Iptintttnn Mmurrfiitg THE LOUIS CLARK VANUXEM FOUNDATION LECTURES FOR 1917-1918 was established in 1912 with a bequest of $25,000 under the will of Louis Clark Vanuxem, of the Class of 1879. By direction of the executors of Mr. Vanuxem's estate, the income of the foun- dation is to be used for a series of public lectures delivered in Princeton annually, at least one half of which shall be on subjects of current scientific interest. The lectures are to be published and distributed among schools and libraries generally. The following lectures have already been pub- lished or are in press: 1912-13 The Theory of Permutable Functions, by Vito Volterra 1913-14 Lectures delivered in connection with the dedication of the Graduate College of Princeton University by Emile Boutroux, Alois Riehl, A. D. Godley, and Arthur Shipley 1914-15 Romance, by Sir Walter Raleigh 1915-16 A Critique of the Theory of Evolution, by Thomas Hunt Morgan 1916-17 The Mineral Resources of Civilization, by Charles R. Van Hise 1917-18 Platonism, by Paul Elmer More LOUIS CLARK VANUXEM FOUNDATION PLATONISM BY PAUL ELMER MORE AUTHOR OF THE "SHBLBTIBNE ESSATS" LECTURES DELIVERED AT PRINCETON UNIVERSITY OCTOBER 29, 30, 31, NOVEMBER 6, 7, 1917 PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PRESS PRINCETON LONDON: HUMPHREY MILFORD OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS 1917 ^i s Copyright, 1917, by Princeton University Press Published November, 1917 Printed in the United States of America !£C -6 1917 ^0,4477869 1 Alo St) ^^17 Sv acrta? €1817 hiDpit^ecrO ai, to fikv dvayKoiov, to Se Oelov, koX to ^ev Oelov iv aTracriv ^TjTeiif KTujcreco^; iveKa evSaCfiovo^ ^lov, Ka6* ocrov rjfJLOJT/ Tj <^vcn<; ivhe^^erai, to he avayKoiov iKeCpcop ^dpiv^ \oyit^6p.evov a)s dvev tovtcov ov SvvaTa airrd iKCLPa i(l>^ of? (TTTOvSoi^ofJiej/ fxova KaTavoelv ovS' av \a^elv ovS' aXX&>9 ttw? joterao-xeiz'. — Timaeus, 68e. 'Ef &v iTTopiadfieOa (^iKocroi^ia*; yepo'?, ov [jLei^ov dyaOov ovr rfXOev ovre rj^ei ttotc tco 6v7]T(o yevei ScoprjOev iK 6ewv. — Timaeus, 47a. PREFACE Though this book goes out under the rather presumptuous title of Platonism, no one can be more aware than the author of the incomplete- ness of its argument. Almost nothing, for in- stance, is said of education and art and govern- ment, to name a few of the subsidiary subjects that occupy a large and important place in the Dialogues. These alluring topics have been passed by, somewhat reluctantly, in order that attention might be concentrated on the ethical theme that runs through all Plato's discussions and is certainly the mainspring of his philosophy. At another time and in another volume I may undertake to fill out the omissions here acknow- ledged; but, whether that is done or not, my pur- pose in the work now pubUshed has been to lay the foundation for a series of studies on the ori- gins and early environment of Christianity and on such more modem movements as the Enghsh revival of philosophic religion in the seventeenth century and the rise of romanticism in the eigh- teenth. My conviction is that behind all these movements the strongest single influence has been the perilous spirit of liberation brought into the world by the disciple of Socrates, and that our vi PREFACE mental and moral atmosphere, so to speak, is still permeated with inveterate perversions of Plato's doctrine. It will be seen that my aim, in the present vol- mne and in its projected sequels, is not so much to produce a work of history — ^though, of course, historical accuracy must be the first requisite — as to write what a Greek Platonist would have called a ProtrepticuSj an invitation, that is, to the prac- tice of philosophy. In saying this I am under no delusion as to what such a work is likely to accomplish. Readers of settled convictions who happen to take up this presentation of philosophy will accept or reject it in accordance with the bent of their minds ; and I know that the current of thought today runs against me and not with me. It is a fact to be reckoned with now, as it was when Socrates talked on these matters in the gaol of Athens, that for those who differ on fun- damental principles there is no common counsel but only contempt for each other ; as St. Augus- tine says, si non sit intus qui doceat inanis fit strepitus noster. My hope would be with those who are still searching — particularly if I might touch the minds of a few of our generous college youth who, finding the intellectual life deprived of centre or significance, drift through the sup- posedly utiUtarian courses of economics and bio- logy, and so enter the world with no better preparation against its distractions than a vague PREFACE vii and soon-spent yearning for social service and a benumbing trust in mechanical progress. I can foresee no restoration of humane studies to their lost position of leadership until they are felt once more to radiate from some central spiritual truth. I do not believe that the aesthetic charms of Uter- ature can supply this want, nor is it clear to me that a purely scientific analysis of the facts of moral experience can furnish the needed motive ; the former is too apt to rim into dilettantism, and the latter appeals too little to the imagination and the springs of enthusiasm. Only through the centrahzing force of rehgious faith or through its equivalent in philosophy can the intellectual life regain its meaning and authority for earnest men. Yet, for the present at least, the dogmas of religion have lost their hold, while the current philosophy of the schools has become in large measure a quibbling of speciahsts on technical points of minor importance, or, where serious, too commonly has surrendered to that flattery of the instinctive elements of human nature which is the very negation of mental and moral disci- pline. It is in such a belief and such a hope, whether right or wrong, that I have turned back to the truth, still potent and fresh and salutary, which Plato expounded in the troubled and doubting days of Greece — the truth which is in religion but is not boimded by religious dogma, and which viii PREFACE needs no confirmation by miracle or inspired tra- dition. The first task before me was to see this philosophy in its naked outlines, stripped of its confusing accessories, and cleared of the misun- derstandings which, starting among the barba- rians of Alexandria, have made of Platonism too often a support instead of a corrective of the disintegrating forces of society. This I have at- tempted to do, with imperfect success no doubt, in the present volume. If, when the series is completed, I may have succeeded in directing a few seeking minds to the inexhaustible source of strength and comfort in the Platonic Dialogues, I shall account my labour amply rewarded. Of strength and comfort we have need enough in these trying times, and shall have no less need in the days of peace, when they come. To one criticism I should be sensitive. Those who have read the eighth volume of my Shelburne Essays will recognize that the present work is virtually an expansion of the views there summed up in the Definitions of Dualism, and they may think that I have tried to impose my own theories on Plato, to measure him in my pint cup. In a way every interpreter of a great author must be open to such a charge; he has no other measure than his own capacity. But at least I am not guilty of attempting to force Plato into confor- mity with a preconceived system ; the Definitions of Dualism were themselves the result of my PREFACE ix study of the Dialogues, and avowedly rejected any pretensions to originality. In making the translations from Plato scat- tered through the following pages I have often had other versions before me, and have not scru- pled to draw on them quite freely for words and phrases. Where these passages are included in inverted commas, I have adhered to the original as closely as possible while conforming to Eng- lish idiom. The passages not so indicated, but noted by marginal references, are rather allu- sions than quotations. Finally, I have to thank the trustees of the Vanuxem fund for permitting me to print in this volimie a large amount of material which it was impossible to include in the coxirse of five lectures. P. E. M. Princeton, N. J., May 1, 1917. CONTENTS PAGE Preface v I The Three Socratie Theses 1 II The Socratie Quest 28 III The Platonic Quest 54 IV The Socratie Paradox: the DuaUsm of Plato 79 V Psychology 118 VI The Doctrine of Ideas 162 VII Science and Cosmogony 204 VIII Metaphysics 232 IX Conclusion 270 Appendix 299 XL PLATONISM CHAPTER I THE THREE SOCRATIC THESES No person of antiquity, scarcely any of the modem world, has been portrayed so vividly as the master whom Plato made the responsible mouthpiece of his speculations. We seem to de- scry the man Socrates in the very flesh ; we can al- most hear his voice, as he talked with friends and strangers in the agora and other meeting-places of Athens. But when we come to consider him as a philosopher in his own right, and to determine precisely what he taught, the way is not so plain. Of the two main witnesses on whom we must rely for our knowledge of his teaching, the one, our gossiping Xenophon, imderstood him too little, whereas the other understood him, in a manner, too well, developing his instruction into so rich and voluminous a body of thought that Socrates might have exclaimed with some apparent reason, as indeed he is said actually to have done on hearing one of the simpler of Plato's Dialogues: "By Heracles, what lies the young man has told about me!" Our conception of the Socratic phil- Parmenides 130a 2 PLATONISM osophy is thus, like the Eros of the wonderful ymposium ^^^^^^ q£ Mautiuea, the child of Penury and Abundance — an Abundance, we might add, "drunken with the drink of the gods." Yet withal the leading theses of Socrates are in themselves, and taken separately, clear enough — or ought to be so to any one who approaches the subject with open mind — and the real diffi- culty begins only when we undertake to combine them into a coherent system, and to weigh their remoter consequences. These leading doctrines, if we may give such a name to the impulses that carried him towards philosophy, were three: an intellectual scepticism, a spiritual affirmation, and a tenacious belief in the identity of virtue and knowledge. Of the sceptical, questioning disposition of So- crates we have ample testimony. This was the trait, particularly as it touched the common tra- dition in matters of government and morals, that most impressed those of his contemporaries who did not belong to the inner circle of disciples. And probably the irony of Socrates, his real or feigned ignorance used as a dissolvent of the as- simied knowledge of others, is the characteristic first suggested today by the mention of his name. He himself, when obliged to defend his life be- fore the tribunal of his fellow citizens, manfully admitted this scepticism, and even claimed for it Apology 2iA a divine sanction. One of his friends, so he de- THE SOCRATIC THESES 3 clared, had gone to Delphi to inquire of the oracle whether there was any one wiser than Socrates, and had been told that there was none wiser. Whereupon Socrates, amazed and incredulous, had put himself to the task of testing this strange saying. His method of inquiry (which we may suppose he had employed from the beginning of his pubhc career, though with less deliberate pur- pose before the intervention of the oracle) was to select a man eminent for wisdom, and to cross- question him about his knowledge; and this he did repeatedly, and always with the same result. "It would soon become apparent," he says, "that to many people, and most of all to himself, the man seemed to be wise, whereas in truth he was not so at all. Thereupon I would try to show him how he was wise in opinion only and not in reality; but I merely made myself a nuisance to him and to many of those about him. So I used to go away reflecting that at least I was wiser than this man. Neither of us, I would say to myself, knows anything much worth while, but he in his ignorance thinks he knows, whereas I neither know nor think I know."^ ^ I hold for many reasons that the biographical parts of the Apology, Crito, and Phaedo present a faithful picture of the man Socrates, and in the main give a true account of his last days, however the glamour of Plato's rhetoric may lie over the whole. It is easier to believe in the power of Nature to create such a character than in the ability of an author to imagine it. Furthermore, though Xenophon 4 PLATONISM But if the existence, even the predominance, of the doubting mood in Socrates cannot be over- looked, the quahty of this scepticism needs none the less to be sharply distinguished from what commonly passes imder the name. The matter stands thus. Absolute suspension of judgment, however a man may profess it in words or strive to attain it in practice, is an impossibility. You may deny the power of human reason to explain the cause and ultimate nature of things; but the moment you do this, you will find yourself, if you examine your mind honestly, putting credence in some faculty either above the reason or below the reason. Some relation to appearances you must assume, some motive of action you are bound to obey, some affirmation you are forced to make ; ^ the only choice is to which of the alter- native sohcitations you will say yes, and to which you will say no. Thus, when a man calls himself a sceptic, it commonly means that he subscribes to some form of materialistic dogma, and practi- probably had little intercourse with Socrates and certainly was lio philosopher, yet he gives the same report of So- crates* ordinary ways of life, and one can find in the Me- morabilia clear traces of the three Socratic theses. ^ This fact is virtually acknowledged by the clever ex- ponent of ancient scepticism, Sextus Empiricus. See his Hypotyposes i, 17, et passim. As for modern agnostics, so-called, they too reserve their scepticism for the "unknow- able" things of the spirit, and are thorough-going dogma- tists in their theories of conduct based on the ikcmi irddrj. THE SOCRATIC THESES 5 cally believes that pleasures and pains of the body, however he may refine and intelleetualize their quality, are the one certain fact of experi- Phaedo ssb ence. As the followers of Aristippus used to say : "Only our sensations are comprehensible." This creed may be adopted from mere indolence of mind, or in the combative manner of the schools — but with results curiously ahke. Ac- cording to his first disciple, Pyrrho, the father of professional scepticism, reduced the problems of philosophy to these three: "What is the nature of things? How should we be disposed towards them? What is the consequence to us of this de- termination?" The answer was that we know nothing of the great forces playing about us, and that he is wise who, freeing his soul of trouble- some fears or questions, does not look beyond the pleasure within his reach.^ There is a pretty parable that tells how Pyrrho enforced this doc- trine. Being once at sea and caught in a storm, he rebuked the terror of the passengers by point- ing to a little pig that kept on feeding through all the conmiotion — such, he said, ought to be the tranquillity of the wise man. There is an affir- mation in this — deck and disguise it as you will — the affirmation of the sty: pinguem et nitidum vises Epicuri de grege porcum. Such a man may call himself a philosophical sceptic by reason of his anti-rationalism, but his philosophy comes ^ See Eusebius, Praeparatio Evangelica xiv, 18, 2. 6 PLATONISM from a plane below the reason, and is hard to dis- tinguish from the indolent self-assurance that is content to do without thinking at all. If we take the word "sceptic" in its truer sense, as describing one who takes nothing on trust but examines the facts of experience to their last con- clusion, the Epicurean or Pyrrhonist has no right to the name, since he still labours under the de- lusion of supposing he knows what he does not know, and has yet to learn that pleasure and pain have no final value in themselves, but must be es- timated by their relation to values of quite an- other order. Manifestly, at least, the scepticism of Socrates was no Pyrrhonic drifting with the current of opinion; it meant to him rather an unwearied questioning of the solicitations of both the reason and the senses, and a continuous ex- ercise of the will, being of all states of mind the rarest and the most difficult for a man in this world to maintain. Doubt was thus to Socrates the beginning both of philosophy and of morality — ^of philosophy, since only those are prompted Lysis 218a to philosophizc truly who are ignorant and, at the same time, aware of their ignorance ; of morality, since only those will feel the compelling of a higher impulse who have seen through the illu- sory curtain of the senses. When Socrates came to explain to the court why he had not hesitated in a course of action which was sure to bring him into peril of losing what most men prize, includ- THE SOCRATIC THESES 7 ing life itself, he replied boldly that he had fol- lowed the behest of the God for the reason that of those so-called perils we have no real know- ledge — ^not even of the greatest of them. "For the fear of death," he said, "is just another form Apology 29a of appearing wise when we are foolish, and of seeming to know what we know not. No mortal '^/ knoweth of death whether it be not the greatest of all good things to man, yet do men fear it as if they knew it to be the greatest of evils. And is not this that most culpable ignorance which pre- tends to know what it knows not?" This sounds like the parable of Pyrrho and his pig; but note the difference in the consequences drawn. So- crates was not contradicting himself, but was basing his conduct on a prof ounder form of scep- ticism than Pyrrho's, when, in one and the same discourse, he avowed that his only wisdom was to know his own ignorance, yet declared himself ready to face death with this downright affirma- tion: "To do wrong and to disobey our superior, whether human or divine, this I do know to be an evil and shameful thing." He had an invincible assurance of this spiritual fact for the very reason that his scepticism went deep enough to include those current judgments and those immediate values of sensation which to a Pyrrho were the only certain guides through the perplexities of hfe. There is, then, no inconsistency in the imion of 8 PLATONISM intellectual scepticism and spiritual afBrmation; rather, scepticism is the negative aspect of the same intuitive truth of which spiritual affirmation is the positive aspect. It would even be a grave error — the gravest of all errors in its possible consequences — to reckon the sceptical attitude, because it is purely negative, as less essential to the Socratic life than its positive coimterpart. It is, if anything, more essential ; for its authority extends in a way beyond reason and the senses to the highest citadel of the soul. Our one safe- guard against a host of ruinous deceptions that speak in the name of the spirit is the obstinate interrogation of every affirmation of every sort, and the holding of each presumptive truth to give proof of itself in experience. In later years these two aspects of Socratic doctrine were developed independently into separate schools, the sceptic, of which we have spoken, and the Neoplatonic. If Socrates had been ahve, and had been forced to choose between the books of a Sextus Empiri- cus, let us say, who in the name of scepticism re- jected all authority of reason and the higher in- tuition, and the books of a Proclus, who accepted almost without discrimination any words uttered in the name of the spirit, he would have ranged himself, I am sure, with Sextus, and would have expended his powers of irony upon the religious jargon of the self-styled Platonist. He would have preferred the half-truth of the one to the THE SOCRATIC THESES 9 sham-truth of the other; and Plato would have made the same choice. But if it is easy to see how true scepticism and spiritual intuition may go hand in hand, the case is different when to these two theses we add the third. It was one of Socrates' favorite maxims that no man errs, or sins, willingly, but only through ignorance — a saying hard to reconcile with the actual conduct of the world, hard to re- concile with the other aspects of the Socratic doc- trine. On its face this maxim implies an equation of virtue and knowledge, and by knowledge the evidence obliges us to believe that Socrates meant, not indeed a Pyrrhonic acquiescence in the solici- tations of the present, but that larger calculation of life in the terms of pleasure and pain which from his day to this has been the mark of the rationahzing utihtarian. As we know better, he would say, the near and remote consequences of our acts in those terms, we are enabled to conduct ourselves more prudently; and this prudence is virtue. How, one asks in some bewilderment, can a teacher maintain such a thesis as this, yet as a sceptic reject the authority of the senses, and as a mystic avow that his morality depends on a superrational intuition? How can the same man be a rationalizing utihtarian and a sceptical mystic? However perplexing such a union of contra- ries may appear to us, we have nothing to do but 10 PLATONISM to accept the paradox as it stands. Above all we must not emphasize the rationalistic thesis so as to suppress the other two. In that way we should fall into the totally inadequate conception of So- crates made current to-day by the Greek Think- ers of Theodor Gomperz. According to that bril- liant and much-quoted history, the Platonic So- crates, with his religious and fundamentally scep- tical traits, is to be rejected for a mere questioner of popular tradition and promoter of the ration- ahstic "Enlightenment." The story in the Apology of his self-dedication to the service of the God is pure moonshine; Socrates had one simple aim, to set forth the unity of virtue and knowledge, and to that end there was no need of exhortation or animating appeal, no room for any positive ethical teaching based on an authority higher than reason. Now the Socrates of this school of interpreters is an impossibility — a crea- ture manufactured in a Teutonic phrontisterion, and not the hving man of Athens from whom the deepest inspiration of philosophy has flowed even to this day. Gomperz himself offers a corrective to his portrait by quoting as the motto for his volume this sentence from Clement of Alexan- dria: "Wherefore also Cleanthes in his second book Concerning Pleasure says that Socrates al- ways identified the just man and the happy man, and cursed him who first distinguished between the just and the profitable as one who had done THE SOCRATIC THESES 11 an impious thing J" There is decidedly something of the exhorter and preacher of virtue in the words itahcized, though we need not, for all that, picture Socrates quite as a Lutheran par- son. If Clement is right, and Plato was not a mere mystificator, and if human nature has any place in the study of philosophy, then Gomperz is wrong. We may be certain that beneath the irony of Socrates, deeper than his questioning of popular phrases and his search for precision of definition, lay a power of very positive teaching and a direct appeal to the conscience, in his own way and at his own time, which smote the heart even of such a worldling as Alcibiades to the quick, and shall never cease to vibrate in the hearts of Uving men. Plutarch was in the right tradition when, remembering the confession of Alcibiades, he said that "outwardly Socrates to those who met him appeared rude and imcouth and overbearing, but within was full of earnest- ness and of matters that moved his hearers to tears and wrung their hearts."^ On the other hand we must be on our guard against the contrary extreme of those scholars, such as Burnet and Taylor of St. Andrews, who, in their laudable desire to reinstate Socrates as a religious teacher and seer, go so far as to make a mechanical division between the rationalistic and the mystical elements in the Platonic Dialogues, * Cato vii. 12 PLATONISM and then relegate all the former to Plato himself and derive all the latter from Socrates. Profes- sor Bmnet^ would even have us believe that in the earher Dialogues, down to and including The Republic, Plato was merely reproducing as a dramatic artist the mystic and idealistic Pytha- goreanism of his master, whereas in the later Dia- logues he breaks away from this and gives ex- pression to his own scientific and anti-Socratic rationahsm. Now, with all due deference to the great learning of Professor Burnet, one must say that such a theory has no warrant in history or in common sense. To assert that a man could write The Republic without a definite philosophy of his own is to run pretty close to a pedantic absurd- ity; and it is not much better to maintain that there was no rationahsm in the teaching of So- crates than that there was no mysticism in the teaching of Plato. The efforts of various scholars to escape the Socratic Paradox by representing him on the one hand as a pure rationalist or on the other hand as a pure mystic are equally untenable. So far as we can judge from the records, Socrates never attempted to find an interpretation of the word "knowledge" which should reconcile his third thesis with the other two, nor did he even, we may suppose, see quite so logical a synthesis of his intellectual scepticism and higher intuition as we ^ Greek Philosophy, Part I, pp. 178, 179 £f. THE SOCRATIC THESES 13 have felt justified in deriving from the language of the Apology. For the most part he was con- / tent, it should appear, to enunciate his three principles as independent truths, and to enforce now one and now another of them as occasion prompted, leaving to his disciples, the creators of the so-called Socratic schools, the labour of constructing from them what properly may be regarded as a philosophic system. Endless in- consistencies and controversies were to arise among his successors from the varying emphasis placed by them on the different aspects of his creed. To Plato alone it was given to combine the three theses without sacrificing one for the other, and so to develop a philosophy that tran- scended the master's actual teaching while in no fundamental matter betraying it. So success- fully did he accomphsh this great task that to the world at large Socrates has come to stand for httle more than a mouthpiece of the Pla- tonic speculations. Nevertheless we shall be do- ing a grave injustice if, caught by the spell of Plato's richer and subtler genius, we forget that the imposing enimciation of his three doctrines by Plato's teacher was the determining event in the moral and religious life of the Western world; for the supreme need of a man's soul is not that he should acquire a splendid system of philosophy, but that he should hold as an inex- pugnable possession that spirit of scepticism and 14 PLATONISM insight and that assurance of the identity of vir- tue and knowledge for which Socrates hved and died.^ Yet however important, even revolutionary, the work of Socrates may appear, we must re- member that he was only one teacher among many; nor can we rightly understand the Pla- tonic philosophy without taking into account the strong currents of thought, sympathetic and antipathetic, amid which it took its origin. The age of Socrates was notable for an intellectual curiosity and a moral fermentation for which there is perhaps only one parallel in history, and that parallel takes us out of Europe to Asia. There, in the country of the Ganges, at a some- what earher date, the old formahties of religion had ceased to satisfy the devout Hindu wor- shipper, and he could no longer accept the tradi- tional precepts of morality until he had justified them at the bar of his own conscience. Every- where men were asking themselves and one an- other about the underlying truth of things, and a rumour went abroad that certain lonely ex- plorers had discovered a treasure of knowledge which they held as a secret possession. And so the books of the period are filled with stories, ^ The Christian philosophy of Pascal is founded on three similar principles: "II faut avoir ces trois qualites, pyr- rhonien, geometre, Chretien soumis; et elles s'accordent, et se temperent, en doutant ou il faut, en assurant ou il faut, et en se soumettant oii il faut." — Pensee 268, Brunschvicg. THE SOCRATIC THESES 15 some of them quaint and obscure, others very beautiful, of eager inquirers who went out into the wilderness, where the sages had their solitary abodes, to question and hsten, and to learn, if they were deemed worthy, the new meaning of the old words of rehgion and morahty. Something hke that, though the methods of teaching and the final results were different, was going on in Greece during the lifetime of Socra- tes. The supposed possessors of the secret were not eremites hiding in the forest depths, but teachers who called themselves sophists and went about from city to city imparting instruction for a price; and the inquirers who flocked to their lectures were not, for the most part, rehgious enthusiasts, but young men of family who were looking for the readiest path to honour and power in civic hfe. Yet, withal, the mental and moral ferments were much the same as in India, and in both lands the deepest problems of law and faith did not pass through the ordeal untouched. Not the least extraordinary of Plato's literary gifts is his skill in reproducing in a colder age the ardour which surrounded his childhood and youth. In the opening of such a Dialogue as the Protagoras, for instance, there is a note of excite- ment, of expectation, which carries the reader back to a society stirred by a veritable renaissance of wonder. Even the more conservative citizens were moved, some to hostility, some to friendly 16 PLATONISM curiosity. So, in the Theages, we have a charm- ingly realistic picture of an elderly man, of posi- tion and property, coming into Athens from the country to consult Socrates about the education of his son ; for the boy has heard rumours of the marvellous cunning of these professors who are flocking to the city from the ends of the world, and is determined to place himself as a pupil under one of them. The father, as befits a solid man of the soil, is bewildered and anxious; he doesn't mind spending the necessary money, but he has his suspicion of these innovations and he fears they are as likely to corrupt as to inform. Whereupon Socrates turns to the young man, and quizzes him to bring out just what he thinks this new wisdom is and what it will do for him. Now to many scholars of our age Socrates was not much different from any other of these vota- ries of new-fangled ideas ; and, superficially, there is some basis for this fatal confusion. But the moment we apply to these wandering teachers the test of the three Socratic theses we see that in their attitude towards the central truth of philo- sophy they stood at the opposite pole from So- crates; we see, too, how deeply the intellectual and moral destiny of Greece was involved in this difference. Some of the sophists may have been inclined to dogmatic rationalism, and could therefore scarcely be called sceptics in any sense of the THE SOCRATIC THESES 17 word. But for the most part they were question- ers and innovators by profession, in harmony with the eonmion imrest of the times. Their general position is fairly expressed in the famous maxim '^""^^^^^ of Protagoras, that "Man is the measure of all things." Such a principle might seem on its face Theaetetus — as it has seemed to certain modern critics — ^to It^^passim be in accord with Socrates' habit of putting the received laws of conduct to the test of human ex- perience ; and this indeed would be the case, were it not for the utterly diverse meanings that may be attached to the word "man." Now Protagoras had in mind to say that right and wrong are mat- ters of human opinion, being actually to each man as his good pleasure thinks them to be. More than that, they not only vary in their na- ture with the opinions of different men, but de- pend on the changing moods of each individual man, so that what is right and just for me at this moment may be at another moment the very re- verse of right and just. In other words, by "man" Protagoras meant the impression of the senses and the dictates of temperament, and vir- tually denied the existence of that unchanging law on which Socrates based his conduct when he declared himself ignorant of all things save of this one fact, that it is better for a man to be just than to be unjust, and better, if needs be, to suffer wrong than to do wrong. The issue between the two ways of life is Theaetetus 162d 18 PLATONISM brought out more sharply by adding to the Protagorean maxim already quoted his other fa- mous saying, that of the gods we have no know- ledge whether they are or are not, and by con- trasting with these statements the terse epigram of Plato, that, if we cared for our happiness. Laws 716c "Not auy man, as some say, but God would be the measure of all things." Plato, when he wrote these words in his old age, was thinking not so much of a deity set apart in a remote region of the heavens, or even of a deity immanent in the human breast, as of that element of the soul it- self which is capable of rendering a man like to a god. He, too, in his Way, was making man the measure of all things; but by man he had learnt from his master to think first, not of the opinions that separate one man from another, and a man today from himself of yesterday, but of the divine principle that is the same in all men and forms therefore the only true bond of friendship and so- ciety. It was just this principle of the innate divine that Protagoras denied — certainly at least Plato so understood him — when he made man the measure of truth and avowed that of the gods there was no way of knowing whether they were or were not. And, whatever apparent exceptions there may have been here and there, Protagoras was in this representative of the whole body of the sophists. By omitting the Socratic affirma- tion from their scheme they turned their philo- THE SOCRATIC THESES 19 sophy, so far as they had any, in the direction of that Pyrrhonic scepticism which is the very con- trary of the Socratic. The same essential difference between So- crates and the sophists comes out when we pass from scepticism and spiritual affirmation to the third thesis. So far as it is possible to group to- gether men who formed no cohesive party, but professed each after his own desire, the sophists were at least in agreement among themselves in the behef that virtue and knowledge are some- how identical ; in fact it was their avowed mission to impart the knowledge requisite for virtue, as the thing virtue was commonly understood. And they had a useful function to perform. Their instruction was partly of a purely objective sort, and as such valuable in itself. As for their rhet- oric, Socrates did not hesitate to admit that he had acquired some of his perfectly legitimate skill in the use of words from Prodicus and other such teachers. And so, in the absence of schools beyond the most elementary sort, the sophists must enjoy the credit of sharing in the advance- ment of practical education. Even here, indeed, we begin to see the divergence between their method and that of Socrates, for Socrates was too genuinely sceptical, of himself as well as of oth- ers, to go about like an ambulatory imiversity lecturing for a fee on any province of science or art then known to mankind. But that is a minor 20 PLATONISM matter. The serious divergence was in their pur- pose. If there is any truth in Plato's account of the debates between Socrates and such masters of the craft as Gorgias and Protagoras, it is clear that the sophists directed their instruction chiefly to the acquisition of skill in manipulating indi- vidual men and popular assemblies. I do not mean to say, following an ancient accusation, that the sophists set out deliberately to instruct men in the art of making the better cause appear the worse, in the sense that they had any vicious or anti-social end in view; but rather that they had in view no end at all, except the end of suc- cess. Their concern was very much with practi- cal cleverness and very little with moral conse- quences, very much with current opinion and very httle with truth for its own sake; hence the su- preme place of rhetoric in their curriculum, as the art of persuasion. They would have accepted as readily as Socrates the identification of vir- tue and knowledge; but they identified the two by making them both a means, without stopping to ask themselves or others the means to what. In the quest of that what Socrates was to pass his life ; and if he was still searching and had not reached the goal of the great quest when death put an end to all his asking, it was because he had not discovered the relation of the knowledge that determines virtue to the knowledge that belongs to scepticism and spiritual aflSrmation. THE SOCRATIC THESES 21 Such is the contrast between Socrates and the sophists the moment we apply to them the test of the three theses. To ignore this radical differ- ence in favor of the surface resemblances, as has been somewhat the practice since Grote's power- ful rehabilitation of the sophists, is to overlook the whole significance of the Socratic teaching, and it is to miss terribly the tragic lesson of his- tory. This was no paltry feud over scholastic terms, but the battle of one man who saw the truth and knew the consequences of error against a host of men who looked upon the truth with the eyes of a Pontius Pilate ; rather, it was the battle of one man for the deeper common sense of man- kind against the sophistries of a people that had lost its anchorage and was drifting it knew not whither. The Greeks are distinguished from other great peoples by their lack of any really sacred books or of a definite revelation ; and to this freedom of their imagination we owe a religion which of all religions is the most purely human and the most nearly universal, almost as full of meaning to- day, for those who understand it, as it was to the contemporaries of Socrates. But this freedom was a peril also, as all liberty is perilous. In an age of doubt and egoistic revolt from tradition such a religion, imless its deeper meaning meets with some authentication in the individual con- sciousness, is peculiarly liable to lose its moral 22 PLATONISM hold and to become a plaything for the fancy of its votaries. This is the easy way; it was the di- rection in which the educated classes of Greece were naturally turning, and the Protagorean scepticism, with its flattering plausibility, was ready at hand to cloak moral indolence in the garb of philosophy. The Greeks, again, as we see them typified from the beginning in Odysseus, were inclined to cleverness and versatility more than to plain truth, and apt to lay weight on the value of worldly wisdom somewhat at the expense of in- stinctive rectitude. They were always a little too quick to applaud knowledge for its own sake and to measure virtue by the standard of success. And this disposition was fostered by the sophists at a critical moment of history. Plato laid his finger on one of the spots where the decay of na- tional character first discovered itself, when he phaednis 272d dcclarcd that for the rhetorician, trained to plead before the courts, there was no need to bother over the exact nature of justice and goodness, since no juror would take heed of such subtleties, but would be guided in his vote by the force of persuasion based on probability. Any one con- versant with the literature of the Greek people knows how large a place the word "probable" occupies in their whole manner of thinking, and how cunningly the sophistical game played with the national foible. THE SOCRATIC THESES 23 What came in the end of this itching cleverness and this adroit flattery can be read in the Roman estimate of Greece in her degeneracy : "Augur schoenobates medicus magus, omnia novit Graeculus esuriens; in caelum miseris, ibit."^ Or, if it seems unfair to accept the petulant sat- ire of Juvenal as historical evidence, some credit at least must be allowed to Cicero's comparison of Greek and Roman witnesses under oath. "He had," he says, in his oration Pro Flacco, "always been particularly addicted to that nation and their studies, and knew many modest and worthy men among them. But as to the sanctity of an oath, they had no notion of it; all their concern in giving evidence was, not how to prove, but how to express what they said. Whereas a Roman, in giving his testimony, was always jealous of himself, lest he should go too far; weighed all his words, and was afraid to let any- thing drop from him too hastily and passion- ately."^ Or still, if we hesitate to take the "^ Juvenal iii, 77. It is amusing to see how Dr. Johnson adapted the lines to what was a corresponding prejudice, in his day not entirely unwarranted, against the French: "They sing, they dance, clean shoes, or cure a clap; All sciences a fasting Monsieur knows, And, bid him go to heU, to heU he goes." ^ Abridged from Middleton's paraphrase, Life of Cicero I, 300, ed. 1741. 24 PLATONISM Roman estimate of a conquered and subject people, there is the direct statement of Polybius,^ himself a Greek, as to the slipperiness of the Greek character resulting from their rejection of the restraints of religion. All this was involved in the difference between Socrates and the sophists; and unless we see clearly how the destiny of the Athenian people, and one might say of the world, was at stake, we shall make nonsense of the solemnity with which Apology 30d Socrates proclaimed his mission: "Therefore,© men of Athens, I am not concerned to plead for myself, as one might expect of me, but am rather pleading for you, lest by condenming me in your ignorance you throw away God's gift to you. . . . That I am really such an one given to the city by God, you may understand from my life ; for it is not from merely human motives that I neglect my own affairs and see them going to waste these many years, while I look imweariedly to your interests, and come to you all individually, as if I were a father or an elder brother, with my message and persuasion of virtue." Such was the last pubhc profession of Socrates, and it was not heard. This is not to say that the general de- cline of Greek civilization should be attributed to any special class of men as the deliberate source of corruption. The serious corrupters of youth, ® History vi, 54, 55. See also the use made of this pas- sage by Warburton in his Divine Legation 1, 408. THE SOCRATIC THESES 25 to use the phrase of the indictment against So- crates, were not the sophists, as Plato himself admits, but the mass of the people, who were ^^4^2''.!''' jealous of any distinction that ran counter to their own ideas, and made resistance to the course they were pursuing extremely difficult, even dan- gerous. The pity of it was that at this moment of intellectual curiosity and moral restlessness, when many generous minds here and there had caught glimpses of a higher law than tradition and needed to be encouraged in their quest of truth, the accredited teachers of the land should have disappointed the searchers and left them without any power of united resistance. The condemnation of the sophists, as a body, is not that they turned the current of thought in a new direction, but that they were themselves so deeply imtmersed in the popular tide, and lent their weight to its onward sweep. Unless this is true there is no meaning at all in those earher Dialogues of Plato in which he at- tacks the rhetoric of the sophists as being no genuine art, but only one of the many branches of popular flattery, like cooking and the rest. When he wrote these Dialogues, the particular men with whom Socrates had contended were no longer living, but the evil they had fostered was very much alive, was even growing daily more manifest to any one who looked beneath the sur- face of things. Hence the note of bitterness and Gorgias passim 26 PLATONISM occasionally of despondence in the writings of the one man who saw to the heart of the contrast between Socrates and the sophists, and, knowing he had failed to convert his own generation to the Socratic doctrine, did not know that he was establishing this doctrine for future ages as the Tiraaeus 47b iudcf cctiblc sourcc of philosophy, "than which no greater good has come or ever will come to mortal men." Out of the depths of his inner life Socrates had arrived at the conviction of three truths, two of which, scepticism and spiritual affirmation, were, as we have seen, intimately associated, while the third, the rationalistic identification of virtue and knowledge, stood in apparently unrelated isola- tion. It was the task of his successor to expound these theses in a way that should force their ac- ceptance upon any man who looked honestly into his own breast, and to carry them up to a point at which they should all three meet in a single harmonious system of philosophy. I do not mean that Plato saw the task lying before him in this limited and systematic form: his mind was too elastic, and his outlook on life too crowded with images of men and their destinies, to be confined in any formula however large. I mean rather that these theses were his funda- mental conviction, as they were of Socrates — the skeleton, so to speak, which, more or less con- cealed, gave shape and strength and coherence to THE SOCRATOC THESES 27 all his thought. And we on our part, if we may borrow Plato's license in shifting a metaphor, we, who would "swim through such and so great ^^^^^j^'^^^ a sea of words" as stretches before us in the Di- alogues, can find no safer light to guide us than these three motives to philosophy which he him- self took from his master. CHAPTER II THE SOCRATIC QUEST The fidelity with which Plato brings out the threefold impulse of Socrates to philosophy is evidence in itself that the same motives were at work in his own mind. But they are equally manifest in passages from which the biographical element is entirely absent. The theoretical basis of his scepticism may be left until we take up the discussion of his attitude towards metaphysics; here it will be sufficient to call attention to the note of profound disillusion running all through his works, and growing stronger with his age. ^^048^°^° "The doings of men," he declares at the end of his life, "are not worthy of great seriousness, yet it is \ necessary to be serious; and this is our misfort- une. . . . Men are for the most part puppets, and little is their share of truth." Socrates, I think, would never have spoken in just that tone of bitterness, born of a longer and sadder know- ledge; but Plato's words, nevertheless, spring ^^6e'''"" from the same vein of sceptical irony as that which he had so often seen his master display in common intercourse. So deeply ingrained is this note of doubt or hesitation in the Dialogues that THE SOCRATIC QUEST 29 the leaders of the Academy after Plato's death passed by an easy transition into a form of scept- icism barely distinguishable from that of the fol- lowers of Pyrrho. These men, if we may accept the verdict^ of a late critic, justified their posi- tion, in part, by Plato's own fondness for such terms as "the probable" {to eikos), thereby forc- ing his philosophy into accord with the teaching of the sophists — an irony of Fate comparable to that which brought about the condemnation of Socrates as a sophist. As for spiritual affirmation, Plato's language is fairly exultant with the faith in righteousness as the one thing which a man may safely assert, against all appearances, to be always desirable. Even above his magnificent art of exposition and dialectic, his real power of persuasion, for those who have ears to hear, lies in the earnestness of this direct and unwavering affirmation. When Socrates, in gaol and awaiting the hour of execu- tion, was urged by his dear friend Crito to bribe his way to hberty, he closed his memorable state- ment of the self-imposed obligations of duty with a simile borrowed from the experience of relig- ious devotees. "These things," he said, "I seem crito s4d to hear as the Corybantes think they hear the sound of flutes, and the echo of these words keeps ^ Prolegomena § 10. This treatise, whether by Olympi- odorus or another, is by no means negligible for the modern student. 30 PLATONISM up such a humming in my ears as quite to drown out any contrary arguments." So it is today with the understanding reader of the Platonic Dialogues; he is like one who has hearkened to the same incantation of magic flutes, the very memory of which is able to overpower all the dis- tracting voices of the world. But Plato was not writing only for the anima naturaliter Platonica, As a teacher needing withal to maintain his doc- trine logically against the attack of adversaries, he could not rest in a bare affirmation; he was bound to discover some authority for his faith, some definition of this higher knowledge, to which reason, if honest with itself, would at least will- ingly assent. Furthermore, the tendency to a positive ration- alism was as strong in Plato as it was in Socrates. His belief in the simple identification of virtue and knowledge is constantly coming to the sur- 860D s face in his writings, and even in the Laws he is still reasoning on the f amihar Socratic thesis that no man errs, or sins, willingly, but only through ignorance. Now, as I have said, such a maxim seems on its face to run counter to the known motives of human conduct, since any man, if questioned on his conduct, will admit that he often does wrong against the knowledge of what he knows to be best for him. Here, then, is an issue between philosophy and apparent fact; and if you solve this difficulty by explaining the equa- THE SOCRATIC QUEST 31 tion of virtue and knowledge after the manner of the utiHtarians, as Socrates and Plato did, you forthwith lay yourself open to the charge of throwing away your spiritual affirmation. At the outset of his philosophical career Plato was thus beset with the double problem, first of justifying separately his rationalism and his higher intuition, and then of harmonizing these two seemingly contradictory positions. So far as we can conjecture from the records, Socrates himself had faced and solved the problem of rationalism raised by his identification of virtue and knowledge, and to this extent Plato, in writ- ing his Dialogues, had only to repeat and clarify the steps of what may be called the Socratic Quest. But at this point Socrates ceased to be an expositor of his own philosophy: for the justi- fication of spiritual insight before the bar of rea- son, which may be called the Platonic Quest, and for the relation of insight and rationahsm, which had been left as the Socratic Paradox, Plato had to rely on his own resources of argument. Our study of Platonism, therefore, will follow this order: taking up first the Socratic Quest, we shall pass then to the Platonic Quest, and from these proceed to the Socratic Paradox. Or, expressed in the language of the three theses, our task is, first, to deal with the rationaHstic identification of virtue and knowledge, secondly to see how scepticism leads from this thesis to spiritual af- 32 PLATONISM firmation, and, thirdly, to discover how this ra- tionalism and affirmation can be held together. Now, there is a group of Dialogues, almost certainly the earliest written, in which Plato is engaged in pursuing the Socratic Quest, as if lured on by a goal already clearly enough seen and within easy reach, yet at the same time with glimpses of another goal beyond, still wrapped in the haze of distance. None of these Dialogues is conclusive, and at the end of each the reader is left in a mood like that of the ancient Persian, who complained that he had heard great argu- ment "About it and about, but evermore Came out by the same door where in he went." Meanwhile, however, these Dialogues wind in and out of their theme with such delightful ease, and gather by the way so many charming pictures of Athenian manners, that they might well be named the idylls of philosophy. Indeed, if I may confess my private taste, I almost at times hold them more precious than those greater Dialogues in which Plato no longer speaks as an inquirer but as a perfect master. For Truth, it may be, is to be worshipped at a distance, a creature so high and divine that no man, not even a Plato, can lay hands on her without a little soiling her robes. And these early Dialogues, as I assume THE SOCRATIC QUEST 33 / them to be, have the peculiar fascination of sug- gesting the truth to us as something certain yet unapproached. Each of them sets out to define a particular virtue — Charmides temperance, Laches bravery, Euthyphro holiness, Lysis friendship — and ends by rejecting as inadequate or inconsistent the various proposed definitions. But through all their inconclusiveness, these two thoughts are continually before the mind: that in some way which the debaters cannot understand the differ- ent virtues are distinct from one another, yet at the same time merely aspects of one all-embracing virtue; and, secondly, that in some way, equally obscure to the debaters, this one inclusive virtue is dependent on knowledge. A glance at one of these early Dialogues will indicate the character of all. In the Charmides we find a boy of this name presented by his elder cousin and guardian, Critias, to Socrates as a perfect specimen of that comeliness and grace and modesty, imited with strength and self- mastery, which gave to the youth of that age and land their peculiarly androgynous charm. He is the embodiment of the much-lauded and much- desired virtue of sophrosyne, which, for lack of a better equivalent, we translate "temperance." And Socrates, having introduced the topic by one of his dramatic ruses, proceeds to question the lad about this virtue, insinuating that he ought to 34 PLATONISM be able to define it if it is really in his possession. Temperance, replies the boy, after some hesita- tion, is a way of doing things sedately, a kind of quietness or slowness in action. And so the dis- cussion begins ; for, in his usual manner, Socrates finds difficulties in this definition. Certainly, he says, and Charmides admits, temperance is one of the fair and excellent things {ton halon) ; yet we should not bestow such epithets upon a person who learned his lesson or ran a race slowly, but upon one who was swift and agile. The lad, thus driven from his first definition, tries another: it is, he thinks, a kind of true shame or modesty. But again, objects Socrates, surely temperance is a good thing, as well as a fair thing, and, as Homer has declared, modesty is not always good for a man who is in need. And so once more the boy and his examiner seem to have reached an impasse. Now, a plain unimaginative man like Grote will see little profit in this sort of word-play be- yond its tendency to shake the ignorant out of their confidence ; and there is that in this first part of the Dialogue — and something more. It is an admirable example of the superficial sophistry to which Plato sometimes descends, whether wit- tingly or unwittingly, while the conclusion he has in view is perfectly sound. The fallacy lies in the ambiguous use of such words as "fair" and "good," which retain their practical popular THE SOCRATIC QUEST 35 meaning as applied to the specific acts of men, while they include also hints and admonitions of a deeper sense as touching the purpose underly- ing any specific act. All temperance is good? Yes. Then it follows, if goodness is such a thing, simple and invisible, as it is becoming in Plato's rational system, that all good is temperance, and all good is bravery, and so with the other specific virtues. In a word there is only one morahty, into which all the virtues are merged indistin- guishably, and any attempt to define or apply a specific virtue will result in confusions and con- tradictions. But then virtue that cannot be de- fined or applied is rather an aerial commodity for this workaday world; and so, where are we? Of course Charmides might have retorted that he was employing the word "good" in one sense and his interlocutor in another; but this would have demanded a power of analysis quite beyond his years — a power, in fact, which his literary creator had not yet attained, or which he most artfully concealed. At this point the argument of the Charmides takes another turn. At the secret suggestion of his cousin the lad asks Socrates what he has to say of this definition: "Temperance is doing one's own business"? That sounds well; but it does not take Socrates long to bring out its in- adequacy, for how can doing one's own business be temperance until a man first decides whether 36 PLATONISM what he is doing is beneficial or the contrary? He might be doing himself an injury while thinking a certain act was his business, and, manifestly, it cannot be acting temperately to do oneself an injury. Before a man can be temperate, there- fore, he must know himself and his business. Here Critias takes up the challenge, and avers that temperance is just the sort of knowledge im- plied in Socrates' queries: it is self-knowledge. Moreover, he has a divine sanction for this defi- nition, and from a source that must appeal strongly to Socrates ; for the God of Delphi who meets the worshipper at the threshold of the temple with the inscription "Know thyself" is not issuing a command, but pronouncing a salu- tation after the manner of our "Hail," "Be well," and to be well is the same as to be temperate. By his manner of salutation, therefore, the God is instructing us that to know oneself and to be well and to be temperate are all one and the same virtue. Thus, by an easy transition, we have the argument slipping from the question whether the virtues are all one to the question whether virtue, this particular virtue of temperance at least, is not identical with knowledge. Critias, in asso- ciating virtue with self-knowledge, might seem to have reached the goal of the quest, but he is soon thrown by Socrates into embarrassment because he is unable to analyse the ambiguity lurking in the word "knowledge" similar to that which en- tangled Charmides in the use of the "good." THE SOCRATIC QUEST 37 Under the cross-questioning of Socrates this knowledge which Critias identifies with temper- ance proves to be, not the knowledge of anything definite, such as that which we obtain from sight or sound, but just a knowledge of knowledge and of ignorance. Eut where is the profit in this in- substantial sort of knowledge? How, for in- stance, shall the possessor of this knowledge be able to distinguish the pretender in medicine from the true physician? To do this he will have to know some of the marks of the physician's art, something about health and disease, and this is a very different sort of thing from the knowledge of knowledge, whatever that may mean. And so it is with temperance; if we define this virtue as knowledge, it must be knowledge of some specific way of profiting ourselves, and not that mere empty knowing that we know or do not know. The argument is all a tangle, in which we have become involved by the treacherous words "good- ness" and "knowledge." Yet we are left with a hint of the way of escape, given in the last beauti- ful address of Socrates to the youth whose virtue was the occasion of all this seeking and doubting : "I would advise you to regard me as a babbling fellow unable to reason anything out, and of yourself to believe that, as you are more temper- ate, so you are happier." Simple as this last sentence may soimd, it is pregnant with meaning. After the fruitless 38 PLATONISM arguing forwards and backwards, it awakens in us the sensation of one who has been long wan- dering in a blind labyrinth, and suddenly comes upon an opening in the wall through which he descries lying before him a clear and spacious garden. So strong is this impression that we should be tempted to believe Plato had written the Dialogue deliberately as a puzzle, having in his hand all the while the clues not only of the Socratic Quest in which he is engaged, but of the larger Quest that is to follow, were it not for the two great arguments of the Protagoras and the Gorgias, which seem to come after the Charmides and its group in time and to represent the author as still searching. Much of the Protagoras is like the debate of the earliest Dialogues, only wider in dramatic scope. The sophist who gives his name to the piece maintains that the virtues are separate. Be- ing separate, they cannot be embraced under any single category such as knowledge, yet they can, he thinks, be imparted by instruction. Socrates holds that they are all a form of knowledge, and so not many but one; and as they are identical with knowledge, he would like to believe that they are teachable, but is troubled because he can find no teachers from whom you can learn them as you can acquire the various arts from prac- titioners. The two disputants are thus complete- ly at cross purposes, and the reader is likely to THE SOCRATIC QUEST S9 be vexed at their apparent stupidity in missing the occasions of coming to agreement. For ex- ample, Protagoras has been forced to admit that three of the virtues — justice, hohness, temper- ance — are at least pretty closely akin, being all reducible to wisdom, or knowledge; but he still clings to his theory that the fourth virtue, bravery, is quite apart from the others. Where- upon Socrates proceeds to show that bravery too can be reduced to knowledge; since, as a virtue, it should not be confused with the headlong impulse of the unthinking animal, and can be nothing more than wisdom regard- ing what is dangerous and what is not. At this point Protagoras takes refuge in silence, and the discussion comes to an end. Yet how easy, the reader is likely to say to himself with some impatience, it would have been for Protagoras to retort: Very good, my dear teaser; no doubt bravery is dependent on knowledge, just as tem- perance and holiness are, but just observe your own addition — "regarding what is dangerous and what is not" ; it is this very regarding that makes the virtues different applications of knowledge, and so not one but separate. The retort is easy ; yet beware. Unless you have got clearly defined in your understanding this slippery thing called knowledge, your questioner will attack you from another side, and you will fall a victim to his cun- ning, as Protagoras had already fallen in trying 40 PLATONISM to explain how the knowledge of virtue is im- parted in instruction. So far, then, we seem not to have escaped from the labyrinth of the group of Dialogues in which the Charmides is included. But there is one im- portant addition to be noted. This you may know, said Socrates at the close of the Charmides, that you will be happier as you are more temper- ate. Now, in the Protagoras for the first time, Plato takes up this further identification of virtue and knowledge with the sum of pleasures which, in ordinary language, is named happiness. We cannot get away from this one fact, Socrates argues, that the feeling of pleasure is in itself good and that pain is in itself bad; hence we seem to have here a sure criterion of the rightness or wrongness of our acts, in the result — ^not, of course, the immediate consequence but the final result — as shown by the balance of pleasure and pain. Virtue is reduced to a pure hedonism (from hedone, pleasure), dependent on a man's ability to calculate and weigh his sensations pres- ent and future. If, therefore, men are to be per- suaded to follow justice and holiness and tem- perance, they must be taught that such a course of life in its totality imparts more pleasure than the contrary course. The conclusion may be given in the excellent language of Bishop Berkeley's use of this argument to undermine the logic of those who make hedonism an excuse for vice: THE SOCRATIC QUEST 41 "But Socrates, who was no country parson, sus- pected your men of pleasure were such through ignorance of the art of reckoning. It was his opinion (Plato in Protagoras) that rakes cannot reckon. And that for want of this skill they make wrong judgments about pleasure, on the right choice of which their happiness depends. To make a right computation, should you not consider all the faculties and all the kinds of pleasure, taking into your account the future as well as the present, and rating them all accord- ing to their true value? And all these points duly considered, will not Socrates seem to have had reason on his side, when he thought ignor- ance made rakes, and particularly their being ignorant of what he calls the science of more and less, greater and smaller, equaUty and compari- son, that is to say of the art of computing?"^ Manifestly, the argument has reached here a certain conclusion, the Socratic Quest has touched the goal. Virtue is an act which will re- sult in the greater sum of pleasure, and he will be the virtuous man who has the knowledge that enables him to calculate the consequences of his conduct, and strike a balance in the terms of sensation. Knowledge has been defined by the content of pleasure and pain, and by such a defi- nition we can say that no man errs, or sins, will- ingly, but only through ignorance. This, ap- ^ Alciphron II, xviii, abridged. 42 PLATONISM parently, is the form in which Socrates held his thesis, and it has maintained its position in the world to this day; since Bentham formulated the utilitarianism of the eighteenth century it may even be regarded as the dominant theory of ethics, however it may have disguised itself by various additions and verbal modifications. And, in a way, when combined, as it was in the teach- ing of Socrates, with another truth of an utterly different order, it contains a kernel of truth. But taken alone as complete in itself, as it is professed by the utilitarian and as it was expressed in the Protagoras, it certainly is inadequate, if not false. What assurance is there that any man, by his own judgment or even by the collective exper- ience of society, shall be able at any critical mo- ment to foresee the long series of consequences that may follow a particular act, or shall be wise enough to determine coldly, amid the warm solici- tations of present desire, where the remote bal- ance of pleasure and pain will lie? Such a calcu- lation is but a fumbling guide at best; unless fortified by a higher truth it is likely to bring us, indeed in the end it has invariably brought men, to the Pyrrhonic form of scepticism, which thrusts aside the uncertainties of the far future, and seeks for tranquilhty in accepting with a kind of stoic Epicureanism the pleasure in sight as the only reality — "Ah, take the cash, and let the credit go." THE SOCRATIC QUEST 43 But that is not the scepticism of Socrates, nor is this the goal to which Plato's mind is moving with the steady sweep of tidal waters drawn on- ward by a celestial force. What is this thing called pleasm^e which we have so lightly accepted as the sole arbiter of life? That is the question agitated in the GorgiaSj and never afterwards forgotten by Plato. By a roundabout way the discussion of the Gorgias is brought at last to a sharp dispute be- tween Calhcles, on the one part, portrayed as a typical demagogue of the day, a man interested superficially in philosophical questions, but at heart an agnostic and egotist seeking for a Uf e of pleasure through power, and, on the other part, Socrates, represented here as the customary iron- ist, but with new resources of sarcasm for those who try to humiliate him and of stirring appeal for those who will heed. The brief for pleasure, which in the Protagoras was held by Socrates, is now put into the mouth of Calhcles, in order to demonstrate its insufficiency when carried to the logical end, while Socrates, as usual, is made the vehicle of Plato's expanding thought — von Aen- derungen zu hoheren Aenderungen. This talk about temperance and righteousness, says Callicles, with a cynicism that reminds us of certain latter-day prophets, is all humbug : "The nobility and justice of nature, as I now 491E s tell you boldly, is really this, that a man who 44 PLATONISM would live rightly should permit his desires to grow to the uttermost and not temper them by discipline; and when they have thus grown he should be able to serve them by reason of his cour- age and wisdom, and satisfy any longing that may arise. But this is impossible for the mob. Hence, for shame, they conceal their own im- potence by blaming such men, and say that in- temperance is a dishonourable thing, as I declared before, thus reducing the better natures to slavery. And, being incapable of satisfying their longing for pleasure, they praise temperance and justice, for their own lack of manhood. Suppose a man were bom the son of a king, or were cap- able by his own nature of making himself a king or tyrant or ruler, what, in the name of truth, would be worse or more dishonourable than tem- perance or justice for such a man — for a man, I say, who, when he might enjoy the good things of life and there was no one to hinder, should bring in the conmion opinion and reason and censure of the mob as a master over himself? And would he not be a wretched creature if he were so sub- dued by the specious honour of justice and tem- perance as not to grant advantages to his friends over his enemies, in the city where he himself was ruling? No, Socrates, the truth is — and you pro- fess yourself a votary of the truth — that luxury and intemperance and liberty, these, if they are supported, are virtue and happiness; the rest is fopperies, the unnatural conventions of society, idle chatter." THE SOCRATIC QUEST 45 Very good, replies Socrates, we have got down to the real point at issue; and he proceeds to draw inferences from this definition of virtue in a way that causes his antagonist to squirm with indignation. If pleasure is all, and there is no criterion beyond it, what should hinder a man from indulging himself in practices which can scarcely be named, which, in fact, we do not name today? Nor was there anything unfair in so pressing the argument. We need only look at the actual life in Athens, or in the Italian cities of the Renaissance, to learn that it is perfectly possible for a man to gratify his lowest and vilest desires without losing that sense of pleasure which the hedonist makes his norm of conduct. These grosser pursuits cannot be rejected on the ground that a true calculation, so long as it con- fines itself to a purely quantitative estimation of pleasure and pain, finds them in the end on the wrong side of the ledger. Such a reckoning may save a man from excess ; it will not teach him to renounce any pleasure in itself. Callicles is decent enough to admit that some pleasures are in themselves better than others, and having thus granted the existence of the good, or the honour- able, as a standard outside of pleasures by which we may grade them, he has virtually given up his case. It is at this point that Socrates utters his ironi- cally exultant cry, "Joy! joy!" — as it were a 499b 46 PLATONISM prophetic note of triumph over the hosts of sophistry. That is one of the great moments of philosophy, the moment when we pass from the Soeratic Quest to the Platonic Quest; and I never read the exclamation put into the mouth of Socrates, but I think of the shout of Achilles, when he came from his tent and stood by the trench, with the divine splendour radiating about him. The real battle was yet to come, but there was terror in the walls of Troy. "Seeing, then," says Socrates, taking up the argument formally, "that we have agreed to- gether, you and I, that there is such a thing as the good and such a thing as the pleasant, and that the pleasant is not the same as the good, and that each is acquired by a certain attention and mode of action, according as we set out after the pleasant or the good — but before I proceed, tell me whether you say yes or no to all this." And Callicles, like a man brought to bay, says yes. Whereupon Socrates returns to the points on which they had differed, and now, fortified by this concession of Callicles, pronoimces the verdict and throws back the slurs of his antagonist, in a way that has never failed to hearten good men against the slanders and insults of unscrupulous power: 507b "And so, Callicles, we come to this necessary conclusion, that the temperate man, being, as we THE SOCRATIC QUEST 47 have described him, just and brave and holy, is entirely good; and the good man must do well and honourably whatever he does, and he who is doing well must be blessed and happy ^ and the bad man who is doing ill must be miserable. . . . Well, then, either this argument of ours must be refuted, that men are made happy by the posses- sion of temperance and justice, and miserable by the possession of evil, or, if the argimient is true, we must regard the consequences. . . . We must consider whether you were right or wrong in your abusive taunts, to the effect that I am unable to defend myself or any of my friends or family, or to save them from the extremity of danger, be- ing, Hke an outlaw, at the mercy of any one who chooses to buffet me on the ear, if I may repeat your insulting words, or to deprive me of my property, or banish from the city, or, worst of all, kill me. Such a state, you declare, is the most shameful a man can be in. But I say, as I have often said, and there is no reason why I should not say it again — I say, O Callicles, the most shameful thing is not to be buffeted on the ear unjustly, nor to have my face or purse cut; but it is a worse thing and more shameful to buffet me and slash me and mine unjustly, and to rob / and abuse my body or my house. In a word, to do any injustice to me and mine is a worse thing and more shameful for the one who does the in- justice than for me the sufferer. This is the truth as it appeared to us in our former discus- sion, and is now made fast and bound, if I may use a bold metaphor, in proofs of iron and ada- '/ 48 PLATONISM mant. So at least it should seem; unless you, or some one more audacious than you, should suc- ceed in arguing fairly against what I am now saying. For as for me, my word is always the same: that I do not know how these things are, but that of all the men I have ever met, as now, no one has been able to say otherwise without making himself ridiculous." Thus, after taking a fall out of one adversary and then another, Socrates is at liberty to profess his tremendous affirmation of the moral life, in a tone very different from that of the calculating argument employed with Protagoras. But ob- serve the door by which he has finally slipped into this new region. Weigh the sentence italicized above, by which the passage has been made, for it is the keynote of Platonism, the despair of the petty logician, the joy of the initiated: "He who is doing well must be blessed and happy, and the bad man who is doing ill must be miserable."^ Now on its face this is no argument at all, but a bit of outrageous sophistry turning on the am- biguity of a phrase. To do well in Greek means both to prosper, he fortunate, and to act right- eously, justly } Callicles would have been ready from the first to grant that to do well in the sense ^"Oo-TC TToA-X^ dvayKr) . . . rbv 8' cv irpaTTOvra fjuaKapiov T€ KoX €vBaifiova etvai, tov Se Trovrjpov kol KaKws irpaTTOvra ddkiov. * In the preceding debate with Polus the argument (474c £f) had taken a similar turn by means of the ambiguity of the word kukov. THE SOCRATIC QUEST 49 of being fortunate is to he happy — naturally ; but if he now makes no objection to the other mean- ing, that to do well in the sense of acting justly is to he happy, it is because he has been brow- beaten by Socrates into a state of submissiveness. To understand the full scope of this silent admis- sion we must briefly recapitulate the argument. Callicles had begun by drawing a distinction between nature (physis) and tradition (nomos) . Nature is what we know by our inmiediate indi- vidual sense, that is by natural feeling; tradition is what we have not learned from our indi- vidual experience, but accept as the opinion, or common sense, of mankind. Nature, he con- tends, tells us that happiness depends upon the amount of pleasure we can wring out of life, and not upon the means by which we obtain this pleasure; therefore, in nature, it is better to be unjust than to be just. Against this precept of nature the law of tradition, or conmaon sense, that it is better to be just than to be unjust, has no weight for any one who is cognizant of the facts, since it is merely an opinion which we try to make prevail with others, for our own advantage and not at all for theirs. The problem of philosophy, therefore, unless it should be content with a brutal form of hedonism, was to confirm the authority of the popular verdict, and to prove that it is true also in nature.^ ^ For this contrast of nature and common sense, or com- mon opinion, see Laws 659d, 889e, et passim. 50 PLATONISM Socrates, as we have seen, takes hold of the distinction thus drawn, and so entangles Callicles in his logic that at last he is obliged to accede to a qualitative difference in pleasures and to a cri- terion of life apart from them and above them. So far the discussion is perfectly fair, and to this extent Callicles has been forced by sound reason- ing to admit that the popular conmion-sense opinion is also true by the test of his own feelings. We do know for a fact that one pleasure is bet- ter, in the sense that we naturally call it more just, than another. But the next step, that our happiness depends on this new qualitative cri- terion, rather than the quantity of pleasure, is not argued at all; it is merely slipped through by a verbal ambiguity, owing to the bewilderment into which Callicles has been thrown. The phrase doing well merges together the two standards of nature and common sense — to be happy by pros- pering is a thesis of nature, whereas to be happy by acting justly is a thesis of common sense — and, however it was with Callicles, Plato should not have let this confusion pass without com- ment. But neither here nor anywhere else in the Dialogue does the author show himself aware of the fallacy. Instead of bringing evidence to prove that the common-sense view is also true by the experience of each individual man, he allows Socrates to maintain his position by the mere arm of an invincible scepticism : "So at least it should THE SOCRATIC QUEST 51 seem; unless you, or some one more audacious than you, should succeed in arguing fairly against what I am now saying. For as for me, my word is always the same, that I do not know how these things are, but that of all the men I have ever met, as now, no one has been able to say otherwise without making himself ridiculous." It is something — a great thing, no doubt — ^to have raised the common opinion of mankind to the solemn utterance of a spiritual affirmation, supported by the powers of scepticism; but this is still not philosophy, however it may be the basis of philosophy. Common sense may be right, but so long as it cannot tell "how these things are," cannot, that is, give an account of itself dialectic- ally, it is open to attack and discomfiture. Now, so far from being able to give an account of itself, conmion sense is painfully aware of its unaided inabiUty to square its verdict with the visible facts of life, and is continually taking refuge in the ex- pected reversals of an invisible world hereafter. It declares that the just man must prosper and be happy, and in this declaration it never wavers ; yet it beholds everywhere the prizes of the race going to the strong and unscrupulous, and in its distress it prays to God for vengeance on the wicked and for help to the righteous. So it was not only in Greece but the world over; and so it is today. How marvellously, for example, the trust and despair of religion were combined in 52 PLATONISM the Jewish Psahns, and how legitimately our worship has adapted those outcries to its sense of present defeat and future victory, any one may understand by reading the great sermon of New- man on the Condition of the Members of the Christian Church. And this is precisely the position of Plato in the Gorgias. Beside the magnificent profession of Socrates that the just man is happy, he sets Callicles' picture of the just man as he may be actually seen on this earth, buffeted and scorned, unable to protect himself against the machina- tions of evil ; and, beyond the quibble of a phrase, Plato has no positive logic to prove that Socrates, in this point, is right. Whether conscious or not of this defect in the argument, he turns for his vindication from philosophy to mythology, flee- ing, like the Christian Church, to faith in the power of another world to make good the dis- harmony of this. The Dialogue concludes with an account of the pagan day of judgment, when the naked soul stands, with all its secrets revealed, before the tribunal of Aeacus and Radamanthys and Minos, and, as these pronounce, is sentenced to reward or punishment. "For this," Socrates says, "was the law [nomos, the divine ratification of nomos as common sense] concerning men un- der Cronus, and is now and always among the gods, that he who has passed through this life in justice and hoHness goes after death to the Isl- THE SOCRATIC QUEST 53 ands of the Blessed, there to dwell in perfect hap- piness beyond the range of evil, whereas he who has lived wickedly and atheistically departs to the prison-house of vengeance and judgment." So far Plato has come in the Quest: he has shown that the popular view of morality has the sanction of religion, and that, if only the myth of future retribution be true, then certainly it is better, measured by the ordinary standard of hap- piness, to be just than to be unjust. But what if the myth be rejected? The effort to confirm this verdict philosophically, by an argument based on the immediate knowledge of men, here and now, will be the task of The Republic, If Plato suc- ceeds in reaching this goal, then the ambiguity of the phrase by which Callicles in the Gorgias was tricked into acquiescence will prove to contain no fallacy, but the truth of philosophy as it is ex- pressed by the instinctive common sense of man- kind. CHAPTER III THE PLATONIC QUEST The Republic is the richest book of philosophy ever yet composed. In its wide scope there is scarcely an important question of human life that is not touched on ; ethics, psychology, meta- physics, science, education, art, religion — every- thing is here. Impressed by this diversity of in- terests, the pedant has undertaken to analyse the work into separate treatises written at different times ; and the casual reader, in his bewilderment, is likely to ask himself whether the whole thing is not the random outpouring of a powerful but il- logical brain, the creation, perhaps, of a poet who has taken up the ungrateful task of philosophiz- ing. Yet, with all its variety, the better we know the Dialogue the more strongly we feel its or- ganic unity ; and, indeed, the thesis that never for a moment is lost from sight through all the diva- gations of reason and fancy, ought to be clear enough to any attentive student. It is pro- claimed by the author categorically more than once, notably in the beginning of the eighth book, at one of the cardinal points of the argument, where he says his design was to set forth the 54. THE PLATONIC QUEST 65 various forms of government, with the corre- sponding characters of individual men, "in order s44a that, having seen all these, and having come to an agreement about the best man and the worst, we might learn whether or not the best man is the most happy and the worst man the most miser- able." Words could not state more plainly than these that the object of the Dialogue is to come to an understanding about that affirmation of Socrates in the Gorgias concerning happiness and virtue, which was there upheld by the force of sarcasm and ridicule, but is now to be confirmed by argu- ment and by illustration of a positive sort. Here the problem arises as to the relation of the Platonic Dialogues to one another. The so- lution depends primarily on the time of composi- tion. If these works which we have considered as forming a propaedeutic to The Republic are com- paratively late in order, following at least the Phaedrus, which an ancient tradition held to be the earliest of all the Dialogues, then Plato, of course, was merely playing a part in them. If, however, they are, as virtually all scholars hold today, the unriper products of his genius, then we have still to answer the question whether they display the candid gropings of a mind attempt- ing to pass beyond the Socratic Quest, or were written purposely as a preparation, with the con- clusions of The Republic already in view. The 56 PLATONISM decision can rest only on subtle inference and on comparison with the procedure of other writers. My own opinion is that the Charmides (with its companion pieces) and the Protagoras, Gorgias, and Republic certainly follow one another in this chronological order. But I cannot believe that they were all planned together deliberately as one complete design; for that would be to grant to their author a comprehensiveness of intellect and a power of artistic restraint almost more than human. Nor can I admit that they are to be taken as purely occasional treatises with no continuous argument ; for that is simply to write oneself down as incapable of reading philosophy. The only other explanation is to see in them the inevitable development of Plato's thought, and to suppose that in each case the larger theme of the Dialogue to succeed was floating vaguely be- fore him, but was not yet worked out in logical form. And this, too, is the most interesting theory ; for I doubt if literature affords any other example of a mind circling outwards from a single central impulse with quite such fateful regularity of pattern — and when we have fol- lowed these broadening rings to the utmost reach of our vision, it is as if they still moved onwards and outwards to some far-off invisible shore. The first book of The Republic is frankly an introduction, in which Plato recapitulates the Quest so far as this had carried him hitherto. THE PLATONIC QUEST 57 After a dramatic exposition of the mise en scene he leads Socrates and Polemarchus into a genial debate on the nature of justice, very much as temperance was discussed in the Charmides, and bravery and holiness and friendship in the other early Dialogues ; and with the same inconclusive result. No tenable definition of justice is reached, but the inference is subtly suggested that in some way justice is merely one form of an all-embracing virtue, and that this master vir- tue is somehow dependent on knowledge. At this point the amicable conversation is broken by the sophist Thrasymachus, as the gambolling of lambs might be interrupted by the advent of a wolf. As CalUcles, in the Gorgias, was a rougher duplicate of Gritias, in the Charmi- deSj so the present antagonist is still more turbu- lent — a veritable devil's advocate ; and to the end of this book we have what is substantially a sum- mary of the main dispute of the Gorgias. You two, exclaims Thrasymachus, are talking silly nonsense and indulging in a game of mutual flat- tery. When urged by Socrates to give his own definition of the virtue, he asserts insolently that justice is the interest of the stronger, and nothing more ; and then, shifting the words to their popu- lar sense and calling that injustice which in his view of life is really justice, he repeats the cyn- ical theory of the day, which we have already heard from Calhcles, and now in this latter age 68 PLATONISM are hearing proclaimed as a novel doctrine by teachers of the Nietzschean type. My meaning, says Thrasymachus, will be clear if we take the extreme case of so-called injustice, and see how happy it renders a man in contrast with the mis- erable creatures who are subject to him and obey the slave-morality — ^the injustice of the tyrant who brings a whole city imder his will and is able to provide for himself and his friends whatever good he desires. The truth of what I say, adds Thrasymachus, is proved by the fact that in their heart of hearts men envy and eulogize such a character; for in reality people give hard names to injustice not because they condemn the thing itself but because they are afraid of suffering un- der it. To this unreserved glorification of power Socrates has no difficulty in replying. The man who holds it right to make his own supremacy the law of conduct must first understand what his interest is, even in this crude form, so that mere strength is not sufficient but must be united with some sort of wisdom ; and as soon as this element of wisdom is admitted, all kinds of considerations of man's higher nature force themselves upon us and make the identification of happiness with sheer power unthinkable. The conclusion of the dispute is like that to which Socrates and Callicles came in the Gorgias, only with this important difference: in the pres- ent case Socrates admits that nothing has been THE PLATONIC QUEST 59 finally decided. "The discussion," he says, at the end of the book, "has brought me no real know- ledge; for while I do not know what justice in itself is, we shall scarcely know whether it hap- pens to be a virtue or not, and whether he who possesses it is happy or not happy." And now, instead of cloaking this ignorance in the myth of a judgment to come, he will settle down with his friends to lay bare, if possible, the inmost nature of this thing they call justice, and to discover the source of their, or rather his, assurance that it is better to be just than unjust, better even, if needs be, to suffer the extremity of injustice than to do injustice. To this end they will strip justice of all the honours and rewards by which a man is lured to act contrary to his natural desires, and will contrast with this the purest injustice, with- out any of the penalties imposed upon it from without. They will picture to themselves a man who pursues through hfe an undeviating course of justice, yet who shall appear to others to be acting unjustly; and by his side they will set up the man who, hke the owner of the ring of in- visibihty, is able to satisfy all his evil propensi- ties without detection. Furthermore, for the sake of argument, they will suppose that the juggling pardon-sellers actually have the power to buy off the vengeance of the gods, so that by the sacrifice of a little of his ill-gotten gains the unjust man can be assured of as fair a prospect after death 60 PLATONISM as the just man. Then they may see whether, imder such conditions as these, the just man is still happy and the imjust man unhappy. If this proves to be the case, it must be because justice in itself brings happiness and injustice misery. The novelty of such a procedure they fully rec- ognize, for, as one of them observes, from the be- ginning of the world, so far as the records go, there never has been an attempt to denounce in- justice and praise justice as they are in the soul, themselves the greatest possible evil and the greatest possible good, even if they are hidden from the eyes of men and gods. How shall this mystery be laid bare, and who shall read the writing on the secret scroll of the human heart? For a while the little band of searchers is daimted by the task; and then So- crates thinks of a device. After all, the State is but man writ large ; if, then, we are balked in dis- covering what we seek in the isolated soul, per- haps its operation will be traced more easily in the conduct of society. And so, for the rest of the Dialogue, the working of justice and injustice is regarded alternately as displayed in the individ- ual and in the Repubhc. To begin with the larger writing, Socrates suggests that the easiest way to track down the virtues of a city or State (the words were about synonymous to a Greek) will be to follow its progress genetically from its feeblest beginnings THE PLATONIC QUEST 61 to its consummation as seen in a highly developed civiHzation. A Mttle examination shows that this advance is by what we should call today the in- creasing division of labour, or by what was sug- gested in the Charmides as the source of the vir- tue named temperance, that is by the practice of each man doing his own business. Such a law must not be limited to the individual, holding the shoemaker to his last and the farmer to his plough, but must permeate the organization of society; it will divide the people as a whole into separate classes, each with its special function in the conmion life. Three great tasks the State has : to govern itself, to defend itself, and to nour- ish itself; and to these vital functions will cor- respond the main division of the people into rul- ers and soldiers and producers. Then, if our principle of organization is sound, the State will possess the various virtues according as each of these classes carries out its proper activity : it will be wise when the rulers perform their duty com- petently, brave when the soldiers defend their fellow citizens under the guidance of the rulers, temperate when the labourers, obeying the rulers and protected by the soldiers, are industrious and productive.^ But we have not yet found the ^ There is some confusion in Plato's conception of tem- perance as given in The Republic. Thus, at 4S2A, it is re- garded, not as the special virtue of the productive class, but as extended through all three classes. On the other hand, 62 PLATONISM fourth of the cardinal virtues, the most important of all, justice. As there is no separate class left this virtue must somehow be spread through the whole of society. What else can it be but that very law itself of doing one's own business, which is the efficient cause of organization and the force behind the specific virtues? Now if the virtues of the single man are analo- gous to those of the State, it must be because the soul itself has faculties corresponding in their functions with the three classes of society. Two such faculties, or modes of the soul's activity, are manifest at a glance; reason, answering to the ruling class, and desire, answering to the pro- ductive, acquisitive class. And the specific vir- tues of these faculties name themselves : a man is wise when reason governs his actions, temperate when his appetites are imder subjection to rea- son. A third analogy Socrates finds in the fac- ulty by which we feel anger, indignation, resent- ment, pride, superiority — the thymos^ as it is called in Greek by an untranslatable term. This, such passages as 434c and 435b would seem to be mean- ingless unless temperance is limited to the productive class. Only by this restriction of temperance to the lowest ele- ment of the State and of the soul can it be separated from justice. So, certainly, Aristotle, with apparent reference to Plato, understood the matter (e.g., Topica v, 6, 10). The confusion in Plato is owing to his occasional failure to dis- tinguish between the division of the State into classes and of the soul into faculties. THE PLATONIC QUEST 63 it should be observed, was not what we mean or think we understand by the "will"; for the will, if Plato had had any word of precisely this sig- nification, would not have been accepted by him as a separate faculty or mode of activity. He would have agreed wdth Hobbes in regarding it as "the last appetite in dehberating," and would have admitted the conclusive statement of Jona- than Edwards, to the effect that "a man never, in any instance, wills anything contrary to his desires, or desires anything contrary to his will, . . . the will is always determined by the strong- est motive." The thymos, then, is the seat of the personal emotions as distinguished from physical desires. It is at once, as an appetitive faculty, akin to the desires, and by its mental character- istics close to the reason ; it Ues between the two, hke the soldier class between the governors and the producers, and its virtue like theirs is bravery, or courage.^ ^ The psychology of Plato for its purpose is sound and effective, and he was within his rights as a moralist when he threw it into relief by the great metaphor of the State. But the reader of The Republic should be warned that Plato's mental procedure was the reverse of his rhetorical method, and that his psychology really preceded his so- ciology. The division of the State into classes was made not so much for itself as for an illustration of the activities of the soul. As such it was an excellent device of rhetoric, even of logic ; but Plato, it must be acknowledged, sometimes overstepped the proper limits of analogy. He did not always remember that the State is a collection of funda- 64 PLATONISM And so, as Socrates says, our dream is com- pleted, and by a fable, for which we may thank the gods, we have been guided to the discovery of justice in the soul. For evidently that principle of attending to one's business which was the or- ganizing force of society and the efficient cause of the civic virtues is a shadowy image of what 443c we are seeking. In very truth the justice of a man is like that of the State, save for this im- portant difference, that it is not concerned with the division of labour in outer things, but with the conduct and being of the soul itself. It is the power that holds the several elements of the soul each to the performance of its peculiar duty, and forbids meddling. By it a man first brings order into his own nature, becoming one with himself, and having his members tempered and harmonized like the chords of a lute that make one music of many notes. And then, when the mental units, and not, like the soul, a unit with various forms of activity. There are in the State rulers and pro- ducers, and the distinguishing virtue of the former is wis- dom, as temperance is of the latter; but these classes are composed of individuals each of whom possesses all the faculties. The neglect of this simple fact has led our "di- vine" philosopher now and then, as it has led modern socio- logists, into strange and devious imaginings. His most ar- dent admirers will confess that, whereas he generally shows a profound intimacy with the intricacies of the individual soul, some of his theories of the State have a remote rela- tion to the realities of human nature. But this is one of the subjects which must be left for another time and another book. THE PLATONIC QUEST 65 ] peace of his inner life is established and he is | master of himself, he will proceed to act, as he ] has occasion to act, whether in a matter of private -i business or pubhc interest, in accordance with the ; law of justice within him, calling any act just which preserves the balance of his soul and co- ^ operates with it, and declining as unjust anything i that would contravene and mar his self-control. : Justice, in a word, might by its very definition be taken to denote the happier condition of the soul in precisely the same way as health of body is ] more desirable than disease. But a definition does not necessarily force conviction, and all that ^ logic can do — though its importance in this re- \ spect must not be underestimated — is to clear away from before our eyes the obstacles thrown up by false reasoning, and then to bid us look at the truth as it stands naked and revealed. In the \ end the success of any moral appeal depends on the consent of the soul itself; for of what avail, as Socrates asked, are argument and definition oorgias 472b unless the hearer in his very heart bears testimony ; to them? And there's the rub. Our life is woven \ of endlessly changing emotions, and few of us ' are capable of distinguishing the permanent from the transient effects of our acts, and of disentan- ghng the threads of experience so as to say that \ we feel thus now because we then did so. To ; draw proper conclusions we need the help of one j who is able to throw such a light into the soul and 66 PLATONISM character of a man as shall make us see clearly into those dark places. The philosopher, there- fore, who is concerned with something besides verbal triumphs has no other recourse than to turn to the power of the imagination; and so Plato will devote the eighth and ninth books of his Dialogue to unfolding such a "counterfeit presentment" of the various forms of government and of the corresponding characters as shall compel the most reluctant reader to say: This is the very truth of things as I myself have seen it— "O Hamlet, speak no more; Thou tum'st mine eyes into my very soul." The method of portraiture will be a union of history and psychology. It will undertake to ex- hibit the cities of Greece actually passing from one form of government to another — from aris- tocracy to timocracy, and from that to oligarchy and democracy, and last to that tyranny which was the perpetual menace of these small and fac- tious States, and which was to close with the despotism of Alexander and the more enduring domination of Rome. And at the same time it will set forth the traits of human nature which lie behind these political changes as their cause Republic 544D aud material ; "for States are not things of stock or stone, but depend on the character of the men in them, which drags all else with it whatever THE PLATONIC QUEST 67 way it inclines." Plato, writing when the forces of his people were at ebb, gave only the descend- ing scale of governments, so that his picture to be complete would need to be balanced by a cor- responding study of the ascending scale. It may be objected also that events in this world are not so regular in their progress as he has made them appear; yet it is none the less true that his gen- eralizations from the short and confused annals of Greece are in the main quite amazingly con- firmed by the larger sweep of history, and it is still more sadly true that a reflecting man can scarcely turn from Plato's account of the weak- nesses inherent in the nature of democracy with- out a shudder of apprehension. To take from Plato's broadly composed narrative a few sen- tences indicating the cardinal points of what might be entitled the Tyrant's Progress must necessarily deprive the picture of its symmetrj^ and its power of persuasion, but that is one of the disabilities we have to face in our attempt to dissect what is a living body of thought and no dead logic. The Dialogue itself remains un- touched for those who will read it. Now the just man in Plato's scheme is the aristocrat, he who has his centre of action in the reason, which is the best part of the soul. Such a man may find him- self in a society governed by quite other ideals than his own, a city where contention is rife and the ambition to prevail over others is stronger 68 PLATONISM than the determination to rule over oneself. He will indeed live at peace with his own soul, content to serve the State as best he can for the unseen rewards of justice. But the son, unless by some divine chance he inherit his father's strength of character, will probably be moved by different considerations. The mother, perhaps, will feel herself humiliated because her husband is not dis- tinguished among the magistrates of the city, but lives in quiet contempt of the brawling courts and contentious assemblies, with, it may be, the appearance of indifference to her own feuds and vanities. She will inveigh against this philo- sophical life to her son, and the friends and very servants of the house will join in the complaints, and will urge the boy to go down into the battle and contend with the world's weapons for the prizes that his talents merit. To these exhorta- tions will be added the force of many examples and the voices of the market place, all telling him that those who mind their own business and fol- low too fine a sense of honour, after the manner of his father, are no better than simpletons — "Honour! tut, a breath: There's no such thing in nature ; a mere term Invented to awe fools." Thus the education of the world lays hold of him, and he loses his best guardian, that divine gift of philosophy tempered with the love of pure beauty THE PLATONIC QUEST 69 which alone dweUing in the soul is able to pre- serve it to the uttermost. He becomes a timocrat instead of an aristocrat, a man in whom the glory of success and the name of authority override the simple law of justice and of intrinsic honour. He is no longer ruled by reason, but by undue pre- dominance of the sort of pride that belongs to the thymos, or spirited faculty. To understand the next step it is first neces- sary to note that by oligarchy Plato meant what we are more likely to name plutocracy, that is to say, "a government resting on the valuation of ssoc property, in which all real power is in the hands of the rich." The individual character corre- sponding to this kind of State will arise when the son of a timocrat sees his father suddenly mis- carry in some magnanimous project, striking against the prejudices of the city as a ship foun- ders on a sunken reef, and losing both reputation and authority, perhaps even life. Then the son, observing the insecurity of such a pubUc career, will turn his attention to the more tangible ad- vantages of money, and will devote his energies to the amassing of wealth. He will eject reason and pride from their high places, and on the va- cant throne of his soul will seat the concupiscent and covetous element, to which he will pay hom- age as if it were the Great King himself. In the ordinary transactions of business he will play the game so as, perhaps, to acquire the reputation of 70 PLATONISM honest dealing — that, indeed, is within the scope of his ambition — but observe him when he has got hold of some trust for which he thinks he shall not be made to account, and you will see the rapacity of his nature. He may appear in the eyes of the world a very respectable sort of per- son, but there is no real health in him, nothing of the power and peace of a soul at one with itself. At the best his is but a sordid life, absorbed in the calculation of profit and loss, in which there is lit- tle room for the education of taste or for the pursuit of pleasure in its higher forms. The very absence of finer interests will permit the grovelling and sensual desires to gather strength within him, and these will be kept down only by the one masterful desire of increasing riches. He will be at war with himself, although the prudent element in him will still be in the ascendant. From such a state the transition to the lower stage of democracy is clear and rapid. Suppose the son of one of these money-getters comes into the early possession of wealth without the disci- pline of acquisition: almost certainly he will be imsettled by vain conceits and puflfed up by the flatteries of those who wish to prey upon him. He will be taught to regard modesty as merely simple; to ridicule temperance as unmanly; to despise moderation and thrift as vulgar and il- liberal. Such old-fashioned traits will be thrust rudely out of doors, and into their place will THE PLATONIC QUEST 71 troop all those passions which his father had sup- pressed — insolence and anarchy and waste and shamelessness — rushing in now like revellers flushed with drink and crowned with garlands. All pleasures and desires are the same to him without distinction. He lives from day to day as his appetites impel him, indulging now in wine and lewd luxuries, then drinking water only and dieting; going in now for physical training, then throwing up everything for a spell of listless loafing; making a pretence even of the philo- sophical Ufe, or throwing himself into some po- litical excitement, or trying his luck in some business venture — living always without law or plan or purpose, taking license for liberty and ceaseless distraction for the pursuit of happiness. He is not one man, but many, the fit double of the democratic city.^ Last of all comes the tyrannical man, by an easy change. In the soul of each of us there dwell desires that are innocent and desires that are harmful; even in the good man the evil pro- pensities are not extirpated, but only held in leash. This we can see in ourselves when, after some undue indulgence of appetite, we fall asleep and, in this relaxation of reason and habit, be- ^ It is only fair to add that by democracy Plato meant the license of equalitarianism ; his aristocratic State was really a democracy governing itself by respect for what is best in human nature. 72 PLATONISM come the sport of fantastic and lawless visions. Then sometimes, in om* dreams, the wild beast within us goes forth boldly to slake its lust, and there is no crime, no shameful act of incest or violence or unnatural passion, which it may not commit. Exactly like this is the condition of the tyrannical man. He has been brought up in a democratical family to a perfectly unrestrained life, which the flatterers about him dignify by the name of liberty. His father and true friends still retain some moderation and balance among the desires that draw the heart this way and that, but the baser sort who hang upon him discover the natural bent of his nature, and by humouring this raise it to be imdisputed lord of the household within him, as it were a huge and winged drone in the hive, maddening him with a kind of frenzy to which every lesser impulse is made subordinate. Then indeed License is crowned king, and sits as the disposer of his soul. What he desires, whe- ther his master-passion be for money or women or power, he will have, though it involve the sac- rifice of every other emotion or necessitate any crime against those nearest and dearest to him. He is not a himian being, but a ravenous beast, or resembles a true man only as a man may seem to act in those hours of turbid dreaming when the soul is swept along by visions of abominable lust. Such is the Tyrant's Progress as it is drawn in THE PLATONIC QUEST 73 the eighth and ninth books of The RepubliCj frightful enough in this brief outline, almost over- whelming when read with all the realistic details painted in by the relentless hand of the artist. Question may arise as to the propriety of apply- ing the names "aristocracy," "democracy," and the rest to the different stages of the degenerating State, and indeed the whole subject of Plato's sociology, in the sense of those terms, must, as I have said, be considered by itself. But of the reality of these various conditions in the hfe of society or of the individual, by whatever political names we designate them, there can be no doubt at all. To take the two limits, with which we are the most concerned, as was Plato, we recognize immediately the man whose faculties are each, so to speak, attending to its own business — the man who is wise by the due exercise of reason, temper- ate by the proper control of his appetites, brave and self-respecting by the measured activity of the thymos; and who deals with the world as he deals with himself. And we know equally well the flimsy creature who is tossed about from one unstable passion to another, until he sinks to the still lower stage, when out of the conflict of un- guarded desires one master-passion arises, like the criminal tyrant in a lawless State, to enslave the man's soul and drive him furiously across the rights of others. Well, Plato may now ask, have I not made out 74 PLATONISM the case for Socrates? No one can look at these contrasted portraits of the aristocrat and the ty- rant without granting their veracity, or without saying to himself: "Yes, if this be justice, then the just man is in his own nature happy, and, if this be injustice, then the unjust man is in his own nature miserable. These equations corre- spond with what I have suspected in the lives of other men, and with what is the certain experi- ence of my own life. It is no more possible to escape these conclusions than to deny that phy- sical health means a state of pleasurable existence and disease means pain." This is the last and supreme argumentum ad hominem: It is better to do justice simply and solely because you are happier so doing than otherwise.* Do we seem to have gone a long way round to reach at the last what was all the while near at hand? The conclusion is a commonplace, or to use a fitter term, it is the common sense of man- kind, defended by the weapons of a terrible irony, confirmed by the insight of the man who perhaps saw more clearly than any one before him or af- ter him into the obscure depths of the human heart, and made persuasive by the art of a mas- terly rhetorician. But there is this remarkable fact to observe about a true commonplace in the * Compare the last proposition of Spinoza's Ethics: Beati- tudo non est virtutis praemium, sed ipsa virtus; nee eadem gaudemus, quia libidines coercemus, sed contra quia eadem gaudemus^ ideo libidines coercere possumus. THE PLATONIC QUEST 75 moral order : it passes current in the mouths of all unsophisticated men, yet if you question them about it you are hkely to discover that they can- not explain its meaning, and if you press them closely you may even bring them to deny that it has any meaning. As for the commonplace which forms the goal of the Platonic Quest, it not only has these features of other conmion- places of morality, but it stands at the bifurca- tion of the road where religion and philosophy part company. Religion, though hke philosophy it is really based on the Socratic affirmation, is yet too fearful to rest on this truth alone, and will seek another foundation for its faith in some miraculous event of history or in some revelation from above. So St. Paul argued to the Corinth- ians: "Now if Christ be preached that He rose from the dead, how say some among you that there is no resurrection of the dead?" "And if Christ be not risen, then is our preach- ing vain, and your faith is also vain." "If in this life only we have hope in Christ, we are of all men most miserable." ^ We are of all men most miserable — is not this the very reverse of what Plato thought philo- sophy was to teach when he set forth on his great ^ I Cor, XV, 12, 14, 19. 76 PLATONISM search in The Republic?^ I have not in mind to speak shghtingly of the Christian faith, or of any- genuine faith; I know the sources of reUgious conviction; but when I see the perplexity into which even St. Paul could be thrown by the fear of losing his belief in a particular miraculous event, I appreciate the force of Plato's boast that he alone, with his master, had the courage to rest his faith on the simple common sense of mankind. This is philosophy. Having expounded the meaning of the commonplace that it is better to be just than to be unjust, and having thus given authority to the affirmation of the spirit, philo- sophy does not seek for extraneous proofs of this truth, but proceeds to use it as a principle for investigating the manifold life and activities of the soul. In the Protagoras we reached the goal of the Socratic Quest, when it was shown that the knowledge identified with virtue was the know- ledge needed for the calculation of the conse- ^ With St. Paul's religious fear of scepticism one may compare the great passage of the Apology (40c-41d) in which Socrates states his philosophic faith as confirmed by the daemonic guide and undaunted by doubt: "To die must be one of two things : either the dead are as nothing and have no perception or feeling whatsoever, or else, as many be- lieve, there is a change and migration of the soul from this world to another. . . . And ye too, my judges, ought to be of good hope towards death, being persuaded of this one truth at least, that no evil can befall a good man either in life or in death." THE PLATONIC QUEST 77 quences of any act in the terms of pleasure and pain. It now appears that the Platonic Quest has also brought us to knowledge, but to know- ledge of a different order. To go back to our starting-point in the Charmides, it will be re- membered that Critias suggested a definition of temperance, there the typical virtue, as the do- ing of one's business. To this suggestion Socrates replied that the endeavour to do one's own busi- ness would profit a man little unless he first had some knowledge of what business was really his own. And Critias, accepting the challenge, de- clared that temperance, or any other virtue, did presuppose knowledge, and was, indeed, such knowledge as the God of Delphi impHed in the words "Know thyself," with which he greeted his worshippers in place of the ordinary salutation among men, "Rejoice." One feels, while reading the Charmides, that in Plato's eyes Critias had enounced a great truth, and that his subsequent entanglement by Socrates was owing to his in- abihty to defend dialectically a sound position in- to which he had, so to speak, stumbled blindly. And now, in the appeal of The Republic to the inner experience of the hearer, we learn at last what was meant by connecting morahty with the Delphic salutation. The knowledge commanded by the God is no empty "knowledge of know- ledge," as it became to Critias under the fire of Socrates' questions, but receives a very definite 78 PLATONISM content. To know myself is to be effectively con- scious of this certain fact, that I am happy when I act morally, and, conversely, that I am acting morally so long as I am happy. This knowledge of happiness is not of things future, nor is it, like the knowledge of pleasure, dependent for its authority on a fallible science of calculation; it is immediate and independent. Here, evidently, are two different orders of know- ledge, on both of which our conduct is based, and Plato's philosophy has yet to explain the para- doxical bond between the knowledge which So- crates identified with virtue and the knowledge by which we confirm our spiritual affirmation. CHAPTER IV THE SOCRATIC PARADOX: THE DUALISM OF PLATO The conclusions of The Republic, it will be seen at a glance, are reached by a thoroughgoing dualism. In particular the criterion of happi- ness, whereon, as I think, the whole ethical sys- tem of Plato finally rests, will have no clear meaning for us unless we see how it came to be used by him as something essentially different in kind from pleasure. In the Protagoras we heard Socrates arguing that, whatever else may be open to doubt, all pleasure in itself is certainly good and all pain evil. If on any occasion a man seems to reject a pleasure as evil, this is only because, if admitted, it would deprive him of a greater pleasure or re- sult in an overbalance of pain. Therefore virtue is a science of mensuration applied to pleasure and pain ; when we err in our conduct it is through lack of this kind of knowledge, and the common reproach that a man is overcome by pleasure is no condemnation of pleasure itself, but of the man who is in a state of ignorance regarding the most important matter of life. This is the so-called philosophy of hedonism, 79 80 PLATONISM or, if the phrase is not self-contradictory, indi- vidualistic utilitarianism. It probably, to judge from the way it was carried out in the Cyrenaic and Epicm^ean schools, represents a genuine as- pect of the Socratic attempt to identify virtue and knowledge. But Plato, as we have seen, soon passed beyond that position, if indeed he was ever really satisfied with it. In the Gorgias he introduces Socrates as forcing his opponents to admit a seemingly quahtative difference in pleasures, and in so doing he virtually takes the foundation from under hedonism as a self-suffi- cient scheme of ethics. For the moment you grant a choice among pleasures not determined by the scientific mensuration of more and less, but based upon a qualitative criterion of good and bad, you are far along on the path towards admitting a criterion which is outside of and above pleasures and depends upon a generic dis- tinction between all pleasure properly so-called and a feeling of another order. The ruthlessness with which Plato at first ap- plies this criterion would rather indicate that it was a new discovery with him and had not been in his mind when he wrote the Protagoras, Hav- ing perceived that pleasure, so far from affording the final measure of good, might even be contrary to the good, he seems for a while to have taken pleasure in denigrating pleasure. So, in the Gor- gias, he outruns the requirements of his argu- DUALISM OF PLATO 81 ment in forcing attention upon the disgusting possibilities of a hedonistic standard. Again, in the PhaedOj he recurs more definitely to the 64d ff. theme of the Protagoras, and repudiates its con- clusions in the most vehement language. What are we to think, he asks, of those who, as the popular opinion holds, are brave because they are afraid to be cowards, casting out fear by fear, or of those who are temperate through calculation of future pains, masters of certain pleasures be- cause they are the slaves of other pleasures? No, this is not the real business of morality, to barter pleasures for pleasures and pains against pains, the greater and the less, as if they were pieces of money. But that is the only right currency when we exchange all these things for wisdom and courage and justice, all these pleasures and pains for true virtue. Do you believe for a moment that the philosopher has any serious concern for these baubles that we call pleas- ures? They are but the poor affections of the body, whereas all the study of the philosopher is to escape, so far as mortal man can escape, from the body and its obscure interests into the world of Ideas which are the veritable hfe of the soul. The very intensity of a pleasure may be a hindrance to the soul in her labour of purgation and her search for the truth, since those things that cause us to feel most strongly are apt to seem clearest to us and truest, and so 82 PLATONISM the keenest emotions may be those that bind us most closely to this earth. Every pleasure and every pain is, as it were, a nail that clamps the soul to the body and makes her corporeal, creat- ing the opinion that those things are true which the body affirms, and preventing the soul from passing to the other world in her own purity and power. This is the tone, too, of the MenOy though less poetically coloured, and of parts of The Re- public, and appears to represent Plato's middle period of lyrical revolt. At times he almost ap- proaches the paradoxical enthusiasm of the first CjTiic, who used to avow that he would rather go mad than feel pleasure. But this unmitigated asceticism is a passing phase of Plato's philosophy and does not repre- sent his final judgment of human life. In his later years he was to settle back into a saner at- titude towards the common-sense view, and to recognize that pleasure was not in itself necessar- ily an evil, but mixed with good and bad, and, properly considered, one of the decisive guides of conduct. Much of the Philebus is given up to a dispassionate analysis of pleasure and an en- deavour to determine its relation to knowledge as the highest form of mortal activity. Still later, in the Laws, almost as if in a spirit of recantation for his earlier severity, he descends from his high philosophical scorn to discuss the quotidian uses of pleasure and pain as constituting the practical DUALISM OF PLATO 83 problem of education. These first books of the Laws are so frequently disregarded by writers on Platonism that it will be worth while to dwell at some length on their expression of his ripest and mellowest views. In The Republic Plato had entered upon a dis- cussion of the sort of education suitable for a citizen of the world, but had been turned away from this topic by the allurements of pure philo- sophy. After writing this Dialogue he went through what may be called a metaphysical period, and then, in his closing years, as life be- gan to look less solemn to him, he seems to have felt doubts of the availability of his high morality for the common needs of mankind. And so the talk of the three friends, which forms the matter of his last work, will be "the temperate play of Laws 685a old men amusing themselves in regard to the laws." Instead of a debate on the uncompromis- ing ideals of the philosopher, this Dialogue will deal with the education of the ordinary citizen and the formation of a practical government. The heart of the whole argument is in this no- table passage of the first book: "We should con- 644d sider that each of us as a living creature is but a divine puppet, whether created as a plaything of the gods or in some more serious mood. Of this we are not certain, but we know that the feelings [of pleasure and pain] are the sinews, or cords, that pull us in various directions." Hence the 84 PLATONISM lawgiver who has to study the well-being of so- ciety cannot afford to neglect these motives of action; rather, his first object will be to get them into his own hands so as to be able to form and control the character of his citizens : 653a *'I say, therefore, that pleasure and pain are the original perception of children, and these are the things in which virtue and vice first come to the soul. As for wisdom and settled convictions of truth, fortunate is he to whom they come even in his old age, and he is the perfect man who pos- sesses them with all their blessings. Now the virtue first appearing in children I call their edu- cation. If pleasure and hking, pain and hatred, are rightly implanted in the souls of those who have not yet learned to know them by reason, and if, when reason is added, their souls are in accord with it as to the fact that they have been rightly trained by suitable habits, this harmony is virtue in its completeness ; but the part of virtue that has to do with the right training in pleasures and pains, teaching us to hate what we ought to hate from the beginning of life to the end, and to love what we ought to love, — if we separate this part in our discourse and call it education, we shall in my opinion be using the right name." ^ The point to remember, then, is that to Plato's sober thought pleasure was not in itself a thing ^ I am not at all sure that my translation of this difficult passage is correct in every detail, but the general sense of the Greek is plain enough. DUALISM OF PLATO 85 undesirable, nor yet in any way negligible (such a belief would have been simply inhuman), but was rather the most important matter to be con- sidered in education from the earhest years of childhood. The health of the soul was involved, he thought, in the acquisition of right habits of feeling. At the same time it is clear that this healthy but unreasoning state of virtue ulti- mately was dependent upon something besides the mere difference between pleasure and pain; and, in fact, all through the first books of the Laws the education of youth is placed in the hands of men who have attained "wisdom and settled convictions of truth," and who are able to mould the habits of their pupils by the authority of "virtue in its completeness." The wisdom of these guides is the knowledge, as expressed in the conclusion of The Republic, that as we act mo- rally we are happy; their authority is in the fact that this feeling of happiness is of itself and al- ways good, whereas pleasure is a subordinate feeling, to be controlled finally by a power out- side of itself. In other words, Plato in the Laws has reverted from his temporary rejection of pleasure as intrinsically a snare of evil, but still adheres to his belief in the radical difference be- tween pleasure and happiness, pain and misery.^ ^ I am fully aware of the ambiguity of "happiness" as a translation of Plato's evSaifiovta, but no better term seems to be available. "Eudaemony" is not English. The words 86 PLATONISM This most fundamental distinction of Plato's dualism is alluded to many times in the Dia- 470b logues, notably, and apparently first, in the Gorg- iaSj where Socrates, to the amazement of his hearers, will not admit that the Great King, to whom every possible pleasure is open in the high- est degree, is happy unless he is also just and righteous. In The Republic the same theme is taken up and elaborated in the strongest conceiv- able terms. For the sake of avoiding any mis- understanding two extreme types are isolated and contrasted one with the other. The unjust man is to possess all the pleasures and so-called good things of the world, with unrestricted power to carry out his desires and with no prospect of coming pain to mar his enjoyment. Even be- yond that, he is to have also the reputation of justice, so that the finer pleasures of honour shall fall to him as well as the grosser material plea- sures. With his wealth he can even, as people suppose, make himself acceptable to the gods by the magnificence of his sacrifices. On the other side is set the just man, in his noble simplicity, "felicity" and "blessedness" suggest themselves, but are barred out by their association with a future life. I must beg the reader to divest the word "happiness" of the sense customarily given it in philosophy as meaning no more than a sum of pleasures, and to accept my use of it as signifying a feeling different in kind from pleasure. As a matter of fact this deeper meaning is often unconsciously, or half- consciously, conveyed by the word in ordinary speech. DUALISM OF PLATO 87 the man who, as Aeschylus says, wishes to be and not to seem good. He is to possess his justice alone, without even the reputation of it, but, be- ing the best of men, is to be reputed the worst. Let him be scourged and abused and cruelly tor- tured ; let him know all the pains of existence and none of the pleasures, with no hope of compensa- tion hereafter. Would Socrates dare to affirm that under such conditions the just man is still the happier and the imjust man the more miser- able? And Socrates does not waver. Nor does Plato waver. In the matter of lan- guage he may now and then fall into apparent ambiguities; for it must be remembered always that he had no technical terminology at his com- mand, and employed words pretty much as they came to him. We should not therefore be sur- prised if at times, when the philosophical distinc- tion is not the matter uppermost in his mind, he fails to discriminate sharply between the words pleasure (Jiedone) and happiness (eudaimonia) , or even seems to take the latter consciously, in what was then, as now, its popular use, to mean merely pleasure in its larger and more stable as- pect. There is, for instance, a curious passage of the Laws in which he begins by making the dis- 660e a. tinction clearly, as he had done in the Gorgias and The Republic, and then draws back from his position as if alarmed by its possible conse- quences. If, he says, the just life is not repre- 88 PLATONISM sented as offering also the greater sum of plea- sure, and we force upon men the uncompromis- ing question whether he is the happier who lives the justest life or he who lives the most pleasur- able, why, they will retort upon us by asking what is the profit to your just man from his ex- istence devoid of pleasure. Somehow, therefore, the lawgiver must refrain from separating the pleasurable and the just. He will say that we see these things but dimly, and so they appear differently to different men, just things appear- ing pleasant to the just man and unjust things unpleasant, but contrariwise to the unjust man. Now the judgment of the just man we must sup- pose to be more valid than that of the unjust man, and our task will be to make his judgment pre- vail as a criterion of pleasures. Such a conclu- sion might seem to carry us back to the aban- doned position of the Protagoras; yet even here a phrase slips in which shows that Plato was merely arguing on a lower plane for practical purposes. This belief that the balance of plea- sure belongs to righteousness is perhaps only a 663d salutary illusion, he says, which the cunning law- giver can implant in the minds of the young, sim- ilar to the myths of the gods with which religion is bound up in the popular creed. Plato, in other words, was here writing for practical men and making his appeal to the ordinary intelligence. He saw that for such minds it would be useless, DUALISM OF PLATO 89 if not actually prejudicial, to present his thesis in the absolute terms of philosophy; just as the preacher today who is engaged in the cure of souls would probably succeed only in rendering relig- ion fantastic or repugnant to sober people of the world by describing the agonies of a martyr at the stake and trying to make his audience reaHze that it is possible amid such torture to die in an ecstasy of happiness. Such a preacher would be proclaiming a psychological fact, but it is doubt- ful whether his words would be for edification. So, I take it, there is a certain philosophical "economy" here and there in the language of the Laws; possibly, too, Plato's own naked convic- tion seemed to him in his later years, not less true, but less urgent for the common need of mankind. However that be, one thing is indubitable: he who has not grasped this distinction in kind be- tween happiness and pleasure will wander in the labyrinth of Plato's Dialogues with no clue to guide him. He may admire their various beauties and their infinite riches, but they will be to him a maze without ultimate plan or exit. This dualism of feeling, as I have said before and must say again, is the great discovery of Plato; its vital importance is proved by the course of philosophy among writers of the mod- em world who have forgotten it or tried in one way and another to avoid it. Certainly the his- tory of ethical theory ought to estabHsh one fact 90 PLATONISM incontestably : no doctrine can speak with the per- emptory voice of truth which eschews all forms of reward and penalty. No statement of a cate- gorical imperative, no trust in an innate sense of duty, no exhortation to the love of God or of man, will avail against the temptations of the world unless the admonition bears with it the promise of satisfying what all men instinctively crave. The heart of man naturally demands pleasure or happiness, and will not forgo its de- mand.^ On the other hand those who have understood this trait of human nature, without admitting, tacitly it may be, the radical dualism of pleasure and happiness, have fallen invariably into one of two difficulties: either they have sunk into a de- grading form of Epicureanism, or, shunning this error, they have lost themselves in the pursuit of elusive shadows. These difficulties are abund- antly evident in the development of English utilitarianism. The strength of Bentham's sys- tem — and it had undoubted strength — lay in his steady perception of the relation between the practice and the reward of virtue. But his purely quantitative standard of pleasures left out of the account too large a part of human nature to sat- isfy the finer minds even among his followers. ^ Those who think that happiness is omitted from the Buddhist scheme of salvation have strangely misread the books or, more probably, have not read them at all. DUALISM OF PLATO 91 So we see John Stuart Mill endeavouring to abide by the half-truth of utilitarianism while giving to it a colour and a tone which should raise it out of the sty. "When thus attacked," he says, "the Epicureans have always answered, that it is not they, but their accusers, who represent human nature in a degrading light ; since the ac- cusation supposes human beings to be capable of no pleasures except those of which swine are capable. ... It must be admitted, however, that utilitarian writers in general have placed the su- periority of mental over bodily pleasures chiefly in the greater permanency, safety, uncostliness, &c., of the former — that is, in their circumstantial advantages rather than in their intrinsic nature. And on all these points utilitarians have fully proved their case ; but they might have taken the other, and, as it may be called, higher ground, with entire consistency. It is quite compatible with the principle of utility to recognize the fact, that some kinds of pleasure are more desirable and more valuable than others. It would be ab- surd that while, in estimating all other things, quality is considered as well as quantity, the esti- mation of pleasures should be supposed to depend on quantity alone." ^ Bentham had recognized no difference at all between pleasure and happiness. Mill, by his addition of a qualitative standard, was really * Utilitarianism, Chap. ii. 92 PLATONISM feeling his way towards a standard of morality above pleasure, while still verbally denying the existence of such a standard.^ He is the example ^ Surely there is no consistency, but inconsistency, in the two members of Mill's sentence : "On all these points utili- tarians have fully proved their case; but they might have taken the other, and, as it might be called, higher ground, with entire consistency." If the utilitarians are right in making "permanency, safety," etc. the standard of value and desirability among pleasures, what is the need or mean- ing of another, qualitative standard.^ — I admit freely that this question of a qualitative and quantitative standard of pleasures is extremely subtle, and for its complete answer, in accordance with the Platonic philosophy, should be de- ferred until after the consideration of Plato's psychology and cosmology. A qualitative standard would seem to rest on the difference between the sensation of pleasure in the fulfilment of physical desires (the IttiOvixyitlkov') and the emotion of pleasure in the satisfaction of personal desires (the 6v/i6<;)f between, that is, such a sensation as that which accompanies the quenching of thirst and such an emotion as that which accompanies the satisfaction of pride or vanity. But the consistent utilitarian would maintain that the difference here is still really quantitative, and so com- mensurable, being measured by permanency, etc., as well as by intensity ; and he would argue that the personal emotions are more considerable than the physical sensations by a true quantitative standard. I am inclined to think that the utili- tarian has proved, or could prove, his case. If this double quantitative standard of intensity and of permanency is re- ferred to the cosmological dualism of the one and the many, the immutable and the flux, it will be seen that pleasure, as a momentarily shifting sensation, tends to commingle itself with pain, and, as an unchecked distraction moving in the direction of the flux, must be so far adjudged evil. It becomes good on the contrary only in so far as it subserves the more stable part of our personal self. Meanwhile there DUALISM OF PLATO 93 par excellence of a philosopher who combines the most lucid powers of exposition with an incapa- city of clear thinking. The entanglement of Mill and the later utihtarians was patent to T. H. Green, who sought a way of escape by saving de- sire as a motive of action while changing the ob- ject of desire. To this end he sets up a distinc- tion between pleasure and what he calls "self- satisfaction," and argues that the object of our desire is not pleasure or even the pleasure of self- satisfaction, but is this self-satisfaction for its own sake, while pleasure, if it comes, is a mere contin- gent effect. By this analysis of the object of de- sire he thinks he has pointed to the source of Mill's confusion and has estabhshed a criterion of val- ues superior to pleasure. Now many of Green's pages devoted to the elucidation and expansion of his idea of self-satisfaction are rich with the burden of history, and there is a hearty kernel of truth in his argument. But there are two fatal weaknesses. In the first place Green's notion that 5^Z/-satisf action may consist in the sacrifice of the individual's well-being for the well-being of so- ciety is only Bentham's old fallacy, decked out in new terms, of supposing that we can appeal to pleasure as the motive of conduct and then avoid can be no harm, I think, in speaking of the admission of a seemingly qualitative difference in pleasures as a step towards recognizing the fundamental distinction between pleasure and happiness. 94 PLATONISM the egotistic consequences of such a creed by merging pleasure in the greatest happiness (as the utihtarians use the word) of the greatest number. And, secondly, Green is blind to the fact that, by rejecting pleasure as his motive yet failing to find the criterion of self-satisfaction in happiness as a feeling distinct in kind from pleasure, he leaves his standard of self-satisfac- tion — so long as he writes consistently — without verifiable meaning or content. Take one of his typical sections: . . . "To the question. What is the well-being which in a calm hour we desire but a succession of pleasures? we reply as follows. The ground of this desire is a demand for an abiding satisfac- tion of an abiding self. In a succession of plea- sures there can be no such satisfaction, nor in the longest prolongation of the succession any nearer approach to it than in the first pleasure enjoyed. If a man, therefore, under the influence of the spiritual demand described, were to seek any suc- cession of pleasures as that which would satisfy the demand, he would be under a delusion. Such a delusion may be possible, but we are not to sup- pose that it takes place because many persons, through a mistaken analysis of their inner ex- perience, affirm that they have no idea of well- being but as a succession of pleasures."^ How often, while reading such passages as ® Prolegomena § 234. DUALISM OF PLATO 95 these, we feel that Green is on the verge of mak- ing the great discovery made by Plato so long ago, but is held back by the age-old fallacy of regarding happiness, or whatever you choose to call it, as nothing more than a succession or con- summation of pleasures! What vain circumlo- cutions his noble spirit would have been spared, and what hair-sphtting subtleties of argument, if he had been able to say in simple, straightfor- ward language, "This self-satisfaction or well- being which I am trying so hard to offer as a substitute for the unsatisfaction of pleasure is just the happiness that every man has felt and may understand"!^ No, mankind craves happiness; it can be weaned from the seduction of false pleasures only by this possession which is so like pleasure yet greater and essentially other than pleasure, and it will be diverted by no empty promises or threats. The whole religious hterature of the world, truer in its candid reliance on the intui- tive knowledge of the soul than are the rebeUious searchings of the schools, is replete with appeals to our consciousness of the difference between pleasure and the rapture, or peace, or happiness — the word is nought but the fact is everything — ^ The distinction between pleasure and happiness is im- plicit in such passages of the Prolegomena as §§ 228^ 238; but it is never defined or brought out into the light^ and for the most part Green accepts happiness in the utilitarian sense as the sum of pleasures. 96 PLATONISM of obedience to a higher law than our personal or physical desires. I could cover many pages with passages to this effect; a single quotation from one of the older of our English divines, the length of which may be excused by the impor- tance of the topic, will suffice : "That joy should be enjoined, that sadness should be prohibited, may it not be a plausible exception against such a precept, that it is super- fluous and needless, seeing all the endeavours of men do aim at nothing else but to procure joy and eschew sorrow; seeing all men do conspire in opinion with Solomon, that a man hath nothing better under the sun than — to he merry, "It is true that men, after a confused manner, are very eager in the quest, and earnest in the pursuit of joy; they rove through all the forests of creatures, and beat every bush of nature for it, hoping to catch it either in natural endow- ments and improvements of soul, or in the gifts of fortune, or in the acquists of industry ; in tem- poral possessions, in sensual enjoyments, in ludi- crous divertisements and amusements of fancy; so each in his way doth incessantly prog for joy; but all much in vain, or without any considerable success ; finding at most, instead of it, some faint shadows, or transitory flashes of pleasure, the which, depending on causes very contingent and mutable, residing in a frail temper of fluid hu- mours of the body, consisting in slight touches upon the organs of sense, in frisks of the corpor- DUALISM OF PLATO 97 eai spirits or in fumes and vapours twitching the imagination, do soon flag and expire. "Wherefore there is ground more than enough, that we should be put to seek for a true, substan- tial, and consistent joy. It is a scandalous mis- prision, vulgarly admitted, concerning religion, that it is altogether sullen and sour. Such, in- deed, is the transcendent goodness of our God, that he maketh our delight to be our duty, and our sorrow to be our sin, adapting his holy will to our principal instinct; that he would have us to resemble himself, as in all other perfections, so in a constant state of happiness. Indeed, to exercise piety and to rejoice are the same things, or things so interwoven that nothing can disjoin them."« It is the honour of Plato that he held fast to this fundamental truth of religion, while basing it on the immediate intuition of the mind, with- out necessary recourse to the problematical re- wards and penalties of another state of existence. This is the beginning of Plato's dualism, but not the end. If happiness and pleasure are dis- tinct feelings, it will follow that the activities they accompany, or the motives of our activity, are likewise distinguished in kind. We are brought back to that troublesome and recurring question of the early Dialogues as to the identity or sep- arateness of the virtues. Somehow it appeared ^ From the forty-third sermon of Isaac Barrow^ with omissions. 98 PLATONISM there, as we took up bravery and temperance and holiness in turn, that they all had a tendency to run together into one supreme virtue; yet, as soon as we reached this point, invariably the par- ticular virtue under discussion lost its concrete value, and we were left with an empty word on our hands which had no significance for solving the specific problems of life. Now, if we return to these unanswered puzzles after considering Plato's later Dialogues, we shall see that the dif- ficulty lay in the ambiguity of the word "virtue" {arete), which is used for two quite different things. For our own convenience, therefore, we will henceforth make a distinction in language which Plato himself never made, by using differ- ent translations for the same word to denote a distinction in fact which he did make. So far as possible we will reserve the word "virtue" for the art of living, for right conduct, that is, as manifested in specific spheres of activity, and will adopt the word "morality" for the higher unity in which the particular virtues seemed to have a way of losing themselves. It is not easy to decide how fully Plato him- self in his earlier Dialogues was aware of this dis- tinction which later becomes so important to his ethical system. In the Protagoras it is latent. We can see it growing clearer in the Phaedo and the Meno, though it is there still only implicit. In The Republic the distinction is something DUALISM OF PLATO 99 ' more than implied by the separate treatment of I the group of virtues — wisdom, bravery, temper- ! ance — on the one hand and of justice on the other. Wisdom is the right action of our reason, brav- ery of the thymos, and temperance of the desires. These are the specific virtues. Justice is the com- ■ pelling and governing force behind all these ■ forms of activity, the healthy balance of the soul j as a whole and its right energy as a unit. This \ distinction between morality as the central gov- j erning force and the virtues as specific forms of \ activity is brought out even more clearly in the j Politicus, where it is shown that the specific 306a s. j virtues, or perhaps we should say the tendencies that create them, may come, if left to them- selves, into actual conflict one with another. Thus, for example, bravery and temperance \ are not only different one from the other, but ; may take hostile sides in the soul of a man \ or in a State. Bravery, in so far as it is the quality of a temperament quick and virile by j nature, is apt, if unrestrained, to run into im- j petuosity and insolence; whereas temperance, as j it is found in a disposition inclined to slowness | and quiet, may very easily sink into sloth and i cowardliness. These temperaments and virtues \ manifest themselves in two classes of men who | may divide a city into factious parties (Plato j would say today into radicals and conserva- ! tives), and whom it is the art of the true states- 100 PLATONISM man to reconcile in friendly co-operation for the common good. Though Plato does not here draw the parallel out in so many words, it is every- where implied that this royal art {basilike techne) of the governing statesman is but an- other name for justice, equivalent to the moral principle that in the individual soul resides above the various activities, and governs and harmo- nizes the specific virtues. But for the final exposition of this, as of so many other doctrines, we must turn to the book Laws 963a ff of Plato's old agc. All our laws, he says at the conclusion of that long treatise, must be con- trolled by some one purpose. As the physician has a definite end in view, the preservation of health, to which all his activities are directed, and as the pilot has a definite task, so it must be with the statesman, or lawgiver. The aim of the statesman is the creation and preservation of vir- tue in the State ; and as his aim is thus not many, but one, so the virtues which have appeared to us all along as fourfold must also in some way be one virtue, or subordinate to some one moral pur- pose. It was easy to see what was meant by the special virtue of bravery ; it is a manner of facing things fearful. The nature of wisdom, too, is clear; it is a kind of prudence in the choice and use of means. And in the same way we imder- stand temperance and justice. But what is the character of the moral force in subservience to DUALISM OF PLATO 101 which these various virtues are united? It is a kind of wisdom — ^not prudence, but the mind, or intelligence — ^working in him who is able not only to discern the many different activities of life but to look beyond them ; the divine vision of him who, whatever may be the field of observation, is able to behold the changeless law above all change. It is the knowledge, rehgiously speaking, of the gods, that they are and that they govern the world by a beneficent design. There are two ways by which we may approach this supreme knowledge: one by the soul's perception of her own nature, that she is the oldest and most divine of existing things, lord of the body by right of age and dignity; the other by the perception of the ordered motion of the stars and of all created objects that display the governance of an omnis- cient intelUgence; and these two ways are virtu- ally one. He will be a true worshipper of the gods who has attained to this knowledge of the soul's hegemony and of the indwelUng reason of the imiverse. He alone possesses that saving moraUty {arete soterias) which fits him to be the 969c ruler of himself and of the State.^ ^ Philo Judaeus, in his Legum Allegoria (1, 63 ff.) has a quaint comparison of the dperr] yeviK-ri, as he calls the super-virtue, and the four dperal Kara fxipos with the river that went out of Eden to water the garden, and from thence was parted, and became into four heads. The doc- trine is Stoic as well as Platonic. See, for instance, Sto- baeus, Ethica VI, i. 102 PLATONISM Such, freely and succinctly rendered, but I think not misinterpreted, is the ethical position of Plato in the conclusion of the Laws and at the end of his life. Substantially it is the same as the doctrine of The Republic, though the termin- ology is different. In both Dialogues there are four virtues, one of which is taken — with some confusion of thought, it must be admitted — now as parallel with the others, and now as distinct from them by reason of its quality of leadership and comprehensiveness. The Republic gave the double function to justice; in the Laws justice tends to be limited to the political virtue of right distribution, whereas the moral leadership is transferred to the reason, in such a way that wis- dom is treated both as one of the four cardinal virtues and as the queen over them all. Evi- dently this ambiguous position of wisdom is ex- plained by the fact that we are dealing with two kinds of knowledge, and points to a further dual- ism of Plato's philosophy. Along with the question of the unity and di- versity of the virtues there ran through all the early Dialogues another problem, which was left in an equally unsettled state. The morality, or super-virtue, into which the specific virtues had a fashion of merging and so escaping our search, was always some kind of wisdom or knowledge. Bravery, so soon as it became a desirable quality and no mere impetuosity of temper, involved a DUALISM OF PLATO 103 knowledge of what things are properly to be feared and what are not. Temperance was meaningless until we acquired an understanding of ourselves and of what was good for us. It would follow that, if all these forms of virtue rest on a body of knowledge, they ought to be teach- able, like medicine or any other art ; yet in prac- tice there seem to be no teachers to whom a man can go to learn morality as he can go to a physi- cian to learn medicine. This paradox reached its climax in the Protagoras, where Socrates argued that theoretically all the virtues are knowledge yet practically are not teachable, while his an- tagonist held that the virtues have each their indi- vidual character apart from knowledge yet can be taught. It now appears that this paradox lay in the ambiguity of a word ; and in the later Dialogues, whatever may be said of the other aspects of Plato's philosophy, the double character of the relation of the mind to facts is brought out with a precision and dwelt on with a persistence which leave no doubt of his fundamental dualism. In The Republic the distinction is represented pic- torially by the bifurcated Mne, separating know- ledge proper from what is properly called opin- ion ; and thereafter these two terms are employed regularly for the two processes that caused the earlier ambiguity. The full bearing of this ter- minology on Plato's system must be left for an- 104 PLATONISM other chapter. Here the point to observe is that the primary motive for making the distinction is rather ethical than metaphysical, as may be seen from the trend of the argument in the Theaetetus. 163A The avowed purpose of this Dialogue is to de- termine whether knowledge and perception {episteme and aisthesis) are the same thing or different things; to discover, that is, whether we have any fixed and certain form of knowledge. But this thesis soon becomes involved with the subsidiary questions whether all things are in a state of flux and whether man is the measure of l^^^ all things. Twice at least these three problems are brought together quite definitely, but for the most part the discussion passes from one to an- other of them after the rather disconcerting man- ner sometimes adopted by Plato. The best clue to guide the reader through this labyrinth is a sense of what was the dominating interest in the author's mind; nor is this interest hard to dis- cover. Here, as almost everywhere in Plato, the bias is ethical ; the real animus of the Dialogue is i57d the desire to demolish the belief, shared by the sophists with their audiences, that there is no certain reality behind our sense of the good and the beautiful. And so, in a way, the process of proving is inverted ; if this stronghold of popular unreason is undermined, then the answers to the three troublesome questions will follow of them- selves. If you grant the existence of a principle DUALISM OF PLATO 105 of goodness, fixed and immutable, then there is a standard of values fixed, there is something be- sides the flux, there is a knowledge superior to that depending on outer perception (which Plato will grant to the flux), and man, in the Prota- gorean sense, is not the measure of all things. To this end the arch-sophist Protagoras is brought to the bar, and under the cross-question- ing of Socrates is forced to admit the inclusion of a standard of "better" and "worse" in our judg- ments. But, while making this admission, he still clings to his dogma that man (that is, al- ways, man as a creature totally immersed in the flux) is the measure of all things; he still main- tains that as things seem just and beautiful to i67c each State, such they are as long as the State so judges them. Socrates retorts with the argu- ment that, if there is no objective and fixed re- ality in the moral world, no standard by which the degrees of better and worse can be deter- mined, then the use of such words as "just" and "beautiful" is perfectly meaningless — a conclu- sion against which our coromon sense revolts im- placably. Furthermore, though a man may as- sert that the just is whatever a State regards as better for itself in the sense of being more profit- able, yet no one will say, unless he is merely amusing himself with words, that whatever a State regards as profitable, and so establishes as i77d the law of justice, will necessarily turn out to 106 PLATONISM be profitable in the event. This introduces the question of the future, and shows that at least the profitable is not measured by the present opin- ions of men (in other words, that to this extent man is not the measure), and that probably the justice which the sophists are so fond of connect- ing with profit may also be something uncon- trolled by opinion — something about which it very much behoves a man to get not opinion but knowledge. But is there any such thing as knowledge? How shall we take it as a guide unless we know what it is ? Plato has no answer to this question put as a problem of epistemology. We cannot, 209E he declares, get at a knowledge of what know- ledge is by analysing the process of knowing, for the reason that this analysis implies knowledge of the parts, and so on ad infinitum. And again 196D he asks, as might be asked of any one, ancient or modern, who thinks the tantalizing problem of epistemology has been solved, whether perhaps it was not a bit impudent ever to have supposed they were going to define the process of knowing when they did not know what knowledge is.^^ It is characteristic of Plato, however, that he does not deny the possibility of defining knowledge in the terms of the intellect, but only confesses the ^^ For Plato's scepticism in regard to epistemology see also Charmides 169a. DUALISM OF PLATO 107 failure on this occasion to reach such a definition. He will not step beyond the bounds of Socratic scepticism: so far, he says, using Socrates as his 210c mouthpiece, and no further my art prevails, to clarify the mind of the docile listener and make him more agreeable to his friends. But with this sceptical outcome as regards the avowed epistemological issue, the Dialogue con- tains two statements, one dropped casually by the way, the other uttered with all the impressive- ness at Plato's command, which permit us to see what positive answer Plato had in reserve. The former occurs in connection with a rather whim- 202B sical account of the aboriginal irrational elements underlying phenomena, which can be named but of which nothing can be predicated, and suggests that there may be similar elements of sensation in the soul, in regard to which the soul may be in a state of truth, although it cannot be said to know them, since knowledge comes only with rational discourse. ^^ The other, and more ex- plicit, statement is made in the digression on the i76b ^^ This passage of the Theaetetus is, I admits obscure. My interpretation of it would be confirmed by a sentence of the Philebus (66c), as read by Ficino: HifiTrrat tolvvv, as ^ySovas Wefxev dXvTrov? opKra/xevoi, Kadapa.<: «7rovo/w-acrai/TCs t^S ^v)(rj<; avTrj<; €Tn(rTrj/jLasy rats Be ala-Oya-ea-LV €7rofX€vas — puras nominantes animae ipsius scientias, sensus autem sequentes. But however this passage of the Theaetetus be taken, there is no possibility of misunderstanding the words in which Plato affirms the reality of the superrational intuition. 108 PLATONISM philosophic Hfe, which, to one not familiar with Plato's indirect methods, might appear to be strangely out of place in the heart of this Dia- logue. Our only refuge from the evils of this world, says Socrates, is to render ourselves like unto God. In him there is no injustice, no shadow of wrong, but, as we conceive things, purest jus- tice; and there is nothing that more resembles God than he among us who becomes as just as it is possible for man to be. The knowledge (gnosis J superrational intuition) of this truth is wisdom and morality, and the ignorance of this truth is folly and manifest evil; and all other seeming wisdom is comparatively a vulgar and mean thing. The Theaetetus, so analysed, bears throughout on the question now imder consideration. Leav- ing aside as doubtful and, for the present pur- pose, relatively unimportant the suggestion of an infrarational intuition of immediate sensation, we have these two conclusions: an admission of the practical impossibility of discovering any defi- nition of knowledge regarded as the relation of human reason to objective facts, and an affirma- tion of the higher intuition, which is above reason and is true knowledge. The gist of the argument is the opposition between the Platonic dualism of knowledge and opinion and the Protagorean (and, in general, the sophistic) monism. Plato does not deny that men move about in a world of DUALISM OF PLATO 109 shifting impressions, and are constrained to base their conduct on judgments drawn from observa- tion of facts which never can be complete ; in our practical life, so far as it is concerned with phe- nomena, we have only the guidance of opinion. To this extent he agrees with Protagoras, though even here he draws ethical conclusions very dif- ferent from those of the sophist ; but he does deny flatly the Protagorean dogma that this shadowy form of opinion is all we have. Were Protago- ras right he might have referred to a tadpole or a uu pig as Well as to a man for his measure. No, Plato asserts, besides opinion, whether true or false, man has also knowledge. The operation of this faculty we may not be able to analyse, but it is there, within our souls, giving us certain in- formation of the everlasting reality of righteous- ness and loveliness in themselves, as things apart from the flux, and bidding us look to the God of these realities for the measure of our nature. Now, in this duahsm of knowledge and opinion is found the answer to the paradoxical question as to the teachableness of virtue. Morality, as the force behind the specific virtues, is a matter of knowledge, whereas the specific virtues are de- pendent on what is commonly called knowledge but is really opinion ; and opinion can be formed by instruction, whereas knowledge cannot be. Thus, the virtue of temperance may be described as a golden mean in our action, a result of obe- 110 PLATONISM dience to the precept "Nothing too much," which announces to each urgent desire: So far shalt thou go and no further. If, for example, we eat a certain amount and kind of food (and no chance intervene), we shall be healthy and enjoy the pleasure of health; if we transgress through ig- norance or wilfulness, we shall surely injure our health and suffer the pains of disease. And so it is with all the other activities of life, under which- ever of the specific virtues they may fall. Our judgment of the point at which any activity ceases to be a virtue and becomes a vice is deter- mined by a calculation of consequences in plea- sure and pain, and the rightness or wrongness of our calculation will depend on our own exper- ience and on the similar experience of others. The experience of others is imparted to us by in- struction, and so it is that the specific virtues are teachable; we can go to a man of experience to learn the nature of temperance and bravery and wisdom and justice, as we can go to a physician to learn the precepts of his art. Hence the weight which Plato lays on the edu- cation of youth in the choice and control of pleasures and pains. In the average and in the long run the man so trained, having the tradi- tion of society to correct his own narrower ex- perience, will act instinctively on a proper calcu- lation. But it is to be noted that this trained in- stinct, though the only guide we have in our DUALISM OF PLATO 111 specific acts, casts no more than a flickering light. Thus, bravery, when it rises to the dignity of a virtue, is determined by a man's opinion of what should be feared and what should not, and of the extent to which he should give rein to his im- pulses of hostility and self-defence. It is a reck- oning of the balance of pleasure consequent upon his own safety and upon the rewards of public esteem. But our judgment can never be infalli- ble in such matters : any man, by an error of cal- culation, may attack where true bravery would have counselled retreat, or may retreat where true bravery would have counselled attack. The outcome, moreover, is subject to hazards beyond the scope of his consideration. In an attack which from the point of view of his company is prudent, he may be the one who falls into the hands of the enemy: and he may suffer torture and death in such a way that his act of true cour- age may end, so far as he personally is concerned, in pain, and no pleasure at all. At the best, though we have an immediate intuition of plea- sure and pain as present realities, as soon as we begin to calculate consequences in order to act, our judgment can be verified only eoc post facto, and the virtues cannot be raised out of the region of uncertain opinion. This treachery of calculation is what tends to drag the hedonist down to the sty, bidding him distrust the more elusive rewards of virtue and 112 PLATONISM lay hold of any pleasure near at hand whose pun- ishment is not swift and visible. If there be any steady law of conduct it must be referred to a principle freed from the chances of fortune and so fortified against the immediate cravings of appetite. For this principle, as we have seen, Plato turned to the moral impulsion behind the specific virtues. In the Laws he identified it with wisdom, but with a wisdom drawn from the soul's knowledge of herself as divine and akin to God, a wisdom quite different from the virtue identi- cal with a calculating prudence. In The Repub- lic the same moral impulsion was called justice; but there again justice was so defined as to be synonymous with a form of knowledge; it was the intuition commanded in the Delphic saluta- tion "Know thyself," as the virtues are taught in the other Delphic precept, "Nothing too much." And this higher knowledge, as we have also seen, is not vague or empty of content, but rich with fruition. It, too, is concerned with a state of feeling — ^not those pleasures, in which the opin- ions of virtue have their range, but the happiness present in the soul with the purpose to act virtu- ously and dependent on the purpose alone. No man can impart this knowledge to us, though he may exhort us to look more intently into the na- ture of our being ; the knowledge of the happiness of morality is not teachable, but comes to each of us secretly, by what Plato, speaking mythologic- ally, caUs a "divine chance." DUALISM OF PLATO 113 I would not for a moment maintain that no difficulties adhere to this dualism, partly implicit and partly exphcit in the philosophy of Plato, which sets pleasure, virtue, and opinion in one group, and over against them happiness, moral- ity, and knowledge. We are here, let us admit frankly, in the region of paradox. Indeed dual- ism is but another name for that Socratic Para- dox which results from accepting simultaneously both the spiritual affirmation of Socrates and his identification of virtue with knowledge (that is, with opinion, as something distinct from the knowledge of the spirit). It is of the nature of the dualistic intuition that it cannot be ultimately explained by reason, but we can perhaps make its operation clearer by an illustration. When Socrates lay in prison, awaiting the day of execution, he was visited by one of his power- ful friends, Crito, who pressed money upon him to bribe his way out and so to escape an unfair doom. Socrates' reply is given in the Dialogue that goes by the name of his friend. The conver- sation turns on two main theses. First Socrates asks Crito whether he still abides by their old de- cision of former days, that it is better, no matter what the circumstances may be, to do justice than to do injustice, better to suffer injustice patient- ly, if needs be, than to do wrong in return? To this thesis Crito is committed, and he will not now draw back. And note that there is no real dis- 114 PLATONISM cussion here, but a direct appeal to the moral in- tuition; for, as Socrates declares, between one who assents to this affirmation of the spirit and one who dissents there is no common ground of debate, but each necessarily will look with con- tempt on the views of the other. Then fol- lows the question: What is the right course of conduct for me, Socrates, under the particular circumstances in which I am now placed? How shall I do justice? This is not a matter of intui- tion, to be settled by an affirmation, but a point to be argued out and decided on its merits, like any other specific case of virtue. And what is the argument? In the first place Socrates re- peats the statement of the Apology, that we have no certain knowledge of death whether it be a good thing for man or an evil thing. So far the principle of scepticism rules. But men have learned by experience that it is a good thing for a city to be governed by laws ; since then only is order possible, and that like-mindedness of citi- zens on which hang all the strength and blessings of civilization. By our very birth and education and volimtary residence in a city we have entered into a kind of contract with it, and we ought either to submit to the laws as they are or to bring about the passage of other laws. That is what men mean by justice, that we should obey the behests of the city or persuade it to think other- wise ; and, in view of our ignorance of death and DUALISM OF PLATO 115 money and so many other things of the sort that seem to people to affect their personal welfare, the pursuit of justice is probably the best calcu- lation of pleasures a man can make. Moreover, by obedience to the laws of men we shall put our- selves into harmony with the spirit of law in gen- eral, and with the peaceful and orderly move- ment of the universe. Therefore, Socrates rea- sons, it is better for me to stay here where I am, and to abide by the voice of the laws of Athens. Now, in this discussion of law and duty So- crates says not a word which would not have been accepted by John Stuart Mill. Wherein, then, is the difference between Socrates' position and that of a high-minded utihtarian? A¥hen it comes to the decision of a particular case, they argue and decide alike ; both reach the same defi- nition of what is just, and both say that this deci- sion must be followed at the risk of losing money and comfort and even hfe itself. So far they agree, but at this point they part company, and their ways are in opposite directions. To Mill there was nothing beyond the decision, nothing (in his philosophy taken literally, that is, for in his character he was inconsistent) to give vahdity to the decision of virtue when it might be weak- ened by doubts. For, after all, any such calcula- tion as this made by Socrates, and as would be made by Mill, is in the region of guessing ; unless it can be reinforced by some surer intuition, it 116 PLATONISM will yield to men in general only a treacherous foundation for conduct, and this enforcing power of intuition is precisely what Socrates had and what utilitarianism lacks. Suppose there was an error in the reasoning of Socrates when he re- fused the opportunity, as Crito says, not only to carry on a life of virtue but to provide for the proper training of his children — suppose Crito was right and Socrates was wrong (as the case might well be) , what recompense was there for a man who sacrificed himself for an empty name? And without the assurance of some criterion other than the very fallible calculations of reason and the conflicting precepts of tradition, from what source was a man in Socrates' position to draw the strength of character that should with- stand the temptations of the nearer pleasure? There is no such resource in the philosophy of hedonism. But Socrates did not waver. He knew that it was better to do justice than to do injustice, not because justice would probably bring to him the larger pleasure as a man living in a city and universe of law (though this too he guessed) , but because the very intention of doing justice certainly brought its sufficient reward. The feeling of happiness associated with moral purpose was so much more real to him than were the stings of pleasure and pain that, under its compulsion, he could afford to laugh at the doubts which might weaken his loyalty to ap- DUALISM OF PLATO 117 parent virtue by contrasting the security of im- mediate pleasure with the insecurity of a long calculation, and by pitting the intensity of per- sonal desires against the duller sense of partici- pating in the public good. Fortunately for the world the conmion sense of mankind is more in conformity with a hedon- ism complemented, as it was in Socrates, by in- tuition and scepticism, than with a hedonism that thinks it unnecessary to look for any guide be- yond the hght of its own tremulous lamp. CHAPTER V PSYCHOLOGY Plato's ethical philosophy is connected, as any system of ethics must be connected, with a par- ticular way of regarding the soul. Its end is in psychology, and we are thus brought face to face with a problem of consistency : the soul under his analysis fell into three faculties (if we may use this word without its modern psychological impli- cations), yet his ethics is essentially dualistic. How are these two positions to be reconciled? The apparent discrepancy of Plato's philo- sophy in this matter has troubled more than one of the commentators on The Republic, In a 602c note on a critical passage of the tenth book James Adam has these significant words : "The reasoning from here to 607a has been supposed to rest on a psychological theory irre- concilable with that of Book iv, to which the dis- cussion expressly alludes (in 602e). See for ex- ample Krohn PI, St, p. 255 and Pfleiderer Zur Losung etc. p. 38. It is true that Plato is here content, in view of his immediate purpose, with a twofold division of the soul into (1) a rational and (2) an irrational, alogiston (604d, 605b), or lower element. But the resemblance between the two theories is greater than the dif- 118 PSYCHOLOGY 119 ference, for (a) the logistikon is common to both, and (b) on its moral side the irrational element appears sometimes as the e pithy metikon (606d), sometimes as a degenerate form of the thymo- eides (604e, 606a)." The point is well taken, and is enforced chiefly by the characterization of the good man under the stress of adversity. "There is," says Plato, 604a "a principle of reason and law in him which com- mands him to resist, and there is hkewise the sense of his misfortmie which is forcing him to indulge his sorrow. But when a man is drawn in contrary directions at once in regard to the same object, we say that there must be two elements in him. The law affirms that to be patient under suffering is best, and that we should not give way to impatience, since in fact it is not clear whether our state is good or evil, and anyhow nothing is gained by resentment ; none of the events of hu- man Uf e is of serious importance, and grief stands in the way of that state which we need to attain as speedily as possible. Then there is the other principle, which inclines us to recollection of our troubles and to lamentations, and can never have enough of them; this we may call irrational, fu- tile, and cowardly." Such a description admits of no ambiguity. On one side it sets the govern- ing, controlling, inhibiting energy of the soul, working to the end of law and reason; on the other side, all that part of the soul which suffers 120 PLATONISM and desires and which is repugnant to self-mas- tery. Mr. Adam was correct in arguing that this analysis is only superficially inconsistent with the psychology of the fourth book, but he errs, I think, in holding that the dualism here imposed on the threefold division of the faculties is for immediate purposes alone, rather than funda- mental to Plato's philosophy. He might have been warned of this error by a consideration of the series of portraits of the eighth and ninth books, from which was drawn the account of the Tyrant's Progress, and which is avowedly a re- turn to the interrupted argument of the fourth book. What is the cause of that degeneration from the highest type of liberty down to the basest condition of slavery? The just and good man is called the aristocrat for the reason that he is governed by the moral force which is the better of the two halves of his nature. When the worse half breaks from this control and begins to act for itself, the balance of the soul is disturbed ; but the rebellious desires are still at first of a specious kind, the ambitions of elevated rank and au- thority which have very much the look of pure virtues. The next step is taken when the weight of desire passes to a lower form of ambition, and the man begins to crave money as the material reality beneath everything the world reverences. For a while the spendthrift passions are held in PSYCHOLOGY 121 subjection by a kind of mild compulsion. But this balance is precarious; the desire for money, following the nature of any desire, grows more and more excessive, imtil the very excess leads to a revolt of the other desires. Then we see the emergence of the distracted soul, across which all desires move with equal authority and to which all passions are in turn equally alluring. Again the change comes from the tendency to unbridled expansion which is in the very nature of desire. Soon there is a contention among all the loosened passions, until some one evil and devouring lust gathers strength above its rivals, and snatches a despotism, the last and most miserable state of a man's soul. Certainly if anything is evident throughout the whole course of this decline, it is that the soul is regarded as composed of two warring elements, and that the descending steps are measured by the degree to which one of these elements throws ^ off obedience to the other. The sum of the mat- ter is in the words of the Laws: "To have won 85oc the victory over pleasures, this is to live happily, the life of felicity, but to fail before them is the very opposite." This does not mean, as the pre- ceding discussion of the Laws abundantly proves, that pleasure is in itself a thing to be scorned, or is in its nature necessarily destructive of happi- ness; but it does mean that pleasure may on oc- casion draw us away from our true goal, and that 122 PLATONISM happiness is dependent on the dominance of one member of the soul over the other. The duahsm of Plato's psychology is less en- tangled in other Dialogues where the classifica- tion of the virtues does not come so prominent- ly into view as in The Republic, Thus, in the PhaedOj, it falls into rather a harsh opposition be- tween the soul and the body {soma = sema) , and in this form, unfortunately, it was to be taken up by the Christian Platonists and developed into an asceticism which, with Plato, had been only a passing phase of philosophic bitterness. It is to be remembered, also, that even in the Phaedo the "body" is really not so much the material flesh as a symbol for all that part of the soul which is swayed by the baser desires. For, as it is argued i29e ff. in the first Alcihiades, a man is a different thing from the body which he uses, neither is he both body and soul, but soul ; and in the tenth book of The Republic, where Plato is arguing for im- mortality, he traces the source of evil to the soul itself, as distinct from the body, with no uncer- tain note. So strong is this thought of the inner dualism that in his later years he would even speak as if we were not one soul but two. In this way his dualism colors the mythology of the Timaeus: 69c "He himself [God] was creator of the divine, but the creation of the mortal he laid upon his offspring to accomplish. And they, in imitation PSYCHOLOGY 128 ' of his act, took from him the immortal element of i soul, and then fashioned about her a mortal body, j and gave her all the body as a vehicle; and in it ,j they framed also another kind of soul, which is ' mortal, having in itself dreadful and compelling j passions — pleasure first, the greatest incitement j to evil, then pains that frighten away good, and besides these confidence and fear, witless counsel- i lors both, and wrath hard to appease, and allur- | ing hope. Having mingled these with irrational sensation and with love that stops at nothing, \ they composed as they could the mortal soul of i man." In the LawSj by a change of allegory, the soul 896c fif. is regarded as herself the creator, instead of the created, and as such the source of all good and evil in the world, of what is beautiful and what is ugly, just and imjust. From her proceed the passions and powers of man, and from her pro- ceed the motions that rule the heavens and every moving creature — yet not from one soul but from two souls, the beneficent and the worker of all that is contrary. In view of this persistent dualism it is clear that the three faculties of Plato's psychology are not independently co-operative powers, but merely different phases, sometimes sharply dis- sociated, sometimes merging into one another, of the activity of what we may call, using a termin- ology strange to Plato, the personal element of our being. The faculties might have been four 124 PLATONISM or five or any other number, instead of three, if the analysis of the virtues had been carried fur- ther — if, for instance, bravery had been subdi- vided into endurance and aggressiveness. The only obscurity in this scheme is chargeable to Plato's careless treatment of the word "reason'' when he passes from epistemology to ethics. By employing the same term now for the higher of the two elements of the soul, and now for the prudential faculty of the lower element, he intro- duced, or at least encouraged, an ambiguity which has never to this day been purged from the body of philosophy, as any one may know who will trace the meaning of "reason" and "rational" through the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries down into modern literature. In one place you will find Plato drawing the reason close to the 411c «F. desires, as in the passage of The Republic which deals with education imder the two heads of "music" (including hterature, etc.) and gymnas- tic. Here reason and the concupiscent faculty, taken together as opposed to the thymos, have their discipline in music, whereas the thymos is 4391 s. fortified by gymnastic. Yet in another part of the same Dialogue the thymos is regarded as the spirit of indignation and self-respect which is normally on the side of judgment against the desires. In either case the assimilation of the reason whether to the desires or to the thymos shows that we have to do here with a prudential PSYCHOLOGY 1«5 faculty different in kind from reason regarded as an element of the soul set over against all the practical activities. A hint of this double nature of reason may be found in the most picturesque presentation of Plato's psychology — the famous metaphor of the chariot in the Phaedrus, Superficially, the divi- 246a £f. sion is tripartite, as made by the driver, repre- senting reason, and his two horses, the one docile, the other self-willed; but, more carefully consid- ered, the image shows the usual dualism under a novel guise. When the soul comes into sight of a fair and beloved object, the wild horse rushes forward to satisfy his base lust, dragging along with him his mate (the thymos, as instinctive self- respect) and the driver. At first the driver and the better horse resist ineffectually ; but of a sud- den there comes to the di'iver a remembrance of the pure eternal beauty he has beheld in a pre- vious existence with the gods, and, as it were, smitten by that vision, he himself is thrown back- wards and pulls both the horses to their haunches. By this check the driver and the docile horse gain control of the concupiscent beast, and the soul is turned from its evil deed. The power of resis- tance came at last, not from the driver as a de- liberative agent, but from the knowledge that belongs to a diviner reason, and strikes into him after the manner of the Christian's grace of God. But Plato's symbolism is interpreted more 126 PLATONISM Republic 439E clcaply by the story of a certain lieontius, who, coming up to the city one day by the north wall, was troubled by the sight of some dead bodies lying in the place of execution. For a while he was divided between his curiosity and a feeling of repulsion, and stood with closed eyes, debating with himself. But at last his desire got the mas- tery, and, forcing open his eyes, he ran up to the place, crying, "Look, ye wretches, take your fill of the lovely spectacle!" The moral of the tale, Plato adds, is the distinction between the thymos and the desires, as proved by their enmity. But it suggests something more than that. The de- liberative pause of Leontius, while reason and self-respect are contending with desire, points to the function of that element of the soul, whether it be called reason or by another name, which is above them all, and upon whose exercise rests the possibility of forming judgments and deter- mining our actions.^ The problem of Platonic ^ Schleiermacher, in his note to Republic 572a, gives a clear statement of this separate governing element of the soul: "Ich will aber hier, wenn auch nur im Vorbeigehen, aufmerksam darauf machen, wie ausser den dreien, dem be- gehrlichen, dem eifrigen und dem verniinftigen, noch ein vierter, namlich der von jenen dreien bald dieses bald jenes beschwichtigende oder aufregende sich einschleicht ; so dass nun dieser hier der Fuhrmann wird, und wir ein Dreige- spann haben nebst einem Fuhrmann, wie es scheint, indem was im Phaidros der Fuhrmann war, hier als Ross erseheint, und zwar nicht in einer in gleichem Grade bildlichen Dar- stellung." — This is good Platonism, except that Schleier- PSYCHOLOGY 127 psychology is to define, or at least to understand as clearly as may be possible, the operation of this dualism. In a general way the substratum of the lower element of the soul is easily found in the desires and emotions (the thymos is, succinct- ly, the desires as these assume the guise of per- sonal emotions) ; the difficulty is in coming to terms with the higher element. It is tempting to associate this governing prin- ciple with the free will, or liberum arhitrium, which has been a theme of metaphysical debate ever since it was brought into prominence by the contest of the orthodox Church with the Pelag- ians ; and there is, perhaps, no better way to ob- tain a clear notion of the intention of Plato's psy- chology than by turning aside for a moment to the last great discussion of this question in mod- ern times. For the support of the Calvinistic doctrine of predestination against the Pelagian error of the Arminians, Jonathan Edwards had, in his Treatise Concerning Human Affections, denied the existence of any such faculty as the will in the ordinary sense of the word. The will, or the heart as he calls it, is merely the inclination of the soul towards the good as this is present to us at the moment of action. This thesis was later taken up and developed in his inquiry into the macher's aufregende, though a literal translation of Plato's KLvr)