MASTER NEGATIVE NO. 93-81194- MICROFILMED 1 993 COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY LIBRARIES/NEW YORK as part of the . t^ • *» "Foundations of Western Civilization Preservation Project Funded by the ENDOWMENT FOR THE HUMANITIES Reproductions may not be made without permission from Columbia University Library COPYRIGHT STATEMENT The copyright law of the United States - Title 1 7, United States Code - concerns the making of photocopies or other reproductions of copyrighted material. Under certain conditions specified in the law, libraries and archives are authorized to furnish a photocopy or other reproduction. One of these specified conditions is that the photocopy or other reproduction is not to be used for any purpose other than private study, scholarship, or research." If a user makes a request for, or later uses, a photocopy or reproduction for purposes in excess of fair use," that user may be liable for copyright infringement. This institution reserves the right to refuse to accept a copy order If, in its judgement, fulfillment of the order would Involve violation of the copyright law. A UTHOR: REES, DANIEL TITLE: CONTEMPORARY ETHICS PLACE: LEIPZIG DATE: ^^^^^g^g^jyMMM^Mj^AHMlHHIlHg COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY LIBRARIES PRESERVATION DEPARTMENT Master Negative # BIDLIOGRAPHIC MICROFORM TARGET Original Material as Filmed - Existing Bibliographic Record •«*P|i«"«* Z8 V 2 Rees, Daniel 1866- Dlas#rtatlgn Leipzig 1892 Contemporary English ethics o > Restrictions on Use: S^^y^ TECHNICAL MICROFORM DATA REDUCTION RATIO: /^i^. FILM SIZE: IMMiE PLACEMENT: lA Ol^ IB IIB _ DAfE FILMED: W^jf3_ INITIALS__^4z___ HLMEDBY: RESEARCH PUBLICATIONS. INC WOODBRIDGE. CT ■MM Association for Information and Imago Management 1100 Wayne Avenue, Suite 1100_ Silver Spring, Maryland 20910 301/587-8202 Centimeter 123456789 10 11 '""""■ ' iiinlimlmiliiiiliiiiliiiilmiliiiiliiiiliiiiliniliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiili Inches 1 T TT7TT 1.0 I.I 1.25 I I I I I [fia 2,5 ■ 43 iri Itt US \2^ 140 1.4 2.2 2.0 1.8 1.6 12 iiiiliin 13 14 15 mm iiiiliinliiimiiiliiiil r I 1 i I I I f MRNUFRCTURED TO RUM STRNORRDS BY RPPLIED IMRGE, INC. ^ ^ ed. 1882: Descent of Man 2® ed. 1877. Organism and environment. Variation. Natural Selection. Habit Instinct — natural and domestic. Growth of moral sense. End of conduct CHAPTER III. Spencer : Data of Ethics; Stephen : Science of Ethics (1882). S I. Spencer. A. Descriptive — from physical, biological, psycho- logical and sociological standpoint. B. Normative: ultimate end happiness ; immediate end distribution of means to happiness. Egoism. Altruism. S 2. Stephen. Conduct determined by feeling and reason. The individual and the race. Society an organism. The family the social 7^ unit. Contents of the Moral Law. Sympathy. Sanction of Morality. ^-.5CHAPTER IV. Sidgwlck: Methods of Ethics f ed. 1884; Sorley: Ethics of Naturalism (1885); Alexander: Moral Order and Progress (1889); Muirhead: Elements of Ethics [i^gi). Pleasure. Desire. Is desire always interested? Sidgwick's account of the end, criticised. Desiderata in the evolution theory. CHAPTER V. Martineau: Types of Ethical Theory 2« ed. 1886. Perception and Conscience. Objects of Moral Judgment. Springs of action— psychological and moral order. Duty to God, to man, to self. CHAPTER VI. Green: Prolegomena to Ethics 2^ ed. 1884. Theory of knowledge. Want impulse, desire. Desire and Intellect Desire and Will. Intellect and Will. The Moral Ideal: its personal and formal character; its origin and developnjent Its application to Conduct CHAPTER I. UTILITARIANISM. "Kant, in the Metaphysics of Ethics, lays down an uni- versal first principle as the origin and ground of moral obli- gation; it is this:— 'So act, that the rule on which thou actest would admit of being adopted as a law by all rational beings'. But when he begins to deduce from this precept any of the actual duties of morality, he fails, almost gro- tesquely, to show that there would be any contradiction, any logical (not to say physical) impossibility, in the adoption by all rational beings of the most outrageously immoral rules of conduct. All he shows is that the consequences of their uni- versal adoption would be such as no one would choose to mcur. So run the opening sentences of Mill's treatise on Uiili' iartanism. They point to an implied contrast in the views of the two writers, to a totally different standpoint. When deal- ing with the Practical Reason Kant alights upon a "factum" of consciousness: the moral law he regards as an indisputable fact of reason in its practical application. And just as the slightest admixture of the empirical, as a condition in a mathematical demonstration, would lower the value of the proof and do away with its universal cogency, so the slightest consideration of the pleasure or pain that might result as the consequence of any particular action would mar the worth of moral judgment, would, in fact, appeal not to the reason which is universal in man but to the sensibility of the indi- vidual, to what is ever changing in him, varying with every 6 — variation in the conditions of his existence, external and in- ternal. Mill maintains that the result of Kant's procedure ends in something only short of the grotesque. Ethics can not be thus formulated without regard to the conditions of organic life and the thousand considerations which arise in consequence of differences in the conditions which hem in the individual or assist him in his growth. Rather than proceed then from the consciousness of the individual regarded as free from the limitations of space and time— with unbounded indifference to the conditions of earthly existence — , Mill prefers to give the problem a complete turn, to take as his basis the firm ground of experience. 'Give me a nov ) From the preceding it would appear that the dictates of conscience can be followed in two ways — deliberately, and instinctively: on the one hand the good of others may be — 19 — sought out of regard for the external (physical, political and social) and internal sanctions, — the point of view of the Utilitarians ; on the other hand the social instincts may be followed impulsively, through inheritance and without the stimu- lus of either pleasure or pain, and they lead naturally to the good of others. If it be maintained that such instinctive actions can hardly be accounted moral, the objection would seem to have little weight, seeing that instinct, according to Darwin, has a close connection with habit and that often we are dis- tinctly accountable for the habits we form, and remembering further how "we all feel that an act cannot be considered as perfect, or as performed in the most noble manner, unless it be done impulsively, without deliberation or effort, in the same manner as by a man in whom the requisite qualities are innate." So that "although man has no special instincts to tell him how to aid his fellowmen, he still has the impulse." And even in seeking how to aid others he is not left without assistance : "with his improved intellectual faculties he would naturally be much guided in this respect by extended sympathy, by reason, and by experience." "To do good in return for evil, to love your enemy, is a height of morality to which it may be doubted whether the social instincts would, by them- selves, have ever led us. It is necessary that these instincts, together with sympathy, should have been highly cultivated by the aid of reason , instruction, and the love or fear of God, before any such golden rules would ever be thought of and obeyed. But as love, sympathy and self-command become strengthened by habit, and as the power of reasoning becomes clearer, so that man can value justly the judgment of his fellows, he will feel himself impelled, apart from any tran- sitory pleasure or pain, to certain lines of conduct. He might then declare, I am the supreme judge of my own conduct, and in the words of Kant, I will not in my own person violate the dignity of humanity." ^) Instead of selecting his own good he will work for that of others: he will adopt as the end of 1) Descent of Man^ p. 1 1 6. *) Ibid. p. no. — 20 — 21 conduct "the rearing of the greatest number of individuals in full vigour and health, with all their faculties perfect, under the conditions to which they are subjected" ; he will give way to his social instincts in cases of conflict, having **no doubt that the welfare and the happiness of the individual usually coincide". Thus the reproach is removed of laying the foun- dation of the noblest part of our nature in the base principle of selfishness; unless, indeed, the satisfaction which ever>' animal feels, when it follows its proper instincts, and the dis- satisfaction felt when prevented, be called selfish. CHAPTER III. HEDONISM WITH EVOLUTION. The writers whose systems we have to set forth in this chapter — Herbert Spencer and Leslie Stephen — have this m common, that they seek to graft on to the evolution hypo- thesis the theory that pleasure is the end of action ; the struggle is no longer one for existence simply, but for pleasurable or desirable existence. Spencer further differs from Darwin in that his system is an attempt at reconciliation between the two opposed schools of English ethical thought; he is more avowedly Utilitarian, but his Utilitarianism is scientific and not empirical; and he regards the intuitions of the moral sense as trustworthy, but accounts for them — as he accounts for the notion of space — by holding that they are the experience of the race rendered organic through inheritance. On one other point Spencer differs from Darwin, viz, on the relation be- tween Egoism and Altruism; according to Spencer it is not possible to merge Egoism into Altruism. Here Stephen seems to side with Darwin, just as he also does in regarding Sym- pathy as a primary animal instinct, although the Sympathy treated of by Stephen is for the most part that which exists -between persons, arising out of interest in persons as such. § I. Spencer. In all judgments of conduct Spencer finds a postulate is involved — one in which pessimists and optimists agree — viz, both their arguments assume it to be self-evident that life is good or bad, according as it does, or does not, bring a surplus of agreeable feeling to self or others or both. The proof is that reversing the application of the words creates absurdities. Every other proposed standard derives its authority from this standard. Whether perfection of nature is the as- signed proper aim, or virtuousness of action, or rectitude of motive, the definition of the perfection, the virtue, the rectitude, inevitably brings us down to happiness experienced in some form, at some time, by some person, as the fundamental idea. Pleasure is as much a form of moral intuition as space is a necessary form of intellectual intuition. "The view for which I contend is, that Morality properly so called — the science of right conduct — has for its object to determine ?ww and why certain modes of conduct are detri- mental, and certain other modes beneficial. These good and bad results cannot be accidental, but must be necessary con- sequences of the constitution of things; and I conceive it to be the business of Moral Science to deduce, from the laws of life and the conditions of existence, what kinds of action necessarily tend to produce happiness, and what kinds to pro- duce unhappiness. Having done this, its deductions are to be recognised as laws of conduct; and are to be conformed to irrespective of a direct estimation of happiness or misery."^) Consequently Spencer's treatise divides itself into two III parts, — one descriptive, and the other normative. The de- scriptive portion deals with conduct regarded from four different points of view — physical, biological, psychological, and socio- logical — and traces the development of conduct from the simplest adjustment of acts to ends, to the more complex, and up to the last stages of development — as displayed by the highest type of being, when he is forced, by increase of numbers, to live more and more in the presence of his fellows, and where conduct simultaneously achieves the greatest totality of ^) Data of Ethics f S 21, quoted from letter to Mill. — 22 — life in self, in offspring, and in fellowmen. Once the conditions under which this highest life has been brought into being have been stated, the conditions of its increase in length and breadth would seem to be a matter of deduction : by this process the conflicting claims of egoism and altruism are set at rest, and a sketch is given of what conduct ought to be. A. Turning now to the descriptive part, and remembering that conduct is the adjustment of acts to ends, we may state moral conduct in (i) physical terms by saying that it is conduct where this moving equilibrium between organism and environment, this adjustment of acts to ends, reaches completeness, or approaches most nearly to completeness. The same conduct, from the (2) biological standpoint may be defined as a balance of functions. The implication of such a balance is that the sev- eral functions in their kinds, amounts, and combinations, are adjusted to the several activities which maintain and constitute complete life. Passing to the feelings which accompany the performance of functions, Spencer maintains that of necessity during the evolution of organic life, pleasures have become the concomitants of normal amounts of functions, while pains positive and negative, have become the concomitants of excesses and defects of functions. And though in every species de- rangements of these relations are often caused by changes of conditions, they ever re-establish themselves : disappearance of the species being the alternative. From the (3) psychological point of view, we have to consider repre- sented pleasures and pains, sensational and emotional, as con- stituting deliberate motives — as forming factors in the con- scious adjustment of acts to ends. Throughout the ascent from low creatures up to man, and from the lowest types of man up to the highest, self-preservation has been increased by the subordination of simple excitations to compound excitations — the subjection of immediate sensations to the ideas of sensations to come — the overruling of presentative feelings by represen- tative feelings, and of representative feelings by re-representa- tive feelings. As life has advanced, the accompanying sen- ill — 23 — tiency has become increasingly ideal; and among feelings produced by the compounding of ideas, the highest, and those which have evolved latest, are the recompounded and doubly ideal. Hence it follows that as guides, the feelings have autho- rities proportionate to the degrees in which they are removed iy their complexity and their ideality from simple sensations and appetites. There arises a certain presumption in favour of a motive which refers to a remote good, in comparison with one which refers to a proximate good. This conscious relinquishment of immediate and special good to gain distant and general good, while it is a cardinal trait of the self-restraint called . moral , is also a cardinal trait of self-restraints other than those called moral— the restraints that originate from %tiix of the visible ruler— political— of the invisible ruler- religious— , and of society at large— social. The idea of authoritativeness has come to be connected with these representative feelings: the implication being that the lower and simpler feelings are without authority. And this idea of authoritativeness is one element in the abstract consciousness of duty. But there is another element — the element of coerciveness ; this is simply the feeling of compulsion accom- panying the political, religious, and social sanctions transferred by means of association to the moral sanction. "Emerging as the moral motive does but slowly from amidst the political, religious, and social motives, it long participates in that con- sciousness of subordination to some external agency which is joined with them; and only as it becomes distinct and pre- dominant does it lose this associated consciousness — only then does the feeling of obligation fade." We cannot help thinking that Spencer's account of moral obligation would have been more successful had he worked out the thought dropped in § 45 : "Moral restraints refer not to the extrinsic effects of acUons but to their intrinsic effects . . . Throughout, the moral motive differs from the motives it is associated with in this, that instead of being constituted by representations of inci- dental, collateral, nonnecessary consequences of acts, it is con- stituted by representations of consequences which the acts — 24 — 25 — \i naturally produce." This necessity of inner experience, this natural sequence of intrinsic effects, in the life of the moral man, is something very different from the illusion of associa- tion into which Spencer reduces the feeling of obligation; associations may arise and fade, but surely increase of morali- sation implies increased sensitiveness to moral feeling — or evolution has little meaning. Regarded from the (4) sociological standpoint, Ethics becomes nothing else than a definite account of the forms of conduct that are fitted to the associated state, in such wise that the lives of each and all may be the greatest possible, alike in length and breadth. Such "definite account" is not yet at hand, but its leading features may be stated. The fundamental requirement is that the life-sustaining actions of each shall severally bring him the amounts and kinds of advantage naturally achieved by them; and this implies, firstly, that he shall suffer no direct aggressions on his person or property, and secondly, that he shall suffer no indirect aggressions by breach of contract. Observance of these negative conditions to voluntary cooperation having facili- tated life to the greatest extent by exchange of services under agreement, life is to be further facilitated by exchange of ser- vices beyond agreement; the highest life being reached only when, besides helping to complete one another's lives by speci- fied reciprocities of aid men otherwise help to complete one another's lives. B. In the normative portion of Spencer's work, we find that the end of action is set forth as the greatest surplus of pleasures over pain. "There is a truth also in the doctrine that virtue must be the aim: for this is another form of the doctrine that the aim must be to fulfil the conditions to achieve- ment of the highest life. That the intuitions of a moral faculty should guide our conduct, is a proposition in which a truth is contained: for these intuitions are the slowly organised results of experience received by the race while living in presence of these conditions. And that happiness is the supreme end is beyond question true : for this is the concomitant of that highest life which every theory of moral guidance has distinctly or iiiiiil vaguely in view." ^) But what are we to understand by happiness as the end? How can we conceive it to be experienced by innumerable other persons, all diflferently constituted from our- selves and from one another ? Pleasure, we know, is not trans- ferable and cannot be distributed. As in the case of "pleasures of pursuit" it cannot in general be reached by making it the aim ; in order to get it we must somehow forget it. Pleasure then rather consists in or follows upon the due exercise of the various functions of the organism. This exercise requires the presence of certain conditions, on the existence of a structure which is called into play, and on the condition of that struc- ture as fitting or unfitting it to its environment. But if there are any conditions without fulfilment of which happiness cannot be compassed, then the first step must be to ascertain these conditions with a view to fulfilling them ; and to admit this is to admit that not happiness itself must be the end, but ful- filment of the conditions to its attainment must be the immediate end. Now certain conditions to the achievement of happiness have already been partially, if not wholly ascertained; and if so, our first business should be to look for them. Having found them, our rational course is to bring existing intelligence to bear on these products of past intelligence, with the ex- pectation that it will verify the substance of them while possibly correcting the form. But to suppose that no regulative prin- ciples for the conduct of associated human beings have thus far been established, and that they are now to be established ■It . , , . j./v. r ae novOj is to suppose that man as he is differs from man as he was in an incredible degree. Thus we are again brought back to experience : and in this matter as in others experience gives no direct "yes" or "no" in answer to our enquiries. Indeed it lands us in difficulties. For i", "Ethics has to recognise the truth, recognised in un- ethical thought, that egoism comes before altruism. Any arrangements which in a considerable degree prevent superior- ity from profiting by the rewards of superiority, or shield in- ») Ibid. S 62. — 26 — feriority, from the evils it entails— any arrangements which tend to make it as well to be inferior as to be superior, are arrangements diametrically opposed to the progress of organi- sation and the reaching of a higher life. But to say that each individual shall reap the benefits brought to him by his own powers, inherited and acquired, is to enundate egoism as an ultimate principle of conduct/* Hence one vague rule :— "the pursuit of individual happiness within those limits pre- scribed by social conditions, is the first requisite to the attain- ment of the greatest general happiness." ^) But 2®, "in the course of evolution from first to last there has beJn sacrifice involving a loss of bodily substance. . . Self- sacrifice, then, is no less primordial than self-preservation. Being in its simple physical form absolutely necessary for the continuance of life from the beginning ; and being extended mider its automatic form, as indispensable to maintenance of race in types considerably advanced ; and being developed to its semi-conscious and conscious forms along with the con- tinued and complicated attendance by which the offspring of superior creatures are brought to maturity ; altruism has been evolving simultaneously with egoism. The same superiorities which have enabled the individual to preserve itself better, have enabled it better to preserve the individuals derived from it; and each higher species, using its improved faculties for egoistic benefit, has spread in proportion as it has used them secondarily for altruistic benefit." «) But neither principle must be pushed to an extreme : the need for a compromise is thus made conspicuous. "Our conclusion must be that general happiness is to be achieved mainly through the adequate pursuit of their own happiness by individuals; while, reciprocally, the happinesses of individuals are to be achieved in part by their pursuit of the general happiness." ») The conditions for the carr>'ing out of this reciprocity in conduct are not wanting : for the whole tendency of evolution is, on its social side, towards the equal — 27 — distribution of the conditions under which happiness may be pursued — and this is nothing but a roundabout insistance on equity; and as far as concerns the individual he is to judge between his own happiness and that of others as an im- partical spectator would do — equity is again the sole content of the principles of conduct. So that, in Spencer's system, the ideal turns out to be Justice , quantitatively determined. § 2. Leslie Stephen. Stephen's pet aversion is metaphysics. His ^'Science of Ethics'^ is an attempt to establish the science on an empirical basis. Abandoning the enquiry into the origin of this or that faculty he takes the case as it stands, formulates its implica- tions, and points out in what direction the line of progress }ies and how most smoothly it can be traversed. Two character- istics he insists on: (a) every state of desire is marked by feeling, and it is this state of feeling that determines conduct ; (b) man lives in society; man independent of society is a nonentity ; hence the need of the science of sociology, which how- ever as yet "consists of nothing more than a collection of unverified guesses and vague generalities, disguised under a more or less pretentious apparatus of quasi-scientific terminology."^) Stephen is further interesting as being one of the most candid exponents of the biological view of ethics: he is not blind to its short- comings, and in transcending his system he approaches very near to the phase of ethical thought represented by the late Prof. Green. Looking at society as we find it we observe that there ^ are in existence a set of rules which, as a matter of fact, is respected in the given society. This set of rules Stephen calls the moral code; and the very fact of their being respected so far determines the ordinary approvals and disapprovals as to be an effective force in governing conduct. Accordingly ethical speculation must be implicated in psychological and sociological enquiries: in the former we have mainly to do with emotion, in the latter with the activity of reason. (a) Feeling and Emotion, Conduct is determined by feeling ; 1) Ibid. S 69. *i Ibid. S 65. *) Ibid. S 9i. *) Science of Ethics ^ pp. 10, II. ^ 2H ^ — 29 — 111^ J m we fly from pain; we seek pleasure; life is a continuous struggle to minimise suffering and to lay a firm grasp upon happiness. "Good" means ever>thing which favours happiness, and "bad" everything which is conducive to misery: nor can any other intelligible meaning be assigned to the words. Happiness guides us when we are eating our dinners, or studying metaphysics, or feeding the hungrj^ It must be equally good for saints, martyrs, heroes, cowards, debauchees, ascetics, mystics, cynics, misers, prodigals, men, women, and babes in arms. Pain and pleasure are, then, the determining causes of action. It may even be said that they are the sole and ulti- mate causes. They are the sole causes in this sense, that where two courses of conduct are otherwise possible, and the choice of one depends upon the agent's own decision, his will is always determined by the actual painfulness or pleasure- ableness of the choice at the moment of choosing , and that there is no different kind of motive. They are ultimate in this sense, that it is impossible to analyse pain and pleasure into any simpler elements. It may happen, but it may also not happen, that the passions may be so regulated that the conduct dictated by our immediate feelings may coincide with that which would be dictated by a judgment of our total 111 happiness. And this leads us to our next problem. We can only be affected by the prospect of the future in so far as we are reasoning beings. We must, therefore, consider in what sense the mere blind action of immediate feeling is governed and regulated by the reason. (b) Reason as determining conduct. Reason, whatever its nature, is the faculty which enables us to act with a view to the distant and the future. Consequently, in so far as man is reasonable, he is under the influence of motives which would not otherwise be operative. Now man's reasonable interests may in the main be classified into (i) those which have regard to his own future pleasures and pains, and (2) those which have regard to the condition of the social organism of which he forms a part. In relation to the former man may be regarded as a hierarchy of numerous and conflicting passions, each of which has ends of its own, and each of which, separately con- sidered, would give a different law of conduct ; it is the reason that brings the whole conduct into harmony and unity; it forbids us to pursue trifling objects at the expence of im- portant; for instead of allowing each instinct to operate ex- clusively in turn, it subjects each to the implicit and explicit control of the others. But reason further enables us after a time to judge even of our own character as a whole, to rehearse not only particular acts but moods, and so become spectators of ourselves, and regard our own feelings with disgust or com- placency; every such reflection tends to modify future action by revealing to us more distinctly its social consequences, and by investing it with certain associations of approval or disapproval. Thus the function of reason is twofold — it regulates the self- regarding impulses, and the relation of the individual to society,^ In cases of conflict between feelings inclining now towards the individual's welfare, now towards that of society, who is to decide? what is the criterion by which we can judge of feelings ? what has evolution to say to the matter ? So far as adaptation has taken place the line of progress has been "useful" in the sense of pleasure-giving; so far as the type thus formed represents a favourable adjustment of organism to conditions, the result is "useful" in the sense of life-pre- serving: and a fundamental doctrine from the evolutionist point of view is that pleasure-giving actions must likewise be self- preserving. And this, thinks Stephen, we may certainly say, that there is as close a connection between health and happiness as between disease and misery, and that the anomalies which present themselves in attempting to generalise this theory might be cleared up by a more accurate investigation. Races survive in virtue of this correlation between pleasure-giving and life- preserving actions. But the quality which makes a race sur- vive may not always be a source of advantage to every indi- vidual, nor even^ if we look closer, to the average individual. Since the race has no existence apart from the individual, qualities essential to the existence of each unit are of course essential to the existence of the whole. But the converse pro- 1 I — 30 — position does not hold. Hence the necessity of considering the relation of the race to the individual. / Ever}- man is both an individual and a social product, and ever}' instinct both social and self-regarding. The individual is the product of the race; and the race the sum of the in- dividuals. Our ancestors have created a new world for us ; and each individual, in whatever department he labours, assumes that others are labouring in tacit or express cooperation. Thus society is a vast organisation, and it exists as it exists in virtue of this organisation, which is as real as the organisation of any material instrument, though it depends upon habits and instincts instead of arrangements of tangible and visible objects ; for instance, in the social organisation we find political, eccle- siastical, and industrial organs, growing more and more distinct and more interdependent as society advances. But there is an- other form of association, viz, the family, which is frequently mentioned as though it were a coordinate group alongside of the state, the church, and industrial bodies. This mode of speech leads to confusion. The sentiment of loyalty to a state, e.g., is clearly a derivative sentiment; it is the product of many instincts or modes of feeling, each of which has its own laws, independently of this special application. The family, on the contrar}\ depends at once upon the most primitive instincts of our nature, which are the direct products of our organic constitution. The family tie is more or less the ground of every other, an antecedent assumption in all human society, and therefore not explicable as a product of other modes of association. Clearly then, we must regard the family as the social unit. For a great part of every one*s life the family is the whole world. It is the true school of morality. Family aflfections are both the type and the root of all truly altruistic feeling : here we have the raw material of the moral sense, which will after- wards be developed and regulated by our position in the whole social organism. What then are the constituents of this raw material, found in the family, and afterwards built up into the whole structure of society? To answer this question is to give / The Contents of the Moral Law. The law of nature has — 31 — but one precept, "Be strong". This law has two main branches "be prudent", and "be virtuous", corresponding to the distinction of the qualities which are primarily useful to the individual and those which are primarily useful to the society— utility meaning — fitness for the conditions of life. The law of prudence corresponds rather to a precedent condition of morality than to morality itself. Morality proper arises with the regulation alike of the passions which have a direct bearing upon the individual life and those which have a direct bearing upon the social bond ; whence the virtues of temperance and chastity. Further, the individual, so far as reasonable, must avoid error on his own account and must avoid the propagation of error for the wel- fare of the society, whence the virtues of wisdom and trust- worthiness. And, finally, since the social union implies a direct interest of the individual in the welfare of the society, we have the directly social virtues, which imply at once benevolence and justice , according as we attend to the motive or to the regulated action of the motives. These classes of excellence, which by their mode of development are necessarily reconcile- able and mutually implicatory of each other, seem to con- stitute all that is meant by the general moral law, though admit- ting, of course, an indefinite variety of special application. Briefly"^ then morality is a statement of the conditions of social welfare ; / and morality, as distinguished from prudence, refers to those conditions which imply a direct action upon the social union. But how impress virtue on the individual? Nature helps us a long way, for, to put it briefly, we cannot help being altruistic. The world is interesting to me so far as it is the dwelling-place of myself and of beings analogous to myself, moved by passions like my own. And it is a part of my nature to be sympathetic. To be reasonable, I must be sym- pathetic; to be thoroughly and systematically selfish, I must be an idiot. There is no more reason for denying that we may receive pleasure from the pleasure of another man than for doubt- ing that we may receive it from the combustion of coal. Sympathy is not an additional instinct, a faculty which is added when the mind has reached a certain stage of development, a mere incident _ 32 - — 33 II 1 of intellectual growth, but something implied from the first in the very structure of knowledge ; it is a natural and funda- mental fact. Seeing that sympathy depends largely upon our relation to others, we may take it for a fact that our sympa- thetic feelings may often lead to altruistic, nay even, self- sacrificing conduct. But altruism or benevolence is not yet virtue : this latter rather implies the elaboration and regulation of the sympathetic character which takes place through the social factor. In the moral man this regard for society is free from all external compulsion: his motives are instrinsic: for him the form of the moral law is not "do this", but "be this". This recognition of the law as intrinsically binding is, on every hypothesis, the crown and final outcome of the moralised character. The moral law being conformity to the conditions of social welfare, conscience is the name of the intrinsic mo- tives to such conformity. It is the utterance of the public spirit of the race, ordering us to obey the primary conditions of its welfare, and it acts not the less forcibly though we may not understand the source of its authority or the end at which \it is aiming. Kg. if you ask, "why is maternal love virtue ?" the answer from one point of view is, "because it is essential to social virtue." Looking at the case from the opposite side, we must invert the order of deduction : the mother loves because she is so constituted as to be capable of loving, and because she is part of a society in which the instinct is stimulated and fostered : for her the love is its own justification, she has the sentiment, and need look no further. The maternal instincts, however, and their accompanying satisfaction are exceptionally strong; we are still at a loss to discover an all-sufficient reason for virtuous conduct on the part of an individual not completely moralised. "The attempt to establish an absolute coincidence between virtue and happiness is in ethics what the attempting to square the circle and to discover perpetual motion are in geometry and mechanics. For my part, I accept the altruist theory, and I accept what I hold to be its legitimate and inseparable conclusion— the conclusion, viz, that the path of duty does not coincide with the path of happiness." *) But there is no need to despair. If a man has the normal constitution, he will presumably be the happier for a moral development, as, if he has the normal intellect, he will derive the normal benefits from education, or, if he has a normal stomach, he will derive the normal benefits from observance of sanitary rules. It is hopeless to produce a balance-sheet of pains and pleasure which would prove that the virtuous man gets a greater sum of pleasant emotions or a sum of emotions superior in quality ; but it may be proved that a man gains by growing as much as it is in him to grow, and that this necessarily involves moral growth. Still it is possible to make a man less fitted for enjoyment under normal circumstances by trying to put too high a polish upon his moral nature, as it is possible to achieve the same result by cultivating tastes for art or intellectual study in those who have no natural aptitude. But whatever doubts we may have as to the possibility of making any given person moral, and of contributing to his personal happiness by doing so, we can have no scruples in making him as moral as we can. For we cannot know till we have tried what capabilities of development there may be in him, and the general principle that moral development involves good to him and still more to the society, is sufficiently demon- strated to compel us to do what we can. So that "I take for granted that as a rule it is prudent to be moral, and still more unequivocally that it is prudent to encourage the morality of our neighbours." 2) To make our neighbours really moral we must stimulate their instrinsic motives to action; and this must be in all cases the product of the pressure put upon them in gradually imbibing the principles developed by the social factor. "This is recognised in the statement that a religion is always more than a morality. It is not a mere statement that certain rules of conduct are desirable, but it is such an embodiment of some theory of the universe as may impress the imagination and govern the emotions." ^) But are we not thus, after all, landed in a "metaphysic" of ethics? 1) Ibid. p. 431- ^) Ibid. p. 432. ^) Ibid, p.^ 457- I-. -J I ti il — 34 — CHAPTER IV. REVIEW AND CRITICISM. Among moralists there is general agreement as to what is the right in any particular case ; and in daily life there is seldom any difficulty on this point. But the case is different when we turn to the motive to right conduct. We can't help believ- ing what we see to be true; but we can refrain from doing what we see to be right. The fact of irrational impulse leading to irrational conduct remains whatever theory of ethics we adopt. Sidgwi ck distinguishes three kinds of conduct:— a. mn-roHonal; e^. as in instinctive action, where impulses to action seem to take effect "instinctively" without definite consciousness of end or means. b. irrational; — the result of irrational desires, impelling us to volitions opposed to our deliberate judgments. c. rational^ Judgments relating to rational conduct contain the notion "ought" or "right", a notion essentially different from all notions represented by empirical facts: it is fundamental, ultimate, and unanalyseable. The judg- ment is objective ; what I judge "right" or "ought to be" must, unless I am in error, be thought to be so by all rational beings who judge truly of the matter. And along with the cognition of the rightness of the action is given an impulse or motive to action, though this is only one motive among others which are liable to con- flict with it, and is not always a predominant motive. Accordingly the answer to the question "why should I do what 1 see to be right" varies with the emotional characteristics of different minds; e^, in the mind of a rational Egoist the ruling impulse is generally what Butler and Hutcheson call a "calm" or "cool" self-love: whereas in the man who takes universal happiness as the end and standard of right conduct, the desire to do what is judged to be reasonable as such is commonly blended in varying degrees with sympathy and philan- thropic enthusiasm. Again, if one conceives the dictating Eeason — whatever its dictates may be — as external to — 35 — oneself, the cognition of rightness is accompanied by a sentiment of Reverence for Authority; which may by some be conceived impersonally, but is more commonly regarded as the authority of a supreme Person, so that the sentiment blends with the affections normally excited by persons in different relations, and becomes Religious. While again, if we identify Reason and Self, Reverence for Authority blends with Self-respect; and again, the antithetical and even more powerful sentiment of Freedom is called in, if we consider the rational Self as liable to be enslaved by the usurping force of sensual impulses. Quite different again are the emotions of Aspiration or Admiration aroused by the conception of Virtue as an ideal of Moral Perfection or Beauty. Other phases of emotion might be mentioned, all having with these the common characteristic that they are inseparable from an apparent cognition, — implicit or explicit, direct or indirect, — of rightness in the conduct to which they prompt.*) "Evidently then Ethics has to do with the cognitions which these various emotions, with their common characteristic of "rightness", accompany. Now Reason, whether applied to the facts of nature or of conduct, seeks after unity ; is there any unity underlying the various cognitions of right ? In the main two "ends" have been regarded as worthy objects of pursuit: at one time Happiness, at another Perfection has held sway. The writer s »/ hitherto dealt with have adopted Happiness as the end, and by happiness they mean pleasure. Pleasure is a kind of feeling which stimulates the will to actions tending to sustain or produce it ; Pain^^o actions tending to remove or avert it. Feeling in itself is non-moral ; it only becomes the object of moral judg- ment when it accompanies a volition. The volitional stimulus to the attainment of pleasure is Desire, to the avoidance of pain, Aversion. The question we have to decide, in criticis- ing the Utilitarian doctrine as set forth by Mill, is whether there are no desires and aversions which have not pleasures and pains for their objects. But we must first of all distinguish *) Methods of Ethics (3<> ed.), pp. 39, 40. I i^ — 3,6 — between prospective and resultant pleasure. Do I eat because I am hungry, then the end is the satisfaction of hunger, and the satisfaction of any instinct brings with it resultant pleasure ; do I eat for the sake of the pleasure of eating, then to attain pleasure is my motive, and the pleasure attained is the gour- mand's. In the former case a want, the feeling of hunger, is the direct impulse to the eating of food; in the latter case the pleasure expected is the object of a secondary desire. And it would seem as if the question is narrowed down to this — whether, in the sphere of moral conduct, all desires are secondary desires for pleasure? On the face of it this looks absurd ; nay more, reflection shows us that as a rule secondary desires are just those which, along with irrational desires, are universally condemned. Life is not a state but an activity, and the pleasures with which it abounds, though intertwined with, are consequent upon action, and not its object; to get these pleasures one often must forget them. The student desires knowledge with a view to getting a firmer grasp of things, not primarily for any pleasures of thought. The artist finds satisfaction in producing works of art — he is only secondarily concerned with any pleasure they may subsequently afford. The impulse to bene- volent aifections is essentially a desire to do good to others for the sake of others : true, the flow of love or kindly feeling is itself highly pleasurable and might cause pain if the act of benevolence were withheld ; but the cultivation of this affection for the sake of its sympathetic pleasures would at once be condemned as egoistic and mean. **So far, then, from our conscious active impulses being always directed towards the attainment of pleasure or avoidance of pain for ourselves, it would seem that we find everywhere in consciousness extra-regarding impulses, directed towards something that is not pleasure, nor relief from pain ; and, in fact, that a most important part of our pleasure depends upon the existence of such impulses." *) We may take it then that there exists the phenomenon — 37 — of strictly disinterested impulse. Mill does not deny this : he only asserts that it has become disinterested owing to well- known psychological laws. Without however prejudicing the question of the validity of the moral sentiments with a theorj^ of their origin, we may perhaps assert that the Utilitarian, more so than others, must assume this phenomenon of disinterested- ness: for he is in the curious position of having the end of conduct determined by reason irrespectively of his own feeling in the matter. Mill, at any rate, hardly attempts to arrive at the Utilitarian en4 by any empirical induction from experience. And in fact the most-H;enowned living representative of Utili- tarianism-rSidgwick^liiaintains that the end cannot be so arrived at^^-h^^establishes it on grounds of Reason, from self-evident principles intuitively known to be valid. The chain of reasoning is as follows : — the satisfaction of any desire is pro tanto good; and an equal regard for all the moments of our conscious experience — so far, at least, as the mere differ- ence of their position in time is concerned — is an essential characteristic of rational conduct. Reason accordingly estab- lishes the law of Prudence. None the less are we forced to admit the universal validity of the principle of Benevolence; "by considering the relation of the integrant parts to the whole and to each other, 1 obtain the self-evident principle that the good of any one individual is of no more importance, from the point of view (if I may so say) of the Universe, than the good of any other." "As rational beings we are bound to aim at good generally, not merely at this or that part of it."*) Then interpreting the good as "desirable consciousness"T:^as happiness or pleasure — he arrives aTThe end, viz, "desirable consciousness or feeling for the innumerable multitude of living beings, present and to come, an End that satisfies our ima- gination by its vastness, and sustains our resolution by its comparative security-^ He allows "that the pursuit of ideal objects such as Truth, Freedom, Beauty, &c., for their own sakes, is indirectly and secondarily, though not primarily and *J Ibid. pp. 50, 51. ») Ibid. p. 93. ^ Iticl- P- 381- "") Ibid. p. 401. .. .iiiiii II i ^ 38 ^ absolutely rational ; on account not only of the happiness that will result from their attainment, but also of that which springs from their disinterested pursuit."*) But what if one denies the advisability of pursuing Truth, Freedom, Beauty >r their own sakes ? Just as material or other objects are nothing con- sidered apart from some relation to consciousness, so these objective relations are nothing when distinguished from the consciousness accompanying and resulting from them, or, more correctly, from the consciousness that makes them objective relations at all. ) It would seem as if Sidgwick, over-anxious to escape the circle in which he finds aBcieat Greek philosophy moving, had, in this "desirable consciousness or feeling for the innumerable multitude of living beings present and to come", set up as abstract a conception as was ever proposed for poor human nature to follow. The conception presupposes the commen- surability of pleasures and pains, a condition without which the hedonistic calculus prior to the determination of action would^be^mpossible. It sets up as final the judgment of the sentient individual as to the question how far each element of feeling has the quality of ultimate, that is, universal Good. 2) The necessary reference to the innumerable multitude of living beings present and to come would seem to make it an im- possible conception— not to speak of additional difficulties if we admit, as perhaps we should, that pleasures differ not only in quantity but also in quality, according to the nature of the conditions under which they arise. J^one is more alive to the difficulUes of the position than pidgwiek himself. For, "pass- ing over the uncertainties invdived m hedonistic comparison generally, let us suppose that the quantum of happiness that will result from the establishment of any plan of behaviour among human beings can be ascertained with sufficient exact- ness for practical purposes; and that even when the plan is as yet constructed in imagination alone. It still has to be asked, what is the nature of the human being for whom we — 39 — are to construct this hypothetical scheme of conduct? For humanity is not something that exhibits the same properties always and everywhere: whether we consider the intellect of man or his feelings, or his physical condition and circumstances, we find them so different in different ages and countries, that it seems prima facie absurd to lay down a set of ideal Utili- tarian rules for mankind generally."*) It seems to us that it is just here that Sidgwick's system comes to grief: the end, discovered by reason and deliberately adopted by an act of will, turns out to be a maximum of desirable consciousness; in the analysis more stress is laid on the desirable than on the conscious element of the end; it is made to consist in feeling pure and simple— an abstraction— and not in self-consciousness in all its phases. This restriction of the content of the end to feeling is the more remarkable when we remember that the object of moral judgment is admitted to be not consequences of actions as such, but more strictly "the volitions themselves ac- companied with intention- whether the intended consequences be external, or some effects produced on the agent's own feelings or character." «) And when the question is raised as to the value of "formally" right conduct— where the agent in willing is moved by pure desire to fulfil duty or chooses duty for duty's sake— as compared with "materially" right conduct —where the agent intends the right particular effects, we are told that "the moral sense of mankind would, under ordinary circumstances, regard the Subjective rightness of an action as generally more important than the Objective," 3) owing to the superior worth of right character or disposition. Of course we are aware that Utilitarians have been most eloquent in their praise of good dispositions as being the most likely means to bring about maximum happiness, but again dispositions are nothing apart from the persons whose dispositions they are, and persons, moral beings, are something more than the tran- sient state of pleasurable feeling insisted upon in the sensa-. tionalist philosophy .~^^^ -1 ») Ibid. p. 403. *) Ihid. p. 396. 1) Ibid. p. 462, 3- 'i Ib'd- P- 57, 8. ^) Ibid. p. 204, 5. n I 55 f 'il — 40 — So that when the time arrives for decision upon a course of action, the ordinary man, if not the Utilitarian philosopher, will seek a rougher and a readier method than that afforded by the hedonistic calculus. He will seek his good, as Aristotle said he ought to, in the exercise of virtue : he will attain his end, in whatever small degree, in the cognition of Truth, in the contemplation of Beauty , in Freedom of action. It will not matter to him if he is told he is moving in a circle. "Granting it to be a circle, it may be none the worse for that. No one complains of the guide who takes him up the mountain that he takes him back to the starting-point. The journey may have been of value, though he returns at the end of it to the same place. As a matter of fact, the same trav- eller never does return to the same place. He is a different man when he comes back, and the home he comes back to is a different place."i) So the virtuous man's act has been one step further in self-realisation: he is in possession of a permanent good which does not pass away with a momentar>' feeling in consciousness. Not that pleasure can or need be renounced altogether. "It is always a part of the desired or willed object. But this pleasure is not prospective pleasure: nor is it the dause of the desire ; nor is it independent of or separable from the rest of the object. Its presence means that the object is an object of desire or wi//. And the pleas- ure is always the pleasure of the action itself. If, then, it is asked whether we desire pleasure or certain objects, the most natural answer is that we desire sometimes one and sometimes the other, according to whichever is more prominent in our minds. Moreover, the pleasure is not pleasure in general, but is my own pleasure, but it does not for that reason make my act a selfish act, any more than it is selfish of me to take my fair share of profits in a partnership, or in general to make the best of myself." "Without the pleasure the standard of action would be something divorced from our experience. And if it is an abstraction to consider pleasure apart from the ») Muirhead, Elements of Ethics, p. I73- — 41 — f act, it is equallyyan^bstraction to regard the act without its pleasure." 1) ^.^<*C Turning now Jo the evolutionist writers, we find it the less necessary to refer to their merits seeing that the luminous idea of differentiation and integration is likely to remain for a long time to come the controlling idea in methodical in- vestigation. We have seen how Darwin pursued this method and with what success. He endeavoured to show how along with differentiation and organisation in the race there grew up in the individual a subjective reflection of the same fact, a feeling of sympathy with the feelings of others ; and how in this way we are to account for the growth of moral sentiments. It may be said in general that Darwin's only fault was that he considered a description of the facts as they appeared to an onlooker to be a sufficient explanation of these facts; but, in reality, the struggle for survival represents not the cause of growth but its method. Spencer's method is still that of the onlooker; so much so indeed^hat it is difficult at times to draw the line that separates simple mechanical adaptation to environment from truly moral action. This blending of the non-moral with the moral is no doubt a part of his plan, but the result is un- satisfactory in that the facts that come under consideration are only the external effects of actions, not actions as a whole proceeding from characters conscious of the end aimed at. His morality may be summed up in the formula "Do this"; it has not attained to the true character expressed in "Be this". Tliis transition from a "Do this" to a "Be this" we find in Stephen; "that man is meritorious who does from an intrinsic motive what another man will do only from an extrinsic motive", 2) who regards the moral law as the "objective" law of his con- duct, and not as the "subjective" law or "reason". The re- cognition of that law as objective is held to be, on every hypothesis, the crown and final outcome of the moralised 1) Alexander, Moral Order and Progress, pp. 223, 21 1. *) Science of Ethics, p. 267. Ml I il Jf — 4^ ' character But when he sets out to explain this objective conduct of the moral man, Stephen has recourse to the social organism with its various functions as they are exercised m contemporary civilised communities. The individual is shown to be a member of different organisations-the family, the state, the church ; it is from his relations to them that his character is what it is. But from the persistent emphasis laid on these objective conditions, and owing to morality being regarded as consisting of actions tending to further the health of the social organism , the individual tends more and more to retire into the background, and society proceeds on its course, unconscious of its movement or its destiny. For assu- redly if there are "no persons without society*', it is quite as true that there is -no society without persons", and more so; for it is the individuals that make society what it is, and to introduce the conception "society", in order to explain why the individual is what he is, thus turns out to be an explana- tion of the obscurum per obscurius. Further, it has to be remarked that both Spencer and Stephen have encumbered their theory with hedonistic pre- sumptions. For them the end is not simply Existence— as on the theory of evolution we might expect— but existence qualified by pleasurable feeling i.e. Welfare, Happiness, or Health of the social organism. Now, before this additional quality can be added on to Existence as the end of evolution two points have to be made out, viz (a) that life-preserving actions are pleasure giving ; and (b) that continuous differentia- tion and integration of organic functions implies an increased amount of happiness. In support of these positions Spencer maintains that "those races of beings only can have survived in which, on the (werage, agreeable or desired feelings went along with activities conducive to the maintenance of life, while disagree- able and habitually-avoided feelings went along with activities directly or indirectly destructive of life ;"») and Stephen con- tents himself with saying that life -preserving and pleasure- — 43 — giving actions "approximately coincide"; but anything like a proof of optimism is not attempted — in spite of there being pessimistic views of life abroad. And again, it is doubtful whether much is ganied by setting up the happiness of society as the end, for this cannot mean the happiness of the social organism, but is only a concise formula for the aggregate happinesses of the individuals composing it, and is as such subject to the same criticisms as apply to the Utilitarian end. So that, briefly, "the doctrine of evolution itself, when applied to empirical morality, only widens our view of the old land- scape—does not enable us to pass from *is' to 'ought', or from efficient to final cause, any more than the telescope can point beyond the sphere of spatial quantity."*) The truths established by evolution may be of use in restraining the ardour and tempering the enthusiasm of those who think they have a panacea for all the ills of life, provided they once had a free hand to apply it; its insistence on heredity and environ- ment as all-important factors in the constitution of individual and social life helps to show that we are still at a distance from that "far-off divine event to which the whole creation moves". But evolution cannot solve the problems it has raised. "What is required to complete the evolutionist theory is (i) once and for all to renounce Hedonism and all its works; (2) to add to its empirical demonstration that the individual is essentially social a teleological demonstration that his good is essentially a common good." '^) CHAPTER V. RIGHT CHARACTER. "In the recognition of conduct as 'right' is involved an authoritative prescription to do it: but when we have judged conduct to be good, it is not yet clear that we ought to prefer i 1) Data of Ethics, S 33- ») Sorley, Ethics of Naturalism, p. 139. *) Muirhead, Elements of Ethics, p. 145. m I — 44 — this kind of good to all other good things. In short, the notion of brightness' is essentially positive, and that of 'good- ness' admits of degress." ») Taking advantage of this distinc- tion, we propose in this chapter to set forth and characterise Martineau's system— reserving for the next Green's theory of the Good. As was the case with the writers whose systems have been discussed, so does Martineau claim to rest his system on a psychological basis. But a psychological theory of ethics, so long as it remains at its own centre— individual life— lies under all the disabilities to which every system of Monism is exposed. And Martineau is deeply persuaded that no monistic scheme, whether its starting-point be Self, or Nature, or God, can ever interpret, without distorting or expunging, the facts on which our nature and life are built. He has devoted many pages of his treatise to show that a system proceeding from a naturalistic or materialistic standpoint to deduce the moral from the non- moral either reads into the non-moral a meaning which is not there, or fails to note the characteristically moral where it exists. Accordingly taking his stand on self-consciousness as declaring truths notiora nobis he seeks to discover their mean- ing and to set forth their implications. Consciousness would seem to spend itself in two main directions : i», attention to the facts of nature, observation of its order, perception of its laws, may lead to a theory of know- ledge; but 2<», as persons we stand in relation to other persons — our fellowmen— and to something higher than we, but still a person, viz, God. The fields are fairly distinct: for is it not true that the sense of shame is different from the sound of thunder, and the comparison of triangles unlike the aspiration of prayer? The activity of consciousness in the pursuit of knowledge may be characterised as Perception^ in the establishment of a system — 45 — of morals. Conscience, Apart from any metaphysical assump- tions, both may be said to find the law, but not to make it ; they reveal, but do not frame it. Each is to be dictator in its own sphere] — perception, among the objects of sense, — concience, as to the conditions of duty. The objects of sense "a^ arranged according to the organs of sense, not according to any inner principle; but "there are no bones, or muscles, or feathers appropriated to the exclusive use of self-love; no additional eye or limb set apart for the service of benevolence ; no judicial wig adhering to the head that owns a conscience ; so that in this field, i.e. through the whole scene of the moral phenomena, no help can be had from the zoological record." But just as in the field of perception, j. the impulses must be simultaneous inter se, and they must both be possibilities to us. So then we come to the conclusion that the objects of our moral judgment are, originally, our own inner principles of self-con- scious action, as freely preferred or excluded by our will. Our next object will be to enumerate these springs of action, first in psychological, and then in their moral, order. (a) Springs of Action: Psychological Order. Martineau begins by distinguishing between two sets of impelling principles; viz, those which urge man, in the way of unreflecting instinct, to appropriate objects or natural ex- pression — Primary springs of action ; and those which supervene upon self-knowledge and experience, and in which the pre- conception is present of an end gratifying to some recognised feeling — Secondary springs of action. This too is the order of their derivation: The secondary feelings are the primary over again, metamorphosed by the operation of self-consciousness. Of the primary springs of action we may distinguish four classes : — I. Fropensions, bearing in the highest degree the character of subjective appetency and mere drift of nature and requir- ing from external objects the minimum of importunity and reaction to move response: viz, two having reference respec- tively to food and sex (appetites), and animal Spontaneity (the tendency to physical activity alternating with repose). PI I — 48 — 2. Passions: they are what we suffer at the hands of other objects— objects which are in every case painful and uncon- genial; so that the emotions towards these objects are in- variably repulsions, thrusting away what is hurtful or inhar- monious , or else withdrawing us thence. The passions are three: towards an object of natural aversion immediately before us we feel AnHpathy\ towards that which has just hurt us, we experience Anger; towards that which menaces us with evil, we look with Fear. Not one of the principles hitherto enumerated has any reference to Persons, or involves more than a relation to tilings,— Irving things, it may be, but nothing more. Two classes of active principles remain to be mentioned ; and though in the first of these we find still some affinity with lower tribes of being, yet the special element oi personality so predominates in their human manifestation, and even so reacts on them and exalts them in the animals that are companions of man, that in dealing with them we must regard ourselves as crossing the line, and say that, in a world without persons, they would fail of their proper idea and identity. 3. Affections : called so , because they take us and form us into a certain frame of mind towards other persons , and operate therefore as attractions, and not, like the passions, as repulsions. They belong to us as surrounded by beings more or less in our own image, and repeating to us our own ex- perience; and the lowest condition of their existence is, the presence of living creatures, reminding us of our kind , if not belonging to it. Of these, the first in order, as the least ex- clusively human, is the Parental; the conditions of which aie, that the beings on whom it is directed be , independently of us, the image of our essence, and, dependency upon us, the continuation of our existence. The second is the Social; directed not only to our like, as the former, but to our equals, as respondent natures , holding up the mirror to our being, and at once taking us out of ourselves and sending us mto ourselves. Neither the family nor the community fulfils its idea — 4Q — without the coexistence of the other; the home never reveals its true meaning or perfects its constitution but in society; and society never finds its soul or discloses its moral essence, till formed into an aggregate of families. The third affection, drawing us to the beings we interpret by ourselves, is com- passion, the feeling that springs forth at the spectacle of suffer- ing. There is no feeling which it is less possible to deduce from any interested source. 4. Sentiments: which direct themselves upon ideal relations, objects of apprehension or thought that are above us, yet potentially ours. They divide themselves no other than the faculties and sciences of our nature; and as that nature is intellectual, giving us a science of Logic; and imaginative, affording ground for an Aesthetic; and moral, giving rise to a doctrine of Ethics and Faith ; so are there three correspond- ing sentiments, operating as the mainsprings of the respective faculties , and supplying the tension of all their activity : viz. Wonder, asking for Causality ; Admiration, directed upon Beauty; and Reverence, looking up to transcendent Goodness. They all meet their objects first beyond the realm of mere pheno- mena, and at once attest and interpret an ulterior sphere of spiritual realities. When we look back on the springs of action in their serial order, we cannot fail to notice the law of their succes- sion. They are none of them mere egoistic phenomena, scin- tillating and quenched within our isolated history; they all have their external correlates. In the part they play within us, these correlates rise from a minimum to a maximum of qualitative influence; being of the Propensions, mere conditions; of the Passions, causes ; of the Affections, personal objects ; of the Sentiments, the perfect realisation. These twelve primary principles are essentially disinterested in their action, simply impelling us hither and thither, without choice or reckoning of ours. But they cannot play their part on the theatre of a self-conscious nature, without our soon discovering what they do with us. Each of them, in the attain- ment of its end, yields us a distinct kind of satisfaction ; and, 4 — so- on next taking possession of us, finds us with a preconception o? TexpenLL to which it leads. These -eral saUsfac- Ls. it is manifest, may themselves become .n^s a taste for rea" ing which will constitute new springs of acUon, added on tTL former, variously mingling with them, .ften qmte ascendent over them. , . These are the s.onJary principles; '^»'«'^<=*''"^f ^^^ ^ ^" interested nature, or invariable aim '^ ]>^°''j''\Z^^J^l of ourselves. This change is great and ethically -°«^^ but as it is uniform throughout the list, a P^--^ "^ J^^f. series which is but the self-conscious counterpart of the pn n>ar>- principles, and which might be psychologically disposed mar> prmcip „™„,i„„ The moral effect however of of with this general descnpUon. 1 he moral self-consciousness is ver)- different in '^'ff^^f J^"^. f ^^'^ series: some of the principles no ---. ^°-!' ^'^J^f ^^^ they run out into ulterior forms more important than them selves, and demanding recognition by separate names. Thus 7^&co«dary Propensions : appearing as love of Pleasure, Money. Power, the second being a development out of the first and third secondar)' spring. 2 Secondary Passions; the fondness for anUpathy, or pleas- ure in hating, we call, as a feeling. lU-wiU or Malice, and in its expression Censoriousness ; the cherishing of resentment, Vindictiveness; of fear. Suspiciousness, or Mistrust 3. Secondary Affections; may be classed together as Sen- """T Wary Sentiments, giving rise to Self-culture, Aesthe^ ticism, and Interest in Religion. ^ c.v,<. iov7 There are numerous ulterior compounds, such as the love of Praise, EmulaUon. &c. ; with the help of the laws of asso- elation, of sympathy, and of distance, these compound forms of motive can be easily resolved into their elements, (b.) Springs of Action: Moral Order. This classification does not follow any orgamc pnnciple of growth ; nor is it an arranging of the springs according to strength of impulse. It is an order of gradaUon according to ill — 51 ~ moral worth, and moral worth does not admit of further ana- lysis. It is an attribute of the moral man and his character- istic. Now if it be true that each separate verdict of right and wrong pronounces some one impulse to be of higher worth than a competitor, each must come in turn to have its rela- tive value determined in comparison with the rest; and, by collecting these series of decisions into a system, we must find ourselves in possession of a table of moral obligation, gradu- ated according to the inner excellence of our several tenden- cies. This is wholly a task of introspective classification and comparative estimate. It is one followed, more or less, by the chiefs of both ancient and modern philosophy, and has fallen into disrepute mainly through the influence of writers who have approached the study of Morals from either the casuist's or the jurist's point of view. Martineau's table as finally ar- ranged is as follows: — Lowest. 1. Secondary Passions; Censoriousness, Vindictiveness, Suspiciousness. 2. Secondary Organic Propensions; Love of Ease and Sensual Pleasure. 3. Primary Organic Propensions: — Appetites. 4. Primary Animal Propension; — Spontaneous Activity (un- selective). 5. Love of Gain (reflective derivative from Appetite). 6. Secondary Aifections (sentimental indulgence of sym- pathetic feelings). 7. Primary Passions ; — Antipathy, Fear, Resentment. 8. Causal Energy; — Love of Power, or Ambition; Love of Liberty. 9. Secondary Sentiments; — Love of Culture. 10. Primary Sentiments of Wonder and Admiration. 11. Primary Affections, Parental and Social; — with Gene- rosity and Gratitude. 12. Primary Affection of Compassion. 13. Primary Sentiment of Reverence. Highest. — 52 — We are now prepared for an exact definition of Right and Wrone- which will assume this form: Every acUon is Rtghi, wWch in presence of a lower principle, follows a higher: every r^on is Wron,, which, in presence of a higher pnncple follows a lower. * Have we. when we have proceeded thus far, got at a sufficient condition of duty? Does the statement square w.th L fact conveyed to us under the feeling of obhgaUon? Mar- Lu would be the last to say so: for. "-th°ut '..y..*;'^"^; ditions, the idea of Duty involves a contradiction and Us ph aseology passes into an unmeaning figure of speech". Now. rememSg how in perception it is Self and Nature, m Morals SeTfTnd God. that stand face to face, we are not surprised fo find that the moral order of the springs of action, proper^ arranged and sorted out, "fall into the systematic code of SvTne Law". It is this theistic background that prevents us Slregarding the theory as hanging in the air; it is owing o their springing from this source that the dictates con- science obtain their unconditional -*°"~^^ ^ J^J^^^, sense of authority means anything, it means ^^^ ''--"J^^ of something higher than we, havmg claims on our self ot someimug 6 .—hoverinK over and transcending therefore no mere part ol it, — noveiius " iTr personality, though also mingling ^^^^^^^^^ and manifested ^^ ^^^^^^^^ owl "S, bTIm this senUment, I cannot stop w.thm m> own , irresistibly carried on to the recognition of ''°°*t>«; ^^^ " Nor doe that — 59 — according to the extent of his knowledge and to the degree of attention aroused in him in the particular case. And any combination of the data of feeling as qualities of an object, or as facts related to a certain sensation, which the occurrence of that sensation may recall to us, implies the action of a subject which thinks of its feelings, which distinguishes them from itself, and can thus present them to itself as facts. The constituents of a perceived object, whether we consider them qualities or related facts, survive in their multiplicity at the same time that they constitute a single object. The condition of their doing so is the self-distinction of the thinking subject from the data of sensation, which it at once presents to itself in their severalty as facts, and unites as re/ateti facts in virtue of its equal presence to them all. So that the ordinar>' per- ception of sensible things or matters of fact involves the de- termination of a sensible process, which is in time, by an agency that is not in time,~in Kant's language, a combination of *empirical and intelligible characters'. This however is only set forth as a statement of what is implied in perception as it is; what are we to say of its be- coming, of its history, of the growth of perceiving conscious- ness? This will be found to be a history— not of conscious- ness itself, for it can have no history, but— of the process by which the animal organism becomes the vehicle of an eternally complete consciousness. "Our consciousness", in fact, may mean either of two things; either a function of the animal organism, which is being made, gradually and with interruptions, a vehicle of the eternal consciousness; or that eternal con- sciousness itself, as making the animal organism its vehicle and subject to its limitations in so doing, but retaining its essential characteristic as independent of time, as the determinant of becoming, which has not and does not itself become. "A familiar illustration may help to bring home that view of what is involved in the attainment of knowledge for which we are here contending. We often talk of reading the book of nature; and there is a real analogy between the process in which we apprehend the import of a sentence, and that by which we x — 60 — arrive at any piece of knowledge. In reading the sentence we see the words successively, we attend to them successively, we recall their meaning successively. But throughout that suc- cession there must be present continuously the consciousness that the sentence has a meaning as a whole; otherwise the successive vision, attention and recollection would not end in a comprehension of what the meaning is. This consciousness operates in them, rendering them what they are as organic to the intelligent reading of the sentence. And when the read- ing is over, the consciousness that the sentence has a meaning has become a consciousness of what in particular the meaning is,— a consciousness in which the successive results of the mental operations involved in the reading are held together, without succession, as a connected whole. The reader has then, so far as that sentence is concerned, made the mind of the writer his own."*) Green maintains that there is no incompatibility between this doctrine and the admission that all the processes of brain and nerve and tissue, all the functions of life and sense, or- ganic to this activity (though even they, as in the thinking man, cannot properly be held to be merely natural), have a strictl) natural history. "And having admitted that certain processes in time are organic in man to that consciousness exercised in knowledge which we hold to be eternal, we have no interest in abridging these processes. If there are reasons for holding that man, in respect of his animal nature, is descended from *mere' animals— animals in whom the functions of life and sense were not organic to the eternal or distinctively human consciousness,— this does not affect our conclusion in regard to the consciousness of which, as he now is, man is the subject; a conclusion founded on analysis of what he now is and does." 2) So far we have dealt with perception. But the animal system is organic not only to impressions, but also to wants. These wants, with the sequent impulses, must be distinguished from the consciousness of wanted objects, and from the effort 1) Prolegomena to Ethics, pp. 75. 6. «) Ibid. p. 87. — 61 • — to %vi^ reality to the objects thus present in consciousness as wanted, no less than sensations of sight and hearing have to be distinguished from the consciousness of objects to which those sensations are conceived to be related. The transition from mere want to consciousness of a wanted object, from the impulse to satisfy the want to an effort for realisation of the idea of the wanted object, implies the presence of the want to a subject which distinguishes itself from it, and is constant throughout successive stages of the want. The idea of an end, which a self-conscious subject presents to itself, and which it strives and tends to realise, we call a motive. An appetite or want only becomes a motive, so far as upon the want there supervenes the presentation of the want by a self-conscious subject to himself, and with it the idea of a self-satisfaction to be attained in the filling of the want. The motive is not made up of a want and self-consciousness, any more than life of chemical processes and vital ones ; but, indivisible as it is, it results, as perception results, from the determination of an animal nature by a self-conscious subject other than it; sore- suits, however, as that the animal condition does not survive in the result. This will become more clear after an Analysis of Desire. How do we come to desire food? What do we mean by the desire? Do we mean by it (i) hunger itself, as a particular sort of painful feeling ; or (2) an instinctive impulse to obtain food, excited by this painful feel- ing but without consciousness of an object to which the im- pulse is directed; or (3) an impulse excited by the image of a pleasure previously experienced in eating, such as we seem to notice in a well-fed dog or cat when the dinner-bell rings; or (4) desire for an object in the proper sense; that is, for something which the desiring subject presents to itself as distinct at once from itself, the subject that desires, and from other objects which might be desired but for the time are not? In (i), desire being equivalent to hunger cannot be ex- plained by it. As regards (2), the human infant seeks food instinctively without any previous experience of it as something that will remove the pain of hunger. And (3), the mere revival I — 62 — in a sentient being of the image of a past pleasure, with the consequent impulse after the renewal of the pleasure, does not imply any consciousness by the subject of itself in distinc- tion from the pleasure as the subject which has enjoyed it, and may enjoy it again , and which has also enjoyed other pleasures comparable with it; nor any consciousness of an objective world to which belong the conditions of the pleasure —the means to it, and its consequences. This is what gives its character to the moral and intellectual experience of man. There is for him a world of feeling , however limited in its actual range, yet boundless in capacity, of which he presents himself as the centre. It is by its relation to this world that any particular pleasure is defined for him as an object of desire, and thus, however animal in its origin, becomes to him through such reference to a 'before and after' of experience, what it is not to the animal that feels but does not distinguish itself from its immediate feeling. Apart from self-consciousness animal desire would have no moral character. There is a real unity in all our desires ; only it is not Desire, but the self. But this also is the unity in all acts of intellect; how then are we to reconcile this with the obvious difference of intellect from desire? Desire ami IniellecL We must ascribe to the self-con- scious soul or man two equally primitive, coordinate, possi- bilities of desiring and understanding. The element common to both lies in the consciousness of self and a world as in a sense opposed to each other, and in the conscious effort to overcome this opposition. Desire implies, on the part of the desiring subject (a) a distinction of itself at once from its desires and from the real world ; (b) a consciousness that the conditions of the real world are at present not in harmony with it, the subject of the desire ; (c) an effort, however un- developed or misdirected, so to adjust the conditions of the real world as to procure satisfaction of the desire. So it is with the intellect: the establishment or discovery of relations —we naturally call it establishment when we think of it as a function of our own minds, discovery when we think of it as - 63 - a function determined for us by the mind that is in the world —is the essential thing in all understanding. Whatever the object which we set ourselves to understand, the process begins with our attention being challenged by some fact as simply alien and external to us, as no otherwise related to us than is implied in its being there to be known; and it ends, or rather is constantly approaching to an end never reached, in the mental appropriation of the fact, through its being brought under definite relations with the cosmos of facts in which we are already at home. This community of principle in the two cases we may properly indicate by calling our inner life, as determined by desires for objects, practical thought, while we call the activity of the understanding speculative thought. Nor is this all. The exercise of the one activity is always a ne- cessary accompaniment of the other. No man learns to know anything without desiring to know it. Similarly, so soon as any desire has become more than an indefinite yearning for we know not what, so soon as it is really desire for some object of which we are conscious, it necessarily implies an employment of the understanding upon those conditions of the real world which make the difference, so to speak, be- tween the object as desired and its realisation. Thus thought and desire are not to be regarded as separate powers, of which one can be exercised by us without, or in conflict with, the other. They are rather different ways in which the consciousness of self, which is also necessarily consciousness of a manifold world other than self, expresses itself. One is the effort of such consciousness to take the world into itself, the other its effort to carry itself out into the world. Desire and Will. The distinction between desire and 1 will seems firmly established in the experience of men as ex- pressed in our habitual language, *1 should like to but I wont' : we say *a man may be torn by conflicting desires'. What are we to say to the distinction ? Simply this : — that the final 'desire' differs in kind from the other competing impulses. It is what none of them were while competing, what none of them are, so far as any of them survive along with it. It ¥ f - 64 - implies, as did none of them, the presentation of an object with which the man for the time identifies himself or his good, and a consequent effort to realise this object. He now, as he did not before, consciously directs himself to the realisation of a desired object. If he desired before , it was owing to the result of his organisation , of habits (his own or his an- cestors'), of external excitement, &c. ; it is at any rate in an- other way that he desires now. In fact, the final preference is an act of will. "When it is urged, therefore, that the will often conflicts with and overcomes a man's desires and that an act of will therefore must be other than a desire, we answer, certainly it is other than any such desire as those which it is said to overcome. But it is not other than desire in that sense in which desire is ever the principle or motive of an imputable human action, of an action that has any moral quality, good or bad, that can properly be rewarded or punished, or is fit matter for praise or blame."*) The true distinction lies between passions as influences affecting a man —among which we may include 'mere desires', if we please —and the man as desiring, or putting himself forth in desire for the realisation of some object present to him in idea, which is the same thing as willing. And so with regard to IntdUa and Will] speculation and moral action are coor- dinate employments of the same self-conscious soul, and of the same powers of that soul, only differently directed. Will then is equally and indistinguishably desire and thought as they are involved in the direction of a self-distinguishing and self-seeking subject to the realisation of an idea. The will is simply the man. Any act of will is the expression of the man as he at that time is. The motive issuing in his act, the object of his will, the idea which for the time he sets himself to realise, are but the same thing in different words. Each is the reflex of what for the time , as at once feeling, desiring, and thinking, the man is. The real nature of any act of will depends on the particular nature of the object in ') Ibid. p. 149- _ 65 - which the person willing for the time seeks self-satisfaction ; and the real nature of any man as the subject of will — his character — depends on the nature of the objects in which he mainly tends to seek self-satisfaction. Self-satisfaction is the form of every object willed; but the filling of that form, the character of that in which self-satisfaction is sought, ranging from sensual pleasure to the fulfilment of a vocation conceive