Sheldon & Coi ~ )ezi)y's ext-Wooks. PROFESSOR OLNEY'S NEW MATHEMATICAL SERIES. The success of Prof. Olnley's series has been most wonderful. With all their admitted excellencies, both the Author and Publishers have felt that it was possible to retain their many attractive features and yet adapt the books more perfectly to the special school-room wants. To accomplish this most desirable end, Professor Olney has been accumulating very valuable suggestions. He has also, for several years, had associated with him in the preparation of this new series, som e of the b est prac tic al teachers in the country. The design is to present to the educational public the best and most teachable series of Matlhematics ever published. The work is now so far advanced that the Publishers are able to make the above pleasing announcement, which they feel will be of great interest to all who are engaged in teaching. THE NEW SERIES EMBRACES: I. Olney's First Lessons iX Arith)letic. JUST PUBLISHED. II. Olney's Practical Arithmetic. This book has been published but a short time, but it hag already had the most wonderful success. They are models of beauty and cheapness. For schools of a high grade, Professor Olney has prepared III. T ~e Science of Artseti'c. Tit SciCOMPLETE ANDhtetc Olney's Comtplete Algebra. NEW EDITION, rN LARGE TYPE. This book is now entirelv re-electrotyped in larger and more attractive type. The explanatory matter is greatly lessened. The attractive features of this book, which have made it the mo8t popular Alglqeba ever published in this country, are all retained. 11 I IV. The -Fii-st Pi-i)tcii)les of Algebra. Ax INTRODUCTION TO T]IIE AUTI-IOR'S COMPLFTF, AND UNIVERSITY ALGEBRAS. V. I JAMES HI FAIRCHILI)D: ISIDZXT OF OBBRLIN COLMBI NEW YORK: SHELDON & COMPANY, THlE bUlbN(;{N UT' Uilhlt~_AllUll. n , ccord,lg to Acet ot ongress, in the year 180, I JAMES Ii. FAiRCHILD, le Ork's Office of the District Cob- of the United States for the Nll s District ot Ohio, ( I l -- i - s j . I' I' 4.: {I.; PREFAOC Tmis volume, like most text-books on morals, has its origin in a course of instruction given by the author, in his regular college duties. Pupils who have listened to the lectures, naturally desire thein in a permanent form; and in deference to this want, very generally expressed, and often urged, they are now submitted for publication sentially as given to the classes. The system here presented is that which has grown up in this college, during the past thirty years, under the hand of the leading instructors here. It is not claimed as original in the +ullest sense, because the theory, in its germ; has been presented by various authors, especially by President Edwards, in his treatise on "The Nature of True Virtue," ad by his pupil and friend, Samuel Hopkinh Still less does the author of this volume claim originality for himself, ill reference to the more prominent features of the system. While he is responsible for some modifications of the views, for the form and order of presentation, and for the details of the treatise in general, he is happy to ascribe to the instructors of his youth, tle fi-iends and colleagues of later years, President Finney aind Professor Morgan, the honor and responsibility of being the leaders here, in the development of the theory Other associates have aided by their suggestions. No reference is made, in the following pages, to the recent able work of President Hopkins, for thb simple d. PREFACE. reason that the manuscript was prepared before that work was published. The appearance of that work might seem to render this unnecessary; but, while the leading principle in the two treatises is the same, the Inethods of development are, of course, entirely different; and it cannot be amiss to view the same general doctrine from different stand-points. A system of psychology must lie at the foundation of every system of morals. Such a system is, in general, assumed in this treatise; but on some special points, psychological investigations are introduced, because the ethical questions, related to those points, could not otherwise be elucidated. The effort has been to make a small book, instead of a large one; hence, the necessity, in the wide range of topics, of presenting brief statements of principles, rather than extended discussions and illustrations. For students, and others accustomed to think for themselves, this feature will not prove a defect. If the book should be introduced to classes of less maturity, the last three chapters of the theoretical part might be (emitted O~U COLLAi hy, 1a, IV CONTENTS. PART I.-THEORETICAL CHAPTER L xT-oDUcTooRY DemtxoNs.-Divisions of the Science-Topics treate of-obligation a Simple Idea-Undefinable-Attempted Definitions-A Moral Being or Person-Essential Attributes-Intellect-Sensibility-Free Will-A Moral Act-The Moral Element, where found-Different forms of Voluntary Action-More exact location of the Moral Element-Character and Intention-Two kinds of Moral Action...........................Page 1-30 CHAPTER II. KI,eRT OR VIRTUOUS ACTioN.-The True Good-Absolute and Relative Good-Illustrations of the two-Mere Animal lIife valuable-The sum mum bonum-No Comparison of the two forms of Good-Happiness-Obli gation, how perceived-Reg,ard to our own Good-Of Virtue as Good-Of Benevolence as Virtue-Benevolence in Consciousness.................... 21 CHAPTER III. WRONe OR Snoi AcioN. - Its Nature.- Its Motive - Its Form, how Determined-Gratification ofDesire not Sin-Sin Subordinates Reason-No Rational end in Sin-Sin not a Choice of Evil-Sin not Selfishness-Impos sibility of making one's own good the Supreme End-Sin in Consciousness -Self-gratification not the Intelligent End-Sin Subjection to Impulse, or Carnal-mindedness-Desires and Passions not Sinful-Their Uses......... 80 CONTENTS. CHAPTER IV. OF THE PABRTICULAR VIRTUES.- Benevolence +,he Root-Constitntes Right Character-Its Relation to the Particular Virtues, and to Right Acts Love-Gratitude-Justice not an Independent Virtue-Mercy notOpposed to Justice-Self-denial-Veracity-Humility-Faith-Obedience-Thc Teach ing of Scripture-Misapprehensions of Benevolence-Inter-dependence of the Virtues............................................................. 04 CHAPTER V. OF PAaTICUrAR Viczs.-Their Common Element-Their Re.lation to Sin fal Character-Their Origin-Sensuality-Ambition-Avarice-Pride and Vanity-Selfishness-The desire not Sinful-Malevolent Impulses-Natural or Impulsive Goodness-Two Characters Possible-Apparent Goodness Right Moral Judgments-Kindly Affections-Devotional Feelings-Impul sive Virtues, their relation to True Virtue-Imitative Goodness-Deficiency Exhibited-Are the Impulsive Virtues Sinful-Their Utility.............. Ax CHAPTER VI. ADDITIONAL R xMARs AND INFIRENCES. - Universality of the Law of Benevolence-Works of Supererogation Impossible-Morality Personal, not Transferable-Ambigtity of the term Character-The Seat of Moral Depravity-Total Moral Depravity-The Moral Change Required-Relation of Emotion to the Moral State-Moral Character in Consciousness-Moral Consistency............... 6 CHAPTER VII. RIGHT AND WRONG - DuTrY, KNOWN AND UNKNOWN - NEED OF A ETVELATION.-Ambigillty of the terms Right and Wrong-Absolute Right and Wrong-Relative Right and Wrong-Objective and Subjective Right and Wrong-Right and Wrong per se-The Expedient and the Right-Our Know.edge of the Right-End and Means-Doing Evil that Good may come-Least of two Evils-Known and Unknown Duty-Need of Revelation to frnlsh Motive and to indicate Objective Duty.......................... 66-714 CHAPTER VIILI. CoNscrzcz — Is rr A GUE? - Definition and Office- Impulse of Con science-Approval and Condemnation-AsEth tic Conscience-Conscience 6 CONTENTS. as a Guide-Intervention of Judgment-Different Views-Whately and Alexander-Sins of Ignorance-Rational Conscience the Guide, not the 1mnotional, nor the Esthetic-Conscientiousness-Paul-Honesty-Sinrlty-Conscience Educated, Enlightened, Perverted..................... CHAPTER IX. Ulrlm OR Sn(LJCITY Or MoRA AcTio. — Virtue and Sin Contradic tory-Their Co-existence Impossible-Different Hypotheses to explain their Co-existence-Imperfect Powers-From the Fall-From Past Sin Right Intention with Wrong Thoughts and Feelingsa-Mixed Motives- Par tial Regard for Good-Lack of Intensity-Right Ultimate Choice and Wrong Acts-The Teaching of the Scriptures-Practical Teaching-Taylor and Metcalf-Objections and Answers-Prevailing Consciousness-Negative Testimony-No Room for Improvement-Degrees of Goodness-Degrees of Sinfulness-Temptation and Guilt-Knowledge of Past Sinfulness-Gen eral Bearing of the Doctrine............................................. 810 CHAPTER X. TLoars opr OBLIrGATIO.- Th Question-Different Answers-Reason for the Difference-Socrates and Plato-Aristotle-Doctrine of the Stoics Of the Epicureans-Modern Views-Paley-New Haven Theory-Difficul ties-Psychological Error-No Freedom-Misrepresents Benevolence-Mis takes the Motive-Makes no Difference between the Good and the Bad Does not Accord with Scripture-Utilitarianism-Misapplication of the Term-Needed Discrimination-" Holy Happiness."................. 10-111 CHAPTER XI. TzomR s oF OBr IATION.-Of Right as Ultimate-Of Obligation a originating in the will of God-Difficulties-Reason not Ultimate-Obliga tion known Intuitively-No Character in God-Relativity of Morality-Un scriptural-Founded in the Reason or Nature of God-Of Spiritual Worthi ness as Ultimate-Difficulties-Not an Ultimate Good-Still less one's Own Worthiness-Inverts the Order of Thought-Of Virtue as Ultimate-View of Edwards-Andover Theory-Difficulties-Complacency not Virtue-Not a Higher Virtue-Conf'ision in the use of the term Good-Virtue a Quality of (,oice, not its Object-Of Abstract Right as Ultimate —Axiom of the Theory-Does not explain the Virtues-Gives no Unity to Virtt-Right ness not a Motive-Maxim of tbh Theory-Acting from Principle-Right ma not Ultimate-Incidental Advantages of the Theory of Benevolence. 116-1N 7 CONTENTS. PART II.-PRACTICAL ETHICS. PapL~TI RT ]................................................... 11N FIRST )IVISION. CHAPTER L GovZR - ITs NATURE AND FOUNDATION. - Definitions - Relation of Sanctions to Government-Object of Government-Its Right to Exist The Right to Govern-Duty to Govern-Designation of the Ruler-Form of Government-Extent of Authority-Not Dependent on Desire of the Governed............................................................... 137-1U CHAPTER II. I!H DivrE GovTERENT. - Its Constitution - Why God Assumes the Government-The Divine Law-How Known to Men-Revealed Law-Au thority of Examples -The Saviour's Example-Genuine Virtue Required Personality of the Law-Application to Communities —Dealing with Na tions -National Sins.................................................... 142-14 CHAPTER III. PENALTIES UNDER TH DivINr GOVERNMENT.-Nature of Penalty Effects of Penalty-Relation of Penalty to Desert-True Reason of Penalty -Its Extent-Discipline and Penalty-Necessity of Penalty in the Divine Governmenut-Degree and Duration-Guilt Everlasting-Natural Conse quences not Penalty-Physical Law and Penalty-Remorse and Penalty Providential Consequences..............................................11 CHAPTER IV. (,im GovERNXMENT. - Its Foundation - Right to Govern - The Form of Government-A Legitimate Government-A Tyranny-Constitutions Not a Social Compact-Right and Duty of Voting-The Ruler a Servant Doctrine of Instruction-Right of the Majority-Principle of Representa tion-The Will of the Governed a Controlling Element-General Tendency . to Democracy-Relation cf Law to Righteousness-Mistakes....... 1-1 8 CONTENTS. CHAPTER V. PENALTES IN CIVIL GOVERNMENT. - Uses of Penalties - Dangerous TendencyCapital Punishment-Reasons for it-Objections.............. 170-1, CHAPTER VI. IXITS OF OBEDIENCE TO CivI GOVERNMENT. - Government Subordinate-The Higher Law applied to a Democratic State-No General Formula-Laws, just, indifferent, unjust-Two Possible Courses-Duty of a Subordinate Magistrate-Right of Revolution-Apprehended Tendency -Errors in two Directions.............................................. 17181 CHAPTER VIL To RELATIONS OF NATIONS TO EACH OTHER.-Obligation of Nations limited-Laws of Nations-Duty to respect each other's Sovereignty Duty in case of Rebellion-In Treaties-In Commercial Intercourse-Duty of Self-preservation-The Rightfulness of War-In case of Resistance at Home-In case of Aggression from Without-In Defence of the Weak —In Suppression of Outrage-In Justifiable Revolution-ObjectionsThe True Aim in War-Duties in War............................................. 188-198 CHAPTER VIII. FAMILY GOVERNMENT. - Has a Natural Foundation - Limited in its Subjects-Wide in its Application to Interests -Mode of Constitution Question of Headship-A Relation of Confidence to be entered upon with Deliberation-Maintained with Care-A Natural Sphere for Each-Rela tions of the Family to the State and to Society........................... 19905 CHAPTER IX. DUTIES OF PARENT AND CHILD-Or TEACHER AND PIUPIL.-Chief Work of the Family-Place of Parental Affection-Leading Duty of the Parent-Duty of Obedience and its Natural Termination-Claim of the Child-Limit of Obedience-Duty in Maturity-Towards Dependent Parents-The Teach. er's Authority-Its Extent-Need of Closer Definition-The Pupil's Duty -Unnatural Antagonism-Mutual Regard-Unfavorable Tendencies-Ex treme Individnalism-Independence of Opinion.................... CONTENTW SECOND DIVISION. PERSONAL RIGHTS AND DUTIES8. CHAPTER I. Ao t PRtixcas.-Basis of Rights-The Comprehensive Right-Ins lenable Rights-Basis of Duties-Corelation of Rights and Duties-Positive and Negative Precepts-Subjects of Rights and Duties-The Rights of Brut Superior Right of Rational Beings............................. 216 CHAPTER II. RtSHS-LIP.-Basis of the Right-Guilt of Murder-Malice and Hatred Man-slaughter-Related Crimes-Right of Self-preservgtion Limited-Self defnce-Protection of Property-Carrying Weapons-Duelling —Objec ions to Sal-defence..................................................... 222-2 CHAPTER III. iG-L rszr.-Def mnition and Extent-Basis of the Right-Misappr hension of its Origin-Applicationl to Different Powers-Principle of Tol eration-Freedom of the Press-Free Discussions-Intervention of Gov ernment in Worship and Education-Subjective Limitations-Respect to the Consciences of Others-Use of Definite RulesViolations of LibertyIts Defense..............................................................2298 CHAPTER IV. bGTs-Rp.uTvATiog.-The Interest Involved -How a Good-The PreceptTemptations to its Violation-Duty of Exposing Wrong-Slander in Trutb elling.......................................,........................... 4S CHAPTER V. GHTs-PROPERTY'.-Origin of the Right-The Precept-Property How Ao quired-Transferable-Right of Discovery-Effect of long Possession Things not to be Appropriated-Animals made Property, Human Being* Limitations of the Right-Law of Exchange-Duty of the Vender 10 CONTENTS. Standard of Value-Managing the Market-Cicero's Example-Law of Wages-Woman's Wages-Work that Is above Wages —Violations of the Right of Property-Bankrupt Laws-Prevalence of Fraud upon the Governmeat-Mischief )f Repudiation-Immorality of Gambling................ t CHAPTER VI. )tq-PhiT.-Origin of Duties-Nature of Piety-Its Relation to Rell. glon-Morality and Religion-Morality Attained by Religion-Opposite of Piety-Duty of Worship-Possibility of Prayer-Speculative Objections Social and Public Prayer-The Sabbath-Change of Day-Obligation Per manent-Proper Observance-Duty of Promoting Religion............... 25~2 CHAPTER VII. U'Izs —PMLANTR PY- -PATRIOTISM.-Nature of Philanthropy-Its Rela lion to Religion-Its Scope-Proper Test-Misanthropy-Patriotism as a Virtue-Required by Benevolence-Things Opposed to Patriotism...... 266271 CHAPTER VIIL D wzcr L.-Its Nature and Reasons-Extends to all the Facul ties-Spiritual Culture-Its Relation to Virtuous Character-Intellectual Culture-Things to be held Subordinate-Kind of Knowledge to be Sought ulture of the Sensibility-Gives Power-Relation to Moral Character Control Indirect-Associations-Books-Perfection of Character.......... 27'2m CHAPTER IX. DTs — Sm C-CUTUR -B. - Esthetic- Its Expensiveness- Elevating Ten dency-Increases Power-False-reflnement-Fastidiousness-The Culti vated Lady-Culture, How Attained-Degree of Attention Proper-Other De mands to be Considered-Physical Culture a Duty-Health-Manual Skill Manners and Habits-Predominance of the Soul........................... 28 CHAPTER X. DuTrns-le-UsE ss.-The True Aim-The Natural Impulse-Proper Os cupation-Notoriety not Usefulness-Wealth and its Uses-Special Oblig tion of the Rich-Social Influence-Difficulties and Duties-Special Duties of the Young-The Grcat Want...............................-... 2. I1 CON1ENTS. CHAPTER XI. DuTzs —]uTY.-FaithfUlness in Contracts-Binding Force-Threats and Promises-In what Sense Binding-When Null-Conditions-Express and Implied Contracts-Effect of the Oath-Marriage Engagements........... 8031 CHAPTER XII. DUTIES-VERACITr.-Its Nature and Obligation-Significance of the Oath Its Rightfulness-Profanity-Violations of Veracity-Limits of the Obliga tion-Words and Gestures-Legal Practice-Instinct of Veracity........ 311-11 CIIAPTER XIII. DUTS —CHAsTITY.-Nature of the Duty-Effect and Criminality of Unchas tity-Injustice of Society-Marriage Provided for-Its Nature and Condl a Mo.m ILawof Di vrce il LAw-Incest —Ctneluding emar.. 819 is MORAL PHILOSOPHY. PART I.-THEORETICAL. CHAPTER I. IODUCTORY DEFINITIONS AND REMARKS. MORAL PHILOSOPHY is the science of obligation or duty l states and analyzes the facts connected Definitiono w th obligation and its perception, and deter- andtopi. mines principles of action and rules of duty. More particularly, the subjects of which it treats are moral beings, moral action, moral law, moral government, and personal rights and duties. It is often called the science of ethics, and is divided into two parts, theoretical and practical Theoretical ethics presents the principles of the science, while practical ethics applies those principles and solves particular problems of duty. The treatment of special cases is sometimes called casuistry. Obligation, the theme of ethical philosophy, admits of no definition, except by a synonyme. The Oblgation not dinable. idea conveyed by the term is a simple one, incapable of analysis. Its import is manifest to every rational being, given immediately in his own thought It cannot be imparted from one to another; and every attempt at definition or elucidation proves abortive. Thus, Paley says, "Obligation is nothing more than ani inducement of sufficient strength, and resulting in somg ItORAL PHILOSOPHY. way from the command of another;" and N. W. Tay lor, "Moral obligation is the binding influence of that necessity which a moral being is under of performing that action which is decisively proved to be the best ac tion." All such definitions tend to bewilder. The thought in every rational soul is clear and unequivocal and its existence is proved in the universal use and ap prehension oi such terms as oughbt, duty, right, and wrong. Not so much the nature of obligation, as the grounds and conditions of its existence and apprehension, is the proper subject of inquiry. A moral being is a being to whom obligation pertains, moralbeing of whom it can be said, he ought, or ought ,r penon. not, who affirms of himself, I ought or ought not. Such a being we call a person. He differs from all other beings, not merely in the degree of his intelligence, but in the kind of intelligence with which he is endowed. Possessing some faculties and susceptibilities in common with beings of a lower order, in others he is peculiar, and is thus separated from them by a line which they can never pass. The attributes essential to moral agency are commonly Essential at and properly designated as intellect, sensitributes, In. tellectte. bility, and free-will. The intellect is the general faculty of perceiving and knowing, and comnprehends the faculties of sense, memory, imagination, judgment, and reason. The perception of the true end of life, and thence of obligation, is an intellectual act; and thus intellect is essential to moral agency or personality. Sensibility is the susceptibility of pleasure and pain, of ,ensibility natural good and evil. Such a susceptibility ii ISE. the only conceivable channel of the idea of good and evil; and this idea is the necessary antecedent 14 DEFIN1TIONS AND REMARKS. uf that of obligation, and hence of right and wroing. Thus, every moral being must be a sentient being; only on this condition can he be a subject of obligation. It might be added that obligation terminates on sentient beirg -is only die to beings susceptible of natural good and evil. Hence, if there were no sentient life, obulga tion would lack both subject and object. In a world des titute of sensibility, whatever intelligence there might be, no obligation or thought of obligation could ever arise. Free-will, or the voluntary faculty, is the power of choosing or refusing the true end of life, as Fre-will presented by the intelligence. The possession necessary of this faculty is implied in the very idea of obligation. To affirm obligation of a being destitute of the faculty of free action, is impossible in the nature of the case. Power for any act, in the sense of ability to do or not to do, is a self-evident condition of obligation to that act Ability to do, in its proper sense, carries with it the ability not to do; and thus free-will is an essential attri bute of personality. It may be spoken of as the charac teristic attribute, because obligation always accompa nies it. A moral act is an act to which obligation pertains, of which we affirm that it ought or ought not to Amoral act aproved or be done. The performance of such an act adiapprove(l. involves the idea of good or ill desert, of praiseworthinress or blameworthiness. The doer is approved or diapproved. This judgment is wholly peculiar, incapable o,f analysis, not resolvable into a judgment of wisdom )r unwisdom, of utility or inutility, of esthetic pro?picty or impropriety. It is a moral approval or disap. proval, a judgment perfectly apprehended by every moral being. la MORAL PHILOSOPHY. Where is found the moral element? Every moral act Moral e.e- implies the activity of the three departments ment where foetw?oer of the mind, involving thought, feeling, and willing, and is often attended by outward or corporeal ac tion. Does moral responsibility attach equally to eacl of these exercises, or to one alone? Where resides the element of morality? Not in the outward action. The muscular movement Not in the is connected with the action of the mind by ou~tward action.rd a a law of necessity, and is inevitable when the conditions are supplied. We do not know the character of an act from the outward manifestation. It is but an index of the internal state, often ambiguous; and the moral character is the same with the same mental action, whether the outward action follows or not. Not in the movement of the intelligence; because that Not in the in- movement is governed by necessity. Our telligence. conceptions and judgments are necessarily what they are. No praiseworthiness or blameworthiness accrues to the agent directly from the action of the in, telligence. A judgment or conception may be adequatet or inadequate, correct or incorrect, and in this view right or wrong; but it is not an object of moral approbation or disapprobation. We praise or blame the agent for the moral disposition which leads to the just or unjust conception or judgment. For the disposition, we hold him responsible directly; for the action of the intelligence, in. directly. Nor is the moral element found in the movement of Not in the the sensibility. That movement is necessary. snsibityv. The emotions result from their exciting causes. With given conditions they must be as they are. They are pleasant or painful, desirable or undesirable; but in 16 DEFINITIONS AND REMARKS. themrnselves not praiseworthy or blameworthy. We intel. ligently approve or disapprove of the disposition or con. duct which p)roduces or fosters particular emotions, and regard the emotion as an index, more or less sure, of moral character. The element of morality is found in the action of hlie will alone. Hiere is firee, responsible Found In vol action. Whatever motive or inducement to ntaryaction voluntary action may exist, the agent himself is the responsible cause of the action, and hence is properly approved or disapproved, according to the nature of thaws action. To this, and to this only, does obligation di. rectly attach; when the voluntary action is wholly such as it ought to be, all present obligation is met. This is a necessary intuitive judgment, and must be accepted as an axiom in morals. Of its truthfulness there can be no doubt in any mind, except such doubt as may result from obscurity of thought or expression. A moral agent may be held responsible indirectly for thoughts, and feelings, and external actions, because these are more or less modified or controlled by the will; but all this responsibility attaches directly to the voluntary action. If thought, or feeling, or external action be ever spoken of as involving moral character, it is because it is regarded as voluntary. Upon this point there is practical agreement among men: the differences, if they exist, are speculative and theoretical. But voluntary action exists in different forms. Does the element of morality attach directly to all Different forms of vol these forms? The act of the student in at- funitary aton. tending a recitation is voluntary — hence is a moral act, where in this process of voluntary action do we find the moral character? Nearest to our observation and most 17 MOR AL PHILOSOPHY. anperficial is the volition, or series of Volitions, which causes the outward act of coming; but these volitions do not reveal character, bec.ause they do not involve it. The good and the bad alike put forth these volitions. Back of these volitions we find a more general purpose, from which the volitions spring-the purpose to secure an education, or still further back, the purpose to gain influence and power, to which education is a means. But in these more general purposes, although voluntary states!, we find no revelation of moral character. The good and the bad alike cherish the same general purposes and pursue them by the same means-sit side by side in the same class. Enquiring still further, we find in one a voluntary choice of the proper end or object of life; that end which the intelligence approves. His other purposes and volitions are all subordinate to this ultimate choice, and are executive of it. Another does not accept this end of life, but freely declines it. Some other scheme or impulse of desire or passion occupies him, and with refer. ence to this unworthy end he forms his purposes, and puts forth his volitions. Hiere we have the key to the character of the action and of the agent; and in this ultimate choice of the right end, or refusal to choose it, which Exact place of is still a choice, we necessarily locate the moral the moral element. element. In this respect the two agents and their actions morally differ; while in their subordinate purposes, and executive volitions, and outward actions they may be alike. One conforms to obligation, the othei does not. The general conviction that the moral element of ac Chmcter as tion is here found, is indicated in the populai ntention. Iexpression that the character of an act depend upon- the intention. The expression is true of the ulti 18 DIFINITIONS AND REMARKS. mate intention —the voluntary attitude in reference to the rational end of life. It is not true of any subordinate purpose or intention, or of any action which is execuive of a more remote choice. The character dces-not lepend, in the case supposed, upon the intention to gain n education, or to secure influence and power, but upon the choice of the end which these are to subserve. All subordinate or executive action derives its character fromn this choice, and is made necessary by the choice, in the sense that, the convictions of the intelligence remaining the same, the executive action must be as it is while the ultimate choice remains. The young man who proposes to obtain an education to serve God and his fellow-men. pursues his course because he believes it the proper mode of accomplishing his end. While he believes this, he cannot turn aside from his course without abandoning his ultimate end. If he enters into business while he believes that a course of study is the proper means, he abandons his end. This he is always Executiveacfree to do, and hence executive action is tionfree. properly free action; but its morality is wholly dependent upon the fundamental choice. HIence obligation, strictly speaking, attaches only to this ultimate choiceaction in reference to that end of life which the intelligence approves, that predominant state of the will which determines all other action When this is right, the action is right, the character is right, so far as pertains to morality. Two kinds of moral action, and only two, are possible. The agent may accept the right end of life, Two positiong and thus his action become right, virtuous; only. or hlie may reject that right end, and thus his action be come wrong, sinful. No neutral position is possible to, 19 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. rational being, because, when the right end is proposed to his intelligence, he must accept or not accept; and not to accept is to reject. Moral freedom lies in the ability to accept or to reject this end-an ability which is essentia' to moral agency. 20 CHAPTER H. RIGHT ACTION OR VIRTUE) GOOD. lt]GHT or virtuous action is the action which we mot ally approve, and for which we pronounce the Right action agent praiseworthy. It consists;n the choice of the right end of life, that end which the intelligence approves. To be virtuous is to be reasonable. It is to accept and treat as good and valuable what the intelligence presents ao good. The virtuous man is the reasonable man, the man that follows his perceptions and convictions. It is in the light of these perceptions that obligation arises, and in following them obligation is met. But what is the good which the intelligence recognizes, and in the presence of which obligation is The true seen-that good which every moral being good. holds himself bound to respect? What does the reason present as truly valuable This is a psychological ques tion, yet every theory of m.-'als involves an answer to it, expressed or implied. Absolute good, that which is valuable in itself and for itself, is found only in connection with being Absolute -sentient being-that is, being endowed with good. ensibility. It consists in the satisfaction of that sensi bility-satisfaction in every form in which it can exist Fullness of satisfaction in the case of any sentient being s completeness of good in his case. It is well-being, or lappiness, or blessedness-all words of the sane general import. The capacity for such satisfaction or good gives to being its absolute worth and importance; and in the MORAL PHILOSOPHY. experience of such satisfaction is absolute good, or ulti. mate and final value. In a state of dissatisfaction or of pain and misery is found absolute and ultimate evil-that which is evil in itself and on its own account. Absolute good is no abstraction or mere conception; it is an ac tual experience or state of sentient being. It is valuable for what it is in itself, and is necessarily regarded by every rational being as having intrinsic worth. Relative good, on the other hand, is good that is valued Relative for its uses. It is good for the purposes it can good. serve in the satisfaction of sentient being. All forms of material good are of this nature. A uni. verse of it would have no value, unless there were beings to use and to enjoy it. When its utility fails, it ceases to be accounted good. Robinson Crusoe, in his exile, spurned the lump of gold because it was not iron. Iron he could use, gold he could not. When about to return to civilized life, he takes with him the gold, because it will be useful. Thus relative good is dependent for its value upon its usefulness to being, its adaptedness to produce satisfaction. Absolute good is satisfaction itself, and is not contemplated with reference to anything beyond. Our instinctive discrimination of these two forms of Instinctive good may be illustrated by the supposition discrimination illustrated. that we are passing through an uninhabited region, beyond the reach of any beings who can appropriate its advantages. We traverse fields of waving grain -good if there were beings to use it, but worthless where it stands. We heedlessly trample it down, kindle our camp fires in the midst of it. In itself it is good for nothing, and there is nothing to which it can sustain a relative value. We regret that so much good should be wasted, and the sight even of herds of animals to feed and thrive upon it, 22 RIGHT ACTION OR VIRTUE, GOOD. would be a relief. For their sake we would save it; fot itself we do not. Trees loaded with the choicest fiiiits overhang our path. We renmorselessly shake down the fruit, appropriate what we can use with satisfaction, and carelessly trample on and leave the rest. If there were beings to use it, it would be good. In itself it has no value The apprehension that others might follow and need the fruit) would make us careful. We pluck the most beau. tifuil flowers without misgiving. So far as they please us, we account them good. For the rest we account them as nothing. The thought that invisible intelligences might rejoice in them, would lead us to spare them. We mnar and destroy the most beautiful trees; for a beautiful tree is good for nothing beyond its uses, and beyond the reach of sentient being it has no use. If those trees should utter sighs and groans, as in the fables of Virgil and Tasso, we should shrink appalled from our work. They must then be regarded for what they are in themselves. They cease to be merely relative good. A being endowed with intellect meets us. Angelic in its powers, if you please, but, if conceivable, destitute of sensibility. No thrill of pleasure, no twinge of pain ever moves it. All experiences are equally indifferent to it; it is destitute of experience, like a stone or tree. When we fully under stand the case, we regard the being as like any mere torce ot nature, good for what it can bring to pass, and good for nothing else. If we can appropriate this intel ligence to ourselves, we do it without scruple. Witlion' such appropriation it is wasted power. Add to this intel ligence a powerful will, if this is conceivable. The case is not altered. The being thus endowed is still only a power, good for what it can accomplish. You may at tacb the being to yourself as an advantage, make it your 28 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. slave, and no wrong is done. Nothing is due to it; tl:e nrly question is, how can it be best used? Unless it can be employed in the service of sentient being, it is w-asted good. Add to this being feeling, sensibility, a susceptiI)ility of pleasure and pain, and the case is entirely clianged. IHereisthesusceptibility of absolute good. The bI)eing, has claims to regard on its own account-has interests and rights of its own which must be respected. AIny use to which you can put the being, without interferirg with the good there is in its own life, is legitimate. A worm lies in our path, repulsive and loatihsmne. It is nothing to us; it is something to itself and in itself. Before, we trampled on beaiuty and utility without scruple; now we hesitate. This susceptibility of good, even in low and loathsome forms, makes us pause, and suggests obligation, questions of right and wrong. Cowper has well said: "I would not enter on my list of friends Though graced with polislhed manners and fine sense, Yet wanting sensibility-the man Who needlessly sets foot upon a wormn." That regard for lower animal life is not a mere poetic lwver ant- sentiment, is shown in the fact that the law meals protected by law. of the land punishes cruelty to animals. If it be said that the law is intended to guard society against a demoralizing influence, that the man and not the animal is the being cared foi, it may be replied that cruelty to animals is demoralizing because it involves Jisregard of absolute good. Ornamental trees are pro toeted by law, but simply as valuable to the owner or to the community, not as having thlemselves rights. Abso lute and relative good are often found combined in the same being. Animal life is a good in itself and a rela. 24 RIGHI- ACTION OR VIRTUE, GOOD. tive good as well-a utility. Indeed, in general, utility is the leading element in our estimate of the worth of animals. A good man is valuable both for the good of his own well-being and for his usefuilness-the good lie can do. We regard a child for what he is in himself and for what he is to others, but the two forms of good are still distinct in thought and in fact. Wherever we find being endowed with sensibility, there and there —only is the capacity for absolute good. Whatever can be used directly or indirectly for the satisfaction of this sensibility, is relative good. Well-being,, satisfaction, happiness, then, is true goodthe summum bonum, not merely in the sense TheSummum of the highest good, but of the final, ulti- Bonum. mate, absolute good-that in which all other goods terminate and find their value. To determine this good was the enquiry of the ancients ini their pursuit of the sum mum bontm. Socrates evaded the question when he was pressed by Aristippus, the sophist. "Do you ask whether I know anything good for a fever?" "No." "Good for ophthalmia?" "No." "Good for hunger?" "No." "Well, if you enquire for a good that is good for nothing, I neither know it nor do I want to." And yet the good which is good for nothing is the only good which has intrinsic value-the only good which we regard on its own account. Absolute and relative good admit of no comparison as to degree or as to value. They are totally Absolute and relative goodl different in kind, and can never be regarded as differ in iinad ival interests. Relative good has only a derived value corresponding with the absolute good, the well-being which it is capable of producing. The comparison of the two which we seem to make in the use of animals is ap. 2 29 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. parent, not real. The comparison is in fact between the absolute good in the animal life, and the absolute good which can be secured in some other being by the use of the aninal as a means of satisfaction. IRelative good can iinever be for its own sake an object of regard. We always look beyond to the good on which it teruminates, and value it for its bearing on that good. It is true that de sire fastens on relative good as its object, and thus there is an apparent regard for it on its own account. Still, its value is not in itself and on its own account, but in its rela tion to sentient life, as is seen in the fact that it is utterly wasted and lost, unless it has been used for the advantage of being. If it were not an object of desire, it could n(t be even relative good. Well-being, satisfaction, happiness is a good, independently of any desire which may faster. upon it, and of any relation whatever. We always so regard it, and never fear lest it should be wasted; for we do not look for any use of it beyond itself. The terl Thetermhap- happiness is used in this treatise, not in the low pines I restricted sense given it by some writers, but as comnprehlensive of all satisfaction, blessedness, wellbeing,, from the lowest forms of animal pleasure to the highest joys which dwell in the bosom of God. In this sense it is absolute good, and the only absolute good. In the presence or thought of this good, obligation is Ideaofoblig. perceived. The intelligence sees the good to tion, its origin. be an object of value, and with that percep tion arises the idea of obligation, of duty to respect it, to treat it as good, to will it to all sentient beings, to stand ready to promote it, and, as occasion or opportunity arises, to put forth effort to promote it. This perception of obligation is entirely independent of the relation of the good to ourselves, or to any other particular being. The obli 26 RIGHET ACTION OR YIRTUE) GOOD. gation to choose the good is dependent upon the value of the good in itself. The perception of this value brings with it the obligation. The being whose good is conteinmplated, may be wholly beyond our reach; the obligation to choose the good is still the same. It may be impossible r even improper that anything should be done to plo mote that good; this does not affect the obligation to will the good. Hence, to every moral being, the only condition of obligation is the perception of the good. In reference to the obligation to promote that good, there are other conditions. There must be a possibility of success in the effort, and on the whole it must seem wiser that the effort of the agent should take that direction, rather than another; but independently of all such conditions, the obligation to will the good, to be well disposed towards it, still remains. Our own good is included in this absolute good, the good of being, and hence is a proper object Ourowngoo of our regard. It is as valuable as that of included. our neighbor, and no more valuable. This is the place which the intelligence gives it, the place which it occupies in the primary obligation to choose or will the good; but as an object towards which effort is to be di rected, our own good sustains to us a very different relation. It lies within our reach as no other good does, and hence arises a special obligation to promote it. To choose or regard the good of being is primarily and directly binding upon all moral beings; this Right action is; enevois primary, fundamental obligation. Right lence.e or virtuous action is conformity to this obligation, and consists in choosing, or willing, or regarding the good on its own account, for its own inherent value. This action is properly called Bcovolence, to use the term in its strict 27 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. etymological meaning, as the willing of good. The sul ject of the action must be a moral being, a person, with faculties to apprehend and choose the good; the object )f the action is sentient being — being in whose litf good exists, or is possible. Hence, President Edwards properly defines benevolence as the love of being. It expresses a state of the will, not of the sensibility or of the intelligence. It is a voluntary exercise, and hence always possible to a moral being, and always obligatory. As a conscious exercise, it in general terminates on Benevolence individual beings, particular objects. The in consciousuess. general statement of the obligation to choose tile good of being, may not be in the mind, or might not be apprehended; stilt the duty is perceived in reference to every individual being, and every such being, as it is made an object of thought, becomes in the benevolent mind an object of regard. This necessarily follows from the very nature of benevolence, which is a choice of the good of being on account of the inherent value of the good, not on account of somethling agreeable or inviting in the particular object of regard. Thus, benevolence is, in its own nature, disinterested, Impartiality and needs no qualifying term to indicate this of benevolence. attribute. It must be impartial, or it is not the choice of good for its own value. If we embrace in outr regard one being and exclude another, whatever that exercise may be, it is not benevolence. Thus, the Saviour proposes as the test of virtuous love, the love which fulfils obligation, that it shall extend to enemies as to friends, to our neighbors as to ourselves. This is, in the very nature of the case, the characteristic of benevolence. To choose the good of one for its own sake, is to choose 28 RIGHT ACTION OR VIRTUE, GOOD. the good of all, whether good or bad, insect, angel, oy even God. It may be necessary to mention here that the term good is used by some writers to mean the Of right ac right-or that action which is in accordance tionalg' with obligation. To prevent ambiguity, the qualifying term moral is sometimes prefixed in this case. Thus, moral good should mean that course of action whi(h is conformed to obligation, or virtue considered objectively Virtue considered subjectively, as a quality of character is sometimes called the good, but should rather be called goodness. Natural good, or well-being, and moral good, or virtue obior'vely considered, have a fixed and necessary relation to each other. The conception of natural good logically and chronologically precedes that of moral good. The two ideas are utterly distinct, but the last can never arise in the mind but in connection with the first. These two kinds of good admit of no comparison as to value or excellence, because they are totally unlike in kind. One is happiness, the other is duty, or virtue. Virtue is also a good, that is, a relative good, as promotive of happiness. It is the grand condition of blessedness to moral beings. Great confiusion arises fromr a careless use of the term good in these various sense 20 CITAPTER Ill. WRONG ACTION OR SIN. WRONG or si,ful action is the action which we mor ,ture of in ally condemn, and for which we pronounce ction. the agent blameworthy. It is a refusal to meet obligation or duty, a refusal to be benevolent, or to will the good of being as in itself valuable. It is, of course, unreasonable action; for reason presents happi.ess, well-being as good, and benevolence or the choice of that good as duty. Sinful action is opposed to reason and intelligence, and must find its motive elsewhere than among the facts and considerations which reason presents. Its sinfulness consists in the refusal to be benevoent-the duty ever present to the moral agent. But nreasonable action must have a motive-an inducement to refuise a choice so excellent and praiseworthy. The motive to wrong action is found in the impulse Motive in sin- of the desires and passions. These have their fl action. seat in the sensibility, and,when aroused, soicit the will to seek their gratification, even at the sacrifice of good and the claims of duty. The man,in the exercise of his freedom,hlas power to yield to these solicitations, neglecting the claim of duty, or to refiluse to yield; and in this choice he determines his moral character. Yielding to desire or passion as his controlling motive, he becomes a sinner. The desire terminates on some object, some relative good which excites desire, and the attainiment of which tends to gratification. The immediate aim of the action to which the desire impels is the at WRONG ACTION OR SIN. tainment of this object. But it cannot properly be said that the object of desire is the motive. It is the motive only as it awakens desire, and that desire itself is the immediate motive. The object may be really valuable, a means of good, as contemplated by the intelligence, or it may be in the end harmful, pernicious, and known to 1)( sich; it matters not, so long as desire fastens upon it. The inebriate, mad with the love of drink, quaffs the poison, even though he knows that at the last, " it biteth like a serpent and stingeth like an adder." Desire is blind to the good or evil, on the whole, there is in the object. It operates upon the will by its own blind force as an impulse, and not by considerations of interest or value. Thus, motives to sin come through the desires and passions, while motives to virtue appeal to us through the intelligence and reason. The formn of the sinful action depends upon the ruling desire. In general these desires change; one Different .S satiated or fails, and another takes its place, forms. and the action varies in form with the desire, now terminating on this object and now on that. The moral action is, however, still the same, as long as there remains the refusal to be governed by a regard for the good. In such cases there is not that concentration of action upon the achievement of the end which results firom benevolent choice. In other cases, more rare, some absorbing, predominant passion determines the will, and produces constancy of action, as in the case of the avaricious or the ambitious man, with an intensity of activity whicl cannot result from varying impulses. In all these case the sinful element is the same-the neglect of sin not in yielding to good, the refusal to be benevolent. Apart fronm Desire this element there is no sin in yielding to desire. Yielding 31 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. to desire is the sole law of action with brutes; but with them it is not sin, because there is no apprehended good to be sacrificed to desire. It is right for moral beings to gratify desire, when the gratification is not in conflict witJl the claims of benevolence. The gratification of deshre is to be accounted a good, to be held as a part of general good, ul)ject to the claims of duty-the decisions of reason. Ifere was the failure of our first parents. When they "4saw that the tree was good for food, and that it was pleasant to the eyes, and a tree to be desired to make one wise," they took of the firuit; while duty, as indicated by divine command, and their own reason as well, forbade the eating. This was the nature of the first sin in our world, and has been the characteristic of every sin from that day to this. Without such a command, and without any apprehension that the eating was improper, the grat. ification would have been indifferent, or even a duty There is no sin in mere pleasure or enjoyment the sin i in the unbenevolent choice which is involved in the acceptance of th e pleasu. We have seen that virtue involves obedience to reason Reason ubor- and intelligence, and sin subjection to the dedinate. sires and passions. It is still true that the evildoer employs his intelligence in determining his course; but he uses it in a subordinate capacity, not to furnish him the principle of action, but to serve him in the pursuit of the objects of desire; no longer an authoritative leader, but an impressed and subjugated guide. Is he avaricious? ltie prostitutes his intelligence to the service of his passion for wealth, and becomes the shrewd and successful moneymakler; thus, the intelligence may pander to every desire Obedience to impulse, in a rational being, then, does not lead to the same simplicity and directness of action as in the 32 WRONG ACION OR SIN. brute. A long train of appliances and cunning schemes mnay intervene between the desire and the attainment of its object, the result of calculation and not of mere instinct. The desire itself may be held in abeyance-suppressed for thie time, that its final gratification may be more sure and complete. One desire may be utterly repressed because of alpprehended difficulties, and another enthrena.i in its place. The degree of intellectual culture -v determine these matters. The savage seeks the objects of his desire with more directness; he has little ap. prehension of things remote or future. tie will scarcely scatter the seed and wait for a harvest. In the cultivated man the case is entirely different. The coarser passions are to a great extent subdued. Iis refined desires fasten on objects in the distant future; it may be even in a life hereafter; and his action assumes the intelligent,moderated forms which result from this wider view. Yet the principle of action is the same in every evil-doer; desire, impulse controls; the intelligence is subservient and not dominant. In sinful action we find no general comprehensive end, which is th(,bject of pursuit in all No intelligent forms of evil-doing, corresponding with the end in sin. good of being in right or benevolent action. In so far as there can be said to be a chosen end, it changes with the clianging desires. Properly there is no end which is pursued on its own account. Desire, passion, operates rather as a vis a tergo, an impulse moving the will by its own direct force, than as presenting an object of pursuit which the intelligence embraces, and which urges to piursuit by its intrinsic character. The reason which an evil. doer gives for his action when he fathoms his consciousness is, I wished to do it, Statro ratione voitntas. Tho 33 r MORAL PHILOSOPHY. desire itself stands for a reason, and induces him to dis regard the good. This peculiarity of sinful action has been in generial yverlooked by writers on morals, and various objects have )een proposed as the end pursued in all sin A very common but superficial view represents the sI DO' a sinier as choosing evil instead of good; and chi,ceof enL. by evil is intended, in general, unrighteousness, or objective wrong, the performance of which becomes sin or subjective wrong. But evil-doing has itself no attrbations even for the worst of men. The wrong course is pursued in spite of its wickedness, and not for the sake of it. The evil-doer would be glad to avoid the wickedness of his doings, if he could reap the advantages. The world would probabl be traversed in vain to find a man ho consciously sins or the sa e .i an apparent example could be found, it would'e a case where perverted desire is aroused by a zontemplated course of wrong, and the man acts in obedience to that desire. Such cases are sometimes alleged; but they cannot be admitted as examples of sinning for the sake of the sin. It is still more common to represent selfishness as the ,S n not self- fundamental sin; probably because selfish hness. ness seemns, in its nature, so directly opposed to benevolence, and benevolence is virtue. In this view selfishness is defined to mean the choice of one's own good, as the supreme end, while benevolence is the choice of all good. This representation supposes two possible ultimate ends of action-the good of all, the choice of which is benevolence, or virtue, and our own good, th choice of which is selfishness, or sin. The evil- ioer, then, is pursuing, as his supreme end, his 34 WVR(ONG AC'iON (7)rP IN own good. Pursuing this end, he must bring, all his resources into service, and call upon his intelligence to devise ways and means to promote his own highlest hap piness, so far as calculation and wisdom can compass it. He will not sacrifice a greater good in the future to a present indulgence; for tl-his is opposed to his supreme end. HIe will not confine ]iis attention to thlis life, if lhe has anv evidence tlhat there is another life because thus he woul(-l sacrifice his own interests. if hle has reason to believe that the faivor of God has more to do with his welfare than that of any othler being, he will be most iiligent to secure that favor. If he learns that "' honesty is the best policy," and that benevolence, virtue, is the truest source of satisfaction, hle will give liiinself vith all his soul to an honest and virtuous life; and if lie does not do this, it will be because lie is iiioranit of the aet that blessedness cones with virthue Thus, selfislhness must, in the end, annihilate itself. In fact, it is onily fiom ignorance that it can ever exist. It is fiom the beginningff only a blulnder. The truly selfis}l man, in the sense above defined, a man seekling his own highiest good, needs only to learn the good Twllich comes fromn benevolence, and he becomes virtuous at once, because his good requires it. If it be said that hle cannot become virtuous for such a reason, I answer, thein lie cannot seek his own highlest good as his supreme ei(ln, l)ecanlse that end requires hiai to becomne benevolent; and if Ite refuses he relinquishes his end-ceases to pursue his hig,hest good. We have reached the conclusion, then, that it is impossible for a finite moral beilg to purslue his own highlest good, or his own good at; all, Iopossrblity as his supreme end. In such a pursuit lie gardforelt. muist take his intelligence as his gtuide, otherwise he does 35 I MORAL PHILOSOPIIHY. not pursue the end proposed at all; and one of the filst facts which reason offers to him is that benevolence is essential to happiness, and benevolence is the choice of all good as the supreme end. Thus he ceases to pursue his own good as supreme, and relinquishes his end n otbedience to that end itself-a contradiction whiech a inevitable upon the theory that Sill is the pursuit of one's own good. The doctrine is equally at fault when viewed in the Sinner not light of the life and consciousness of the evilpursuing hi on good. doer himself. That lie is not pursuing his own good as his end, is manifest tLpon the slightest consideration. One of the most notorious facts of sin is that it is utterly opposed to the interests of the sinner. In its most promising and successful forms it is confessedly a sacrifice of greater interests to the less. The sinner, in his best estate, aimns at some worldly advantage, and fails of the life to come. lIe seeks some temporary pleasure, and foregoes the higher joys of a virtuous and benevolent life. Even if we conrfine our attention to material, worldly good, the lower forms of satisfaction, we find feiw who have sufficient self-control to surrender an insignificant present enjoyment to a greater future good. " A little sleep, a little slumber, a little fo(lding of the hands to sleep," is the cry of the slutgard, while "his poverty comes as one that travelleth, and his want as an armed man.." We come no nearer the truth to say that the iner I conscious thinks he is pursuing his owin interest_. of the fact. has no such thought. He sees, when_Jl gives attention to his case, as those around him see that he is his ow worst enemy-laiig snaies for his feet.g his own ruin. You would not insult S6 WRONG AeCTION OR SIN. the drunkard by asking him if he follows his best jit dgmnent in reference to hIis own welfare. Your hope of recovering him from the way of death,is in the fact that his own jucldgment condemns his course as ruinous. H1 knows, as no other one can know, that the seeming good w,hich hie pursues is an illusion and a lie, and yet he is lot persuaded to renounce his folly and accept substantial good. If it -)e said that the evil-doer pursues his own good impulsively, not rationally, it is the same as Impulsive to say that he does not pursue his good as pursuit. his inte]ligence apprehends it, but under the guidance of desire and passion. Th-e real thought corresponding with the expression is, that he aims not at his own good at all, but yields to propensity, sacrificing his true interests. If it be said that sin is the choice of self-gratificationi as an end, the doctrine is not materially changed. Self-gratific tion not thae The pursuit of self-gratification as an end must end. put the agent up)on a careful course of inquiry as to the joys within his reach. or that he may hope to attain. Contemplated in this view, the only view in which selfgoratification can be pursued as an end, it is the same as the pursuit of one's own happiness. The sinner sacrifices his own gratification, even as he apprehends it himself, to his appetites and passions. No one has ever doubted that a well-regulated life brings with it more gratification, even of the bodily appetites, than a course of unrestrained passion; yet on every side we find men obliterating, by over-indulgence, the very susceptibility of enjoyment. If they pursued self-gratification as an end, they would act more wisely. It is as difficult to persuade Wien to be considerate and just 37 MORAL PHILOSO.PiHY. toward themselves. as toward God or their fellow men. The only sense in which the sinner lives for himself Caal- mnd- is that he regards not his rational self, but Wr*ess. his psvelychical self, the animal, or rather sen tient nature, made up of the desires and passions. Ilemr he finds his motives to action, and thus lives a life of impulse and not of reason. The name by which Paul designates this state is not selfishness, but carnal-mindednes,8-caring for the flesh, a term which expresses with philosophic accuracy the nature of the action. By the term flesh hle means not merely the bodily appetites, but the aggregate of the desires and passions, of which tlhe bodily appetites are the most conspicuous. Let it not be forgotten that the sin is not in the deNo sin in sires or passions themselves, nor even in their desires. gratification, but in the constant retfusal to accept the good as tie aimn of life. The desires and passions are the motives which induce this refusal. The desires and passions are a part of our constitution, given as by the Creator, but given to be controlled and not to control. We are rational beings, and the truths and realities in view of which we ought to act are presented by the reason. If it be asked, why are these desires given us, since Desires, why they furnish the impulse to sin and are the given. source of all evil, it may be said that theyf are the condition or channel of all good as well as evil Witlhout t]lei we should be as valueless as dead matte]; ,)ir being would be nothing in itself, and usetifl only as t eTle Ivwere other beings endowed with desires who could ise us. It is throlugh the sentient side of our nature thlat all precious things exist to us, and the broader, 38 WRONG ACTION OR SWN. and deeper, and more various these susceptibilities and wants, the higher we stand in the scale of being. If the desiresbe eradicated as the occasion of sin, the pos sibility of virtue ceases at the same time. It is only re quired that we set the limit to our gratifications whicl duty enjoins, sacrificing no good to impulse or desire. 39 CHIAPTER IV. OF PARTIC'ULAR VIRTUES. BIWEVOLENCE, or the willing of good, lies at the foiuInda Benevolence tion of all right mooral character, and con the fouiida-I tion. stitutes it. It animates and characterizes all right mnoral acts. The one fliundamenetal virtue, foiund i,t all vir tuous character, is voluntary iregard for the good of being. Out of this controlling pri-iciple spring, particular rigllt acts, and all the virtues and graces of character. The moral goodness or praiseworthiness lies in that controlling choice. AWVlhile that choice exists, the character is right, worlthy of approbation; and the rightness or worthiness is as co1istant as the governing choice. The forms iii which it may reveal itself depend upon the particular circumstances in which the agent may be placed, and upon his individual constitution or type of culture. These partieuiar manifestations of benevolence are called ri,ht acts. The various states Particularvir- of miniid resulting from benevolence, as mo(i. tues. fied by and blended with the different natu ral affections, take corresponding( names, and constitute the particular virtues. Of this nature are such exercises as love, gratitude, justice, inercy, self-denial, veracity, ihumility, faith, obedience, and othlers like tl)helu. These are all manifestations of benevolence, and all their moral excellence or praisewvorthiness is found in the benevolent choice whlich underlies them. A particular rigltt act is an exhibition of benevoleince arnd filrnishes oasion for approval of the agent; but vve are iiot to OF PARTICULIAR VIRTUES. inpp,se that his moral goodness is all concentrated in these special acts. These are but out-crop- ooodness not limited to the pings of the principle of benevolence, which act constitutes the right character. If there had been no op. portunity for the act, the agent might have been just as virtuous and praiseworthy. The virtue is as constant s the benevolent choice. We praise the patriot soldier who stands bravely in battle; the same patriotism was in him before the battle, and is in another who has no suel occasion for its exhibition. Virtuous character lies bac' of particular virtuous acts. It is the root of the tree, of which the particular developments are the foliage, and flower, and fruit. The particular virtues have different names, not because they differ from each other in the virtuous element involved, but because this element is blended with others which make them differ in consciousness, and in outward form. Love is a term employed to designate a particular virtue. It is also used to express the common Love as a virelement of all the virtues, and in this sense tue. it is synonymous with benevolence. This is the use of the term in the Scriptures, where it is represented as the fulfilling, or content, of the law-all that the law requires towards God and towards men, the good and the bad. As a particular virtue, love is benevolence blended with and working through the natural affection which bears the same name. In the different relations the modifying affection varies, and the love is called parental, filial, or social. The natu.'al affection may exist without he benevolence to control and regulate it. It is still called love, but it is no longer virtue. Benevo- L.ove of com. lent affection exercised towards the good, is llacerjy. attended with approbation of the character of the olobject 41 IMORAL PHILOSOPHY. and hence is called love of complacency. This is the formi which love takes when exercised towards God, because the contemplation of God's character affords satisfaction. The perception of the worthiness is intellectual, the resulting satisfaction is emotional; the benevo'eiice is still the voluntary and virtuous element. The oomplacenev without the benevolence is not virtuous. Love to enemies and to the wicked is benevolence accompanied by disapprobation of the character, or displacency. There may be less of enjoyment in the immediate exercise, but it is still as high a manifestation of virtue as any other. In all its varieties, love is virtuous in so far as it is benevolent, and no farther. Gratitude admits of a similar analysis. As a virtue it Gratitudeasa is benevolence toward a benefactor. We have virtue. also the perception of a benefit received, pleasure or satisfaction in view of it, and an impulse to requite the benefit. The emotional and impulsive action, without the benevolence, is still called gratitude, but it is not virtuous. It is a common experience of the good and .he bad. Justice as a virtue is but another name for benevolence utice. dealing with the interests and deserts of men. There is an impulse to treat every interest according to its value, and every person according to his deserts, and there is satisfaction in witnessing such a result. This characteristic of our nature is often called the principle of justice; but it becomes the virtue of justice when benevolence enters in to regulate and limit it. What is called justice becomes sin when it goes beyond the linmits which benevolence appoints. To se eure to a moral being his deserts, is a virtuous act when benevolence requires it;'t is a sinful act when a proper -i 2 OF PARTICULAR VIRTUE8. regard for all good forbids. To pardon a sinner is duty when the common good permits. The final appeal is to this standard, and justice becomes virtue by being be nevolence. The only just man is the man who regards all good for its value and according to its value. It is common with writers on morale to represent jus tice as an independent virtue, distinct from Not an Inde pendent virand even opposed to benevolence; yet no tue. definition of justice as a virtue can be given which does not imply benevolence, and no rule of action in accordance with justice can be given which does not find its limitations in benevolence. Dugald Stewart, after strenuously rejecting the idea that benevolence is the substance of all virtue, defines justice as "that disposition which leads us, in cases where our own temper, or passions, or interests are concerned, to determine and to act without being biased by partial considerations." What is this but a definition of benevolence-a disposition to treat every good and every interest according to its value? Even the popular definition of justice, as "the rirtue which consists in giving to every one what is his Jue," involves the same limitations. What is his due is determined, not by any abstract rule of desert, but by a eareful comparison and adjustment of interests according to their value. Justice, then, is not an independent virtue, but is an exercise of benevolence in certain relations and with'certain modifying affections. The term justice often has an objective sense, indicating not the virtue, nor any disposition whatever, but what is outwardly right between man and man; and this outward justice finds its authority and its limitations in the common good. We have a perception of the deserts of men, and, in an inexact way, often speak of these as the ground and nea, 43 MORAL PIIILOSOPHY. sure of justice in their case. It is true that these deserts are significant facts, and are to be made account of in the estimate of what the common good requires or permits, out they are not the standard of justice. It is not always unjust to treat men better than they deserve, or even worse at times. Justice as a mere sentiment is blind to everything but desert; justice as a virtue has an eye for every interest. Mercy is compassion exercised towards the undeserv ing, limited by regard for the general good. Mercy. ercy. It is benevolence saving offenders from deserved retribution; without the limitation of benevolence it is culpable weakness, not a virtue. We naturally pity the miserable; when guilt is combined with the misery, our pity becomes mercy-a mere sentiment, emotional and impulsive; when benevolencepermeates and limits, and controls the sentiment, it is the virtue of mercy. Mercy is a necessary product of benevolenIce; for benevolence is the willing of good to all, to the good and the bad alike-not the actual effort to do good to all, but a readiness, a disposition to it-an actual effort to secure it when the general good will permit. Asvirtues, mercy and justice can never be antagonistic, Mercy and because they have their ground in the comnmoi justice not opposed. principle of benevolence; as sentiments or impulses, the one may counteract or exclude the other. To settle their limits and applications in outward life is just as difficult as to determine what benevolence requires, and no more so. This is the only test-the final appeal. Self-denial is benevolence holding in subjection the s —eneal. desires and passions, and putting personal in terest in its proper place-a readiness to fore go self-indulgence at the bidding of benevolence. In 44 OF PARTICULAR VIRTUES. reality, it is not the sacrifice of any interest of our own It is the only way in which real interests can be se cored. Moral beings will always prove the truth of the goispel paradox: hlie that will save shall lose, and he that will lose shall save. The denial of one desire at the bidding of another is not self-denial. It may involve all the pain, or even more, but it does not bring the satisfaction of virtuous self-denial. Veracity is benevolence exercised in communicating impressions of facts to our fellow-men. Truthfulness in communication from any other Veracity. than a benevolent motive is not the virtue of veracity. It may be sentimental, impulsive veracity, resulting from the instinctive admiration of truthfulness existing in every mind. To speak the truth for the sake of the truth, if there be any thought corresponding with the expression, must be to yield to this sentiment as an inipulse. The truth in itself is nothing; it is merely in strumental. The final value is in moral beings, whom it serves. Humility is not a depreciative judgment of ourselves, nor a feeling of depression in view of any Humility. personal disadvantages; it is benevolence exercised in conceding precedence to others, and in accepting cheerfully the place which falls to us. The sentimnent of humility, as distinguished from the virtue, is a trait of character natural to some, having its basis in the emotional constitution. Faith is a benevolent attitude of mind acceyting the edence of facts, and bestowing confidence upon the pessons to whom it is due. The in- Faith tellectual element is a convictiol of the truth to be ac cet)ted, and of the fidelity of the persons who are the ob 45 MORAL PHILOSOPHTY. jects of faith. The moral element is the benevolent at titude of mind which disposes to the acceptance of this evilence, and to the treatment of the truth as true, and of thie p)erson as trustworthy. The emotional element is tile peace, and rest, and satisfaction which flow from cr follow this acceptance of evidence and bestowment of confidence. Each of these distinct exercises is sometimes called faith, especially the intellectual and emotional; but the virtuousness of faith lies in the right voluntary state which yields to evidence, and accepts a well founded claim to confidence. No degree of mere convic tion is virtuous faith, nor of emotion in view of the con viction. " The devils believe and tremble." The excellence of faith is not so much in a right belief, as in the state of mind which leads to right belief. That state of mind is benevolence. The idea is somewhat prevalent that reason and faith are opposed to each other, and that we leave reason when we take faith as our principle. Faith depends on reason,in the sense that we can accept as true only what comes with evidence addressed tc reason. We have faith in God, because we have reason to believe him trustworthy; and from him we accept revelations beyond, but not opposed to reason. Faith without evidence is presumption, not faith. Obedience is a benevolent submission to authority. Submission for any other reason, for safety Obedience. or from a sense of the power or superiority ,f the ruler, is not a virtue. These considerations are ,ften involved in virtuous obedience, and are not incon. sistent with it. They are involved, too, in the cowardly submission of one whose heart is opposed to the anu. thority, and destitute of any trace of loyalty or duty. If it be said that submission because it is right is obedi 46 OFl PARTICULAR VIRTUES.. ence, the definition is correct, but the analysis is ineom. plete. WThat is right is what is obligatory; and what is obligatory,is determined by the interests involved —the good of being. Let it appear that these interests ale not promoted by submission, and all sense of obligation is lost Thus the virtuous element of obedience is benevolence. All virtuous exercises admit of a similar analysis. Whierever benevolence is found, there is vir- This analysis sustained by tue, praiseworthiness, the fuilfilment of obli- Scripture. gation; where this is wanting, there may be amiable sentiment and comely outward action, but there is no virtue. This view accords so fully with the doctrine of the Scriptures that it is remarkable that any other has had sway among Christian moralists. The doctrine is so distinctly announced that a passing reference will suffice. The Saviour distinctly presents love to God and man as the sole requirement of the law. There can be no doubt as to the nature of this love when we remember that he represents it as due to God and to man, to the evil as to the good, to enemies as to friends. The love which is due to all beings, irrespective of character and relations, can only be benevolence, the willing of good to all. Paul, in announcing that love is the fulfilling of the law, enumerates the leading precepts of the deca logue, and lest something should be omitted, lie adds, "and if there be any other commandment, it is briefly comprehended in this saying, namely,'thou shalt lovo thy neighbor as thyself;"' and in a chapter of marvel bus beauty and power, he proclaims the emptiness of 11 high-sounding virtues and showy deeds without harity, love, benevolence. If any doctrine is clearly tauglit in Scripture, it Mould seem to be that bene volence is the sum of duty. 47 MO., AL PIILOSOPHIY. Bitt let it be remelmbered that the love wlhchl fiilfil1 3enrevolence the law is an active voluntary state, and not not mere mnotion. a mere emnotion. It may co-exist with al the emotions that are natural to man, and prompt to al! the deeds promnotive of well-being. It is not mere ten e,i-lieartedness, good nature, kindly feeling, a weak dispi)JsitioI to make everybody comfortable. IBenevolence is alive to every interest discriminating, earnest conii rgeo-us. It is gentle or stern, forb. orindinant, as the occasion may require. Those writers, as Butler, Msapprehen- Stewart, Cousin, 3JeCosh, and others, who siolns of benevolence. discard the doctrine that benevolence is the whole of virtue, seem to treat it as emotional rather than intelligent and voluntary. Says Archibald Alexander, "'If a judge should feel a stro)ng benevolence towards all criminals, so as to avoid inflicting on them the penalty ,f the wholesome laws of the country, we should judge )t wicked." hence he concludes not only that benevolence is not the whole of virtue, but that it is not alwvavs virtuous. It is not nece,ary to say that the benevolence of which he speaks is a mere sentiment, and is not embraced in the definition of benevolence which we have given. It is no more benevolence than wrath or jealousy, or the other malignant passions. The benevolent mnai cannot intentionally sacrifice the good of the community to his reluctance to inflict pain on a criminal. Such action is in direct conflict with his principle-regard to th good of all on account of its value. The doctrine of the old philosophers, that he that h:L The ancient one virtue has all the virtues, proves true i jocte. a very important sense. Every genuine vir. tue ilas benevolence as its foundation; and benevolence is the germ and root of all the virtues. In time, with ts OF PARTICULAR VIRTUES. lavoring circumstances and culture, they must appear. The genuine viritues are not independent of each other. They are all special exhibitions of benevolence, and each in a sense implies the other; not in its outward form, but in its principle and root. We do not find the benevo lent all alike in their exhibitions of character. Th,ey are alike in their principle of action, but the outward life varies with individual constitutions, with varying light and circumstances. Benevolence is often fettered by a poor judgment and a very imperfect constitution, and its exhibitions become greatly distorted by the crude media through which they must struggle. a 49 CfHAPTER V. Of PARTICULAR VICES-NATURAL OR IMPULSIVE GOODNE'& I so far assin presents unity of character it lies in the refusal to regard the well-being of all Unity of sin. and give it its proper Dlace. This constitutes thile wickedness of aiI sinful action; and in this respect it is, as it should be, the contradictory of benevolence. Where this rejection of the good as the end of life exists, there is sin -the violation of obligation, whatever mnay be the outward action. The evil-doing is as continuous as this attitude of will, . and particular vicious acts are but the outIts continuity. croppings of the sinful character. The par. ticular exhibition gives occasion for our disapproval and condemnation; and it is not unnatural to direct our attention to these acts as involving all that is blameworthy in the character. But the vicious attitude of will existed before that action, and may remain afterwards. Occasior may be wanting for the exhibition of the vicious princi ple, the persistent voluntary state of refiusal to choose the good; yet the man is sinful, blameworthy, and will surely act unrighlteously, when the time for action comes The outward wrong action takes its particular name farticiai and character firom the desire which pro vicees. ces. dominates, and which prompts to the action, or from the particular relations in which the act is performed, or from the outward form of the action. In such a principle and motive originate all the vices whlich deform character and injure society, as sensuality, amnbi OF PARTICULAR VICES. tion, avarice, pride, selfishness, envy, and the like, differ ent in the desire which controls, and in the outward form of the action, but alike in the element of blame worthiness, the exclusion of benevolence. Sensuality is a subjection of the will to the bodily app; tite. These solicit to gratification, an d fur- Sensuality nish the motive to loathsome vices which so degrade men. The wrong is not in the appetites; they belong to our constitution, implanted by the Creator. They are as innocent as our most elevated tastes and susceptibilities, and perhaps are even more necessary and useful. Their gratification is not a sin, as long as no good is sacrificed. The sin consists in giving these the rein, subjecting the will to their control, instead of holding it subservient to the good. Ambition results from the surrender of the will to tle desire of power, of control of men. The de- Ambition sire is doubtless constitutional, belongs to us by creation, and has its purpose to serve; but to allow the desire to control and turn us from the path of duty of benevolence, is the sin of ambition. We often hear of a laudable ambition. It must consist in the purpose to secure position and power for the furtherance of worthy ends. Avarice results from the love of wealth as the predominant desire. The desire exists in all men, but in the avaricious man it becomes the controlling motive. When the desire terminates directly on the wealth, and finds its satisfaction in the mere possession, the man is a miser. If he conterAIates the enjoyment which the wealth may purchase, he is still ava. ricious; but the avarice iscombined with another passion, as the love of pleasure, or distinction, or independence 51 MORAL PHILOSOPHIY. Properly controlled and directed, the desire of wealth ii a wholesome impulse. Pride is subjection of the will to the desire of eleva ride and tion or distinction, and implies dissatisfaction aity. in occupying one's proper place, an unwillingne. to be regarded according to one's worth. If the Usioli be attended, as it often is, by an over-estimate of )ne's accomplishments or advantages, it takes the form of vanity. If it exist in connection with a low estimate of one's self, it becomes mortified pride; it is still not humility. WVe often hear that a degree of pride is necessary to a well-balanced character; of course a proper self-respect must be intended. Selfishness, as a special vice, is subjection of the will Selfihne to the desire of good, involving an over-esti8efishhess. ~,novn noe-si mnate of one's own importance and a disregard of the equal rights of others. When good is to be distributed, benevolence asks only its proper share. Selfishness craves more, is greedy of good, and careless of others. This is the vice in its popular sense. Theological writers often use the term as expressing the opposite of benevolence, or the essence of all sin, an unfortunate use of the word, as we have seen, and implying a state of facts which does not exist. Thus we may pass over the entire catalogue of the deThe desire sires and find a. form of sin corresponding not sin. with each. The sin, as we have seen, does not lie in the desire, nor in its gratification, but in the voluntary refiusal to regard the good, under the impulse of "he desire or passion Even if the desire be artificial, created by self-indulgence and sin, as the love of strong drink, still the sin is not in the desire, but in allowing it sway. Tlhe highest forms of virtue are sometimes ex 52 NATURTAL OR DI'IULSIVE GOODNESS. hibited in connection with aggravated or perverted pat sions. To nurse or foster a passion, even without iiidulgence of it in outward form, implies sin, a latent spirit of self-indulgence. The malevolent impulses, in so far as they are merely emotional, come under the same principle as Malevoleni the amiable ones. Wrathi, indignation, re- impulses. sentment are not sinful in themselves. They have their place in human nature-probably in every moral nature. and imply sin only as they control the action and deter mine the will to the disregard of duty. Like all the impulses, they are to be controlled. They present, like the desires, temptations to sin, but temptation is not sin. We have considered the two forms of moral action, benevolence and its opposite, and have seen that Only two charactersi all moral goodness, virtue, lies in benevo- cpossraibctle.r lence, and all sin in the refusal to be benevolent. Nc third attitude, no neutral position,is possible to a moral being. To regard the good,and not to regard it, are the only conceivable positions; and not to regard the good is, in a moral being, to refuse to regard it. But there is much moral action, or action of moral beings, that is proper, amiable, and useful too, Apparent thatit is sometimes difficult to classify. It has goodness. the aspect of virtuous action, but lacks the vital elemnent. The action may lie entirely out of the range of morality, in the necessary movements of our nature, or it may be merely impulsive. We find in all men right and proper judgments on moral questions, a clear discernment, and Right judg more or less accurate expression of propriety ments. and duty. But these judgments are wholly intellectual, not at our control, and therefore have no moral char 59 lMORAL PHILOSOPHY. acter. A perception of the first principles of morality is essential to moral agency; it is provided for in our constitution, and is as inevitable as the perception of the axioms of iiiathematics. This element in our nature Is a DOo(l, elevates us in the scale of being, but does not make us virtuous. Closely allied to this is the moral approbation of right NfMoral approv- doing, of right character, of God, and of good al and disapproval. men, and disapprobation of wron- in act aind character. This exercise is constitutional, not voluntary. To approve and admire virtue is not to practic't and to condemn the wrong is not to abstain from it. " leliora video proboque, deteriora sequor." see the right and I approve it too, Condemn the wrong and still the wrong pursue." ,However low a moral beinog may sink, there must re, anin. while moral agency survives, the approbation of virtue and the disapprobation of vice. A eal to a mr-al bein, in beafof rigiteo usness always finds a response in thee judgment, if not in the Will. But that resdonse i=-wi response is not virtue, it is the involutmar testimo ny of his nature in favor of virtue. In connection with these judgments in favor of the ~iation right and against the wrong, there arises an Aspimtlon ri n d for virte. aspiration, an impulse, more or less distinct, towards the attainment of right character, a desire for it as the hiighest excellence, the essential condition of one's own approbation and that of others. Not only virtue in its general fIrmn, but each of the particular virtues and every virtuous act, excites admiration and desire, an inlmulse called by Lord Kames the sympathetic emotion of virtue, which prompts to the attainment of a like character. But to desi re tb eitou ot to so 64 NATURAL OR IMPLLSIVE GOODNESS. A sinful life may repress and ob,cure this desire, but probably never obliterates it. There are, again, inr. every human being, kindly affee tions and sentiments, the social sympathies Kindly affe belonging to human nature, which afford a tions. foundation for the various relations of life, and make society pleasant and desirable. There are natural gifts and graces which adorn the character, beautifil and good, but no more virtuous than the beauties olf a gem or a flower. There are simiilar instincts even in animals of a lower order. A virtuous life best improves and displays these natural gifts, and sin may dwarf and perhaps obliterate some of them, while others are vigorous even in connection with the grossest degradation. They make our nature a good, but do not constitute it virtuous. In the contemplation of God, of his greatness and goodness, pious and devotional feelings arise Devotional awe, reverence, admiration, gratitude, an in- sentiments. stinctive tribute of our nature to its author. These natural sentiments of piety constitute man a religious being, not a virtuous being- religious in the sense that provisio I is mnade in his nature for worship, devotion. Even witl out a right heart hie feels the propriety, and in some sencm the need of worship. These sentiments are traces of God's handiwork, and indicate the style of life which is appropriate to man. Vitalized and sustaino d by genlme goodness, they characterize the trulyv pious m nan, and in such circumstances are best illustrateod; but they exist in every cultivated mind, even without virtu3 and are nol wholly wanting in the rudest savages. The sentiment of devotion is nearly related to the poetic in our constitu tion, and hence has become in modern times an important element, even in our lighter literature Some of our sa 55 MORAL PHILOSOPh Y. cred lyrics, beautiful expressions of pious feeling, have been furnished by writers who can scarcely be supposed to have an experience of devotion, except in its poetic and sentimental forms. Such feelings are beautiful and wor thy of cultivation, but they are not necessarily virtuous exercises. Thus every recognized virtue finds in human nature X Impulsive vir- corresponding desire or impulse, and froim tues. these, as from other impulses, there results impulsive action in the direction of all these virtues, producimg natural loveliness, many beautiful acts and graces of character, all the social virtues in their external emotional forms. As examples of these we have generosity springing from a desire to gratify others; charity, works of beneficence, from the impulse of pity for the suffering, as in the case of Goldsmith, who would give his coat to a beggar in the street; philanthropy, as of Lord Byron in his sentimental devotion to the interests of Greece; patriotism, which has led multitudes to count it sweet to die for their country; friendship involving personal affection, and furnishing beautiful exhibitions of unselfishness, and, most striking of all in the self-sacrifice involved, parental affection, maternal love, sometimes called the holiest of human exercises; but if it be merely instinctive or impulsive, it is no holier than the sunlight or the shower. Even ill the vile and degraded it is exhibited as an intense passion. The virtuous element of benevolence flowing thro hthis chanr l of maternal love beautifies it and ives consisteucand wisdom.. Without this elemen parental affection often Os 1t5-weakness by thwarting what would seem to be its own proper ends. Of the same general character is the integrity which flows from the admiration of justice, or from the maxim that honesty is the best policy; 56 I NATURAL OR LIMPULSIVE, G(I)T)NESS. also the obtrusive and pretentious virtues which spring from a sense of honor, as it is called; a principle too ca pricious to be depended on, and determined in general by what is considered respectable in a particular circle. For every genuine virtue there is a corresponding fac titious virtue, involving the external form Relaticnto and some of the emotions of the genuine, true virue.s but lacking in the element of benevolence, which alone gives virtue to action. It is not, in general, true that these virtues are counterfeited-assumed intentionally tbr the accomplishment of an end, as the attainment of respectability, or the advancement of worldly interest in other forms. They are superficial, impulsive, but not hypocritical. The man acts as he feels, and because of his feeling; and when his feeling changes, the action changes. Itfere lies the deficiency. The true principle and reason of action is higher than feeling. The feeling enriches and beautifies the action, but should not govern it. There is mnueh apparent goodness that is imitativea reflection of what is genuine; but even Imitative here the goodness is not affected-put on goodness merely as a fashion; the emotions which produce the ae, tion are communicated-propagated by natural sympathy, and thus some particular form of goodness becomes contagious. Religious or philanthropic sentiments pervade a community, and the corresponding virtues become epidemic. The affection is not a dangerous one, blt gennine goodness is not so easily propagated. The tide of feeling changes, and you look in vain for the luxuriant harvest of good which was promised. "It has no root in itself; and so endureth but for a time." In other cases the feeling is permanent, groundel in the constitution, and the impulsive action is equally permanent. 8* 57 MORAL PHEILOSOPHY. These instinctive Nvirtues are seen to lack genuIlineness (rn)live vr l the fact that they are often partial, liav3 r,I'mlslive vi.r tue partial. arbitrary limitations such as are imposed by feeling, not reason. They often co-exist with the clear est failures in morality, in other directions. A pirate nmay exhibit a chivalrous honor among hlis associates, mav evel be a tender father and a faithful friend; yet his ]i1e is a war upon manLind. BIyron encountered dan ger and met deathl in his romant interest fo ireece, yet iris p ivaite life was too deeply stained witli t o atl low e- eni a hope that hit's virtues wee rel. aLe iust be a v e.-.-i and abandon ed man r },.ras o ro ret form ot 4 -O to ritlate the senseci i(,l 0ef t The man who has cast off all ta ou -it od dty or ioaty to God comforts himself uponII his fidelity to man; yet genuin duty admits no such limiitations A change of circumstances or of locality and surroundottransport- ings, sometimes proves fatal to the imrpulsive ible virtues. It has long been a proverb that "1Englishmen going to India, leave their religion at the Cape;" and it was often remarked, before the rebellion, that ~New England morality, emigrating to the Southwest, rariely survived the passage of Vieksburg. True viirtue will bear transportation. 3By, such weaknesses and failures the factitious virtues betray themselves. But is this natural, impulsive goodness sinful? Are not persons better for the possession of these qualities? r, ionever the motive,.ot sinful, nor is th i mot-o,ni Whie1t p'....npt and attends the ation; but the heart wmItirvohgh er otih"" an feeling, is destitute of'ade__, t a lic iovi-ern- by lirpulse rathe- than the princi)]e of benevole nce is a 58 NATURAL OR IMPULSIVE GOODNESS. tful life. The man would be worse if divested of these natural graces of character-less hopeful in himself more injurious to society. ITnpulsive goodness i~ a rosl good, of use in the world. It helps to make up the general public sentiment, which in Christian countries favor8 virtue. The genuine goodness, even of a few, operates beyond these few, upon the feelings ancl acts of the corn Iunity, moulding the secrtiment anlc the outward life, and finally, in many cases, establishing itself in the heart. Thus virtue finlds in the feelings and sympathies of men, as well as in their convictions; a suiport which evil must always lack. Vice, as such, is always repulsive, and finds no sympathy in the human soul. 59 CHAPTER VI. ADDITIONAL REMARKS AND INFERENCES. THE law of benevolence is the universal law. In the Un.versal ty nature of the case it extends to all moral be of the law. ings and covers all their moral action. The apprehension of good and the power of choice are the sole conditions of obligation. Obligation, then, is as wide-spread and as permanent as moral existence-the obligation of benevolence; and all moral goodness, al] that is praiseworthy in character, consists in meeting obligation, in being benevolent. Where there is no obligation, there can be no goodness. The law of benevolence extends to God as well as to his creatures, and he is good because he meets the obligation. "God is love," because his entire character is conformed to the requirements of benevolence. This is the holiness of God as a moral attribute; of holiness in essence or being, as distinguished from holiness in character, we can have no conception There is no thought answering to the words. Works of supererogation are impossible to a moral beEupereroga- ing-the performance of more than dutytio-n impoissit1e. Obligation keeps pace with ability. "A that knoweth to do good and doeth tnoti to him itis si' There can be no meritorious works that are iiot obligatory. No being, divine or human, can ever do mnore than duty, because he can never transcend ability. The obligation of each moment is measured by the abil ity of each moment; hence the failure at one point can never be cancelled by the surplusgoodness at another. Nol ADDITIONAL REMARKS AND INFERENC-E,S. has one moral being an excess of virtue, to meet the deficiencies of another. Moral acts and moral character are personal-insepar able from the being to whom they originally Morality per pertain. Each moral being is responsible r sonal. .his own character an that resp onsibility can in no ma merbe transferred to another. Each man is praiseworthy fbr his good deeds, and blameworthy for his bad deeds. The good deeds may have been induced ill him by the influence of another; but they are still his deeds, and he is praiseworthy on account of them. So the bad deeds mlay be occasioned by temptations proceeding from another, but the blameworthiness goes with the deeds. The promoter of virtue in the one case, and the tempter in the other, have their own responsibilities. Each moral agent is the responsible cause of his own deeds and character, both good and bad, whatever the ooeasimo of the deeds may have been. Hence moral character can never be transferred. It belongs inevitably to the subject of it, and Character not must arise, in every case, from free voluntary transferable. action Guilt, in the sense of ill-desert, cannot be communicated~ from one to another by imputation, or by natural generation, as from parent to child, or by any device whatever. It must come into existence by the free action of its subject. Infirmities of constitution, tendencies to wrong action, temptations, may be transmitted; and these may lead to a reproduction of sin in the child, like that which existed in the parent. Hience, in a loose and popular sense the sin is said to be transmitted; oI one may be involved in the consequences of another'a acts and thus be said to share his sin; but in strict thou1ght and expression, sin belongs only to the agent 61 MORAL PHTLOSOPHTY. who commits it, and cannot be transferred. The same principle applies equally to virtue. The ambiguity of the word c/taracter sometimes'eads Character, to confusion of thought and expression. In different senses. the most general sense, character embraces all that belongs to the soul-its combination of powers, and susceptibilities, and tendencies, as well as the result of these in moral condition and action. In this sense, character is doubtless transmitted from parent to child. In a stricter sense character is limited to the moral state or action, and the limitation is usually e-xresed by the epithet moral. But the term moral character has a three fold use: frst, to indicate the present momentary moral state, the inimmediate condition of the soul in respect to virtue and sin; secondly, with a retrospective view involving the element of time, to express the aggregate of moral action-thie accumulated merit or demerit of all the mnoral life; and thirclIy, to express the prevailing or predominant moral condition, determined by the average of moral action during a period of time sufficient to afford an indication. Moral character in all these senses is strictly personal and intransmissible. The seat of moral depravity is in the will-moral deseat orde- pravity being sin. The sin consists in the pmvity. voluntary refusal to respect the good. The intellect and sensibility cannot be morally depraved; there is no sin in them. They may be diseased and perverted, and these corruptions may become occasions of sin. But in all moral beings, depraved or undepraved, the sensiblility must, fromn its very nature, operate as an inmpulse to self-indulgence. To resist this impulse, from a regard to good, is virtue; to yield to it and neglect the good,'s sin Tlhe idea of a sensibility in harmony with 52 ADDI'IONAL REMARKS AND lIN'ERExNCES. irtue, so that to follow its impulses will be vilrtuous ac tion, involves a contradiction. To follow an impulse of the feeling because we judge it, under the circumstance our best guide, is not to be governed by feeling. Total moral depravity oughlt to mean the entire absence of the choice of good on its own ac- Total depmvcount-the entire commitment of the will to ity. the desires and passions, as the motive of action. In this sense only is total depravity predicable of any moral being. All this is compatible with much that is correct in the moral judgment, and much that is pleasant and amiable in emotion and action. it is true that sin tends to pervert the nature, to obscure the tjudgnenrt, and to corrupt the desires; but until moral agency is utterly subverted, and the man ceases to be accountable, he can judge correctly of his own duty and that of others, he approves virtue and condemns sin. The moral change required in every sinner is to cease to do evil and learn to do well; a change Change re. from subjection to desire and impulse, to the quired. choice of good for its own sake, a change not in nature, but in moral character and action. This is the point in which the sinner is wrong, and by such a change only can he become right. Other changes may be desilrable; this is obligatory. It is obligatory because it is voluntary, hence, always possible. The change muist inrovae the sinner's own action, for the sin is his, and tl e vi'tuie is his. Every moral agent has in his own tlhol,glut ,'on,siderations which ought to induce the change; but Qilch are the fascinations of sin, that men do not surrender it wittiout l)owerful influence from without, persuading, not compelling. It is not power, but persuasion, that is brouglht to bear. In no other manner can Omnipotence I J 63 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. itself secure right moral action. Neither'virtue nor sib can be imposed by any extraneous force, however great, A change in moral character is not the work of power but of motive. Intensity of emotion in connection with any mora, Emotion and state or act is not the test of its character, or Character. the measure ofitsdesert. The emotion varies with varying circumstances, with thie object of immediate attention; the moral state is as constant as the attitude of the will. The emotion is sometimes an indication of the moral state, more or less reliable. A man's fidelity to his family is not determined at any time by the intensity of his emotional affection. He may be so absorbed with his duty, that the thought which excites emotion may be impossible to him; and when the emotion arises, it may be, in some circumstances, not a help to his duty, but a hindrance-a temptation to drop the duty and give himself to the enjoyment of the society of his family. The emotional affection has an import ant office, and constitutes much of the value of the so cial relations, but neither its presence nor its absence de telrines the question of fidelity to duty. The nzalic prepense which constitutes crime does not necessarily in volve the emotion of hatred; it expresses only the ante cedent purpose to do the deed. The highway robber feels no emotion of hatred towards his victim, but he ihas a definite intention to perpetrate the crime; it is of the slightest importance what his emotions may be. The ultimate governing choice, that which determines Ultimate moral character, is often less distinct in con choice in consciousness. sciousness than accompanying emotions, and executive purposes and volitions. It underlies all ot,hei exercises, is transparent and intangible, so to speak, axd 64 ADDITIONAL EMfARKS AND INFERENCES. bence often escapes our direct scrutiny. It reveals itself in the current of life which it directs, and in the general tone of thought, and feeling, and action; but what is called self examination frequently occupies itself with thoughts and feelings, and fails to reach the seat of character. Direct, immediate observation of one's own moral state is difficult to attain; and often the examination which results in strong confidence is quite superficial. Genuine honesty of heart must in the end bring satisfaction. Moral consistency is persistence in the benevolent choice-regard to good as good. The expres- MoralcolsiSt sion of that choice will vary with varying ency. light and other conditions. Benevolence may require us to do to-morrow what we cannot do to-day; because our views of duty and our circumstances may change, exposing us, perhaps, to the charge of fickleness. Outward consistency has its value, but is only proximately attainable to finite beings. Moral consistency is essen tial; it is the genuine jewel. 65r CIIAPTER VII. .U43HT AND WRONG —DUTY, KNOWN AND UN KNOWN —NEBD OF A REVELATION. THERE is an ambiguity in the use of the terms right Abs,lite and and wrong, which tends to confusion. Berelative right and wrong. nevolence, a regard for sentient being, is right in its own nature, witlout any condition or limita, tion, and always implies virtue in the exercise. This may be called absolute right. Tile refusal to be benevolent is absolute wrong. No contingency, possible or sBvpposable,can make it otherwise in fact or in appearanqe. On the other hand, all executive action is conteinplated in its relation to benevolence, and is called right or wrong according, as it is or is not the form in which benevolence expresses itself. That action which tends to promote the good is ri,ght action, and will be performed by virtuous, intelligent men. This may be called the relative right, to distinguish it from benevolence, whith is the absolute right. Execitive action wlicd is opposed Lo the good is wTrong, and, as distinguishled from wrong in ultimate intention, it may be called relative wrong. Relative ri,ght and wrong are known, not by their intrinsic character, like benevolence and its opposite, but by their relation or tendency. There is anothler ambiguity in the use of the terms Objective ande right and wrong, in reference to which dissubjective righlt&wrong. crimination is even more i important. Execu. tire action, considered apart fnom the agent, simply in RIGHT AND WRONG. its bearing upon the good of sentient being, is called right or wrong, according to its tendency. This is objective righttor objective wrong. Again, an act is contemplated in its relation to the agent, and is called right when, witl] his particular views and convictions, it ought to be done; and wrong when, uinder these circumstances, it ought not to be done. A right act,in this latter sense, involves a right ultimate intention or choice onil the part of the agent; and a wrong act, a wrong intention; all, without reference to the act in its outward or objective character. This is subjective right, or subjective wrong. The fact really contemplated in this view is the moral state of the ag,ent, his rightness or wrongness. To illustrate: a physician gives a proper remedy, one tending to good. The act is objectively right; Differentcorn. it ought to be done. If he had a proper in- binations. tention, the act is subjectively right; he is virtuous in the doing of it. Again, he gives a poison, tending to evil; the act is objectively wrong; in general ought not to be done. If he intends harm in the act, it is subjectively wrong; ie incurs guilt. He gives a proper remedy, thinking it a poison and intending mischief; the act is objectively right and subjectively wrong. Jle gives a poison by mistake, with an honest intention; the act is )l),jectively wrong and subjectively right. All these diie'rent combinations of right and wrong in action are possible and act,ual. The character of the agent depends upon the act subjectively considered, and not upon its ob,jective character. Wrong done proves a wrong doer, a sinner only when the wrong is subjective, or involves the wrong intention. It would seem desirable to limit the use of the terims right ard wrong to acts viewed objectively, and to ex 67 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. press subjective relations by the terms virtuous and sinful, securing thus not only distinctness of expression, but clearness of thought as well. An act is sometimes spoken of as right or wrong per Right and se-in itself. If anything is involved in wrong r,per. this expression beyond the objective character of the act, it ought to mean that the performnance of an act right per se, necessarily implies virtue; and of an act wrong per se, sin. This seems to be the sense intended by many writers. Thus we hear the question, is slaveholding wrong per se? If the question be answered affirmatively, the conclusion follows that every slavehliolder is a sinner. But to justify this conclusion, such a definition must be given to slaveholding as to involve inevitably the wicked intention, e. g., the holding of a man as property without any respect to his well-being. Thus every slaveholder is a sinner; but those who sustain the legal relation without such heartlessness are not slaveholders. If the definition be so extended as to include these, then slaveholdingisnotwrongperse. The answer to such a question must turn upon a definition, and the definition once settled, all discussion of the question is at an endcl. Is slaveholding wrong? is the natural and proper question for discussion. Then the enquiry is in reference to the objective character of the action, whether on the whole it tends to evil. If this be settled affirmatively, then one who sustains the relation can escape condemnation only by showing that in his ease the wicked intention does not exist. He mlust be justified on the ground of his ignorance. No definition of any merely outward act or relation can be given, such as to exclude one involved in it from this defence In order to suchl exclusion, subjective wickedness niast be Ss DUTY1. KNOWN AND TUNKNOWN. expressed ir the definition. Murder is wrong Ever e, because it iimpiies a wicked purpose, and the only justi. fication is to prove that one is not a murderer. Ilomieide is not wrong per se, because it may be acci(ldeital or justifiable; stealing is wrong perse, because the nameexpressesthedishonest intention; taking the property of another without his knowledge or consent, is not wrong per se, because it is not always stealing. Benevolence alone is right per se; the refusal to be benevolent is wrong per 8e. A distinction is often made between the expedient and the right. The truly expedient must be Ex.edien.t that which, on the whole, is promotive of anright. good. In this sense it is identical with the objective right. The final test of the objective right is its bearing upon good, well-being; we have no other means of knowing it. Hence, aside from the positive command of God, which rarely enjoins particular acts, we must determine outward duty by enquiring what, on the whole, is expedient, or promotive of the good; we have no other guide. In reference to the right state of heart, the inward duty, we are not dependent upon any such enquiry. The duty of benevolence is universal, absolute, not limited or determined by any consequences whatever. The term expedient is sometimes used in a limited sense, as that which is temporarily or partially profitable-conducive to the immediate advantage of an individual, a party, or clique, out mischievous on the whole. In this sense it is not a guide to outward ditty and it is justly a reproach to be governed by it in action It is urged by some that finite beings can never know xith certainty what is expedient on the DifficltyW whole, and hence must have some other guide. kowing. ob MORAL PHIILOSOPHY. It is true that the knowledge of the expedient is never absolute, but it is just as sure as the knowledge of the outwardly right. The only absolute knowledge of the right which finite beings can have, pertains to the rightness of the fundamental duty of benevolence. This governs the state of heart, but other conditions determine the outward conduct. In outward conduct, finite beings must govern themselves by apprehended tendencies and consequences. T-at, and that only, must be done which on the whole seems profitable, that is, conducive to general good. But does not this principle sanction the corrupt maxim End and that the end justifies the Imeans? So far as Means. pertains to the grand end of all action, the universal good, the mnaxim is not corrupt. This end justifies any and all means which tend to promote it, and all men sustain the maximll. But the maxim is false when applied to anylimited good or subordinate end. A means may promote a particular good, and yet be harmfill on the whole. Hence no such end can justify all means. This was the alleged perversion of the maxim by the Jesuits. The building up of the church was their good, and falsehood and treachery were justified when they seemed to be conducive to this end. All means promotive of a particular end must be tested by their bearing on the great end. But is it ever right to "do evil that good may come?" Evil for the Yes, natural evil. This is the work of every ELke ( f goo dly. We bring about desirable ends by means which in themselves involve pain, suffering, expense, natural evil. Evil in the sense of sti we may never do for the sake of any good. To commit sin for the sake of good in the strict sense, that is, on account of To DlUrIT, KOWN AND UNKNOWN. the value of the good in itself, is an impossibility, and the claimn, therefore, a hypocritical pretense. Are we permitted, then, to "choose the least of two e,ils?" Certainly, the least of two natural fhoce of evils. We rarely perform an outward act ens. wl.ich does not involve such a choice. The leasr of two Bills we are never left to choose. The word duty has an ambiguity similar to that of right, arising from the objective and subjective Knowledge of application of the term. In its objective sense duty. duty is synonymous with the objective right, that which in general ought to be done. In its subjective sense, reference is had to the circumstances of the agent, and the term duty indicates that which is binding upon him. But we speak of duty as known and unknown, and of an anxious desire to know duty; what is the significance of these expressions? The fundamental, primal duty of benevolence is known to all moral agents-the duty to be honestly regardful of every good. The knowledge of this is a condition of moral agency. This is duty in the subjective sense. In reference to duty in this sense there can be no ignorance among moral beings; the knowledge is direct and absolute. But this is the point upon which moral character turns. When this is attended to,thle moral character is right; hence there can be no ignorance of duty which hinders the fulfilment of obligation. But there is ignorance of objective, outward duty, of the things which are objectively right in con- Ignorance of duct, and which would be duty if they were duty. understood. No mortal knows perfectly the objective ighlt; probably none but God thus knows it. But these unknown objective duties are not duties until they betome known. Nothing can be duty, in the sense of mo 71 MORAL IPuILOSOPHY. ally binding upon us at any time, which we have not at that time the means of knowing. The idea of unknown duty, as present obligation; is an impossible one. Thec nmiaximn that "ignorance of the law excuses no one," is 8imply an expression of general expediency in the admninistration of human law. Still, it is not rigidly applied in any civilized society. Satisfactory proof of entire ignorance will mitigate or set aside the penalty; as a principle of morals the maxim is utterly false. What, then, is meant by ignorance of duty, and by the What s in- apprehension that duty may be mistaken? tended. When we understand ourselves, we mean that we are ignorant what course of outward action it is wise and best to pursue, and we fear that we may take an undesirable course, which will bring regret, not self-condemnation. Whoever is honestly bent upon doing duty, does it, even if he fails to find the course that is wise and best. His honest purpose leads him to use all accessible light and knowledge, and there is then no room for self-condemnation. If the present darkness be the result of the past neglect of light, there is sin in the past; but present light is the measure of present duty. With this accords tie Scripture:'" eloved, if our heart condemn us not, then have we confidence towards God, and whatsoever we ask we receive of him, because we keep his commandments, and do those things that are pleasing in his sight." In the deepest darkness of the human soul, the path of duty, of present obligation, lies open, accessible. However gre-t the perplexity upon questions of speculative belief, and of practical life, duty is always known. Failure in obligation is always with )ut excuse. Every moral being can,at any moment,take the attitude that is fundamentally right. 72 NEED OF A REVELATION. Why, then, is a revelation needed, if there be no suchl ignorance as is necessarily fatal? It is not Need of re needed to reveal unknown duties-duties act- lation. nally binding upon us, and which we sin in not performing. There are no such duties. But the first great need of a revelation is to furnish motives, considerations to persuade men to perform the duties already kn(owin. Among the motives thus broughlt to lght,is the magni tude of the good that men refuse to regard, the value of the blessedness, the well-being of God and man. There is power in the clearer apprehension of these things as divinely revealed. A revelation of the rewards of virtue and the penalties of sin is a wholesome force; not that hope and fear are the immediate motives to virtuous action, but they induce that consideration which is essential. A definite apprehension of God as a personal moral governor, and of his administration as given in revelation,is conducive to obedience. A clear statement of the great law of obligation as a divine enactment, although already known in principle, operates as a powerful force. Ignorance of God and of his will is no excuse for sin, but a knowledge of him is highly promotive of virtue Especially that exhibition of the divine character, involved in the incarnation and the atonement, is needed to inspire men with benevolence; and perhaps no virtue ever existed among men except as the result of such rev elation, more or less distinct. A second and subordinate need of revelation is t( I)ring to light courses of conduct that are Subordinat wise and right, and which become duty need. a hen revealed. Among these are the proper constitu tion of the family, and the positive institutions of relig ion, the Sabbath, modes of worship, and other outward 4 73 I MORAL PHILOSOPHY. ordinances. But it is not the chief object of revelation to solve problems of practical, objective duty. These are mlostly left to be wrought out in experience. The general principles and examples are all that could b)c given for gtiiclance, or rather all that we could use if giv eii. X'great want is motive for performance of duty already known. For this chiefly the gospel is needed in the dark places of the earth. Revealed religion supervenes upon the systemn of obligation as intuitively known, and gives effect and vitality to the knowledge. This is, in fact, our only ground of expectation that men will be brought to act in harnony with known obligation. Such a force from without in needed. 74 CHAPTER VIII. CONSCIENCE-IS IT A GUIDE C,osCIENcE is the faculty by which we perceive and affirm duty, or obligation. As obligation per- Cofnsciene, d definition al'tains primarily to the fundamental duty of office. benevolence, the ultimate choice of good, so conscience directly enjoins only this duty. Its action,thus far,is absolute and universal, requiring in every moral being benevolence, without any condition. This is the perception and affirmation of subjective duty. But when any course of outward action is seen to be promotive of the good conscience enjoins as obligatory the pursuit of this course Its action in this case is conditioned upon the action of the judgment in reference to objective or outward duty. Conscience, then, requires of us benevolence, and the use of all the means which seem to promote the good. Conscience in this sense is an intellectual, rational faculty; its office is to perceive obligation. Connected with this perception of duty, which is the legitimate work of conscience, there is an im- Impulse of pulse of the sensibility, moving to the perform- conscience. ance of duty. Hence, we speak of conscience as impel ling to the performance of an act of duty. With some writers this seems to be the leading use of the term conscience. In the performance of an act, right or wrong, there is ali affection of the sensibility corresponding Conscience approving and with the character of the act: selfapproba- condening. tion, satisfaction for the right, and self-condemnation, re MORAL PHILOSOPItY. tnorse for the wrong. This affection is more or less dis tinct, according to circumstances and character. In popli. 'ar usage this emotional exercise is often primarily indi ated by the word conscience. Again? in aid of our rational faculty of conscience and( lsthetic judgment, we seem to have a spontaneous in }el ~stinetive judgment, a kind of moral tastewqlieh acts instantaneously upon the contemplation of miiany courses of conduct. This may be called the aesthetic conscience. It acts in advance of the slower processes of the judgment proper, upon many questions of outward duty. We have an instantaneous judgment, or ethical instinet, in favor of all such conduct as is coinmonly embraced under any of the recognized virtues. An act of decel)tion,or of taking another's property,is at once pronounced against by the testhletie conscience, in advance of any examination of the particular circumstances, a judogment based upon the mere form and generally accepted character of the act. A sober second thought may reverse the decision. and approve the act. This direct, spontaneous judogment is in part, perhaps, an original element of our constitution, intended as a prompter to outward virtues; in part and chiefly it is an instantaneous application of past decisions, and judgments, and maxims, to the case in hand, determined by the most ob icus nature and relations of the act. Thus we have an .nstinct of justice, of mercy, of veracity, of magnanimity, and so for all the accepted virtues; and every act which seemns, at first view,to present the form of any of these virtues, is at once endorsed by the esthetic conscience. A particular education gives rise to additional spontaneous juidgments. Thus the Puritan condemns at once any a(lt which seems inconsistent with a scrupulous observance 76 CONSCIENCE-IS Ir A GUIDE? of the Sabbath, and the Romanist shrinks from eating flesh on Friday. Aiany writers seem to have no conception of conscience, beyond this instinctive or immnediate judmcuent. The question, is conscience a sufficient guide to duty, is essentially answered in the foregoing an- Sufficiencyof aiy-sis. The rational affirmation that we coliscience. og,lht to choose the good on its own account, is iiievit ably right, and hence conscience is a guide to immediate duty. The obligation to regard the good implies the obligation to use all practicable means to promote the good; hence conscience, in its direct affirmation, imposes this obligation. Thus far there is agreement among all moral beings, and the decision cannot but be right. But to determine what outward acts will promote the good, is a work of judgment, and not of Work of judg rational intuition. By light and evidence ment. derived from every accessible source, from revelation, from reason, from experience, our own and that of others. we determine the objective ighlt, or, in other words, the course of action which is promotive of well-being. In many cases there is no hesitation; the decision is imnme diate and infallible. In others we find room for doubt, and liability to error. But when the balance of probabilities is settled, then conscience endorses the probable course. And in this the conscience is right. We ought to follow our best judgmenet in outward duty. If not, what guide remains? The poet is right in his' Universal Prayer: i What conscience dictates to be done, Or warns me not to do, This, teach me, more than hell, to shun; That, more than heaven, pursue." 77 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. Bult, is the man virtuous who thus follows his con science and an erroneous judgment? Certainly he is; it is the only virtue possible to men. Following his conscience he is benevolent; and to be benevolent is to be virtuous. On the duty of following conscience there is no differ Diverse view6 ence of opinion among writers on morals Whately. All agree that one must follow his conscience even in error of judgment, doing that which is objectively wrong; but that he thereby fulfils obligation, all do not agree. Thus Archbishop Whately says: "Any one, therefore, whose conscience has been in any way depraved, and who is proceeding on some wrong principle, cannot possibly act rightly, whether he act according to his conscience or against it, till he is cured of this defect in his moral judgment. If, however, any one has done his best to form a right judgment, but has fallen into error through unavoidable ignorance or weakness of understanding, we may hope that his all-seeing and merciful Judge will pardon this involuntary error." Dr. Alexander expresses himself still more decidedly: "It is true if a man's conscience dictates a Alexander. certain action, he is morally bound to obey; but if that action is in itself wrong, he commits sin in performing it, nevertheless. Ile who is under fundamental error is in a sad dilemma. Do what he will, he sins. If he disobey conscience, he knowingly sins, doing what he believes to be wrong; and a manl never can be justified for doing what he believes to be wrong, even though it should turn out to be right. Alie if he obey conscience, performing an act whi h is ir itself wrong, he sins; because he complies not with iIs 'ONSCIENCE-IS IT A GUIDE the law under which he is placed." A sad dilemma, truly; and it is not strange that this writer retires from the discussion with the remark that "metaphysical rea soning rather perplexes and obscures, than elucidates,such points." But the intuitive perceptions of men for ever contra diet the doctrine that there is sin, blame- Unreasonable and unscripworthiness in an honest, conscientious error. tural. The ignorance miay imply a past sin; but the present rule of duty is present light. This is the law under which we are placed. It is not the objective right that determines duty, but the right as apprehended. The doctrine is as unscriptural as it is offensive to our necessary convictions. "If there be first a willing mind, it is accepted according to that a man bath." "If ye were blind ye should have no sin, but now ye say,we see, therefore your sin remaineth." The servant, in the parable, that knew his lord's will and did it not, is beaten with many stripes; while he that knew not is beaten with few stripes; manifestly on the ground that light is a test and measure of guilt. But do not the Scriptures recognize a sin of ignorance Yes, in two forms: first, an outward or for- Sins of igno.anal defilement, contracted inadvertently, and rance. discharged by prescribed outward observances and sacrifices. No moral failure is implied. Secondly, sin is committed under comparative ignorance, and is spoken of as involving less guilt. Sulch was the sin of those for whom the Saviour praved. "Father, forgive them, foi they know not what they do." Such was the sin of San of Tarsus in his persecution, of which hlie says, "I did it ignorantly, in unbelief." The ground upon which Paul pronounces the heathen guilty in their idolatry, is not 79 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. that they are doing what is outwardly wrong, but that they have the means of knowing the right. These prin. eiples are so obvious,as well as scriptural, that men in practical life never fail to apprehend them. Conscience, then, taken as our best judgment of duty Rational coL- is our only guide; and as a guide to ree sctienee the gilide. titude or virtuous conduct, the subjective right, it is infallible. The judgment may fail as to the objective right, but conscience indicates all obligation. Let it be understood, however, that conscience is a sure Not the emo guide,only as the intellectual faculty by which tional. we judge of duty. Conscience, as a miere impulse to duty, or as an emotion of self-approbation or disapprobation in view of any act, is never to be taken as a guide. To perform a doubtifl act and wait for the result in feeling, is no proper consultation of conscience; no merefeelingis a guide to duty. Nor, again, is the instinctive,oesthetic conscience an ul Nor the timate authority. It is like our appetites, ethetic. designed to suggest the proper course oi ac:.on; but there is always an appeal from it to a fuller and more deliberate investigation. It serves to hold us in check, for the judgment to come to our aid, and the judgment may reverse its decisions. Thus,at first view we shrink from any act of deception; for example, a false dispatch to mislead an enemy in war, a feint to divert a kidnapper firom the track of a fugitive; but a calm judgment will justify the act. One educated as a Rornanist hesitates to take flesh on Friday, and until he gets better light he has no right to taste; but a full investig,ation will relieve him from the restraint. He stir t;,)ll)ws conscience while appealing firom the spontane ous decision to the slower judgment. 80 CONSCIEN7CE-IS IT A GUIDE?E 8 The truly conscientious man is he who takes, as his end of life,thlat which reason approves as the True conseci good; thus hlie meets all real obligation, be- entiousness comes benevolent, and necessarily adopts such courses of )itward conduct as approve themselves to his judgment. Such a man alone follows conscience. It is a mistake to call one conscientious who has a strong instinct of the right, and yields to it as an impulse. It is a very plausible form of impulsive action, but does not involve benievolence, the only geniine rectitude. Nor is he necessarily conscientious who pursues some right outward course, with the full conviction that he ought to pursue it. The first and chief requirement of conscience is benevolence; and if this be not rendered, there can be no conscientiousness in outward life. It is right and duty to be honest in business, and the man who scrupulously discharges this outward duty is sometimes regarded as conscientious; and so he may be, but the outward right ness does not prove it. Conscientiousness is anl inward state, and not any outward act or course whatsoever. But was not Saul conscientious in his course of persecution, since he verily thought he ought to do Saul's consci many things contrary to the name of Jesus of entiousness. Nazareth? No, hle had not a right or benevolent heart, and hence failed to meet the primary requisition of con science. Ilis own testimony is conclusive: " Being ex ceedingly mad against them, I persecuted them even unto strange cities"-a spirit utterly opposed to benevolence. lHe was sincere in his belief that what he was doilg ought to be done, but he knew that the hatred which he cherished was wrong. It would not have materially changed the case if his outward course had been right. The malice within would have corrupted the whole ac 4* 81 M')RAL IPHILOSOPHY. tion,and excuded conscientiousness. Sincerity in refer ence to the outward action, with a bitter, malignant heart. is the characteristic of fanaticism, and the moral state is all the same, whether the outward action be right or wrong. Benevolence alone is conscientiousness. Honesty, in the high sense of the word, is conscientious ness. It is meeting one's convictions; and True honesty. the first grand conviction of a moral being is that all good must be regarded. Honesty, then, nmust begin at the fotundation,witli rightness of heart. Thus the honest man is the thoroughly true man, or, as Pope calls him, "the noblest work of God." Two persons equally conscientious may differ much ir Difference of their outward conduct. They are alike in conduct. their subjective state, act upon the same great principles, are equally virtuous and worthy of approbation, but differ in the light they have, and hence in their ,udgmient of outward duty. There is ground for mutual confidence; they can trust each other's hearts while they distrust the judgment. The doctrine is sometimes maintained, perhaps more Sinerity, often reprobated, that it is not important what partial and complete. one believes or does if he is only sincere; he is virtuous and to be approved. In one view the doctrine is false. The partial sincerity involved in a particular course of conduct, which is believed to be right, does not necessarily imply moral rightness. This was the sincerity of Paul in his persecution. In another view the doctrine is true. The sincerity which(,l begins with the heart and sets it right upon the great point of obligation, involves all that is essential to nmoral rectitude. The theoretic belief may be inadequate and erroneous the outward life defective, according to 62 CONSCIENCE-IS IT A GUIDE? the standard of objective rightness; but the man is right at heart,and cannot be in any fatal error. The usual i. lustrations of a traveller that has wandered firom the path and of a ship's crew that have lost their reckoning, by which it is attempted to prove that sincerity cannot save from the destruction which comes from error, are utterly fallacious. They overlook the distinction between an error of the heart and of the head, and assume that men can be mistaken in fundamental duty, when with all honesty of heart they aim to be right. Is conscience the creature of education? Certainly not; it is one of the original faculties of our Education of moral constitution. It is even doubtful conscience. whether the rational, intuitive faculty, which alone dis cerns obligation, can be educated in any proper sense Perhaps it mnay be educated, in the same sense as the eye, t;o see with discrimination, what, without education, it would still see. No being can be taught obligation,who has not the idea to begin with. The judgment may be educated to discern more clearly the objective right The feeling of obligation may be quickened by culture, and the Aesthetic moral sense may be developed and modified; but in none of these senses is conscience made by education. By an enlightened conscience we ought to mean an enlightened judgment, a clear discernment Conscience,, enlightened of outward duty. A tender conscience is a tender, seam keen sensibility in refbrence to right and wrong. Men are probably different constitutionally in this respect, and the difference is enhanced by habits of life. A seared conscience is a hardened sensibility an obtuseness of feeliiog in reference to moral conduct, the result of habits of sin. This is sometimes partial, sometimes genera]; 83 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. but however extreme the obtuseness of feeling, there must remain, while moral agency remains, the intellec. tual apprehension of obligation. Conscience proper can be obliterated,only by the annihilation of moral agency. By a perverted conscience we should mean a perverted erverted instinct, the esthletic conscience, which scan )nsciences. not given as an ultimate reliance; or we might refer to the judgment of outward duty,misled by education, by custom, and habits of life. But the rational facutltvy of conscience, that which perceives obligation, cannot be perverted. The affirmation of primary duty is for ever the same. The great axiom in morals involving the obligation to choose good, rests upon the same general foundation as an axiom in mathematics; and no perversion of the reason is possible which admits of the denial of one more than of the other. Such a condition,in either case,involves a subversion rather than a perversion. The man has ceased to be rational and ae. countable. 84 CHAPTER IX. UNIITY OR SIMPLICITY OF MORAL AOTICN. IN order to a more complete elucidation of the nature o'f moral action, it seems necessary to discuLss Question the question of its entireness or unity. Can stated virtue and sin co-exist in the same heart? It is perfectly possible that they should alternate, because either is always in the power of every moral agent. The virtuous man can become sinful;the sinful man can become virtuous. Can the same man be both at the same time? With few exceptions, writers on morals and theology answer this question in the affirmative; but if the foregoing views of the nature of moral action, of sin and virtue, be correct, the question must be answered in the negative. Let it be remembered that all moral action is voluntary —that virtue and sin are found in the Virtue and sin contradie,. action of the will,in ultimate choice alone- toyntradi. that virtue is the voluntary choice or regard of good as good, or on its own account, and that nothing else is virtue-that sin is the voluntary refusal to choose or regard the good, and that nothing else is sin; and the conclusion eems inevitable that the two cannot co-exist, that where one is the other cannot be. The two forms of action are directly contradictory to each other, and,in the very nature of the case,eachl must exclude the other. Their co-existence is neither conceivable nor possible, but upon the hypothesis of a dual action of the will, which in effect involves two wills and g MORAL PHILOSOPHY double personality. Even then there is no proper co existence, for we have essentially two persons instead of one. If virtue and sin, then, are confined to the actio of the will, there would scarce seem room for argument uad if they are not confined to the action of the will lley are no longer virtue and sin. But let us attend to the various hypotheses upon which a deficiency of virtue is maintained, resulting in a character in one point of view praiseworthy, and in another blameworthy at the same time, or in reference to the same action. It is maintained by some that as the powers of the Virtue defect- race have been dwarfed by the fall, and by lve from the faln. the sin of past generations, and as the law of duty is the same as for a race with perfect powers, all] ulfilinent of obligation is necessarily defective; the virtue must fall short of the true standard, as the powers employed do of full perfection. The obvious mistake here is in the assumption that Obligation the law of duty is not adapted to tie powers and ability. of the subject, whatever those powers may be. By the law of nature, ability and obligation go hand in hand; and the very conception of the existence of obligation in the sense of present duty, where there is no ability, is impossible. The divine law corresponds in express terms with this law of nature: "Thlou shalt love the Lord thy God withl all thy heart, with all thy soul, with all thy mind, and with all thy strength." Ilere the mea sure of duty is the power we have, not any ideal power sU(Ih as the race might be imagined to hlave if there had )eeil no sin. But is not this accommodating the law to iiim,nan infirmity? Certainly it is: to infirmity of power; and a law which is not accommodated to human infirmity is no law of duty or obligation. If we deny our necessary se UITY OR SIMPLICITY OF MORAL AC'ION. convictions in this matter, there is an end of all knows edge of duty. But it is urged again that by our own sin we have weakened our energies and obscured our Defects from mninds, while the law of duty requires of us persona. sin according to the powers we might have had. It is not to be supposed that men by any wicked act of their own should diminish their obligation or duty. The argument is only plausible. MIen can by their own sinful act diminish their power to do, and to the same exteit their subsequent obligation to do. They are held responsible for that past act or course of sin by which their powers were injured, and are liable to plunishment for it; but ever after it is required of them according to that they have, and not according to that they have not. This we know directly and absolutely, as we know a truth of mathematics. "But can a man who owes a debt, cancel his obligation to pay it by wilfully destroying his own property? " He cannot escape the fact of past obligation nor the guilt of wilfully declining to meet it; but for all subsequent time he fulfils actual obligation by doing the best he can. When ability returns, the obligation revives in all its force. The fact of weakened powers, then, affords no foundation for the idea of defective virtue, whether the power was lost by the fault of others, or l)y our own. Again it is said that thle purpose or intention, the a,: of the will, may be right, and yet many of the Sin in thoglia tiiotkrhts and feelings may be such as they and feeling, ouilit not to be. It may be replied that such tliouiglits and feelings do not fall within the field of obligation. They are involuntary exercises, to a greater or less extent indrirectly under the control of tile will. If the voluntary 87 MORAL PHILOSOPH Y. attit,:de be right, the thoughts and feelings will be con trolled so far as they are subject to the will; beyond this there is no power, and no obligation. It should be re. memnbered that temptation to sin, addressed to the thought or feeling, is not sin, except as it is voluntarily admitted or cherishled. What are calle(d wicked thoughts and fel ings are sometimes of this nature. Another theory is that the motives which bear upon us Mixed mo- at allny time are various, some good and others tives bad, and that the resulting action must be complex like the motives, partly good and partly bad. There is confusion in the use of the term motive. MAotives may be contemplated in two points of vievw-first, as the outward facts and forces which address themselves to the thought and feeling, and secondly, as the inward reason in view of which the mind chooses and acts. Thus motives are objective and subjective. The character of the action must turn upon the subjective motive, that is. the reason which is accepted as the ground of action. It matters not what the objective motives may be; only that which actually moves the will, is of account in character. Motives, objectively considered, are of two classes; thos( which appeal to the intelligence and persuade to a regard for good on its own account; and those which address the feelings desires, and passions, and persuade to a disregard of good. To suppose that these two are accepted at the ame tinme as reasons of action, involves that contradictory movement of the will, the dual action, which we have seen to be impossible. Motives are mixed objectively, not sub, jeetively; thus they afford no foundation for mixed action. Again it is maintained that the choice of good, in PaN alrerd which virtuie lies, may be defective, from its not embracing al' good, or rather all appre 88 UNITY OR SIMPLICITY OF MORAL A('fON. hended good. But we have seen that to regard good in a single instance on its own account, which is implied in the choice of good, is to regard all good. It is the benevo lent attitude of will, and any other good will be em. braced without any change of spirit or of action. Ii one arbitrarily limits his regard to the interests whiceL are agreeable to him, or sustain some special relation to Iiim, then riegard for good is not at all his principle of action. He is not benevolent even in a partial sense. Partial benevolence is a selfcontradiction. A more common ground upon which defectiveness of virtue is maintained, is that the choice of Deficiency of good, though genuine, may lack intensity, intensity. and thus the action be partly right, partly wrong. A psychological inquiry arises here, whether we can predicate different degrees of intensity of that ultimate att'tude of the will which alone is moral action. It is conceivable, and perhaps probable, that the different degrees of intensity in our action pertain to our emotional, executive activity, rather than to the ultimate choice. [n that case the regulation of the intensity of our action lies out of the field of obligation. But if the will acts with a varying intensity in its ultimate, moral action, the regulation of this intensity may be under our control or it may not. If not, then obligation does not pertain to it. All that can be required is that our benevolence be genuine; and the degree of its intensity will be ieterminiied by conditions for which we are not responsi ble. But if, on the other hand, the will determines the intensity of the choice as well as its general character-the only supposition upon which it becomes an element of moral action-then, in order to a genuine choice at all, the will inlst act with all its energy. If it does not, then self 89 MORPAL PHILI,OSOItY. indulgence or personal ease is preferred to good, and the choice is utterly vicious; or the will is divided between the vhoice of goo)d and the refiusal to choose, a ease of that contradictory, dual action whlichl is inconceivable and impossib e. The inference, popularly expressed, is that virtuous action, to be genuine, must be wholehearted. Allyreservation of power corrupts the whole. A more popular form in wlhich the doctrine of mixed Acts opposod action is maintained, is found in the idea to ultimate choice. that a good man, still retaining his benevolent, virtuous choice, rmay, from sudden impulse, perform acts in conflict with this choice, and thus be virtuous in his fundamental choice, and sinful in the opposing acts. Tlhus, it is said, a man with a purpose to go to New York, may turn aside for business or pleasure, without surrenderinig his final purpose. The execution of it is merely lelayed. But the illustration does not meet the case. The going to New York and the turning aside for business or pleasure, are both proximate to some other end of pleasure or of profit, to which they both contribute. IJence the two actions harmonize in their relation to that ulterior purpose. But the relation of ultimate choice to executive action is totally different. The benevolent choice, while it exists, necessitates the perft rmance of all acts judged to be promotive of the good, and the abstaining from all others. If an opposing act be performed, then benevolence has failed; another and opposing principle of action is accepted. It is doubtless true that a good man, yielding to ilnpulse or temptation, and sinning, has a feeling or expectation that he shall return to his virtuous, benevolent life; but such a feeling o)r thought is not benevolence. It is doubtless true that many good thoughts and feelings and proximate purpose 14 C) UNIY OR SIMPLICITY OF MORAL ACTION. survive a fall into sin, and co-exist with it, and seemn,in a degree, to obscure to the erring man the nature of his action and his character. But these good thoughts and feelings and purposes are not virtue; thev are but con stitutional exercises, or the echo of a goodness that lia failed Such thoughts and feelings constitute a saving l)ow-e,aconstantpressure to restore the man fiom his way-ward action, and terminate the lapse from righteousness All that goes to make up the habit of action remainr. an ever-present motive soliciting a return from the abterration. Thus we cjnfidently expect when a good man falls he will rise again; and there is ground for the expectation in the nature of the case, as well as in the divine promise. There are doubtless other forms in wvtich the doctrine of mixed action is set forth, but they must involve essentially the same principles as those which have been presented. In every form they seem to overlook the very nature of moral action. A thorough examination of the teachings of Scripture would show that they are in harmony with criture the necessary deductions of our reason upon cg. this question. There are several passages which seem to teach the doctrine of simplicity of action with almost philosophical directness, and there are multitudes of passages in which the doctrine seems to be assumed; and we look in vain for a passage which upon any proba ble interpretation implies the opposite doctrine. Take the following texts as examples: " No man can serve two ,nasters; either he will hate the one and love the other, ,r else he will hold to the one and despise the other. Ye annot serve God and mammon." " le that is faithful in that which is least, is faithful also in much; and he that ii unjust in the least, is unjust also in much." "Except a 91 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. man forsake all that he hathli, he cannot be my disciple." 'For whosoever shall keep the whole law and yet offend ill one point, he is guilty of all." " If any manl love the world, the love of the Father is not in him." The Sa vioiur's exhortation: "Be ye therefore perfect eveni as yori Father which is inii heaven is perfect," taken in its con ection, accords with the doctrine. The perfect love which he requires is simply genuine love, the benevolence which embraces enemies and friends, the evil and the good. It is not an exalted state of virtue to which he exhorts, but simply genuine virtue. Nothing lower than this meets his approbation at all. The spontaneous utterances of the teachers of practical Practical virtue and religion, take the same tform. With beaching. one voice they require whole-heartedness, and announce that any voluntary reservation corrupts the whole action, and mnakes the apparent virtue a hypocrisy. It is only when their theory comes to mind and qualifies the expression that we hear any other voice; and the theory is never presented to one who comes with the earnest enquiry: "Wherewith shall I come before the Lord and bow myself before the high God?" Even philosophical writers, with their attention directed Spontaneous to the nature of moral action, often announce Taylor. the doctrine of simplicity or unity of action in the strongest terms. Thus, Dr. N. W. Taylor: "While such is the peculiar and exclusive character of the benevolent and selfish preference, every moral being is doomed by a necessity of nature to place himself under the absolute dominion and control of the one or the other of these preferences. It is an ordinance of his very being, that he cannot serve both these nmasters, and must serve one. The preference of one of the only 92 UMTY OR SIMPLICITY OF MORAL ACTION. two objects of moral choice excludes the other from all thought except to oppose and resist it, and therefore shluts off all controlling influence from it as an object to be attained, as it were, by its utter annihilation, and so consecrates his whole being to the attainment of the supreme object. He thinks, he feels, he wills, he acts, he lives, or, as the case may be, he dies for it. Such is the nature, such the tendency of each of the two great moral principles, or preferences of a moral being, as a predominant principle." And yet Dr. Taylor in other places discards the doctrine of simplicity of action, but without explaining the grounds of its rejection. MAetcalf, in a recent work on the nature of obligation, says: "Unless the law of right be taken as Metcalf. the rule of duty without reserve, there is not the beginning of the spirit of holy obedience to it. If an ntention to disobey in one point be reserved, so that only partial obedience is intended, the whole is vitiated. Not being a purpose of the highest good, it is wanting in an essential element of virtue." On the opposite page we read: "In some parts of this treatise, the author has found difficulty in expressing what he conceives to be the exact truth, without implying more than is true. Although, in some instances, his language may seem to imply that there can be no true virtue in a man's character when that character is not perfect in holiness, or entirely firee from sin, or that he can perform no part of his duty without performing the whole, yet he has not designed to convey this sentiment." And yet he has not undertaken to show how one can perform a part of his duty without performiIng the whole. There ought to be some strong reason for rejecting a view which seems an inevitable deduction from the very nature of moral action, and 93 MORAL PHILOSOPHY which is essential to a proper presentation of I)ractical duty; a view, too, which is not only consistent with the ,(Ieral current of Scripture doctrine, but seems to be in -.lcated by its express words. Tile following popular objections present some of the reisons that are supposed to bear against the doctrine. The prevailing consciousness of men is a refutation of Ol)jections, the doctrine. It is the feeling of all who re popular con- z ciouess. fleet on their own moral state, even of the best aen, that their goodness is not complete, that their best achievements are marred with deficiency. " Forgive the iniquity of our most holy thiings," has been the petition of the good in all times. They neither wholly approve nor wholly condemn themselves. No mere logical inference can stand against this testimony of the common consciousness of men. The general impression of deficient goodness is admit ted; and the fact of deficiency is also admit"swer. ted; but it is a deficiency which arises finom the alternation of good and evil in the heart, and not fromn their co-existence. A brief retrospect of a good man's experience will bring into view things to approve and things to condemn; and hence the impression which he has of a mixed life and character. Ilis consciousness on the subject is not so definite as to discriminate between these two forms of mixture; either of the two will account for his experience, and explain the general consciousness. We are at liberty. then, in the presence of this general tesimnony, to adopt that view which the nature of the case -cems to require. Again, allowance must be made for some confusion in confusion or the minds even of good men in reference tij thoughts. the nature of virtue and of sin. A want of 94 UNITY OR SIMPLICITY OF MORAL A(CTION. discrimination between thlouglits and feelings and purposes, and a failure to locate the moral element in it, proper place, would produce a general impression of tlhe o-existence of virtue and sin,even when there is no suchl o-existence. We have seen that the seat of moral chalr wcter is below the surface of tliougllt,and feeling,and )lir ['ose, and that the reflective consciousness often fails to reach it. Hence, the judgments of men in reference t( their own present moral state are always to be received with caution. It is an accepted doctrine of a large portion of the Christian world that the character of the unregenerate is entirely destitute of virtue, that there is no adlmixture of good and evil,even by alternation; yet there is with these the same consciousness of a mixed character, the same vague impression that they are partly right and partly wrong. A want of discrimination and a superficial consciousness will explain the impression. Some allow. ante, too, must be made for the theories of Effect of tha moral character which are in vogue. These ories. will be reflected in the experimental consciousness. Instead of being proof of the theory, the consciousness is simply the result of the theory. The case of the person in President Edwards' congregation who was convicted for the sin of Adam, is an instance in point. But no va,gue impression of the general consciousness, which admits of various satisfactory explanations, can be urged in opposition to the clear intuitions of the mind,and the teachings of Scripture. Another objection brings in the negative testimony of onsciousness against the theory of unity of Neative boo ction. It is said that when a good man timony. falls into sin, if the character changes from wholly good to wholly bad, there ought to be a shock in experien ~e, a 95 MORAL PIIILOSOPTY. convulsion, as in the fall of an angel and his transforiiis tioii into a demon. Consciousness reveals no such conivul sion. The man is often left in great uncertainty as tc the fact of his failure, and may need some light from without to reveal it. This experience is supposed to in m'cate that the only change is in the ratio of the good -itd the bad in the soul, involving a little less of the good,and a little more of the bad. We must bear in mind the ambiguity of the word character. It is often used to embrace all Answer. Anwer. that belongs to the soul, thoughts, feelings, purposes, all in the man that relates to the present, the past, and the future. Our inquiry does not relate to chai aeter in this wide sense, but to character as expressing simply the moral status, the condition as to virtue and sin at a particular moment. A change from virtuous tc sinful action does not necessarily imply a change in any thought or feeling or proximate purpose. These, in gen eral, do not admit of any sudden change. If the moral character becomes permanently changed, the thoughts and feelings and purposes will be modified to a greater or less extent. But yielding to a sudden temptation to evil, does not affect at once these exercises of the superficial consciousness. There is for the moment a surrender of the principle of right action which underlies these conscious exercises; then the right principle is resumed again, and the current of conscious action goes on without interruption. It may require subsequent reflection, and an earnest inquest upon one's self, to bring out into flll consciousness the fact of sin. It is not rare that the great moral change of life, the commencement of a lifo of virtue, occurs without any such experience as to reveal the fact in immediate consciousness. It is common 96 UNMTY 011 SIMPLICITY OF MIORAL ACTIOiN. to refer this great moral change to a moment of high emotional experience, but often there is no such experi ence; and when there is, it probably does not mark the precise instant of the moral change. That any sudden lapse into sin should be marked by any instantaneous emotional experience, is still less probable. The objection assumes a difference between the vlrtu ons and the sinful, which in general does not Assumed di exist. The difference is in moial character, ference. while in many thoughts and feelings and purposes they are alike. The good man is not an angel in ecstatic emotion and exalted view, and the bad man is not a demon in malignant feeling and malicious purpose. These are but the extreme points toward which their divergent courses tend. In this life,these points are probably never reached. They are the result of a long course of development and growth. The difference in moral character is indeed a capital one, but other differences are mnore distinct in immediate consciousness. If virtue, wherever it exists, is entire and complete, then there is no room for improvement, for growth; No room for no use for moral discipline and culture. The growth. man may be dismissed from the world as finished. There is still room for establishment in virtue, for the attainment of persistency and stability, a habit of virtuous action. Character, in the wer. broader sense, is incomplete from moral inconstancy. Is not this condition of instability the conscious weakness and want of all in their first experience of a virtuous life? The attainment of greater stability is one of thit results of a "patient continuance in well-doing." In this respect the work is essentially the same as to eliminate the remaining evil from a heart in which virtue and 5 97 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. sin co-exist, as upon the hypothesis of mixed action. On the hyp)othesis of simplicity of action the struggle is be. tween two forces, one within and the other without tie t~itatel; upon the other hypothesis the opposing fores loll,e joint possession. Then, again, there remains. as work to be done, the attaimnenlt of all the particular virtues and graces of character. Benevolence is the root or germ of them all but a complete character, in the broader sense, involves tle carrying out of this principle in all relations,under the guidance of " sound wisdom and discretion." With time, and opportunity, and self-culture, the principle of benevolence extends its transforming power to the whole innerando:iter life. Htere is work, even in the domain of one's ownl character, for the longest earthly career, and room for every form of discipline. But are there no degrees of goodness? Are all good Degrees of men equally virtuous? And is the same man goodness. no more virtuous after years of experience and progress than at the commencement of his virtuous course? If virtue is complete wherever it exists at all, it would seem to follow that no good man can be more virtuous than another; and this is contrary to the instinctive judgment of men. One mnan may be more virtuous than another in the Aswer. sense that his virtue is more persistent, and suffers less interruption. There is more of virtue in his continuous life. In the same way a maii may be more virtuous at one time than at another lThien, again, one man may afford a better example of practical virtue than another; and every man may make progress in the applications of the law of benevolence to his outward life. These differences in character afford 98 UNtIY OR SIMPLICITY OF MORAI ACTIl(. abundant ground for the popular idea of d(lifferent degrees of virtue. But whether, in reference to the momentary moral state, one good man is more virtuous than another in the sense of more praiseworthy, is a curious question, somewhat difficult to answer upon either of the twc hypotheses of moral character. If there be such a differ ence, is the higher virtue with him who has the higher light,and superior advantages and motives for a virtuous life, or with him whose situation is less favorable? We certainly admire more the virtue that struggles through difficulties, and "comes out of great tribulation," It excites surprise, and the surprise enhances our approbation. The probability would seem to be that all virtuous beings, in reference to their momentary moral state, are equally praiseworthy. They differ in the permanency of their fidelity, in the intensity and energy of their virti ous activities, in the success with which they apply the law of benevolence to all outward action, and in the magnitude of the powers and energies subjected to that law. In reference to degrees of sinfulness the case is some. what different. The guilt of sin undoubtedly Degees of increases with the light under which the sin sin lIness. is committed. Sin is the refusal to regard the good, and the guilt or ill desert of it must be proportioned to the apprehended value of the good that is disregarded. Every additional interest perceived enhances the guilt of persistence in the sin. The effect of temptation, upon the guilt of sin,is to be determined on this prin- Temptation ciplg When temptation obscures the under- ard guilt. Btanding, diminishes the light, it would seem to abate from the guilt; but if, as the case often seems to be, +emptation quickens the perceptions, and places in a 99 MORAL PHEILOSOPTY. Stronger light the good or evil involved, it must increase the guilt of transgression. Perha.ps no one has so strong a sense of the guilt of murder as he who has stood face to face with the crime, with the deliberate thought of its perpetration. In this ease it may not be the temptation proper that increases the light, )ut attendant circumstances. At every point of his career, the sinner is guilty of disr egarding all known good, and the guilt must increase with his wider vision The converse of this principle does not seem to apply in the case of virtue. The virtue may not increase necessarily with the sense of the value of the good regarded. LUpon the theory of simplicity of action, is one justified L1aim of paSt in the claim to have lived for any definite nl-sne3ss. time in the past, without any moral failure? There is no ground of positive knowledge that there nas been no such failure. Even present failure is not always a matter of distinct consciousness; and the past belongs to memory and not to consciousness. Only distinct consciousne,ses reappear in memory, and even these are often lost. No claim canll be justified that is more positive than the knowledge, aside from any question o)f propriety or impropriety on other grounds. In concluding this topic, it may be said that the doeLogical result trine of simplicity of action seems a logical of axiom. inference from the axiom that moral character, virtue, and sin, can be predicated only of voluntary states; and if thlis axiom be rejected, all clear ideas of virtue and sin, of good and ill desert, must go with it. Sin that has not its seat in the voluntary action, can sever be felt, or thought of, as sin. That is the deepest view of sin which brings it nearest to our personal responsibility; any other view must break the force of ob. 100 UNITY OR SIMPLICITY OF \[ORAL ACTION. ligation to virtue, and of condemnation for sin. The doetrine of simplicityof action seemstocontributetoclearei apprehensions of the nature of moral character, of Sill and holiness; in other respects its practical bearings may not differ greatly from those of the opposite do( trine. The theory of mixed action presents formidable difficulties of its own, which it is not necessary to con sider here. it)l CHAPTER X. THEORIES OF OBLIGATION. ThE great problem in morals is,the origin of duty, o rhe great the nature and foundation of ol.Iigation. question. Hiow, under what circumstances, does the perception or affirmation of obligation arise in the mind; and what is that obligation in its simple, elementary fbrm? "The nature of virtue" is sometimes given as an expression of the problem; but this is too limited; the nature of sin would convey the idea as well. Virtue and sin are the two opposite modes of action in view of obligation; the real question is, what is obligation, as to its nature, and the conditions of its existence? The answer to this question must of course be found Different an- among our primary intuitions and judgments; swers. and,at first thought,we should anticipate perfect harmony among ethical writers upon this point. But remarkable as it may seem, it is the point upon which the gravest differences of opinion exist. In practical morals, where we might look for difilerences of jud,gment, there is essential harmony; in the theory of the science there is as yet 1no harmony. These differenees must arise, not from the fact that men differ in the data of consciousness, but from the different degrees of success in the analysis and interpretation of the facts of conReasons of sciousness. Our primary perceptions are il dffer.-ences. accordance with facts, and facts are for ever the same; but there are various degrees of success in reaching and expressing these perceptions. The case THEORIES OF OBLIGATION. has many parallels. In general it is most difficult to exp)lain the origin and mode of our knowledge, when the knowledge is immediate and direct. Noething, is more surely and directly known than the fact of our own existence; but tie origin and history of the knowledge itif difficult to trace. A belief in the being of God found in all minds, but whllence its origin and authority is matter of question. Our intuitive judgments and( direct perceptions we fail to traee,whilewe can always give a reason for the results of our laborious processes and deductions. This view may indicate the occasion of difference, on a question so fundamental as the origin of obligation. Without attempting a history of ethical opinion, or even a synopsis of the various shades of doctrine which have had currency, we may still be profited by a brief review of some of the leading theories of obligation which have prevailed, or are still in vogue. According to the older Greek Philosophy, as represented by Socrates and Plato, right action Socrates and is the certain and necessary result of knowl- Plato. edge. All wrong action is the result of ignorance; of wrong action in spite of knowledge, they seem to have had no distinct conception. The idea affords no proper foundation for moral merit or demerit. The only failure is ignorance, and knowledge is the remedy. Aristotle held that personal happiness is the great good, and virtue is moderation; such a reg- viva of ris ulation of the desires and passions as leads to totle. happiness-the attainment of the golden mean betweei excessive indulgence and the suppression of desire. Tlhe ultimate aim of virtuous action is one's own happiness. Two prominent ideas divided the schools of Grecian 103 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. Philosophlly after these leaders. One view is represented Doctrine of by the Stoics, who inculcated a contempt of the Stoic. happiness, treated the advantages and disad vantages of life, its pains and pleasures, with equal indifference, and made the good to consist in living according to nature and reason. This is virtue, right action, the sole good; not because of the satisfaction resulting, but because of its rightness. The connection between virtue and happiness is an accident. The standard or law of right action is revealed in nature, and is not regulated by any reference to well-being in the form of happiness either of ourselves or others. The virtuous man is selfsuflicient, because in his virtuousness he has attained the true good, and hence all that is essential is within his own control. The other view was maintained by the Epicureans, Of the Epicu- who held that happiness, in the sense of enjoy reans. ment, is the true good,and the proper aim of life. Epicurus himself was not properly a sensualist. His idea of happiness was not realized in immediate or corporeal pleasure, but in the higher pleasures of the mind. He was a materialist, and hence his rules of conduct had no scope beyond the present life. All the leading theories-of modern times gather about Modern theo- these two centres, either making happiness ies. the supreme good, or finding ultimate good in she right, objective or subjective. Of those which account happiness the supreme good, there are again two classes; first, the theories which represent one's own hap pil ess as the ultimate aim,and grand motive of all virtuols action; and secondly, those which regard the happiness of all,general well-being,as the end. Of the writers that have maintained the first view L04 THEORIES OF OBLIGATION. Paley in England, and Dr. Taylor of New Haven) maj be taken as representatives. The second proition of various writ view has been maintained by Priestly and ers Bentham in England, Jouffloy in France, and Presi. dents Edwards, Dwilght, and Finney, in Anierica, with others less Frominent. Each of these writers has his peculiar views and modes of statement, but the theories may still be embraced in two general classes. Paley defines virtue to be, " doing good to mankind in obedience t~ the will of God, and for the Paley's doo sake of everlasting happiness." The end of trinle. all proper action is one's own highest happiness. The means by which this end is to be secured is doing good to mankind, beneficence; and the rule by which this bene ficenee is to be regulated, is the will of God; because God is infinitely wise, and his will indicates the proper mode of action. The difference between the good and the bad, according to Paley, is that one seeks everlasting happiness, the other happiness in this life. What has sometimes been called the New Haven theory, represents that all conceivable motive New Haen to action is desire of happiness. Says Dr. theory. Taylor: " Intelligent voluntary beings never act volum.tarily,without acting from a regard to their own well-being." Again, "There can no more be motive except in the formn of good or happiness to the agent, than there can be motive which is not motive." And again, " There can be 1no tendency to moral action, in a moral being, except ultimately to obtain happiness by acting; andi the greater the happiness known by the agent to depend on one kind of moral action, the greater thile tendency to that action." To the same effect, but even more emphiatically, Mr. Metcalf says: "It is a law imposed by 5* 10.5 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. an in vincible necessity of his nature upon every ratioial sentient, voluntary being, that in all his voluntary action he must seek happiness. To escape from the dominioni of this law is an absolute impossibility." These same Xotive tobe- writers teach that the true motive to benevovolence. len(e, or doing good to others, is in the perceiv ed adaptation of the action to promote the happiness of the agent. Says Dr. Taylor: "Were the agent wholly uniisusceptible to happiness from the happiness of others, and as, therefore, lie must be wholly indifferent to their happiness, he lmust be wholly indifferent to benevolence on his own part, as the means of their happiness." Aetealf maintains that the happiness of others is the objective end in benevolence- that which awakens desire; but that the -atisfaction of that desire, or the happiness of the agent, is the subjective end, in fact the only final motive. Tlhe happiness of others is soughlt, because it is the mieans of View ofbe- highest satisfaction to self. In his view, it is nevolence. benevolence to regard the good of others as the greatest good to self, and to pursue it for that reason. [In his own words: "The holiness of a holy being consists in seeking and finding his happiness in loving and serving and pleasing God, in contenml)lating and promnotimg the highest happiness, and of course the highest holiness, of all the subjects of his moral government." "This instinctive, innate, irresistible yearning, after good is the ultimate reason, the last reason that can be given for holy action." "The last subjective reason that can be g,ven for holy action is, that by this only can the agent's highest happiness be secured," and the suljective reason or motive is " the motive felt in the consciousness of the mind." Sin is seeking one's happiness in the wron way........only possible supreme 106 THFEORIES OF OBLIGATION. choice which we can make i,i regard to our seekiiig hal)p nesS, is to choose in which of these two methods -l whthle in benevolence or selfilness, in the right or wrong, we will seek it; in other words, to choose from what sources we will seek to derive our happiness, and on what ob- 3bligation jects we will place our supreme affections." andutility Obligation to benevolence or to any choice, according to this theory, is conditioned upon the usefulness of the choice, ultimately, and in fact to ourselves, but iimmedi ately in the promnotion of tihe direct object of the benev alence. Says Paley: "We canl be obliged to nothing but what we ourselves are to gain or lose something by." Says Dr. Taylor: "All the worth or value of lman or of any other moral being consists in his capacity of happiness, and of that self-active nature which qualifies him to produce happiness to other beings and to himself. Al] the worth, or value, or goodness, or excellence which pertains to action on the part of a moral being, is its fitness or adaptation to produce these results;" and this writei seems continually to confound the obligatoriness or right. niiess of an action with its worth, or value, or tendency to prodace good results. Indeed, he seems to have no 3ther conception of obligation. Says Mietcalf: "The intent and tendency of holy action to promote happiness, is the reason why it is, in and of itself, immediately pleasing, agreeable, and comely in the siglt of God and of all holy beings." This view of obligation has given the svstem the name of Utilitarianism; while its view of virtuous action, as in the last analysis, regard for self, self-gratification, has given it the name of the selfish systeilu Among the difficulties and errors pertaining to this view of obligation are the following:~ The mistake out of which all the others spring, is the .107 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. assumption that desire is the only motive to action. The funda- This is a preva-ent psychological error, and mental error. disfigures many systems of morals and of the logy. It is true that there can be no motive for action to a being destitute of sensibility-the susceptibility to good and evil; because to such a being there could be no cop ception of good, and hence no idea of obligation,which is the logical consequent of the idea of the good. A moral being must have a sensibility; but having, received the idea of good through the sensibility, that apprehended value becomes a motive for action, whether the good be in himself or another. It is true that the good, intel lectuall, apprehended, is calculated to awaken desireperhaps always does; but the final motive for virtuous action is not the desire, but is the value of the good as perceived by the intelligence —not its value to me as related to my desire, but its value absolute and in itself. According to the theory that desire is the only motive to action, there is no absolute good known to us but the good of self. The good of others is simply relativaegood in that it awakens desire in us, and the realization of the good gratifies that desire; thus it becomes a means of happiness to us. This is not the view a rational being has of the good of others. He judges of that good in the light of his own experience of good, and knows .hat the good of one like himself is the same as his own good, and has an absolute value. It is as obvious as aiy fact of reason that that good is to be respected on its own account, for its own value, independently of any desire that may be awakened,or may not be. The obliga tion to respect or choose it, is seen at once, even if there be no desire mnoving to the choice, or if all the desirei be against it. 108 THEORIES OF OBLIGATION. Thus, in apprehended value, there exists a source ol motive aside from desire of our own happi- Destroys fro ness,or any other desire, and this is the proper dom. motive to virtuous action. We have, then, two sources of motive to moral beings, and thus, and thus only, is provision made for moral fireedom. Here, then, is the ,econd obtjection to this system, that it leads logically and iievitably to necessitated action; not that its advocates deny the fieedom of the will: they are among its stannchest defenders. But if there be no possible motive but desire. there can be no freedom. Is it maintained that the fi'eedom lies in choosing between the desires, and gratifying this or that,at will?:But there must be a motive to this choice, and that motive must be some differ ence in the desires themselves, or some other desire that lies back of the choice. If the motive be in this third desire moving to the choice, there is no fieedom; for there is no power to get back of the desire and modify it. If the motive for choice be in some difference in the desires, and if desire is still the only motive, then that difference must be a difference in strength, and the strongest desire will control. If it be any other difference that determines the choice, it is a difference that appeals to the intelligence, as, for exanmple, the propriety or profitableness of the gratification of one desire rather than another, and thius we have at once a miotive for action aside from the desire. Some such ground of action there must be, or there is no escape from the domination of the strongest desire, or rather from the resultant of the desires. And such a ground of action there is in the consciousness of every man, so that he denies one ]esire and gratifies another, or denies both, all in obedi ence to his convictions of interes* or propri(ty, or duty 109 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. This difli,,lty pertains to the psychology of the system rather than its morality, and is by no means peeculiar to the upholders of this theory. An error, more strictly ethical, is in the character t;truptsbe- which the system ascribes to beiievolence e l ence. and here the appeal must be to the conscious knowledge of every man. Benevolence does not consist in doing good to mankind for the sake of everlasting happiness, or for the gratification of desire, near or remote, or for the sake of anything whatever, except the value of the good of mankind in itself. We feel and know that benevolence is vitiated when it looks,for a motive,bevond the good itself; to some satisfaction to be derived from the action. We call such an action prudence or shrewdness, not benevolence. It is true,beyond doubt, that there is such satisfaction to be derived from benevo,ence-a satisfaction higher than any other; but when hlat satisfaction is the motive, it fails at once, because benevolence has failed. "tIe that savethl his life shall lose it." Benevolence is choosing the good of mankind, and of all sentient beings, because of the value of their good, and the resulting satisfaction springs from the disinterested action. The good manlTaboring, zealously in a good cause, is Mistakes mo- not actuated by desires terminating finally tve oofand the on himself. Ile is not pursuing his own hapgood and t e z ad. i)iness as the sole motive. He puts his happiness in with the common interest, where it belongs, and finds it safe in the end. Still less is the bad man, in yieldng to his desires and passions, pursuing his own happiness o,r interest, iii any proper sense. Sinful action does not even involve the delusion or thought of pursuing one's own good, The theory, then, fails to explain the principle of 110 iI I i ii I t THEORIES OF OBLIGATION. action m the case of both the virtuous and the sinful. Ta yield to the control of desire is not to pursue happiness. The theorv fails to furnish ground for the differenoe 'between the good and the bad. Their subject- Provides for ive motive is the same-desire of happiness. no differenoe They differ in the means they use. But in the pursuit of an end, every man uses the means which commend themselves to his judgment, and can use no other; else he surrenders his end. The difference between the virtu- i ous and the sinful, then, niust be a difference of judgment, and sin is a mistake. The true difference is that the good man followis his convictions, and chooses the good of all; the bad man follows his desires, and neglects the good of all. The theory could never suggest the language of Scrilp ture, nor be suggested by it: " If any man Doesnotmeet will come after me, let him deny himself and Scripture. take up his cross and follow me. For whosoever will save his life shall lose it; and whosoever will lose his life for my sake shall find it." "If any man come to me and hate not his father, and mother, and wife, and children, and brethren, and sisters, yea, and his own life also, he cannot be my disciple. So likewise, whosoever he be of you that forsaketh not all that he hath, he cannot be my disciple." The theory is wrongo in making the utility of benevolence a condition of its obligatoriness. Be- Mistakes re lation of'itinevolence is seen to be obligatory at once ity. np(,n the apprehension of the good, without any thought (r consideration of the question whether the benevoencie will promote the good. Benevolence is a state of vil favorable to the good, regardful of it; it is not purpose to promote it. Such a purpose will spring from benevolence when it is ascertained that anything can be ill MORAL PHILOSOPHY done to promote it. But antecedently to all such thought or information, the obligation to choose the good because of its value, is clearly seen. This choice puts one in the attitude to promote the good, a readiness foi the work; but it precedes all purpose. Such is the pri mary, benevolent choice; and the obligation to it is grounded in the value of the good, not in any tendency in the action whatever, either to promote the good )f the agent or of any other b,in,. On the contrary, if there were positive knowledge on the part of the agent that his benevolence would yield no result, the obligation tc choose the good would still subsist in full foree. Indeed if he positively kInew that his benevolence would do harm instead of good, and should attempt to withhold his benevolence, this very act would still imply benevolence. Of course there is an absurdity in the refusal to be benevolent for such a reason; but the supposition shows that the obligation is independent of tendency. Any purpose to do good, or any executive action whatever could be restrained for such a reason; but the primary attitude of benevolence would still remain, implied ill the very withholding of the purpose. Hence, benevolence in its fundamental form, lies back of any purpose whatsoever. It is the voluntary attitude out of which good purposes grow, whenever they are seen to be proper. And here we mark a distinction between the ultimat Utility as re- benevolent choice, and all executive acts and lated to execttive actioa. purposes which spring from it, in the fact that obligation to benevolence arises immediately upon the perception of good, while the obligation to form purposes and put forth executive acts,does not arise until it is as. certained that such purpose or act will probably or possi 112 THE)RIES or oBLIGATION. bly be useful. The obligation to executive action is con ditioned uponl perceived useful tendeney; the obligationr to benevolence is independent of tendency. We are bound to be benevolent toward Sir John Franklin, lost in hlie Arctic seas; we are not bound to form any purpose, )r put forth any act, until we perceive a tendency in the ,urpose or act to help him. This distinction leads to a remark upon the second class of theories which make happiness the The termutl itarianism sole good, but find the grand motive for ac- misapplied tion, not in self-love or desire of good, but ill the value of the go(od wherever perceived. All good is to be chosen and pursued; and this choice of good is benevolence, which alone is virtuous action. Many writers have failed to disting,uish between these two classes of theories, and have applied to them both the term utili tarianism, which is no more applicable to the doctrine of benevolence,as set forth by President Edwards and President Finney, than to the transcendental views of Zen( or of Kant. It is true that some of the advocates of the doctrine of benevolence, as co,iprehending Occasion for the misappreall virtue, have, by their want of discrimina- hension.PP tion, exposed themselves to the charge of utilitarianism, and have even accepted the title as appropriate to the doctrine. Thus the younger Edwards, who maintained the true doctrine of benevolence, as set forth by his father, asks, " What is the primary reason that it is my duty to love my fellow-men? " and after considering, with great discrimination, the various answers given to the question, presents his own view thus: "I am obli rated to love my fellow-m-n, because that love tends to their happiness, and to the happiness of the intellectual eystem." He fails to discern that the love of which he 113 MORAL, PHILOSOPHY. speaks is not primary benevolence, but that course of action which follows it, the obligation to which does depend upon the tendency of the action. This is clear fi'om his next sentence: "But if love and attachment to an individual, ill any ease, as to a murderer, whose life and prosperity are ilnconsistent with general liappiness, tend to ilmpair the general happiness, I am not bound in that case to love him." How could so discerninus a mran deny the duty of benevolence towards a inurderer or any other being? He failed to discern the real nature of benevolence, as a disposition of mind lying back of all purpose to do 7ooc, and of all executive acti tn. That antecedent,benevolent disposition is as really obligatory toward a murderer as a saint; and is exercised in the effort to inflict the penalties due to him, as tr-uly as in showing mercy. Dr. Taylor,and the writers of his school,have made the same mistake, and thus have contributed to bring, the reproach of utilitarianism upon the noble doctrine of benevolence as set forth by the elder Edwards. It is not the worth, or value, or tenExcellence of deney of benevolence, that is its most signifibenevolencet cant characteristic, but its obligatoriness; and not in its utili~ty. its value, worth, tendency, depends upon its obligatoriness, ratller than its obligatoriness upon its value or tendency. No consideration of tendency or of usefulness ever enters into th,- original percepltion of the obligation of benevolence. It does enter into the estimate of the obligation of every subordinate act. I am to be be nevolent, or to love my neighbor because his g,od is aa absolute value, and therefore I see that it ought to be re garded in the heart; I must pursue thlis or that course ol life because it is useful, or tends to pro,mote the good. Tlfis distinction is clearly in our consciousness, and, prop 114 THEORIES OF OBLIGATION. erly c(,nsidered,would save from confounding the true doctrine of benevolence with utilitarianism. A modification of the idea that happiness is the sole good, and that obligation is seen only in the Combinatio. In ~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~f holinessi li,ght of this good, represents that simple hap- andhappines, piness is not the true good, but the happiness which re Aults from virtue, or " holy happiness," as President Hopkinis calls it. This is an attempt to blend the two distinct ideas of virtue and happiness into one comnpound which shall differ from both components. But they are still distinct. The good man is both virtuous and happy, and his happiness results greatly from his virtue; but the virtue is in the action of his will, and the happiness is a condition of his sensibility. The two things are so utterly unlike, that if one is ultimate good, the other is not. Both are ultimate in a very important sense, but in different ways. Happiness is ultimate as good, benevolence is ultimate as obligation. Virtue rests on its own intrinsic authority; but it exists only in reference to one fact, and is only seen in the light of that fact; that fact is happiness,or the good. If one kind of happiness is to be chosen rather than another, then happiness is not iltimate, but that is ultimate in the light of which the kind of happiness to be elosen,is determined. 115 orl CHAPTER XI. THEORIES OF OBLIGATION. WE will next consider some of the theories which find Of rightas ul- the ground of obligation in a standard, or )rin tiniate. ciple, or fact of ultimate right —this right itself haviing, no foundation, ald needing none. Back of this righit, our reason canTlnot go. The theories are vari ous, and have little ill common, except this fact of au ultimate ground of right,or law of duty, which is differ ent in the different theories. A popular notion of the foundation of obligation or Will of God duty is,thlat it originates in the will of Godthe origin of duty. that his command renders one tliino right, another wrong, and that there is no other known reason for the rightness or the wrongness; that the will of God does not merely indicate or reveal the right, but constitutes it. This view of the origin of morality is not maintained distinctly by any large proportion of ethical w-iiters but is held in a popular way by large numbei who have not been accustonied to any analytical tliouglit upoln such questions. With some limiitations and mnodifications, it is maintained by Paley, Warburton, RiellcTard Watson, Dymond, Chalmers, MIansel, and others. Among the modified forms of the doctrine, is tihe viewv Modification of Warburton, and perhaps of Manasel, tlll of the theory. there may be a distinction, in the nat'ure a thinigs,between right and wrong, which is appreciable in thought, yet it carries no force with it as law. There is THEORIES OF OBLIGATION. no obligation, or thought of it, except as imposed by God's command. Still another modification of the theory is, that obligation has its origin, not in the will of God, but in his infinite and perfect nature, or in his reason; that it is the province of reason to originate principles, inc not of will. The general argument by which the theory is sustained, is this, that obligation or duty implies a law, Mode of arand a iaw implies a law-giver, and this law- gument. giver is God. The same argument is often used to prove the being of God, firom the acknowledged fact of obligation, even by writers who do not refer the origin of obligation to the will or nature of God. The apparent force of the argument lies in the ambiguity) of the word law. One use of the word Its fallacy, is to express a fact or principle, or order of events, or a certain dependence and relation of things, without reference to any origin whatever. Thus we speak of the law of gravitation, the law of the binomial series, the law of obligation; and it never occurs to us that we imply a beginning of the law, or a lawgiver,in using the expression. There is no such significance in the word as thus used. It is only when we speak of law as a statute, an enactment by some legitimate authority, a part of the machinery of moral government, that it implies a lawgiver. The argument derives its apparent orce from the transfer of this sense of the word to the other case, where it has no proper application. Another form of the argument is that obligation im. plies an obliger; but this does not corre- Another form. spond with our consciousness. We affirm ob ligation without anythought or knowledge of one who imposes the obligation. It is dout tless true that the fact 117 MORAL PHI LOSOPHY. that duties are endorsed and eifoiced by the divine corn tialld, greatly adds to their force and authority withl us l;)it without any knowledge of such a fact, obligation still ,.xi,ts, and is recognized. The knowledge of God,and of iti law, adds the sense of accountability to that of obli 4ation, and gives vitality and power to duty; but this sho(uld not be mistaken for the origin of obligation. Among the obvious difficulties of the theory are the followingg: It fails to afford a foundation that satisfies our thotught. Not the ilti- A reason can be asked and given, why we mate reason. ought to obey God; and the attempt to rest upon his coimmand as ultimnate, is vain. ]Beibre we are aware, we find ourselves affirming) that God's will is right, that his law is "holy and just and good," that he is infinitely wise and good, and therefore his command must be righit, and ought to be obeyed. All this shows that we have in our tlhought somnethlilg back of thie mere will, upon which we depend. If G(o's will were utltimate, we could ask no reason, and offer none,wliy we should obey hinm. We know that love to our neighbor would be duty, Benevolence even if God should not require it; and in refoblilgatory in itself. erenee to many particular duties, we perceive first that they are duties, and then infer that God requires thtem. If duty originated iu his will, the order would always be reversed. If two beings like ourselves should exist alone in the universe, we can see that they would ,e boundl to respect each other's interests. God does not eate or origiliate the principle of obliatio,I.L. cieates moral beings and in tle er nature o tif e nase .the.come under the law of obligation. He does not create space, but he uses it in the disposition of the material 118 THEORIES OF OBLIGAT1ON. nniverse. le does not create geomnetry, but le "geollectrizes "-nor morality, but hlie establ)slises and lllaxilltlil his -overnmient in accordance with its princil)les. It iF no I)art of the honor due to God, to attribute to limi i,Ji i)(,ssi})ilities., AVWe speak of the goodness of God and believe in it \We have an idea of moral character in him, No bafi, tot and regarid that character as the perfection nes'. god of virtue. All tliis would be ipl)ossil)le to our tlhought -— incoueeivable. if we did not look beyond lhis will for the riglht. AVe could have no conception of his inorali character, and hlie could have no such character. Our idea of goodness in him shows that we have a standard of goodness outside of his will. God is holy, virtuous, because he is benevolent; lie meets o:)ligation. As a moral being' he comes under the great law of duty. Ile is not under authority or government, still he confor,si to the law of obligation, and thus is the object of our moral approbation. But here the modern believers in "the relativity of humiian kno-wledge" meet us with the ol)jec- Relativity of tion that we know morality, duty, obligation, morality. only for ourselves; that the law of obligation, as we know it, is relative, is obligation for us; of God we can make no affirmation of duty. Says M[ansel: "The fiction of an absolute law l)inding on all rational beings, has only an alq)arent universality, because we can only conceive other ra. tional beings by identifying thleir constitution with one 3Wll and inalking humian reason the measure ald represen ative of reason in general." A writer in the P'rincet(on [eoview makes a practical app)lication of this principle of relative moralitv. " The perennial fact in huinan j(]dg VCent, that God's nmoral administration of this world l]as al lig 3MORAL PIIILOSOPHY. ways seemed to human reason less perfect in justice than the n.oral standard which man sets up in each age as the criterion of moral conduct, seems conclusive that the finilte moral conceptions of man furnish no adequate type of the rule of God's conduct, whose ways are not as our ways, in his eternal administration over the life of man." Ift' these views were correct, then our thought of God's goodness would be but a fancy with which we atmuse ourselves, the reality of which is utterly beyond our knowledge. The principles of morality rest upon the Fami,( foundation as those of Mathemnatics, and all necessary truth. They are absolute truths-truie to us and to all rational beings. It is the nature of the truths in themselves, and not the nature of the faculties by which we apprehend them, that gives them their authority. The whole tenor of Scripture corresponds with this Correspond. view. It is always assumed that men have ence with Scripture. faculties to judge of God's character, and lihe submits to be judged upon the common principles of mora]ity. Of the modification of the doctrine, that obligation has Foundationin its origin in the reason of God, it is only nethe reason or natureofGod. cessary to remark that reason does not originate principles or truths, it only perceives those already iii existence. The reason of God must perceive and affirm obligation, and so does the reason of man. Of the statement that obligation originates in the nature of God, it does not seem unreasonable to say that the idea is too transcendental for ordinary comprehension. A few ethical writers find the standard of action, that Ofworthiness upon which obligation turns, in one's own as t;mnate. worthiness; and all questions of duty are, according to this view, to be referred to the bearing of 120 THEORIES OF OBLIGATION. the action on our worthiness of approbation,or of happiness. Thus, Kant, in his "Critique of Pure Reason," proposes three questions about which all interests gather: 1. What can I know? 2. What ought I to do? 3. What may I hope? The second question covels the field of morals, and his general answer to it is, "' Do that which will render thee worthy of happiness." This answer presents the germ of the theory in question, but it is not the theory which Kant himself adopts and expands in his system of ethics. Dr. Hickok, in his "Moral Science," adopts this view, making "the highest good, the summu. Hickok'! bonumr, worthiness of spiritual approbation." view. "Every man has consciously the bond upon him to do that, and that only, which is due to his spiritual excel.ency." "Every virtue finds here its end. Why he should be benevolent toward man, and why reverent toward God, have each the samne end-namely, then, and then only, is he acting according to that which is due to his spirit, and thlus worthy of spiritual approbation." "Every. where, in acting for spiritual worthiness' sake, I shall be fulfilling what I intuitively see to be the end of my spiritual being." The rules for action, according to this theory, are "the imperatives of the spirit's own excellency; " implying a faculty by which we discern directly, in every question of duty, what is consistent with our own worthiness. The following are among the difficulties of the theory The worthiness spoken of does not appear to be an ultimate good at all. It is a condition or re- Worthinesw not a ultl ai-d lation of a moral being, resulting from a cer- mate 6 1'21 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. tain course of action-the simple fact of his having met obligation. That fact is no ultimate good. It is a sine q?a non of blessedness, and hence is a relative good; but only the satisfaction itself is ultimate. But if worthiness be the ultimate good, the summ,u;n Dil leso bonum cannot be our own worthiness, but the vworthiness. worthiness of all moral beings. Our neig]libor's worthiness is of equal value with our own. Elow then, can we be worthy while living and acting with reference to our owvn worthiness? The true end must be the worthiness of all. If it be said that we secure our own worthiness by aiming at the worthiness of all, this is true, but it proves that the proper end is the worthiness of all, which is contrary to the theory. The theory inverts the dependence of worthiness and Order invert- of action. We determine our worthiness irl ed.w the light of our action, and not our action in the light of our worthiness. We first judge of duty, and, in performing it, have the consciousness of worthiness; while the theory requires us to determine our duty by a reference to the test of our own worthiness. We have no faculty for seeing duty in the light of our own worthiness, but we have the faculty of seeing our worthiness in the light of duty performed. Worthiness and unworthiness are incidental results of Worthiness moral action, but cannot be clearly thought not an aim in action. of as the aim in either kind of action. Worthiniess sustains the same relation to right action, that unworthiness does to wrong action. In either case the action is independent of that result. Practically the theory must have much the same bearing as that which grounds obligation on self-love. It tends to make all action and aL thought revolve about self To such self-centred ac. 122 THIEORIES OF OBLIGA11CX. tion the scriptural name love could never be given True virtue looks abroad, seeks not its own chiefly, cither in the form of blessedness or worthiness, becomes bothi worthy and blessed in its comprehension of all good This is the most obvious and conscious quality of vir tuous action. There is a modification of the Edwardean doctrine of benevolence which represents that virtue is Virtueas in itself a good. Happiness is a good, but highest good the choice of happiness is a greater good; the choice of happiness is virtue, the love of virtue is a higher virtue. Thus we have two objects of virtuous action; first the happiness of being, and secondly, and higher, the virtue of being. This view is attributed, by certain of his admi. rers and reviewers, to Edwards himself. The Attributed t( President Ed. ground of claim is that Edwards distinguishes wards. between primary love of being, or simple benevolence, and the love of virtuous being which involves moral approbation or complacency; thus: "When any one, under the influence of general benevolence, sees another being oi the like general benevolence, this attaches his heart to him, and draws forth greater love to him than merely his having existence." He goes on to say that this "comrnplacence" is but a form of benevolence, and necessarily springs from it. "Loving a being on this ground, necessarily arises from pure benevolence to being in general, and comes to the same thing." It is doubtless true that Edwards failed to distinguish clearly that love of comnpla cency differs from benevolence only in the addition of the illvoluntary, intellectual, and emotional element of approval of virtuous action. The psychology of his time had not clearly discriminated between the voluntary and involuntary in choices and emotions; but there is very 123 MORAL PHfILOSOPHY. little apparent ground for the idea that he reckoned this Complaeency a different style of virtue, higher than pure benevolence He expressly names this form of virtue benevolence. "A secondary ground of pv'ae benevolence," he says, "is virtuous benevolence itself,in its object." T)r. Hopk-ins, the pupil and friend of Edwards, recognizes the love of complacency as benevolence modified by the enmotion of approbation. He writes thus: "This love of benevolence does not exclude, but necessarily includes that whichl is called love of complacence; for he who is good, benevolent, and friendly, must delight in goodness." "Therefore a complacency and delight in holiness or moral excellence is always implied in holiness." "Therefore when we think and speak of holy love, benevolence should be the primary and chief idea in our minds, as being the sum of all, and implying the whole; for holy complacelncy, is complacency in benevolence, and a benevolent complacency. And if we leave benevolence out of our idea of the love of complacency, we have no idea of true holiness, nor understand the Scriptures where they speak of holy love in God or creatures." The ground of this complacency Edwards represents to be, a certain quality of excellewe or beauty in the virtuous being. " Virtue is the beauty of those qualities and acts of the mind that are of a moral nature, i. e., such as are attended with desert. or worthiness of praise or blame." This intrinsic quality of beauty in virtuous action, he often refers to, meaning of course the quality of moral rightness, which excites our approbation, in which virtuous action differs fhoniom all other things. These views of Edwards and Hopkins have been exAndover panded into what we may be permitted to heory. call the Andover theory of virtue, as repre~ 121 TIILORIES OF OBI,IGATION. sented by various writers in the "Bibliothcca Sacra," as follows: * "Accordingly there are two diNisions of viituie; the love of benevolence, or good will toward being viewed as capable of happiness or holiness, or both; and the .ove of complacency, or good will toward beings viewed as holy. The love of benevolence is exercised on account of, and in proportion to the susceptibilities or capacities of sentient being; and the love of complacency is exercised on account of, and in proportion to,the holiness of being. The love of the general happiness is a good in itself; and does not derive its goodness merely from its being a nmeans of the general happiness. The love of the general holiness is also a good in itself, and does not become such by its mere conduciveness to some other end. The greatest good in the universe is holiness, although, in point of time, the last good aimed at is the general happiness. In kind, the highest of the specific virtues is the love of comnplacency, although, in the order of the growth, the root of all other virtues is the love of benevolence. In point of dignity and worth, the chief end, which is a good in itself, is the love of geneial holiness; but in the order of development, the final object of pursuit, the last but not the best, is the general happiness." Another of these writers speaks as follows: t According to this theory, virtue is the highest good in the universe, though the general hap. iniess is the last or ultimate end of virtue." " This hig' est good secures, or is that in which consists,the higher, tappiness of the universe. In its primary form it ha, happiness for its immediate object; in its secondary forn t has the love of happiness for its immediate object and in its highest formn it has the love of the love ol happiness, a. e., the love of complacency, for its inmmedi VoL X., p. f Vol. XXII., pp. p84, . * Vol. X., P. 72& t Vol. XXII., pp. 484, 485. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. ate object. In one sense this last form of virtue is iti highiest forni,." But not feeling quite sure-tooted in these transcendent regions, the third heavens of virtue, the writer feels for a firmer foundation in the following sentelice: " Still, this love of complacent love, is virtue only M it is an emnanation fiom, and so involves benevolence o iove of happiness." This is solid ground. In reference to this view of virtue as having a two-fold or three-fold nature, the following suggestions may be offered: Complacent love differs from benevolence only in the Nature of additional element of approbation of charac complacency. ter. This approbation is not strictly volun tary. It involves the intellectual apprehension of virtuo as praiseworthy, and a feeling of delight in the contempla tion of it. This intellectual and emotional exercise is experienced more or less in every human soul, even where benevolence does not exist; but whatever the degree, it is not virtue. It is the involuntary testimony of human nature to the excellence of virtue. All our responsibility .n reference to it is, to take the attitude of benevolence; then the complacency arises when virtuous character is the object of contemplation. A benevolent attitude is favorable to comnplacency, because it puts one in sympathy with the virtuous character contemnplated, and gives a better understanding of it. This is the love of complacency, as the term is generally used. In this sense complacency must be proportioned to the holiness of the char,cter contemplated. This is manifestly the sense in which Edwards and Hopkins use the term, and this is the sense of the writers quoted. What is there virtuoiiis in the exercise, except the benevolence? and what proprieta in reckoning it a distinct type of virtue? With equal 1. "f) ruEOR1IES OF OBLIGA'TION. propriety might justice, and mercy, and gratitude, and veracity be distinct types, being benevolence modified by special perceptions and emotions. But admitting that complacency is a distinct form of virtue, what authority have we for reckoning Not a higher it a higher form than simple benevolen,e? foinmofvirtaoue Is it obviously a higher attainment, or reach of virtue, ti) love the virtuous than to love the sinftil? "Peradventure for a good man some would even dare to die; but God commendeth his love toward us in that while we were yet sinners Christ died for us." The love connected with displacency, the love of the sinful and of enemnies, seems, according to Scripture, to take the lead; but ac cording to the writer quoted, the love of the general lioli ness stands first "in point of dignity and worth;" noc the cAoice of the general holiness, for such a choice is benevolence, not complacency, and is proportioned to capacity for holiness, not to the possession of it. "First n dignity and worth; " but what is the dignity and worth of virtue, but its virtuousness? and is the virtuousness of love for the deserving, greater than of love for the undeserving? Where is the authority, and what is the standard? Undoubtedly the immediate subjective satisfaction in the love of the virtuous, is greater than in the love of the sinful; but the pleasantness of a virtuous exercise cannot be the test of its dignity or worth. And if the love of benevolence is higher than benevolenee, and the love of the love higher than Ascending s the love, why stop at this third degree? The ne law developed seems to indicate an endless, ascending series in the scale of virtue. We are constrained to think that we have here the results of a misdirected logic, 127 MORtAL PHIIILOSOPIIY. and not the content of consci( asness. But such error in result indicates error in the premises. This error seems to begin in the confusion of using the Conflusion in term good as applicable both to virtue and to theterm ngood. happiness. Both are called good, different in kind, to be sure, but alike in such a sense that they can )e compared together, and virtue pronounced the higher or greater. HIence, as there are two kinds of good, there must be two kinds of virtue, and that the higher which has the higher good as its basis. But now we encounter another confusion. Consistency would require that as one style of virtue is choice of happiness, a voluntary act, the love of being, so the other should be the choice of virtue, also a voluntary act; but this choice, too, would terminate on being, and be only benevolence, as these writers seemn to admit. Hence, it is called love of virtue, and the clear thought is lost in the ambiguity of the word love. In logic it is the voluntary exercise called love which is required; in consciousness it is the emotional exercise whick is yielded; and thus that which by the reasoning is a virtue, is in thought not a virtue, but an involuntary exercise. But, then, is not virtue an ultimate good? Yes, in the Senseiro only sense in which action can be good-in which virtue Is good. the simple sense of virtuous, meritorious, praiseworthy. It is also good in the sense of promotive of happiness, subjectively and objectively; thus it is a relative good, a means of happiness; lort its virtuousness, its moral goodness, its beauty, as Edwards uses the term, does not consist in, nor depend upon,this adaptation to produce happiness. This peculiar characteristic is its rightness, its satisfaction of obligation; and if we call it good, we must so define the term as to designate this pe 128 THEORIES OF OBLIGATION. culiar quality, or we are at once involved in confusion Only in this sense of the term good, is it an objeet of complacency; in any other sense it is but the object,or rather instrument, of benevolence. But in this sense it is not an object of ultimate choice at all; it Virtue a qnal S propellv a quality of that choice. or, more not its objetct. oosely, the choice itself as exhibiting the quality; the choice must terminate on the good of being, and thus it becomes right, virtuous, beautiful. In this view it is an object of complacency, of intellectual approbation and emotional satisfaction, not of virtuous choice. Ilappiness is good, virtue is right; and the two admit of no comparison in the way of competition, to determine the greater or the less. The choice of the good of being is virtue, and that choice is obligatory to every moral being absolutely, unconditionally, while in the use of his ra tional faculties. Thus virtue has a su-e foundation in the nature of things, irrespective of its tendency. Virtue is right in itself, and happiness is good in itself; and they are inseparably connected in the fact that the only conceivable virtue is the choice of happiness or regard for being. The view which is sometimes called the Rightarian theory, finds the foundation of obligation in Abstract right the nature of things, and finds also in man asultimate. moral reason, a faculty by which the nature of things is perceived with reference to obligation. It holds that action in accordance with the nature of things is seen to be right and obligatory, and that no reason for the right ness can be given beyond the fact that it is, and is seen to be; that this rightness of the action is the reason foi 6* 129 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. its obligatoriness,and the chief motive for its performance The theory maintains that obligation is apprehended in reference to a variety of objects, and in connection w;thl many different relations of the nmoral agent, and thas we have a variety of virtuous courses or actions, independent of each other, and having nothing in common except the fact that they are in accordance with the nature of things; thus the good of being ought to be chosen, truth ought to be respected, gratitude toward a benefactor ought to be exercised, virtue ought to be loved and rewarded, crime ought to be detested and punished, an honest man trusted, the parent honored and obeyed by the child, the child protected and guarded by the parent, God reverenced and honored by his creatures, and so through all the different natural relations. In each particular case the duty rests on a special foundation, something in the nature of the case, and is seen directly in its own light. The view is, that we are not left in general to inquire into the tendency and probable results of the action, but duty is seen at once without reference to consequences. The maxim of the theory is, "do right for Maxim and the sake of the riht," and its fundamnental axiom of the theory. axiom is, that everything ought to be treated according to its nature. This view is maintained, with special forms of statement, by the great majority of writers on morals, and is perhaps the prevalent doctrine of the Christian world. After what has already been said, only a few suggestions need be offered. The fundamnental axionm is true in a special sense. Axiom exam- Good,well-being,ought to be treated accordned. ing to its nature. But in the whole range of thought or experience,there is no other object which sug. gests the thought of obligation as to its treatment. No 130 THEORIES OF OBLIGATION. other object has a nature calling f(,r any special treat ment. The element of truth in the axiom is,that natura; good, happiness, must be respected because of its nature But we can stand face to face with truth, and beauty, and intellect, and will, and body, and space, and tinie, and eternity, without the thought of obligation, until sen tient being, with its capacities and wants, comes before us. There is nothing in the nature of anything else to call for any action whatever, except as it comes into relation with sentient being. The good of being is seen to be flt to be regarded on its own account, and in the light of it we perceive obligation and understand the nature of virtuous action. The particular duties of gratitude, veracity, reverence, confidence, justice, mercy, and the like, as we Special virtues have a common nave seen, are not so many independent foundation. forms of virtue, each with its special foundation in the nature of things, but they are merely the forms which benevolent action takes in different relations, and modi fled by different intellectual and emotional elements. Primary duty is seen directly, as the theory claims, without any inquiry as to consequences or tendencies; but the only duty thus seen is the all-compre- Are not seen ..!, 1. r n..,}. ~~independenthensive duty of benevolence. This in fact is ly. the only duty that exists, the only absolute ultimate right; but the various directions which benevolent action should take, all subordinate duties, are determined by ai knowledge of tendencies and probable results. Sucl knowledge is our only guide to practical duty. There is, in the theory,no provision for that unity of virtue which the Scripture recognizes. Be- No unity of nevolence, or the love which is the fulfilling virtue. of the law, is only one amoing a multitude of independ 13 i. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. ent obligations, and is the only one to which ithe term love is appropriate. If the theory in this respect be true the Scripture statement given in so many different fcrmsi can only be received as a figure of speech. The grand motive for action is not the rightness mghtnes1 not of the action, but is the value of the good iL amotive. view of which obligation is perceived. Riiglit ness is a quality of the action, but the motive for action is in the nature of the object contemplated, whichl sug. gests obligation; and that is the value of the good. The proper maxim for action is not, to do right for the Maximexam, sake of the right, but to choose good and do lned. good for the sake of the good. The right is a mere relation, an abstraction, for the sake of which nothing can be done; the good is a living, breathing interest addressing itself to every power and susceptibility of our nature, for the sake of which it is possible and right t( live and to do. The first of these maxims leads to fatnati. cisin. It conveys the impression that there is a righteous ness which is above respect to particular and, perhaps, minute interests-that has its eye on a right which is a sure guide, for ever the same, unmodified by changing circumstances and contingencies. The man who adopts the maxim is wont to appeal to the eternal principles of rectitude in justification of his questionable course, and exhorts others to "do right if the heavens fall," carefil to allay their misgivings, however, with the assurance tha the heavens will not fall. The other maxim tends to secure a just respect for all interests, and makes the careful, considerate man, for whose benevolent regard no being, or good, is too low or too high. But what is meant by "acting from triinciple?" Are there not fixed principles of action, which are to be out 132 THEORIES OF OBLIGATION. guide, forever fight and subject to no contingencies I Yes, the principle of benevolence is such a Acting from principle, and out of that springs the principle principle. ol obedience to the will of God-a duty as unchangeable as the duty of benevolence and the divine nature. \Where the will of God is specifically expressed, there is no room for inquiring, except to ascertain that will. But in general, the expression of his will is in terms as brortd as the duty of benevolence-love to God and man;a and iVe are left to judge, in the midst of multiform interests, whlat course benevolence requires. By immediate instincts, by judgment, and by experience, we settle certain general rules of conduct, which we call principles, and l)y which, in general, we govern our li e. Among these are the duties of respect for property and life, of obedience to au thority in the family and in the State, of simplicity and truthfulness in communication with our fellow-men; but such principles derive all their authority from their rela. tion to the duty of benevolence; and, from time to timne. as circumstances change, we are o' liged to limit or miod ify the practical principle, in obedience to the higher, unchanging law of benevolence. To act thus, is to act from principle-the only eternal principle that exists. Lastly, the rightness which is supposed to be ultimate in thought and in fact, is not ultimate. Rightness not Rightness is conformity to law, and the law ultimate. is the perceived obligation, and obligation arises only in the presence of the good. The good is thus the founda tioni of the right. We always ask and give a reason for the rightness of an action; and that ever recurring reasoni is, the value of the good of being. In concluding this brief discussion of the foundation of obligation, it may be remnaked. that the the,)ry of beney 133 IMORAL PHILOSOPHY. olence as comprehending all vilrtue, and having its foan Incidental ad. dation inl the immutable nature of tllingh vantage. has this to recommend it, in addition to its intrinsic reasonableness, that it combines the leading ideas of the two great classes of philosophers. It accepts th( doctrine of the utilitarians, that all ultimate good is in the satisfaction of sentient being; that is, all good whiclh is an object of ultimate regard or choice. At the sanme time, it holds, with all classes of anti-utilitarians, that the foundation of obligation is in the nature of things, and that virtuous action is obligatory, independently of all tendencies and relations. It avoids the tendencies of the selfish system, which corrupts benevolence by presenting desire of happiness as the only motive of action; and of the utilitarian system, which at the best degrades virtue illto the position of a mnere servant of lial)l iness, having no authority, or excellence, or worth, exc.el t as it tends to promote happiness; while on the other hand, it presents no cold abstraction called right, the measure and the end of virtue, which robs it of its warmith and soul. The virtue which the theory provides for, is warni with all living sympathies, having an ol)ject which the soul embraces with perennial interest, and works for with a strength cheerfully expended, but always renewed. It is the love which fulffis the law. 134 I PART IL PRACTICAL ETIICS. PRELIMINARY REMARKS. TrE enqniry in this department of morals pertains to olliga,;iDn, orduty, in particular circumstances Gener,al,tit and relations. The grand primary duty of ment. benevol(nce is already determined; it remains to ascer tain thc' outward fbrms which benevolence assumes in the various relations of life-not that a knowledge of these things is a pre-requisite to the meeting of obligation. Every person in the exercise of the faculties of moral agency is in a condition to meet his obligation. Hie can exercise and maintain the benevolent temper of mind. without any knowledge of outward or practical duty; but that benevolent disposition at once puts him upon the work of ascertaining outward duty, the ways and means of serving God and his fellow-men. The pursuit of such knowledge, then, is the necessary dictate and outgrowth of benevolence, and neglect of it is utterly inconsistent with benevolence. In this enquiry we are not looking for any standard of abstract right, which shall indicate duty in each particular relation. The sole principle to guide us is the good of being; and in every case the final enflliiry is, what will advance the general in- Knowledge o, practical terests? Of course, knowledge of practical duty. duty, to finite beings, must be contingent, not absolute MORAL PHILOSOPHY except where there is an express divine revelationi, indi eating the duty. In many cases the duty is so clear as to admit oif no doubt; in others, honest, conscientious and intelligent men will differ, and the judgment of the Christian world will vary, from age to age. It might seem convenient to have more perfect knowledge, but it is not necessary to the complete fullfilment of duty. "Who does the best his circumstance allows, Does well, acts nobly, angels could no more." It is necessary that the knowledge of fundamental duty should be absolute, and admit of no contingency; but the knowledge of subordinate duty may, in some cases, be dim, and uncertain, and varying, without involving any necessary failure in moral character. Such, in fact, is our condition in this world. Coming to the work with a benevolent heart, we are in an attitude most favorable to a knowledge of objective duty. The subjects cf which we propose to treat may be conSubjects tobe vt'niently arranged under the general dividiscussed. sions of Government, and Personal Rights and Duties; not that these divisions are perfectly distinct, and exclusive each of the other, but they afford such a grouping of topics as will serve our purpose. The field is of indefinite extent, and an attempt to cover the whole must be vain. 136 FIRST DIVISION. CHAPTER I. GOVERNMENT-ITS NATURE AND FOUNDATIOCN. GOVERNMENT is a systematic arrangement,for the exer cise of power and authority over moral beings, to secure their conformnity to obligation, and thus promote the individual and general well-being. In every government there are two parties-the person or party that governs, called the ruler, or simply the gov ernment, and those who are governed, called subjects The authoritative expression of duty is called law-somelimes positive or objeetive law, to distinguish it from the great principle of obligation in the nature of things, wvhich may be called al)solute law, and from apprehended duty as affirmed in the reason, called subjective law. The motives which the government brings to bear in en forcing duty are called sanctions. These are of two kinds, rewards, and punishments, or penalties. In general, penalties are most conslpicuous; the reward of obedieni(e consisting chiefly in thie enjoyment of the adrantages secured by the government. It is somewhat comimon to speak of sanctions as an essential part of the 'aw; and hence, it is often said that a law without sanetions is no law. It seems more simple to regard the mnere authoritative expression of duty as law, and sane MORAL PHILOSOPHY. tions as a part of the necessary machinery of government, without which it is no governmenet. The proper end of goverinment is the promotion of the Object of gov- good of all concerned in it, by seculring, to a ernnment greater or less extent, conformity to obligation. It exists not for the pleasure or benefit of the governing party alone, but chiefly for the advantage of the subjects of the goverinment-really for all. in its adaptation to secure these interests, we find the its right to right of a goverinment to exist. Finite beings, exist. cotuing( into relations with each other, whether well or ill disposed, require some regulative authority to provide for the general good, and guard and limit ilidividutal interests. This is the siiiiple ground upon which any government can claim a right to be; and if this neressity should cease, the government ought to terminate. Its furthler existence is an impertinence. No one can have a right to govern moral beings simply for his own pleasure or amusement. Who has the rig,ht to govern? Manifestly, he who The right to possesses such qualifications, and occupies goveri. govern such a position, that he can best secure the ends of governmient. These qualifications extend te moral character, and to mental and physical endowmlents -everything( that will contribute to one's power as a ruler. Proper position involves such conspicuity in the one iwho affects to rule, that the subjects of the government will most naturally concede to himn the right t( govern. The duty to govern, in general, accoinpalies the right. Dulty to gov- The possession of such qualifications is a emn. power for good, and the refusal to employ that po,,wer is a failure in duty. The power to goveir 138 GC VERNMENT-ITS NATURE AN'D FOUNDATION. 139 gives the right, and implies the duty to govern. In the family, the parents have not only the right to govern, it is their dutv as well. The same is true of the teacher in the school, and of the ruler in the state; neither teacher nor ruler can abdicate his authority without a failure in duty. There is no fixed and universal method by which th ruler is to be designated. He may be indi- Ruler, how cated by his position, or by the possession of designated qualifications so pre-eminent as to admit of no challenge. Thus parents stand in the family, and the teacher in the school. Or, one may have in himself such conscious strength and ability as to make it safe for him to assume the government; as in the case of a skillful navigator on dhip-board in a storm, in the midst of a disorganized crew, or a well-disposed and vigorous man in a group of quarrelsome boys. They need to be governed, and he feels competent to the task; he needs no other charter. One may come legitimately to the government by birth, as in a hereditary monarchy. In such a case, position stands before other qualifications, and is made by the thought and habits of the people the chief element in the power to govern. Among those essentially equal in ability and position, the natural mode of designating the ruler is Amon by election. Such a designation gives posi- equalB tion and power to govern, and therefore the right. It is only in a case of extreme necessity,that any qualification whatsoever in another, will indicate that he should gov ern,iiistead of the one elected. That form of government is legitimate which is bes adapted to answer the end of government, Form of gov under all the circumstances of the case. It is ernment. VMORAL PHILOSOPHY. not self-evident, nor even probable, that one form of gov ernment is under all contingencies the best. That gov. irnment is relatively the best, which, on the whole, best promotes the interests of its subjects; it may be a democracy, a monarchy, limited or absolute, or even a military despotism. Whatever, under the circumstances, is best, is legitimate, and needs to offer no apology for its existence. A change of conditions may make another form better. The extent to which the authority of a government Extent of may reach, is to be determined by the wants authority. of the community to which it pertains, and by its ability to meet those wants. In general, the right to control extends no farther than the interests of the subjects demand. A parent has a right to control his family,to the extent of the interests of the famnily, and no farther. Any authority beyond this,transcends the legiti mate scope and purpose of government. In order to the right of a government to exist, it ip Right not in not necessary that all who are to be its sub desire. jects should desire it, nor even that any should. It is enough that they need the government, and that there is one who can govern to their advantage. It is often a duty to do for others what they need to have done,without their consent, and even against their will; as to rescue one who, on the point of freezing, chooses to sleep, or to save one who purposes suicide. The less the children of a family or the pupils of a school, desire to be governed, the more they need it. The right to govern on the one part, implies the duty of obedience on the other. The right and the duty are correlatives; each implies the other. The principal governments in which we are concerned 1 N GOVERNMEFNT-'TS NATURE ANAD FOUNDATION. 14] &re the Divine government, Civil government, and Family government. These are permanent Leading go. and universal; there are others which are ernments. temporary, limited in their application, as in thle case of associations for business, or for literary or religious pur poor. CHAPTER II. THE DIVINE GOVERNMENT. THE Divine government embraces as its sul)jectf all [ts constitu- finite moral beings, and the authority of the fion. government extends to all their moral conduct; hence the government is, in every sense, universal. The head of this government is God, who in his own person exercises all the functions of government-legislative, judicial, and executive. Thus he is absolute Monarch no constitution limits his authority, and he receives no counsel firom his slub-jects in aiiy form. HIe needs none, either in himself, or for the satisfaction of his stlubjects. Any participation, o)n the psrt of finite beings, in the gov. f (nlent,'woIIld not add to our confidence in the government, but detract fi'om it. God assumes thle government, not simply because he What aie not is the Creator, and therefore has a right to do the reaions. vwhiat lie will with his own. In a very iml ortant sense hle owns the universe; but there is no sicli ownership of moral beings possible, as makes it preper to dispose of them arbitrarily, without reasonable regard to their good. God never claims the right to appoint arbitrarily, without due reason, the destiny of his creattuoes. Nor merely becaluse he is good does he claini the riglht to govern. There are other good beings in the nni. verse, but they have no such right. Good'iess is one of the qualifications, but that alone does not confer the right. The duty would exist without the goodness; he wnld THE DIVINE GOVERN-IENT. be under obligation to become good, and to establish a righteous government. God governs the universe because it needs to be governed, and because he, and he alone, is per- What are tLe fectly able to govern. These two facts would reason. constitute him ruler, even if he were not the Creator rhe fact of his being Creator demonstrates his qualifications-reveals him to man as the infinite and perfect, capable of universal dominion. Hie does not ask the consent of his creatures to his exercise of authority. Hlis right to govern rests on no such contingency. Hle assumes the government, and requires the obedience of his sub jects. All moral beings are constrained to acknowledge his right to govern, and their own duty to obey. The law which God proclaims and enforces, is the moral law-the law of nature and of reason. The The divine great principle of obligation he does not cre- law. ate. It exists in the nature of things, is affirmed in his own reason, and re-affirmed in every finite reason. As thus existing in the reason, it is law-subjective law, a real expression of obligation; and conformity to it would be virtue. God adds to this original principle of obligation the authority of his own will, and pubishbes and enforces it throughout the moral universe. It thus becomes the law of God, having a vitality and impressiveness to his creatures, indefinitely greater than that of any abstract principle. This expression of his will is found in the constitution of his creatures, in the course of hi providence, and in his written word. The knowledge of God's existence and attributes, )rings to men, from their own moral constitu- How knowv ticn, the conviction that he holds them ac- to men. countable for all their moial conduct. The ap)prehension 143 MOR AI. PIIILOSO'IIY. of accountability is not strictly intuitive, like that of ob ligation; but the conviction of it fastens upon the sou, with an authority which it can never throw off, however at may resist ]ien do not need an express announcement that this accountability extends to every thought, words aind deed-all their moral life the knowledge of God's character, and of their dependence upon him, brings with it this conviction. Children look to parental authority for q vindication of the common principles of humanity and morality. No child could complain, if punished for an %ct of cruelty, or an immorality, that the parent had not expressly forbidden it. The relation itself, in which he is placed, leads him to expect such supervision of his life, and to regard all matters, seriously affecting charac ter and conduct, as embraced, of course, in parental law. So men instinctively look to God, when once they know nim, as their guardian in reference to all matters of obligation. In virtuous action they expect his favor, in sin they dread his frown. Thus they apprehend that the law of nature and of reason, the law of obligation, is the law of God. All this is true to thoughtful mninds, even without what we call revelation. But his written word cometi with its clear utterances, the published law of God's gov. eminent, and removes all excuse even from the thoughtless. The revealed law we have in the decalogue, the ten commandments. These express, not the ab stract principle of obligation, but the law of duty in its application to the great interests of life-the lawc in a concrete form. The general method is to sug gest the great classes of duties by leading examples. Thusn in the fifth commandment, honor to parents is expressed, and duty in all similar relations is implied. In the sixth, 14 THE DIVINE GOVERNMENT. murder is expressly forbidden, and all malicious injury to life or limb is prohibited, by implication; and so throughout the decalogue. In this form the law is adapted to the comprehension of the unreasoning, serving all the purposes of an abstract, comprehensive statement of obligation, and of a definite, specific expression of objective duty. The later revelation presents the law in the more comprehensive form of love to God, and love to our neighbor; and again in the practical, suggestive form, called the golden rule: "As ye would that men should do to you, do ye even so to them "-a maxim which furnishes a stand-point from which our duties to men are to be viewed. At last we have the expression of duty in its simple, subjective form: "Love is the fulfilling of the law,"-implying that the attitude of mind required, toward God and toward men, is essentially the same, and '.hat virtue is one thing and only one-benevolence. It E worthy of remark that in every one of these forms, in which the law of God is embodied, sentient being alone is made the object of regard. Every precept expressing duty, every prohibition forbidding crime, directs the thought to God or man. We have no abstract right or truth set up as an object of respect, but every command is warm with living interests, presenting the great object upon which obligation centers. The authority of examples, the actions of good men as recorded in the Bible, extends to the principle Authority of of action alone-subjective duity, not objective. examples. Abraham was obedient, walking according to his light We are to take his life as an indication of his spirit, and cherishing the same spirit, must walk according to our light. So of all the good men of the Bible: their outward life is not our guide, but their inward obedience 7 145 MORAL PIILOSOPHY. The good mian, under our clearer lighlt, can l)e as good as tlhe faithful of olJi only by l)resentitg a better outward lite. Is it not possible that a similar principle applies even rhe Sa viour's to the Saviour's example? In appearing efafuriu. aluolig men, his outwar-d conduct niust be suchl as could coimmend itself to the judgineLit ot' the gool around him. In order to this, he miust walk by li,lght accessible to themi, not by his own clearer vision. Upon any otlher pIiineil)le tlhai this, his charaeter woull have been misunderstood, and his coniiduct would have raised questions not pertinent to his mission. lie camne to exhibit the spirit of love and obedience. It was just as necessary that his lite should take on bforms .whlichl the people could comprehend, as that he should speak to tlemn in a languag,e which they understood. llis lite was such as the best of his time would approve. It is not certain that his style of dress as a inan or his work as a carpenter, should be accepted by us as a model, or that we should use wine because he made and used it. Though gifted with infinite knowledge, he was obliged in a great degree to conform his outward life to human judgment. The world was not sufferi-ing for light in referencee to outward dlty, but for motives to inward righteousness. We imitate the Saviour, then, by partaking of his spirit of benevolence, and walking by the light we have. It is to be observed that obedience to the divine law Genuine vir- iS genuine virtue; that its requirements refer tue required. primarily to the internal moral state, and secondarily to the outward conduct. The law is satisfied with the inward obedience, not with any outward conduct vhatever. In this respect it differs from all human laws 146 THE DIVINE GOVER-NMiENT. The illlmediate object of human law is the outward con. duct; it is satisfied with conformity in this re&,pect,with)ut reference to the moral state. "Man looketh on the ,utward appearance, but the Lord looketh on the heart." We sometimes hear that physical law is a part of the aw of God, and ought to be obeyed. The Physical law, .anguage implies great confusion of thought. notmoral. Physical law is simply the mode in which forces act in the natural world, or the order of events in the relation of cause and effect. It is a fact which is to be considered in our judgment of outward duty. The facts of our physical constitution, the laws of life and health,as they are called, are of account to us, and call for attentionare to be taken for what they are worth in determininig duty. But every law which ought to be obeyed, wlicli involves the idea of obligation, is a moral law. Physi cal law contains no ougqt. If it is merely intended that the laws of our physical constitution are always to be con formed to, so as to secure the highest health and the longest life, even this is not a universal truth. The moral law often leads us where health and life are sacrificed. It sends the gospel missionary to a malarious climate, the soldier to the battle-field, the martyr to the stake, and lays upon men, in the work of every day burdens which crush their strength and shorten their days. The law of God is strictly personal; it addresses every one on the ground of his own personality, Personality o and adapts itself completely to his condition thelaw. and circumstances. It has no average standard of duty, adapted to families, or ages, or races; and the final ap Dointmient of good or evil is not made to men in gr'oiups or by nations, but with a discrimination which takes note 1.1.7 MORAL PHILOSOPHTY. )f personal character. Yet there is a sense in wllich the dlivitie government peirtains to famrilies and nations, ini Application their collective (chIaaecter. Tlicse have a kinld (, famnilios rnd nations. of iunity, a continuous collective lite, trans. tllitted from generation to generation. The individual ']hat c(nilpose the family, or the nation, pass away;but tlteis succeed to thleir places, sustain similar relations nd responsibilities, and atdopl)t the practices and princiI)les of' actioni, and thus endorse the deeds of those who hiatve p)receded tlem. Thus, in a oeneral wa, we attriI)lit to the British nation, or to the French, the charactei, and acts even, which have been exhibited in their Jistory during several generations. We refer them to no individual, but to the nation at large. In a simiilar manner, God, in his word, speaks of the Jewislhi people, and of otler nations, and clarges upon them sins which, in their specific f,rmn, had been coimnuitted( ages before. But the sin lead never been put away; no amends h]ad even neen atteripted, and the people still held to thle same general course. A nation may adopt a system of injustice or oppression, and transmnit it, as we have seen in our own land, from generation to generation, becoming thus a nation of oppressors. The guilt is all personal, as all sin must be. The sin of the nation is but the aggregTate of the individual sin; it characterizes the nation, and it is a part of God's administration to s]how his disapprobation of such nations, that other nations may be instruceted. The yations dealt career of nations is limited to this wvorld, and xilh in this world. the display of the divine judgment upon nations must be made here. The catastrophe may be long ]eifrred, blut it comes at lengtl, and bring,s retribution fobr the sins of generations; thus God " visits the iniquities of the fathers upon the children to the third and fol'th L48 THE DIVINE GOVERNMAIENT. generation of them that hate him." Still the guilt is all individual; and in the final allotlment of the dcstiiiies of men, this national sin will be distributed to its })rol)el owners. " The son shall not bear the iniquity of tlifalther, neither shall the father bear the iniquiity of tl)( son. The righteousness of the righteous shall be uipo him, and the wickednes-s of the wicked shall be upon him."" WThat is properly called a national sin imust have some specific outward formn, either sanctioned by v atiai < Nati(- Hal sins. the government, or sustained by general society, or both. But one may share in the national sin, who has had no connection with it in outward form. It; in any respect, he has failed in obedience to the divine law, he lias,so far,presented an examnple of disobedience. Thus he gives his sanction, in the most effective form, to any wrong to whilch the people may be inclined, and strength ens and extends the national sin. Hence, the duty of repentanice for national sins, and confession of them, pertains to every member of the community who has not "a conscience void of offence toward God and toward men." It I CHAPTER III. ?ENALTIES JUNDER THE DIVINE GO)VERNMEl'T. PENALTY is evil inflicted by the government upc: L a Nature of transgressor, as an expression of his guilt or penalty. ill-desert. The object of the penalty is, in general, to sustain the government and the law, and thus to suil)seirve the public good. The effect of the penalty is two-fold: First, it induces Primary fear, the apprehension of similar evil in the effect. case of transgression. The immediate effect of fear as a motive, is to secure an outward conformity to the law. Thus, Burns says: "The fear of bell's the hangman's whip, To haud the wretch in order." Such outward confo)rinity secures thie end of humnan gov. ernment, but in the divine, outward conformity is no obedience. True virtue cannot result immediately from fear, but indirectly it may. Fear leads to reflection, and reflection often leads to a renunciation of sin, and the practice of virtue. Hience, the fear of punishmnent is a proper consideration to urge upon the thoughtless and the waywarld. But a second and much more important effect of pensecondary alty, is to make an impressive exhibition of effect. the nature and ill-desert of sin, and thus lead to its renunciation. The guilt of evil-doing is most forcibly exhibited in the light of the penalty which it doe serves and incurs. Crime unpunished ceases to be reo PENALTIES UNDER THE DIVINE GOVERNMENT. 151 garded as crime, and the denial of punishment in the divine government is wont to be attended by a low estimate of the guilt of sin. It may be the occasion or the consequence of the denial, or both; but when penalty ceases to be contemplated, sin will be considered an igno rance or a blunder. It is a matter of intuitive perception that the evil-doe deserves punishment, but ill-desert is not a IL.aesert and sufi cient reason for the infliction of punish- penalty. me 4t; if it were, pardon would always be wrong when pn? isliment is deserved. It is true, we have an "ethical nal Ire," involving a sentiment of justice, which is gratifie( with the appropriate punishlment of sin; but we ha, a, as well, a sentiment of compassion disposing to mercy. Ne tlher of these feelings, nor any other feeling, is a gl tle to right in the case. The proper end of punishme it is not to meet the desert of the sinner, and thus sat sfy the law; it nmay be abstractly right that he shcould have his deserts, but abstract right is not an end to be pursued, still less is it a reason for inflicting any evil; and the law, apart from the good it secures, is nlothing. The satisfactory reason for punishment is, that it is necessary to the general good. Its tendency to Reasons fot restrain from transgression, to promote vir- penalty tue and happiness, warrants its infliction. Any coimbination of circumstances which removes this reason for tho pena,ty, makes its infliction imprcper. The existence of ill-desert is necessary to punishment but of itself it is nt satisfactory reason for punishment. Ill-desert exists evei after pardon has been bestowed, bat it is not a reason for punishment. In regard to the extent of Denalty, its degree and du. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. ration, we have no natural, intuitive rule. To the hu ;ent of man understanding, there is no common tnea I-etyl. sure of guilt and of evil, by which we can balance a given degree of guilt by its equivalent of pain. And, again, if there were such a standard, it is not self: evident that the penalty should iii every case reach tlhe ,xact desert of the tiransgression. It could not properly exceed the guilt; but if it were clear or probable that the public good could be as well sustained by a penalty less than the desert, it would be ri,ght to inflict the lighter penalty; because the only true reason for the penalty is, that it subserves that good. Unlquestionably there should be some general correspondence between the penalty and the sin, the more aggravated crine being visited with the sterner penalty; beyond this somewhat vague idea, we have no exact knowledge. It is a matter of experlience, in human governments, to ascertain how severe iii degree and in duration its penalties should be-hlom many years of imprisonment to appoint to a given criene, and how much of hardship should be involved in the imprisonment. These question, are settled only by tlhe experience of generations; and it is altogether possible that the proper standard of Decalty in one state of society, may not be suited to another. If it be true that lighter penalties, in our day, answer the ends of government, as wet as did the severer ones of former genera ions, this of itself does not prove that those severer p)enalties were out of place. Perhaps they were needed then. Such is the attitude of the transgressor of law, that it is just to inflict upon him any evil that is necessary to counteract the mischief of his doings. Until that degree of penalty is reached, he cannot (complain that it exceeds his desert; but beyond that 152 PENALTIES UNDER THE DIVINE GOVERNMENT. there is, in the nature of things, no warrant for inflicting penalty. A distinction is to be made between discipline and penalty. These are often confounded. Dis- Discipline cipline, is imparting instruction and culture not penty b)y the infliction of pain. It sometimes follows transgress ion, for correction; and sometimes it is bestowed in advance, for prevention. Its chief aim is the improvement of the subject, and it sustains no certain relation to guilt. Discipline may exist without guilt, punishment cannot. Discipline is not always an expression of moral disapprobation; it always indicates a want, for which the discipline is offered as a remedy. Punishment, on the other hand, respects the public good. The criminal has forfeited his own good by his crime, and the government is required to remedy, as far as may be, the mischief of the crime by punishment. The good of the community and not of the offender, is the measure of the punishment. If it can be made to subserve his good, at the same time, all the better; it serves then the double pur. pose of discipline and of punishment. Such a comnbination often exists, especially in family and Combination school government; but, even in the family, of the two. the idea of good to the offender must sometimes be relinquished, and punishment must be inflicted for the good of the family alone. It is not true, then, that punishment contemplates, primarily, or even at all, the reformation of the offender, nor is it necessary that, in form, it should be adapted to this end. The first point to be secured is the protection of society; and whatever can be done for the offender, consistently with this, be nevolence requires should be done. Punishment aims to prevent crime by its effect upon the subjects of the 7* 153 .IMORAL PHI.OSOPHY. government at large, and not chiefly by its effect up)on the criminal himself. The term penitentiary is an in adequate name for the state prison. It should be first a prison, and afterward a school of reform; and it cannot be a successful school of reform, without being distinctly a prison, Penalties are of thie same essential nature in the diPenaltyin di- vine government as in human government, vine governmtnt. and must be inflicted upon tile same conditions,and for the same end. They are natural evils, inflicted upon the transgressor by the governmient, to counteract the mischief of the transgression, and promote obedience to the law. The necessity for penalty in the divine administration, is the same as in any government. It is a government of moral beings, by motive, not by force; and an essential element in the moral power of the government, is penalty. There is a vague idea, somewhat prevalent, that God, by his attribute of almighty power, can govern the world without such motives; but the subjects of his government are moral beings; and virtue, which alone is obedience to the divine law, is the free action of moral beings. Almighty power can create and destroy moral beings; it cannot compel virtuous action. Omnipotence and moral power are totally distinct, and one cannot take the place of the other. The material universe, God controls by physical power; lhe persuades to viIrtue by motives. Of the form, and degree, and duration of penalty in Degree and God's government, we have no intuitive duration. knowledge; all that we know, positively, is matter of revelation, either thlrough God's providence or his written word, and a full discussion of the subject belongs rather to Biblical Theology than to morals. It 154 PENALTIES UNDER TIlE DIVINE GOVEITNMENT. ] 53 may be sutfflcit-nt to say here that the announcements of the penalty of sin are among the most striking and in pressive and unambiguous declarations of God's word(J They are found, not in the older ilebrew Scripture atone, but, in most positive and definite forms, in the latest revelation, and none more significant than thoso which fell from the lips of the Saviour himself. -Iis work of redemption and pardon needed to be exhibited upon the terrible back-ground of the penalty of the law, to save it from misconstruction. The human conscience, in all ages, has responded to these declarations, and has even formed to itself such conceptions, without the light of revelation. Speculative philosophy has sometimes attempted to break the force of these announcements, by showing that there was no ground for thein-that there could be no such ill-desert on the part of finite beings as would justify everlasting punishment. A simple reflection uipon the n ature of guilt, will set aside the Guilt everspeculation. Guilt is, in its own nature, as lasting. enduring as the subject of it. While the sinner exists, he must be guilty for every sin he has committed. The sin renders him ill-deserving, and that ill-desert attaches to his personality, and can never be discharged. No subsequent virtue can offset it, because the virtue can never exceed the obligation under which it exists. It canuot be cancelled by punishment; it is not in the nature of punishment to remove guilt. The ill-desert is just as great after punishment as before. Piardon sets aside penalty, but does not remove the guilt. The pardoned sinner receives favor that he nevel can deserve. Giul is, in the nature of the case, as lasting as the soul. Tlti, affords a natural condition for everlasting punishment. If such punishment is necessary, it will not be unjust, Of MORAL PHILOSOP HY its necessity, human reason cannot properly testify. Of the fact of such punishment, revelation alone can speak It is often maintained that guilt is itifntite, and therefore pu.iishment may be everlasting. It is better to say, what seems clearly comprehensible and true, that guilt is end ess. It is sometimes urged, that the natural consequences of Natural con- wrong doing are the proper penalty of the s,equences and penalty. sin, the appointed means by which God ex presses his disapprobation of it. This view is restricted, wholly, to the divine government. No one dreams that the natural consequence of transgression can be penalty in any human government. Does it answer this purpose in God's government? Natural consequences of acts of transgression are of Twokinds or two kinds; the consequences of the outward consequences. act as a physical act, and the consequence of the inward sinful state. The result of the outward act is the immediate physical effect, of which the act itself is the cause. The pain and injmuy of burning, come from contact with fire, the inevitable consequence,whether the act, with reference to its internal character, be sinfii, accidental, or benevolent. The effect of taking poison, is death, whether the act be intentional or not. So, of drinking alcoholic spirits, the result is intoxication, without reference to the motive of the act. The injury of the burn is not the penalty of encountering the fire; if The injury so, the fireman is punished for his heroic benot penalty. nevolence. Death is not the penalty of swallowing poison; if so, the innocent are often punished. In all these eases, the consequence is the mere effect of the( external act; but it does not serve the purpose of a penalty. It is in the established order of nature, and thus 156 E5ALr lES-i UNDEIR THIE DIVINE GOVERNMENT. 1; i., part of the divine arrangement; but the evidence io ei;irely wanting that it is an expression of God's disap pr)bation of the act, any more than the pleasure of an act of sin is an expression of his approval. If so, he does not discriminate between an act of duty, which in volves self'sacrifice and pain, and an act of sin. It is in .Conceivable, that penalties uinder God's administration should be dispensed so iiidisciminately. Any government must fail that should depend onl such a distribution of penalties. The sinple fact is, that God has connected the consequence with the external act, without reference to its character. In general, it is duty to avoid the act, and the injury that follows. At tiles, it is duty to elncounter the evil. It is not possible to conceive that God punishes anl act of duty. Can we, then, discriminate and say, that when the act is virtuous, or innocent, the evil consequence is not punishment, but it becomes punish ment when the act is sinful? But the fact that it is in evitable, whether the act was virtuous or sinful, miust destroy its effect as penalty. It is not seen to be an unequivocal expression of disapprobation on the part of the government. The acts in question become sin ful, only in consequence of the evil that follows. The use of intoxicating drinks would not be sinful, but for the harm that follows. We have, then, the singular combination of a penalty attached to an innocent act, which becomies sinful on account of the annexed penalty. To account these inevitable consequences penalties, cannot fail to lead to confusion, in reference to the divine governmnent and to abate firom the significance of God's disapprobation. It is a common remark, that physical laws are God's _aws, and that these inevitable consequences Physical lawy are the penalty of physieal 14w. We have and penalty M1ORAL PIIILOSOPIIY. seen that, to speak of physical law as obligatory, or capa. ble of being violated, or as bringing punishment, involves utter conftision. Physical law is no law of obligation, and can have no penalty. There is no clear thought thia' answers to these words. But is not the remorse, the self-condemnation, which le remorse attends upon a sinful act, a real penalty? I penalty? iS true that this does not occur without sin, unless it sometimes results, under morbid conditions, from fancied sin. Remorse is a natural consequence of sin, provided for in the very constitution of moral beings; and the very fact that it is an inevitable c(onsequeince, inseparable, in thought, from a moral being in an act of sin, unfits it to serve the purpose of penalty. It cannot serve as penalty in human government, because it'not inflicted by the government, and can be no10 expression of its disapprobation. I-luian governlmeilt may bring its penalties to bear, in connection with -his tendency of the soul. It may shut a mlan up to himself, and compel to reflection, and thus make its penalties effective. For the same reason, mere self condemnation cannot become penalty in the divine government. Its existence is not the result of a governmental arrangeinenit. It is true that God created the moral constitution, but it is inconceivable that a moral being could be made without the constitutional necessity for self-condemnnation. Ilence, simpler inevitable self-condemination does' not carry with it evidence of disapprobation from the government. It would arise all the same, if moral be !ngs could exist and sin, without any divine governiiient. It is not a result of government, but rather of the perception of obligation, and a failure to meet it. and obligation is not founded on goverinment, but gov. 158 PENALTIES UNDER THE DIVINE GOVERN ENILNT. 159 ernmentt is founded on obligation. Remorse, in itself, id not properly penalty, under the government of God; but penalties may reach the sinner through this channel, That remorse which results fiom providential May be made arrangement, involving the evidence of God's penalty. tiitervention, the pain of which is intensified by the con sciousness of his displeasure, is an effective punishment This is no mere natural consequence. It is a positive divine action upon the soul, through the natural channels of the moral nature. There is also an important distinction to be observed between natural and providential consequences. Providential Many of the firequent results of sin, which we consequences. call natural consequences, are not strictly such. They are not the inevitable, necessary sequences of the acts, hut come about through a combination of forces which FugOgest,the intervention of providence. A drunkard, in his intoxication, is precipitated from a height and crushed. This is not strictly a natural consequence of his sin. It .s not rare that such circumstances attend an event of 'he sort, as to impress all beholders with a conviction that it comes of divine appointment. It is true that an innocent blind man may suffer a similar catastrophe, and it may be dicffiult to determine what circumstances are necessarv to indicate that one of these events is a divine judgment, and the other not; but the difference is sometimes so clearly marked as to remove all doubt, and tot impress all beholders with awe, in view of this foreshladowitlIg of "the righteous judgment of God." Such evente has e occurred in the history of individuals, and of nations) rlley come, to all human appearance, througth the operal t iol, ofC natural laws; but they are accepted is providen tial, not merely natural, consequences CHAPTER IV. CIVIL GOVERNMENT. CWIL GOVERNMENT rests on the common f)undation !ttfounds -of all government-itsnecessity for the welltion. being of its stlubjects. It seems essential to the safety and prosperity of mnankind. Without it, there is no progress in civilization, in the general social or moral condition; and in proportion as the government becomes settled, and is made effective for the protection of the interests of the people, the general condition of the, community is improved. This fact, of the necessity of government to the well being of any conmmunity, gives to one who occupies a Right to favorable position, and possesses other qualif govern. cations, the right to govern, and imposes upon the rest the obligations of obedience. In order to this obligation, it is not necessary that the ruler should be desi,gnated in anyv one specific form. The mode of his designtation, or appointment, is involved in the form of the government; and the form of government, actual or possible, depends greatly upon the condition of the peo pormn of gov- ple, as to intelligence and virtue; but more, eriimeit. perhaps, uponI their origin and historical growth. Out of these the ritling forces of society commonly arise. The civil governments of the world have not, in most cases, been adopted arbitrarily, nor have they been complete, in form, at their first institution. They nave grown to their ultimate proportions from some formative principle, existing in the earliest condition of the CIVIL GOVERNMENT. people, and from additional forces which have operated from time to time. iAIueh depends upon the original chlaracter of the people, as a whole, and somewhat upon the mouldinug power of individual minds that have appeared in its history. There seems to be no power in a ration to change, utterly, and at will, its form of government. Great and sudden changes occur, but they were provided for in the antecedent condition of the people, and do not come arbitrarily. That form of government, then, is legitimate which actually exists; because, in general, it is the Legitimate form which is adapted to the people, by reason governlment. of their character and history. It is legitimate, because it best subserves their interests. TWhenever another form will better serve the purpose of government, will better secure the interests of the governed, they have a right to secure it. A distinction has been made between a government de facto, and a government de jure —between A common the existing and the legitimate government. distinction. But the existing government, whatever it be, must bie aecounted legitimate until a better or another takles its place. The government exists because there is at present no power to secure a better; and it must be respected, and sustained, within the limits always set to submission to human authority. It nmay have originated in wickedness, or usurpation, as most of the governments of the world have done. yet, until something better can be secured, allegiance is due it. We are not to look at its origin but at its immediate bear ing on the interests of the people. It ceases to have author ty when a better is attainable. The " Southern Confed eracy," if successful, would have been a legitimate govern ment, to the extent of claiming the obedience of the peo 161 - MNIORAL PHILOSOPIIY. ple, although it originated in a wanton and wicked re bellion. A tyranny is a government which is administered foi the pleasure or advantage of a class, or of a a tyranny tyranny few, in opposition to the interests of the many [t fails to answer the ends of government. Any govern ment may properly be called a tyrIanny,whichl holds it3 place and form to the exclusion of another which is possi. ble, under all the circumstances., and which would better promote the end. In this view, many governments are tyrannous in some of their features, while beneficent on the wh-ole. The chaltacter of a government does not depend, wholly, upon the personal character and intentions of the rulers. They may be corrupt, in character, and yet not able to pervert the government; or they may be honest and well-disposed, and still be unable to give the government a beneficent bearing. Good rulers may render a badly constituted government tolerable, and bad rulers may pervert a good government. The constitution of a government is the established The constitu- mode in which the overnment is adminisIfh oat ion.- erm tion. tered, including the appointment of rulers, and the distribution of the fiunctions of government. The constitution may exist in a generally accepted order of things, transmitted from one generationi to another, with little change or questionI-an unwritten constitution or it may exist as a written document, prescribing, in definite terms, the mode of administration. A constitution written or unwritten, to have stability, must conformn t( the general views and life of the people. It must be the outgrowth of the social forces which prevail. A written constitution, to be successful, must, in general, exist before as an unwritten one; or rather, it must lhave its found, 162 CIViL GOVERNMENT. tlon in the established thought of the people. A constitution, written, ard formally adopted, cannot be consid. ered as established, until it has been subjected Its establishto years of trial, and has served its purpose in ment. times of conflict, as well as of peace. No constitution can be established for all time. The people change, and thus arises anew adjustment offorces. New emnergencies arise, not anticipated, and for which no provision has been made. Hence, constitutions must change. Their only binding force, or sacredness, is in the interests they sustain. When they fail to meet the want, they must give way. If the change can be effected by modes prescribed in the constitution itself, it is well; but in any case, the safety of the people is to be secured, if possible, even if the constitution suffers. The constitution is a means, and not an end. Every progressive state is evolving new constitutional principles. The somevwhat popular idea that civil government is a social compact, and derives its authority Not a social fi'om general agreement, or consent, is not an compact. axiom, or even a truth. With rare exceptions, governments have not arisen in this manner; and even if such had been their origin historically, it would not have been the foundation of their authority. Alen need to be governed. If they consent, it is well; if not, they must still be governed. It may be said that, in yielding, they consent; but the right of the government to command, precedes the yielding. It may compel the obedience of e, or of many. The right to govern does not,universally, rest with the i,aj(frity. It is not a question of will, but of Riht of tan nterests. The presumption is in favor of the majority. majority; but if, at any time, a few can better secure the 163 IIMORAL PHILOSOPI]Y. interests of all, it is their right and duty to do it. This is always the case in the fathmil.y-, and iii the school; it may sometimes be so in thi state. The principle of representation, as a condition of obli erincipre o nation to obey and support the government, ,on. is not a universal one. It is not always true liat such a constitution is possible, as shall secure fuil] representation of all classes;yet the government is valid, and can require the support of its subjects, while it serves the ends of government. Taxation without formal representation, is not necessarily tyranny. Where protectionI is afforded to persons and to property, the right of taxation exists, both on the basis of persons and of property. The cost of protecting the person can be required of each person; and the cost of protecting property, of each holder of property. The right or privilege of voting for rulers is to be deRight of vot- termined upon similar principles. The lri(rht ing. depends uponl the constitution of the government, and the constitution of the government is determined by what is possible and best. It is not a right which attaches to human nature, unconditionally, and ne one can demand it as a condition of submitting to gov. ernient. No one can claim the privilege, except upon the ground that his exercise of the right will be promo tive of the public good, or, at least, not detrimental to it. If the right is claimed for foreigners, the claim must be based, not on any abstract justice, but on a probable benefit to the community. If the claim is made in )ehlalf of women, it must be on similar grounds. The exercise of the right of suffrage is a governinental Duty of vot- function. It directs and controls the advini. Heg. istration of the government, and hlence should 164 CIVIL GOVERNMENT. be contemplated as a responsibility, and not as a per. tonal privilege, to be used or neglected at will. Those to whom the right is extended, have a duty to perform, and carelessness or dishonesty is a breach of trust. if the intelligent and the virtuous neglect this duty, they surrender the government to the ignorant and the vicious. It is not a question of personal convenience, or interest, but of public responsibility. The ballot does not of itself afford a just distribution of influence. It gives to the ignorant and the corrupt the same weight in government, as to the wise and virtuous. This, in itself, is wrong; but the evil is, to a great extent, remedied by the operation of personal influence, which gives to a wise man the direction of the votes of the ignorant and Thoughtless. Thus, a widely extended suffrage becomes safe and just principle of government. The idea that rulers, in a democratic state, are the servants of the people, to execute their will, con- A false de rains only a partial truth. They are servants, in the sense that they are to promote the real interests of the people, not to do their pleasure. They are elected to govern, not to serve. In the same sense, parents are servants of their children, and teachers of their pupils. They are to do what is needed —not always what is de sired. There is a similar error in the doctrine of instrue tion-that a representative must vote accord- Doctrine of ing to the will of a majority of his constitu- instruction. ents. Hle is to take his place in a deliberative assembly where the interests of all parties, and of all portions of the country, are to be considered. These interests, in all their extent, are to govern his vote, not simply the special interests of those who elected him, and certainly not their mere will. 165 1MORAL PHILOSOPHY. In every civil gove nment, whatever its form, the will : of the of the governed is a controlling powel, wletlie(.verned. er expressed by vote and representation, or ,,lot. A government in direct conflict with the aggregate ,vill of the people, is always impossible. An absoltute IIollIarclI is not indepen~lent of his subjects. Sooner or later, he must yield what is required. In a democratic government, there are settled, constitutional methods in whichl the public will makes itself felt. This removes all excuse for revolutions and violent convulsions, and, to a great extent, removes the inducements to such inovemenTts. Whlen suclh a constitution is consistent withl thle degree of intelligence and virtue whichl prevails, the public security, and the pertanetice of the governmetnt, are best secured by it; but, in every governmnent, there is a tendency tc -hange aind revo,lltion,ultil all interests are properly p)r(,vided foir. To;onstruct a government whllich shlall provide for all the interests of a p)eople, for 'niany generations. is a pr(ol)letn that lias prolbably never been solved. The history of the world leaves little room Tendency to for doubt that the tendency, in all progressive democracy. society, is to a democratic form of governnieit; and the nature of the case seems to present tlle same idea. The hereditary advantages of classes niust lillally disappear with the general progress of the people, and the natural and necessary result must be an equa, representation of all classes in the government. A teiidetncy to the democratic form, in any government, is pre suinptive, not conclusive, evidence of progress in civili zation; and such chlanges should be hleartily welcomed, because they lie in the direction of the ultimate cojidition. On the other hand, all re-action from demnocratic formus should be resisted, or accepted, with great reluct 166 CIVIL GOVERNXMIENT. ance, 1)ecause every such re-action is a loss which Iniitt be retrieved, if there is to be continued progress ill (:isvi ization. It is a misbfortune to a people to be ol)liged tf takle such a step. The safest and surest nmeans to duIlit u-ratic liberty in government, is advancement in iilllIi ,eiiee and virtue. Political revolution, if necessary, i A later step in the inovetment; and anarchy or despoti.cii, not liberty, is the result of premiature attempts.'tt revo lution. The ordinary work of human government is sufli ciently obvious, but it is more difficult to de- Speres o n ~~~~~~~~~~~Spheres of termine the precise limits of its proper ope- government rations. What interests it can wisely undertake to regu. late, and what should be left to the spontaneous action of the people, are questions that can be settled only b)y ex perienee. They belong to political and social sciec(,e, rather than to morals. As a quiestion of right, it is lear that government should undertake such responsibilities as it wisely can, and the light which is to guide, is derived fiom experience. In one state of society it is wise, and therefore right, to underltake whlat, under other ciircumstances, would be impossible. The maxims adal)ted to one state of society, will not apply to anotler. Whether the regulation of the interests of education, and of religion, belongs properly to government or not, can be determined by no intuitive principle, and the question admits of no universal answer. Whatever is wise, in any case, is rioht. Government, like an individual, iyiust (t what good it can, and it is under no obligation to make al tteinpt when there is no reasonable prospect of success. Thie positive requirements of government must be, at far as they go, re-ena(tments of the law of RIelatioi to obligation. It can never rightfully require righteousune 1 C). MORAL PHILOSOPHY. what it is wrong for the subject to do, but its require ments may properly fall far short of duty. They aIre probably, never complete expressions of duty. In t4ii respect they differ firom the divine laws. The divine law covers all duty; human law only such duty, and so' uiiel of it, as properly falls within its sphere. Many matters of important obligation are never touched by human law. Indeed, the substance of all duty, the duty of benevolence, is not at all enjoined by human law. But aside from this, there are multituiides of outward duties, which ihumani law does not contenmplate. It does not require politeness, or chlaiity, but these are mlanifest dluties. The payment of all honest debts is not provided for by law. Certain forms of debt, only, are made co,l('etable. All this lies in the nature of the case. It is irmi,,)ssible to do more. Even in matters of which hnunan legislation takes note, the law must often fall far short of obliga-M - fall short. tion. It cannot always coffe up to the standard of objective rigihtniess. In legislating for the suppression of drunkenness, the question is not so much what is desirable and right, as what is practicable; and what is practicable determines what is proper. What can be done,is the measure of what ouglt to be done. The prohibition of all harmful use of intoxicating driinkls is )bjectively right; but if such a law cannot be executed, a less comprellensive, but more effective one, must be accepted(l. There is neither duty nor propriety in the enactment of a law which cannot be maintained. It is not necessary, however, that a majority of the community should approve a law in order to its execution. A small minority of determined men can sometimes give effecttveness to a righteous law. At other times, such may be t68 CIVIL GOVERNMENT. the stupidity or ignorance of a whole people that the legislation cannot be brought up to the standard of outward righteousness. The law of divorce among the Hebrews, in the time of Aioses, is an example. There was no lack of wisdom in the legislation, but, for "the hardness of their hearts," they were suflered, on certain con ditions, to put away their wives. It was the best tha could be done with such a people. In connection with such a conforming of the law to human weakness, two mistakes are sometimes Two mismade; first, that it is a sanctioning of ini- takes. quity to abate, in the form of the law, from the perfect standard of righteousness, on account of the wickedness of men. For legislators to do the best they can in the suppression of wickedness, is certainly no sanction of wickedness. Prohibiting and suppressing a part, is not approving of the rest. The second mistake is, that conformity to human law, in reference to any obligation, is the fuilfilment of the obligation. The law does not undertake to express the full obligation, but only so much of it as is essential to the outward regulation of society God's law, not man's, is the standard of righteousness. 169 9 CHAPTER V. PENALTIES IN CIVIL GOVERNMENT. THE use of penalties in human government is the same Je of penal- as in the divine-to restrain by fear of'pnnishties. ment, and to instruct by an exhibition of the ill-desert of crime. Since outward conformity is all that human government takes note of, fear operates directly as a motive to obedience; but the far more important influence is, the light which the penalty throws upon the nature of the crime itself. The wickedness of transgression is the great restraint, and nothing so impressively exhibits this wickedness as an appropriate penalty. The right to inflict penalties has the same condition and foiundation as in the divine government-they are deserved and are necessary. The same distinction is to be observed between discipline and punishment, and the right to punish is to be maintained against the sentimentalism which would substitute reformation for punishment. There has been a tendency, in some parts, to attribute Adan, erou crime to ignorance, and account it a misfor A anerous tendency. tune, to speak of the criminal as the victim of a false social system, and to blame those whom he wrongs, rather than the wrong-doer himself. There is, doubtless, room for pity, in the case of every criminal, and crime is never perpetrated without temptation; but pity should not be more prominent than blame,in the treatment of crime, and temptation does not remove the propriety or necessity of punishment. It is never to be forgotten, that the criminal is a man, and has a claim to PENALTIES IN CIVIL GOVERNMENT. all] the offices of humanity which are consistent with the treatment of him as a criminal. The humanitarian sen timent which rejects punishment, is most prevalent in communities where crime is least known. In the presence of monstrous offences against society, it can find no place. [L connection with the recent rebe]lion, and the crime rlhich follows, it meets with little favor. The right of government to inflict capital punishment has been specially resisted. The death pen- Capital pun. ishment, how alty has obviously another aim than the good justified. of the criminal, and hence urgent, and persistent, and partially successful, efforts have been made for its abolition. The grounds upon which capital punishment is to be justified, are, that it is deserved, and is necessary. That murder, treason, and other crimes which imperil life, de serve the penalty of death, is beyond question. These crimes, in their own nature, suggest death as the approi)riate penalty. The penalty must be an expression of the guilt of the crime. No other penalty so fully serves this purpose, either in form or in degree. The offence is against life, and what more fit than that life should answer for it? Any other penalty would fail to meet the demand for correspondence in form. There are crimes of such a nature that no corresponding penalty is possible; but where it is possible, the correspondence is desirable. In degree, no other penalty meets the case Life is the highest earthly interest, and a penalty which ffccts a less interest, fails to express the guilt of crimes against life. In the nature of the case, then, this penalty eems necessary. The experience of the world sustains this view of its necessity Those nations and communities Testimony of that have made the highest attainments in experience. 171 MORAL PHILOSOPIHY. social order, have done so in the use of capital punish ment for marder and related crimes. The thought of lispensirng with it, was never suggested in these commu ities until murder had almnost ceased to occur, and the quiestion had become theoretical rather than practical Probably not an instance can be found, in the history of he world, of any great progress n civilization without this penialty. Capital punishment is sustained by revelation. The injunction upon Noah and his posterity was, Scripture. Whoso sheddeth man's blood, by man shall his blood be shed, for in the image of God made he man." The connection shows that this is a positive precept, apparently intended for all the coming ages. The reason given is perpetual. Capital punishment was prescribed in several of the laws given to the Jews, indicating that it is sometimes appropriate. The ground upon which it was prescribed, is significant "The land cannot be cleansed of the blood that is shed therein, but oy the blood of him that shed it." The objections to capital punishment which call for consideration, are the following: The spirit of the New Testament, and the whole drift Objections. of the gospel, is against such punishment. Spirit of New Testament. The injunction, "Love your enemies, do good to them that hate you, and pray for them that despite fully use you and persecute you," is essentially a prohibi tion of capital punishment. The obvious answer is, if such general precepts forbid Iapital punishment, they forbid all punishment, both fines and imprisonment. But it is a mistake to suppose that the benevolence required by the New Testamnent, or that in the nature of the case can be required, is incon 172 PENALTIES If CIVIL GOVERNMENT. sistent with any necessary punishment. Love to man, requires the use of all means necessary to human wAelfaie. If capital punishment is adapted to this end, its infliction is benevolent. Again, it is objected that capital punishment is not no cessary, because solitary imprisonment for life is just as efficacious in the prevention of ecery crimne; and this is maintained, on the ground that it is naturally as influential, and that in experience it has beel found to be as effective. In reply, it may be said, that the convictions of men do not accord with the idea that imprisonment is as inpressive. In the nature of the case, it is not so. A few per sons have been known to commit suicide to escape imprisonment, but more have done the same thing to escape the evils of life. Such cases do not present the normal judg ment of men; they are exceptional. Few cases of capital punishment occur without a strenuous effort in behalf of the criminal, to secure a commutation of his sentence for imprisonment; and such a commutation is welcomed almost like a pardon. The question is not whether, in actual experience, solitary confinement may not be as terrible as death, but whether it strikes the mind, in conteimplating it, with equal force. To this question, but one answer can be given: life under almost any conceivable conditions, is preferred to death. The great Dramatist has, unquestionably, expressed the common feeling: "The weariest and most loathed worldly life, Which age, ache, penury, and imprisonment Can lay on nature, is a paradise To what we fear of death." It is not actual terribleness, but impressiveness, that ii required in a penalty If, as is probable, solitary con 173 MORAL PHILOSCIPHY. fneinenet for life is, in actual experience, so distressing [mpressive- as to make death seem preferable, this fact is nets needed. in favor of death instead. The effect of iln. prisonment, in anticipation, is by no means as great as that of death, yet those who have seen their friends becoming hopeless, imbecile, and idiotic, under the pressure ,)f solitary confinement, have sometimes, in view of this Petitioned for the death penalty. Benevolence would dictate that those years of hopeless wretchednessshould be spared to the criminal, buried, as he is, from the eyes and the thoughts of men. The simple announcement of the sentence is all that operates upon the public mind; of the years of misery that follow, there is almost no knowledge, and little thought. Solitary confinement, with all its hopelessness, is far less effective as a penalty, and is probably less merciful. The opportunity of preparation for death,is quite as favorable to him who meets it in the full possession of his faculties, as to one who, shut away from every wholesome influence, gradually lapses into hopeless idiocy. The limited experience of recent times, in the substitu Experience tion of solitary imprisonment for capital oolimited. punishment, cannot be regarded as satisfactory. In the first place, it is, by no means, generally agreed, in the communities where the experiment is in progress, that the result is auspicious. The conviction, on the part of many of the most trustworthy and thoughtful men, is that the actual result is unfavorable. But, again, if statistics should show no marked increase .f crime, during the few years since the experiment began, no positive inference can be drawn,favorable to tllhe abolition of capital punishment. The experiment is inadequate. It is made in communities where the public 174 YENALTIES IN CIVIL GOVERNMENT. sentiment, in reference to murder, has been produced by the operation of the death penalty. )Icre than one generation will be required, to show distinctly the effect of any other system. In such a community, if all penal ties for murder were abrogated at once, the effect might not be immediately visible. It is not true that in suchl communities there are multitudes of persons intent on miurder, and only restrained by fear of punishment; but an inadequate penalty must in the end produce crime. The tree will finally be known by its fruit, but it may require generations to mature it. Objection is often made to public executions as demoralizing, and the proof commonly adduced Thiblic execu is, that such occasions gather the low and tions. vile, who exhibit in their demeanor a loathsome levity, rather than the solemnity which befits the scene. But we must distinguish between the exhibition of wickedness, and the promotion of it. In all gatherings of the degraded, wickedness will appear, but this is no proof that the gathering is unprofitable. The solemn exhibition may profit even the degraded, and it may be profitale to the community to know what vileness is hidden in its dark places. But if experience shall prove that public executions are corrupting, they can be dispensed with. The public exhibition is not an essential part of the penalty. The public announcement of the day and the hour, and, perhaps, the tolling of a bell, would give the needed publicity. One of the great advantages of the death penalty is, that it does not need to be witnessed in order to be impressive. Another objection is, that so strong is the general feeling against capital punishment, that juries Popllar feecannot be brought to convict, even the mani- Ing against It 175 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. festly guilt, because they shrink from the penalty that must follow. A sure penalty, it is said, is better than a severe one that cannot be executed. Undoubtedly there has been an indisposition to iniiflict capital punishment, and many a murderel has escaped in consequence; and such a public sentiment may at length compel the adoption of another penalty. But it will b6 observed that this is no proper objection to the penalty itself. If the sentiment be a false one, let efforts be made to correct it. The crime which the sentiment will nourish, will, in the end, correct the sentiment, and the proper penalty will be invoked again. In the presence of the great crimes connected with the rebellion, and consequent upon it, the false sentiment is nearly obliter ated. It is said, again, that the capital penalty is suited to A relic of a barbarous age, when less striking penalties barbarism. would have little force, and that Christian civilization has made men more sensitive to evil, so that milder penalties are sufficient. Thus there has been a constant ten dency to mitigate penalties, and to make them less loathsome in form,and less severe in fact; and the same movement continued, will at length render capital punishment unnecessary, and bring about its abolition. We answer, if,in the progress of civilization,the barbarous crime of murder shall become unknown, capital punishment will, of course, disappear, because not needed but as long as so much of barbarism remains that it is necessary to prohibit murder, let that penalty, which properly represents the crime, sustain the prohibition. Objections like these, that "human life is inviolable,' Frivolous ob that "we have no right to take away what Secions. we cannot restore," and that "capital punish i il 6 PENALTIES IN CML GOVF,ERNMENT. anent is the perpetration of murder for the prevention of mniurder," are so utterly foundationless, as to require no answer. All objections must be essentially frivolous,except sicel as are urged against the necessity of capital unishment. r 17IT CHAPTER VI. LDITS OF OBEDIENCE TO CIVIL GOVERN.NT OBEDIENCE is to be rendered to all human govern >(>oegient ments, in subordination to the will of God. ubordna These governments are a recognized necessity, in the nature of the case, and their existence is manifestly in accordance with the divine will. Hence the presumption is always in favor of the authority of civil law; and any refusal to obey, must be based on the moral proof that obedience will be sin. The one who proposes to disregard human law, must be persuaded in his own mind that, in that course, he will meet the approval of God. It is too obvious to need discussion, that the law ,f God, the great principle of benevolence, is supreme, and that " we ought to obey God, rather than men," inl any case of conflict between human law and the divine. This is the principle of the "higher law" doctrine, Higher law. as it has been called in political circles in Lower la. our land. The "lower law" doctrine, which hlas been maintained in opposition to this, is, in its leas' odious form, that,as "the powers that be are ordained of God," obedience to human government is always obligatory, and in accordance with his will. This doctrine, puslhed to its legitimate consequence, implies that God has given to human government authority to abrogato the divine law. and release men from obligation to God This absurdity proves the doctrine faise. A modification of the doctrine is maintained as appli LIMnITS OF OBEDIENCE TO CIVIL GOVERNMElNT. 179 cable to our democratic government, that as the people all have a voice in the making of the laws, they In a demomust render obedience to every law, while cratic state .t remains a law, usillg their influence, meanwhile, for the repeal of a wvicked statute. The principle will not bear investigation. The voice of the people is not the voice of God, and we have no license to "go with the multi tude to do evil." There is no power in a democrati. majority. to set aside personal obligation. The fact that the government is democratic, and that there is a mode in which every one can make his influence felt in setting right the wrong, has its force in rendering revolutionary mnovements unnecessary and improper; but the great law of personal duty must hold against all such considerations. Cases may arise, under any government, in which the individual conscience, which is but the jutdg lent of duty, will require a course of action inl opposi ion to the law. It would seem satisfactory if some general test could De presented, by which such cases of duty No general may be determined; but no general formula formula. is possible. Each case must be settled in its own light, and settled, too, by each interested person, for himself. Two equally intelligent and conscientious men may pursue different courses, and both be not only subjectively, but objectively right. What is duty to one, in the case, may not be duty to the other, because of their different rela tions. The question is, like all questions of practical duty, to be decided in the light of the claims of benevolence, alld the will of God. A few suggestions may not be amiss. It is manifest that all laws, requiring what is just an( proper is itself, must be obeyed. These Just laws t. right acts would be obligatory, if not enjoined bo obeyed MORAL PHILOSOPHY. by law, and the law affords an additional reason foi their performance. This needs no proof. Acts indifferent in themselves, cease to be so when re. Indifferent quired or prohibited by human law. We are also. not to follow our own convenience or plea sure, against the naked authority of the law. The gov. ernment is essential to the good of society, and it must be sustained at the sacrifice of personal preference, and even of personal interest. We are often bound to do as much as this, out of regard to the judgmenit or feelings of a neighbor; more is due to the influence and authority of the government. In a case of doubt, the law should have the benefit of the doubt. Laws which may properly be called unjust, muse U1njst at sometimes be obeyed. An improper or un equal tax, unless levied for immoral purposes may, in general, be paid without hesitation. The inter est of the subject is infringed upon, but it will not be se cured by resistance to the law; and even if it were, it is still better to make the sacrifice to the authority of the government. It is wrong for the government to levy an unjust tax, but it is not, therefore,wrong for the subject to pay it. It might be wrong for him to make such a payment if not required. It is possible that human'aw Possible should make that right, which would be effect. wrong without the law. The principle, sometimes announced, that "a law requiring what is wrong is no law," has its limitations, and is true only in this sense that what is wrong, even after it is required by law, can not be binding by reason of the laiw-a manifest truismn The fact simply is, that government is an interest, as real as any other, an essential means to the general welfare and that it is better to submit to some injustice rathle I80 LIMITS OF OBEDIENCE l'O CIvIL GOv ERNMEENT'r. 181 than to interrupt the established order. l'o)r this reason an officer may collect a tax, which, in individual cases, he sees to be oppressive and unjust, rather than interrupt the regular operation of the laws. The degree of the injus ice is an important element in the estimate of duty. The injustice may be so gross that the, government would suffer more detriment in its permission, than in the irregu.arity involved in its prevention. But in deciding upon duty, in reference to any act required or prohibited by the law, the fact of the law is to have weight, and this will sometimes make proper what would otherwise have been wrong. After all these exceptions and allowances, it is still true that obedience to human law often involves Obedience sometimes sin against God and man. There are cases so wrong. clear that no one can question the duty to refuse obe dience. In all times and in all lands such cases have arisen. In a case of this kind, either of two courses is possible: to disobey the law, and resist the Two coursed government in its attempt to execute it, or to possible. disobey and quietlv suffer the penalty. The first is revolutionary, and can be justified only when the case is flagrant, and affects such numbers that a revolutionary movement will be sustained. Sometimes a decided atti tude, on the part of a large number, in opposition to a wicked law, will set the law aside, and make it inopera.ive. Such a movement is as justifiable as any revolution. But these cases are rare. The second course will, in general, commend itself to considerate and conscienti(us men. It is a testimony against the law as unrighteous, and,at the same time,a recognition of government as a grave interest. It is not, however, duty to invite the penalty, or to expose one's self vol.untarily to it, as a reparation fox MORAL, PHILOSOPHY. the hlarm done in violating a wicked law. We may es. cape the penalty by honorable concealment, or by sona technicality, or by flight, according to the Saviour's ad. vice to the disciples, " If they persecute you in one city flee ye to another." All such devices are to be preferre to a violent resistance of the penalty. Violence is comn monly mischievous. The duty of subordinate officers and magistrates, exe Duty of a sub. euting the laws under a higher authority ordinate. sometimes involves doubt. They are not re lieved fi'om all personal responsibility, at liberty to do whlatever is enjoined upon them,without enquiry. The wickedless of a wicked law is not confined to the legislative p(w er, but extends to all who knowingly share in its execution. In ordinary cases, a sheriff or a soldier may ho without question what he is bidden to do; but if there oe manifest wickedness in the transaction, or ground to apprehend that there is, the subordinate must judge of his duty for himself, and act on his own responsibility. fle cannot shift the burden from himself to his superiors. They must answer for their duty, and he must answer for his. It is maintained by some, that in all cases of a conisciMst he re- entious inability to execute the law, the subeign? ordinate must retire from his office, and, of t ourse.leave it to be occupied by one who will perpetrate (lie wrong. This is by no means a manifest duty. Let him retain his place, and withstand the injustice, while h an Such an extension of responsibility is an importan 3afegnard against tyranny. But for this principle of )ersonal responsibility, extending to inferior courts and tilagistrates, all the checks in the exercise of power are removed and a government like ours is subordinated to the 182 LIMITS OF OBEDIENCE TO CIVIL GOVERNMENT. 183 control of the supreme court. The custom of inferior courts to follow the decisions of the higher courts, instead of iudging each case on its own merits, is a questionable surrender of persona responsibility. Would it not be higher wisdom to discard unrighteous precedents, and,iu every new case, to "judge righteous judgment," laying nl)on the higher court the responsibility of reversing it? When a government becomes inefficient or corrupt, and the constitutional means of remedy fail, Extraordinthe people have a right, if they can, to supply ai measures. the deficiency, or correct the wrong, by extraordinary means. The necessity is a painful one, and the experiment is always hazardous, but the emergency justifies it. A resort to violence in rectifying the abuses of the gov ernment, always tends to disorganization, and it is difficult to arrest the movement at the proper point;but the concurrent judgment of the friends of public order, will sometimes warrant the undertaking. The "vigilance committee" of San Francisco, in 1856, is an example of justifiable and successful interference with the operations of government. When a government becomes a tyranny, and fails to do its essential work, it is the right of the i)eo- Right of re ple to break it down,if they can, and institute olution. a better. This is the right of revolution. It is based on the principle that government rests for its lawfuil authority uponi the interests of the governed. A manifest and utte failure to secure these interests annuls its right to exist It matters not what the form of the government may be; the right of revolution pertains to all forms, after all constitutional remedies have been applied in vain. The dangers, and difficulties, and probabilities of success,are to be balanced, as far as may be. and a revolution under MORAL PHILOSOPHiY. taken when the circumstances justify it. An attempt tc set right, by violent means, a great wrong in government; is wise, and right, if there be reasonable hope of suc cess; if not, it may be folly and madness. We sometimes admire the daring and heroism of tile man who daslhe himself against an obstacle, that,to all human calculation is immovable. Hie may have some inward light that justifies and sustains him in the encounter, and the result may show that the wisdom that guided him was more than human. Such cases are exceptional, and lie beyond the range of ordinary rules of duty. A revolution is justified where the interests of the govWhen justif- erned require it. This is the ground and limit able. of the right. The fact that men desire it for their pleasure or pride or ambition, is no justification of it. it is not the will of any number that makes it right but their real wants. Nor will the interest of a few jis tify a resort to violence, nor a trifling interest of many The remedy for such inconsiderable imperfections in government, is in moral effort, light, and persistence, and time. An attempt at revolution, without sufficient reason, is rebellion, and the result does not change the character of the undertaking. It is often urged that the right of private judgment, Objection as now maintained, in reference to obedience tends to anarchy. to the laws of the land, will subvert government, and introduce confusion and anarchy. Whatever danger there may be in this direction, is to be properly considered and provided for, as far as may be; but the right and duty of meeting one's own convictions of conscience still remain, and government must get on with the difficulty as well as it can. The da,,nger, however, is greatly over-estimated. Government is never the gaine 184 LIMITS OF OBEDIENCE TO CIVIL GOVERNMENT. 1 8 in the execution of a law that is manifestly unjust. It may set forth the strength of the government in mere physical force, but there is a loss which more than counterbalances, in the diminished respect and confidence of the people. That loss is in part averted by the conscientiots refusal to obey such a law, or by a quiet interrupion of its execution, on the part of a private citizen or an officer. Strength ill injustice, on the part of governmenit, is not strength, but weakness. Conscientious men are not the elnemnies, but the friends, of any government but a tyranny. They are its strength, and not its weakness. Daniel, in Babylon, praying, contrary to the law, was the true fiiend and supporter of the government; while those who, in their pretended zeal for the law and the constitution, would strike down the good man, were its real enemies. It is only when government transcends its sphere, that it comes in conflict with the consciences of men. But it is objected that the example is corrupting-that a bad man will violate a good law, because the Example good man refuses to obey a wicked law. The harmful. cases are just as unlike as right and wrong, and any attempt to justify the one by the other, is gross dishonesty. Unquestionably, the principle can be abused by the wicked, and so can any truth, whatever;but the principle of unquestioning obedience to human law, is false, and needs no perversion to niake it mischievous. Practically, the cases are few, in well-established governments, where the law encroaches upon the rights of conscience; but if she principle be surrendered, the cases will multiply. Obedience is, of course, the rule, and disobedience the rare exception. It should always be remembered, that the great end ot MORAL Pl'HILOSOPHY. government is human well-being-that law and antho Eld of gov- rity are nothing in themsel ves, and that aL ernment. their sacredness arises from the uses which thev serve. The machinery of government is valuable, only for the work it does; in itself; it has no value. It is better that the just result should be brought out, even at the expense of a little jostling of the visible machinery The vital power of government is not so much in its outward adjustments, as in the hold it hlas upon the respect and confidence of men; and that hold is proportioned to its effectiveness for good, rather than to the regularity of the outward working. Both are desirable, but one is necessary. The true estimate of government lies between two errors. Jurists and legislators-those Two errors. who are chiefly occupied with the forms and processes of government, are liable to over-estimate these forms. The machinery comes to have, to their thought value in itself, and they learn to depend Upon its perfeet working. Any irregular operation or friction, is cause of grave apprehension. They fail to see that the most grievous of all imperfections in government, is the failure to secure the just and good result, and that injustice and oppression are not made tolerable, by being in strict accordance with the law. Nothing is surer,in the end,than the reaction of such wrong to break down the most perfectly constituted government. On the other hand, if the general welfare is carefully provided for, even with some irregularities in the working, the governmiient will grow strong in the midst of convulsions which would shatter any government, the strength of which was in its perfect organization. The other error is on the part of those who hare little thought of forms and organizations snd whose chief attention is directed to the outcome 186 LIMITS OF OBEDIENCE TO CIVIL GOVERNMENr. 187 They undervalue the importance of established arrangements, and would accept almost any irregularity with the promise of immediate good. They fail to observe that tire novelty which serves them now, may to-morrow prov their enemy; and that the steadiness and regularity whiel seemed to work to their disadvantage, is their surest reli ance. In its best forms, human government will be im perfect; and it is often better to tolerate the imnperfec. tions, than to peril the general good by any rash attempt at re-adjustment. For the settlement of all these questions, science furnishes no universal formula. Every emergency brings with it the best light for the guidance of those who are to meet it. CHAPTER VII. THE RELATIONS OF NATIONS TO EIAOH OTHMLI THiE various nations of the earth, through their govern Obligation of ments, act upon each other, and affect each ations. other's welfare. In these relations they come under the great law of benevolence, as really as individuals. A nation can have no more right to act without regard to the welfare of other nations, or to promote its own advantage at the sacrifice of their interests, thait persons have, in similar circumstances, to disregard each other. The relations of nations are, comparatively, few and Obligation remote. In the present state of the world limited. national jealousies are so prompt and general, that comparatively little can be done by governments to help each other. The proposal on the part of one nation to help another, would often be regarded with suspicion, and be a source of weakness instead of strength. The government accepting suchn help, would sometimes endan ger its own existence. Ilence, to a great extent, the action of nations upon one another, is, necessarily, of a negative character, leaving one another to pursue the path of interest without obstruction, giving here and thlere such countenance and support as may be possible. The law of benevolence still holds, and the nation should ac tnowledge its claims, as well as the individual. Among civilized nations, certain habits of propriety Laws of ta- and comity have been established, which are ,ions. recognized as the laws of nations. There is THE RELATIONS OF NATIONS TO EACH OTHER. 189 no recognized authority to define or execute these laws; blt the nation which contravenes a well-estabslished priniciple of intercourse, wvill find its violent dealing returning upon itself, in the treatment it receives from other nations. These established principles, so far as thev go, are an approach to the law of benevolence in the case but they are often very imperfect expressions of it. The constant intercourse of nations, and their progress in Christian civilization, will effect a clearer definition, and an extension of these laws; meanwhile, it is the duty of every nation to coniform its conduct to the requirements of benevolence, and to respect the interests of other nations, even beyond the demands of recognized international law. Nations are bound to respect one another's sovereignty. The people of the world are arranged Norightto nnder separate governments, and their wel- absorb. fare depends upon this separate national existence. No nation can have the right to assume the control of another people, setting aside its government, and absorbing into itself its resources and powers. Such a centralization of the powers of government, would no more conduce to the general welfare, than would the assumption, on the part of the strong, of control over the weak, in personal relations. A nation acquires no such right by the conquest of another people in a just war, except, in a possible case, where the existence of the conquered people, as a separate nation, is a nuisance to themselves and thei neighbors. Nor can one nation have a right to render anotlihe dependent upon itself, and tributary. The Or make tri1 weak may be naturally dependent upon the t y. strong, and may be under obligation to make return foi MORAL PHILOSOPHY. the hell) theyl receive, as in the case of two indivlidtlals; but no nation can have a right to demand of aiiotller colltri I)Iltions of nmen or money for its own advanitage. Stlch pr lacrLetice does not differ, in its morality, from robbery. It must be the duty of one nation to aid another, when to aid. its existence is threatened by vi(lence, pro vided the relations are suchl that the prof fer will be a real help. The obligatioln is the same as in the case of individuals, to hlelpl those that need; the powel to help is more limited, becallse of nlational jealousies, and the danger that what is intended as help may prov-e a hindrance. In cases of unwarrantable rebellion, it is the duty of Duty in rebel- surrounding nations to give their countenance lion. and moral support, at least, to the lawful authorities of the distracted country; and it is a gross fail nre in public morality to exhibit such sympathy, or per mit such support to rebels, as will tend to overthrow the government, or prolong the contest. The nation that fails to respond to such obligations, must, at leingth, reap the fruits of its own meanness and selfishness. In all treaties, and arrangements for national iiiter Duty in trea- course, it is duty to aim at mutual benefit. Belt Any attempt to get the advantage, in slch a transaction, is as dishonorable as in personal mnatters, and any exultation over a one-sided treaty, is rejoicing over dishonesty. The only proper aim of diplomacy, is to secire an equal and honorable adjustment of all questions of interest; and a resort to concealment or chicanery, in a1iy form, is as contemptible as in personal intercourse. Questions of tenritorial lines, and other interests, between neighboring nations, should be settled with the same magnanimous respect for each other's rights and views, as 190 THE RELATIONS OF NATIONS TO EACH OT 11 E R. 19 ] in the case of two neighbors. The wish or aim to elicroach upon the domain of another nation, is l1alli)l~ selfishness and injustice. A readiness to enter ilto allI freaties promotive of the general welfare, and to abitl, ,)y treaties when formed, is as manifestly the duty ot al ins, as a similar spirit on the part of individuals. All restrictions of commerce, and of intercourse 1)e'ween nations, mnust be regulated by the re- In commer I n ~ ~~~~~~~~~~~cial initerquirenents of benevolence. Each nation is coaui.e. bound to favor the trade and commnerce of other natiol,s, to the extent of the common welfare. A nation cannot be bound to sacrifice its own essential prosperity, for tlhe sake of fostering the coinmerce of another nation. It is the privilege of a nation to restrict its trade with others by any necessary impediments, when its own good requires, as a family may limit its purchlases when its own good demands. A tariff of duties on importations or exportations, to limit, or even to prohibit trade, in cerltail things, and at certain times, is not, nrecessarily, an immorality. The only self-evident principle of morality that applies to the case, is the universal duty of benevolence. Since vast interests depend upon the maintenance of the organic existence of the state, it is the Duty of self d(uty of nations to protect themselves, and preservation. the interests which depend upon them. This involves the uightfiulness of war-the use of whatever force mnay 1)3 necessary for self-protection, and the defence of the in terests at stake. This right of self-preservationr. is in -olved in the right of a government to exist. A natio,n bus maintaining its existence, is contending nriot merely for its owr immediate interests, but for the common right upon which all governments must stand. Take MORAL PHILOSOPHY. away this right, and governments have practically no al thority. It is generally conceded, even by those who deny the Genera con- rightfulness of war under any circumstances essio. that a government must have the right to execute its own just laws. If resistance is offered to te execution of them, it must be put down, or govern ment is at all end. If a mob interferes, the mob must be quelled, at any necessary sacrifice of life; otherwise government is impossible. If the resistance grows into an insurrection, it must still be suppressed, and all the appliances of power, necessary for the work may be freely brought to bear. If such a manifestation and use of power is war, then war on the part of a government, in the execution of its wholesome laws, is right. But it is said by those who accord to government this Objection to right to put down resistance to its own au the name. thority, and still deny the rightfulness of war, that such a use of power is not war; that an army raised for such purposes, is only the police force of the country engaged in its legitimate work of enforcing the laws. The name is not much, but the principle is important. Whatever the work be called, it is lawful for a government to maintain itself, and the interests it protects, by any necessary force, and at any necessary sacrifice of life, against any violence from within. Is it not evident that that same right exists for a govAse,,i on ernment to protect itself, and the depending frm without. interests, against any violence from without If there be any difference in the two cases, the latter is the stronger. Violence from within, may indicate a weakness in the government, a failure to meet the necessities of the people;and what is called a rebellion, 192 THE RELATIONS OF NATIONS TO EACH OTHER 193 may be a justifiable revolution. There is no such presumption, in the case of the attack from without; aLd must the nation yield to the violence, and submit to the overthrow of its institutions and interests, when it has power to prevent it? Only a direct revelation to this effect could warrant the improbable conclusion, and we have no such revelation. War, then, carried on by a useful government, for its own existence, is not wrongs on the part of that government. lN*or can it be reasonably questioned, that a strong nation may be bound to defend, even by war, Duty toward a weak naa weak nation unjustly attacked. In most tion. cases,a simple protest, or warning, would prove sufficient. but the force of the protest lies in the fact that war impends, if it is disregarded. Then, again, a nation may be bound to punish or crush a power that indulges in piracy and robbery, and becomes the common enemy of mankind. Thus our government broke the power of the piratical states of Northern Africa, and delivered the Toward a pt nations from their aggressions-a work of ratical one. oenevolevnce and imercy. In a similar way, the leading Christian nations have combined to prevent the slavetrade by ships of war, stationed on the coast of Afrtica. An oppressed people may have the right to overthrow a tyrannous government, and establish a better, war fr,revo even at the expense of war. The war will lution. involve great calamities, but these may be accepted in preference to injustice and oppression. The sentiment ttributed to the late Daniel O'Connell, that "no politi cal change is worth one drop of human blood," is not sustained, either by reason or by history. Many of the privileges of civilized society have been bought with blood, 9 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. and we could better afford to pay the price asain, than to part with them. It is sometimes asked, if one nation sustains obligations case of cor upt fcover- of benevolence to another, may it not be melt the duty of a powerful, civilized people, to put down a corrupt government, and give a better one tc an oppressed people, or to restore peace where civil dis cord prevails? An intervention of this kind is, in genera! unprofitable. A stable and free government, can only come from within-the result of forces in the nation itself. Any force from without, will prove a disturbance, rather than a help. A settlement, resul ing from such a force, is not permanent, and will show its instability when the external force is removed. When long continued civil strife in a nation,interferes with the quiet and prosperity of other nations, these nations may have the right to compel its cessation. The propriety of the intervention will depend upon the probable result. The question, is war right or wrong, admits of no No direct direct answer, because war is not a simple answer. moral act. There are always two parties concerned, sustaining very different relations to the war. It is not rare that both parties are guilty of wrong, and that either might have prevented the war by an honorable course; but it is evident that one party may be the aggressor, and that the other may be acting merely in selfdefence. It is preposterous to state the question of the Rightfulness of war, in such a way as to overlook this difference of position. When a nation is unjustly attacked, the presumption is The presump- that it has a right to repel the violence and tio. prevent the injustice and injury by suach force as maybe required. If this right is called ir Ads. 194 HEI RELATIONS OF NATIONS TO EAOC OTHIER. 195 tion, it must be on the ground that such resistance ias wrong in its own nature, or that it is directly prohibited Dy the law of God, or that there is a better way to prevent the injury. If national self-defence is wrong in its own nature, it ie because it is unbenevolent. If it be incon- Opposed to * Opp~~~~bneosedcto sistent with benevolence, it is, of course, nevolence wrong. That it is unbenevolent, is maintained on two grounds; first, because it necessarily involves an unbenevolent heart in those who share in the war. Benevolence is love, a disposition to benefit and bless; and this is due towards enemies, as well as friends. War involves violence and evil towards enemies. True, and so does the punishment of crime, by fine or imprisonment or death. But the highest benevolence requires the punishment of crime, and the officer of justice performs a benevolent act in inflicting the penalty. It is just as consistent with a benevolent heart, as an act of charity or mercy. To save a nation from threatened danger, is an act of benevolence, and the patriotism which leads one to risk his life for his country, is one of the noblest forms of virtue. It springs naturally and necessarily from love to God and love to man, and involves no hatred towards the enemy, even in the very act which causes his death. The responsibility of the act is to be accepted, as a stern and awful duty, like the execution of the sentence of the law upon a criminal. In such a spirit men may, and do, engage in war. But, secondly, it is urged that the evils of war are sw great as to prove that war is "contrary to the The erlU, order of nature," and therefore wrong. But the g9at evils of injustice and oppression and outrage are also great aed unless it can be shown that national resistance to un IMORAL PHILOSOPHY. just aggression increases the evils of the world, the argu ment from the evils of war has no force. The evils of wai are manifold and fri ghtful to contemplate. They come in siich forms, and are so concentrated, as to be appreciable to the d u'lest apprehension; but the evils of tyranny, and op Sression, and national degradation, though less striking in torm, affect the character and condition of every individ ual, and endure through generations. The general judgmnent of men has been, that war is sometimes to be preferred to these evils, and the result has often justified the judgment. The punishment of crime involves great evils, but to leave it unpunished involves greater; and no one could urge the horrors of the prison and the scaffold as an argument against the punishment of crime.' That defensive war is prohibited by divine command, Divinely for- does not appear, unless the general requireidden. ment of love to enemies, and the exhortation not to resist evil, be taken as such a prohibition. But if these prohibit war in self-defence, they equally prohibit the infliction of any evil in punishment of crime. This interpretation is manifestly too sweeping, and is in conflict with the whole tenor of Scripture, and with sound reason. The love due to mankind, is not opposed to the ir;:liction of any evil which the good of mankind req tires. These general precepts can be brought to bear at;ainst defensive war, only by showing that it is not nec,ssary to the good of mankind. That there is a better way to avert the evils which war is better ay. employed to remedy, is maintained on differ ent grounds; first, it is said that God will p,otect a people that comnmit their cause to him. No D rlnepro- doubt he will; but he works by means, and to ro- the means he has been accustomed to employ 196 THE RELATIONS OF NATIONS TO EACII OTHER. 197 for the protection of his people, is theil courage and strength, inspired and sustained by his own presence and power. lie enables " one to chase a thousand. and two to put ten thousand to flight." What right have we tc trust himn for deliverance, while we decline to use +ht means which hlie provides? God's view of such remiss ness, is expressed in the curse pronounced on those whl "came not up to the help of the Lord against the mighty.' Unless we have explicit warrant to forbear isuch effort, oni faith becomes presumption. The argument assumes, at the outset, that any effort at self-protection is displeasing to God —the very point to be proved. Again, it is maintained, that an exhibition of the gospel spirit of non-resistance to threatened vio- Non-resist ance effica lence, will disarm the enemy, and turn him cious. back from his purpose. This argument also assumes that an attitude of non-resistance is the right and proper atti tuilde, that which the highest benevolence requires. Un til this be proved, there is little encouragement to take the position; and if it be the proper attitude, there is little ground to expect absolute safety from violence in it. There would be safety in the final outcome, as there always is in the way of duty. But the proof is wanting that this is the path of duty. Again, it is urged that reason and good sense would suffice to settle all international difficulties, Good sense Is ,vithout a resort to war. This is true, beyond sufficient. all question; but the difficulty is to bring an aggressive and ambitious nation to use reason and good sense. It is not clear that reason and good sense on one side alone, will secure the desired end; and if these fail, there remains the right to repel aggression. The triumph of reason anid good sense in the world, will bring the end of war, and .IMORAL PHILTOSOPHY. of every crime as well-a result for which we are to la l)or and to pray; and among the essential means of has teeinig the good time, is the prevention and punishment of,rimne within the state by governmental force, and the prevention and punishment of aggression from witl.out, by a wise and benevolent use of the power of the nation To rendei' wars unnecessary, and to bring into disus the whole system of military and naval equip The true aim. ment, should be one of the first aims of every enlightened nation. For rational and successful labor in this direction, it is not necessary to adopt the false princi ple of the wrongi'ulness of war in every possible case. A_ aggression and injustice is wrong, and the suppression of this will "make wars to cease unto the ends of the earth." A readiness to settle international difficulties by mutual conference and concession, or by arbitration, is one of the highest duties of the nation; and a resort to arms for the gratification of malice, or pride, or ambition, or for national aggrandizemient, or for any unworthy reason, is the greatest of crimes. Public morality in this matter has already made great advances, but much still remains to be done. The war spirit, as it sometimes exists in a nation, in both government and people, is the spirit of demons, a "kind that goeth not out, but by prayer and fasting." When a nation engages in a righteous war. all the re ties in war. quirements of benevolence, in the treatment of prisoners, in the recognition of the rights of non-combatants, and in the mnitigation of the calamities of war in general, are still in force. When thejust object oI the war is accomplished, it must cease, and no advantage must be taken from the victory,to injure, or even to hu mniliate, unnecessarily, the offending nation. t9s CHAPTER VIII. FAMILY GOVNMENT. THE family organization involves, among other inter ests, that of government. This is, perhaps, not Government the most prominent feature, or the highest in- in the family. terest, in the family constitution, but it is essential, and the ends of the organization cannot be attained without it. The necessity for government, and the objects of it, are, in general, the same as in civil society: social order, and the advantage and welfare of every member. The right, on the one hand, to govern, and the duty of obedience, on the other, rest oni the same foundation: ability to secure the interests of the family, and the need of direction and control. The limits of the family, in respect to the persons embraced, are determined by tile nature of the Limited in case. The parents and their children, and numbers. other persons who find their home in the household, constitute the family, and share in its rights and duties. The limits of the government, in respect to the interests embraced, are much wider than in civil gov- Wider In in. ernment. Everything that affects the welfare terest. of the child, the regulation of his conduct, the cultivation of his mind and heart, the employment of his time, and the establishment of relations with general society, falls within the domain of family government; because, in all these things, the child needs the supervision and control of the parent. The right of the parent to control the child in all these relations, is limited only by the welfare MORAL PHILOSOPHY. of the family. He has a right to govern, so far as the good of the household requires, not at all for his own pleasure, or under the promptings of any pa:sion. The constitution of the family, like most other consti Mode of co- tutions is determined by the nature of the stitution. case. It is not properly a social conmpact, ex cept as to the determination of the two parties that lay ,le foundations of the family, and perhaps in some other subordinate interests. The original organization of the family,is strictly matter of independent agreement. The parties are perfectly free to enter into the arrangelient, or to decline it; but once having entered into the marriage relation, they have their general rights and duties assigned themn, by a law above their will. Nothing can be right or duty to either party, which benevolence does not permit or require. Unity of interest and of action is essential to the family Qustion of welfare; and in order to unity, there must be head hip. a head. There is little room for doubt that the man is, by nature, indicated as the head of the house. The evidence is too patent to require presentation. Even if there be entire equality in intellectual endowments, still, the physical constitutions and liabilities of the sexes would alone determine the matter, and mankind have in general accepted this determination. Nature and revelation are equally explicit. The man is the head of the house, in the nature of the case, and only some special inbecility can set him aside. This condition of things is not the result of any special Provded for agreement, nor can any agreement greatly In nature. modify the relation. It is not necessary that the duty of subordination should be acknowledged by the wife,in the marriage covenant. The duty is involved iii 200 FAUlLY GOVERINME.NT. the relation itself, and depends on no p)romiise for its ex isteiice. It will not rarely happen that the welfare of the fainily will depend upon the clearer judgment and stronger claracter of the wife; but, even then, true delicacy and the highest decoruim would sugg,est, that shle ito-,ld direct affairs through the hiubband, as the primine Iniiister governs E1nglanid through the queen. The stronger character will inevitably control, but this should not disturb the natural order of the household. There nay not be, on either side, the consciousness, even, that the power is not -lwhere it seems to be, and the world has no concern in it. But if the man is so contemptible, by vice, or any imblecility, that hlie cannot stand in his place, the womanI must take upon herself the headship of the famnily in formi as well as in fact. The view sometimes urged in opposition to this, ia that in nature there is no precedence on Opposing either side, that the man and the woman con- view. stitulte the "united head," and that they are equal in tl.e family goverlnment. There is truth in this view of the relation, and somewhat of error. To the children, the will of each parent is law. " Honor thy father and tny mother," is the universal doctrine of Scripture, and'he dictate of good sense. But if the parents are equal in authority, in their relation to each other, there may be a conflict of parental will, which will destroy the governmenit of the family. To set aside the danger of such collision, it is made the duty of one, to yield in the finlal issue. As a matter of propriety and courtesy, to forestall the slightest approach to a collision, it is the duty of either to yield to the wishes of the other, a duty which probably devolves upon the husband, oftener than upon the wife. But if there should occur the misfortune 9* 201 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. of a trial of authority, the woman is to recognize the head of the house, and honor the divine appointment, as indicated in nature and in revelation. But is it not better that the parties should enter the relation upon equal terms, and find their Another niew. place, in reference to each other, as a resul of their mutual acquaintance and their experience? If that arrangement had been better, the two sexes should have been constituted with equal endowments, physical and intellectual, and neither should have been rendered dependent upon the other, by any delicacy of constitution, or liability of condition. But, even in such case. the relation could not have been as happy. It is not desirable that, at the outset, it should be an open question, which of the two shall be the head of the house-a question to be settled by some trial of force or will, or provided for p advance by mutual contract. It is better that all such questions should be set aside, Wisdom of by indications so marked that there is no the arrangement. ground for hesitation. That there should be more of strength on one side, and more of delicacy and dependence on the other, exalts the relation of marriage, and changes it from a mere business co-partnership, to a divine institution, the conditions of which are not determined by mutual agreement, but by the nature of the case. Any attempt to render it, by mutual contract, essentially different from what it is in nature, must fail. It is no mere human arrangement, of which the Saviour says: "Have ye not read, that he which made them at the beginning, made them male and female? and said, for this cause shall a man leave father and ino.her, and shall cleave to his wife, and they twain shall be one flesh, wherefore they are no more twain, but one flesh. What 202 FAMILY GOV:RNMENT.o therefore, God hath joined together, let not man put asunder." Any conception'of marriage as a business arrangement, between two similar and independent par. ties, mnst fall infinitely below this divine ideal. But nature is stronger than a false idea, and the truth will maintain itself in the world against any false philosophy. The marriage union, provided for by this divine consti tntion, is one of confidence and trust, and mu- A relation of tual favor. It nmay sometimes be wise to ad- confidence. just subordinate inerests, affecting the relations of the parties to others, in matters of property and the like, by a marriage settlement; but, in general, it is the higher wisdom to allow all interests to adjust themselves, under the natural operation of the marriage union. The civil law may intervene, here and there, to determine some of the remoter limits of the rights and duties involved, but in general it is too rough a force to be intrusted with the regulation of such relations. Society has an interest in the prosperity of the family, and has a right to protect itself against the burdens and immoralities which must result from its dissolution. Hlence, law naturally comes in to prescribe the rough outlines of duty, when mutual confidence and affection fail. Such being the nature of the marriage union, implying a comtnon life and destiny, a unity of interest, To be entered ' upon de'-iberjustifying the bold figure of the early and the atly. deierlater revelation, it should not be formed at the prompting of impulse or passion, nor without the most serious purpose to meet it? responsibilities. No man can have a right to propose marriage with a woman, with whom he cannot enter heai tily upon the earnest work of life, witl a satisfactory assurance that she will help him to become *11l that he is capable of, in excellence and duty, and that 203 MIORAL PHIILOSOPHIY. he can help her to be what she needs to be, as a social and rational being. No woman can have a right to accept the proposal of any man whose character she cannot respect, whose honor she cannot trust, and to whose wisdom she cannot cheerfully yield, in any serious difference of judg ment. When the union is once consummated, it must be care Maintained filly maintained. Although a natural relation, with care. it will not take care of itself. There is con stant opportunity for mutual forbearance. and thoughtful ness, andl concession, and confidence, and love, a tender ness toward each other's infirmities, a care fcr each other's convenience and comfort, an appreciation of each other's burdens and trials; the husband "giving honor unto the wife, as unto the weaker vessel;" weaker as respects the delicacy of her organization, and dependent by the conditions of her sex; the wife respecting her husband, and putting him in the place which belongs to him before the world. Any occasion for the display of authority, or even the thought of it, between the two, is offensive and odious. There is a natural sphere, where each has the preceRegard for dence, and each should there respect the eah ther's position. otler's prerogative. The wife is the proper mistress of the home, and, within all reasonable limits, should be left to order its internal arrangements, according to her own judgment and taste. The husband is the natural representative of the family, in its relations to general society, and out-door affairs naturally fall to him. Each may counsel and aid the other, and mutual deference is ulways in place; but for one party to intrude upon the other's domain, in the way of control, involves the degradation of both. These, ard similar, considerations are 204 .I. - FAMILY GOVER2X0ENT. perhaps too obvious to require suggestion, but the importance of the relationshit) will warrant the brief reference. The relations of the family to civil society, and the outer world, are not so much individual as Relation te organic. Its duties to society, and its partici- the state. ration in public operations, are all subordinate to the unity of the family. Its voice in public affairs is natu rally expressed thiough its head. Hle represents not him self, but the family. The claims upon the family foi public service, tfall immediately upon him, but actually upon the organic unity. Hle responds to the claim of the government for pecuniary support, for service in office and in war. The family is known in civilized society by his name, and its property is recognized as his; not because he may use it for his own pleasure, or personal advantage, but because, before the world, he is the agent of the family, and manages and disposes of its property. All these and similar arrangements subserve the family interests, and conduce to its organic unity and life. If the individual members of the family had each an independent relation to general society, uttering an individual voice in public affairs, filling a separate place in public office and duty, and recognized as con- Relation to trolling separate interests, the organic life society. of the family would be feeble and comparatively valueless. In all the efforts to improve the relations of the individual to society, the interests of the family should not be forgotten. Every other organization, civil or ecclesiastical, is secondary in importance to the famnily; and all other valuable organizations flourish, in proportion as a wholesome foundatiQon for the family is secured. 205 CHIAPTER IX. ES OF P1ENT AND CHILD —OF TEACHER AD PUPIL THE institution of the family contemplates, as its chice Chief work of object, the proper training of children. Foy the fmily. this work family government exists, and it is always tc be exercised with reference to this end. The child is made dependent upon the parent, during many years, to afford opportunity for parental authority and in fluence to mould the character of the child, and fit him for the responsibilities of life. This end determines the direction, and defines the limits, of parental authority. The child is to be controlled, just so far as his good requires, or for the common benefit of the household. The form and spirit of this control, are almost wholly deterrnined by the parent. The responsibility is a most sacred trust, and should be accepted and discharged with conscientious fidelity to the interests of the child. Parental affection, a powerful instinct, has been pro. Place of pa- vided as a necessary check upon parental aurental affection.a thority, and a stimulus to parental duty. Such control as the parent naturally has over the child, would be unsafe without this tempering element. Authority, softened by love, loses its repulsive character, and becomes to the child a fountain of good. There is noth Ang he more needs than a kindly and beneficent controlt will to limit his freedom, guided by wisdom and affecti)n Authority without affection, is popularly, though often erroneously, supposed to characterize the lot of kter children and step-children. The mnost scrupulcu l i DUT1ES OF PARENT AND HILD. conscientiousness cannot make up for the absence of pa, rental love. On the other hand, the instinctive affection equally requires the balance of conscientious wisdom. Mere tenderness toward the child, will as surely miscari] as stern authority. Benevolence is the comprehensive duty of the parent-a blending of wisdom and love. This proper balancing of forces, is divinely provided for in the union of the different elements of character found ill the father and the mother. The resultant is a more wholesome force than either element alone. The duty of parents to provide for their children, and secure for them a favorable entrance upon the Leading duty. responsibilities of life, is second to no other dtuty. Parental fondness or pride often perverts the judgment, and craves for children ease instead of usefulness, social position instead of character, and wealth instead of goodness. The highest blessings which children can inherit, it is in the power of all parents to provide; and earnest fidelity to the interests of the child can scarcely fail to furnish him with the best of outfits-cheerful hopes, noble principles, and a fair reputation. The combined resources of wealth and wisdom and position, can accomplish nothing more. The duty of obedience on the part of the child, arises, as we have seen, from his need of guidance and Duty of obey. dienee, and control, and must continue while this necessity its limit. continues. The law of the land wisely prescribes the age at which the child may assume self-control. Thus, some strnggles may be saved between the spirit of independence m the child, anld authority in the parent. There may be case, in which children are competent to provide for themselves and direct tl.eir own ways, before they reach the legal age; yet, if parental authority still holds them, they have 207 MORAL PHILOSOPH]Y. no right to throw it off. Something is due to the principle o.f filial obedience. An example of subordination is prof itable; and to break away fiom parental control,before the recognized period, is mischievous in its influence. Something, too, is due to the judgment and feelings of parents, who have brought the child on to this condition of independence. But it is not true that the duty of obedience termi Maynotterm- nates, in all cases, with the period prescribed ate. by the law of the land. The obligation con tinues during the entire period of dependence, and the need of guidance. The child at home, or at school, sus tained from the famnily estate, must listen to parental counsel; and the duty to respect such counsel, often con tinues after all dependence for material support has ceased. The claim of the child to care and support, is a claim Claim of the of benevolence, not of debt. It is a substanchild. tial claim, but not such as to make it tolerable for the child to say, " Father, give me the portion of goods that falleth to me." The obligation of the parent is as positive and peremptory, as if the child had earned his living, but the child must receive the parental bounty with grateful recognition. Children cannot require, as a condition of obedience, Ureasonable that parents be infallible in judgment or in requirements. spirit. Nor may they refuse o)bedience, in all cases, where the requirement is severe and unreasonable. The child must often obey when his own judgment disapproves of the command, and even when lie knows that hlis own interests have not been properly considered. The parent's command will render that duty which would not have been duty, or even right to do, without the commandl 208 DUTIES OF PATENT AND CIIILD. It might be for the child's interest, and therefore his duty, to obtain a thorough education; parental authority may make it his duty to forego these advantages. Of course, his final interests will lie in the direction of his duty. But, as in the state, so in the family, there is a limit to the duty of obedience. Parents may enjoin A limit to the what it will be wrong for the child to do, after duty. giving due weight to parental authority. As in other doubtful cases, no definite line can be drawn between the right and the wrong; no absolute formula of duty can be given. A right heart, and such wisdom as is granted to those who seek, will carry one through the emergency with "a conscience void of offence toward God and to. ward men." When the period of positive obedience has passed, the duty of respect and honor still remains. It is Duty in ma, a most desirable thing, to be able to rise grace- turity. fully from the position of a child under authority, to that of a young man or woman, paying all due deference to the judgment of parents, yet assuming the responsibility of self-diiection. In this work the parent must co-operate, substituting counsel for command, and laying upon the child the responsibility of his own conduct. Perhaps the highest style of family government is that where personal influence is most prominent, and authority is kept out of sight, resorted to only in an emergency. Tlen tie time when authority ceases, is never known; thie youth becomes the man, without any consciousness of saving escaped parental control. When conditions are changed, and the parent becomes aependent upon the child, the duty to render Duty to de pendent pacare and support is as imperative on the part rents. of the child, as before on the part of the parent. It i; 209 MoRAL PHIILOSOPHY. just as monstrous for the child to forsake the helplea Is rent, as for the parent to forsake the child. No plea of other duties, or of the claims of general benevolence, is available. The Saviour has pronounced his condemnation upon this hypocrisy. Such ingratitude is rare; bu children sometimes fail, in arranging too soon for a de pendent condition on the part of their parents; too anx ious to anticipate the possession of the property which they expect to inherit. It is more seemly that the old people should enjoy their pursuits and responsibilities, until they p)refer to lay them off, even if the young people must comnence with a scanty outfit. The relation of teacher and pupil rests,ultimately,upon The teacher's tho same ground as that of parent and child. authority. The right to govern, on one side, and the luty to obey, on the other, are essential to the teacher's work, and the pupil's welfare. This is the simple origin of school government. The teacher's authority has, by some writers, been derived from authority delegated to him by the parent. The theory is far-fetched, and unnecessary. If the pupils had been gathered from the streets, or the forests, having known no parents, the same relation would exist. If parents should refuse their consent, the teacher must still govern. The teacher's duty is difficult in such a case, but he must govern if he can. One who undertakes the instruction of children and youth, has a right to govern by virtue of his work. Any person entering a group of children, may, when occasion arises assume authority. We need no more warrant for it than for liberty to do them good in any other way. The extent of the teacher's authority depends upon fte *entt the necessities of the pupil-Lis age and dis cre+ion. The degree of control which is prof 210 DUTMES OF TEACHER AND PUPIL. stable and proper, ranges from the close restraint of the boarding-school for children, to the almost complete free. dom of the scientific and professional school. In every case, what is best is the test of what is right. In general, it will be found true that that system of government is most wholesome and most effective in the school, as weL as in the family and the state, which provides for indi vidual responsibility, and acts upon the sense of character and personal self-respect, rather than upon the regard for authority, and fear of exposure and of punishment. Extreme surveillance on the part of teachers, provokes resistance on the part of the pupil, and puts him in the position of self-protection. A generous confidence will ;neet a generous response. In school government there is need of closer defini tions of duty than in the family, and often of Need of rules written rules. There is more room for suspicion of arbitrariness and unreasonableness, than in the closer personal relations of parent and child, and more care is required to retain the convictions and sympathy of the pupils on the side of the government of the school. Without this moral support of the pupils, the influence is disastrous upon character, and the government is essentially a failure. The duty of the pupil involves obedience to all necessary regulations, such as may be deemed ne- The pupil's cessary by teachers. The judgment of the duty pupil cannot control in the matter. It is his privilege to express, with due respect, his opinion, and to expect all reasonable attention to his representations and wishes but here his responsibility in government ends, and the remaining duty is obedience. The pupil may be wiser than the teacher, as many private citizens may be wiser 211 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. than the president; yet it is the teacher's duty to govern, and the pupil'sto obey, and any attempt on the part of pupils to subvert this order, by dictation or combination, is pernicious and wrong. There sometimes exists a strange and painful antagoUnnatural an. nism, in large public schools and colleges, toagonism. ward the authorities-not the result of any real oppression, but the outgrowth of a natural repugnance to restraint. This is often regarded as a necessary incident to student life, as an opposition party is an in cident to civil government. In itself it seems a most un desirable condition of things, one which tends greatly to counteract the proper influence of teachers. It seems, too, unworthy of young men, possessed of good sense, and well disposed, to take an attitude of hostility toward the government of the school, and to regard with favor a breach of the laws, as if they were opposed to the interests of the student. If any ten of the same students were entrusted with the government, they would enact the same laws, and maintain the government, essentially, in the same form. The feeling must, in the first case, result from thoughtlessness, and a selfish regard to personal convenience and pleasure; and when once the sentiment is established, it is transmitted from generation to generation. The same obligation of deference and respect rests Duty of mu- upon the pupil, as upon the child in the family. tueal regard. There should be an appreciation of the teaclher's good intention, a toleration of his infirmities, and patience even under an ill-judged and hasty word. The first impulse of the pupil may be to place himself upon his rights, and make an issue with his teacher. A graceful yielding is the truer propriety, and the higher wisdom. A 212 DUTIES OF TEACHER AND PUPIL. corresponding duty rests upon the teacher to exercise pa tience, to put aside suspicion, to appreciate the generous disposition of his pupils. All successful school government involves this mutual co-operation-teaechers exhibiting a generous confidence, and pupils responding with a hearty sul)port of the government, and an intelligent interest in the order of the school. In concluding this brief examination of the subject of government, a remark or two may be offered upon some tendencies in our country, not altogether desirable. Respect for authority, and due regard for superiors in age and position, seems a little odious to our Unfavorable Intensely democratic sentiments. There is a tendencies. sup)erficial feeling, that it is unworthy of a man to lookl utip with deference to a tfellow-man in any relation. Yet, a hearty respect for age, and wisdom, and authority, is essential to manliness, and forms an important element ;n every true character. "Thou shalt rise up before the hoary head, and honor the face of the old man, and fear thy God," is the dictate of nature and of inspiration alike; and if the institutions of a country tend to sub vert the natural sentiment of reverence, they must in the end prove disastrous. It would not be strange, if, in the development of the democratic principle of government, extreme views should, for a time, obtain, and the natural and proper limitations of the doctrine of personal equality be left out of view. The rough freedom with which the highest officers of the governmnent are greeted in the gatherings of the people, is not wholly satisfactory It does not indicate a want of hearty respect for the gov ernment, and confidence in it, but rather the reverse, Still, it is proof of the breaking down of a natural senti ment which beautifies charac(ter, and adds a charm to tho 218 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. varied relations of society. True democracy, while it corrects the superstitious reverence for those in authority, does not subvert the natural relations of ruler and subjeet; and we may confidently expect that these extrava,,aiices will ultimately disappear. The chivalrous regard -liown to woman, in our country, is proof that, in the end the sentiments appropriate to all the relations of life will prevail. A similar extravagance of democracy, is seen in the Extreme indi- tendency to extreme individualism, exhibited vidualisn. in our civilization. The attempt at a sharp definition of human rights-the rights of men:, of women, and of children, providing a complete legal basis for the various relations of the family, is an exanmple. There is, doubtless, room for improvement in the laws which define these relations, but there may be danger of siub,ert ing wholesome institutions, breaking up family unity, in the endeavor to protect the individual. It is true that .1l institutions, governmental and social, are entirely instrumental-good tortheir uses, and of no value in themselves, and that all ultimate value is in the individual. But the good of the individual depends upon these instrumnentalities, and cannot be secured by any other means. To resolve the family int) a business organization, chartered by the laws of the land, the interests of the various partners to be secured by a specified dividend of the pecuniary proceeds, cannot benefit the individual. D)iities are quite as important as rights, and social rela lions as individual standing. Oui institutions encourage independence of opinion, independence and, with natural and proper limitations, it i of opinion the strength of our civilization; but there ii an extreme of independence which is offensive and up 214 DUTIES OF TEACHIER AND PUPIL. safe. It is in the order of nature that the young shloul(-J receive many of their views friom others, and formi their own opinions slowly, and with modesty. There ailt other duties beside that of independence of thoughlt. Ii1 the experience of all whose culture and pursuits incliile then: to thought, there is a period of transition frion vouth to maturity, a time for the examination of Oii('s beliefs, and their foundation. At this period there is danger, in the case of young, men especially, that they will break away from the views in which they have been educated, before they have become capable of laying sure foundations for themselves. Ill-considered and reckless opinions must be the result, and a general unsettling of the character. This danger is often encountered in passing from youth to manhood, and it is aggravated by a general pride of opinion in the community. M1odesty in the individual comes with years, and so,we may hope, it will come to a people. 21 t,, BECO1\D DIVISION. PERSONAL RIGHTS AND DUTIB& CHAPTER I. GENERAL PRINCIPLES. RIGHTS are based upon susceptibilities or wants. A tsotf capacity to enjoy, implies the right to the i hts. lative good adapted tc that capacity, unles some higher good, personal or general, contravenes. This principle is but a corollary of the broader principle, that the good of being is to be regarded for its own value. The great comprehensive want of every sentient na. The compre- ture, and the corresponding right, is wellhensive right. being, satisfaction, happiness. The capacity for this well-being is thle basis and condition of the right to it. The nature of each being is his charter of rights, and these rights can be determined only in the light of that nature. All the essential conditions of happiness, or well-being, are embraced in this charter of rights. Inr a human being, the right to happiness involves the subo-dinate rights of Life, Liberty, Reputation, Property because these are essential to his happiness. The list might be extended, but it is sufficient for our plrpose to consider these. GENERAL PRINCIPLES. Our Declaration of Independence, in its catalogue of rights, seems to make the pursuit of happiness a siubordi nate right, co-ordinate with others, whereas it is the sole generic right, comprehensive of all the rest. These rights, the general righlt of happiness, and the subordinate rights, which are the conditions of Inalienabe happiness, are often spoken of as inalienable. ght The term needs explanation and limitation. Every hu man being may forfeit these ri,ghts by crime, making his happiness, or some of the conditions of it, a proper sacrifice to the good of society. And even without crime, the right of the individual iiust sometimes be surrendered to the higher right of society. The only right which is strictly inalienable, is the right belonging to every being to be regarded for what he is, to have his interests made due account of. This right can never be compromised, or forfeited-is in the strictest sense inalienable; but the privileges which it secures, will vary with relations and circumstances. Duties are distinguished from rights, as having their basis in faculties, instead of susceptibilities; Basis of duin power to do, instead of capacity to enjoy; ties. blut in common with rights, they spring from the broad principle that the good of being is to be regarded for its own sake. The duty of benevolence is generic, and allcomprehending. All other duties come under this coinprehensive one. Among these may be enumerated, Piety, Philanthropy, Patriotism, Self-culture, Usefulness, and uch special virtues as Fidelity, Veracity, and Chastity No such enumeration can be exhaustive, nor are the du ties named perfectly distinct. They spring alike from be nevolence, and are but modifications of it; and, objectively, they may in some cases include, or imply, each other. 10 21,i' MORAL PHILOSOPHY Duties and rights maybe contemplated as correlatives Correlation of Every duty which we owe, terminates on rights and duties. some being as its object, and implies a right ill that being-a claim to the fulfilment of the duty. His right is infringed upon, if the duty is not performed. So cv ery right, pertaining to any being, implies a correspond iig duty on the part of all beings who are cogcnizant of that right. Duties, in general, are enjoined by positive precepts, Positive and while rights are protected by regative prenegative precnepts.ive cepts. " Thou shalt love the Lord thy God with all thy heart," " Remember the Sabbath day to keel) it holy," " Honor thy father and thy mother," are examples of duties enjoined; "Thou sllalt not kill," " Thout shalt not steal," " Thou shalt not covet," are examples of rights protected. A failure in duty may be forbidden by a negative precept, and respect for a right may be eiijoined by a positive precept; but this is not a departure from the principle, for a failure in duty is violation (,f a right, and respect for a right is fulfilment of a duty. But while rights and duties are thus intimately related, Subjects not the subjects of right and of duty are not nethe same. cessarily the same. A sentient nature, capacity to enjoy, is the sole condition of rights. and every sentient being is the subject of rights. A rational or moral nature is the condition of duties, and moral beings only are the subjects of duties. Moral beings are also sentient, and thus are the subjects both of rights and of duties. While every sentient being is the subject of rights, the rights must vary with the nature of the being. Even the brute has rights, which we are bound to respect; or, to speak more definitely, in brute life there is capacity for good, whtich moral beings must make account of. A 218 GENERAL PRINCIPLES. brute is not to be treated like insentient matter, but always with due respect to his susceptibility of pleasure and of pain. The absence, however,.f the rational element, gives us a freedom in the treatment of brutes, which Limit to tU rights of no being can exercise in the treatment of brutes. rational agents. The brute lives in the present. To him there is no past, no future. The value of his life consists in the aggregate of the animal enjoyment,which is involved in his experience, from the beginning to the end of that life. The satisfaction of to-day, is not affected by the remembrance of yesterday, or the hope of to-morrow. His life is an aggregation, not a unity. Hardship laid upon him, is simply a subtraction firom the present animal enjoyment, and leases no sense of injustice, or of apprehension, to cast a shadow over subsequent experiences. An unusual accession of enjoyment is simply an addition to the present good, and can never stand, in the experience of the brute, as compensation for the past, or promise for the future. His enjoyment goes for what it is worth in the present moment. Again, the fate or experience of one individual of the species, has no bearing to occasion pleasant or painful remembrances, or hopes or apprehensions, in another. There may be a present sense of loss, when a companion falls, but no pain. ful inferences mar the animal enjoyment. "The lamb thy riot dooms to bleed to-day, Had he thy reason, would he skip and play? Pleased to the last, he crops the flowery food, And licks the hand just raised to shed his blood." Ilence, we are permitted to use animal powers and Lfe as utilities, to minister to our own hap- Tobe treate[ Siness or welfare. To occasion wanton pain as utilities. 219 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. to brutes, is a wrong. It is a destruction of good without any resulting good. But if the good is transferred, bj nereased satisfiLction to a higher being, or even to a be. ,ng of the same order, such treatment is the proper use, and not the abuse,of brute life. WVe may take brutes to bear our burdens, or to minister to our good by their life, ar by their death, and we use them in accordance with their nature, under the law of benevolence. Tlhey may be treated as utilities, with the simple limitation that no wanton pain shall be inflicted, no animal life wasted. Such a use of brutes is in harmony with their nature, and doubtless secures the greatest amount of good,in connection with animal life, of which the nature of the case admlits. But no such privilege can exist on the part of any Human be- being. higher or lower, in the use or treatment ldgs not. of human beings. A rational being has a past and a future, as well as a present. His life is a unity, and not a continuity. An experience of ill in tle past, is not a mere subtraction from his happiness by the amount of that ill. The experience may bring a sense of injustice, ,)r of fear and apprehension. Iis highest interests depend upon his personality, his capacity to form purposes and plans, and realize them, and to sustain responsibilities and meet them. Subjection to the will of another, in any such sense as to preclude these plans, or essentially interere with these responsibilities, is inconsistent with his 1iihest well-being. Again, the experience of one rational being is of interest to all who become cognizant of that experience. Hope and fear, confidence and distrust, arise to men from the experience of others, as well as froro their own; and thus the interest of one becomes the in. terest of all The moral universe is a unity. The lhappi 220 GENERAL PRINCIPLES. ness of all depends upon the treatment of the individual; and injustice or hardship, in a single instance, unsettles the confidence and security of all, and makes their well-being mpossible. Some of the German philosophers seem to overlook this fact of personality, as distinguishing man A misappre. trom the brute, in his conditions of well-being, hension. and represent nature as careless of the individual, and careful of the species or the type. Schelling seems to represent that the individual is contrary to nature; and when the species is secured, the individual is swept away, as of no account. The species man, would be a blot upon creation, if the individual man were not cared for according to his wants and rights. Human society exists for the supply of these wants, and for the protection of these rights; and it is successful in proportion as it secures the welfare of the individul. Let us turn to the consideration of the leading rigL's with which man in society is invested. 221 CHAPTER II. RIGHTS-LIFX. As ife is a prime condition of well-being, the generi as ofr the right to be happy embraces the particulat eight. right to live. Every man, whose life does not stand in the way of the general good, can claim, in his relation to his fellow-men, the right of continued life. This right is protected by the sixth commandment: "'Tliou shalt not kill." The manifest interpretation of the precept is —thou shalt not murder, but, like the other commandments, it comprehends,by implication,a class of )ffelces against the person, and prohibits all violence, a', wickedness, all carelessness. The guilt of murder, which is the gravest form of {uilt of mur- violation of the right to life, lies, of course, in der. the cherished ill-will or bad intention-the misc(hievous purpose. This is the malice prepense which constitutes, according to human law, as well as divine the subjective element in the crime. Without this elec ment, homicide ceases to be murder; with it, the guilt exists, even if the outward act be wanting. "Whoso hatethl his brother, is a murderer." The legal term, malice, and the scriptural term, hatred, misunder- are often misunderstood as expressing a stnding. malicious feeling, the emotion of malice or hatred; but this is not the proper signification of the terms. The nmalice of thi law, that which constitutes the guilt, is an intent or purpose, irrespective of any feeling; and malice prepense is a definite, settled purpose against the RldITS —LIFE. life. The feeling is an unimportant matter, except as it sheds light upon the purpose,inaquestion of evidence. Malice of purpose may co-exist with utter indifference of feeling toward the victim, or even with intense pity. The highway robber, or the pirate, whose aim is plun. der, cherishes no malicious feeling towards the unknown victim,whose life he sacrifices to conceal the evidence of his crime. The man who plots a railway disaster, with the hope of plunder, feels no hatred towards the passengers whose lives he imperils or destroys. Yet these are all murderers, and their malice is in their purpose. They are enemies of the human race. The unnatural mother who murders her own child, may even weep in pity, while she nerves herself to the deed. The purpose to commit the crime, the malicious intent, may be more or less distinct and de]ib- Modifications crate; hence, it is customary, in legislation of the crime. and in judicial proceedings, to discriminate different degrees of crime. The modification of the crime of murder, which is called manslaughter, is involved in any destruction of human life, occasioned by negligence, or carelessness, or recklessness, without a definite purpose to kill; e. g., leaving a pit uncovered into which men are liable to fall; dischlarging a gun under such circumstances as manifestly to endanger life; driving a railroad train at a reckless speed, or with an unnecessary risk; attempting a case in medicine or surgery, involving a risk of life, without the necessary qualifications in knowledge and skill; or the crime may be committed while in th perpetration of any other illegal act, as theft or burglary because in all such crimes there is danger to life. The essential element, in all these grades of the crime, is the samne in kind-the absence of proper regard for human life. 223 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. Any crime, such as arson, highway robbery, kidnap Oter relates ping, slave-trading, obstruction of railroads, crimes. which involves danger to life, implies the guilt of murder, in a degree proportioned to the perceived danger. The guilt is incurred, even if a fatal result be averted. An occupation, like that of rum-selling, though generally recognized as a business, and not as a crime, if t involves danger and mischief to human life, and is in no proper sense necessary to the general good, carries with it the guilt of murder. Every man is held responsible for the obvious and natural consequences of his doings. It does not avail to say that the rum-seller intends no murder, that he regrets the loss of life which results from his business. A proper regard for human life would lead him to renounce his calling. In his regret at the destruction of life, he does not differ from the pirate, who would prefer to gather his spoils without murder. The time is sure to come when such a pursuit will be treated,is a felony. According to the Mosaic law, the man who suffered his "ox, wont to push with the horn," to go at large, was held responsible for all damage to life or limb which resulted. The principle is just, and capable of wide application. The right to life, does not imply the right to preserve Riglit of self- it at every sacrifice. Another may have no preservation limited. right to demand, what we may be under obligation to surrender. We are not permitted to avoid al exposure of life, or to pursue always the course which promises the longest life. The way of duty often lies through dangers. To keep one's self always out of the reach of harm, is y no means the privilege of responsib]e beings. In a common danger, others inay require us to expose 224 RIGHTS-LIFE. our lives to repel the danger. Thle government may righltfully compel a service, fraught with ex- Ina comaor treine peril, as in the mnilitaiy draft. The life danger. of aii innocent person may, in a rare emnergency, be re quired and taken, to save the lives of many. The pan amount law of benevolence affords thie only criterion foil suech cases. The right to life carries with it, with certain limita tions, the right to protect that life — the righbf zn ~~~~~~~~~~~~~Self-defence. of self-defence. There are methods of self -defence protection, universally acknowledged to be proper. We inay avail ourselves of any reasonable opportunity to escape the danger, or of any police arrangement which the government may afford for protection. But beyond all thlese, in a pressing danger, we may repel violence by such force as we may be able to command, even to the extent of taking the life of an assailant. The aim should be, in every case, merely to avert the danger, and never to inflict injury beyond the requirement of self-protection. The emergency which calls for such exercise of force will, of course, preclude very careful discrimninations; but such as are possible, should always be made. The right to defend life, extends to lives under our protection; and the right is even broader in ref- Defence of erenilee to such lives. We might be allowed others. to surrender our own lives to an assailant, when we coul, assume no such responsibility in reference to the life of aln other. We can have no right to occasion a wanton destruc tion of life in self-defence. We must have Wanton desome reasonable prospect of escape; other- struction. wise, the sacrifice of the lives of assailants is inexcusable To sell one's life as dearly as possible, is not a prope, 10' 22.5 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. maxim in self-defence. This principle applies only whlen there is some object to be attained beyond self-preserva tion. It would apply in the case of Leonidas and his men, when the safety of the countrv was at stake. The taking of life in the protection of property, is, in Not for pro general, utterly unjustifiable Those who use tection of property. deadly weapons to protect their grounds from marauders, have entirely transcended the limits of the right of selfdefence. The common law agrees with the Mosaic code in discriminating between the midnight burglar, whose purpose may be assassination, and the common thief. The one may be repelled with deadly weapons, at the hazard of taking life; the other may not. An attempt to punish ar assailant,oy inflicting injury iotto punish upon him, is not self-defence. The fact that A assilant. an assailant deserves the blow, is no proper -eason for inflicting it. When the assault has been revelled, further violence cannot be justified on the ground of self-defence. Retaliation must be carefully discriminated from self-defence. Those who discard the right of self-defence, often fail to make this discrimination. It is a grosser perversion of the doctrine of self-defence, to repel an insult, or abuse in words, by violence. The corrupt customs of the land have sometimes sustained such outrages. The general practice of carrying concealed weapons Carying cannot be justified on the ground of selfws~pons. defence. The custom is dangerous, pernicious, and doubtless results in the destruction of life, instead of its preservation. It is an offence against society, and is properly made a misdemeanor by law. The barbarous practice of duelling has sometimes been defended on the ground of self-protection-protection, not 226 RIGITS —LIFE. so much of life, as of honor. The principle of self-defence admits of no such application. The honor that is vindicated by the result of a duel, is un- ueing. worthy of the name. The preservation of true honor,which is only another name for rectitude, might justify the sacrifice of one's own life; but to assail the life of another, on such a pretence, changes honor into dishonor; yet this is the nature of the modern duel. The idea of the duel, in its origin, involved an appeal to Heaven to vindicate the right; and though such an appeal is utterly unwarrantable, it is not so utterly loathsome, as the attempt to save one's honor by shedding the blood of another. The motive to the duel, as it exists in modern society, is either vindictive hate, or moral cowardice under pressure of public sentiment. Neither of these notives can save either party in the transaction, from the guilt of murder. Objections against the Uoctrine of self-defence are some times based upon the Saviour's precept, "Re-, Resist not sist not evil. To him that smiteth thee on the evil." one cheek, offer also the other." But a caretful study of these, and similar passages, will show that they are directed against a spirit of resentment and retaliation, and not against proper self-defence. The love which " workethl no ill to a nei,ghbor,"is only benevolence, and benevo!ence is good-will governed by reason. If self-defence is reasonable, it is required by benevolence. The objection that the Lord will protect those who trust in him, and hence self-defence is unne-,The Lord eessary, assumes that self-defence is improper. will protect." If self-defence be right, then a trust in the Lord which is not presumption, will require the use of the legitimate means of self-protection. We must trust the Lord for 227 MORAL PHILOSOPIHY daily bread; but he that will not work for it, cannot exigect to eat. Trust, without labor, is not genuine trust. The idea that the avowal of the principle of non-resist ]ffectiveness ance,would exert such a moral force as, in a of non-resistance. great degree, to do away with violence, is based upon the same assumption of the wrongfulness of self-defence. If self-defence be reasonable and right, then there is no special moral force in tile principle of non-re sistance. It is simply an amiable blunder. As a rare exhibition, it might move an assailant to forbearance, like auy other unusual, kind-hearted scrupulosity. 228 CHAPTER IIl. RIGHTS - LIBERTI. LIBERTY iS the opportunity for the free exercise of out own faculties, in the performance of duty, and Definition in the pursuit of good, under the law of be- and extent nevolence The right covers not the privilege of doing as we wil, but as we believe we ought to will. Freedom from the restraints of duty and obligation is license, not liberty. No one can have a right to use his liberty beyond the limits of benevolence; but, practically, it is impossible to secure to men the privilege of free action, within the limits of benevolence, without giving them, at the same time, power to transcend those limits. The basis and the general limitations of the right, belong to morals; but the practical degree of freedom to be allowed by government, under different conditions of civilization is a problem in social and political science. That degree of freedom of action, which, under the circumstances, is consistent with the general Basis of the good, is the right of every moral being. Such right freedom is to him a condition of happiness or well-being; and the right to happiness, which is the comprehensive, generic right, implies the right to the essential conditions of happiness. The limits of the freedom which he can claim, are not fixed and unchangeable, but vary with his surroundings, or his relations to others. A being exist ing alone in the world, would be without restraint, except such as regard for his own good would impose. He would have a right tQ use e ery utility for his own ad MORAL PHILOSOPHY. vantage. Let a neighbor be given him, and his liberty is at once circumscribed. Adam, alone in the garden, had a right to consult simply his own convenience and coiifort in his movements. When Eve came, this right was circumscribed by the fact that her welfare ".s to be re Epected. Her right is of equal force with his, and thli ight of eaeL is limited by that of the other. The opinion has sometimes been set forth, that, in a Misappre- state of nature, men are perfectly free; but hension of its origin. choosing to enter society for their own advantage, they surrender to the society, as represented in the government, a part of their freedom, in exchange for the advantages it offers, retaining what is not thus surrendered. Such a view is wholly ideal, and does not tend .o elucidate the subject. A state of nature, as thus represented, has never been realized,except in the case of the first man. Men are born into society, and never have the choice of entering it submitted to them. There is no surrender of rights, for the advantages of society, as the theory supposes. The rights never existed. No one ever had any rights, but such as are consistent with the common good. These are the facts in respect to general society. There are some special relationships, which we are at liberty to form, or not; and, in forming them, we surrender a part of our freedom, for the advantages we secure. On this principle, we connect ourselves with others, in business, or in marriage, or enter a school, or a church. The right of liberty, limited lby benevolence, extend Extends to to all our powers and activities. Our bodily bodily pow.rs. powers, we are permitted to use, in accordance with our own wisdom. Others may be more wise, and thus more competent to give direction to these powers; 230 RIGHTS-LIBERTY. but they cannot, for such reason, assume the control of our powers, except in cases where the general good may re quire it. The results of our labor are ours, to use a(ccor(l iig to our discretion. We have the right of locomotion, the choice of place of residence, and of occupation. Yet these rights all have their limits. The governmelin may require and compel our service, for the promotion of the common interests, or restrict our locomnotion, and con fine us to our own locality, if the public good so demands. Such limitations may seem to render human freedom precarious, but they cannot be set aside. It is the more necessary, to guard the right with jealous care. The same right of self-direction pertains to our intellectual powers, and their results. These pow- To intellectu ers are ours, to cultivate and employ in fiee alpowers. thought and free expression. True liberty leaves us free, in the exercise of our tastes-the lower and the higherouresthetic nature. Sumptuary laws, regulating expenliture for personal gratification, are, in general, an infringement of human rights. Extreme public necessity, as in a famnline or a siege, will sometimes warrant the regulation of these interests by authority. A depraved or corrupted taste, like the love of strong drink, injurious alike to him who indulges it, and to society at large, may be rightfully restrained by law. Our moral and spiritual nature comes under the same principle of liberty, with even less restrictions. To the me.al We lhave a right to our own opinions, in mat- nature. ters of morality and religion; and to a free expression of our opinions, in action and in worship. Yet, even her6, liberty has its limits. Society has a right to maintain public order and morality, and to place such checks upon individual action as those interests may require. A re 231 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. lig,ious system, like Mormonism, which strikes at the foundation of public morals, or open idolatry, wljich tends to break down the religious sentiment of the coin. iunity, can claim no indulgence on the plea of liberty of conscience. Absolute toleration of all conceivable teaching and Limit of tol- practice, in morals and in religion, is by no eraticn. means a self-evident principle. There are sentimnents too atrocious and corrupting to be allowed utterance. The precise limit of legitimate toleration is matter of experience and judgment; and this limit will vary with conditions and circumstances. The right to cherish an opinion is not subject to limitation from without; but the right to express that opinion is always limited by the requirements of the general welfare. Until it can be proved that universal toleration is consistent with the best interests of men, government must have the right to impose some restrictions uponi the expression and practice of what may be set forth as a conscientious belief. Every error of opinion is more or less mischievous, and subversive of the public good; but, in general, it is wiser and better to leave such errors to find their own correction in the conflict with truth, than to attempt their suppression by authority. When the evil is gross and notorious, the right to toleration ceases. The freedom of the press is subject to the same limitaFredom of tions. In an ordinary condition of society, the press. little restriction is called for; but in times of public danger, the right to restrict and regulate, must be maintained and exercised. The power of the press is to be used, like every other power, in harmony with tllhe public interests. The claims of what is called free discussion, are not ab 232 RIGHTS-LIBERTY. solute and universal. Hie who has an opinion to set fortli cannot always claim a hearing whenever it Free discusmay seem to himi desirable that he should be Zion. heard. Each man has the right to protect his own famnily against the intrusion of what he deems dangerc us error; and the promulgator of a doctrine cannot complain against a conscientious exercise of this right. We have a right to establish a school in the interest of religion and truth, and to exclude from its positions of influence the teachers of irreligion and falsehood; and the conscientious exercise of this right, cannot properly expose us to the charge of illiberality or bigotry. We may organize a church, and build a house of worship, for the mainten ance of our religious views and our chosen modes of wor ship; and no demand for free discussion can require us to invite into the pulpit those whose teachings are subver sive of our conscientious faith and worship. We must accord to those of different views the same prerogative in their own field; and a conscientious exercise of this right, is neither ungenerous, nor intolerant. We are under no obligation, in our personal arrangements, to give to error the same opportunity which we secure to whlat we believe to be the truth. It is reasonable and wise to listen to the views of others, even when we deem them wrong, and often to give even to mischievous error an opportunity to set forth its claim; but the claim to such a hearinig niust be presented on the ground of courtesy, and not of right, or the hearing may be granted on the ground that it gives a better opportunity to the truth. How much civi. government may properly undertake, Duties ofecivil in the way of sustaining and enforcing edugovernment. cation, and morality, and religion, is to be determined by the prospect of success in the undertaking 233 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. No d prinmi principle can define the limit. Diffelett e-,nditions of society will give different solutions of the )rublemn. A state church, and ordinances of religion es tablished and enforced by the government, were approp)riate in the early history of the pecple of Israel. Oomipulsory education seems still successful in some of Worship and the states of continental Europe; but, in genoducation. eral, voluntary arrangements, both for educatiIon and religion, are found to be more in harmony with aodern civilization. But this condition of society does adot require that the government should be indifferent to education or religion, or should make no provision for them. A systemn of public instruction, sustained by taxation, of which the people may avail themselves, is found to be most efficient, and this fact is the warrant for its existence. Upon the same principle, the government may be justified in guarding a day from such secular occupations as would destroy its usefulness as a Sabbath, that the people may employ it for the purposes of religion. Such governmental protection seems necessary to the establishment and successful maintenance of the institutions of religion. The public enforcement of quiet, on one day in seven, is not an encroachment upon the rights of conscience; and if secular interests, in general, are not injured, then the appointment is in no sense oppressive. Even without divine authority for the Sabbath,civil government would be warranted in the appointment. In the domain of personal or private action, our liberty Subjective is, of course, limited by our own conscientious lmitations. convictions. We cannot maintain liberty of action,against our final judgment of duty. When another has no right to limit our freedom, our own consciences 234: RiGHTS-LIBERTY. Impose restrictions. But, beyond this, there is an impor tant sense in which we are limited by the consciences of others, and even by their imperfect views and infirmities Habits and practices, which might be safe and wholesomie to us, we have no right to indulge, when they become anti occasion of temptation to others. The apostle yields t( this limitation of his freedom, when he says: " If mea make my brother to offend, I will eat no flesh while the world standetli, lest I make my brother to offend." Tlhus our "liberty is judged of another man's conscience." The duty of total abstinence from intoxicating drinks, rests upon this principle more distinctly Total abstithan upon any other. In view of the weak- nence. ness of men in this direction, and the importance of diminishing temptation, and strengthening every favoring ,nfluence, it may be the duty of those to abstain, to whom a simple glass of wine would bring no harm or danger. If my indulgence would endanger a brother man, it is unbenevolent for me to vindicate my right. The claim of personal liberty in the case, is the plea of the selfish and self-indulgent. The same principle must apply to other indulgences, entertainments, and amusements, which have Other indulb come temptations to many. It is not gence. enoug(h that to ourselves they bring no danger, or even that in themselves, apart from perverted associations, they iiav be wholesome recreations. If they serve as a snare to others, the earnest and thoughtfiil will find their recreation in other channels. The effort to recover these iuestionable entertainments firom their evil associations, hias generally proved a failure. In the regulation of one's own conduct in these doubt tul miatters, definite lines, not to be passed, are of great 235 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. practical value. There is a gradual inclination from the Use o' do- innocent to the harmful, each downwar(dl step nite ides. so gentle and uniform, that one finds himself on forbidden ground before his attention has been aroused. In the midst of the enticements of pleasure, the necessary discriminations will not be made. ".Facils descengu8s, d revocare gradum "-the descent is easy, the return is difficult. There is sound wisdom in adopting a practical rule for ourselves, a rough formula, which we can always apply, even when, in the pressure of excitement, we cannot undertake an exact solution of the problem of propriety. The young man who adopts the maxim never to touch, in its mildest form, the intoxicating cup, will walk safely; while he who undertakes to decide each case upon its own merits, will be ensnared. Similal rules will be found profitable in reference to games and other amusements. These are for the regulation of our selves, and not a standard by which to judge others. They are not exact expressions of what is right, but conve nient approximations. Encroachments upon personal liberty appear in various Violations of forms. Government, in the family, the fibefty. school, the church, or the state, may oppress the individual with unnecessary restrictions, or with burdensome requirements and exactions. These may have been necessary in their time, and the necessity may have passed away, so that the subject is entitled to a larger liberty. Public sentiment, concentrated in the form of offensive or burdensome customs and usages, may lay upon the individual burdens grievous to be borne. It is not rare, in student life, that one feels compelled to incur an unreasonable expense, or sanction a folly, to maintain his respectability. Fashion is often tyrannous. No apparent 236 RIGHTS-LIBERTY. force is employed, but substantial penalties are inflicted The most odious instances of encroachment upon liberty are in the tform of personal violence- strength, oppress ing weakness s and the extreme example of this oppressior is found in chattel slavery, where manl is treated merely as a utility, an appendage to another's convenience ol interest. Slavery originates in personal violence, and is maintained by violence. The laws which regulate and sustain it, spring from slavery; they do not create slavery. We have a right to maintain our liberty, under an op pressive government, by moving for its refor- Defence of miation, and finally by revolution; under an liberty. oppressive public sentiment, by declaring our independence, and disregarding the corrupt custom; under personal violence, by an appeal to the law, by flying fromn oppression, and by personal resistance to aggression. The riglit of resistance has its limits. Even a chattel slave cannot properly vindicate his rights at any unlimited sacrifice of life, or open a path to freedom through indiserininate slaughter. An enslaved race or people, may be allowed to do, for themselves and their posterity, what fhe individual slave might not do. 237 CHAPTER IV. RIGHTS-REPUTATION PRoMNWr among human interests stands reputatlin Rep,tteation To every moral being, it is a condition of In iterest. happiness to be held in esteem by others. "A good name is rather to be chosen, than gieat riches, and loving favor rather than silver or gold." Reputation extends to all personal attributes and ac Extends to complisliments-everything which adds to in what? fluenece and power, or enhances one's position among, men, or which makes one an object of regard. That reputation is of most value which is based upon the Ihiglhest qualities. As moral integrity, genuine up. rigihtness, is the highlest personal attribute, a reputation ror such a character is most to be prized. But it is im portaint to be held in esteem for good sense, natural ability, professional acquiirements and skill, and every personal attribute necessary to success or happiness. Reputation becomes a good in two respeets, di rectly and indirectly. The moral approval aowagood. of others is immediately grateful. To be held in esteem for virtuous character, is, probably, next to his own approval, the highest good of every moral being. [here is substantial value, too, in esteem, bestowed for any personal excellence. Indirectly, reputation is valuable, as it is a condition of success in the work of lin. In any calling, a reputation for honor, and good judgment, and professional ability, is more important han capital. RIGHTS-REPUTATION. There is no one, however exalted, or howevei humble, t( whom a good name is not more than property. The proper claim to a reputation extends no fiuitliet than the real facts in the case will sustain. No oire can hlave a claim to be regarded beyond his true merit. The precept of the decalogue wlhich protects this right r unterest, is the ninth: " Thlou shalt not bear false witness against thy neighbor." The The precept. grosser form oi offence-false-swearing —gives form to the precept, but the law unquestionably forbids assault upon a neighbor's reputation, by positive misstatement, by insinuation, or innuendo, by expression of suspicion or apprehension, by partial statements, and even by silence when the circumstances require utterance. Even truth-telling, may carry with it the force of slan der; as when a past misdemeanor, long since discarded and corrected. is set forth as indicative of character, or an exceptional act is given as if it were characteristic. Such truth-telling is prohibited by the law. The sin of slander, like all other sins, is primarily sub jective-a state of heart,involving a disregard Temptations for a neighbor's reputation-one of the forms to slander. in which a want of benevolence shows itself. The temp tations to the sin are manifold. One of the most coni mon, is the consciousness of an unworthy character iii onle's self, to which an apprehension of similar unlworthi ness in others affords some relief. Out of this springs the disposition to uncharitable judgcinent of others, a censorious spirit, amounting at times almost to an inca -)acity of fair judging. It shows itself in a disposition t( oe pleased with the failures and frailties of others, a in,)sl unnatural and unbenevolent pleasure. A hleart greedy of scandal is another of the results-an ear open to di& 239 MORAL PHILOSOPHY paraging reports. In genera., it requires two parties t. perpetrate a slander, one to bear the false report, anothler to receive it. There is usually wrong in both parties to the ti aisaction. Another temptation to a disregard of the reputation Interest in of others, is in the pleasure derived from rsoual mat,rs. hearing or teAling some matter of personal interest. We are so constituted that facts of personal history and experience are naturally attractive and interesting. They form an inviting topic of conversation. There is a natural love for canvassing the peculiarities of our neighbors, which leads to hasty judgments of their character and conduct, and to inconsiderate statements. No malicious feeling is cherished, and it may seem a harmless style of conversation; but unfavorable impressions often result from suchl conversations; the reputation of a nleilghbor suffers. These communications are sometimes excused, on the ground that it is a convenient method of improving our knowledge of character, of hlltman nature. We might study anatomy by extending a neighbor upon the dissecting table, but the end would scarcely justify the means. It is better not to cultivate, or indulge, the habit of dissecting the characters of neighbors and fiiends. The habit of making prominent, even in thought, the Propensity to weaknesses and foibles of others, is not to be cacature. approved. All have their peculiarities, their infirmtities. In a sense, they have a right to them, as being inseparable from human nature. At least they have a right to considerate and benevolent treatment in view of them. Ridicule can be brought to bear upon the most exalted human character, by making these foibles prominent, presenting, the character out of proportion. 240 RIGHTS —REPUTATION. The result is, A caricature-a real misrepresentation, painful to the object, and tending to depress him unreasonably in the esteem of others. Ridicutle has its uses, but it should be aimed at follies, not at personal charac ter. The pleasure afforded oy it, when thus perverted, is an unworthy one. It cannot be denied that men hlave. very generally, a taste for personalities, and that a tale ol scanidal gratifies this taste. So does human flesh the per verted taste of cannibals; but we cannot afford victims for such barbarous pleasures. We have a right to speak truth unfavorable to reputation, when the common good requires. If Duty of exwe become cognizant of imposture that ought posingwrong, to be exposed, of crime that ought to be punished, or )f less formidable misdeeds that should be brought to light and corrected, it is not only right, but duty, to corn municate the facts to those who ought to know them. Each member of the community is, to this extent, s guardian of the general welfare. This principle applies in more limited communities; for example, in a body of students; and any view which holds it dishonorable for any member of the body to discharge such a duty, s false and corrupting. It may be called honor, or any other high-sounding name. It is, in fact, a base betrayal of grave interests, from a cowardly fear of a dishonest public sentiment. True honor requires every membe' of such a conmmunity to protect its real interests, by tlihe exposure of crime and dishonor. There is a cleardistiinc tion, which every honest man sees, between the work of e busybody, an informer, and the open and manly exposur, of wrong. We have no right to utter even truth. that is prejii dicial to another's good name, when no interest requires 11 241 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. it. Disagreeable facts in reference to personal 3har Slan(ler In acter, are to be left to forgetfulness, unness truth some harm is to be apprehended fromI sileiice. Slander may be perpetrated by speaking the truth, as wel as by propagating a falsehood. The same disregard I a nciglhbor's welfare, is involved in the one, as in tihe Ither. 242 CHAPTER V. RIGHTS-PROPERTY. TEEx right of property grows out of the prior right to our own faculties, and their results. Property Orgin of tw is the result of labor, or of the use of our right. powers. That this belongs, by right, to the producer, is as evident as that he has the right to use his faculties for his own good. The possession of the faculty would be of no advantage, unless its product could be appropriated, or made property. The good of the individual, and the welfare of society, alike depend on the recognition of the righit. Civilization advances, as this right becomes well define I and protected. A perfect civilization involves an exact distribution of the result of labor among the various partie that have contributed to the result. The idea that the claim of property is wrong and selfish, has been set forth at times in different formns of socialism and agrarianisin; but the comnmon-sense of mankind repudiates the idea. The right of property is recognized and protected in the eighth comirmandmnent: " Thou shalt not steal "-a prohibition of the outward act, in every form in which the right may be invaded; also in the tenth: "' Thou shalt not covet," which touches the sin 'n its subjective form, the indulged desire which leads to fi'aud. The methods by which property may be rightfully aL qtiired are various. The most simple, and Method a preol)ably the first, historically, is the appropri- acquiring. IMORAL PHILOSOPHY'. ation of what nature spontaneously yields. The capacity for enjoying, is the warrant for appropriating whatever may be at hand adapted to the want, both for present nnd future use. The good thus accumulated, or taken possession of by fore-sight and labor, becomes prloperty & new-corner must gather for himself; and not invade hit neighbor's possessions. A further step in the acquisition of property, is the employment of our faculties in the cultivation of the soil, profluting material for food and clothling. The product thus obtained, belongs, in the nature of the case, to the producer. The manufacture of articles for use, from material which nature spontaneously affords, or which is yielded from the cultivation of the soil, is a simnilar ground of possession. Articles thus possessed, may be transferCan be tranc- red by gift or by exchange. The owner of ferred. property can transfer his claim, in all its force, to another. The right to property descends, upon the death of the owner, to children or near relatives. If the right terminated with the life of the original proprietor, property would lose half its value. The fact that the government regulates the succession, does not prove, as some authorities claim, that the property-right has terminated, and is revived by the action of the law. Tlhe law merely recognizes the right, and makes it definite. The fact of discovery is sometimes spoken of as conRight of do ferring the right of possession. It is only overy. another form of acquiring, by the use of our faculties. If the finding be accidental, the case is not materially changed. The article must be appropriated, to be useful, and the finder is indicated as the natural owner. This law holds only when there has been no previous owner, and when the government has made no 244 RIGHTS!-P-ROI'E.RTY'. provision for the disposal of the property. This it may do, on the ground that such commodities belong to sociut) at large. Long continued possession may not only confer tlhe ight of property, but may transfer the right Effect of po. from an original proprietor, to the present sesion. possessor; because his interests are more connected withl the possession than those of the original owner, and to disturb such possession makes the right of property precarious. Even if possession were unjustly secured at the outset, the principle will still hold in the ease of an innocent possessor. To disturb such possession, on the plea of exact justice, is often the height of injustice. " Extremum j?us, extrema ifjuria." There are things which are most valuable in the sense of meeting want, which still cannot be Things not to be appropri. appropriated; either because they cannot, ated. in the nature of the case, be taken possession of, or because they belong to the race as a common inheritance. Of this class are air, and water, and sunlight, and space. Portions of these gifts of nature we can appl)ropriate, and exclude others thus far from their use; because thus only can these things be made useful. But no one can call the air or water of a vast region his own, and compel others to compensate him for its use. Equally preposterous is it, to take possession of the unoccupied land of a continent, and exact rent of all others who enter upon it. So much as we can profitably cultivate and render useful, we are permitted to possess, and beyond this the claim is very unsubstantial. The gov elnment rightly holds these unappropriated lands foi the benefit of society at large. A barbarous people, occupying a vast territory as a hunting ground, incapable 245 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. of vai;llg tlhetnselves of its agricultural resources, may be eoiiil)elled to accept civilization, and surrender a por tion of their domain to those who need. Their property. right is very slender, and may be extinguished somnetimei against their will, but not to their real disadvantage. Animrals are made property by divine appointment, and f,nim~s in accordance with their own nature; and nade property. yet they are not property, "to all intents, t)urposes, and constructions whatsoever." There is an absolute value in their nature, apart from their utility, and that nature must be respected. An utter disregard of their sentient nature is cruelty, and cruelty is a crime. A rational being cannot be held as property, a mere Human be- chattel. His true good requires that his 1ngs not. powers be under his own control-directed by his intelligence, and according to his own convictions of duty. Ience, he can never be, rightfully, made a mere appendage, a means of good to another. No human being can, in this sense, own another. This is the essence of slavery, according to its legal definition; not mere constraint, or compelled and unrecompensed service; but it transforms a man into a thing, treats him as a utility. One man may claim the service of another, and this claim may be treated as a property interest, and even transferred, as in the case of a child or an apprentice; but in every such case the manhood is respected, and the property interest is made subordinate to the personal good. Where the substantial interest of the individual requires, the property interest may be rightftll~y extingulished. The right of property, in its fullest extent, has its liar Limitations itations. There is, of course, the moral limJf the xight itaticn, which belor gs to all rights. Property 246 RIGHTS-PROPERTY. by moral right, is ours, to use benevolently, not waste fully, or wantonly; to use as we ought, not as we may please. We have the prerogative of controlling it, as against others. even beyond this; but to use property for any other than the best ends, transcends our moral right. Our property is liable for the support of government snd for our fair proportion of the burdens of Some of its society. Property must pay for its own pro- liabilities. tection; and assessments,to this extent,may be rightfully collected, even without the owner's consent. But beyond this, in great emergencies, the government may use private property for the public good, affording conipensation where this is possible. In the pressure of war, private buildings may be appropriated to public uses, or even demolished, to afford scope for military operations If compensation is possible, afterwards, it is well; but if :ot, the right to devote the property to such necessary public use, must still exist. The constitution of the United States, which forbids such use without compensation, expresses only the general propriety, not the absolute right. A private individual may, in a similar way, overstep the ordinary restrictions, in regard to property, to per form an act of common humanity, to feed the starving, or rescue the perishing, or even to save other more valuable property from destruction. The right of property arises under the great law of benevolence, and exists in subordination to that law. In exchange of property, the true principle is, to ask and offer what is equivalent in value-to give Law of ex what, in the market, will exchange for that change. which is received. Any other aim is dishonest, a violation of the rights of property. This is true commercial 247 MORAL PHILOSOPIIY. integrity. It is opposed to all sharp bargaininig, and tc all scheming by which the more valuable is obtained in exchange for the less. There is abundant opportunity for skill, and sagacity,and shrewdness in business; bul these qualities are to be employed in determining the real value of commodities, and what, and when, it is expe liest to buy or sell, not in getting the advantage in ex change. An honest bargain is advantageous to both par ties, and would be entered upon, even if all the facts in the ease were understood by both. The boast of having bought an article for less than its value, is an unworthy one, as really dishonorable as the boast of having passed base coin. Yet the perceptions of men are very obtuse on the subject. " It is naugit, it is naught, saith the buver; but when he is gone his way, then he boasteth." Of course, the true principle of exchange must take account of the condition of the market, and permit an article, under pressure, to be purchased for less than its ordinary value. All such limitations are involved in the principle itself. The ordinary business maxim, to assume that every Business man in trade will attend to his own interests, maxim. is, by no means, a safe principle of conduct. This maxim makes the simple the prey of the shrewd. Every man is, in some sense, his neighbor's keeper, even in business transaction; and if he finds him failing in discernminent, he is to protect his interests. In the matter of setting forth the qualities of the corn. ",t of the modities offered for sale, duty will vary with tender. circumstances. Every opportunity must be afforded for examination. Concealed defects must be disclosed. All that is said in commendation must be truth. The vender must see that the price he asks is a just and 248 R1GHTS-PROPERTY. fair one; and if the buyer is manifestly acting under some illusion, or mistake, he is to be set right. Beyond this, the seller is not, generally, called upon to offer his judgment in reference to the advantage of the purchase. Commercial honesty requires the correction of all er rorz, on either side. If the goods do not cor- Coretio of respond with the bill of sale, or if a mistake error. has been made in the transfer, honesty requires that the matter be set right. In general, the standard of value is the price in the market. It is not often possible to test or Standard of correct this standard, by considerations of the val,e. cost of the article, or by its intrinsic value. Its exchange value is the point of enquiry, and this is the market price There are times, indeed, when a conscientious man feels obliged to look beyond the temporary condition of the market. He may have every reason to believe, that the, present price is the result of some temporary excitement and that he who buys, at such a price, will inevitably suf fer. Can it be right to sell at such prices? or must the general market price be the standard for honest men, instead of the temporary price? There are practical difficulties in the case, which preclude a general answer tc the inquiry. Each case must be decided in its own light The alternative to a sale, at the market price, will comni monly be to suspend business until the speculative move ment has passed. This may often be impracticable, Hence the practical rule, for honest business, admitting of few exceptions, is to exchange at current rates. An effort to raise or depress prices, by shrewd maniago. ment, as in securing a monopoly, or p)rodu- Managingtb cing a glut, making a profit out of the loss of maket others, is utterly unjustifiable. A man of scrupulous in. 11~ 249 ,MORAL PHILOSOPHY. teg'ity would as soon take what does not belong to himn, by any other indirection. Extravagant prices, forced by a special and pressing necessity, it is not right to accept. If a king, in the crisis of battle, offers his kingdom for a horse, it cannot be right to accept the offer. In such emergencies, there is no market price; and transactions must be governed by those primary considerations which lie at the foundation of values. In cases of general scarcity, as in a famine, the usual law whirl governs prices must prevail. It is often duty to distribute to the needy, at prices below the market rates, but in deference to the claims of charity, and not of commercial honesty. Cicero, in his "Offices," proposes an instance under this general class: "A ship laden with corn, on its way from Alexandria Cicero's ex. to Rhodes, while a famine exists at Rhodes, ample. passes several other corn vessels, bound for the same port. When the vessel has reached its destination, shall the master sell his corn for what lie can get, conpealing the fact that such a supply is at hand, or shall he tell the facts, and then find a market for his corn" Cicero decides that he must tell, and that, to do otherwise, is to act the part of a swindler. The law of wages, is the same as that which regulates Law ofwages. other prices. The market rate is, in general, that which the employer is bound to offer. There are instances in which it may be necessary to look behind this, and correct a prevalent injustice, but, in ordinary cases, thie resultant of forces, represented in the market, involves more wisdom than any individual judgment. The fact, too, that it is impossible to employ labor, on any large scale, at wages materially above the market price, will justify adherence to that price. For the surest way 250 RIGHT —PROPERTY. to correct the market, and elevate wages, is not to refuse to employ the labor, but to open for it every possible channel. The price will advance under the increased demand. The price of labor, by right, depends upon what the aborer can accomplish, and not upon his per- Depends (on sonal wants. Every laborer needs all that he ability. can earn; if he receives less than this, he is wronged; if more, because he needs more, it is charity. If there be any reason, in morals, why a man's wages Woman's should be above those of a woman, it must wages. be because he earns more, can accomplish more work, and not because his wants are greater. If the wages of woman were increased, she would assume a part of the responsibilities which now fall upon man. It is to be observed that it is power of accomplishment, rather than the actual amount accomplished, in a particular employment, which is the basis of wages. In some varieties of work, a boy may be as useful as a man; but the boy cannot, therefore, demand a man's wages. If you call a man to do a boy's work, you occupy his powers-call him away from work suited to his capacities-and must pay for the power you engage. That a man and a woman should be employed in the same service with equal efficiency, and the man receive a higher compensation, does not necessarily imply injustice or wrong. It does imply, that the man is out of his place, because his powers are not employed to advantage. If, on the whole, in the rough work which calls for wages, with all allow ance for liabilities to interruption, man is the more pow erful working force, then there is a moral ground foi difference in the wages of men and women. But these principles apply only to those varieties of t 251 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. service which have an exchangeable value, and which Work above are quoted in the market. The highest waes forms of service which the world needs, and which men can render, lie entirely above the plane of wages. They have no equivalent in money. Of this higher kind, is much of the work of the faithful preachy and pastor, the missionary, the philanthropist; and even ot the patriot soldier. The pittance, furnished in money, does not pay for such service and sacrifice. We are ashamed to offer, or receive, a price for such work. The money compensation is regarded simply as a necessary outfit for the service, or, if more munificent, a grateful recognition of it. In this higher domain lies, to a very great extent woman's peculiar work —that of the wife, the mother, the daughter. For these higher services, the highest that can be rendered to humanity, there is no price. When we talk of wages, the wife becomes the housekeeper, the mother becomes the nurse, and the daughter the hired servant and paid domestic. Wages afford no The claim expression of the value of such work. Yet which arses. the claim of the wife, the mother, the daughter, is a real and substantial one, higher than the claim for wages. It is a claim for protection, and favor, and love, and all the material good which the husband, the father, or the son, can bestow from his poverty or his wealth. The woman, in the family, is neither a beggar nor a hireling. The law, in adjusting her claims, recognizes her right to wages; but this is only a rough attempt to save to her a remnant, after her higher rights have been denied. It is true, that the life of many women does not lie in this higher plane. They are obliged to fall back upon their power as laborers, and engage in the struggle for wages. They must work at a disadvantage 2.52 RIGHTS-PROPERTY. but they have a right to such a place as they can occupy in this field, and to wages corresponding with the work they do. Offences against the right of property, appear in all the forms in which it is possible for one man to Violations of ecure what belongs to another. The grosser the rigkt oreaches of the right are condemned by public sentiment, and are disreputable; but the less odious forms often involve grievous wrong. To contract a debt, without prose pective ability to pay at the appointed timle, or without a definite purpose to pay, is a common form of failure. To defer the payment beyond the time, without any ar rangement with the creditor, or to neglect the payment of wages that are due, is a still more frequent failure. These things betoken an absence of neighborly regarda want of respect for the rights of others. To neglect a debt until it is legally uncollectable, and then n. ~ ~ ~ ~~~~~~~Legal i eleame. account the claim as liquidated, is a more gross dishonesty. Morally, debts are never outlawed, buless, originally, they existed with some special limitation There is, doubtless, propriety in the law which sets a limnit to the collectability of a debt, but such a law cannot discharge the moral obligation. The proper force of bankrupt laws, is not in any power to release the debtor from his moral obligation. They have no such power; but it is in the protection they afford to the debtor, in his effort to recover himself, and acquire the ability to meet his obligations. The release from indebtedness is technical and legal, not real. Probably, the form of fraud most prevalent in our country, at present, is that which arises in the Aialrming d relation of the citizen to the government. moralization. From the pitvate Citizen, who conceals his property from 253 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. the assessor, or misrepresents its value, to escape &n i i significant tax, to the high official, who compromises the revenues for vast sumns, the lack of honesty is wide-spread aitd alarming. Unless the demoralization shall be found to be temporary, a result of the disturbance of values from an inflation of the currency, and of the sudde amassing of fortunes, in connection with the vast expeii ditures of the war, then the future of the country is discouraging and threatening. Corruption, generated in one relation, will pervade every other; and the very foundations of society will be broken up. There is reason to fear that the want of conscience toward the government, as a creditor, will soon display itself in respect Tendency to to the government, as a debtor. If it is not repudiation. wrong for the citizen to defraud the government, it cannot be wrong for the government to repudiate its obligations; and, before we are aware, we shall have become involved ill a permanent national dishonor. However intolerable this may seem, in itself, it is a light thing compared with the general corruption of personal and private faith and morals, to which it must tend. May God avert the calamity. The immorality of gambling lies not so much in the Immorality of fact that it involves the obtaining of money gambling. without an equivalent, which gives it the character of ordinary fraud; because the transaction is understood-agreed upon by both parties, each encountering the risk in the hope of gain. Undoubtedly the transaction is a dishonest one, in this view. But the chief mischief lies in its effect upon the character, unsettling all wholesome habits of thought and action, and stimnulating the imagination, with the hope of easy and speedy wealth1 without corresponding labor. Gamb)ling, in all 254 RIGHTS-PROPERTY. its forms, in the milner's tent, or at the stock exchange, appeals to this infirmity of human nature, and begets a reckless and unprincipled character. There are modes of conducting business, generally considered legitimate, which involve much of this element of risk and expectation. A single turn in the market may make or ruin a fortune. The man who prays, "lead us not into temptation," will shun these ways. In concluding the subject of rights, it may be well to call attention, again to the fact that the speci- Concluding tic rights now presented, are but particular remark. applications of the comprehensive right of well-being; and that the catalogue of specific rights may be extended to embrace every human interest. I have undertaken to present only the more prominent examples. Let us turn tc the subject of dutie& 255 CHAPTER VI. DUTIES-PIETY. Dur-ns are distinguished from rights, in having, as then Origin of du- basis, faculties-power to do. They are all ties. comprehended in the generic duty of benevo lence. They are alike, in that they imply regard for good for its own sake; they differ, in that they present different channels for benevolent action, or different forms of that action. The leading duty of man is piety-benevolence exerPiety, its na- cised towards God-regard for him for what ,"M. he is, in his being and character. The duty is expressed in the command, "Thou shalt love the Lord thy God with all thy heart." tie is to stand before all other beings in our regard, because he is before them. So we necessarily comprehend him. Since his being is greater, more valuable, than all other being, benevolence towards him must give him his proper place, must make him sFupreme. Piety, in its root and substance, is benevolence; but the Tn conscious most distinctly conscious exercise of the pious exercise. heart is not benevolence, but rather obedience to specific commands. The benevolence of the child townard the parent, shows itself in obedience. So,of the creature toward God. "This is the love of God tha we keep his commandments." Love of complacency-approbation of God's character, l,ol~veom- and delight in it-is necessarily involved in placency. piety. It is the certain result of a benevolent DUTIES-PIETY. attitude toward God. Benevolence is, doubtless, tfie love which the law requires; for love to God, and love to our neighbor are enjoined in the same precept, under one and the same expression, and must, therefore, be of the same nature. Any delight in God, without benevolence, is not the love of obedience. Piety invo'ves a recognition of personal relations with God, and the exercise of the feelings of de- Personal re ognition of pendence and gratitude and filial confidence. od. A benevolent heart places us in the relation of children, in personal affection and friendship. It leads to the exercise of reverence and awe, and all the emotions naturally expressed in worship. These are all provided for in the human constitution, and follow, spontaneously, the attitude of good-will toward God. Piety is the moral or virtuous element in religion, considered as a fact of experience. It is the ele- Relation to ment of duty-that which man is called upon religion. to render. It may be called the human element, in that it is a human exercise, though divinely moved. In religion, as an experience, there is another element-the divine-the supernatural communication of God with the soul. Religion s not whlolly benevolence, obedience, duty-doin,g —not wholly human. It brings pardon, peace, anid life-divine gifts-God's response to man's obedience. The entire experience is expressed in such scriptures as these: "If a man love me, he will keep my words; and mIly Father will love him, and we will como unto him, and make our abode with him." "Behold I stand at the door and knock; if any man hear my voice and open the door, I will come in to him, and will sup with him, and he with me." Religion, thus, vonsists of two elements-duties and experiences —what 257 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. we are required to render, and what God bestows in responlse. True morality or virtue always involves religion for Moality and true morality is benevolence, and benevolence religion. implies regard for God above all other beings A benevolence which should pass by the claims of God, would be an absurdity. But benevolence looking towards God. is piety. Every truly moral or virtuous man, is essentially a pioulS mnan; and piety is the duty-element in religion. The other expressions attend in their time ans place. It follows, of course, that there can be no true religion Religion without morality. Any mere movement of without morality. pious feeling, in the form of awe, reverence, adoration, joy, is not genuine piety, apart from a committal of the will to a true regard for God, as shown in benevolent obedience. Thus, religion becomes genuine Dy being grounded in morality. Attempts have some times been made to separate these two, which are naturally inseparable. Moralists, so called, forget God, and call themselves virtuous; religionists discard morality, and call themselves pious. They are equally,and fundamentally, mistaken. Still further, it should be said, that the natural approach Morality at- to morality is through religion. The most tained by religion. potent force in overcoming sin, is the constrainini, motives which religion, as a system of truth, presents; the great facts of God, his character, his provi deuce, his government, and his love to the unworthy, are the considerations which move to repentance, and to virtue. The first outgoing of the soul, in benevolent regard is towards him, who is the embodiment of excellence and goodness. Men become virtuous in becoming religious 258 DUTIES-PIETY. The reverse is a philosophical possib lity, but scarcely a practical fact. There is little power in abstract truth to move to virtue. Regard for the good of being may be seen to be virtue. The human will may be seen to be fiee to take the virtuous attitude. Virtue may be seen to be excellent and righlit-benevolence, the only true principle of life. The heart will still cling to its idols, with a result like that in Paul's case: " To will is present with me, but how to perform that which is good, I find not." The motives of religion, alone, are effective. Hence, morality prevails, only where the truths of religion are known and inculcated. The intuitive apprehension which all men have of virtue, is not effective to produce virtue. The philosophy of morality is useful and elevating, but practical morality does not spring immediately from philosophy. Man's first, great duty, is to come to God -to renounce self-dependence, and put himself under heavenly guidance. Thus, morality is realized through religion, and the extension of morality in the world, depends upon the extension of true religion. The most common opposite of piety, is not positive impiety-contempt of God; but, rather, a opposite of life of self-pleasing, and neglect of God. piety. Piety, as a duty, involves the obligation to observe all the ordinances of God's appointment-the Duty of woarduties of religion. Foremost among these, ship. stands the duty of prayer-of worship. This exercise is a communication of the creature, withtheCreator. If such conmmunication be possible, it is an obvious duty. Thle regard for God, must show itself in expressions of regard, in acknowledgment of benefits received, in con fession of sill, in seeking guidance, and help, and bless ilg. 259 MORAL PHIIILOSOPIIY. This is worship, involving adoration, tbhanksgiviliig, Posibiity of confession, supplication. rhe propriety of prayer. such approach is clear; the only question is as to its possibility. This is strictly a theological question, and the answer can only be suggested here. That prayer-communication of the soul with God-is possible, may be mnaintained, (1) From the nature of the case. God has made man dependent-needing his help, and guidance, and access to himself. Hle will afford the opportunity. (2) From the general instinctive movement of human nature. All tribes, and races, pray, and have always done so. (3) From Scripture. This sets aside all doubt. Prayer is everywhere presented as a privilege, and enjoined as a duty. Speculative objections to prayer are often felt, in referSpeculative ence to which it may be well to offer a word: objections. (1) God is benevolent, disposed to do all possible good. Hie can need no urging from his creatures. True, but he can do more for his creatures when asked, as a benevolent parent can for his children. The recognition of dependence on God, and the invocation of his help, gives him an opportunity to do what, otherwise, it would not be best to do. (2) God works by established laws, and we cannot suppose that he will modify his plans, or re-arrange his work, upon the application of his creatures. I answer, there is some misapprehension here. We cannot suppose that God is fettered by his own laws, so that he cannot respond to the expressed wants of his creatures. To be thus restrained by the machinery of his own devising, is a characteristic of a flinite being, and not of the infinite. God's laws cannot hinder his doing what needs to be done. (3) Prayer can only be valuable and i;nfluential, in its reaction upon the petiti,)ner. It 260 DUTIFS- PIETY dos him good to pray, and beyond this it can effect nothing. Then, when we discover this fact. there is an end of prayer. No one could ever pray with such a theory of prayer. The objection makes prayer impossi. ble, and the instinctive aspirations of men an illusion. Social and public prayer is as clearly appropriate as pri vate prayer. Tile family is, in an impor- Social and public wortaiut sense, a unity, with common wants and ship. trials, and joys and blessings. How fit to approach, in this capacity, the Giver of all good! The larger com munity of families has a similar demand for common worship. THE SABBATH. Since public worship is an obvious duty, and public relig,ious instruction an obvious want, a stated A Sabbath de time, appropriated to this duty and this work, is sirable. desirable. So much is clear from the nature of the case; out what amount of time, and what precise period we are to set apart for these uses, is a matter of revelation. The Sabbath, in its principle, is a law of nature - in its form, a positive institution. That positive enact- Its institu ment we find in the fourth commandment: tion. "Remember the Sabbath-day to keep it holy." The form of the precept indicates a previous establishment of the Sabbath. Of this we have the record in Genesis, which presents the institution as co-eval with the creation of man; an indication that the Sabbath was fo,r the race, and not for a particular people. A Sabbath divinely appointed, was desirable, to secure uniformity, and to gi\ve authority. A successful Sabbath, without such authority, would seem impossible. The intrinsically important elements in the institution 261 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. are, the proportion of time, and the precise ieriod. The Two impor- first, divine wisdom alone could deterllinle. ant elements. Human experience would probably nievel lctiiiitely decide the point. The last is a matter uponi viisiCh our judgment might act with more success. The lav is for rest from secular pursuits, and for religious celture and worship- a day to lead out the thought toward God. That day, then, most distinctly associated with the manifestation of God, is the one naturally indicated. Thus, at the beginning, it commemorated the work of creation. If we could not fix upon the day, in advance, we can, at least, justify the divine selection. Upon the consummation of the higher manifestation A change de. of God in the work of redemption, it would irable. seem desirable that the Sabbath should carry with it the associations connected with this higher work. If the old day were retained, the old associations would prevail. It would be difficult to turn the thought conr!ected with the Sabbath.fi'oln the old channel. A chancge of the Sabbath to another day-a day associated with the crowning event in the work of redemption - would serve this end. Thus the Sabbath would be enriched by the accumulated memories and associations. Such a change would seem desirable, were it only allowable. As a historical fact, this change was made early in the The change Christian era, and has been maintained down made. to the present time. As to the authority for the change, only a word or two can be suggested here. Fhe resurrection occurred upon the first day of the week 'Flie disciples gathered to consider the marvellous event. The Saviour appeared in the midst of them, and blessed them. A week later, on the first day, as they were gathered, the Saviour came again. Six weeks later, on 262 DUTIES-PIETY. the first day, the Pentecost, the promised gift of the Spirit was bestowed. Such memories and experiences gathering about the day, made it sacred in the regaid of the disciples. It would have required a divine prohiyi tion to prevent their assembling, thenceforth, on the firs' day. No such prohibition appeared, and it became th gathering day for Christians. The indications of this, in the New Testament, are few, but they are significant. In Acts xx. 6, 7, we read that Paul tarried seven days with the disciples at Troas; and on the first day of the week, when the disciples came together to break bread, Paul preached to them, " ready to depart on the morrow." The obvious implication is, that Paul waited for the usual gathering, on the first day, improved the opportunity with a long, discourse, and left the next day. The first day was thle gathering day of Christians at Troas. In 1 (or. xvi. 2, Paul directs that the people, on the first day of the week, shall lay by their contributions, "that there be no gatherings when I come," implying that they were together on that day. In Rev. i. 10, the prophet says: "I was in the Spirit on the Lord's day," indicating that at that time a day was designated as the Lord's day -a name by which the Christian Sabbath has been known from that day to this. We find no definite, express command, changing the Sabbath; but the manner of the change harmonizes with the genius of the gospel system. Other ordinances- public worship, baptism, and the Lord's supper-were instituted in a similar manner, anr in the same way the whole ceremonial systiem was abro ated and the spiritual instituted. That the ancient law of the Sabbath remains, only modified in one of its features, as a positive Obligation institution, is probable, from the fact that all permanet 263 MORAL PHILOSOP HY. the reasons for the institution exist as of old. Ratmr manente lex manet. The law stands while the reason stands. The introdluction of the precept enforcing the Sabbath, into the decalogne, among the principles of flindamental morality, is another indication of its permanence. The prpper mode of the observance of the Sabbath, we troperob- gather fromn scripture, and from consideration ,roervaob ervance. derived firom the nature and purpose of the Sabbath. Like all other ordinances and institutions, it is a means, and not an end. " The Sabbath was made for man, and not man for the Sabbath." It is subordinate to the claims of benevolence. Yet its chief and highest utility to man, doubtless, lies in its adaptation to religious uses. For these purposes, it must be protected from the intrusion of secular business and pleasure. There is a growing tendency in our land to make it a day of recreation and amusement, after the fashion of continental Europe. Such an appropriation of the day would degrade it from its highest uses. M]any cases of doubt can be proposed, as to duty, in the Casesof observance of the Sabbath. Such cases usu doubt ally bring with themtn the light, in view of which they are to be decided. So that an honest purpose to respect the Sabbath be maintained, these particular cases are less important than they may seem; and men of equal intelligence and integrity may differ in the decision of them. Students, perhaps, need special caution in reference to the uses of the Sabbath. Thley are not taken away fromr the scenes of daily thought and labor. The associations of every-day life gather abou them; yet none more need a Sabbath. The duty of piety includes the obligation to extend,in the world,the knowledge of God, and the institutions of 264 DUTIES-PIETY. religion; not i.e-ely as a means of securing the wellhing of then, bitrt promoting that regard and Duty to honor which belong to God in his own right. motereligion It is not for us to art that, in his exaltation and independence, he does Lot need this service. We have abundant reason from h-s word, and from the nature of the case, to believe that the regard and love of his crea tures are a good to him, and that he feels a loss, and a wrong, in their ingratitude nlid neglect. Loyalty to God must lead to all reasonable effort to exalt his name, and extend his worship in the earth. The view is very inadequate which bases this duty solely on the wants of men. The.laims of God are paramount. is 265 CIIAPTER VII. DUTIES —PHILANTHROPY AND PATRIOTISML NExT to piety stands the duty of philanthrory, which he duty.. is benevolence exercised towards mankindUse nature Its uature. regard for man, as man, because of his value, the susceptibility of well-being in him. Philanthropy is not a mere emotion, but is positive and responsible action-an attitude of will. It is exercised towards all men, irrespective of character or rela. tions, the good and the bad, kindred and strangers. The duty is enjoined in the conmmand: "Thou shalt love thy neighbor as thyself." The duty extends to enemies, as to friends: "Love ye your enemies, do good to them that hate you, and pray for them that despitefully use you and persecute you." It co-exists with complacency, when the object is worthy, and displaceicy, when the object is unworthy. There is a philanthropy of mere sentiment-a liking for our kind, which is natural ai)d commnon to man, and in degree to the brute —a kindly affection promipting to kindly deeds, more prominent in somne than in others. This is not inconsistent with the virtue, but may exist without it. There has been a tendency, at times, to set philanthlroRclation to py and religion in opposition to each other. reigion. They are, in fact, inseparable; neither is gen. nine without the other. True benievolence'comnprehends them both. This is both rational and scriptural. " Ie hath shown thee, O man, what is good; and what doth the Lord require of thee but to do justly, to love mercy, DUTIES-PHILANTHROPY AND PATRIOTISM. and to walk humbly with thy God." "Pure religion, and undefiled before God and the Father, is this, to visit the fatherless and the widows in their affliction, and to keep himnself unspotted from the world." True philanthropy prompts to every honest effort for the good of man. It does not aim to promote woe interest at the sacrifice of another, but is t favorable to every real interest. A true philanthropist may devote himself to a special work in the service of mankind, on the principle of division of labor, or because of special adaptedness or ability. Whatever his work may be, whether in the way of spiritual or intellectual or material advantage, hlie is still entitled to the honor of a philanthropist. It is somewhat common to appropriate the name to those who endeavor to benefit men in their outward condition; as to Howard, who labored for the improvement of prisons and hospitals. The distinction is arbitrary and technical. Paul, who preached the gospel from land to land, was as true a friend to man. Every good man is a philanthropist. The best evidence of genuine philanthropy, is not in the interest felt for some distant object which Test of phil. appeals to the imagination, without the often- anthropy. sive concomitants of actual present misery, or for popular enterprises, in which it is easy, or fashionable, or romantic, to be interested, but in the regard shown for those whom wo can reach, and the help afforded to the needy by our side, even when a love of ease, or a fastidious taste, or popular prejudice, would tempt to forget the work. Itf the para. e of the good Samaritan had been uttered in our land, the text would have been applied to our national infirmnity coiitempt for the colored race. This crime mars much that is plausible in religion, among us, and pretentious in 267 MORAL PHILOSOPHYt. philanthropy. "Inasmuch as ye did it not to one of these, ye did it not to ME." Misanthropy is not the usual opposite of philanthropy. rhe opposite. This is a feeling of aversion or repugnance to e op mankind, with corresponding action. It is, of -ourse, opposed to philanthropy; but a life devoted to per as nal advaneminent, regardless of human interests, using men for one's own aggrandizement or pleasure, or nieglecting them entirely, is equally opposed to philanthropy, and far more common. Patriotis,m is benevolence toward our own countryPatriotism as the people of our own land or nation. Love of i virtue. country-a sentiment of interest in the people to which we belong —is natural to us. This sentiment, sustained and directed by benevolence, is the virtue of patriotism. The natural feeling, associated with the impulsive action to which it prompts, without benevolence, is sentimental patriotism. This lower form of patriotism, is useful in society, gives unity and vitality to the nation, even in the absence of the genuine virtue. The impulse which rallies the frivolous, the selfish, and the vicious, to the defence of the flag, is the patriotism of sentiment, and not of principle. It follows the flag in a just or an unjust cause. True patriotism is not inconsistent with general benevReqireby olence, but is required by it. In the nature enevolenceof the case, those with whomn we are associated heave claims upon us which others have not. We are specially responsible for their interests, as having special ability to serve them. "He that piovideth not for his own, and especially for those of his own house, hath de nied the faith, and is worse than an infidel." But since patriotism is always regulated and limited by benevo. lence, it can never require us, in the interest of our 268 DUTIES —PHILANTHROPY AND PATRIOTISM. country, to trespass upon the rights and interests of another people. It is a blind sentiment, and not a principle of duty, which makes this demand. " Our country, right or wrong," is the watchword of passion, and not of virtuous patriotism. The sentiment is pernicious-subversive )f the true interests of our own country, as of No wrong to those of others. The true patriot does, in- others. deed, stand with his country; when wrong, to recall her from a course of aggression and injustice; when rig,ht, to maintain the right. Of patriotism, thus regulated and elevated, the mass of men are wont to be intolerant; and the true patriot often finds his sternest conflict with those who are controlled by the blind passion of patriotism. A low jealousy of other nations, a readiness to take a belligerent attitude towards them, is, by no means, indicative of true patriotism. The country may well pray to be delivered fiom such friends. Hatred of the " British" is not love of country. Intense party spirit is opposed to true patriotism. 1t is devotion to a faction, and not devotion to Party idtt the country. It is not rare that a political oppose. party will peril the welfare of the country, to promote its own interests; and will brand, as a traitor to the party, the man who, firom fidelity to the country, withstands the corrupt movements of his party. Political parties are, doubtless, necessary and wholesome; but they must be subordinate to the demands of patriotism. Disrespect toward rulers is unpatriotic-a disposition to discredit their motives, to injure their rep- Disrespect to utation, to embarrass their action. Even nrllers. when the ruler is personally unworthy of respect, there is sominething due to the position he holds. To treat himn with the consideration due to the office, is respect for the 269 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. nation, and not for the man. To have rulers whomn we cannot respect personally, is a source of corruption and of dang(er. We fail to discriminate between the man and his office; and contempt for the man grows into contempt for the government. The habit of disparaging an opposing candidate, puts him at a disadvantage when he has entered upon his office. A large portion of the people have been taughlt to despise him, and they do not readily accord to hiai the honor which is his due. Thus, intense and Inscrupulous partisanship makes him, who should be the hlead of the whole people, merely the leader of a party. The magistrate, in turn, is too apt to accept this position, to recognize his political friends as the firiends of the government, and his opponents as its enemies. Such are some of the fruits of party spirit not regulated by patriotism. A deep sense of wrong in the country, and the govern. Wrongingov- ment, sometimes leads to unpatriotic sentitrnment a temptation. meint and action. The earnest opponents of slavery have been, in past years, under great temptation. They were in danger of failing to appreciate the real value of the government, and of assailing slavery, by acts and measures, scarcely consistent with patriotism. It is the common danger of those who rise up against a wrong sustained by government. A strong provincial, or sectional sentiment, setting intense pro- aside proper national feeling, and interest in cialiM the country as a whole, is inconsistent witl true patriotism. This was the failure in Southern society. The people were Virginians, Carolinians, Georgians, Southerners, not Americans. They had not eniough of national interest and feeling to stand by a stable government. Indeed, the civilization in some parts of the 2'i 0 DUTIES —PHIL,THIoPY AND PATRIOTISM. South was, to a great extent, opposed to the idea of gov. erilment, whether national, or state, or municipal. The tendency was to a feudal or barbaric freedom-every man supreme in his own domain, much after the fashion of the time when there was no judge in Israel: "Every man doing that which was right in his own eyes." Every organization, political or social, which tends to clannishness, weakens the common interest, Unpatriotic and diminishes the proper national feeling, is tions.iz inconsistent with the highest patriotism. Secret political and social organizations, as existing in this and other lands, seem to be of this nature. They tend to disorganize society, to sunder the ties upon which national uity depends. 271 CHAPTER VIII. DUTIES-SELF-CULTURE. EviRY human being is under obligation to make the It rature and most of himself-to become all that is possi reasons. ble to him, in excellence, efficiency, and capa city for good. The work of making such attainments may be called self-culture. The reasons for the obligation are, fbst, the intrinsic value of every man's being, the absolute good which it involves; and, secondly, its value in relation to the good of others. Every human life involves good, in both these aspects; and the amount of good depends on the culture attained-the perfection of faculty, and susceptibility. The work of self-culture pertains to every department Extends to all of our nature - the moral and spiritual, the our faculties. intellectual, the emotional, the esthetic, and the physical; and the demand in these various directions is more or less pressing, according to the bearing upon our welfare, or our usefulness. In itself, a symmetrical culture is desirable, a harmonious development of all the The true faculties and susceptibilities. This is the ideal. true ideal, but it is not always attainable, not always to be aimed at. The aim of every one must be to walk in the path of duty, and to pursue that form and degree of culture which lies in the line of duty. He must meet his obligation; he may or may not attain to any high standard of culture. Personal wel Duty fare and usefulness, both, require that duty have the first place; and it is entirely possible that duty DUTIESS —SELF-CLULTURE. may not lie in thle direction of the highest culture. In deed, personal welfare and usefillness are both subordi ilate to the general good, or, in other words, to the claims of duty; hlence, the all-controlling aim of every moral being must be, to maintain the attitude of benevolence. Everv form of personal good is subordinate to this. To maintain a rilght moral attitude, is rather a matter of self-control than of self-eculture. The religious faculties and susceptibilities stand first in their claim upon our attention, requiring what Spiritual cup. we may call spiritual culture. It is desirable ture. that our spiritual nature should respond fully to the re vealed facts of the spiritual world - that the truths we intellectually apprehend and embrace, should move the setr sibility, and stand before us as permanent realities. It is un worthy of beings, of a spiritual nature, that the great truths of the spiritual world, truths pertaining to God and our own immortal being, should seem to us unreal and dream like, accepted in the thought, but not reaching the heart These are the great truths of the universe, and should have their due place in the soul. This con- Added to vit dition of experience, and of life, is not identical tue. with rightness of heart, or a correct moral attitude. It commences with such a state of heart, but extends to the intelligence and the affections. It is not attained by mere exercise of the will, because it is not simply an attitude of the will; but it is a matter of culture and of growth, like every permanent habit of the soul. The first right step is the commitment of the will to the truth, a treatment of the truth as true - the exercise of faith, in the sense in which it is a duty. Continued contact with the truth will bring the soul permnanently under its powers This is a work of time and of culture - of contempla 12* 273 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. tion of spiritual realities, and communion with God in prayer, and in the ordinances of religion. It is, of course, Progressive a progressive work, like all culture, and call work. never be said to have reached its limit. It requires time, and faithful endeavor, like every other ex. eellelt attainment; but the result is worth the expenditure. In the technical language of the Church. this work is often called sanctification, and results in permanence of the religious life, and enlargement of spiritual power. All the spiritual faculties and susceptibilities share in the 5nproveinent, and this growth must continue until, as the Apostle expresses it, " we all come in the unity of faith, and the knowledge of the Son of God, unto a perfect man, unto the measure of the stature of the fullness of Christ." At such spiritual culture it is the duty of every man to ttainable to aim. A good degree of it is attainable, in S l. every walk of life; and what are often reckoned as disadvantages, may be made to contribute to spiritual growth. It is to be distinguished from that moral state which we call virtue, or rightness of heart. It enmbraces virtue, and is based upon it, but involves conditions and experiences outside of the attitude of the will. Intellectual culture is so obviously a want, and a duty, Duty of inte- as scarcely to require mention. It is a conldilectual cul- tle ual cup tion of self-satisfaction, and of power for good. To what extent it is to be pursued, how much of time and energy are to be devoted to it, are questions which must be carefully settled in each particular case. There are duties more pressing than that of high intellectual culture and attainment. The claims of dependent parents on their children-of the country, in an emergency, upon its young men, and ether duties growing out of the natu 274 DUTIES-SELF-CULTURE. ral relations, must be carefully discharged, even if the work of intellectual culture is thereby deferred or arested. Health is not to be sacrificed in the pursuit of intellectual training, for learning and culture, with- Things to be held suborout health, lose their power and their value. dinate. Money may be freely expended, and the opportunities of acquiring it relinquished, because intellectual culture is better as a possession and a power. Time may be generously devoted to the work, because the time that remains will bring richer results; and it is doubtful whether any expenditure of time, on the part of the young, could be more satisfactory, irrespective of results, than that devoted to intellectual pursuits. The opportunity of immediate usefulness may be deferred, in the prospect of higher usefulness to come. the young, in their ardor, sometimes press into the field, when they would better serve their friends, their country, an,i the world, by awaiting the drill and discipline required to make their lives effective. A favorable opening for a settlement in life may be bravely disregarded, for one who is well prepared for life, will find in this superior preparation more abundant openings. Inability to secure the advantage of schools, will not excuse from the duty of intellectual self- Duty under disadvanculture. -Iuch is still possible in the way of tages. self-improvement; and the more difficult the attainment, the more useful it may prove. A brave heart will trans form difficulties into advantages. In so far as the acquisition of knowledge is involved in education, the useful is to be preferred to Knowledge to the curious, because culture is to be used, as be sought. well as enjoyed; and, indeed, the use is essential to the enjoymnent. For knowledge that is not, useful, there can 275 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. scarcely be a place in a course of education. But the inexperienced are often deceived in their efforts to dis. criminate. They seek the knowledge which affords im mediate material advantage, in preference to that which enlarges and elevates. Our view of utility must compre. bend man's entire nature and destiny. There doubtless is knowledge that is more curious than useful; and a life devoted to its pursuit, is a life of self-indulgence, lit erary dissipation-less degrading than gluttony or drunk enness, and yet to be avoided. Our emotional nature, the sensibility, requires care and Culture of culture. Upon this part of our nature, many ensibility of the influences from without, the good and the bad, operate; and from this source spring the impulses which move to action, and which give effectiveness to action. Motives to right action, and temptations to wrong, alike address themselves to the emotional nature. Our established associations, or trains of thought, are greatly dependent upon the sensibility. What we call habits, both in the realm of thought and of action, have their seat chiefly in the feelings. Power with others, depends greatly upon a quick and Gve power. generous sensibility. Personal influence, the Gares power. power of one man over another, is the result, not chiefly of superior discernment, or logical acumen, though these are helpful, but of the impulse and inspiration springing from the emotions. It may not admit of logical explanation, but it is the secret of magnetic per sonal power. There is, properly, no moral character in the move Relation to ments of the feelings, but the feelings are moral chat ter. greatly dependent upon the character, and are often indicative of the character. As modified by the 276 DUTIES-SELF-CULTURE. moral attitude, tbhey fall within the province of oblige tion, and hence, in general, appropriate feelings are required of men. Still further, from the feelings springs the immediate impulse to action, the internal force which rouses the soul, and prompts its movements. Thus, the feelings are potent in determining the character; and the precept of divine wisdom is rendered most appropriate: "Keep thy heart with all diligence, for out of it are the issues of life." What a calamity is a perverted sensibility, depraved and aggravated passions and desires, or an imagination charged with corrupting and loathsome imagery! What a blessing is a pure heart, each desire chastened and regulated, every train of thought tending to elevate, and the imagination wholesome and helpful To secure and maintain such a heart. is a work of care and culture. It is only indirectly that we can regulate or cultivate our feelings. We cannot, at will, summon Control inda those which are desirable, or dismiss the un- rect. desirable; but we can give direction to our thoughts, and occupy our minds with the things which purify and elevate, according to the injunction of the Apostle: "Whatsoever things are true, whatsoever things are honest, whatsoever things are just, whatsoever things are pure, whatsoever things are lovely, whatsoever things are cf good report; if there be any virtue, and if there be iny praise, think on these things." By such diligent and persistent attention to the things which are excellent, the imagination can be cleansed and elevated. The regulation of our associations with others is of equal importance. "Evil communications Care in smWa (associations) corrupt good morals." Cor- mtercourse. rupt and degrading feelings are contagious, and diffuse 277 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. themselves mnore readily than mischievous ideas. False. hood, in thought is, in general, quite obvious; in feeling it is hidden, and the error enters more readily through the heart than the head. A sneer is often more effective than an argument, and an appeal to feeling prevails when direct attempt to pervert the judgment would fail. IIu nmai feeling diffuses itself like leaven. If the contagion of impurity exists in any heart, it extends itself to others. Let your friendships, your life associations, be with the pure in heart. Similar importance attaches to the books which we Danger from take into daily companionship. Each writer books. infuses his own personality into the book Which is an expression of his life; and if his personal presence would corrupt, it cannot be safe to associate with him in his books. It is not necessary that the volume should present false ideas or doctrines, or any error which admits of logical expression. A false spirit is even more dangerous. A refined and latent misanthropy, or voluptuousness, may be diffuised through the pages, as potent and as baleful as the miasm which breeds fever, or pestilence. Positive falsehood, or gross sensuality, attracts attention, and arouses resistance, while the miscllievous spirit springing from a corrupt sensibility, and tending to corrupt, escapes observation. The reader is fascluated and degraded, while he imagines himself refreshed and elevated. It may not have been the purpose of the writer to lead astray. The mischief is in him, and diffu ses itself like the contagion of disease. Shun the im pure, even in their books. Pleasant and profitable relations with others, depend Relations more upon the regulation of the feelings, than wth others of the thoughts, (r ideas. The discords which 278 DIJUTIES-SELF-CULTUR E. disturb the family, or society on a larger scale, do not arise from difference of opinion, so much as from excited feling, which refuses the control of reason. Incompatibility of character, which interferes with the relationships of life, is the offspring of feeling, and not of thought. What are popularly called notions, as distinguished from rational convictions and principles, are conditions of the sensibility. There are characters that seem to be made up of likes and dislikes, that have their right sides and wrong sides, that must be managed as carefully as an illtrained animal, lest some perverse feeling should disturb the quiet. All such liabilities are unreasonable, the resuilt of an unregulated sensibility, and are unworthy of beings endowed with the regulative principle of reason. Some persons seem to excuse themselves for their unreasonableness on the ground of strong feeling, and even to require the respect of others for their extravagances of temper, which render them disagreeable. It is better to cover up and repress our own infirmnities, while we defer to the weaknesses of others, as far as the requirements of good society may suggest. Perfection of character consists in the supremacy of reason, and such Perfection of movements of the feelings as correspond with character. the occasion. To this result, self-knowledge, self-govern. menlt, and self-culture, all conspire. 279 CHAPTER Im DUTIES-SELF-CURLTUE. THE development and culture of the higher tastes is Esthetic cul- essential to completeness of clharacter. These ture. tastes are, in part, intellectual, and, in part, emnotional; but it is convenient to consider them as a dis tinct department of our nature. Their improvement becomes a duty, not on the ground of the intrinsic value of the beautiful, but of its relative value, its adaptedness to satisfy a human want, and add to human power. Theiculture and gratification are sometimes thought to be unauthorized, as involving an expenditure of time and means, that should bc. devoted to better uses. but it is no. difficult to see that they pay their way, blessing their possessor with a richer subjective life, and endowing him with greater efficiencv in his action upon others. It is true that these tastes are an expensive part of our nature. They multiply and extend our wants. Our chief expenItsexpensive- diture, in the way of dress, and food, and neft. dwellings, and surroundings, is imposed by our higher tastes. It is on this account that provision for human comfort is more costly than for that of brutes, aInd that civilized life involves greater expenditure than savage life. But man is better than a stone, or an oyster, because of his multiplied susceptibilities, and necessities; and his true elevation is found, no(t in suppressing or Elevatingten- neglecting these wants, but in adjusting dency. them to each other, and to his conditions, in1 giving prominence to the genuine, and permanent, DUTIES-SELF CULTURE. and ennobling, and in repressing the unreasonable, the factitious, and degrading. Those who have labored in the dark places, to elevate human character, have often found, that one of the first steps, is, to awaken a desire for a better external condition, to implant or arouse some w;ant or sense of the seemly, and the decorous, in apparel or in dwelling. To want,,is the nature of man, and low animal wants and passions are repressed, and held ill check, by awakening the elevated tastes and desires. Nature will break out in somie unseemly form, if the proper channels for its movements are obstructed. In place of comely outward adorning and appointments, we shall have tawdry display and barbaric splendor. In place of genuine social enjoyment and refinement, we shall have gross sensual pleasures, and a grovelling life. The result warrants the expenditure. But while esthetic culture is expensive, it increases the productive power of a people in a greater Increaqes ratio than the expense. The power of the power. world lies in the cultivated nations. They not only supply their own increased wants, but have a surplus of energy, and power, to expend in benefiting others. It is the rude, and uncultured, that constitute the needy and dependent of the world, even with their diininished wants. There is power in men, according to their motives for action; and their motives for action are multiplied and elevated) in the multiplication and elevation of their wants, and in the conscious excellence of their being Culture brings self-respect, and in self-respect there L power. There is a somewhat prevalent idea that high culture brings weakness, in the sense of inability to A miappi* endure hardship; that the increased sensitive- bensio. 281 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. ness to the annoyances and inconveniences of life, idihcates inability to bear up against them. The idea is not well founded. The cultivated man has resources within himself, which are not dependenlt upon mere outward condition. He finds relief and refreshment, where another finds nottling to meet his wants. He has superior strength to struggle with difficulty, because he has higher motives in the conflict, and a greater stake upon the result. This view is abundantly supported by facts. The men who survive the lhardships of a perilous expedition, like that of Dr. Kane, are those wliole minds are enriched, and characters elevated, by the higher culture. Even with less stalwart frames, they wvill live to bury their comrades, who rejoiced in mere physical strength, or to bring them through by their superior endurance. Women, refined by culture to true delicacy of feeling and perception, stand up and tive under the self-denials of emigration, and of frontier life, while those, apparently less sensitive, and better fitted to endure, die. They have higher reasons for living. Life is more full and rich to them. Young men, brought up in the midst of the refinements of life, and trained in the schools, endure the hardships of the camp and the field, while the rugged, but uncultured, are broken down by disease, or die of nostalgia. We often pity molt, those who least need our pity. There, doubtless, is a form, or show of culture, which Fae refne- brin gs weakness instead of strength. There ment. is an outside refinement which etherealizes and attenuates the body, instead of expanding and ennon bling the soul, which burdens the person with unreal wants, instead of sustaining him with substantial and permanent resources. Thene seems to be a point where civilization or refinement ceases to be an advantage, and 282 DUTIES-SBELF-CULTURE. becomes a burden-a limit beyond which the conveni. ences and comforts of life become annoyances; and yet it will perhaps be found that the failure is not in degree, but ill kind. True refinement has its foundation in the permanent susceptibilities of the soul, and consists in a reasonable provision for these. False culture consists ir generating unreasonable and arbitrary wants, and in a(, cepting the burdens which they impose. These two are as clearly distinguishable as the dictates of true taste, and the demands of fashionable life. There is, too, a refinement which degenerates into fas tidiousness-a self-conscious and pretentious Fastidiousdelicacy, more alive to the offensive than to ness. the pleasing. There are those whose culture is more a source of annoyance to themselves and to others, than of pleasure, and more to be avoided, even, than rudeness or coarseness. The preventive and the remedy for this disease,is benevolence; a true and genuine sympathy with God and humanity. A true culture is as valuable in our adjustment to others, as it is satisfactory in internal experi- Power in cul. ence. If not an original element of power in ture. personal influence, it is at least a regulative force which gives effectiveness to personal power. It is like the balance wheel in machinery, which regulates the movement; or like the oil, which reduces the friction. Steam power would be utterly useless without a lubricator. So a sense of the proprieties of time and place, an appreciation -)f fitness and unfitness, brings al' the movements into har,,,v. It tones down the ruggedness of mere intellec ilitl or physical power, and gives it wise direction. A lelicate and discerning lnovement is more efficientt than 4 stronger but rougher force. Such an instinct of pro 283 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. prieties, in part original and inl part acquired, is some times called a knowledge of human nature; but it in volves no theories, no conscious ideas; it tempers and ad. justs theories and ideas to practical and effective use. It is in demand in all the relations of life. The rough and uncultivated yield to the charmasreadilyas others. The influence in society exerted by a lady of true refineThe cultiva- inent and delicacy of character, it is difficult d lady. to analyse or explain. It lies not so much in beauty or elegance of person, in vigor, originality, or brilliancy of thought. All these are valuable, and contribute to the result. Nor is it merely the power of moral worth. This is essential, and without it there is no satisfiactory result. But add to this a delicate sense of proprieties, a quickness of perception, to adjust herself to others, to occupy the place that falls to her with dignity and ease and you have a civilizing force not easily estimated Her power will not lie in the new ideas she sets forth, nor in the vigorous enforcement of her views. Shle may not vote or lecture. There is power in the graceful goodness which beams from her countenance, in the beauty and harmony of her action and her life. Evil will fly before her as darkness yields to light, and truth and goodwill spring up in her pathway. The general culture of which such a character is the pro Iowattae duct, I have called aesthetic culture, using the Ilow&trained.X term, possibly, in a wider sense than is coininonly accepted. Its attainmer t does not come with what are technically termed, in education, the acconmplishments. They may fail to bestow it, and it may be secured without them. Profie.ciency in the fine arts, even to the extent of an appreciation of the great masters, is not a guaranty of true refinement, and genuine culture. 284 DTIES-SELF-CULTURE. All these are helpful, but there is a way more sure and simple. He who opens his heart to the requiremenets of benevolence, who conies into sympathy with divine goodleSS and love, walks abroad upon the earth where God's beauty smiles, and lifts up his eyes to the heavens in which his glory shines, will sooner or later find that beauty and glory reflected in his own spirit. Thus we may attain a culture higiher than ancient or modern art can give. The question how much time and means we are per. mitted to devote to the culture and gratifica- The attention tion of our aesthetic nature, has never been proper. answered, and cannot be. lIany modifying circuinstances enter into each particular case, excluding the application of any general formula. The claims of )enievolence are always paramount; and in the ever-varying conditions of life, we must render a conscientious judgment upon the demands of propriety and duty. Station in life, and relations to general society, are among the factors which determine the result. The man in public, and the man in private litfe, have different necessities, and different standards. What would be propriety for the one, would be extravagance for the other. The mistress and her mnaid sustain different responsibilities, and, in the mnatter of personal adornment, one cannot be the Anodel for the other. Life in the city, and life in the country, student life, and life in general society, have each their own requirements, and each gives its own solution of the problem of good taste and propriety. Some allowance, too, is to be made for personal peculiarities iL taste. To one, a picture, or an instrument of music, is only less necessary than daily bread. To another, the absence and the presence of such things are alike indifferent. These persons have lifferent wants, ""I 8 5 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. and are permitted to make reasonable provision for these wants. TLe world is the richer for these personal differelices. Propriety and duty are also modified by the demand )rtherde- for effort in other directions. The world is ,iands to be on..idered. full of pressing want, sometimes at the very door. Purple and fine linen and sumptuous fare are pleasant and desirable; but the benevolent, and the conscieIlitious cannot enjoy them,wliile Lazarus lies at the gate. The wants of the country and of the world must always be considered. In the presence of great destitution, especially near at hand, large expenditures for the indulgeice of taste are offensive and unwarrant able. Attention to the impulses of taste, to the neglect ot Neglect of higher personal wants, is equally unwvorthy. higher wants. A character formed under exclusive or excessive attention to the niceties and refinements of life, is sure to be feeble and shallow. It is thus that dandies and fine ladies are produced, and the dilettanti of literature and art, not the soulful men and women, whose personal presence is a power and a blessing. To buy a coat when you need a dictionary, to travel for culture when you need to work or study for discipline and strength to patronize the milliner and neglect the instructor, are mistakes of this sort. Taste and art furnish the adornments of life, not the grand material of life. A clear discrimination is to be made between the A discrimina- requirements of good taste and the demands tion. of fashionable life. A nmoderate outlay would meet the real natural want, while the arbitrary demands of fashion and ostentatious display are a bottomless abyss, swallowing all resources, and yielding only empti 286 DUTIES-SELF-CULTURE. ness. The attempt to meet such demands is utterly vain and the burden which they impose is too grievous to be borne. In this direction, sad mistakes are nladle. Those who, with moderate means, could nmeet their own simple and reasonable wants, and have a surplus for works of charity and beneficence, with enlarged resour es, falling into the tide of fashionable life, find thei, wants mrlltiplying more rapidly than their means, and charities give place to indulgences. There is a proper ratio, variable, not constant, between expenditures for beneficence and for tine refinements of life; and those who find the former yielding to the latter, need to readjust their plans. Our physical powers are given us to improve and tc use, and the general duty of self-cultutre ex- Physical ca. tends to these. This duty has a two-fold as- tureaduty. pect. The body is the instrument and organ of the mind, and our intellectual and spiritual activities and movements are dependent upon the conditions of the body. A sound mind comes with a sound body. Every disturbance of the physical condition produces a reaction upon our highest and noblest powers. Duty to the soul, involves duty to the body. Again, our physical powers are among the faculties which we are to employ in the service of God and lman. To neglect, or abuse, or pervert them, is to fail in the trust committed to us. Duty, in the way of physical culture, implies proper attention to health. Health is the condition Attention to of effective action in all the work of life; and health. ,ny course which undermines the health, or fails to supP]y its conditions, is wrong, and if unnecessarily pursued, is a sin. Excessive exertion of body or of mind, neglect of bodily exercise and relaxation, harmful indulgence of 287 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. appetite, are among the ordinary forins of transgression It is rare, in experience, that due thoughtfulness conmes, until the evils of neglect and abuse are incurred. The acquisition of manual accomplishl)ents and skill, anud ski is among the duties connected with the body. I.Jrlbe. It was a wise provision of the ancients, that en erv inan, whatever his condition or calling in life, shoul,' acquire skill in some handicraft. This wholesome prac Vce has fallen into disuse. Yet utter inability to use, for the ever-present wants of life, so cunning an instrument as the hand, which God has given to every man, is a misfortune and a wrong. It gives, even to the best, an appearance of dependence and inefficiency, which is unworthy of them. The hours of leisure and relaxation, which belong to the busiest life, are adequate to such attainments. Proper attention to form, and bearing, and manners, Peno,olman- belongs to the duty of physical culture. Each le>@ man should endeavor to get full possession of iis own person, and be at home with himself-not seem an ntruder in the body given him to inhabit. These per%onal accomplishments are pleasing in themselves, and add to the influence which it is every one's prerogative and duty to exert. The formation and maintenance of such personal habits, And habit. as render one agreeable as an associate itn the family, and in general society, is an obvious duty. No one has the -light to render himself offensive and loathsome by habits which mar the counten-ancee, or pollute the breath, or detract from the dignity and excellence of his physical nature. Nor has one a right to sllbject himself to the slavery of unworthy habits, in eat. ing or drinking, or in the use of vile narcotics, which seem 28.q DUTIES-SELF-CULTURE. to be the evril genius of fallen human nature. From all such unclean spirits, it is the privilege and duty of God's rational creatures to be free. In a l efforts at Plysical culture, it should be borne in mind, that the soul is predominant, and the The soul prt body subordinate. The highlest condition of dominant tie man is that in which the soul acts with greatest free d)m and vigor This is, in fact, the highest corporeal c,,ndition, as well; or rather, it is the condition of great ebt physical efficiency and enldurance. It is not estabilied that the fullest muscular development, or the most porfect exhibition of the animal man, is most favorable to efficiency or power. It is by no means clear that muscle is not sometimes cultivated at the expense of brain, and animal strength at the sacrifice of nervous energy and power. It is at least questionable, whether he who makes a gymnast of himself, is not sacrificing the higher to the lower nature, and, whether, in the end, he s not the loser, even in the domain of physical power and achievement. This is a question for physiologists, but it is one which cannot fail to interest every friend of humanity. The growing admiration, in our land, for exploits of mere physical strength and prowess, possess- Retrograde ing the popular mind, and even invading our tendency. schools of learning, looks like a retrograde movement in civilization, rather than an advance. It is, perhaps, but a needful reaction from the general neglect of physical culture which has prevailed; but it cannot be necessary at this day to repeat the experiment of Sparta. It is a grave mistake, too, in the question of physical culture, to overlook the predominance of the The moral moral element in human nature. He who predominant. 13 289 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. studies man, in his capacities and wants, as lie would study a mere animal, can never trust his conclusions. Man is a complex being, and must be contemplated in the completeness of his nature. The effect of moral motives ul~on human power and endurance, must nct be 'ver]ooked. Men live and work, sometimes, because they have good reasons for it, and not because there is any apparent basis in their physical condition for so doing. If the facts were gathered, in reference to those who have b)een the benefactors of the race, in the fields of literature, and of moral progress generally, it would probably be found, that the vast majority of them have wrought under a constant struggle with some physical infirmity. Pain has often proved the necessary stimulus to exertion. The nervous restlessness, which comes with suffering, expends itself upon enterprises which bless mankind, and the interest felt in the enterprise reacts upon the sufferer, to lift him above his infirmity, and give him new energy, and a longer lease of life. It is no rare thing that the feeble outwork and outlive the stronger. All this does not prove that health is not a good to be sought and preserved. It is one of the compensations by which Divine Wisdom balances the advantages and disadvantages of life. Those deprived of full physical vigor, may still labor with good courage and hope. These hints may serve some purpose, in suggesting tlhe different forms in which the great duty of self-improx einent may be pursued. It is a duty that ends only with life, perhaps not then; and when all that is possible l as bI)een accomplished, there will still remain sufficient:f infirmity and defect to save from -elf-exaltation, and to test the f)rbearance of friends. 290 CHAPTER I.' DUTIES-USEFULNESS. Ti duty of usefulness may seem somewhat compre hensive or vague, but it expresses the obliga- Its naturead obligatorition resting upon every one to hold himself, his ness. faculties, and resources, at the service of being, subject to the claims of God and of man. This is the duty in its generic form, expressing what should be the aim and purpose of every one, to make his life subserve some good end; to contribute, according to his ability, to the aggregate of general well-being. A life thus devoted, stands opposed to a life of self-indulgence-a nursing of one's own ease, or comfort, or pleasure. It is not, in any sense, opposed to one's higihest good, or to a true regard for his own well-being. The duty rests on the double basis of good to others, and good to ourselves; what we can do, and what we shall receive. A life of usefulness is the only satisfactory life, and this, of itself; would be a sufficient reason for its pursuit. It is the practical outworking of benevolence, which is the vital principle of all duty. The benevolent man necessarily enquires, how much good can I do?-not, how little may I do, and still secure the reputation and rewards of a virtuous life. There is in the human constitution, an impulse to uso ulness, as to every other duty, and much Thenatural human effort must be attributed to this gen- impulse. ,rous impulse. It exists in different degrees, in different natiures. One person is naturally self-seeking, a receiver, rather than a giver; looking for benefits rather than MORAL PHILOSOPHY. bestowing them, accounting it a hardship t,) have to con tribute to another's welfare. Another is natutrahy self forgetful, looking for opportunities of usefulness to others, finding a pleasure in meeting their wants. The obligations of benevolence rest upon these alike; operating, in the first case, to suppress the selfish impulse, and form lihe life and character to generous action; in the second, to sustain the generous impulse with a permanent principle, and render genuine the goodness which was only specious. But the duty of usefulness must be made a study. It is not enough to maintain a benevolent heart, and assume that the way of duty will open of its own accord, and the life take care of itself. "Wisdom is profitable to direct." The purpose of usefulness must enter into all plans, and govern the life. The choice of an occupation, a life-calling, is to be de a} ocp termined by its relation to our usefulness. ti quired. Industry, employment, is a duty, even when it is not a necessity. Indeed, it may be said to be always a necessity-a necessity for self-satisfaction and comfort, if not as a means of support. But, aside from this, no one can have a right to leave his energies unemployed, while there is work to be done which would contribute to human welfare. Every one needs an oc( apation, one that commends itself to his judgment as worthy of him. In the first place, it must not be harmful-a business Not to be that panders to the vices of men, and derives trmfni. its profits from their weaknesses. The man is a nuisance in society, whose business contributes to humanl degradation. In the advance of intelligence and public virtue, he will be accounted and treated as a felon. At present, a gross offender is restrained by the necessity of procuring a lic(,ense from the state, or is restricted in 292 DUlTIES-USEFULNSS. his mischief by statutes. Wiiat relation has the production or sale of ruin or tobacco to the proper work of life t In the next place, the occupation must not be- useles No business can be approved which does not contribute to human welfare. It is not eea enough that it brings satisfactory returns, and that these may be used in the work of usefulness. There is no propriety in accepting any return for a work which the world does not need. It is of the nature of fraud to take pay for such work. It is an unworthy occupation to fasten one's self upon the business of the country, with the purpose to contribute nothing to its movements, but, only to divert something to one's own advantage. Such a man is in a false position, and can give no satisfactory reason for occupying a place in the world, and receiving a support. What good account can he give of himself, whose business is speculation in Western lands, or in Wall-street stocks? The pecuniary return which an occupation may yield, is not the chief point of enquiry. The work The work more than is of more consequence than the pay. The pay. pecuniary return may be regarded as the necessary means of living and working, not as the prime reason for working. The pay can sometimes be dispensed with, the work cannot. This consideration applies not merely to those pursuits which are immediately beneficent in their aim, as the work of the preacher, the physician, the teacher, but to all occupations which contribute to the common good. The man is unworthy of his calling, who finds his chief satisfaction in the wages he receives, and who hastens to shuffle off his work, the moment he can iive without it. Any positively useful occupation is a worthy one; but 2,q "I MORAL PHILOSOPHY. those must be considered as most satisfactory, which beat Adapted to most directly and clearly upon human welpow, 8. fare; and the higher the wants which it meets, the higher the calling. But there must be a correspondence between the faculties and qualifications devoted to any pursuit, and the work to be done. It is unseemly to waste fine abilities, and high education, upon the work of a porter, or a boot-black, although these are useful and proper pursuits. Socrates once said: "The man is idle who can undertake anything better than what he is now doing." There is a vast amount of idleness of this sort; and yet it is better to accept the humbler occupation, than to go staggering under burdens too heavy for us, or to struggle for positions for which we are not qualified. It requires some fortitude and grace to subside from a public to a private position; and he who can do it when the occasion comes, is worthy of all honor. It is better that there should remain some surplus of Not exhaust- strength, after the ordinary duties of the call~.g the enerv es. ing- are discharged. Every man needs a busi ness that he can manage, and not one that will overwhelm him. Some men seem to be absolutely swallowed by their pursuits. You never see the man-only the merchant, the schoolmaster, the mechanic. The man is mnore important than his calling, and should be able to keep his head above the tide of business. He should roe serve some strength for the common offices of humanity, for the family, the neighborhood, and for general society. We are perhaps more ready to look too high, than too Not aboe us. low, for an employment. A longing for what Rot above lu.* seems a more worthy occupation, is no rare tLing in human experience, and it oftener arises from a fwlure to app reciate the work in hand, than from at con 294 DUITIES5-USEFULNE88. ciousness of powers unemployed. One who does heartily what he finds to do, will not often suffer for want of a wider sphere of action. The way to get better work to d), is to do well that we have. "To him that hath, shall be given," is the principle upon which work is assigned by God and by men. There are few that fail in life for want of favorable openings; many because they do not earnestly enter into the work before them. The mistake is sometimes made of confounding publicity or notoriety with usefulness. A work Notoriety not appears useful, according to the display it usefulness makes, or the degree of attention it attracts; hence a disposition to under-value the more quiet pursuits, where the great work of life is done, and seek the more showy. It should be borne in mind that a work is to be estimated by its depth, as well as by its breadth; and that the field tliich seems a narrow one, may yield richer results, by eason of its greater depth of culture. The work that is o wide-spread, is necessarily superficial. All can become heroic; but only a few can be publicly recognized as heroes, or become historical. We can all do brave deeds and if the tide of history turns in our direction, we can launch our bark upon it; but it is not in the power, even of the strongest, to make history, or to compel in it a place for themselves. "Lives of great men all remind us, We can make our lives sublime;" but they do not teach us that we can attract the attention (;f tfe world to the sublimity of our lives. That is th dream of a spirit of self exaltation, not the lesson of history. Wealth, as well as personal influence and power, is to be regarded as a means of usefulness, to be wealth a employed conscientiously and benevolently mea 295 MORAL'PHILOSOPHY. It matters not how that wealth has been acquired, whether by inheritance, or by one's own laboI and econ. omy; the same responsibility attaches to the possessor, to use it wisely for the common good. The money is his, not merely to administer to his eInjoyment, not to be coilumied upon his lusts, but as a sacred trust, to be ein. ployed according to his highest convictions of duty. The responsibility is a grave olne; but it always comes with possession. It is often found easier to acquire wealth, than to use it wisely. The struggle for the acquisition, not rarely perverts the character, and unfits for the enjoyment and wise use of property. The habit of acquiring and hoarding becomes fixed, and the idea of using or dispensing cannot be received. "A penntiy saved, is worth two earned; " but a penny well expended, is better than either. Money is good for nothing else. Careful gather ing and hoarding are virtues only when directed to a worthy end. It is the weakness of men to cling to their wealth until death, and then purchase the mnerit of a beneficent life, by bequests to worthy objects. This is better than to squander it, or to leave it as a burden or a curse to children; but it is better still to devote it to its proper uses, while the owner lives to control its distribution and its use. Children are injured, not merely by receiving the property as an inheritance; they are often ruined by the expectation of receiving. Let it be wisely dispensed as it accumulates, and thus avoid both dangers. Such a course requires benevolence, and wisdom, and decision of character. The owner of property has the prerogative of determining to what good uses to apply it; this privilege or duty comes with ownership. Special obligation devolves upon those who have made large accumulations of wealth. Grant that their acqili. 296 DUTIS-USEFULNESS. sition has been honestly made, without any failure in integrity; it is still true that they have re- Wealth brlngi ceived more than a fair return for the labor specialduty. and skill bestowed. In the distribution of the profits of labor and capital, accomplishled by the rough adjustments of business, they have received more than their just pro portion. No redistribution is called for, or is possible The results of business, honorably conducted, determine the property right. But a thoughtfil and conscientious man will not fail to consider, that what he has above an average return for the labor bestowed, has come by imperfect distribution. His dividends have been unreasona bly large, and others have lost what he has gained. He cannot find the exact sufferers, and make up their loss but he can regard his wealth as belonging, in a very proper sense, to the community, and use it to promote the public interests. In addition to the ordinary claims of benevolence, this obligation rests upon him as a matter of justice. Money may often be devoted to works of immediate charity. This use is the most obvious, and Works of would seem to involve least question. But it charity. is not uncommon that mistakes are made in such a distribution, especially when the donor undertakes to strike out for himself some new line of beneficence. The work requires the highest diseernment-a wisdom which aomes only from experience, and the one who undertakes it without experience, will often be disappointed in the result. But the difficulty of the work will not excuse from the duty. Another channel for the distribution of wealth is in the utilitarian enterprises of manufactures, or Usefal enter. comnmerce or public improvements, whicI fur- vPo 297 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. nish employment to many, and multiply and distribute the comforts of life. It is true that men, generally, invest in such enterprises, purely as a business transaction; but a higher view is possible, and, doubtless, often cherished — the aim to use the money wisely in contributing to human welfare. This aim is sometimes shown in the disposition to distribute, as far as possible, the profits of the investment, among the operatives whose labor has won them, either in increased wages, improved d wellings, or in multiplied advantages of schools and churches. The work of the money-lender is also legitimate, and Money lend- may be made beneficent. It brings together ing. capital and capacity, and opens doors of useful occupation to those to whom they would otherwise be closed. One who resists the temptation to take advantage of the necessities of men, and extends a helping hand to industry and to merit, may serve God and his generation as a money-lender. We may use our money for present comfort and sup Peouses. port, and retain it as a reasonable provision for the future, or as an outfit for children entering upon life. We may expend it in the comforts and refinements of life, in apparel and personal adornment, suitable to our condition and relations, in providinga pleasant home,with suitable surroundings, a refreshment to the owner, and a blessing to the community -not because we have a right to the money, and can use it as we will, but because such uses are benevolent and proper. We have no right to expend a dollar for ourselves, which we have reason to believe would do more good bestowed elsewhere. Possession does not deliver us from this stern law of duty. Social position and personal influence are among the 298 DUTES-USEFULNESS. resources which must be made to contribute to useful ness. This power depends, not chiefly upon Social lnuwealth, but more upon culture and character. e — In part it may be inherited, in part acquired. It belongs not merely to the prominent and the favored, but attaches, in some degree, to human nature in all conditions, to the old and the young, the learned and the unlearned, the rich and the poor. Each, in his own circle, exerts a force which may be used benevolently, or thoughtlessly and harmfully; in the correction of what is wrong in society, and the support of what is right, or in spreading and perpetuating mischief. Social life has claims upon all, and involves responsibilities, from which we cannot be excused. It may seem easier to live isolated, to cast off Dutytoall. social obligation, because it is so difficult to meet it, or because of pernicious customs in society, which it is hard to withstand. The excuse is not sufficient. Society is a necessity, and the conscientious, and tlhe good, are needed here, as elsewhere. The quiet, but mighty influence of oenevolence, and fidelity to duty, will tell, even where worldliness and vanity seem to be predominant. The difficulty, often felt, is to meet the mischievous or questionable customs, which invade social life, and maintain a conscientious position he ty. without failure or offence. We cannot go far without meeting such difficulties, and if we would shun them lit terly, "we must needs go out of the world." The ques tions, how far may we go in the fashionable entertain ments and amusements which tend to dissipation? what may we join in, and what must we omit? where is the linle between the permitted arnd the forbidden? can never be answered and, if answered to-day, they would return 299 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. to-morrow. One may go forward with a frank and ear nest heart, waiting,where doubt arises, until better light ,hall come, and the difficulties and dangers will not be found formidable. Conscientiousness, tempered by gen tleness, will rarely give offence, and will often acconiplisb more in the way of social reform, than vigorous preaching or denunciation. The work calls for courage, and fidelity and patience, and prayer. Young people have their earlier experiences of per fteponsibili- sonal responsibility in these social relations. ty of theoh young.O They constitute a prominent element in this department of social life, and have much to do in deter mining its form and character. They need all the prin ciple and good sense that they can command, to avoid the evil and to follow the good. They determine for themselves whether their associations shell be refining and elevating, and refreshing, or coarse and low, and dissipating. It is vain to look for any sufficient light in definite and formal rules. Many particular questions may be answered, but there will often be occasion to fal] back upon the instinct of a serious and earnest and conscientious heart. This will rarely mislead. In all efforts at usefulness, it is to be borne in mind, The groat that the great want of mankind, is a knowlwork.sr edge of God, and regard for his will. This vant is the source of almost all the dissatisfaction and misery with which the world abounds; and this want supplied, the work that remains is simple, and easily accomplished. Those who wouldlive lives of usefulness, need to carry with them this conviction, inspiring their hearts, and shaping their actions; and, however their hands may be employed, their efforts shall yield a rich result of beneficent an I saving power. The highest good 300 DUTIES-USEFULNESS. that one can lbestow upon another, is to make the facts o3t God's bei(ng and character more real to his thoughts, and this is the work of the earnest ioul, in every sphere of life, and n every occupation. 301 .o CHAPTER XL DUIES- FIDELITo A Ew special duties are still to be considered, and, clenng ol without attaching any significance to the order, we will take, first, the duty of fidelity. This term is commonly used in the general sense of faithfulness il meeting all obligation. In this chapter, it will be used in the limited sense of faithfulness in the fulfilinent of contracts and promises. This duty is sometimes confounded with veracity, but there is an obvious distinction between them. Veracity refers to the attitude of mind in making a statement; fidelity to the conduct which follows, in the case of promises and contracts. There are, at least two parties to a contract. These may share alike in the obligations and Two par. *advantages, or the obligation may be chiefly on one side, and the advantage on the other. In the latter case, the engagement is ordinarily called a )romise. The two transactions differ in form, not in essential nature, and the same principles apply to both. The binding force of a contract lies in the fact that in terests are involved in the agreement, and ~Lnding force. grow out of it. An agreement in reference to a matter utterly indifferent to both parties, has no binding force; or, if any at all, it must lie in the fact that the mere fuilfilment of the engagement becomes an interest, as a matter of morality and duty. That no such )bligation arises, is manifest from the fact that a contract may be dissolved by mutual consent, when the DUTIES-FIDELITY. interest of neither party requires its fulfilment. No inquiry or thought arises in reference to the interests of alorality in the case. If, in any case, the fulfilment of a promise becomes detrimental to the one to whom it ii made, the obligation to fulfil ceases. No solemnity of form can create obligation where no interest attaches Hlence, a threatening differs in its very nature from a promise, and the obligation to fulfil it, rests A threat dif fers from a on a different condition. When the Lord promise. sent Jonah to announce the destruction of Nineveh, both Jonah and the Ninevites felt that the threat might be revoked, and so it was. If it had been a promnise, the announcement of some good, their views would have been different. A child promises to strike another. Fidelity does not require him to give t?ie blow. He promises some favor; he is not at liberty, in the exercise of his own judgment, to withhold Judgment of promiser not that favor. If he ascertains, beyond question, enough. that what he thought a favor, is no favor, no obligation attaches. But, in general, the promiser is not at liberty to be governed by his own judgment in the case. iHe cannot, in general, know what relation the promise may sustain to the good of the promisee-what interests may have gathered aboutt the engagement. Hience, the dissolution of a promise, or a contract, requires mutual consent, in the full and proper sense of the word consent. There are eases in which the community becomes a party in the interest. Then the agreement cannot be dissolved by the mere consent of the original parties. This is the fact in marriage which, therefore, cannot be regarded as a simple contract, but becomes an institution. A promise is binding, in the sense in whi(li it was understood at the time it was made: that is, in the sensq 303 X M(RAT PHILOSOPHY. in which the promiser intended the promisee should an In what sensie derstand it. In the case of disagreement, thi binding. laws of languiage, and the history of th(, transaction, must determine the intent. A contract is binding in the same sense, and under the same conditions But there are cases in which it is not right for one party to hold the other to the obligations of his contract, or promise. If the contract be unjust or unfair to one of the parSwearing to ties, whether the unfairness be apprehlended one's hurt. or not, the party wronged is bound by the contract, but the other party cannot ri,lghtfully enforce it. It would be taking advantage off the ignorance or weakness of another. The scripture aplproves "the man who swears to his own hurt, and changes not," but it would not approve the man who holds him to his hurtful swearing. In morals, it is not sufficient to determine that a contract is binding. That is the mere legality of the case. The man who has the advantage in the transaction, must bring the case to the test of benevolence, before he accepts the fulfilment. There are circumstances which render a contract or When nul. promise null, in the nature of the case. Wn nab When the performance is, or becomes, impossible, the agreement is void. If ability returns, the obligation friay revive. When the fulfilment brings injury to others, its fulfilment becomes wrong. It is imnmateria whether the injury was apprehended or not, in the making of the contract, the ftlilfilmnent is wrong in both eases. The popular maxim, that a bad promise is better broken than kept, needs qualification or explanation. There are promises, wicked in the mnaking, which it is wrong not to fulfil; as when one swears to his own hurt. .$04 DUTIES-FIDELITY. It is wrong to swear to one's own hurt, but the promise must be fulfilled. When one swears to do injury to others, the promise is utterly null. It is a sin to make or receive such a promise, and a greater sin to fulfil, or to exact it. If injury to others is incidental to the promise, fand not the express matter of it, the promise may be binding, to the extent, that some consideration is due to the promisee in the case, but the third party must not suffer by the fulfilment of the promise. AVWen a promise or contract is conditional, and the conditions are not fulfilled, the promise becomes Conditional void. Careful discrimination must be made contracts. between essential and non-essential conditions. A condition can be regarded as essential, only when it compares somewhat, in importance, with the slubject matter of the agreement. The letter, too, must be distinguished from the spirit, both in the conditions and in the agreemnent. .it is no rare thing, to "keep the word of promise to the ear, and break it to the hope." A contract, or promise, may be express or implied; that is, it may be finamed into words, oral or writ- Express or ten, or it may be involved in some voluntarily implied. assumed relation or position, by the nature of the case or by the custoins of society. One who enters a hotel, and accepts entertainment, or takes passage on a steamer, or a car, in the act itself, without any words, engages to pay the usual charges. The party tendering the service, agrees to be satisfied with the usual payment; and it is a b)reachl of fidelity for either party to fail to meet this un derstanding. One who enters a family, or a school, enga. ges, in the act itself, to abide by its established order. It is by no means necessary, that hle should subscribe a pledge to that effect; the obligation is the same in eithel 305 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. case. If he has failed in duty, the written pledge may quicken his sense of obligation, but it does not create the obligation. A profession al man, tendering his services to the community, engages to bring to the work the educa tioa and skill implied in the profession, and to bestow upon it the required time and attention. A merchant offering his goods to the communlity, engages to sell at a reasonable profit, or at market prices; and he Who orders the goods without enquiry, comes under obligation to pay only the reasonable price. It is in the nature of an oath to impress obligation, Effect of the rather than to create it. A simple promise oath. gives rise to the obligation; the oath adds the sanctions of religion, and the fear of God, to impress the obligation upon the heart An oath cannot be binding ivhen, under the same circumstances, a simple promise would not bind; and whenever the mere pronmise would be annulled, the oath fails likewise. Hlence, the oath caii never bind to any wicked act, or to any concealnent which is detrimental to society, nor to any act which is, in itself, indifferent, and to which a mere promise would impart no significance. As a practical illfistration of the duties of fidelity, and Marriage en- because the subject is one of special imporgagements. tance to the young, a few remnarks are added upon the delicate matter of marriage engagements. These are of the nature of simiple contracts, because society is not a party to the transaction. An engagement to marry is not, like marriage, an institution of society; it i. wholly a matter of personal concern. : contract or engagement of marriage, is, of course, in Imi,lied con volved in any express agreement to that effect. There are certaiii conitions, or limi 806 DUTIES-FIDELITY. tations, which, in the nature of the case, attach to it. No definite time may be mentioned; the engagement carries with it a reasonable limit in this respect. The continued virtue and respectability of the parties,is a condition of their claim to the fulfilment of the contract. Slight ab errations, not seriously affecting the character or reputation, do not set aside the claim. Disclosures, made subsequent to the engagement, of serious constitutional infirmity, like a tendency to insanity, would release from obligation. Lighter infirmities could not annul it. The same principle must apply to serious faults of temper, revealed subsequently to the engagement. Conditions like these, whether expressed or not, apply to all engage ments. Arbitrary conditions are sometimes attached, which, in the nature of the case, cannot hold. The Impossblt continuance of interest and affection, cannot condition' be made a condition, because the very point of the obligation is to maintain that interest and affection. The engagement is not simply to marry, but to bring to the marriage that state of affection which makes the marriage desirable. That one shall not fall in with another party that seems more desirable, cannot be made a condition. The engagement precludes that freedom of fancy which the condition implies. A party to such a contract ham failed in duty when he indulges this freedom of fancy. A. marriage engagement, like marriage itself, is not based on a fickle and fleeting emotion, but involves a moral election, a decision of the will, as bubstantial A moral elec. and permanent as the character itself. The tion. affections wait on this moral choice, and are controlled by it. The faithful lover can walk almong the beautiful and lesirable of the world, without danger to his fidelity. 307 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. Without such a power of moral choice, overruling and directing the emotions, marriage itself could never be safe. The condition, then, of permanency of interest, is ruled out of the marriage engagemnent. Marriage engagements are not formed for the sake of Object of en- acquaintance, in the light of which the progagement. priety of marriage is to be determined. The engagement pre-supposes that acquaintance, and the settlemient of the question of the propriety of marriage. The place for consideration is antecedent to the engageinent. The frequent failure of young people is, to move upon the spur of some ephemeral feeling or fancy which dazzles for the hour, and leaves only darkness in the end. It is the truer wisdom to test the fancy by time and a quaintance, and the sober light of the judgment, in a comparison of tastes and tendencies, and aims; to give the fancy the trial of a winter, as well as a summer, of absence, as well as presence, to test its vitality. An engagement thus considerately made, has in it the natural elements of permanence, and the proper aim and purpose of it is, to provide for that mutual adjustment of thought, and feeling, and plan, and purpose, and life, which gives success to marriage. Marriage, without some such previous opportunity, is liable to involve a want of adjust ment, which may peril the result. A marriage engagement, being a simple contract, may Mutual con- be dissolved by mutual consent. If the pargent. ties themselves become satisfied that it is not for their interest to consummate the marriage, they are at liberty to decline it. But this must be determined by the free decision of both parties. It is not enough that one party reaches this decision, and asks the other for a release. Of course, a release will be granted; but tlo 308 DUTIES-FIDELITY. party released cannot indulge the satisfaction of a dissolution by mutual agreemnent. To ask to be released, is only' specious form of breaking the engagement. The Lindlug force of an engagement increases Effectof time with the lapse of timne. The interests which and publicity. cluster about it, in settled affection, and life arrangements and hopes, are constantly increasing; and on such inter Hsts the obligations of fidelity are based. The element of publicity adds something to its force, involving, to a greater or less extent, the reputation of the parties. Like many other contracts, a marriage engagement may be implied, as well as expressed. In gen- Implied en eral, any course of conduct pursued by the gagements. parties, which, in the common judgment of society, inldicates the intention of marriage, involves the obligation of an engagement. Persistent and exclusive attentions, offered on one part, and accepted on the other, without any definite or formal proposal, may brinig the parties under obligation. Either party would have the right to complain, if a subsequent consummation is declined by the other. Young ladies must be allowed a wider latitude, in this respect, because they receive proposals, and do not make them. But they must have the moral cour ag,e and the self-respect to decline attentions which they would not seriously entertain. The force of an engag,e ment lies not merely in words, which might express it, but in acts and relations voluntarily assumed, which ordi narily attend upon the engagement. There is, of course, a general association, in the ordinary relations of society, or foir the purposes of acquaintance, which have no such significaiice. Again, any course of conduct designed to awaken in another the particular personal affection of which mar 309 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. riage is the expression, implies the obligation of an offe0 Im1ied obli- of marriage. The only justifiable reason fox gation. such an effort, is the purpose to go forward, it the conquest is made; and a refusal to respond to Ihe affection thlus awakened, is a gross and wanlton breach )f tidelity. Any proposed arrangement, which, in the natural counmc Grave respon of things results in an engagement of the sibilities. affections, involves grave responsibility. 2 particular correspondence,maintained between two per sons, in marriageable relations, for purposes of persona improvement, is an arrangement of this character. A very particular friendship, intended to be of the Platonic Cast, between two such persons, even though a mutua pledge be taken that it shall be a friendship, and nothing more, involves such liabilities. The parties are not in a condition to maintain an ordinary friendship. Unconsciously, they impart to it a warmth of feeling and imagination, which br ings it under another experience and another name. A pleasant melody of Moore's, erntitled "A Temple to Friendship," will illustrate the tendencies, and the frequent result. Those who place themselves in such relations, should understand the case, and be prepared to meet the obligations which result. The young are inclined to claim for themselves a more extended liberty in such particulars, and to affect a degree of good sense and discretion which insures them against danger. A wider observation or experience will diminish their -unfidence. These facts indicate the ethics of the subiject. As a prudential maxim, it is safe to assume that tio more is intended than is expressed in words, and X withhold the affection that is not distinctly asked for 310 CHAPTER X DUTIES - VERACrIT. VerRACrY, as a virtue, is the benevolent conforming of our communications with men to the truth. Virtuous VW Benevolence, in general, requires this con- racity. fulmity. It is due to God, as demanded by respect foI his character and attributes. It is also an essential condition of the existence of society. Every human being needs reliable information from others; his need constitutes a right; and the right, on his part, imposes duty on others. This, alone, is the basis of the obligation. The truth has no sacredness in itself; all its sacredness is derived from the interests of moral beings. Truthfulness is sometimes discriminated as objective and subjective-truthfulness in expression, Objective and and truthfulness in intention. Either may siubjective. exist without the other. We may intend the truth, and fail; or, we may intend falsehood, and state the truth. Subjective truthfulness alone is obligatory. Nor is it enough to intend to state the truth. In order to virtuous veracity, the intention must be grounded in benevolence. Truth-telling from malice, or even from a generous impulse, is not virtuous veracity. The obligation of veracity is enjoined in the third command of the decalogue: "Thou shalt Enjoined la not take the name of the Lord thy God in thedecalogu& vain;" that is, thou shalt not make oath to a falsehood .ll falsehood is contempt of God-a disregard of his attributes; and, in this precept, the sin is contemplated in MORAL PHIILOSOPHY. this view. False swearing is the forLk of the trans gression expressed, but all falsehood is implied, as exhibit ing similar contempt of God. Its implied utterance, is: " howv doth God know; and, is there knowledge in the Miost High? " It is also a sin against mankind, a violation of his right to the truth, and in this view it is prohibited in telt ninth commandment: " Thou shalt not bear false witaess agaiinst thy nieilghbor." The significance of the oath, is in the fact that God is Significance invoked as a witness, and the relater is ,f the oath. placed under tihe direct recognition of his presence. The imprecation often annexed: "So help me God," is a prayer for God's favor, on condition of telling The truth. It is sometilmes supposed, that the superior force of the oath lies in the civil penalties annexed to per. jury; but these penalties could be provided for, without the oath. The appeal to God, impresses the mind with the gouilt of falsehood, and the importance of truthfulness as a condition of his favor. It adds divine sanctions to human penalty. The oath does not originate the obligation of truthfulness; it only intensifies and impresses it. The question sometimes arises, of the rightfulness of the Its rig,htful- oath. The argument against it is wholly drawn nilS. firom the Saviour's prohibition: "Swear not at all." A careful comparison of the various passages of Scripture on the subject, will sustain the prevalent idea, that the Saviour refers to the light and profane use of the ntame of God, without occasion. The oath was enjoined, in special cases, under the Aiosaic law and the Apostles seem to have employed it at times. The solemn appeal to God, iii courts of justice, and on grave occasions, is not profanity; it tends to honor God, and not to cast contempt upon himn. It is one of the comparatively few 312 DUTIES-VE]ACITY. forms ill which our nation governmentally recognizes Jo horah. The use of the oath on every trivial occasion, as in certifying to a business account, or a tax return, seems undesirable and unwarranted. The careless adminiistra tion of the oath, depriving it of all impressiveness and solemnity, whicl prevails in our courts and legislative bodies, and even in the senate of the nation, can scarcely be distinguished from profanity. If it cannot be rescued from such abuse, it were better that it should be abolished. The sin of profaning the namne of God, is of the same nature with falsehood, regarded as contempt Profanity, its of God; hence, the third commandment is nature. properly applied against it, although this is probably not its primary reference. The offence is a most gross and wanton one, and the existence and prevalence of it would seem incredible, but for the multiplied and painful facts around us. The only apparent motive for the loathsome habit, is in the propensity to strengthen and intensify an utterance. It is not to be assumed that those who indulge the habit, intend to express contempt of God; but proper respect for him, would make such utterances seem shocking. Is it not possible that the habit of intensifying speech with strong words and frequent exclamations, indulged even by worthy people, ministers to the prevalent passion which, in the rough and reckless, results in profanity? The obligation of veracity may be violated by any method by which a false impression may be Violatioas of communicated - by a positively false state- veracity. ment, by an exaggeration, by a partial statement, by ai intonation, by a gesture, or even by silence. Hence the explicit requirement of the oath," to tell the truth, the whole truth, and nothing but the truth." The forms of 14 313 MOR&I PHILOSOPHY. violation most frequent, and to which those who have falsehood in their hearts constantly resort, involve the use of words and expressions of double or unsettled meaning, giving the hearer a false impression, while the falsehood cannot be directly fastened upon the words. This method has the advantage of allowing -he deceiver'o'.omfort lijilself in the delusion that he has not told an untruth. There are comparatively few that have the hardihood to utter a falsehood, distinctly expressed in words. Such an utterance indicates great boldness or great awkwardness. The offence is in the aim to deceive; the mainer is immaterial. The question, as to the limits of the obligation of veraLimits of the city, requires a few words. Are its claims obligation. absolute, to the extent that deception is never allowable under any circumstances, or for any reasons The common judgment of mankind has always answered this question in the negative. It is not difficult to state a case in which deception would be justified, even by the most rigid moralist, unless a favorite theory were at stake. According to the views heretofore pre'sented, the general answer to the question must be, that the limits of the obligation must be. found in the requirements of benevolence. The only absolute obligation is that of benevolence itself; all other duties, veracity ineluded, derive their force from this obligation. If, under any circumstances, proper regard to highest good would admnit of deception, then the claims of veracity cease. That such cases arise, there is scarce room for doubt The false movements of an army to deceive an enemy, thie devices of a fugitive from oppression,to mislead the pursuer, are examples of this kind, never called in question. But to state a principle which shall clearly draw 814 DIUTTVERACIYY. the line between the objective right and the wrong, is probably impossible. In this respect, veracity is ike every other duty. To say that veracity is obligatory, when the person asking has a right to know the truth, is to utter a truism. The very point of the enquiry is, when does that right exist? To say that the obligation *xsts when there is need of the truth, is more to the point; but if we judge of the need by a reference to the person immediately concerned, and to the case in hand, we fail to embrace all interests. The principle of veracity is one of grave importance, and meets a permanent want of moral beings. To maintain this principle, truth must be told, and deception excluded, even when, in the particular case, the communication serves The rule and no interest, and deception would work no exceptions immediate harm. Absolute truthfulness in cummunication, is the grand practical rule. The exceptions will be rare, and indicated more or less clearly, to the practical judgment, by attending circumstances. In general, it will appear in these exceptions, that they involve no appeal to confidence-that something in the circumstances of the case precludes the idea that the communication is to be accepted according to its purport, or leaves the matter wholly in doubt. An enemny, in war, expects to be deceived. Even the dispatches of the opposing general may be intended for this purpose. But when a flag of truce approaches, the presumption is entirely different. Sincerity in the communication is tendered, and expected, and the obligation holds, even to an outlaw. The kidnapper expects to be deceived by the movements of the fugitive. lie has no claim to the knowledge he desires, on the ground of any need on his part; and the general principle of veracity is not at 81s MORAL PHILOSOPHY. stake. Confidence between man and man,is not shaken by the deception. Thus, each particular exception must cairry wi'h it its own vindication. The view is sometimes maintained, that there is a radi. W,tds and cal difference between words and gestures; estures. that deception by gestures is often allowable, by words never. If there be any such difference between these two means of communication, it must lie in the fact that words involve an appeal to confidence, in a sense that gestures do not. There may be some foundation for this view; but it is often true that a gesture is just as significant as a word, and carries with it all the obligation. There are cases, too, where words have no such force, and may be used in a justifiable deception. The relations of the parties, and of the interests involved, must determine the case. Upon this principle, that confidence is not appealed to in Legal prac- the case, the present modes of conducting litigatice.V tions in the courts must be vindicated, if at all. The lawyer, on either side, is expected to make the best possible statement of his case. Hle is not a witness, but an advocate, and his representation is accepted in this view. The hope is, that the resultant of the two opposing statements will be the clear and simple truth. This is the theory of the profession, and thus the obligations of veracity are not supposed to apply to the ordinary arguiments or representations addressed to the court. If the lawyer should, at any time, assume the attitude of a witness, or state his positive opinion as a man, thus appealilg to the confidence of the court, his professional privilege, of misleading or deceiving, must terminate. A false representationi, under tuch conditions becomes unprofessional, s well as grossly imnmoral. That the subjective influence 816 IA'i I S — V E I.CITY.l I. of the misrepresentation and sophistry allowed, should be unhappy, is altogether credible; and that truth and jus tice, in the ease, are always served by the arrangemnent is not supposable. It would seem strange that an ad vanced Christian civilization should not have devised some less clumsy means of conducting legal investiga tionls. The style of communication allowed in polite society, in complimentary address, in which more is Complimenuta said in words than is meant in the heart, is an ry address. out-growth of insincerity and untruthfulness. It would be severe to bring upon every one who indulges such a habit, the charge of untruthfulness. The words are taken for what they are usually held to mean, and allowance is made for their loss of force by the prevailing extravagance and insincerity. It cannot be doubted that the habit is demoralizing, and that a higher type of social communication would exclude these flattering and unmeaning words. The work of improvement must begin with the heart, displacing all envy, and selfishness, by sincerity and good-will, rendering unmeaning and extravagant words unnecessary and unnatural. The utterance, on the other hand, of unamiable, or hateful feelings, upon the plea of frankness, involves hypocrisy, as offensive as positive falsehood. The practice of deceiving in small matters, for personal comvenience, on the ground that these things Trifling dare wholly of private interest, and no one has ception,. a right to know them, cannot be justified. There is room for reasonable reticence, in reference to one's opinions and private affairs; but it is an unworthy and cowardly habit to use deception in regard to them. Truth is wholesome, and simple, and safe; falsehood, managed 311 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. with the pr.ofoundest skill, will fail in the very emergency it was supposed to serve. The instinct of veracity, is one of the strongest of our Instinct of e- ethical instincts, and its influence upon the racity. character is most salutary. It is a great dis ister to have it overborne, or broken down, by loose, pel: ioial habits, or by the false customs of social life. It should rather be guarded with jealous care, as the nattiral safeguard of personal honor and character, and as one of the wholesomle forces of society. Any calling, or pros fession, or practice, which tends to weaken or obliterate it, neet to be remodelled or discarded. 318 CHAPTER ImI. DUETIES HASTrTr. THE virtue of chastity has its basis in the sextal con situation, and consists in a regulation of heart Natue of the and ~;onduct, with reference to this constitu- duty. tion, according to the demands of benevolence. The duty is enjoined in the seventh commandment: "Thou shalt not commit adultery;" the form of tLe precept, as usual, being derived from the leading offence of the class, while the spirit of it extends to all impurity of heart and life. It is not the obliteration of the constitutional propensity that is called for, but a subjecting of it to the claims of benevolence-the suppressing of even the thought of unlawful indulgence. The duty requires the cultivation of pirity of heart, by abstinence from all thoughts, books, scenes, and associations, which tend to corrupt the imagination, or deprave the soul. There is, perhaps, no vice which, in its subjective reaction, so much degrades the entire nature as Efect of uw unchastity, making a wreck of both body and chaity. soul. Honor, and self-respect, and modesty, and shame, fall together. The poet, whom we cannot suppos, ign( rant whereof he affirms, in his letter of counsel to young friend, says: "I waive the quantum o' the sin, The hazard o' concealing, But ach I it hardens a' within, And petrifies the feeling." MORAL PHILOSOPHY. The wickedness of the offence, in its outward relations, Its criminal. can scarcely be over-estimated. With a reck t' ~less disregard of the most sacred human in stincts and interests, it sacrifices the highest welfare tc, tow, sensual pleasure. The poor excuse of temti tationj the only excuse that sin ever has, is all that can be urged for it, in the least aggravated cases of transgression. For those who, in their wanton wickedness, make a spoil of innocence and puIity, no condemnation can be too stern. The crime of murder fails in the comparison. Society is wont to deal unequally with the two parties Unequal to the transgression. The heartless man, treatment. loathsome in his wickedness, often retains his place and respectability; while, for the sinning woman, there is no toleration, and little pity. She is certainly not to be held guiltless. She sins against the strongest instincts of modesty and self-respect, and encounters the most frightful consequences. It is a fearful sin, whatever the temptation. On the other hand, the man violates every sentiment and claim of duty, takes the place of a tempter, and wilfully degrades a being of whose modesty, and fair fame, and honor, nature made him a guardian. It is common for the world to measure crime, in a great degree, by the consequences to the offender, and hlence the shallow discrimination. The outward result of the sin, according to this view, constitutes its shamrne. The true idea of chastity provides for mnarriage —an inMarriage pro- stitution of divine appointment, arranged for vided fr. in the human constitution. Its beneficent influence is demonstrated in the history of the race. The whole tendency of the institution is elevating and ennobling, adding to the excellen(ce of human nature, and to the value of life. The ascetic notion of chastity, whicb 320 DUTIES-CHASTITY. has at times prevailed, exalting celibacy, and represent. ing marriage as opposed to the highest sanctity of char. acter, is not sustained in reason nor ill humnan experience. Monasticism has yielded no flattering results. The marriage, which the true idea of chastity requires is a union for life, of one man with one wo- An exclusiv, man. This order is indicated in nature, in relation. the personal and exclusive character of the domestic affections, and in the equal numbers of the sexes so mysteriously provided for. In revelation, too, we have the fact of the creation of one of each sex, at the beginning of the race. The early revelation, and the indications of nature at the beginning, were, however, not so clear but that good men might mistake. The problem was afterwards wrought out in human experience, and the true arrangement was enjoined in the later revelation. Polygamy is a sin against nature, and always involves the degradation, especially, of the female sex. It makes man a lord, and woman his servant. Polyandry is an offence so gross that it has never existed as a system, and scarcely has a name. That the union must be for life, is clear from the work which comes upon the family-the training of Union for life, children, and the care of dependent parents. The contemplation of a dissolution of the union, would destroy the confidence necessary for the undertaking, while the actual dissolution would utterly frustrate the wurk, and throw great burdens upon the community. Thus the community becomes a party in the interest, and has the right to prescribe the permanency of marriage, Society a anid hold the parties to the union. This rela- party. tion to society, renders marriage, in the nature of the case, an institution, as distinguished from a simple contract 14* 321 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. But permanency is, if possible, more essential to the immae. diate interests of the family, than as a protection to the community. The idea of a dissolution of the family, sets Permaency aside all that is most sacred in the family re..Xnt~a lations, and most precious in its benefits and blessings The very thought of such dissolution, is to be excluded by every possible influence and arrangement. The settled fact that the dissolution is impossible, will have much to do in ruling out what might otherwise become occasions for it. There is true philosophy, as well as simplicity, in the remark of a husband to his wife: " ly dear, it is of no use for us to quarrel, because we shall have to make up again." It is sometimes accounted an offensive thing, that the permanency of marriag( should be made to depend upon any outside constraint But the constraint operates to secure the internal condi tions out of which the permanency grows as a natural reult. The necessity is not consciously felt, in most of the cases in which it may still have operated as a wholesome and potent force. A fair interpretation of the Saviour's teaching on this Thessaiour'# subject, seems to convey the doctrine that rw-. release from the obligations of marriage can be morally justified only on the ground of adultery-a crime which, in its very nature, involves a rupture of the marriage tie, and disorganizes the family. For this cause alone, can either party, properly, put away the other. Against this scripture view, human reason can bring no satisfactory argument. Perhaps this absolute principle would never have been reached in the convictions of men without such a revelation, but the wisdom of it is justified in the light of the ievelation. It is often maintained that wilful and continued deser 322 DUTIESCHASTITY. tion is a moral ground of release from the obligations of marriage, and many Protestant ecclesiastical Anothet courts so decide. But who can decide how ve long the way should be left open for repentance and re turn, and at what point the marriage obligation morally terminates? It is not an uncommon occurrence that desertions, supposed to be permanent at the outset, and so intended, come to a speedy end; and the general recognition of the fact, that the marriage obligation still survives, and is acknowledged, even by the party that has suffered the wrong, will strongly tend to recall the deserter. The still looser view, maintained by Milton and others, and gaining greater currency in our day, that Incompati. unfortunate marriages, involving incompati- bility. bility of temper, should be dissolved, is demoralizing and dangerous. The contemplation of a separation as possible, will tend to foster the very incompatibilities which the separation proposes to remedy. It could only be disastrous to have marriage regarded as an experi.lenit, the permanency of it to be decided in each case by the experience of the parties. Under such a view, marriages would be arranged with little consideration, and as easily dissolved. We cannot afford to lose the moral power which comes from the permanency of the marriage obligation, to relieve the few who find themselves unfortunately allied. Facility of divorce cannot fail to multiply the occasions for divorce. There are cases in which a formal separation may be provided for, not releasing the parties from Allowable all obligation to each other, or giving them sparatiod liberty to form new marriages. It cannot be that a woInan is required to live with a husband maddened by intoxication, or malice, or jealousy, to the peril of lher life 323 MORAL PHILOSOPHIIY. But it does not follow that she may put hiln atviy iirev ocably, and close thle door for ever against repentance and restoration. An unfortunate marriage is a dire cal amity, but facility of divorce is not the remedy for such nm ii;forttunes. This. as I u'iderstand it, is the moral law in referent ivil leeis. to the obligations of marriage, and the propri tion ety of divorce. The question, what the civil law may allow and provide for, is altogether different. The civil law, as we have seen, is not always to be brouilit up to the standard of absolute morality. "For the hardness of the hearts" of men, it may be better to allow some latitude. under the regulation of the law, than to risk the general license which would follow the prohibition of all divorce. What the law permits, is not necessarily morally right. In this view, the law of divorce may properly be different in different states of society, but always tending to the point of perfect morality. The tendency to the multiplication of divorces in the Tendency land, is cause for grave concern; and the fact, ilarming. as shown by statistics, that this tendency prevails in those portions of the land which have attained to the highest degree of intelligence and general culture, is still more alarming. It points to some radical defect in our civilization; or, at least, to some extravagance of iiidividlalisn, springing from our progressive deinocracv. It is possible to press the great fact of individual rights beyond the limitations which are necessary to social institutions. In protecting the individual, we must not subvert the family, or other social institutions, by which individual life is rendered valuable. MNfarriage being thus, in its very nature, exclusive, in volving exclusive relations oetween the two parties, any 324 DUTIES —A S'rITY. conduct which tends to arouse suspicion or jealousy, on either side, is an offence against its obliga- Implied obe tions. It is not enough to avoid the overt acts gatlions. of infidelity, which sunder the marriage tie. All associations, friendships, familiarities, which tend to disturb confidence, are excluded by the relation. They are indel icate and inexcusable. The pure-hearted and thoughtful will repel them. Marriage between blood relatives, of near relationship, is a clime against nature, called incest. There Inicestuous is a natural sentiment against such connec- marriage. tions, and they are prohibited by the laws of the land. This prohibition is based on the established fact that the result of such connections is enfeebled offspring. The final cause, or reason, for the sentiment, and for the unhappy natural consequences, is supposed to be the preservation of "he chastity of persons so closely associated, as members of the same family. It is also a safeguard against the clannish ness which results from continual intermarriages, in thf same family connection. It binds different families together, and extends the circle of society; and, possibly prevents a derangement of human nature, by a constant reproduction and exaggeration of the same family traits. The foregoing survey of the field of practical morals cannot, of course, exhaust the subject. Every Concludiug particular relation of moral beings, every remarks. :hange in knowledge or condition, must give rise to new questions of duty, and to new applications of the great la-f love. The law itself can never change-can neither be )xtended nor restricted. Wherever moral beings exist, un lerwhatever conditions, this great principle of obligation embraces them, binding the universe together in one gi eat family, and providing for the interests and the rights of the 325 MORAL rmLOSoPHY. least and the greatest. It places God at the head of this great family, and claims for him the supreme regard and oboe dience of his creatures, and secures to them his providential care-all the good that his infinite resources can comnnland. It places finite beings side by side, upon a common platfiorm of duties and of rights, and claims for each the equal regard and good will of all. Whatever of substantial evil we experience in this world, springs up in connection with the violation of this law of love, and the universal preva. lence of the law would fill the universe with good. Under God's infinite and pertect control, universal benero [once must bring universal blessedness. 826 2/ >9 I. - t& 7 ~ C i/t I ~, -, -' 4~i z I C,!L A; v'~, ~iI~) ,w ,i r C: —,,-l -~, ~ ' CI A' 4') - I ~' 1 1 t ~.4'C , -- , 0- 11 /1- I , li t, -1, -- -D I-) I t t — I - - - - - W~~~~~ ~: Sheldon & Company's.ext-..ooks. HISTORIES OF THE UNITED STATES. By BENSON J. LOSSING, author of "Field-Book of the Revolu tion," Illustrated Family History of the United States," &c. Lossing's Primary History. FOR BEG_wN-ERS. A charm ing little book. Elegantly illustrated. 238 pages. Lossing's Outline History of the United States. One volume, 12mo. We invite the careful attention of teachers to some of its leading points. In elegance of appear ance and cpious ilu8trations, both by pictures and maps, we think it surpasses any book of the kind yet published. 2. The work is marked by uncommon clearness of statement. 2. The narrative is divided into SIX DISTINCT PERIODS, namely: Discoveries, $ettlements, Colonies, The Revolution, The Nation, and The Civil'War and its consequences. 3. The work is arranged in short sentences, so that the substance of each may be easily comprehended. 4. The most important events are indicated in the text by heavyfaced letter. 5. Full Questions are framed for every verse. 6. A Pronouncing Vocabulary is furnished in foot-notes wherever required. 7. A Brief Synopsis of topics is given at the close of each section. 8. An Outline History of IMPORTANT EVENTS is given at the close of every chapter. 9. The work is profusely illustrated by Maps, Charts and Plans explanatory of the text, and by carefully-drawn pictures of objects and events. Lossing's School Histor,y. 383 pages. Containing the National Constitution, Declaration of Independence, Biographies of the Presidents, and Questions. This work is arranged in six chapters, each containing the record of an important period. The First exhibits a general view of the Aboriginal race who occupied the continent when the Europeans came. The Second is a record of all the Discoveries and preparations for settlement made by individuals and governments. The Third delineates the progress of all the Settlemeents untitcolonial governments were formed. The Fourth tells the story of these Colonies from their infancy to maturity, and illustrates the continual development of democratic ideas and republican tendencies which finally resulted in a poiiticai o)nfederation. The Fifth has a full account of the important events of the War for Independence; and the Sixth gives a conCiSe History of the Republic from its formation to the present time. These books are designed for different grades of pupils, and adapted to the time usually allowed for the study of this important subject. Each embraces the history of our country from its discovery to its present administration. The entire series is characterized by chasteness and clearness of style, accuracy of statement, beauty of typography, and fullness of illustration. The author has spent the greater part of his life in collecting materials for, and in writing history, and his ability and reputation are a sufficient guarantee that the work has been thoroughly done, and a series of histories produced that will be iRvluable in trainimg and educating the youth of our country. I i i I I i