfAe and tt^'_, with the conclusion XfAi, as in the preceding cases, but now fahl and Pael become JaEI and fa^I. Compare art. 30, note, 16. iv. beating, measuring, fog. This gives tfAe and ffEi with the conclusion ffAi, which differs from all the preceding, and now f'aEIand Pael become faEI and fael. Compare art. 30, note, 17. Observe that in working out each separately, it will be best to display the premisses and conclusion in counters, thus— (i.) fAe JaE fEi Jel fAi +al (ii.) fAe faE fEi Jel fAi fal (lii.) fAe JaE fEi fel fAi fal (iv.) fAe faE fEi fel fAi fal The pupils should see that it is only the P compounds that are affected by these changes, and that, altliough the three first con- clusions are the same, the corresponding resultants (which alone fully represent the premisses) are different. All the different cases must always be furnished with instances in words. C2 24 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. i- I I *1 [art. 23. 23. There are eight different cases of this first kind of syllogisni, namely — fAEfel . '. tAI t«E • tel .*. -t«I fAEfei . ■. tAi taE'tet .*. fai fAefEI . •. tAI tcre'tEI .'. fal fAefEi . \ fAi tae'tEi .*. fai These are distinguished by having the short forms of the pre- misses both t, and the mean E in one and e in the other, that is, the contrary in one to what it is in the other. This gives the " skeleton rule." [1.] Means unlike. Both premisses f. Conclusion^ f extremes. Tliis is a valuable rule. See how it applies in each case. Each case has four subcases as before, and each should be worked out separately, with counters, with diagrams, and with words. The pupils should be exercised in drawing diagrams for each of these syllogisms, and in showing all the four cases which can ariso from filling up the blanks in each. In the diagram given above the E-line, or line of the mean, has been completely filled, and the doubts thrown on the other lines. The teacher should vary this, and much vary the lengths of the lines, and show what the essen- tial relations are. This will be excellent practice in understanding the effect of combined assertions. It will soon be found that it is possible to introduce into the diagram a condition which is not contained in the premisses, al- though the full incompleteness of the premisses is retained. Thus the diagram — {A satisfies JAE * tAc * PaE ' Jae, and E also JEI'tEi- Pel- te<:. But it also I manifestly gives JAI • tAi ' Jal * Jai or JtAi instead of tAi, as a conclusion. Why sop Because a new relation has been furtively introduced, limiting the absolute doubt- fulness attachable to PrtE and Pel, by rendering it impossible for them both to be absent at once, namely, JHaE, el), which gives in the resultant JH^EI, aEi, Ael, oel), or since t«Ei*tAeI, only J'(aEI, ael), whence Jal. Thus it is impossible to fill up the blanks in the E line without introducing faEI, or Jael, or both. In fact, both the A and I lines arc completely filled, and the doubts are thrown on the single line E. It will be readily seen that we cannot avoid introducing such an additional condition, if we begin by filling up.the line of either of the extremes instead of that of the mean, as in this case we should have also to fill up the line of the other extreme completely. But if the lines of both ex- tremes are filled up, the conclusion appears as a complete, instead of an incomplete arrangement, limiting the absolute doubtfulness of the two r compounds in the resultant. In actual argument, such new conditions are often covertly introduced, even without the knowledge of the arguer, especially when he is exemplifying his argument, and are then very difficult to detect. But it is al- ways necessary to detect them, as the new condition alters the nature of the argument. In the present case, this new condition ART. 23, 2 k] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN, 25 'J removes the argument from the class of syllogisms, because it in- troduces a third premiis, namely +'(aE, el), which relates to all three of the letters A, E, I at once. 2\. The Second hind ofSi/Uogism. " If no words have E without A, and also no words have E without I; then at least one word has both A and I." First premiss. No words have E without A, or taE. Second premiss. No words have E without I, or fM, EesuUant. After using taE, tEi, (AEI) (Ael) t«EI (ael) r .^. ,+^^' (^^^) t«Et (aei) In this case only three compounds are f. Next work with PAe and Pel, and the resultant becomes (AEI) PAel faEI ?ael fAEi ?Aei fam {aei) Now take |AE, which gives JM AEI, AEi), and hence, since tAiii, determines JAEI. But Jae gives only l\ael, aei), and this is the utmost limitation we can get. Next JEI gives t'^AEI aEI) and as taEI, we have JAEI as before. Lastly, lei gives JHAe'i, aei) and this is the utmost limitation we can get. Now observe that the general conditions are satisfied, without taking any considera- tion of the compound Ael, which was left quite doubtful by the premisses. The final resultant is JAEI PAcI t^EI l\ael, aei) ' J^Aei, aei) tAEi faEi The two limitates are indicated by arranging the counters thus— >*- ton • Conclusion. |AI from JAEI ; l\Ai, ai) from Ji(Ae., aei) ; and + (ai, ai) from J'(ael, aei). Observe that PAel would give PAI but as we have already found JAI from JAEI, this does not affect the conclusion. The only certain thing, then, is, JAI, or that at least one word has both letters A and I. Write the whole syllogism thus t^E' fEi .'. JAI, the two limi- tates of the conclusion being implied, as in art. 14. This is rather a difficult case, especially for the diagram A E ,1 This must also be furnished with words, and the four subcases worked out, as in the first kind of syllogism. The results beinc^ • Jt«E • JtEZ .-. JAI I ttAe-JtE^.-.JtAt JtaE • ffEi .: Xfal \ ttAe • tt^^ /. tfAi. Be very particular in obtaining the full resultant for each case, bhow how the diagram and the first resultant can be altered for each particular case without disturbing any of the fixed parts. The first case may present a little difficulty, because the pupil Will be apt to consider, that when the assertions are complete, he 1 26 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. [aRTS. 24 — 26. i p has to fill up the whole lines, and leave no empty parts. Wc aro ignorant of the extent to which the lines should overlap, and the diagram for Jt<*E'JtEi should present so many blanks that it can be filled up into any one of the forms of the resultant which would give any one of the 5 forms of the conclusion JAI * X^i-^^* ai) ' JHal, cii)- The following will be found to be a mode of filling up the original diagram so as to answer these conditions, but the ingenuity of the pupil should be well taxed before any solution is presented to him. A £ \ 25. There are also eight different cases of this second kind of syllogism, namely — fAE • fEI fAE-fEi tAe fel fAe 'fei Jal ai Xal faE • fEI faE • fEi foe 'fel fae 'fei +Ai Jai XAi JAI. These are distinguished by having the short forms of the pre- misses both t (as in art. 23 •, but the mean is E or e in both^ (which is quite different from art. 23). -This gives the " skeleton rule." [2.] Means like. Both premisses f. Conclusion^ J contraries of extremes. See how this applies in each case. Each case has four subcases as before, and each should be worked out separately with counters, with diagrams, and with words. 26. The Third hind of Syllogism. " If at least one word has both A and E, and not one word has E without T, then at least one word has both A and 1." First premiss. At least one word has both A and E, or JAB. Second premiss. Not even one word has E without I, or f Et. Hesultant. Working first with fEi, we obtain (AEI) (Ael) (aEI) (ael) tAEi (Aei) faEi (aei) Then working for J*(Ae, ae), JKaE, ae), (which may be consi- dered as ?Ae, PaE, ?ae, leaving the limitations to be recovered from the general conditions,) and also Pel, we get — (AEI) PA el PaEI Pael fAEi ?Aei faEi ?aei Next work with J AE, which gives J^AEI, AEi) ; whence, since fAE?', we have J AEI, which has to be put for (AEI). Then work with JEI, giving J\AEI, aEI), whence, as JAEI has already been found, aEI remains doubtful. Next Jei, gives J' (Aei, aei), and nothing further. We have now got J(A, E, I, e, i), but, to satisfy the general condition, we must also have Ja, and this gives J*(aEI, oel, nci)y leaving PAel. The complete resultant then is — {AEI PAel J'(aEI, ael, oeO tAEi iaEl {'(Aei, aei) I ^ I ( I ARTS. 26, 27.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN, 27 The last limitates are most conveniently set up in counters, thus m^ h-l FW %9V • But when several limitates occur, and one compound enters into several of them, it is often convenient to use a special mark both in writing and with counters, called an index, which may be placed before each compound separately. This consists of a large number as 2 or 3, showing how many compounds there are in the limitate, and a smaller number subscribed, showing to which set of 2 or 3 the compound belongs. These should be prepared in counters, about U inches wide, and 3 inches high, iu sets, thus 2] 2„ 22 22, 2^ 23, 24 2^, 3i 3i 3^, &c. The resultant may now be more conveniently written, thus — {AEI PAel 3iaEI 3, ael fAEi 2iAei faEi di2i aei Where 3i 2i aei shows that aei belongs to two limitates. 1 he counters may remain inverted after these indices, to show their doubtful character, but this is no longer essential, as the index itself marks limited doubtfulness. Conclusion. {AI from {AEI; {'( Ai, ai) from 2,(Aet, aei); and {•(«I, ai) from 3i (o'EI, ael, aei). Hence the only thing certain is that at least one word contains both A and I. Write the whole syllogism thus ; {AE-fEi .-. {AI the limitates of the conclusion being implied as in art. 14 Diagrwm : — f A Je ^I Now there are 6 different complete arrangements correspond- ing to the first premiss, and 2 to the second, hence there are 10 syllogisms in which the premisses would be the same in the non- doubtful parts, and each of these would lead to resultants and conclusions, also the same in the non-doubtful parts. In the pre- sent case these 10 syllogisms are — {faE • {tE^ JtAe•{tE^ {fae • {fEi {fAe-ffEi {faE • tfEi X^ai {tA^ {t«I X\ai {fAi tfA* {AT-{aX {AI- {Ai-{al-{at. {AI {fae •ttE^ tfAi ttAe-{tEi ttAe'tfEi {{AE-{tEi {{AE-ffE* All these cases should be worked by counters (they are worked on paper in art. 39 ^ and exemi)litied, and the blanks of the diagram of the general case should be filled up so as to illustrate every one of these cases. This will be found both instinictive and entertain- ing, and will serve to make the process of deduction something real and intelligible instead of abstract and hazy. 27. There are sixteen cases of this third kind of syllogism, eight when the first, and eight when the second premiss is {, namely :— 28 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. [arts. 27, 28. I I ! +AE • fEI jAE-fEi lAe fel jAe • fei +aE -fEI JaE -fEi •f.I Jae lAi lAI JAi JAI pii la\ tal fAE • +EI tAE-+Ei tAe • |el • X^i •tEI • +1 fAe fc^E faE ■fae foe ^Ei tAI tAt Jai JAi. These are distinguished by having the short form of one pre- miss J, and the other f, and having the means likp, that is, either both E or both e. This gives the important " skeleton rule" : — [3]. Means like. One premiss J, and one f. Gonclusiont J eX' treme of the J, with contrary of extreme of the f prem iss. Thus the J premiss in the first case above is JAE, and its ex- treme is A. The f premiss is fEI, and its extreme is I, of which the contrary is i. Hence the conclusion is JAi. Each syllogism has 10 subcases, and each should be worked out separately with counters, with diagrams, and with words. Sec also art. 39. 28. Syllogisms with Dotihtful Conclusions. The 32 syllogisms in the three kinds just considered (with their cases), are the only syllogisms which give any certain conclusion. All others leave every compound in the conclusion cither abso- lutely or limitedly doubtful. It is easily seen that the 16 cases in which both premisses are +, will leave every compound even in the resultant, doubtful. But it is not so evident that the \Q cases in which one premiss is J, and the other f, but the means imlihe, will give only a doubtful conclusion, because two compounds in the resultant will always be absent. Hence it is best to work out a case. " If at least one word has both A and E, and not one word has I without E, nothing can be predicted." First premiss. At least one word has both A and E, or JAE. Second previiss. Not even one word has I without E, or fel. Besultant. Worked for fel, it becomes — (AEI) fAel (aEI) fael (AEi) (Ae^) (aEi) (aei) Now, working for JAE, we get t*(AEI, AEi), with nothing further. Working for JEI, we get J' (AEI, aEI.) Working for Jet, we have J'(Aet, aei). Working for Ja, which is still undeter- mined, we get J'(aEI, aEt, aei). So that, using the indices, the complete resultant is — 232, AEI tAel 3i22aEI faeJ 2i AE* 23Aei 3i aEi 3i ^soei Conclusion, ^or Al, either JK AI, Ai) from 2i (which may be used as an abbreviation for all the compounds bearing that index) or JHAI, al) from 2:. For At, either JHAI, Ai) from 2i or J>(Ai, ai) from 23. For al, either J'(AI, al) from 2^ or J'(al, ai) from 3i. For ai, either JH Ai, ai) from 23, or J'(al, ai) from 3i. But these four limitatcs JHAI, Ai), J'(«I, ai), JHAI, al), J'(Ai, ai) result in every case fjcom the general condition JA, Ja, JE, Je, (art. 12,) and hencQ ARTS. 28 — 30.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 29 s < i add nothing to our knowledge. That is, the premisses tell us no- thing as respects the possession of A and I ; or the conclusion is doubtful. Write JAE-f^I .-. ? Observe, however, that the resultant has a very determinate form, and that we know from fAel that no words contain A and I without E, and from fael, that no words contain I without either Aor E. 29. We may comprise all these 32 syllogisms under two skeleton rules, thus — [4.] Means unlike. One premiss J, and one f. Conclusion doubtful. [5.] Means like or unlike. Both prernisses J. Conclusion doubtful. 30. The 64 cases of syllogism here considered are all admitted by Prof. De Morgan.* The old logic only admitted 11 of them, ^ ♦ Teachers wiU perceive that the number of different syllogisms is limited by the number of different assertions. As there are 26 of these (art. 14, note,) there must be 26 x 26 = 676 possible syllogisms, each of which will give a different resultant. Of these 2x15x11 = 3 30 will have one of the 1 1 complex incomplete as one of their premisses, the other being complete or else simple incomplete; and llxllorl21 will have both premisses complex incomplete. These syllogisms have very httle inte- rest, but may all be worked out on the model of the third kind of syllo- gism, and as such form occasionally useful exercises. The remaining 225 may be distributed into 3 classes ; 8 x 8 = 64 having both premisses incomplete, which are those considered in the text ; 2x7x8 = 112 hav- ing one premiss incomplete and one premiss complete ; and 7 x 7 = 49 having both premisses complete, which comprise all the subcases mentioned in the text under each kind of syllogism. To embrace all these 225 cases, 20 " skeleton rules" are necessary, which are here added, with the numbers of cases comprised in each, and one example in the short form, as they may be useful in suggesting exercises to teachers ; each has been specially considered and worked in my Contributions to Fonnal Logie. Rules 1 to 5 belong to the first class, 6 to 13 to the second, and the remainder to, the third. 1, 2, and 3 are the first, second, and third kind of syllogisms in the text. 8, 8, and 16 cases respectively. See arts. 22, 24, 26. 4. One premiss f, and one J. Means unlike. Conclusion, ?. Ex. fAE • lei .-. ? I AI |. 16 cases. See [4], art. 29. 5. Both premisses J. Means indifferent. Conclusion, ?. Ex. JAE • JEI .-. ? I All, JAE • Xel .'. ? I AI|. 16 cases. See [5], art. 29. 6. One premiss Jf, and one f. Means unlike. Conclusion, Jf extremes.. Ex. JtAE • t«X .*. JtAI. 16 cases. 7. One premiss Jf, and one f. Means like. Conclusion, J contrariea of extremes. Ex. JfAE • f EI .*. Ja». 16 cases. 8. One premiss Jf, and one J. Means like. Conclusion, J extreme of J premiss with the contrary of extreme of Jf premiss. Ex. Jf AE • J EI .*. Jrtl. 16 cases. 9. One premiss Jf, and one J. Means unlike. Conclusion, ?. Ex.. Jt AE • %el .'. ? |_AI |. 16 cases. 10. One premiss ft* aiid one f. Means unlike, by arrangement of the 30 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. [art. 30. ART. 30.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 31 bnt this arose from insufficient knowledge. It maybe convenient for the teacher to have the old forms of syllogisms translated into the present. They are therefore given here as Prof Bain lias presented them, with the old barbarous Latin names having their vowel quantities marked. The present letters A, E, I have been sub- stituted for those of Prof. Bain. There are apparently 19 forms, but 8 are merely verbal varieties of other forms, depending on what is called figtire and mood, (which again depended on the grammatical order of subject and predicate) distinctions rejected by De Morgan, and needless to be considered now. The bracketed numbers at the end refer to the three kinds of syllogisms and their rules, as given above. Arts. 23, 25, 27. Observe that by "all A IS E," Prof. Bain means, in the present case, " all words con- taining A contain E," or fAe ; by " some A is E," he means " at least one word containing A contains E," or JAE; by " some A is not E," he means, " at least one word containing A does not contain E," or JAe ; and by " no A is E" he means " not even +t premiss. Conclusion, f extremes. Ex. ft AE • f^I .*. fAI. Use either ft AE or its equivalent ffae, according to the phase of the mean in the other premiss, for the sake of the rule. 16 cases. 11. One premiss ff, and %. Means unlike, by arrangement of ff, as in No. 10. Conclusion, X extremes. Ex. ff AE • Jel .-. J AI. 16 cases. 12. One premiss tt and one f. Meana indifferent. Conclusion, X the contrary of the extreme of the f premiss with the other extreme and also with its contrary. Ex. tt AE • t EI .-. X{Ai, at). 8 cas«s. 13. One premiss ti, and one t Means indifferent. Conclusion.?. Ex. JJAE-iEI.-.?|AI|. 8 cases. 14. Both premisses Xf- Means unlike. Conclusion, If extremes. Ex, Xf AE • XfeL .-. tfAI. 8 cases. 15. Both premisses tf. Means like. Conclusion, J the contraries of the extremes. Ex. tfAE-JfEI .-. +a». 8 cases. ^ 16. One premiss tt, and one Jt. Means unlike, by arrangement of ft, as m No. 10. Conclusion, Xf extremes. Ex. ft AE • f f^I .-. ff AI. 16 cases. 1 7. Both premisses ft- Means unlike, bv arrangement of ff, as in No. 10. Conclusion, ft extremes. Ex. ffAE • ft^I .*. ftAI, which is the same as ffae • ttEi . •. tt"'. 4 cases. 18. One premiss ff, and one Xt- Means indifferent. Conclusion. 11. Ex. ttAE • ::EI .-. ttAI. 4 cases. ' ** 19. One premiss t|, and one Jf. Means indifferent. Conclusion, X the contrary of the extreme of the tt premiss with the other extreme, and also with its contrary. Ex. XX AE • JfEI .-. J (A», at). 8 cases. 20. Both premisses J|. Means indifferent. Conclusion.?. Ex. llAE-ltEI .-. ?|AI(. lease. "*"*' ** It will be an excellent exercise first to form all the cases of each and apply the rule ; secondly, to form the restdtints of all, and show that even when the conclusions are the same the resultants are different ; thirdly, to show that the conclusions in every case can be deduced from a continual application of the first five rules; and lastly, that everv one of the 676 syllogisms fiumishes a resultant and a conclusion consistent with one or more of the last 49, forming the third class, and for any det4-rminHte case of words selected must always be onn or othrr of tlu'S4; 49. Thtjre is nothing in all this beyond the reach of iutcUigeut boys that can do a sum in the rule of thrc«^ I * one word contains both A and E," or fAE. Observe also that the order in which the premisses are arranged differs from that used in the preceding articles, but that this order is always in- different, so far as the resultant and conclusion are concerned, though made a matter of some weight in the old logic. The mode of passing from the particular cases here worked, to the general case of ordinary logic, is given hereafter. Arts. 4U to 42. Examples of ordinary assertions will be found in Arts. 43 and 44. First Figure. 1. Barbara. All E is I, all A is E, .*. all A is I; fEi- fAe, .-. fAi, [1]. 2. Celdrent. No E is I, all A is E, .*. no A is I; fEI-fAe, .-. fAI, [1]. 3. Darn. All E is I, some A is E, .*. some A is I; fEi'tAE. .-. JAI, [3]. 4. FMo. No E is I, some A is E, .*. some A is not I; tEI * lAE, .-. JAi, [3]. Second Figure. 5. CesUr^. No I is R. all A is E, .-. no A is I ; fEI-fAc, .'. fAI. [1]. This is the same as No. 2. 6. Cdinestres. All I is E, no A is E, .*. no A is I ; fel * fAB, .-. fAI, [1]. ■ 7. Festlnd. No I is E, some A is E, .*. some A is not I ; fEI • JAE, .*. JAi, [3]. This is the same as No. 4. 8. Bdrokd. All I is E, some A is not E, .*. some A is not I : fel • JA^, .-. lAi, [3]. Third Figure. 9. Ddrapti. All E is I, all E is A, .*. some A is I : fEi * faE .-. :AI, [2]. 10. DtsamU. Some E is I, all E is A, .*. some A is I ; tEI * faE. /. lAI, [3]. 11. Ddtist All E is I, some E is A, .*. some A is I; fEi* JAB, .*. JAI, [3]. This is the same as No. 3. 12. FSlajftton. No E is I, all E is A, .-. some A is not I: tEI' faE, .-. JAi, [2]. 13. Bdkardo. Some E is not I, all E is A, .*. some A is not I ; JEi-faE, .-. jAi, [3]. 14. F&risdn. No E is I, some E is A, .*. some A is not I; fEI* JAE, .*. JAi, [3]. This is the same as No. 4. Fourth Figure. 15. Brdmantip. All I is E, all E is A, .*. some A is I; fel* t«E, .*. fal, [1], which is the full conclusion, and this implies JAI (art. 14, vii), which is the old conclusion, where JAI is used instead of fal, simply because the old logic had no terms to express the latter assertion as a conclusion, with A as the *' subject." Sir W. Hamilton introduced the phrase : " some A is all I," for fal, (art 43, vi. and note,) and dismissed the old form BraniayUip^ 16. Camihiis. All I is E, no E is A, .*. no A is I; fel 'fAE .*. fAI, [1]. This is the same as No. 6. t 32 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. [aRTS. 30, 31. 17. Dtmans. Some I is E, all E is A, /. some A is I; JEI* faE .*. JAI, [3]. This is the same as No. 10. 18. Fesdjpo. No I is E, all E is A, .'. some A is not I ; fEI • faE .'. JA?*, [2]. This is the same as No. 12. 19. Frestson. No I is E, some E is A, .*. some A is not I : fEI • JAE, .'. JAi, [3]. This is the same as No. 4. The teacher who has read Archbishop Thomson's Laws of Thought, will find 36 syllogisms given as Sir William Hamilton's, in each of the three figures, of which the Archbishop retains 22 in the first figure, and 20 in each of the others. All of Sir William Hamilton's, except 8, can be immediately solved by the processes here given ; and of these 8, 4 belong to the class of doubtful conclusions, and the other 4 are really not syllogisms, because they implicitly contain a fourth name,* and, when solved] lead also to doubtful conclusions. None of them have been ad- mitted by other logicians, and hence need not be further consi- dered. These are merely notes to help the teacher to translate his old books into these new symbols, and have nothing to do with the children. All remnants of merely medieval formalism and its consequences must be carefully kept from them. To resume : — 31. The three skeleton rules for syllogisms yielding certain con- clusions, and the two rules for syllogisms yielding doubtful conclu- sions, will enable the pupil to solve an immense number of ex- amples without hesitation. Suppose, for instance, we take the ten cases considered in the third kind of syllogism, art 26, (for example, the one JfAe • ffEi, .'. JfAi,) we may solve each of them by a con- tinual application of the rules. Thus JfAe means fAe ' JaE, and tfEi means fEi • fel. Taking each of the first with each of the second, we get cases to which the rules apply. Thus fAe • fEi, .-. fAi, [1]; fAe -fel, .'. J«i, [2]; JaE-fEi, .-. Jal, [3]; JaE • fel, .*. ?, [5] : the conclusion is then fAi (which implies J AI • Jat), Jai, (already implied in the last,) and Jal, that is, on the whole, JAI-fAi-Jal-Jai, or JfAi as already found. And so on for every possible case that can occur. These rules therefore embrace the whole ordinary theory of the syllogism, as enlarged by De Morgan and Hamilton. * Thus one of these syllogisms, reduced to a case of letters in words, is : No words have E without I, at least one word containing A is dif- ferent from at least one word containing E, .*. at least one word contain- ing A is different from at least one word containing I. Now the assertion that at least one word containing A is different from at least one word containing E, means that the firat contains (or does not contain) some other letter, say N, which the second does not (or does) contain. Then we have JAN and +E». There are therefore three premisses fEt, JAN, JE«. Then fEt • JE« .-. Jwl by [3], and J«I • JAN gives a doubtful conclusion, by [5], but contains the expression of Sir W. Hamilton's con- clusion, for we see that at least one word contains I without N, and at least one word contains both A and N, so that these words must be different. ARTS. 32 — 35.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 33 I 32. Again, the rules immediately enable the pupil to solve en- thymemes ; that is, when the conclusion and one premiss is given, the other can be found. Thus let the conclusion be f I, and one premiss be faE, then the other must be fel, by [1], which shows that the conclusion t«I can only belong to the first kind. Hence also if JAE were given as a premiss, having fal as a conclusion, we should see there must be an error. In fact, the only certain syllogisms with JAE as a premiss, are JAE 'fEI, .'. JAi, and JAE-fEi .-. JAI, (art. 27.) 33. Again, given a conclusion and a mean, we can find all the syllogisms which will produce it. Thus : Let JAI be the conclu- sion, and E or e the mean ; we see that t<^E * f Ei, •\ae ' f ei, faE * JEI, t«e • Jel, JAE * fEi, JAfi ♦ fei, and no others, will give JAI, the two first by [2] and the others by [3]. 34. We can also see whether any given syllogism is logically bad. For, stating the premisses, we can immediately read off" the correct conclusion, and compare it with the one given. Thus fAE ' fEi .*. JAI is wrong, the conclusion is Jal, leaving PAI. Thus logical fallacies are detected. The greater number of falla- cies in reasoning depend upon assuming incorrect premisses. One method of showing their error is to combine them logically with correct premisses and obtain conclusions properly drawn, which by their absurdity show the absurdity of the premiss which involved them. 35. We do not disprove a conclusion, by showing that either one or both of the premisses state precisely the contrary of what is true ; for if we change J and f into f and J in either premiss sepa- rately or in both together, we get a conclusion which is consistent with the former. This should be showi>* for each kind of syllo- gism, thus — First kind. fAe • fEi .-. fA^, [1]. But tAc • JEi .-. ?, [4] ; +Ae • fEi .'. .P[4] ; and JAe ' JEi .'. ? [5] ; and a doubtful conclusion is consistent with any conclusion whatever. Second kind. f^^E • fEi .*. JAI, [2]. But JciE • fEi .-. Jal, [3] ; t«E; JEi .-. JA?:, [3], and +«E • JEJ .'. P [5]. Now JAI is consistent with either or both of Jal and JAi, see Art. 14, i Third kind. JAE-fEi.-.JAI, [3]. But JAE • JEi .-. ?,[5] ; fAE • fEi.-. Jal,[2]; and fAE • +Ei .'. +ai,[3]. And JAI is consistent with either or both of Jal, and Jai. To disprove a conclusion, we must prove the correctness of an assertion which is inconsistent with it. Thus to disprove fA?, we must prove JA/, or fAI, or \ai, and the various ways of pro- ving each of these with a given mean are obtained immediately from the skeleton rules, as shown in art. 33. But if none of the pre- misses required for this purpose are correct, we cannot disprove the conclusion, even if we do not admit the premisses on which it is based. Of course, it does not follow that the conclusion was right, but merely that we have not found out the proper form of mean for disproving it syllogistically ; and the choice of means a 34 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. [aRTS. 35 — *67. ARTS. 37 — 39.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 35 t is unlimited. More often, however, the concUision is disproved by some of the inconsistent assertions being established by direct observation or experiment, and not syllogistically. The favourite method of disproving one or both of the premisses, merely shows that a wrong line of argument has been followed, not that the con- clusion is wrong. Thus, assuming the transition from words and letters to ordinary instances, made in art. 40, let the argument be : — "Pompey (A,) is a man (E); all men are mortal (I); hence Pompey is mortal." RerePompey being an individual name is mark- ed A.1, (art. 20,) so that the first premiss is J:A,E or tA,c, and the second is fEi, the conclusion being fAr/, by [1], giving JA,I. Now suppose we deny fAi^?, and declare JAiC, (Pompey is a dog, for ex- ample), and again deny fEi and declare JEi, (at least Enoch and Elijah were not mortal), then JAie • JEi.'. ?, and does not show JAii (or that the dog Pompey is non-mortal !), that is, does not disprove fAii (or that Pompey, be he man or dog, is mortal). 36. On the other hand, if we take one of the premisses and com- bine it with an assertion which is inconsistent with the conclusion taken as a second premiss, we shall find as a conclusion some- thing inconsistent with the second premiss. This is also best shown for each kind of syllogism separately. First kind. fAe ' fEi .'. fAi, [1]. Assertions inconsistent with fAe are J A'?, fAE, fiie ft » „ fEt are JEi, fEI, fei »» ♦, )) fAi are jAi, fAI, fai. Now combine fAe with each of the three last, and we shall get one of the three second in each case, thus : — fAe ' tAl .-. JEi, [3] ; fAc • fAI .'. JEi, [2] ; f A^ • fai .'. fei, [1 ]. Again combine fEt \^th each of the three last and we shall get one of the three first in each case, thus — fEI • lAi .-. :Ae, [3] ; fEr fAI .-. fAE, [1] ; fE^ • fai ,'. +A«, [2]. Second kind. faE • fEi .-. JAI, [2] Inconsistent with faE are JaE, fAE, fae n n fEi ... JEi, fEI, fei It „ JAI is fAI only. Then faE • fAI .'. fEI, [1] ; fEi ' fAI .-. fAE, [1]. Third kind. t AE • fEI .: JAI, [3] Inconsistent with J AE is fAE only ** „ fEi are JE/, fEI, fei tf •• JAI is fAI only. Then JAE • fAI .'. JE/, [3] ; fEi • fAI .'. fAE, [1]. These syllogisms are sometimes called the opponents of those from which they have been derived, but they have not been usually treated with proper fulness. For example, only two ojiponents have been allowed in each case, whereas it has just been shown that the first kind of syllogism has six opponents. 37. Will, then, one of the premisses combined with the con- elusion as a second premiss, give the other premiss as a new conclusion ? Try for each kin 1, taking the three examples just chosen. « ^\ n First. tAc-fAi.-. JEI, which is notfE?:, but is consistent with it ; and fEi • fAi .'. Jae which is also consistent with fAe. Second. faE • JAI .-. ? [4], and fEi • JAI .-. ?, [4], which results are of course consistent with fEi and faE respectively. Third. JAE • JAI .-. ?, [4], fEi • JAI .'. ?, [4], which again are con- sistent with fE^ and JAE respectively. The new conclusion, therefore, in each case differs from, but is consistent with the other premiss. 38. We may therefore believe that if any three assertions consis- tent with the premisses and conclusion of a syllogism are assumed, and any two of them are taken as premisses, the conclusion will be consistent with the third. This belief will be raised to a cer- tainty by considering that the premisses and conclusion are all three of them mere portions of the resultant, which was produced by the joint action of the premisses, so that if merely the resultant were given, all three assertions, namely the two premisses and the conclusion, could be deduced from it. This can readily be done by the process in art. 19, hitherto followed in obtaining the con- clusion from the resultant. The Teacher is recommended to set up a resultant in counters, and obtain from it all the possible results respecting A,E and E,I as well as A,I. The pupil may also be exercised in deducing other assertions respecting the three names A, E, I, from a given resultant. Thus, in the resultant in art. 22, all words containing both A and E also contain I. This is shown by JAKI and fAKi, which must neces- Barily involve the fact that at least one word which does not con- tain both A and E, that is, which is anon- AE- word, (and which is therefore an Ae-, aB-, or ae-wovd,) does not contain I. Now the re- sultant agrees with this by means of Jaei, although fAel, fAei show that no words have A without bl, and ?ael shows that although there is at least one word with neither A nor E (shown by Xaei) yet, even if there are more such words, it is doubtful whether even one of them contains I. A gain ?aEl ' faEi show that though the existence of any words having E without A is doubtful, yet if any such exist, that is, if JaEI, they all will also contain I. The consequence of which is that there must in that case be at least one word which does not contain E without A, that is which is a non-aE-word, (and which will therefore be an A E-, Ae-, or ae-word,) and also does not contain I; that is, that J^(AEi Aei, aei); and we see, in fact, that though fAEiand fAei, yet Xaei. Judicious exercise of this kind, illustrated by examples in words and drawing of diagrams, will materially strengthen the reasoning powers, and at the same time may be made the source of much interest by presenting unexpected problems. 39. The method here adopted is complete and systematic, but the teacher may find it more interesting and instructive at first to adopt an unsystematic method, and then come to system as a means of classifying cases which have already occurred. The pre- sent principles with the use of counters are eminently adapted for such a course. Various cases of the same syllogism, arising from . determining the ? compounds in the premisses as J or f , have ■>-■ .f 36 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. [art. 30. also to be worked out and their results contrasted. This may be done without recourse to the skeleton rules, which may be reserved as convenient " skeleton keys" to pick future logical locks. It should be remembered that the real thing to be obtained and thoroughly understood is the resultant, which is altogether neg- lected in ordinary logical treatises, and that the conclusion is only the statement of jwr^ of the facts contained in the resultant, the whole of which can alone completely determine what is affirmed, denied, or left in doubt by the premisses, when taken jointly. For these purposes the following modification of the forms in which the investigations were conducted will be found convenient. The table on this page shows how the ten definite forms of the third kind of syllogism may be exhibited at one view upon a slate or on the black board, and contrasted with the original indefinite form (involving doubtful compounds). The letters are first writ- ten down, and their columns for each case ruled. The letters for the premisses occupy the upper, and those for the resultant the Premisses. ARTS. 39, 40.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. AE I + 2 3 4 5 6 7 •f + 8 9 + 10 + + + + + ■f + + -• 2, Ae + + t + t 4- t t + + + + 2. aB t + + + t + t t + + + 2.2, + ae EI + ■f X + + t + + + i t + + ■t- + + + + + + + + + t Et t t t t t t t t t t n f el + + + + + t t t + ■f t + + t + JAE ei + + tt«E + + + ■f + + + + + ttA^ + + + + ttA. Jt^r^ ttA. n«E Xfae ttA^ IXAE UAE m ttE/ ttE» 1 JtE» I ttEt ttE» ttEt ttEi ttE» ttE^• ttEt Resultants. AEI 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 + + + + + + + + + + + + + t A Ki t t t t t t t t t t ? A^I 26 24 t + + t t t t t 2b 2, t 23 Act 2324 t + + t > + + t t 2324 + 3, aFA t + + + + t + t t + + f + t aEi t t t t t t t t t t 3, ael 2«25 + + t t t t + + t 2«25 t 3,23 aei 2325 + + t ■f + :tA« + t ■♦■ ttA» + ttA* 2325 + JAI :ai ttA» X\ai XUi Xf"i tAI- Xol iJAi • •i 37 I under part. The symbols J, f, ?, for the indefinite form, stand on the left; those for the various definite forms, on the right. Each pre- miss is written at full length. The several columns are numbered for convenience of reference. In the columns of the premisses appear those variations of the premisses enumerated at the close of art. 26, p. 27. The corresponding columns of the resultant are worked out from them in the way there explained, and the limitate indices are employed as there introduced. Under each column of the pre- misses are written the short forms of the premisses, and under each column of the resultant the short form of the conclusion. The order of the cases is that adopted in art. 26. This mode of workmg will be found convenient not merely for contrasting several definite forms corresponding to one indefinite form of syllogism, but for working out a number of unrelated syllogisms, without writing the letter part over and over again. 40. We are now prepared to make the transition from the par- ticular case of words containing letters, to the general case of things possessing attributes distinguished by names, and thus to transfer all the knowledge and mechanical faciUty already gained to the propositions with which Logic ordinarily deals, — propositions which from their abstract nature are generally ill- adapted for elementary exercise. The pupils will probably have been to a museum, or they may be taken to one, or to any labelled collection of objects, for the purpose of the present course.* Their attention must be drawn to the fact that each object is labelled, and that each label contains several names, and that these names have been given in order to recall to the mind of observers certain thoughts or feelings or sensations which they experienced when they fully examined the objects, not only externally but internally, not only by sight, but by touch, and occasionally the other senses, by breaking, dissect- ing, weighing, burning, trying with acids, observing habits of life, growth, and decay, if the object had been alive ; in short, by every possible way that they could imagine which would lead them to distinguish one from another. That any simple name when placed upon an object implied a simple sensation experienced by the observer, but that, in general, names were put for shortness which implied a great many simple sensations, leaving it to dictionaries or special treatises to explain what they were. Perhaps the teacher may be able to go so far as to explain that there is presumed to be m each object an antecedent of such sensations, and that this antecedent is called an attribute, quality, or property of the object. Ihis IS a difficult matter to make clear, and it must be approached with caution, and always by drawing the thought from the pupil. JNext make the pupil observe that these labels, and the words on them, bear a wonderful resemblance to words and the letters they contain ; that if the labels were taken off you could sort them first * Most schools have museums of quite sufficient extent for this purpose ; but, if necessary, the furniture, books, ink-pots, slates, &c. in a school- room might be labelled for the occasion. Collections of shells, minerals, flowers, or stuffed animals are the most convenient. D 38 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. [aRTS. 40,41. into those containing such a name and those without it ; then could sort the first set into those containing another name and those not containing it, and the second set- likewise ; and so on. We miorht, in fact, suppose that the names were represented by our letters A, E, I, &c., and that the labels not having the names A E,I, had the letters a, e, i respectively, to show that the names A E 1 had not been omitted by oversight, but that the other obiects to which these names had not been affixed really had not the names A, E, 1. This once done, the labels and our previous slips of paper and counters become one and the same thing 15ut now the slips or labels no longer mean words ; the capital letters A E I no longer indicate that the words contain those vowels, and the small letters a, e, i, that these words do not contain them. The slips or labels or counters now mean objects m the museum. The letters A, E, I are convenient abridgments of the names whicli the obiects bore in the museum in order to certify tha. those objects had certain corresponding properties. The Presence of the letters a, e, i, indicate the absence of the names denoted by A E T and hence the absence of the corresponding properties m the objects. Also draw attention to the fact that many different objects have some one name on their labels indicating the exist- ence of the same property in all, and that almost all the objects have several different names on each of their labels, mdicating that one object has several different properties By this means the pupil will readily appreciate the facts indicated m art. b. 41 Now make the transition to language in general. Show how we have named things, (taking material objects first, then their actions, &c.,) on account of some sensations they aroused in ns how we have applied the same name, as man, to various objects because many of the sensations they aroused were identical and how, if each sensation had a different simple name, any name like man would be in fact a compound name made up of the names ot all the diff-erent sensations which must concur in order for us to have the very compound sensation which the simple word man now recalls. Turn to a bird; elicit (rather than show) many pro- perties in common between a man and a bird as ^^^f fJ»Pj™ both are animals and both two-legged. Then elicit their diffe- rences, as feathers, wings, &c., and lead to the conclusion that birds are non-men, and men are non-birds. Find other i^on-men as quadrupeds, which are also non-birds, ^ow abbreviate the ^ords Man into M, Bird into B, Two-legged into T, and Quad- ruped into Q, when of course m, h, t, q will be names of non-men, Zlrds, non-two-legged, non-quadrupeds. Ehcit he following expressions of observations made on these object.^ Not only tM^ giving as a logical consequence, art. 14, vi., JMT and jmi, that' is, " not even one man is non-two-legged, every man is two- legged, every thing which is not two-legged is not a man, but also, as a new observation, u- j» „^+ « mon " +wT ''at least one two-legged thmg (as a bird) is not a man, Bo'thBt the logical ?mT is determined, and we have really ++M< II tMT •mflmT-mt, in which every compound must be thoroughly explained and exemplified by the pupils. Again, find ARTS. 41 — 4o.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 39 fMQ, giving as a logical consequence, art. 14, v., IMq and JwQ, that is, " not one man is a quadruped, every man is a non-quad- ruped, every quadruped is a non-man," and also, as a new obser- vation, Xmq " at least one non-man (as a bird) is a non-quadruped," so that the logical ?mq is determined, and we have really IfMQ II Wq-lKq-lmq-lmq, no term being left in doubt. Similarly deal with fB^ and find J6T, so that really JfB^. Also find fBQ and Ihq, so that JfBQ. Next lead the pupil to observe that fM^ and fB^ show that what- ever you can say of a Man or of a Bird, you really do say of a Two- legged thing, so that there is no property possessed by a man or a bird which is not possessed by at least one two-legged thing. (This is an important general principle, see p. 41, note * ) But as JmT and J&T, there is certainly at least one property possessed by at least one two-legged thing which is not possessed by any one man, and also at least one property, {not necessarily the same as the last,) which is not possessed by any one bird. Show that if it were otherwise, that is, if we had fmT and fhT, in addition to fM^ and fB^ we should have ffMf, and ffB^, in which case every single two-legged thing would be both a man and a bird ! ! 42. Thus the assertions which we have lately considered respect- ing the existence of certain letters in certain words, can all be read as assertions respecting the attributes residing in certain things. In fact all our thoughts may be considered as slips of paper or counters, each containing some one distinctive mark or name which "denotes" the particular slip or counter, and each con- taining the marks or names of the particular attributes of those thoughts which are " con-noted" by that first distinctive mark. Once reduced to this form, all assertions whatev^er become pre- cisely the same as assertions respecting letters in words, where the word forms the "de-notation," and the several letters, being the whole of the distinctive marks or attributes in the word, are its " con-notation."* 43. A large number of assertions must now be analyzed. Ex- amples may be collected from all elementary treatises on Logic. * The order of the letters is important in a word, and must be con- sidered as an attribute. But this may be here disregarded. Thus, so far as possessing the letters I,P,T, and no others, pit and tip are the same. But in writing down the letters we introduce a new attribute, order. In thinking of things, this order is unimportant. "Whether we say a bird is two-legged and feathered, or feathered and two-legged, is of no conse- quence. This little point of difference should be borne in mind by the teacher, but need not be mentioned unless he sees that a diflBiculty arises in the pupil's mind ; and then the explanation must be elicited by questioning. The distinction, however, between the two cases is that mathematically important distinction between commutative and non-com- mutative operations ; and Boole's mathematical theory of logic depends mainly upon the commutative character of attributes, or iadiffcrouoe in the order of mentioning them. d2 40 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. [art. 43. The following specimens will show the relations of the present strict notation to conimon language, and some of the difficulties to be contended with * For convenience some of the words are placed in ( ), and others in [ ] ; the letters A and E refer to these words respectively, so that the expressions have the same form as those considered in arts. 13 and 14. But in practice the letters should be varied, and may generally be chosen so as to recall the words, as in art. 41. i. All (the righteous) are [happy], fAe, or "not one righteous man is non-happy ;" implying JAE, or " at least one righteous man is happy," and Jae, "at least one non-righteous man is non-happy,'* and leaving absolutely doubtful, whether there is or is not even one non-righteous man who is happy, or PaE. ii. No (human virtues) are [perfect], fAE, implying JAe and JrtE, but leaving ?ae. In putting these into language, remember a is the name of a non-human, not of an in-human, virtue. The forms fAE • JaE show that all perfect virtues are non-human. If we were to write " all perfect virtues are not human," the phrase would be ambiguous, and might also mean either JAE, (" although all perfect virtues may not be human, some are"), which is of course wrong. iii. Some (possible cases) are [probable], JAE, or "at least one possible case is a probable case." Observe that " some" in Logic • The first six of these specimens are the six "judgments" of Arch- bishop Thomson (" Laws of Thought, § 78, p. 135 of tenth edition, 1869), which he SATubolizes, in order, by the capital letters A, E, I, O, U, Y. In Sir W. Hamilton's formal language (i^., § 79), translated into the present svmbols, thev art — i. A. All A is some E || fAe i'. E. No A is E || fAE iii. I. Some A is some E || ^AE iv. O. Some A is no E || JAtf V. U. All A is all E || ttA {ib.) : — vii. 71. No A is some E || laH \ viii. a>. Some A is not some E I| J(AN,Ew). Another form of this last assertion is somewhat enigmatically stated by Sir W. Hamilton as : " some A is not some A." This reads like a cc»ntra- diction in terms, but really means l (AN, A«), which is the same as art. 14, note, i. 1) The assertion +(AN, E») states that there is at least one thing called A which (possessing the attribute N) is different from at least 'Q°7pt^i'::^ ';ie"ff;%r/.:s:.»'*-' r ^rp- rj "n7nt'rtlJJ1^r^tr»S a more advanced stage * ^ ImJ Wl for ♦ The real intention of the (rnun^ll^ flmn. fc«^ -.wlj. *v i terms subject, copula, and pr^^S^ ^^SSJ^^ ^"^^ the relation fA,., in its most^c^Sm^ ^f^ ^\ M^i^ ^ ,TVT. one thing caUed A, was also c^S^ ^thli oL^^ift^'' ^i*^*. ^ were also called E, in En^rlish" A i. P^" U, ?!l2 T°?u *^/^*'^ -^ . an^ndiv^dual in the set orthin6;''E tt ^SLS^^.^ (which m many langmffes is oolv AsnaML^i^ Vk i J . S^*P"* the same thing. But this T* ^ - "T^iit^. 1 il7 TT i^*^ *" thingA,, and others also, for eaiir " ^5^ni „2!I!i^J?V2' E- Then. u«tead of sp^ng^JT. X til ll' ESS? j^il^^^ .poken of as " the E thi^" Ld whm jT^ ^/SST^'AT C,. D,. and other things possessed Ok alMtlT. bvEt I*"^ "•* A,. B,, !^>=t . *' * '^ <*r JtR/: p^o* st&d^^h^'r^e.Sr^,^ ^ ^' •' H ynu ckar tisit to my - aU hUihUxfrt m F4lung». Of t>^, Mn4 «bo " Mue ioilividiMl £.(hiiig»a«v m.n.l' .«hW" coi1inff tanMiiini not m> |tfc•i^ and oOm go Viyood the mtak. Hicoe the diiKc^r vw rc< ov» tt <«o eti.. \^; aJtflrijjp the «|.als **rawE m im< (J." or 1>V. w»i •" ih» ol^bv nH/A/;;t„^ tJto •iilmct, -H* E b O." cir fEG. llui Kn«it cod. tapn then ftR«iabavi XBO and fEil, fwit wasiooit fuinkl that vtt ^Mbi »<« tkj other ^y Ortqr, «ad my with inputl tnitlj, '^Mcnd O mlL** wrj^ G U K" Uiuf maida^ tbemtimtf i»to a »uhjf<4, which «m a oooMMit |i t«t«ha-of kgic about it; Md fcr Ujit vrouu^.ty this not*, hm l.*.n wHttfl^ to Ao«r the tctcher the fo- ntKo* which ore railly xu^nX to be nr[irmol 46 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. [aRTS. 45 — 47. for the raoraent our definition of an Englishman, the marks by which we find him out. But it is not the connotation or meaning of the word EngHshman. Bearing this in mind, the teacher will have no difficulty with the cases treated in other books, and with the distinctions of essence (which belongs to the connotation) and accident (which does not belong to, but is not inconsistent with, the connotation). Observe that in the last case fPm, fPn, and fpMN, gives, by the general condition, JPMN * t(PMyi, PmN, Pmn, J9MN) • l^ipMii, j77wN, pnm) ' J'(i>wN, pmri) ' l\pMn, pmn) ; that is, in the instance given, there will be in the room at least one Eng- lishman with a blue coat and buff waistcoat, and at least some one who is not an Englishman, that will either not have a blue coat, or not a buff* waistcoat, or have neither one nor the other ; and there will be also at least one person without a blue coat, who is certainly not an Englishman, but may or may not have a buff waistcoat ; and lastly, there will be at least one person without a buff waistcoat, who is certainly not an Englishman, but may or may not have a blue coat. 46. Disjunctive assertions can now be understood. Thus " all A is either B or C," nieans simply fAhc, or the name A is never found without at least one or other of the names B and C. But the assertion is ambiguously worded, for it may or may not imply that A can be both B and C. If A cannot be both, we have fABC in addition. Hence the assertion " all A is either B or C" means, at full, either fAhc'ViABC, ABc, AtC), or t(ABC, Afec)-J»(ABc, AfcC), the remaining compounds being doubtful. Whenever an ambiguous assertion is made, both its meanings should be dis- covered, and in all trains of reasoning, each of the meanings should be separately considered, and then the various conclusions should be separately exhibited, as if each had been originally derived from a single unambiguous assertion. This is the only certain way to avoid en'or. Other ambiguities are pointed out in art. 43. All such ambiguities should be avoided, if possible, and the use of the present symbols in place of or as an aid to ordinary language, will render their avoidance always possible. When the second kind of assertions are dealt with, similar ambiguities will also arise, as will be seen later on, (art. 59, i, j. 66, 67, 68). 47. The impossibility of referring to any text-book to explain the method of teaching logic to children, which I ani here en- deavouring to indicate, must be my apology for entering at so much length into minute details. What has been here advanced will however suffice, I hop^, to enable any teacher who has him- self studied some elementary treatise on logic,* to apply the ARTS. 47, 18.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 47 * JF. Stanley Jevons, Elementarj' Lessons in Logic, deductive and induc- tive, with copious questions and examples, and a vocabulary of logical terms, London, Macmillan and Co., 1870, small 8vo., pp. 340, contains almost all that is wanted. Lesson 23 contains Prof. Jevons's own arrange- ment of Dr. Boole's system, which is the foundation of that here adopted, and it is my duty to mention that it was through Prof. Jevons's Substi- tution of Similars, 1869, and Pure Logic, 1864, that T was induced to study method I advocate to every case which presents itself, and to solve every example furnished so far forth as the simple assertion and syllogism are concerned. 48. But the simple assertion and the syllogism are the mere beginnings of logical studies. Far more complicated assertions involving the composition of any number of names, and combined in any variety of ways, have to be considered by the advanced student, but of course cannot be presented to a child, as much more highly developed mental powers, combined with a much greater range of general knowledge, are required to comprehend the mere intention of the investigations. Much might be done by extending the examples of words containing or not containing certain letters ; but the more advanced student would feel this to be a childish game (as in fact it is, and is meant to be,) unless he could leel that it had a real application to the nature which sur- rounds him. Hence I do not recommend proceeding beyond the point already reached, with assertions of the nature hitherto con- sidered. Numerically definite assertions, although extremely im- portant, and really easily exemplified by definite collections of words containing or not containing certain letters, are also scarcely adapted for children, even when presented in the simple manner here advocated. The utmost that can be done in this way, is to make clear the very simple case, that if most of the words in a given collection contain A, and also most of them contain E, then at least one of them contains both A and E. This is easily illus- trated by a case like this. AAAAAAAaaaaa e e e e e EEEEEEE. ( Dr. Boole's abstruse mathematical system of logic. As my plan bears in its foundations a great resemblance to Prof. Jevons's, they might appear identical on a superficial examination. It is necessary therefore to state, that the resemblance is entirely superficial, and that my views are not only more extensive than Prof. Jevons's, but aim at accomphshing all that is contained in Dr. George Boole's Investigation of the Laws of Thought, on which are founded the mathematical theories of Logic and Probabilities, (London, 1854, 8vo., pp. 424,) without his mathematical expression, and without those doubtful points of theory on which his mathematical views are based, and also at including the whole of Prof. Augustus Be Morgan's Formal Logic, or the Calctilus of Inference, Necessary and Probable, (Lon- don, 1847, 8vo., pp.336), and his more recent Syllabus of a proposed System of Logic (London, 1860, 8vo., pp. 72), and of furnishing a com- plete explanation of the fundamental theories of Sir William Hamilton's New Analytic, as presented in ArchbisJiop William Thomson's Outline of the necessary Laws of Tl).ought, a treatise on pure and applied Logic, (London, 10th thousand, 1869, 8vo., pp. 304). Some account of these three latter systems is given in Prof. Alexander Bain's Logic, Part I., Deduction, (London, 1870, 8vo., pp. 279), to which, and to Mr. Thomas Fowler's Elements of Deductive Logic (3rd ed., Oxford, 1869, pp. 176), the teacher who shrinks from studying Archbishop Thomson, or the great works of Dr. Boole and Prof. De Morgan, is referred for further infor- mation. Br. F. Ueberweg's System of Logic and History of Logical Doc- trines, translated by T. M. Lindsay, (London, Longman, 1871, pp. 690, 8vo,) gives a full historical account of the old logic. 48 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. [aRTS. 48, 49. ARTS. 49 — 51.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 49 Here are 12 words of which only the A's and E's are written, of which 7 contain A, 7 contain E, 5 do not contain A, and 5 do not contain h. By arranging them as above, it is clear that at least 2 must contain both A and E ; but as they could be arranged thus— AAAAAAAaaaaa EEEEEEEeeeee, we might have as many as 7 words containing both A and E, and may have any intermediate number between 2 and 7. Particular cases of this simple nature may be readily solved by elementary arithmetic : but the general statement involves algebraical con- oiuerations. Passing over these, and assertions respecting pure combi- nations, we come to what really form the most frequent and most important case,— assertions respecting the consistency of other assertions The greater part of all actual ratiocination turns upon the test of consistency, and the whole doctrine of probabilities can be naade to rest upon its proper development. Yet in ordinary treatises on Logic this principal part of the subject is usually dis- missed in a few pages, with one or two almost self-evident examples, under the head of Complex or Hypothetical Propo- sitions and Syllogisms. At the end of a lecture already far too long. It would be out of place for me to attempt giving this class of assertions their proper position; and, fortunately for my present purpose, the real development of their theory is so far beyond any child s mental powers, that it would be useless to make the attempt in these hints for teaching logic to children. But I must endeavour to give some account of the elementary notions, not only because they are usually insufficiently explained, but because some of the most ordinary processes of reasoning in common life, and in trea- tises on geometry, turn upon their application. 49. We are already familiar with cases of consistent and incon- Bistent assertions (art. 15). In the syllogism we have learned that the premisses and conclusion are all consistent with the resultant and with one another, and that although assertions wfthX nn' T'^ *hf Premif es are not necessarily inconsistent with the conclusion, they will necessarily be inconsistent with the resultant (arts 31 to 39). In this consideration of consistency, we did not trouble ourselves with the truth or co.Tectness, th^t is the consistency with actual fact, of the assertions themselves i3ut It will be more convenient in future to speak of this truth, not ?!''. f{ importance m itself, but as being consistent or not With ^e truth of other assertions. " Supposing an assertion to be true, will other assertions be true or false ?" This is the question which InL *^7r^ ofainnvestigations into the consistency of Isser- mZ'tion'^'lT.l ^"?''^ T'*^^^ of proposing it came the deno- mination hypothetical." Again, the results are frequently stated namP^T' ^^^^^V-^I^ 9a«^«^ that will be true," and hence the n^me disjimchve, which implies that the two cases are incon- ftsefft ^""^ WK "'^*'''^- \"«ther form in which this case presents Itself IS : Whenever or wherever this happens, that will happen " Ihis 18 a purer form of stating the question of consistency. What- w it m sufficient to place them on their sides, iImb [^ . H | . AllcovntcrM 8opW will be subject to this law. or form a gnmn. culled » unicate or Yfhich one must be present, and wir one am be rir^- sent, although the conditions assigned hare not boon anOkaml lo determine which one that will be. 63. If two events X", Y" are compatihlf, or eampfmO^, the two assertions X', Y' are consistent, and liirncv tbo two IriHK* X Y may co-exiM The two events may tluT„ bi« wid to fona n iymvfe^ event, (X.Y)', [where the full stop or dut (.) » n*d •*r«m/'l the two assertions form a complex ascrikin (X.Y)'; nmi the two truths form a complex truth, or simplv » fowpUr X.Y. Here be careful to distinguish a complex X.Y,' -• • X 5ri >< • Those foar €oinpl«<3Dt6 Wkay bo readily rcoMmbered fi« axmI that at Vtani t%so of thetn m^rM be preicnt^ to fulfil tiiO fcwnrral coaditkinii (arta. 12. l;^ 1 1>. It iti knpoflrfeant t^t thiM re^^imbUiieo (but not identity.) in form aud dilferanoo in mo&ning should bo tliorongbly woU uudontood. 55. r vc in the lamc way, we »«yi thai if JX.Y, then eithier ;.X.V.yi, or JX-Y.r, and w on for cm<+» K of ibreo trutlift. wo mu^itt havi) *.(X-Y.Zw X.V.:, X,y,2tt ^-y-Sp *.Y.Z, x.Y.2, ir^.Z, r,tf,T), And no o« for complexee of a«iy «ninb«r of tnaths). tbo modo of fodrnuUion bcinir ixrwiwly tbo Kuoe a* for oonipoiind^ of any niimlKr of namcft. The t^wThor, in dnvnlofiin^ thi» «*t of eom^mutf^ wilU of course, iinx^tvd with oountcnrs in a manner prec«w1y (nmilar to tlua exp^uvd in rvforeDCD to oocnpo«nd« in vt. 17. t Ml Kow obaenrc that. «t OQlllf one in each of thejc »c if wo lewiw thut o«c i# porc«cntv we know that all tbo rem ax^ abe««U Th«K, if the tixcntn X^ and Y" nre focnpettible, that i«. if both th^ aAf^rtionsi X' and Y' arc coa5i«t<9it> UicnJX.Y. and tX.y, ar,Y. x.jf), or. th# annrtioii X' ia inoon- •bUynt w ith //. and htAh 7^ and / ar<» idu^ether fal:*©, Thn^ if it b \vm Ihiit Join tnKtA oi» KUhard . ereo if noiUikig is aascrted abo«t calling. JlliiBtfatfi thi4 cnae by n yan*.*(y of flinikr ample cxnmplM of erorj-dny life. 07. If wc know tbai one or mare of scycnil mdi oomplesM iM nr«*ont, wo know for a c<^rtiiinty that oil tbo o4Ii6t» are ftb^^t* ling, if wo know J.lX.V, ^.y)^ that is, thaX either both tbt 52 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. [arTS. 57—59. theftf know ^HY?^\*C^''J"''''- °^ "^"''«'- "^ ^^^"^ happen. hapDen sinX w!'^' f •^'' '^' '*■• "'^» "^'t^er of them can tenTt^^alUrrr; rse17th™7tl"*" "*f '^''Pr "'^«- neither of them happen sb^y. ^ '"'*° '"^ ""'^ '''" a set weTn^r*! *^* ""^ T^ 7 ""'•^ complexes are absent from aTd"didU^earon'hr^ ^Glneral/J'thf^'^h'''^'^'^-^?' ^■'"'»^^' ^^hich involves :. (X.^.-Yr/tr'tl^^^^^^^^^^^^ +Y, then Xx. Or, as it is frequently put, if X" hacDen? V ' Arl not happen, or if Y" happens, X' does not hanr^n^TL ^ e^P^ess.on for either of Xse'^.^o^J^JLtSs iftheSe (a.) fA.i implies ti(X ?/ »• V n/\ "V j v/ &^"x'l^'^''V^Y'•^>on^^^ of both' I' Tdt'tr: ^% is^r^'e!T- Vs'T''. if ^Y-'S'' I' 1^^ ^^ ^^n^be eoneluded from the supposition Thl't I' l^ '^!,, J:^^-$. "ifVutl^X' irl-^-^""^' 'i'-^'' "■' ^ -^ *™-. Y'is true," suDiisidon h^t Y' .Q.r, or R, in virtue of + 7p ^n ^""'^'""g ^ ^^aonot contain Q 9 and r; but by tY « andS?'' ??judicatam c&tulenmt." This'was a cowar^rpr^riT 'bufn?r^^^ 'T^."J been given, we have ty and t-, and L^cT^.^.^ tfo« '"''" '^""^ They^'s^Xte^^SfTt^S^lr^lS^^^^^^^ pcnd upon views of nature have been siTr^H^ i, *v°^'= ^^'^^ de- more accurate observations and LwrimenK ^J''' ^¥ J^'^its ot the deductive logic we havp tn »..:. ^ . , """e™ mduction. For "clearly" anf" rtinctTy" det^^n' J'^t f* ^'^"f'^ "''J'*' '« ^ word is by its visible leVtJrs iC^.^^- '^ 1°^" "«"*«'«. as a written altogether ideal, and nev?; eSts i^ anv ."*' <^»f ''?«»»" thus formed is Hence the distribution oruchTdhriduTlJoZ^r '' ""'"*"'' '■'^ ^^- 8»)- or ultimate classes, is al^pZwi^l¥^^T"^°'t^'''f'^°"<><' arc merely collections of rude^nceitf "'L h» 1i °*"" ^ "^ Aristotle and not on an accurate I^ttTgS'r dStio'ns ""Zr .i''"?"" ««' J?/ietfT;,:rsr.^!;,sr^^^^^^ -in..,)mu.tbc...cgaidcda'trtK'c':X.tr^^^^^^^^^^^ ART. 70.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 59 but I felt that a mere oral exposition of the method proposed would have been barely comprehended when heard, and would have been forgotten immediately. To have a chance of doing any good therefore, I was obliged to furnish something approaching to a Teacher's Guide— to be carefully concealed fro m the pupil , are'nTv^deally or ah^lutely, but merely relatively, « clear' ' (sufficient to distinguish their objects from all others) and ''distinct" (sufficient to dis- tinffui^'sh all the parts of any one from all the parts of any other concep- tion). An attribute becomes simply a mark (as in the old nota, reKti-npiou), in the sense of art. 40. ^ ^, v ^ aa Let both the conceptions A and B be of the class C ; then, by art. 44, i p. 43, tAc and tBt", and on developing the resultant we have, smce J(AC, «;, BC, *.), ^^^^^^^^ 2.A5C, 2,«BC, F«^C, fABc, fAbc, faBc, Xabc, (compare art. 24). This gives the diagram 1, where all the different am- ^ ^ ' biguities are clearly shown by the blank spaces. This most general case, where none of the limitates or doubtful compounds are determined, 80 that it is not certain whether there are or are not any conceptions besides A or besides B which are mcluded in the class C, has not been distinctly contemplated by the old logic. The sub-vaneties JfAc with tB., or tA(j with ;tB^ have also been omitted The case reaUy first ' ' ' taken into consideration was Xt Ac with 2. A- C- B JfBc, giving diagram 2 ; compare the observations on the predicate, p. 44, note. In this case the conceptions A and B were said to be co-ordinated, and each of them to hesub-ordmated to the conception C, which was in turn said to be super-ordmated to them. The resultant is ^^^^^ 2,2,A/.C, 232,«BC, 2,2^bC, fABp, fAic, t«Bc, Xabc, which is more determinate than before on account of J(«C, 6C) ; but there are four compounds stiU left in doubt, concerning which we can make '^Let^^n^^^^^^^ addition to tfA. and tfB., so that not one of the conceptions A is subordinate to any one of the conceptions B, and con- vSnot one of the conceptions B is subordinate to any one of the con- ceptions A. Observe that, as Xabe gives %ab, we could not assume t AB SpTv, atthat would leave ?.^ or assume ffAB, as that would give faj ; 80 that it AB was the only assumption involving f AB that could possibly be made The effect of this is to make fABC, and consequently, through The'^itates 2. and 2„ to make jA^C and >BC, and then again t^^^^^^^^ the hmitates 23 and 24, to leave iab^y fA as in diagram 3, which is formed from 3. < c the last by filling it up to meet this Lb case. The conceptions A and B are now entirely separate or incompatible ; but they remain co-ordi^iate^^ suh- ordinate to the conception C. This case is not ^^^^^^^''^^i:^^'^'^^^ ^! old logic, but A and B may be caUed incompatibly co-ordinate, ihe re- sultant is .^ J. T.r>. o in fABC, jAiC, t«BC, ?«*C, fABc, ^Abc, t«B(?, Jaif', 60 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. I \l [art. 70. whom It could only worry and confuse. I think that if any teacher will have the counige to read my lecture in its extended form, and then work through some treatise by its aid, he will find much clear which was formerly dark, and at least emerge from Cimmerian gloom into a kind of twilight.* so that there 18 still one doubtful compound, ?al>C, to be determined. If we take JrtiC, there will be part of the conception C which is not covered by any part of either A or B, and then the conceptions A and B are said to be (hynnct, bemg incompatible and subordinate to C, but not filling up the whole of C (see diagram 4). If, however, we take iabC, then A and B 3,re contrary opposites, being incompatible, but filling up the whole of C (see diagram o). 4. { Disjunct. A- C- B. '( Contrary opposites. A- C- B. It should be mentioned that the diagram for contrary opposites, which is given in Lindsay's Ueberweg, is quite fallacious. Without reference to co-ordination, we have +tAc for the sub-ordination of A to C, and super-ordination of C to A ; ff Ac for the equipoUence of the conceptions A and C, answering to the identity of objects (p. 41, v.) ; a AB ioT contradictory opposition ; t(A, B), that is, J AB • +A^ • +«B • ?/?A (see p. 17, note, vii.), for intersection, where each conception has some part m common, and also some part not in common with the other ; JfAB for incompatibility, as distinguished from contradictory opposition. These are, however, very imperfect representations of the twenty-sLx assertions m arts. 13, 14, and note, applied to conceptions. In order that two conceptions A and B should be disparate, it is neces- sarj' that they should not be both subordinate to any conception except ^t of an object of thought. Let C be any conception with this exception. The possibihty of having either of the conceptions A or B equipollent with C (or non-Cs or of both A and B beina: subordinate to C (or non-C), is excluded by excluding the pair iAc'\)ic (or the pair tACfBC, respec- tively) ; and these exclusions, whatever be C, are the conditions of dis- parity. Hence the only possible disparate combinations are the twenty- three other pairs, •made up of one of J+AC, XfaC, Xfac, fAC, \ke, and one of ++BC, Jf/.C, If be, fBC, fBc. Of these, the two tAC-fB^" and f Ac -fBC give fAB, by art. 23, [1], im- plying complete separation ; while any one of the other twenty-one pairs will give either ^:AC-+BC or else XKc'X^c, imphing intersection in either C or c. For all these cases, which, though difficult to understand in the abstract language of the old logicians, are simple enough when reduced to the pre- ceding form, see Lindsay's Ueberweg, pp. 130—135. • Instead of reading this lectiure, a mere oral explanation of the nature of the processes was given, and one or two syllogisms, with the example m art. 68, were worked out with the counters. The whole lecture, endino- with art. 70, was printed in the Educational Times for June, July, and August, 1872. Several paragraphs and foot-notes have been added in this reprint, and the whole has been carefully revised. ARTS. 71, 72.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 61 Pajrt II. Inductive Logic. Til .V ? /. '"^"^ ?'' press the preceding explanation of a Method of teaching Logic to Children, by means of words and counters, it became clear to me that I ought not to content myself with tlie passing allusion to induction there made (art. 6), but that i should endeavour to show how induction could be tauffht to children, at least so far as their limited knowledge and capa, cities allow.* In attempting now to do so, my language must be, as before, addressed to tea<;hers ; and, from the nature of the sub' ject, rather consist in an exposition of the general principles which they will have to inculcate, than a j)recise indication of any method which thev can pursue. Hints will be given as I proceed, but de- tails would require a course of instruction rather than a single lecture. » 72. In deductive logic we dealt with heaven-sent assertions. Ihese were assumed to be always correct, or rather all inquiry mto their correctness was tabooed. All we had to do was to as- certain precisely what they affirmed, denied, and lefL in doubt, separately and jointly. With regard to separate assertions, attend tion was confined to the most elementary and most frequently treated, illustrated by assertions respecting the occurrence of certain letters m certain groups of words (arts. 7 to 20) The combined action of assertions was illustrated by the common syl- logism where the premises also related at first to letters in words (arts. 21 to S^) but were afterwards made more general (arts. 40 to 11 1 -^^i m, ^^ ^^ inquiry into the consistency of assertions of all kinds. The very large class of numerically definite assertions, whether of the first kind (art. 48). or of a statistical nature, were passed over as too difficult for children,— the latter were indeed not even mentioned.f The class of assertions respecting mere combinations or juxtapositions of objects was also passed over (art. 4»). And yet numerically definite assertions, statistical con- aitions, and juxtapositions play a great part in all strict induc- tions. Moreover another class of a'^sertions relating to order or succession, m inference, in space, in time, in action, was not even alluded to ; and such assertions have been, on the whole, so little treated by logicians, who for the most part were not already, and were not qualified by their previous studies to become, iuduc- tionists, that even an elementary treatise upon them would be an eaort ol human genius. Yet induction depends greatly upon a The sources of inductive philosophy are the treatises of Bacon and i^esc^rtes, and the prmcipal modem works are by Corate, Whewell, Mill. Md bpencer. The teacher wiU find useful compendiunis in Fowler's and Barn's Inductive Logic, t Except in the note to p. 49. 62 LOGIC FOR CH1LT)KET^. [ARTS. 72, 73. ARTS. 73, 74.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 63 proper method of handlmg snch assertions* Again, the absten- tion from all inquiry into the correctness of assertions conditioned an abstention from any inquiry into the probability of their correct- ness Yet in the greater part of induction, even m the mam tacts on which induction and the verification of induction depend, every assertion has only a greater or less degree of probability of which even the approximate evaluation presents mathematical ditfacul- ties not yet in all cases satisfactorily overcome. Moreover, even it we assume that the main facts can be stated, and the conclu- sions verified with absolute correctness, the method of reaching those conclusions occasionally involves deductions of a nature so much more complicated than any which T have ventured to ad- duce, that their mere statement would be utterly unintelligible ex- cept to persons who had already undergone special and laborious trainincT. It will suffice to say that in order to reduce to a con- dition of verifiability the most complete and general induction with which we are acquainted, the law of gravitation , it was neces- sary to invent an entirelv new branch of mathematical analysis.t and for its subsequent verification so far as that has hitherto pro- ceeded, other and more delicate processes were initiated by Laplace, and carried out by men of the highest mathematical genius. But inquirers even now find themselves stopped by in- superable difficulties in many special domains, as for example, in hvdraulics. In other branches of natural science we are much less capable of arriving at exact verification; and it has been the criory of such a man as G. S. Ohm, who has only lately died, to indicate, and of such a man as Helmholtz, who still lives, to verify approximatively, inductions respecting such extremely elementary and long considered subjects as the sounds of music, on which Pythagoras himself is reported to have dogmatized. 73 With our tew and easily stated assertions m that portion of deductive logic which I previously considered— and I warned you that I was only scraping the soil of a great subject (art. 3)— at was very easy to arrive at clear, precise, and certain results. Ihis is entirely changed in induction. All our data are more or less hazy • and hence our conclusions must share the same fate. Ihe word' induction runs so glibly off* the tongues of most speakers, that I may seem to have been raising giants for the purpose ot slaying them. But unfortunately I found the giants already there : and I am quite unable to slay them. The only comfort for our present purpose is, that even if a steam mitrmlleuse noethod of slaughtering these giants wholesale had been perfected, school children would be quite incapable to manage it, and that if we are content merely to show the nature of the method by rough in- stances which a child can manipulate, we can skirt the fastnesses of these ogres, and make a real advance into their country, on a road suited for infant feet. In fact, as we shall see, much may be • The (imperfect) method in which such assertions of succession are reduced to assertions of mconsistency is illustrated below (art. 81). t Newton's "Prime and Ultimate Ratios," subsequently kno^m as '•'^t^uxions," and now generally replaced by some form of "Differential and Integral Calculus." done without any systematic knowledge of even deductive logic (art. 84). Wha,t I am now anxious to do is to show how teachers may put young minds upon what to present science appears the right track, thus saving them from dogmatism upon insufficient data on the one hand, and from scepticism through despair of all know- ledge on the other; and leading them to feel that when the truth or real law evades us, we can and must put up with a contrivance, a theory, which we are convinced is not the reality, but which we must treat as such, till the means are at hand for correcting it, they probably never will be at hand for perfecting it,— valuing it as the most trusty attainable weapon, but ready to reject it at once if it snaps with any blow, however unexpected ; or, at least, to limit its use to less adamantine obstacles, and leave the others unassailed.* We have, indeed, constantly to be content with a statement of laws which we are convinced are not correct, and to argue from them as if they ivere correct, in order to discover the limits within which they may be used with safety. This is, in fact, our position with regard to almost all physical, biological, social, and moral science. Our knowledge is all on its trial, but is not the less valuable ; for wherever we can predict results with certainty, our theonj, so far, if not true, is at least as good as true. Some metaphysicians are inclined to think that man has never got, and can never get, beyond this. Whether they are right or wrong is of very little consequence. It is quite enough to have got so far. 74. We scarcely ever speak without making an assertion. De- duction, as we have seen, dealt with the meaning of assertions al- ready made. Liduction deals with the method of making verifiable assertio7is. It is easy to make assertions right and left, if we are never called to account for them. Theodore Hook described the pleasure felt by a barrister who had turned parson, that, when he preached. * We shall thus escape the error of those " who set up their own concep- tions of the orderly sequence which they discern in the phenomena of na- ture as fixed and determinate laws, by which those phenomena not only are, within all human experience, hut alwa\ s have been, and always must he, invariably governed," stigmatised by Dr.'Carpenter in his Presidential Address to the British Association at Brighton, 14th August, 4872. This very widely circulated essay contains many illustrated allusions to the matters here treated, in a form having especial reference to children in science as well as adults— the Associates as well as the Members of the British Association. Attention will consequently be frequently drawn to it in futiue notes. The present lecture had been completed a fortnight before Dr. Carpenter's address was deHvered ; and nothing could have been more unexpected than such an address on such an occasion. But the neces- sity for something like scientific instruction in schools was well illustrated on this occasion, for the Lord Lieutenant of the coimty, the chairman of an educational society in high repute, in proposing the usual vote of thanks, seemed to take it as a matter of course (according to the report in the Brighton Daily News for 15th August, 1872, p. 10, col. 1) that outsiders should know nothing about such elementary matters, saying, " I should like to suggest to many of the friends here present, who perhaps, like myself, have not had a very scientific training, that the address is one which will amply repay a second or a third perusal. A good deal of it, I must confess, I did not at first quite understand." 6i LOGIC FOR CIIILDREX. [art. 74. ART. 74.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 65 there was no longer any one to get up on the other side. But the man of science is his own opponent. He is not satisfied with his own assertions till he has run them to earth, deduced from them as many of their consequences as he can (that is, as we now know, discovered their meaning separately and jointly so far as possible), and contrived means of contrasting these consequences with fact. To him vn'ifinhle hnnwhcIgG is the only IcnovHedge. He is very well aware, however, from sad experience— the veri- fication requires no coaxing— that many of his theories are non- verifiable, often as to bare possibility ; but he at least takes care never to call them knowledge. In tliis respect he differs widely from the metai)hysician, the intuitional philosopher,* who fre- quently contends that he is as certain as he is of his own existence that some un verifiable theory re])iesents a iact. Such theories are not without a cei-tain value, and sometimes a vcrj' high value ; but they are never knowledge; they are not inductions, and they do not belong to our present subject, except so far as it is necessary to warn young inductionists that even induction is not everything, and that our world would be a poor world indeed if it only dealt with what happens at the present moment to be verifiable, and that, as the admission of verification into the arena of science is scarcely more than two or three hundt ed years old, and as our nieans of verification have largely and rapidly increased as its ne- cessity has been more and more felt, we ought not to be too hasty in determining the limits of future verifiability.f But this is a question for the master, not the learner, of his art, and we must strictly limit our school inductions to what is apparently verifiable. * Dr. Carpenter says, " By tho iutu'tionalists it is asserted that the ten- dency to form these priraarj- beliefs [« which constitute the groundwork of all Bcientifie reasoning,' as p^e^^«^usly defined] is inborn in man— an original part of his mental organisation ; so that they j,t^w up spontaneously m his mind as its faculties are gradually unfolded and developed, requiring no other experience for their genesis than that which suffices to call these faculties into exercise. . . . The wteUectunlintuitions of one generatian are the embodied experience of the pririous race It appears to me there has "been a progressive improvement in the thinkiytg potrer of man. ... As there can le no doubt of the hereditary- transmission in man of acquired consti- tutional peculiarities, which manifest themselves alike in tendencies to bodily and to m-ntal disease, so it seems equally certam that acqmred mental habitudes often impress themselves upon his organisation with suffi- cient force and permanence to occasion their transmission to ofltspring as tendeneiefi to similar modes ofthoitqhtr This doctrine, as Dr. C. mentions, was " fii-st txpUcitly put forth by IMr. Herbert Spencer." Miss F. Power Cobbe, in her essay called Barnimsm in Morals, combats Mr. Spencer s statement. ^ ,r j + At the Br ghton meeting of tho British Association, on Monday even- in<-, 19th Augi 6t, 1872, Prof. W. K. Cliffunl delivered a lecture on "The Aims and Insln ments of Scientific Thought," which has not obtained so wide a circulaticn as the President's address, but is of extreme value to any persons wl o \n ish to obtain a correct notion of scientific thought. It h-^i boen printed in Macmillan's Magazine lor October, 1872, from which all the citations will be made. " When we are told that the infinite extent of space, for example," savs Prof. Clifford, and the same appUes to any other existing iuia c rifiabilitv, "is something which we cannot conceive at present, we mav i eplv that this is only natural, since our eipenence has Observe that unverifiable assertions may still be made, and deduc- tive rules applied to them ; but the conclusions, as we know can never have anymore weight than the assertions themselves on which they depend. This limitation at once strikes off all supernaturalism. all suppositions of "occult causes," all assumptions of what may be because it cannot be shown not to be, all hypotheses concerning the existence of fluids, ethers, spirits, atoms and what not. made with any other view than colligating results, and obtaining veri- fiable laws * This remarkably simplifies the questions to be con- sidered. Many persons will be induced to conclude that with these limitations " thinking is but an idle waste of thought." but the field will soon be found far larger than man at present can plough, and sow, and harvest. And as far as school instruction IS concerned, there is the utmost value in drawing the line thus sharply. It is not quite that between secular and reliorious in- struction, for it cuts off much which is purely secularf but the wide debateable land thus left between induction proper and religion, will serve not ouly to render the distinction clearer— never yet supphed us with the moans of conceiving such thing's. But then we cannot be sure that the facts will not make us learn to conceive them • in which case they will cease to be inconceivable," (p. 511, col. 2) And speaking of another supposition, he says, "The knowledge of that fact would be different from any of our present knowledge, but we have no right to say that it is impossible." {lb., col. 1.) * "Electric fluid" is a word of constant occurrence in newspapers. Its existence is now entirely discredited, yet two electric * currents,' a positive and negative, are familiarly spoken of by men of science. The * luminous ether, supposed to pervade all space, and to generate, by its various * modes ot motion, heat and Ught, if not other physical phenomena, must be re- garded as a mere vehicle for obtaining and colligating laws. Its existence has never been verified. The mathematical laws might be the same if derived from other sources. Nothing is more delusive in this rejpect than a mathematical formula. Thus, xy = a\ results from a consideration of a bemg a mean proportional between a: and y, from x and y being len"-ths of the sides of a varying rectangle with a constant area, from .rand y beinc the coordmates of a point in an hyperbola, or the distances of two point! from the centre of an involution, &c. "Spirit," in Newton, is an ether, conditioning physical forces. See the last paragraph of the Frincipia. Adjicere jam liceret nonnulla de spiritu quodam subtUissimo corpora crassa pervadente, et in iisdem latente ; cujus vi et actionibus particulae corporum ad mimmas distantias se mutuo attrahunt, et contiguae factae cohasrent; et corpora electrica agunt ad distantias majores, tam repellendo quam attrahendo corpuscula vicina ; et lux emittitur.reflectitur.refringitur, intiectitur, et corpora calefacit ; et sensatio omnis excitatur, et membra ammalia ad voluntatem moventur, vibrationibus scilicet hujus spiritus per soUda nervorum capillamenta ab externis sensuum organis ad cere- brum et a cerebro in musculos propagatis." Such ethereal and spiritual vibrations are only another name for periodically recurring states, and that IS all which 18 expressed by the resulting mathematical formulae. The old "animal spirits" are quite dead. The "spirits of the dead" do not yet belong to science. " Atoms" are familiarly spoken of by chemists, who have formed from them a powerful theory for the investigation of the rela- tions of substances, which we cannot at present replace, but which can only be regarded as provisional ; for though the resulting laws can be controlled, tho existence of atoms is quite unverifiable. 66 LOGIC FOE CHILDREN. [aRTS. 74, 75. because distinctions always become confused near the limits*— but to impress very strongly on the pupils* minds that induc' Han is not the sole sanction to thou{fht recoffnized among men, and hence, to save them from a scientific, wliich is quite as hurtful as a metaphysical or supernaturalistic pedantry. There are several classes of researches where verification is not possible ; as, for example, in theories of the origin and treatment of disease, m geological and historical investigations, where we cannot put back the c'ock of time, and contrast the actual past with its hypo- thetical aspect. Such studies are admitted as partially positive, because the different results are such as contemporary men might have verified, so that, though unverifiable to the present genera- tion, they are not so to humanity at large. But, inasmuch as they are not absolutely verifiable,t they do not possess the same amount of evidence, and require special and very delicate treatment to be admitted as scientific facts at all. In all cases the power of veri- fying must not be limited to the inductionist's own powers, but must be extended to all investigators in all time, the main point being that future verification should not exceed the bounds of human power. But until verification has taken place, we have, at most, reached probability, and real knowledge, science proper, does not exist. „-,.■, ^- • ^ 75. The intention of all the processes called inductive is, /rom ihe Icnotvn present and known past, to discover the unknmcn present and past, and to predict the unknown future. This discovei7 is, at any rate, scientifically, never designed to gratify idle curiosity, but rather to obtain a basis for further prediction. And this pre- diction must not be looked upon as a gipsy peep into futurity, but as the only means we have of preparing lor contingencies, and advancing in any way, material or moral. It is often said, that if man knew what was to happen, he would be the most miserable of beings. Yet man is always striving to know what will or may happen, and to provide for the rainy as well as the sunny day. If, in winter, we could not look forward to seed-time ; if, when sowing, we could not look forward to harvest; our existence would be exhausted in a hand-to-hand fight with death. But we now know how the seed-time can be best utilized by proper prepara- • " The animal and vegetable kingdom have a debateahle ground be- tween them, occupied by beings thiit have the character of both, and yet belong distinctly to neither. Classes and orders shade into one another all along their common boundarv. Specific differences turn out to bo the work of time. The Unc dividing organic matter from inorganic, if drawn to-day, must be moved to-morrow to another place ; and the chemist wiU tell you that the distinction has now no place in his science, except in a technical sense, for the convenience of studj-ing carbon compounds by themselves." (Prof. Clifford, p. 505, col. 2.) . w ^ • t The geologic induction that there will bo a seam of coal tound ma certain locuhty is of course verifiable by digging down. But the geologic theory which accounts for the formation of that seam of coal is not veri- fiable, as the formation of coal toik j^kv in jct-hi^tfinc «««•. 17,* i^t"-*! and dynamical theories of geolog>- *n UArfly UitftttfU HI Um vv*knco «a which they rest. The text especially ftppUoi to Um 1«tl«r. ARTS. 75, 76.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 6? tion of the ground, and how, by commercial intercourse, involving predictions innumerable, we may even supply the dearth of one country's harvest by the plenty of another. The teacher must always be prepared for the old old question. What's the use ? But he should resolutely refuse giving a detailed answer. It is enough to know generallv that, without a means of predicting, however roughly, life would be an abject, objectless chaos, and that what- ever contributes to more accurate prediction, no matter how slight the apparent connection between the discovery and any individual's special needs, is advancing so far the whole human race. We gain knowledge in order to predict, and we predict in order to prerience and pre- vious judgments, but that experience and those judgments are not gene- rally present to our mind when making the new judgment. So frequently are important links forgotten, and judgments first foi-med have to be sub- sequently modified, that "second tlioughts are best," has past into a pro- verb. It is only so iw as this " uncas^sniouA co-ordination" becooMM **ccaMsMu** tkst tniftw«cthiiati»« rwulU,*T/i thcnodl>* (OMugh nut nl- ^y*!' whca -the «1u>lo ^fgitgBt.^ ofoir «xp«ri«i»(«*' kw bcca Uigo, •s ut thiioM* of "oDciU.'^ Tfho r«»l wbols Mgronto to ht conaulM is tkf rcdot^cd oMpakntt of koMniiy. s I 68 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. [aRTS. 76, 77. Tery narrow field of observation and experiment, with, most likely, a very imperfect appreciation of the circnmstances pre- sented to his mind, and also generally in a very awkward and round-about manner.* But the fundamental principle of all rea- soning is merely to form the simplest supposition which is con- sistent with the WHOLE of the circumstances to he represented ; and what is this but the child's process clarified ? All the so-called canons of induction are but evolutions of this one principle (art. 82). The supposition must be the simplest possible, and it must be consistent with every one of the circumstances involved, considered not merely isolatedly, but more especially as a whole, as parts which mutually affect each other. The intentional sup- pression of some circumstances is scientifically unthinkable, ex- cept they be recognized as immaterial, but the accidental suppres- sion of some material circumstances through ignorance is frequent, and hence the necessity for means of detecting them, by observa- tion and, when possible, experiment. Occasions will very fre- quently arise in the course of instruction or in school life in which the teacher will have to suggest material circumstances which have escaped the observation of the pupil. This is constantly the case where the young reasoner sees no difficulty at all. Without a knowledge of any circumstances, no supposition at all can be made. Hence, so-called a priori assertions are misnamed; they are not assertions made without any knowledge, but assertions made with extremely imperfect knowledge, occasioning the em- ployment of inappropriate analogies, and, as we now know, leading generally to worthless results. The light of nature^ which is a very favourite source of inspiration for quick children, is also power- less in presence of ignorance of circumstances, though it will often help towards the solution of a troublesome problem in a more or less awkward manner, for the light of nature is a lamp which re- • quires trimming with the scissors of experience and plenishing with the oil of observation. It burns however with a very different flame in different minds, and the danger is that children will come to rely upon it without troubling themselves with learning, igno- rant that, as has been well said, genius is above all things a capa- city for hard ivorJc. 77. Now the basis for making any supposition concerning cir- cumstances which are presented to the mind, is that the supposer has seen similar circumstances concur, and observed results similar to those which he consequently anticipates. There is no doubt of this fact as regards the supposer, but the question is, what justifies him in this conclusion ? And the only answer as as yet given is, the event. A feeUng has grown up among men, which is stronger the more opportunity there has been for accu- rate examination, that there exist invariable and unconditional re* ♦ This last circumstance does not mark the child only. Every inves- tigfator is aware that the way in which he is first led to some new concep- tion is generally very obscure, and that the processes he consequently adopts to work it out are subsequently discovered to be most unnecessarily circuitous. Simphcity results from much knowledge and many trials. Success is the outcome of numerous failures. ART. 77.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 69 lations respecting the succession and co-existence of all circum' stances* It is felt that it is only our ignorance which stands in the way of our predicting with certainty what events will follow after or concur with any given event. But the mode of express- ing this feeling is yery diverse, and is often accompanied with strange limitations, due to previous ignorance and present pre- judice. On these I refrain from entering. If any child start some question of necessity and freewill,— and he may do so, for he may bring his school knowledge home, and his crude statements of the teacher's doctrines may alarm some sensitive parent into a dread lest the child may be taught some '* unsound" notions of divine government, — the teacher has only to say : "As you learn more, you will understand these things better. You must learn very much to understand them well, but you know now that if you strike a ball, the ball will move from you, and that you need not strike the ball unless you like. The motion of the ball de- pends upon the kind of blow you give it. Your liking to strike it * " The step from past experience to new circimistances must be mad© in accordance with an observed uniformity in the order of events. This uniformity has held good in the past in certain places ; if it should also hold good in the future and in other places, then, being combined with our experience of the past, it enables us to predict the future, and to know what is going on elsewhere ; so that we are able to regulate our conduct in accoixlance with this knowledge. The aim of scientific thought, then, is to apply past experience to new circumstances ; the instrument is an observed uniformity in the course o'' events. By the use of this instrument it gives us information transcending our experience ; it enables us to infer things which we have not seen from things that we have seen ; and the evidence for the truth of that information depends on our supposing that the imi- formity holds beyond our experience." (Prof. Clifford, p. 502.) " We say that the uniformity which we observe in the course of events is exact and universal ; we mean no more than this, that we are able to state general rules which are far more exact than direct oxperiment, and which apply to all cases that we are at present hkely to come across." (Id., p. 506, col. 1.) ** It is possible that by-and-by, when psychology has made enormous ad- vances and become an exact science, we may be able to give to testimony the sort of weight which we give to the inferences of physical science. It will then be possible to conceive a case which will show how completely the whole process of inference depends on our assumption of imiformity. Suppose that testimony, having reached the ideal force I have imagined, were to assert that a certain river runs up hill. You could infer nothing at all. The arm of inference would be paralyzed, and the sword of truth broken in its grasp, and reason cou'd only sit down and wait until recovery restored her limbs, and further experience gave ler new weapons." (76., p. 506, col. 2.) The principle of the uniformity of nature is the postulate of mduction, an assumption without which any inductive reasoning would be iinpossible. We have not yet seen our way to any means of demon- strating its truth a priori. Every coincidence of a result with a pre- diction founded upon it, helps to verify it. But any absence of such coincidence that could not be traced to mere errors of deductive reasoning of observation or of record, would be destructive of its value, would, as Prof. CHfford remarks in the passage just quoted, " paralyze the arm of inference," and leave us ignorant of everything which we are now sup- posed to know. 70 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. [arts. 77, 78. ARTS. 78, 79, i.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 71 or not to strike it, depends upon something else. Thus you may not like to strike it, because you are told to do so, or because you are afraid you cannot make it go far enough, or strike it in the best possible way, or feel ill, or lazy, or * don't see the use,' and so on. The diflerence between the ball's motion and your liking to strike it, is so far a difference of simplicity. Lot us try to under- stand the motion of the ball, which you will find useful at fives and at cricket, and which is quite difficult enough for neither you nor me to understand thoroughly, and leave the liking for another time, knowing that at best we shall always understand it very imperfectly." 78. It is necessary that occasion should be taken very early in- deed to show that this absolute invariability and unconditionality can never be thoroughly appreciated in the things we see or feel, or deal with, but only in certain imaginary things which we come to conceive by leaving out of consideration all those little peculiari- ties that are too complicated to allow for.* Thus, in determining the inotion of the ball, we should first suppose it quite smooth, and this is not the case in the best cricket ball, much less in a common fives ball ; and also that it is perfectly spherical, which we know is never the case ; and also that it is equally elastic in all places, which those who have tried to make a fives ball for themselves will know they could never manage. All these things are better obtained in a billiard ball or a glass globe, but these would pro- bably shiver to pieces with a blow of the bat. We must however consider that the ball will never break, nor the bat either, hit we ever so hard. We hit an abstract ball with an abstract bat, and then we can tell tolerably well how the ball would fly, provided there were no air ! But we have a real ball, a real bat, and plenty of air, already in motion generally, in the shape of wind, hence the ball never goes exactly as we foretold, but always nearly so, and the more nearly the nearer the realities approach to the ab- strations. That is, there are invariable unconditional relations, but these hold in all their perfection, solely for ahsir actions, ab- stract things and abstract events. For realities we have always to make certain allowances.f Why not go to the realities at once ? • Science, therefore, deals with an abstract, ideal world. It is never more than an approximation to reality. This must be carefully home in mind in weighing? the api^irently unqualified assertions of men of science, who are so familiar with the fact that they forbear to mention it, as even the ecclesiastical wTiter neglects putting " D. V." alter every future tense, notwithstandiDg Jas. iv. 13 — 15. t The tlu-ee angles of a triangle, says EucHd, together make up two right angles. Probably no one doubts the fact, although all geometricians know the extreme difficulty occasioned by one of the assumptions (in this case a pure assumption) on which it is based. But try to put it to the test. What man ever drew on paper a triangle which strictly satisfied the condition ? Nay more, what surveyor, in making his triangulations, either with his measuring chain, or with all appliances of scientific apparatus, as in na- tional trigonometrical operations, ever found such a triangle? In the latter case, indeed, where the sides of the triangle are many miles in length, the observer always finds the sum of his three angles greater than two %^i Simply because man*s mind is unequal to the task, the abstrac- tions giving him already more than he is able to accomplish. All we can do is to make the realities as near the abstractions as pos" sible, and alluwfor the differences. And in this precept is involved another extremely important principle, setting forth the bounds of human power. We cannot alter the invariable unconditional relations which determine the order of events , but w& can alter the intensity with which the circumstances enter into the events whose order is thus determined. We cannot prevent the ball starting from the bat when struck, but we can regulate the strength and direction of the blow, and we can abstain from giving the blow altogether. We cannot prevent ignited gunpowder from explod- ing,°but we can keep the heat to so low a degree that ignition will never take place. It really does not require a very great step further to reconcile necessity and free-will, and the teacher will do well to show over and over again, by simple instances, when- ever they occur, that re Zah'otis are fixed, conditions variable. The knowledge of these fixed relations, and of the effect of that vari- ability of condition, is, as Bacon long ago expressed it, coin- cident with human power.* 79. There are a few words which arise out of what has been said, and from being in constant use, and therefore having vague popular senses attached to them, require careful consideration. i. The first of these is law. A sciejitifie, or, as it is often called, a natural law, has only the one determinate meaning, of an invari- able unconditional relation of succession or coexistence. Any other meaning is unscientific. The clear and definite statement of such a relation bears a vague resemblance to the written law of the realm, which however can be altered, and can be evaded, and which has been settled by the will of certain legislators. This law of the realm lays down penalties in case it should be disobeyed, but the appointed executive is often powerless to enforce them, and even to detect the disobedience. These laws are therefore in no respect invariable or unconditional. Owing to our power of modifying the intensity of circumstances, we are able to bring things or events within the conditions which render the results of scientific laws appreciable or otherwise ; but having brought them within this influence, there is no choice of obedience or dis- obedience, the invariable relation invariably asserts itself. What then can be meant by saying that a person by over-eating " broke" the natural laws of health, and suffered the " penalty" of disease ? The whole sentence is one of confused analogy, which is however very widely employed. The real meaning is", that the person has right angles, the difference (known as " the spherical excess," because due to the nearly spherical form of the globe) havmg to be carefully allowed for. If, then, we only knew our geometry by concrete instances, we should be in a state of muddle. It was the happy exercise of man's power of ab- straction by the ancient geometers which allowed us to see the invariable and unconditional abstract law through the tangled net of concrete ckcum- stances. . . • "Scientia et potentia humana in idem coincidunt, qma ignoratio causae destituit eflfectum." — Novum Orffanim, Aphorism 3. ^ • 72 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. [art. 79, ART. 79, i. li.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 73 brought himself under the action of that invariable relation be- tween food and vital functions which results in disease ; whereas, if he had not brought himself within that action, this disease would not have occurred. It does not follow that some other disease might not have occurred, for the person might have come within the conditions for the occurrence of that second disease, even if he had avoided the first. There is, however, a little more meant, namely, that the over-eater has put himself beyond the re- lations which result in health; and it is this voluntary part which apparently gave rise to the whole conception, most widely dis- seminated by George Combe's Constitution of Man, a work which in its day produced a profound impression among a very numerous class of readers * This should be illustrated by such a simple case as a boy putting his finger too near to any flame. The dis- tance at which he holds it is generally voluntary; but he may fall, or be thrown against the source of heat. It could hardly be said that a law had been enacted against his putting his finger too close to the flame, and that the destruction of the skin, and * In the introduction to his work on '* the Relation between Science and Religion," of which the 4th enlarged edition (here cited) appeared in 1857, a year before his death, Mr. Combe says (p. xxx.) " To prevent mis- understanding, I beg here to explain the meaning which is attached in the following work to the expressions * Laws of Nature' and * Natural Laws.' Every object and being in nature has received a definite consti- tution, and also the power of acting on other objects and beings. The action of the forces is so regular, that we describe them as operating under laws imposed on them by God ; but these words indicate merely our per- ception of the regularity of the action. It is impossible for man to alter or break a natural law, when understood in this sense ; for the action of forces, and the effects they produce, are placed beyond his control. But the observation of the action of the forces leads man to draw rules from it for the regulation of his own conduct, and these rules are called natrn^l laws, because Natm-e dictates or prescribes them as guides to conduct. If we fail to attend to the operations of the natural forces, we may unknow- ingly act in opposition to them ; but as the action is inherent in the things, and does not vary with our state of knowledge, we must suffer from our ignorance and inattention. Or we may know the forces and the consequences which their action inevitably produces ; but from ignorance, that through them God is dictating to ua rules of conduct ; or from mistaken notions of duty, from passion, self-conceit, or other causes, we may disregard them, and act in opposition to them : but the consequences will not be alteiei to suit ignorant en-ors or humours; we must obey or suffer." There if, therefore, a constant confusion of the two meanings attributed to natural laws, (1) invariable, unconditional relations, and (2) rules for apply- ing conditions so as to effect desired ends in accordance with those rela- tions. These latter state, ** If you do A, you will obtain the desired B, if you do not, you will not obtain B, and if you do X, or Y, or Z, you will obtain the undesired C." And it is very j^robable that there will be moro or less error in the statement of condit ons and result, because the gene- rality of the terms in which the conditions are stattd leaves out of con- sideration a vast number of peculiar circumstances which seriously affect the result in particular cases. " To break the law," means '* not to use the condition A," or more frequently, " to use one of the conditions X, Y, Z." Upon the " coercive" character of law, see the last foot note to No. iv. consequent pain arising from too near an approach, were the penalty attached to breaking this law. It becomes evident that there was only a certain definite relation between the amount of heat and its effect on the tissue, and something of the same kind was the case in over-feeding. ii. This leads to another great difference between a country's laws and scientific laws. The former are carefully promulgated, so that the judge is always entitled to disregard the plea of ignor- ance of the law. The latter have to be discovered. They are not only in great part unknown still, but are, more correctly speak- ing, only known to a very small extent indeed, and it is the busi- ness of men of science to discover them. What becomes of the notion of penalty attached to breaking an unknown law ? But here steps in a very important word, which will have to be well understood. Chance applies to all those events whose Law is un- known. The feeling that law is universal is now so generally en- tertained, that men of science refuse to believe in the absence of law, much less to erect the absence of law into a disposing goddess co-equal with fate. Hence, when they say that a thuig happens accident' illy, or hy chance, they simply mean that its laws are un- known.* And they point to a remarkable confirmation of this view in the so-called law of avn-ages, which shows that when a large number of events of the same kind is taken into account, although we are unable to predict what will be the result for any one in particular, they will all be grouped round one central phenomenon. This should be illustrated. A boy strikes a ball, say in the game of 'trap, bat, and ball.' The number of times which he strikes it, and the distances at which the ball comes to rest, should be noted. (The problem would be a little too complicated if the exact places of rest, instead of merely the distances, were ob- served.) A distance found by adding all the observed and mea- sured distances together, and dividing by the number of blows * Dr. Carpenter {if/id.), using the flint implements found at Abbeville and Amiens as an illustration, says : " The evidence of design to which, after an examination of one or two such specimens, we should only be justified in attaching a probable value, derives an irresistible cogency from accumulation. On the other hand, the /«/probabihty that these flints acquired their peculiar shape by accident'" — where the phrase only means by some unknown, and even nnguessed relation, different from that previously assigned by ourselves, of having been formed by man as instru- ments — "becomes, to'our minds, greater and greater as more and more such specimens are found ; until at last this hypothesis, although it can- not be directly disi)roved"— that is, although we cannot show directly that our own hypothesis is correct, or cannot verify it — "is felt to l>e almost inconceivable "—that is, incapable of representing to our own minds the whole of the circtunstances knowTi to ?/«— " except by minds previously *l>08sc8sed' by the 'dominant' idea of the modern origin of man." This " dominant idea " means a conception formed from what Dr. Carpenter considers insufficient consideration, or on grounds which he rejects, but which tlie holder maintains to be one of the conditions which he cannot ignore, so that to concludo that the flints had been humanly formed would not represent the whole of the circumstances which he regards as known to him. 74 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. [art. 79, ii. ART. 79, ii.iii.] logic for chh^dren. 75 struck, would give the "average" distance. It would be found that if this average were determined from a large number of trials, say 100, it would be almost precisely the same for another hun- dred, provided the same boy made the trial. Also^ if 100 boys were to try each three times, the average distance for each set of 100 blows would be found nearly the same. Make trials with toss- ing a penny;* with picking balls from bags of white and black balls; with walking to a place or touching squares on a chessboard blindfold : with the number of words a boy can read intelligibly, or write legibly in a minute, the number of words in a line of writing or print, and so on. Show the application of this in the average number of persons who travel by different classes in rail- ways or over different lines, by which the officials have to regulate their accommodation ; by the average number of things sold in the market, and the average supply brought in, and the average prices at which they are sold. In all examples, point out the large number of influences that there must be at work, but which we are unable to evaluate, and hence the great importance of the * Tossinj^ a penny is an admirable illustration, and it is worth while spending a quarter of an hour over it, the whole class experimenting and registering the results as follows. Let each place the penny head upper- most each time, toss it a little height only, and receive it on a crumpled handkerchief, to prevent rebounding. Number 32 lines on a slate, write h for head and t for tail, and write in each line the result, till you get to a h. There will then be 32 trials. The following is the result of 32 actual trials, the commas dividing the lines : k. A, M, //, tth, A, A, th,, A, thy /i, th, /<, /<, A, h, A, A, tith, th, h, h, h, ttttth, tttth, th, th, tttth, h, tth, h, h. Now as there is an " even chance" of throwing h each time, we should expect h in IG of the 32 trials ; there are actually 19. As in two throws we might have hh, ht, th, or tt, it is 3 to 1 against having th, and hence we should ex- pect th in 1 case out of 4, that is in 8 out of 32, we really find it 7 times in the 32 trials. Again, in three throws we might have hhh, hht, hth, hit, thh, tht, tth, ttt, so that it is 7 to 1 against tth or '1th as we may write ; we should therefore expect 2th once in 8 trials, or 4 times in 32, we really find it twice. Similarly for Zth, we should expect it once in 16 times, or twice in 32 times, we really find it once. Again, Ath we should only ex- pect once in 32, we find it twice. But bth should be only half a time in 32, that is once in 64 trials, we really find it once in the 32. Let the pupils add the results, in a table thus : — Now this is a very small experiment, expected, found, and the results are really much closer Trials 32; th, 1th, Zth, 4th, 6th, Total trials 16, 8, 4, 2, 1, 1, 32 19 7 2 1 2 1 to the theoretical amounts than we have any right to think would often happen. But if all the results in the whole class are added after registra- tion, wo should probably come much nearer. The following table repre- sents the restUts for h and th actually found for a very large number of trials, the first 2,048 having been made by the celebrated naturalist Buffon, and are calculated from a table given in Prof. De Morgan's Budget of Paradoxes, p. 170 (London, 1872). The first column givos the actual number of trials, the second the numbers of h or th theoretically expected, the third the numbers of h or th actually found, the fourth what this would give in 100,000 trials at the same rate, and the 32 !'l 1/ V A I t< i ' { law of averages, and of the observations on which they are based, such as the decennial census. iii. Draw attention to the fact that this law of averages applies to volnntarij actions (leading a little further to the solution of the question of necessity and free-will); for notwithstanding the general controlling average, there is no sense of restraint in any actor. This leads to a more accurate notion of restraint, which, in voluntary agents, amounts to the presentation of a choice, coupled with the withholding of a choice usually open. We have no fifth the theoretical amount in 100,000 trials, and the sixth the difference between the two last amounts : — trials h 2048 4096 6144 8192 th 1th 3th 4th bth eth 7th Sth 9th loth nth 12th Idth nth loth 2048 4096 6144 8192 8192 It » >» »» » ft expected 1024 2048 3072 4096 512 1024 1536 2048 1024 512 256 128 64 32 16 8 4 2 1 i i 4 found or in 100,000 instead of difference 1061 2191 3126 4165 494 1001 1548 2028 982 480 266 132 71 36 17 9 2 1 1 2 51806 51489 50879 50842 24121 24438 25212 24755 11987 5859 3248 1611 867 439 208 110 25 12 12 25 50000 »» ti »» 25000 99 12500 6250 3125 1563 781 390 195 97 49 24 12 6 3 2 + 1806 + 1489 + 879 + 842 - 879 - 562 + 212 - 246 - 513 - 391 + 123 + 48 + 86 + 49 + 13 + 13 - 24 - 12 - 12 + 6 - 3 + 23 It is thus seen that the observed corresponds nearer and nearer with the calculated average as the number of trials increases for h, and for the three first for th, but for th it is evident that the numher of trials was not nearly enough. After th the discrepancies become still greater. The table is then reduced to the case of 8192 trials, which gives the sum of four different sets of 2048 each. It is remarkable that in two of the sets 10th occurred once, and in one of the sets llth, 12th, IZth each occuiTed once, while in two of the sets 15^A occurred once. The table is arranged by heads, each trial ending with an A. But the tosses observed might have been arranged by /. Then the actual 32 trials at the beginning of this note would ap- pear as hht, hht, t, hhht, hht, hht, hhhhhhht, t, t, ht, hhhht, t, t, t, t, ht, t, t, t, ht, ht, ht, t, t, t, hht, t, hhh ... giving only 27 trials ending in t and part of another trial, and the trials would have had to be continued. It is best to use such a number of trials as 32, 64, 128, &c., because these numbers divide so often by 2 exactly. Hence 2048 = 2", 8192 = 2'3, were selected for the trials in the table. A few examples of this kind actually worked out from a child's own experience will do more to convince him of the reahty of a law of averages than a month's talk or a year's reading. Thejluctim- tims '* found" above and below the " expected" average will also show him the meaning of " leaving a margin." 76 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. [aRT. 79, iii. i\'. ART. 79, iv. v.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 77 choice with regard to coming into existence or ceasinfr to exist- we have no choice as to living by airandfood; we have no choice as to breathing air or water, flying or walking, having two legs or tour, and so on ; but we never feel restraint respecting these mat- ters. A prisoner who submits to be taken to prison feels restraint because he has the choice of going or of being afflicted for not going, and he has all further choice withheld, and so on. In in- voluntary agents, restraint consists in the introduction of unusual conditions, which bring the event under the action of additional laws. Thus a ball, when thrown, describes a certain path under the action of gravitation. But if a string had been fastened to It, the motion would have been greatly changed. The strin'v in- troduces a new set of laws. Properiy speaking, restraint always consists in coming within the influence of unusual laws. IV. Cause and effect are two extremely common and very loosely employed terms. Scientifically they are used for two sets of events which occur in the order fixed by scientific law. But even scienti- hcally the whole of each set of events is rarely thought of- many being so much a matter of course, that their absence rather than presence would have to be noted. But popularly the one seen and observed event which, like the spark applied to a train of gunpow- der, IS immediately followed by the change, is called the cause, and the change itself the effect.* But, in this very instance, it would be absurd to say that a spark was the cause of the ruin of a fort ^ot only the gunpowder, but a certain collocation of the gimpow^ der with respect to the fort, and a certain constitution and dryness ot the powder, were also required, and formed part of the scientific cause Hence cause and effect are words rather to be avoided f and the teacher must be ca reful that they are not used vaguely. ♦ See Method of Differences, Art. 82. t Prof. Clifford (p. 509), referring to the common phrase, "every effect has a cause asks, "What do we mean by this ?" and proceeds to say. In askmg this question we have entered upon an appalling task. The word represented by cause has sixty-four moanin-s in Plato, and forty-ei-ht in Anstotle. These were men who liked to know as near as might be what they meant; but how many meanin-s it has had in the writings of the myriads of people who have not tried to know what they meant by it will 1 hope, never be counted. ... I shall evade the difficultv by tolling you Mr' Urote s opinion You come to a scarecrow, and ask;\\1iat is the cause ot this .-* lou find that a man had made it to fric^hten the birds. You so away, and say to yourself, * Everj'thing resembles this scarecrow : eveiT- thing has a piin)Ose.' And from that day the word canse for vou means what Anstotle meant hy^fij^al ca,w. Or you go into a hairdresser's shoi), and wonder what turns tlu- wheel to which the rotarv brush is attached. On investigating other i)aits of the premises, vou find a man working away at a handle. Then you go away and say, * Everything is like that wheel. It 1 investigated enough, I should alwavs find a man at a handle ' And the man at the handle, or whatever corresponds to him, is from henceforth known to you as ' cause,' and so generally. When you have made out any seipience of events to your enth-e satisfaction, so that you know all about it, the laws involved being so familiar that you seem to see how the beginning must have been followed by the end ; then you applv that as a simile to any other events what<3ver, and your idea of cause is determined Dy it. Only when a case arises, as it alwavs must, to which the simile The invariable unconditional order of events is a much more im- portant conception, and one to which the former should be always reduced. The invariability and the unconditionality are, however, often difficult to establish, and we are not entitled, when we see a certain order always existing in all the observations we have made on two events, to suppose that that order is invariable and uncon- ditional. The order of day and night is one of the most invariable observed ; we know, however, that it is conditional on the posi- tions of the sun and earth, and the rotation of the earth. This is the distinction of post hoc (after this) and propter hoc (because of this).* We cannot declare the latter unless we feel that there is sufficient evidence of invariability and unconditionality ; this it is the province of scientific induction to investigate ; the mere suc- cession is patent from a single observation. V. When the invariability and unconditionality cannot be tho- roughly established, they may be found to hold within certain Innits, so that, the limiting condition being observed, others may be left out of consideration. This gives rise to experimental or empirical laws, which are of the utmost value as provisional rules. will not apply, you do not confess to yourself that it was only a simile, and need not apply to everything, but you say, * The cause of that event is a mystery which must remain for ever unknown to me.' On equally just grounds the nervous system of my umbrella is a mystery which must for ever remain unknown to me. INIy umbrella has no nervous system ; and the event to which your simile did not apply, has no cause, in your sense of the word. When we say that every effect has a cause, we mean that every event is connected with something in a way that might make somebody call that the cause of it. But I, at least, have never yet seen any single meaning of the word that could be fairly applied to the whole order of nature." * INIany writers are of a different opinion ; but so far as science is con- cerned this difference is inoperative. Dr. Carpenter {ibid.) says :— ** As Sir John Hcrschel most truly remarked, the universal consciousness of man- kind is as much in accord in regard to the existence of a real and intimato connection between cause and effect, as it is to the existence of an external world ; and that consciousness arises to every one out of his own sense of personal exertion in the origination of changes 'by his own individual agency." That sense of personal exertion arises, we maybe said to know, from the corresponding i)hysioiogical changes within him. It therefore only removes the invariable unconditional relations one step further off. But let us go back to the antecedent of these changes, to the causa causa- rum, and we at once transgress the hmits of verifiable science, and hence sail beyond our present purpose. It is widely different to say that the invariable unconditional verifiable relation is the only one to be considered, and to say that that relation is not itself a consequent of an unverifiable (or even possibly at some future period verifiable) antecedent. The latter statement is thoroughly unscientific. Dr. Carpenter considers force, as deduced from considerations of personal exertion, to be the invariable an- tecedent of causation, and says, " whilst no * law' which is simply a gene- ralization of phenomena can be considered as having any coercive action'' — ' law ' is merely a statement of invariability and unconditionality with- out reference to coercion, — " we may assign that value," viz., the posses- sion of coercive action, " to laws which express the universal conditions of the action of a force whose existence we learn from the testimony of our Q 78 LOGIC FOR CHILDKEN. [art. 79, V. vi. ART. 79, vi. vii.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 79 and as grouping phenomena for subsequent inductions.* Thus the etlect of friction is taken to be exactly proportional to the pres- sure, but this strict proportion ceases when the weight is large. Part of a beam of sunlight will be reflected from an unsilvered glass surface, according to the usual law of reflection, and part will pass through. Attempt to reflect both portions from another piece of unsilvered glass. The amount of the second reflections will differ materially according to the angles and planes of both reflections, and it is possible so to arrange the positions of the glasses that either the light reflected or transmitted by the first glass will either not be transmitted or else not reflected respectively by the second. The law of reflection and transmission therefore be- comes conditional. The investigation of this condition produced within the present century the w hole theory of polarized light. Such an experiment requires next to no apparatus, and will amuse as well as instruct the children. But the teacher must have care- fully tried the experiment himself before attempting to show it or to lead a child to make it. Those teachers who think they can perform an experiment in public, which they have not easily suc- ceeded in performing in private, have seriously misconceived their vocation. vi. The reason icliy is constantly asked, and has two meanings requiring discrimination. As respects the acts of a known volun- tary agent, we suppose an acquaintance with laws of nature, and with the method of putting himself or his actions within the influ- ence of certain laws; when therefore he does so, we presume that he desired to bring about the consequent effect. The answer to. Why did you do so ? is consequently expected to be. Because I wished to get so-and-so. That is, the reason ivhy expresses a mo- tive, a desire, an intention, a purpose, an object. A large induc- tion shows that human actions are regulated by such motives, and consciousness" — that is, from ourselves coming consciously under the rela- tion it expresses. " The assurance we feel that tho attraction of gravita- tion niffnt act imder all circumstances according to those simple laws which aiise immediately out of our dynamical conception of it, is of a very dif- ferent order from that wtich we have in regard (for example) to the laws of chemical attraction, which are as yet only generalizations of pheno- mena." The distinction is chiefly one of degree. It is the infinite num- ber of verifications to which science has accurately, and common experience roughly, subjected gravitation, as compared with those to which chemical theories (const.intly changing since Triestley's discovery of oxygen i can be subjected, which gives the real balance in favour of the foi-mer. Force is op/t/ measurable by motion : as Dr. Carpenter says {i>'jiJ.) ** the mecha- nical philosophy of the present day tends more and more to express itself in terms of motion rather than in terms of force." In English books on mechanics tho " force of gravity" is always expressed by the number 32-2, representing the number of feet which a body would describe horizontally on a frictionless surface in vacuo during one mean second of time, if it were to move uniformly with the velocity it had acquired after falling vertically iM vacuo fur one mean second of time previously. Any other mode of mea- siu"ing this force is almost " inconceivable " at the present day ; but how could it have ever been discovered or used " from the testimony of our conscioiLsnesnii " ? [4 bonce we naturally inquire into the motives of any human action Frequently, however, we find that the reason why a human being produced a certain result was nob that he intended it, but that intending something else, and ignorant of all the conditions necesl sary for attaining it, he ended in doing what he did not in the least mtend. When the conditions were such as he could not anticipate, their occurrence is given as an explanation of his failure Thus boys questioned on some school offence, allege such and such unexpected conditions as an excuse. " Why were you late ?" "I fell as I was running to school." •* Why did you not write the exercise ? " "I hurt my hand." vii. But when we get beyond human or living actions, it is not correct to assume intentions. Such an assumption has however often been made supernaturalistically, and leads to iinal causes, the intention of a supernatural being, or of an abstract beino-,' nature herself. But these are excluded from induction proper l>y the total absence of verifiability (art. 74). Suppose the question were, " Why did such a boy fall ill and die ?" No such answer as, " Because it was the will of God," can be admitted in inductioni for it is quite evident that it cannot be verified. The only an- swers would be such as a physician would give, doscribincr t1 e constitution of the boy, the conditions to which he was exposed, the growth and treatment of the disease, and so on. Even these answers are only partially verifiable by a registration of similar cases, and the whole facts on which repose the science of life. How can the reaso7i why be given scientifically? Bi/ showing the known laws wJiich iticlude the jiarticular case. Nothino- more should be attempted, and very frequently even this cannot be done.f It is also evident that we must soon come to the end of * Properly speaking, all the laws that we discover are empirical, limited by our powers of verification. But relatively to us they are perfect when they give results which are as exact as, or are more exact than, our means of verification. Prof. Clifford shows that such considerations apply even to the laws of geometry, as, for example, to the conclusion that the three angles of a plane triangle are exactly equal to two right au'jles. (Id , n. 604.) \ ^ i t Prof. Cliflford, alluding to an illustration, says, " The explanation de- scribes the unknown and unfamiliar as made up of tho lcnoN\Ti and familiar, and this, it seems to me, is tho true meaning of explanation" (p. o08, col. 1 ). "By known and familiar, I mean that which we know how to deal with, either by action in the ordinary sense, or by active thought" (p. 508, col. 2). "That a process may be capahle of explanation, it 'must break up into- simpler constituents which are already familiar to us. Now, first, this process may itself be simple, and not break up ; and secondly, it may break up into elements which are as unfiimiliar and impracticable as the original process It is no explanation to say that a body falls be- cause of gi-avitation. This attraction of two particles must alwaj^s, I think, be less familiar than the original falling body, however early the children of the future begin to read their Newton. Can the attraction itself be explained ? . . . . The attraction may be an ultimate simple fact ; or it may be made up of simpler facts utterly unlike anything that we know at present ; and in either of these cases there is no explanation. We have no right to conclude, then, that the order of events is alwavs q2 80 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. [art. 79, vii. iRT. 79, viii.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 81 onr chain, and get to laws which we are unable to include in any- higher, and then all " reasons why'* are at an end." " Why was this plate smashed?" "A stone fell upon it." "Why did the stone fall ?" " The wind blew it from the top of the wall." " Why did the wind blow it?" "There was a sudden powerful gust in such a direction." " But why sudden, why sufficiently powerful, why in this direction ?" " I don't know." — " Why was that stone on the top of the wall ?" " The builders placed it there as a coping." *' Why was it not tight ?" " The mortar had ceased to hold it ?" " Why ?'* " 1 don't know."—" Why did the stone fall on the plate, and not beside it ?'* " Because the plate was placed in a certain position, and the wind blew with a ceilain force.'* •' Why ?" " 1 don't know." — " Would a little stone have smashed the plate?" " Probably not." "Why?" " Because it would not have acquired sufficient force in falling." " Why ?" " This can be calculated from its weight, the height from which it fell, the law of gravitation, and the cohesion of the parts of the plate.'* " Why was the weight or the height such ? Why does the force of gravitation exist? Why do the parts of a plate so cohere?" " I don't know." — And so on. It is often useful to follow up such a train of questions (here purposely much curtailed) and then finally to show that all the reason given was the inclusion of facts within laws, and these within more general laws, so that the re- sult was simply showing the manner, not the motive or purpose, and that, using whij in the human sense, we may sum up the re- sult by saying, inductive science seeks to know tht how, and not the why.* capable of being explained" (p. 509, c. 1). At the same time, we have no right to conclude that any given order of events will remain for ever in- explicable. As Prof. Chtford says in reference to another question, " It seems to me that we do not know, and that the recognition of our ignor- ance is the 8iu:est way to get rid of it" {ib. p. 505, c. 1). * In the words of Comte, inductive science " ecarte comme radicalement inaccessible et profondement oiseuse, toute recherche sur les causes propre- ment dites, premieres ou finales, des evenements quelconques. Dans sea conceptions theoriques, elle explique toujours comment et jamais pourquoi. Mais, quandelle indique les moyensde dinger notre activite, elle fait, au con- traire, prevaloir constamment la consideration du but." Cath. Fos. p. 13. Dr. Carpenter concludes his presidential addiess thus : — " The science of modem times .... fixing its attention exclusively on the order of Nature," that is, of phenomena — "has separated itself wholly from theo- logy, whose function it is to seek after its cause. In this, science is fully justified ahke by the entire independence of its objects, and by the his- torical fact that it has been continually hampered and impeded in its search for the truth as it is in nature" — for the discovery of invariable im- conditional relations, giving the power of prediction and consequent verifi- cation — "by the restraints which theologians have attempted to impose on its inquiries. But when science, passing beyond its own limits, pre- sumes to take the place of theology, and sets up its own conception of the order of nature as a sufficient account of its cause" — I do not know any man of ' science' who has done so ; the words seem aimed at Comte, to whom the preceding quotation shows that they are inapplicable ; the whole stattmtut should have been worded hypothetically,—" it is invading < viii. One other word, nature, remains to be considered. It has been greatly abused, and is often used euphemistically for a supernatural power. At other times it means the universe itself, or its constitution, or the laws which any object obeys; sometimes it is even used for all the universe except man, or except animals. It must consequently be employed with caution. If we talk of a " natural" spontaneous action, we mean an action according to the laws which we usually see aflfecting the object, so that there is no restraint, in the sense already explained. When we " naturally'* conclude that so and so is the case, we draw our conclusions from such knowledge as we recollect at the moment, without investiga- tion. Policemen see a man stagger from a public-house, and fall down. They " naturally" conclude that he is drunk, and lock him up. But in several instances of the kind, the man has been found dead the next morning, having fallen in a fit. " Naturally" often means " hastily, negligently, ignorantly.'* a province of thought to which it has no claim, and not unreasonably pro- vokes the hostility of those who ought to be its best friends;" and woidd be so if they had had sufl&cient education in those merest elements of sci- ence to understand what science does seek to attain, and not to attribute to science aims utterly alien to any possible conception of science admis- sible in these days. " For whilst the deep-seated instincts of humanity, and the profoundest researches of philosophy, alike point to mind as the one and only source of power" — in man, to assume the same;, or anything approaching to the same superhumanly, is to emulate Phaethon — trans- nature is degraded by reducing it to eis-nature — "it is the high prerogative of science to demonstrate the uuitt/ of the power which is operating through the Hmitless extent and variety of the universe," — ^how if the power itself is beyond scientific ken ? really, science strives to demonstrate the harmo- nious character of the invariable unconditional relations ; it can't do more, and it can only at present forefeel, scarcely state, far from demonstrate, even this — " and to trace its continuity" — continuance of the invariability — "through the vast series of ages that have been occupied in its evolu- tion." The last words appear to be a mistake, for " in the evolution of the universe," see the conclusion of this note. It is curious that Dr. Carpenter should have been betrayed into thus committing the very mistake that he deprecates, — transplanting religion into science. That he has done so, and that it was one of the very objects of his address to do so, Dr. Car- penter admits in a letter subsequently published in the Echo (the date of which I am unable to give), where he says : "I expressed the opinion that science points to (though at present I should be far from saying that it demonstrates) the origination of all power in mind ; and this is the only point in my whole address which has any direct theological bearing. When metaphysicians, shaking oflf the bugbear of materialism," — which is generally the appUcation of lower laws to higher phenomena, and is fl^ best a doubtful analogy, — " will honestly and courageously study the phe- nomena of the mind of man in their relation to those of his body, I believe that they will find in that relation their best arguments for the presence of Infinite mind in universal Nature." This lies beyond the purpose of a purely scientific investigation. It is important that intellectual verifiable Bcience, and emotional unverifiable religion, eihouldbe sharply distinguished. The following quotations from the same letter throw further light on Dr. Carpenter's notion of * coercive' laws. " My object" — in the Brighton ad- dress — "was to show — (1) That what we call *laws of nature' are simply 82 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. [art. 80. ART. 80.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 83 80. Tlio province of scientific induction then is to discover lairs, which take tlie form of genenil assertions respecting such matters as are appreciable by the senses, and are hence called appparancea (Latin), or phenomena (Greek). These appearances are, however, generally supposed to refer to some underlying he!nle, a Diatant) is a plant or an animal, and hence to lay down unmistakable cliaracteinstics which should determine that a man and a zoophyte are ani- mals, and a Sensitive Plant or a Veuus's Fly-trap {Diotiaea muscipnla) are not animals. Much harm has been done by confusing artificial and natural distinctions, and by forgetting that language is founded upon loose obser- v;ition of natural differences which are treated as artificial and strict. One ot the great sources of difficidty in judging of the permanence of species, or natural character of genem, arises from this very looseness. Hence, again, in all cases, the danger of pui-hing home mere verbal distinctions. ( observe how loosely we use such words as hot, cold, black, white, full, « mjtty. One would think these must be absolute terms. But we have hotter and colder, blacker and whiter, fuller and emptier ! To dr?iw the line between hot and cold, black and white, full and empty, becomes really difficult. Don't blame a boy, as I have heard boys blamed, for saying that one cup of tea is "fuller" than another, or that a third is "almost quite empty." They are merely endeavouring to give a precise impress to words long w'om smooth by use. But the teacher may well " imjnove the occa- sion" from time to time, and lead a boy to think more accuratelv, when he catches them out in such tricks. A few laughing words will often be of much greater service on such an occasion than an hour's serious lecture. There is a chance of the joke being remembered through life. The hour's lecture, like other bores, will be certainly forgotten. See also the quota- tion from Prof. Clifford, art. 74, last note, p. 66. ARTS. 80, 8].] LOGIC FOE CHILDREN. 85 \i acquainted with a number of animals, vegetables, and inorganic substances, to render the classifications of animate and inanimate quite distinct, and to make the separation of animal and plant life easy. They will learn to appreciate the great laws relating to all the three sets, and how these are aflfected by plant life, and still more by animal life. But these special considerations belong rather to science teaching, than to the few general remarks to which I am forced to limit myself. 81. The so-called canons of induction need not occupy us much, for school life does not afford many instances by which they can be exemplified. They are (as already stated) merely elaborations of the first principle of forming the simplest possible supposition (art. 76), and serve to show how that supposition may be cor- rected, and how it must almost always be considered as pro- visional. They are, as you know, the methods of agreement, dif- ference, concomitant variations and residues, which may be used sepa- rately or jointly, and are chiefly applicable for experimental research. The object is in every case to determine between which two sets of events there exists an invariable unconditional rela- tion. One of the first discoveries made is, that one set of events may be preceded, and apparently invariably and unconditionally preceded, by totally different sets of events. Thus, a man's death is the consequence of certain diseases, certain poisons, certain wounds, certain constrictions, &c., so that, given a dead man, to find how he came by his death, is often a difficult, sometimes an impossible problem to resolve, as shown by coroner's inquests. In making deductions from inductions, we are obliged, from our present ignorance of the logic of sequence, to reduce the problem to one of consistency of assertions, thus : — Let the assertion, " the events A come first," be X!', " the events B come first," be Y", "the events M come second" be Z." Then fX.z, \Y.z represent the assertions, "if the events A (or B) come first, the events M come second," (art. 59, b.) On develop- ing the series of complexes (art. 54) we obtain X.Y.Z X.7/.Z aj.Y.Z x.y.Z fX.Y.z fX.i/.z faj.Y.z x.y.Z. Consequently the occurrence of the events M as second are con- sistent with the occurrence of either or both or neither of the events A and B as first, and the only conclusion which can be drawn is, that if the events M do not occur, neither of the sets of events A or B can have preceded. This is the ambiguity which arises from what is called the plurality of causes, and which besets us in endeavouring to find the cause from the effect.* * Dr. Carpenter [ibid.) gives as an example of this Mr. Lockyer's speak- ing " as confidently of this sun's chromosphere of incandescent hydrogen and of the local outbursts which cause it to send forth projections tens of thousands of miles high as if he had been able to capture a flask of this gas, and had generated water by causing it to unite with oxygen" — hydro- gen being the only know n gas which will do so, whereas hydrogen has not been proved to be the only extra-mundane gas which when incandescent 86 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. [art. 81. But here a new point has come to light. Both sets of e\'eiits A and B might come first ; that is, they might occur simultane- ously before the events M. Do sets of events which concur modify each other or not ? Here we come to three laws, which were first only known as laws of motion, but which science has come to extend over the whole of its region. They are extremely extensive inductions, and can be only partially illustrated. ITie real proof is in the verification of the deductions made from them. Succinctly stated, they are, — i. The Law of Persistence. Every condition of things tends to remain imaltered, and resists external attempts at alteration. ii. The Law of Compomtlon. Every action upon a system or condition of things produces its whole eflect, without regard to any simultaneous action. iii. The Law of Reaction. Every action upon a system of things calls up a contrary, and, when properly measured, a precisely equivalent action. The law of persistence is however partly due to an hypothesis by which internal are replaced by external actions ; and that of c^m- positi^m, to the consideration of so-called generated forces as new forces, bearing in mind the great law, quite recently evolved by men still living, the conservation of energy, showing that no really new force is ever generated, but that such apparent new forces are but transformations of others which have superficially disap- peared.* These matters can of course only be touched on in passing. It will simply be the teacher's business, in any investi- gation, to bring back the pupils' thoughts when they wander from these secure paths. Analogy is not so much an inductive method, as a means of sug- gesting the direction for inductive investigations. Two sets of events agree in a*nuraber of particulars. The first has certain consequences. We conceive that the second will have conse- quences also agreeing in many particulars with the first. This is merely a simple supposition, founded on induction based on such observations. But observation also shows that the analogy fre- quently breaks down, and hence we now use it sim])ly as a sugges- tion. The analogies of sound and light suggested the undulatory ■will produce a certain coloured line on being viewed through the spectro- scope, on which Mr. Lockyer's conclusions were based. For the same reason he shows that a new yellow line which has been ohserve<^l in the Hpectroscope need not necessarily be duo to a new metal helium. In fact, the state of temperature at the sun's surface so far exceeds any on which "we can experiment on earth, that the incandescent substances in the sun may affect our spectroscope differently from those on earth. • Perhaps this conservation of energ\' may be considered as merely a phase of the law of persistence, when stated as by Dr. Caq:)enter {ibid.), " Energy of any kind, whether manifested in the * molar' motion of masses, or consisting in the 'molecular' motion of atoms, must continue under some form or other without abatement or decay." The forms, however, aro •o different, that it is only by the precisely equivalent mechanical effects that we infer the identity or conservation of the energy. The law of persistence, however, extends to social relations. ARTS. 81^ 82j i. ii.] logic for children. 87 fA n( p^( theory for the latter ; but this has to repose upon its own merits, and the whole nature of wave motion in the latter had to be con- ceived so difierently from that in the former, that the analogy rapidly ceased to be useful. Ordinary language is full of analogies arising . from vague metaphors or partial resemblances hazily seized, and the results of" pushing these home" are often sufficient to discredit them. But, in all our formations and applications of inductive laws, we assume that there are events and objects so similar, that if one be substituted for the other, the results could be substituted one for the other. This inter changeahility is dis- tinct from analogy, although it probably suggested it, because the interchangeability is only partial, not total. Thus, in respect of being an object of thought separately conceivable, a mouse is in- terchangeable with an elephant, and on such grounds reac all the inductions respecting number. In respect of being fluid at ordinary temperatures, water is interchangeable with mercury. By inves- tigations of waves formed in mercury, important conclusions were c()nse((ueritly obtained for waves of water. But here the resem- blance was so great, we should hardly call the effects analogous. The resemblance between the government of a family by the father, and of a state by the sovereign, is however merely an ana- logy, suggesting much, but not giving a ground for transference of conclusions. 82. i. The method of agreement is simply this. A great number of diiferent sets of autucedcnts (or events which come first) having been naturally or experimentally observed, in all of which the same events A occur, and it being found, on noting all the corre- sponding different sets of consetpients (or events which come second,) that the same set of events M occur in all of them, it is assumed as the simplest (of course provisional) supposition that there is an invariable, unconditional relation between the two sets of events A and M, so that wUenevev A occurs (and not merely in the cases hitherto observed) we shall look to see M, and whenever M occurs, we may possibly learn that A preceded. Having made this assumption, we reduce it to a formal assertion, and use it as in our previous deductive logic, in connection with other asser- tions, and then compare, if possible all, but at any rate some of the conclusions with accurate observation. If the two again agree, we feel more confident. But a great degree of hesitation will always attach to this method owing to tlie plurality of causes (art. 81, p. 85). ii. The method of difference is much more satisfactory. A set of antecedents and consequents being known and observed, sup- pose that when one of the antecedents is omitted, the consequents also are observed to become different by the omission of one ; or when an additional antecedent is introduced, the consequents are likewise changed by the addition of one. In these cases the sim- plest supposition is that there was an invariable unconditional re- lation between the omitted antecedent and consequent, and also between the additional antecedent and consequent. But numerous experiments aro necessary to force this scientifically home to the mind, as it is evident some intermediate links may have been ^^ I-OGIC FOR CHILDREN. [aRT. 82, iii. iv. overlooked, or some other additions or omissions unobserved It has however given rise to the popular use of the word 'cause' (art. 79, iv.)* iii. The method of concomitant variations is a common variety of the method of difference. Here no antecedent is entirely re- moved or added, but one antecedent is varied in intensity, and a corresponding variation of intensity in one consequent is ob- served. We must guard against expecting these variations to be ot the same kind, or that if one takes pla^e in one direction, the other will also constantly take place in one direction ; or that the antecedents will alter in the same ratio as the conse- quents. It IS very commonly said that the effect varies as the cause. I his is an attempt to give mathematical accuracy of expression to what has been only vaguely observed. As thus expressed, the proposition is far from being generally true. If you spill a glass of water over a person's hand, the effect is very different ti-om letting a small quantity drop upon the hand gradually. This ii an excellent experiment for boys. If you diminish the heat, alcohol continually diminishes in volume ; water diminishes to a certam extent, and then increases. This should be shown, for the lact is valuable. iv. The method of residues consists simply in deducting from a set of consequents those known, from previous complete inductions, to be the result of a portion of the antecedents, and then making the simplest supposition that the remaining consequents are due to tlie remaining antecedents. We might go on to the combination of the different methods, but the only real point of importance in all these methods for our present purpose, is to understand that they are all referable to the one law of forming the simplest supposition, and that the conclu- sions are therefore all provisional, requiring constant verification. ±rom this we see the necessity of registering all such conclusions ARTS. 82, 83.J LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 89 * Dr- Carpenter says (ibid.): "While fully accepting the logical defi- f^^pV .'•'''" "' ^^I'^^^-r"^^^^ ^'^ <^«°^'^rence of antecedents'on which l^e onf nnlT"^^^^ unconditionally consequent,' we can always angle out one dynamical antecedent-the power that does the work-from the aggregate ot material conditions under which that power may be dis- tributed and apphed." This distinction of the ^ot^v./Jand th^J^^.I . " No donh?''!'>,^^ ^'"r ^^''^'^T^ ^°d theoretical. It is never obiTgatory. No doubt, he continues, " the temi cause is ver>' loosely employed hi which^^l^f, '' power which acts m each case, from the conditions under from Vi«h1 a *^' ."^'"^l^^ ^^^^'^^ "P ^y gunpowder, a man falling ^uTes" " f h^' r ^i^^'v T ^^ ?*"^' ^'' ^^^n>enter make^ the « efficient causes "the force locked up in the gunpowder, ... the gravity which was equ^y pulling him down while ho rested upon it [the ladder 1 ^ndiffnn^T ""fft^ °''/f ^^'" ^l«P^«vely» and all thereat, " the material ^^^ ' '' ^^«*^\"^}°§. (*!> "se the old scholastic term) only ' their formal ^^?H ,.^%^J«1« distinction scientifically appreciable, excluding the o?aA 7^^ Ti'^^S" ^f^^^' metaphysical te^rJns, is sh;>wnat the^close vLnVJnl!: 5> \l .^^ ^^^ *^® quotation from Prof. Chflford respecting the vagubnees of the term cause m the note f to art. 79, iv., p. 76. as have been satisfactorily verified, and this registration takes the form of a -treatise upon a particular branch of science, as distinct from the general investigation of the principles which lead to the necessity of such investigation. Induction is the father of science, not science itself. But science cannot be properly appreciated till its parentage is understood.* 83. In the preceding remarks I have endeavoured to indicate the principal points which" a teacher must attend to in teaching induction. On account of the great difficulties which attend the preparation for verification in all great inductions, it is not pos- sible to obtain a complete view of the subject without long and arduous study of the principal inductive sciences. Hence treatises upon Inductive Logic drift more or less into a philosophy of the elementary principles of the special sciences, which cannot be even partially understood without something more than an ordi- nary household acquaintance with them. Thus almost half of Prof. Bain's work on Induction is devoted to the " Logic of the Sciences," and yet each science is treated with almost bald suc- chictness. Now it is evident that all this is out of the question in schools, and that it is only in advanced schools with very capable masters, that it can be even partially taught, in respect, for ex- ample, to geometry, mechanics, chemistry, sociability. But a few great principles can be always inculcated, on innumerable occasions, so that when the child grows up he may find the forest cleared for the subsequent cultivation of science. These are the principles which I have been trying to present to your notice. If a child leaves school with a firm conviction of the uniformitij of nature, that is, the invariahility and unconditumality of relationSy and a constant habit of making the simplest suppositions consistent with a representation of the whole of the facts hnown, he will be a totally different being, intellectually, from the child who has been taught the usual routine, in which no notice of these great * Prof. Cliflford concluded his admirable lecture as follows (p. 511, c. 2) : " By scientific thought we mean the application of past experience to new circumstances, by means of an observed order of events. By saying that this order of events is exact, we mean that it is exact enough to correct experiments by, but we do not mean that it is theoretically or absolutely exact, because we do not know. The process of inference we found to be in itself an assumption of uniformity, and that, as the known exactness of the uniformity became greater, the stringency of the inference increased. By saying that the order of events is reasonable, we do not mean that everything has a purpose, or that everything can be explained, or that everything has a cause ; for neither of these is true. But we mean that to every reasonable question," [previously defined (p. 611, c. 2) as one which is asked in terms ot ideas justified by previous experience, without itself contradicting that experience,] " there is an intelligible answer, which either we or posterity may know by the exercise of scientific thought. . . . . Scientific thought is not an accompaniment or condition of human progress, but human progress itself. And for this reason the question what its characters are, ... is the question of all questions for the human race." 90 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. [art. 83. ART. 84.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 91 princi])Ies occurs * And there seems to be no good reason why a child should not attain to such habits and convictions. The material is all there, and it remains with the teadier to employ it. A few occasions have been pointed out as they arise, from which the method I would adopt generally may be inferred. But some additional special observations seem desirable. ♦ In the preceding articles I have made much use of the philosoj)hic laws as stated by Augnste Comte. As these laws are not easily accessible in the form he has assigned, it seems expedient to annex them, as far as possible, in the words of his Politique Positive, vol. 4, pp. 173 — 180, pub- lished in 1854. As they are there always stated in an oblique form, I have thought it best to alter the construction, and also to disinter them from the body of the paragraphs in wliich they occur, and arrange them in the order which Comte has i-ather indicated than actually carried out. The greater part of these laws are generally recognized, and it is only the form which has been given to them that is peculiar to Cemte ; this form, however, is of consider.ible importance. Laws 7, 8, 9 are peculiar to Comte's philosophy, and have been vehemently disputed. Laws 10, 11, 12, 13, in their original form, are Kepler's, Galileo's, and Newton's laws of motion, and D' Alembert's principle, respectively. The law of the Conserva- tion of Energy, due to Mayer, Helmlioltz and Joule (art. 81), was unknown to Comte, but he would probably have included it under law 10. At the end of each law here referred to, I have added the number of the article in which it is used and explained, and this will dispense with the necessity of any translation. The law is generally printed in italics in the articles cited. ^Ticre no article is referred to, the law has not been used. " Principes TJniversels snr le concours desquels doit reposer la systema- tisiition finale du dogme positif. Les quinze lois universelles do la ]>hilosophie prijmiere, reparties entre trois groupes, dont les deux demiers, doubles chacun du j)remier, se decomposent respectivement en deux series cgales. I. Le premier groupe, non moins relatif a la constitution interieui-e de nos speculations qu'ii lour destination exterieure. 1. Principe fundamental. Fomiez I'hypothi se la plus simple que com - porte I'ensemble des documents a representor. (Art. 76, p. fiS.) 2. Reconnaissez rimmuabilite des lois (juelconques, qui reginsent les etres d'apres les evenements, quoique I'ordre abstrait permette seul de les ap- precier. (Art. 78, p. 70.) 3. Les modifications quelconques de I'ordre imiversel se trouvent bor- nees a I'intensito des pheuomenes, dont rarrangement demeure inalt*^- rable. (Art. 78, p. 71.) IL Le second groupe, directement relatif a I'entendement, se decompose en deux, statique et dynamique. a. Statique. L'ordro consiste dans I'etablissemont de I'unite. 4. Subordonnez les constructions subjectives aux materiaux objectifs. (Art. 80, p. S3.) 5. Les images inttrieures sont moins vivcs et moins nettes que les im- pressions exterieiu*e8. (Art. 80, p. 82.) 6. Que I'image normale aio la preponderance sur celles que I'agitation cerebrale fait simultanement surgir. b. Dynamique. Le progres consiste dans le devcloppement de I'ordre. 7. Chaque entendement pr^scnte une succession de trois etats, fictif, abstrait et positif, envers des conceptions quelconques, mais avec ime vi- teasc proportionnee a la genenilite des pheuomenes conespondauts. ( 84. Deductive logic can be taught by a continual recurrence to one single class of instances, the occurrence of letters in words. Inductive logic cannot be taught without recurrence to a great variety of classes of instances, as the great variety alone can give suflRcient sanction to its conclusions. Deductive logic requires a very close attention to a large number of particulars, which in- volves a great strain on the mind unless assisted by something approaching to mathematical severity of notation, while the very abstractness of that notation makes it formidable to many minds. Inductive logic, in its widest and simplest principles, can be studied at first without the same attention to minute details, without any approach to a mathematical notation, and by a con- tinual recurrence to facts actually present to the eye or mhid, which arouse and fix attention by their concrete character. It is quite true that we cannot proceed even a moderate distance in strict induction, without close deduction (art. 72); but in the familiar instances of daily life, the deductions are usually so simple that they may be assumed as self-evident. The habit of making them by aid of the simplest supposition principle (which the teacher will take care is properly applied) will be an excellent introduction to that stricter form already explained, which is, after all, merely an application of the same principle. Hence we must not wait for instruction in deductive logic before we proceed to induction, and we must therefore not begin by teaching induc- tion systematically. The object is to lead the young mind by mere work to appreciate some of the great principles upon which 8. On reconnait une progression analogue pour I'activite, d'abord con- queranto, puis defensive, enfin industrielle. 9. On eteud aussi la meme marchc a la sociabihte, d'abord domestique puis civique, enfin universelle. * III. Le troisieme groupe, ou domine robjcctivite, se divise en deux series, celle des plus objectives, et celle des plus subjectives. a. Les plus objectives ne furent d'abord appreciees qu' envers les pheno- menes mathematiques. 10. Tout etat, statique ou dynamique, tend a persister spontan^^ment, sans aucune alteration, en resistant aux perturbations exterieures. (Art. 81, p. 26.) 11. Un systeme quelconque a I'aptitude a maintenir sa constitution, active ou passive, quand ses elements eprouvent des mutations siniul- tan^'es, pourvu qu'elles soient exactement communes. (Art. 81, p. 26.) 12. II existe partout une equivalence necessaire entre la reaction et Tac- tion, si leur intensite se trouve mesuree conformement a la nature de chaque conflit. (Art. 81, p. 26.) b. Les plus subjectives, oti I'origine mathematique devient moins appre- ciable. 13. Subordonnez partout la thoorie du mouvement a celle de 1' exis- tence, en concevant tout progres comme le devcloppement de I'ordre corre- spondant, dont les conditions quelconques regissent les mutations qui con- stituent revolution. 14. Le classement positif s'effectue toujours d'apres la generaHte crois- sante ou decroissante, taut subjective qu'objective. (Art. 80, p. 24.) 15. Subordonnez tout intern ediare aux deux cxtiOmes dont il opere la Uaisou." 92 LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. [arts. 84, 85, i. ii. indnctions are made, but not itself to make larj^e or accurate in- ductions. The following are merely suggestions, which an intel- ligent teacher will readily seize, and which indeed do not in them- selves present any novelty. 85. i. The first care must be to put a child into the proper con- dition of mind to make or appreciate inductions. Hence accurate ohsei-vation must be cultivated. The children must see things and describe them. Enter a room, remain a short time, retire and tell, or better still write down, the names of all the objects you can re- collect, (this was one of the exercises of the celebrated French con- jurer, Robert Houdin). The room may be exchanged for a shop, and entering for passing. Take a walk, name all the roads turning to the right or left, the bridges, rivers, streets, isolated houses. Pass a house, describe the number of storeys, the nature of the roof, the number and situation, or any peculiarity in the shape of the windows. Describe a person seen, height, sex, age (child, adult, old), colour of hair and eyes, complexion, hands, boots or shoes, dress (especially the colours of its parts, or any peculiarity in its shape). In a walk mention the number of persons seen, and divide them into male and female, and subdivide according to age; also divide first by age, and then subdivide by sex; also mention number of quadrupeds, and number of each kind of quadruped observed. Describe each child in the school (if not large) or in the class, or class-room. Such descriptions and sta- tistics should be reduced to writing, and stated in a tabular form. The above arc merely specimens to guide the teacher. Occasions for such observations arise constantly in the course of instruction, in languages, in arithmetic, in geometry, in lessons on objects, especially when concerning minerals, crystals, shells, flowers, animals. Extreme accuracy should be always appreciated. The natural powers of observation, however, differ materially. Beware of thinking a quick observer clever, or a slow observer dull. A teacher can hardly make a greater mistake. ii. Next take invariable sequences of common occwTetice^ with a view of making the /ac< of the existence of such sequences familiar. The rising of the sun and all heavenly bodies in the east, their passing to the south, and setting in the west. Light following sunrise, and disappearing at sunset. Power of vision following lighting a candle in the dark. Falling of a stone unsuppoi-ted ; weariness resulting from supporting a stone in the hand ; weari- ness from any continued exertion. Sleepiness following wakeful- ness. Wakefulness following excitement. Pain following burns or blows. Hunger and thirst following much exertion, or long abstention from eating and drinking. Heat from approaching fire, or from exercise. Solution of salt and sugar, and non-solu- tion of stones in water. Sinking of stones and non-sinking of cork placed on surface of water. Children growing taller as they grow older ; adults not altering in height. Adults growing weak as they grow old. Death following life with or without disease, in vegetables, domestic animals, and man. Budding in spring, fall of leaf in autumn. Meat rendered fit to eat by cooking. Improve- ment in sports and work by practice. And so on, and so on, the ART. 85, iii. — v.] LOGIC FOR CHILDREN. 93 great point being by extremely numerous examples, sure to be familiar to children, to prepare them for the acceptance of the general principle of invariability throughout nature, inanimate and animate, involuntary and voluntary, individual and social. iii. Accidents of common occurrence should also be noted, and it should be shown that in several cases an invariability was unex- pectedly brought into action. A boy runs, trips, falls, cuts his hand ; here the accident was his tripping, that is, his having so wrongly measured his distance as to strike the stone ; this was " avoidable," the rest " unavoidable," an important distinction. Two boys running round a corner in opposite directions collide with pain; here there was ignorance; see whether it was alto- gether unavoidable. A boy writing is startled by a sudden noise and blots his book ; which is the accident — the noise, the start, or the blot ? After many such notions of accident, proceed to others, as the state of the weather on certain days of the month, at cer- tain changes of the moon, &c. As these changes are badly re- membered, make boys record them, as well as they can. It is very important to upset the prophecies of weather almanacs, espe- cially in agricultural districts. Show, however, that weather obeys the law of averages, so that we expect a certain kind of weather in certain months. See the former exercises (art. 79, ii. p. 73.) iv. Slimple inductions may now be introduced. The fir st kind which I would suggest aie not the most simple in themselves, but are most simple to the children, because they have probably been in the habit of making them. They consist of investigations into what has happened, inquiries into circumstances of school and social life. Thus, " Has John been here ? " Some children may have seen something which John usually brings, a book, a hat, a parcel, and hence conclude he has been here. This should be followed up. " It is a very good simple supposition, but could not the things have come otherwise? Are they always brought by John, and no one else ? " We have here the plurality of causes exemplified. Again, a dispute arises in a game; the evidence on each side is taken, the importance of accurate observation appears in contradictions where good faith is assumed; the necessity of deliberation is shown ; inferences will have been probably substi- tuted for the statement of direct observation ; the differences be- tween eyesight and hearsay will be displayed; the impossibility of decision, that is, of making a safe induction, may become appa- rcTit, or hasty decisions may be shown to be false. An event hap- pens in a town, there is a trial reported, a question of identity or alibi arises ; the evidence must be scrutinized. And so on. V. The next class of inductions are really more simple, but re- quire more careful and exact treatment, and hence have to be taken last. Two stones are let fall from the same height, and reach the ground at the same time. Does this depend on their weights, actual or relative, on the particular height? Vary both. Very light weights, pieces of paper, or feathers, take a longer time in falling. Show that this time can be increased by creating a wind : show that if, by attaching a little weight, the paper be made to fall sideways in calm air, it more nearly falls in the same time as a heavy stone. Show that if upon a flat weight (as a penny) a smaller piece of paper be laid, both the paper and 94 LOGIC FOR CHILDEEN, [art. 85, V. wciKbt will fall in the same time. Make simple suppositions with re- Tpect to time of tall ing being independent of weight but dependent on air Experiment on resistance of air generally, by movmg hand or flat body, full face or sideways. Similarly m water Ex- Sent with kites and oars. Experiment with throwing bodies E" motions cf rotation. Experiment with throwing and droppTng in water. Two weights slung over a pulley, give a rou-h Atwood's machine, and lead to many valnable results, as to rateof falling in equal times, as to time of falling depending on I^ra and difference' of weights. Make pendnluni of thread and buUet of stone, find law of variation of its length as compared w"th its time of vibration. Find length of seconds pendulum, by Counting oscUations-swings is the child's word-and difference o?rates^of different pendulums by observing th^Sn'of '^v^s Apply to clocks, beating time m music, &C; Reflection of faves balls carefully observed and measured, giving average angle of reflection equal to average angle of incidence, and leading to the induction that it is only obstacles (such as rough vvall or ground and imperfect elasticity) which prevent exact equality. ReA/f ''?" of light" showing the law to be exact. Refraction of light Limits to both by polarisation, as before explained (art. 79, v. p. 77) Ma-Tetic attraction, formation of needles into magnets, polanty of Seedles, the north of the magnet compared with position ol polar star Determination of south from the position of sun Ened by observing shadows of a pole in the P^^ygff^; com^rison of this with magnetic south, and comparisons of time of s^n's southing with the clock noon. Electric attraction of rubbed sealing wax and rubbed glass for chips or pieces of cork, e pectuy suspended by silk strings and the Bubsequent repulsion. Experiments on sound, law of reflection of sound as in light, echoes, whispering tubes, scratch at end of long pole heard at ^therrates of light and sound. This last should be reauced to measurement. Children at different distances clap hands when Another ^-^ises his hand, the sounds are heard m succession. Measure distance (about 1120 feet, at a te^P^f '"[k "^ ^, Fahrenheit) at which sound is heard one second after the hands were seen to be clapped. Apply to thunder and lightning, to determine the distance of the storm. It seems scarcely necessary to repeat that no one can have a proper notion of the meaning and power of induction who has not Sone through at .east some course of some particular science, fr° ated in sSch a manner as to show.the elementary ob«.ervationB the primary inductions, the experiments for gendering those inductions more precise, their statement as definite assertions, Ihe deductions dmwn from these assertions, the verifications of the conclusions thereby obtained, and the F«'-*""°°^,.'f ^" throughout to avoid error either from maccurate observation, or imperfect ratiocination. Success in teaching depends on the teacher's own knowledge and power °/ communication. Book learning can at most suggest. He must have hand ed the tools hTmself He must know what induction is, practically as well as theoretically. A few such teachers are even now to be touna. May they soon be rife. , Printed by C. P. Hodgson k Son, Gough Square, Fleet Street, B.C. i / ^=*.\ COLUMB A UNIVERS 002605341 1 . ' J -I' t '■r ' f .^ -^-* -r?^.'?? 9PM ^w. -5 V .-* v.? # A !\ rr>;^ *l»^ ^* ^■' ' ^ Jt- '^ *^S '•• '-.v'SI jJi.*J!f.^.^ |«|r.^*^ s --^-t f^w^^^p--* '''' "" • " ■ "•-» ' :^-;l-. Sf,^ 1 ^XiJ^ ■-^f; l~ •^■■^ ^' *^^il}»|^-, 'yi K"'- m ''%.- i. "'If^-^ ^X (*<^=" l'*^:>.J f?J •j(*i ,«•«■■ aii«if^