Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2011 with funding from The Library of Congress http://www.archive.org/details/freedomofmindOOhaza FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING; OE, EYERY BEING THAT WILLS A CREATIVE FIRST CAUSE. BY ROWLAND G. HAZARD. NEW YORK: D. APPLETON AND COMPANY, 443 & 445 BROADWAY. LONDON: 16 LITTLE BRITAIN. 1865. Entered, according to Act of Congress, in the year 1864, by D. APPLETON & COMPANY, In the Clerk's Office of the District Conrt of the "United States for the Southern District of. New York. P REFA CJE. The public mind is at present so engrossed with other pursuits, and so satisfied with its progress in them, that there is little room to hope that it will bestow much attention upon the subject of this volume. Physical Science and Material Progress are now the absorbing objects of effort. To these all utility is ascribed, to the exclusion of the Metaphysical, which lies under the imputation of being both uninteresting and useless. Why this opprobrium and whence the general neglect, the absolute indisposition, to inquire into the struc- ture and conditions of our spiritual being, which, as the source of all our power and all our enjoyments, one might naturally suppose would most interest us, and at the same time, by its mystery, most excite our curiosity ? That the discoveries in Physics, so varied and so magnificent, have largely contributed to our material comforts, have feasted the intellect and even regaled the imagination, is undoubtedly one cause of this neglect of the science of mind. But there are other reasons, IV PREFACE. among which, we may mention the real difficulties of the subject. These are of two distinct kinds ; first, those of ascertaining the truths ; and second, those of imparting them after they have been ascertained. The first of these are, in some respects, peculiar. We want to examine that which examines ; we want the mind to be employed in observing its own action, i. e., we want it to be doing one thing when it is of necessity doing another. A farther difficulty, even in the investigation of the phenomena of mind, arises from the fact that the language applied to metaphysical science is very imperfect as an instrument of thought. The science of mind has very little language of its own, and in adopting for it what has been formed and fitted to another department of knowledge, much con- fusion and error result. The ambiguity, or various mean- ings of the terms, so often mislead the investigator himself, that he is not unfrequently obliged to relinquish the instrumen- tal aid of words, and directly examine his original ideas and conceptions of the subjects of inquiry. The difficulty of imparting the results in a language so imperfect is obvious, and is increased when it has been discarded in reaching them. But, with all this inappreciation of its benefits and all its recognized difficulties, Metaphysics has its peculiar attractions. The questions of every child, the yearnings of the adult, though in expression only occasionally gleam- ing through the settled gloom of discouragement and de- spondency, still manifest the fervid curiosity in regard to that mysterious invisible, which knows, thinks, feels and PREFACE. V acts ; and even in those too busy, too sluggish, or too hopeless to put forth an effort to gratify it. The reason of its being neglected lies not so much in its want of attraction, as in the prevailing idea of its in- utility ; and this idea, though now magnified by temporary causes, has a foundation in the fact, that no investigation of the nature of our faculties and powers, mental or physi- cal, is essential to that use of them which our early exist- ence demands. For this we have the requisite knowledge by intuition. We can use our powers without studying either Anatomy or Metaphysics. It is not, then, surpris- ing that we should early direct our attention to the study of those extrinsic substances and phenomena of which more knowledge is obviously and immediately useful. The want of satisfactory results has also had its influence ; and per- haps there is no question, the discussion of which has tended more to bring upon Metaphysics the reproach of being unfruitful, than that of the " Freedom of the Will." The importance of removing this grand obstruction to the progress of ethics and theology, is appreciated only by those who in their researches have encountered it. They alone have caught glimpses of the radiant fields of specu- lation which lie beyond ; and most men regard the specu- lations upon it, not only as having furnished no new truth, but as having obscured what was before known. Whatever opinion may be formed of the success or failure, of my effort to elucidate this subject, I trust it will be admitted, that the arguments I have presented, at least, tend to show that the investigation may open more elevated VI PREFACE. and more elevating views of our position and our powers ; and may reveal new modes of influencing our own intel- lectual and moral character, and thus have a more imme- diate, direct, and practical bearing on the progress of our race in virtue and happiness, than any inquiry in physical science. CONTENTS. BOOK I. FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. PAoa CHAPTER I.— Of the Existence of Spibit, ....... I Postulates of the argument— Knowledge, thought, sensation, emotion, want and effort recognized as in one combination ; one mind — Each of such combina- tions, associated with a particular form, constitutes what each denominates I — Idea of form not essential to oar idea of spirit, or intelligent being — Certain sensations, which we can and do ourselves produce ; some of the same kind, which we know that we do not produce, and, attributing to others, get the idea of other finite minds ; and others, which we cannot produce ; and thus get the idea of Superior Power — This power really infinite, or to us the same as if it were so— "We thus come to know ourselves, our fellow beings, and God, as Cause. CHAPTER II.— Of the Existence of Matter, 5 We know of it only by our sensations — Sensations not conclusive proof of its existence — Sensations may be the thought and imagery of the mind of God directly imparted to us — In either case they represent His thought, and are equal- ly real — That they are thought and imagery directly imparted to us, the more simple hypothesis, and more in accordance with our own conscious powers — Matter not necessary for Spirit to act upon — This illustrated by geometrical science— To ignore matter would simplify the question of freedom of the mind and make creation more intelligible — Not sufficient proof to warrant this course ; but, in either case, the phenomena are the same, and matter is unin- telligent and inert. CHAPTER III.— Of Mind, . 9 Its attributes and its faculty of will— Its sensations and emotions not de- pendent on its will — Its knowledge also not so dependent — But act of will may be essential to the acquisition of knowledge — Feeling a property, or suscepti- bility, rather than a faculty— Ability to acquire knowledge a capacity, or sense, rather than a faculty — Object of act of will always is to produce some effect in Ylll CONTENTS. PAGE the future — Supposed faculties of mind, other than will, all but naxces of some form of knowledge, or of some mode of effort to acquire it — All knowledge, in the last analysis, a simple mental perception — Objection, that these supposed faculties sometimes seem to act of themselves, considered — Definition of knowledge and of metaphysical certainty. CHAPTER IV.— Liberty, or Fbeedom, 19 Opposing terms, compulsion, control, constraint, and restraint— That which controls its own action, acts freely. CHAPTER V.— Of Cause, 21 Cause used as that which produces change — Four distinct conceivable kinds enumerated — Two of them material, and two intelligent. CHAPTER VI— Of the Will, 24 Confusion in treating will as a distinct, active entity — "Will defined as the power or faculty of the mind for effort — Mind cannot be inert cause— Mind has two distinct spheres for its activity ; in one, it seeks to learn what is, and in the other to influence the course of events in the future — These connected by the mind's prophetic power. CHAPTER VII.— Of Want, 27 The term want used to express the conscious condition of the mind, and not the thing wanted — A mere sensation, or emotion, or its absence, is not in itself a want — The idea of change an essential element of want — Primary and secondary wants — Natural, acquired, and cultivated wants — Natural wants not the result of volition — Acquired want results from some increase of knowledge — Influence of want on will not varied by the cause of it. CHAPTER VIIL— Of Matter as Cause, 32 All changes in matter must arise from motion in it— Cannot move itself, and hence cannot be cause, except by first being in motion — Can it thus be- come cause ? If so, as it may have been in motion from eternity, may always have been cause — Other questions upon which this depends— If motion gives it causative power, that power is diminished in producing effects ; and hence, in an eternity, must be reduced to an infinitesimal — Matter in motion subject- ed to intelligent control — Matter cannot be made cause by impressing laws upon it — Matter an instrument, a means, by which one intelligence communi- cates with, or produces effects upon another — If matter be cause, its effects cannot affect the freedom of the mind in willing, any more than the effects of intelligent causes can — Action of mind on matter — Independent action of matter. CHAPTER IX.— Of Spirit as Cause, 42 Spirit is an indispensable, if not the only cause — Relations of the finite to the Supreme Intelligence, as cause — Creative powers of the finite mind of man similar to those of the Infinite — Man has no faculty by which he can create, or even conceive of the creation of matter as a distinct entity, and there is no necessity, or reason to suppose that God has— Tho human mind, within the CONTENTS. 12 PAGE sphere of its knowledge, with a coordinate finite presence, is creative — Its in- cipient creations are conceptions of its own mind — Its creative power exerted in the same manner as that of the Infinite — Creative power of man may be secondary in its character — That is, moulds its conceptions in the same mate- rial which God has previously used for a like purpose — Our own ideal concep- tions distinguishable from the external creation only by their subjection to our will— God's conceptions, or creations, also subject to change or annihilation by His will— Man's limited power to transfer the conceptions of his own to other minds— Finite mind can create not only new forms and new combinations, but new thought and-new beauty. CHAPTER X. — Fkeedom of Intelligence, 51 The question should be, not, Is the will free ? but, Does the mind will freely ? — The willing distinct from its sequence or effect — Connection between volition and its effect — Intelligence must have an object for acting, rather than not act- ing — This object must be an effect which it wants to produce ; must arise from a want — With this want must be associated knowledge of the means of its grat- ification — Action different under different circumstances, and the first step must be to examine, or to ascertain the circumstances, and this fact is probably intuitively known — Want and knowledge the source in which volitions origi- nate and receive their direction — Sources of volition resolvable into an active being with knowledge and want- Want and knowledge may be without voli- tion — A want may itself be the object wanted — We do not make, but find knowledge ; and for intuitive knowledge do not have to seek — Deliberation necessary in applying acquired knowledge — Without the knowledge of a choice in means, the first perceived would be adopted — Experience teaches delibera- tion — Deliberation still but the application of knowledge to action — Delibera- tion is the considered application of knowledge, leading to a judgment — Time devoted to it decided by the mind — Mind can arrest its impulse to gratify its want by the first perceived means, to consider its proposed action — This power makes one distinction between instinctive and rational actions — We do not make any effort for what already is— Every effort is a beginning to do, and is an exercise of creative powei'— Finite mind has creative powers, and capacity to use them — Circumstances, examination of which is essential to proper ef- fort — We never will to do what we know we tfannot do — Mind does not always adopt the easiest mode of attaining the ultimate object of its effort — Illustra- tion from the want of food — Efforts must be in a certain order, otherwise abor tive — Effects of a series of finite efforts as clearly manifest design as the plan etary system — Deliberation illustrated — We do not will as to what is past, but to produce some effect in the future — Mind forms preconceptions of this future effect of effort — To will requires a prophetic view of the future, making a broad distinction between intelligent and unintelligent cause — The mind's pro- phetic power fits it for ajirst cause — The mind must determine what change it will try to produce — For this, if want and knowledge were not fixed and in- dependent of will, the data would be insufficient — If want and knowledge not fixed, the mind must form hypothesis to act upon — No power, ignorant of the want and th/e perceptions of the agent, could determine the will of that agent — That want and knowledge are not subject to the will, facilitates the mind in the exercise of its freedom in willing — Whether the mind's preconceptions are realized by its own power, not material to the question of its freedom in will- A* X CONTENTS. PAGE ing — Finite mind exerts its creative power in same manner as the Infinite — Each, respectively, subject to its own conditions — Conflicting wants and wants of activity and repose (note)— Supposed commencement of creation — A creative God must make effort — Intelligence a cause, which produces various effects — Another step in creation supposed — Every creative act a beginning of a new creation — (Supreme Intelligence acting with coexisting blind causes — Acting also with coexisting intelligent causes — In either case, must will freely— Amount of its power makes no difference to the freedom of intelligent being in willing — Nor does the amount of its knowledge — Hence, the finite intelli- gence may be as free as the Infinite— One intelligence may shape circum- stances to influence the will of another, which may be effective if that other acts freely — The period of creation at which the finite mind begins to act does not affect its freedom — Every act of will the same, in some respects, as a first act— Is the finite mind, in willing, controlled by any other power ? — Conceiva- ble modes of external control — These modes considered — Influence of other intelligences — Influence of circumstances — If mind wills at all, it must will freely — Same result more concisely reached through the logical relation of terms. CHAPTER XL— Instinct and Habit, 9» The sphere of liberty varies in different orders of intelligence — Each equal- ly free in its own sphere of knowledge — Matter has no such sphere, aud hence, if it had the essential attributes, could manifest no freedom — Being, with sen- sation, but no want, could not will — Knowledge, to be available for willing, must extend to the future — The lowest order of intelligence, admitting of will, is that with one want and one known means of gratifying it, and this intuitive — Instinctive action still voluntary and free — And free, not merely as not coun- teracted — In the instinctive, the spheres of knowledge and freedom reach their minimum, but are still coexistent — But for the element of knowledge, instinct- ive action would be mechanical — Conceivable that first instinctive actions may be mechanical — Knowledge that we can will, and how to will, and that by will we can produce change in ourselves, could not be taught by practical exam- ples, but must be intuitive — Hence, not mechanical — All the requisites of will incorporated in our being — Instinct may bwng the infant within easy effort of its object— Absence of deliberation in intuitive action — Muscular action the basis of our plans for external change — Bodily movement always instinctive — This is the point from which instinctive and rational actions take their depart- ure—In the instinctive, not only the mode of making the action, but the plan, the successive order of volitions, is intuitively known — Inferior free agents may still subserve the purposes of a superior — Conflicting modes and wants are cases for the exercise of judgment— Imitative actions diverging from instinct- ive — Distinguishing features of instinctive action — Some cases of rational ac- tion liable to bo confounded with instinctive — When we are conscious of form- ing a plan of action this does not occur — "When we work from memory of a plan, intuitive or acquired, it is hakit — Peculiar characteristics of habit— Sim- ilarity of instinctive and habitual action — Analogy of habitual to mechauical action — Rational actions, in becoming habitual, approach the instinctive — Cus- tomary actions belong to the same group— Recapitulation of actions, mechan- ical, instinctive, rational, customary, and habitual— Habit has same relation to CONTENTS. XI PAGH action that memory has to knowledge, and depends on memory and associa- tion — That habit applies to actions which we have most frequent occasion to perform, increases its benefits, yet often regarded as a vice of the mind — Rea- sons why it is so regarded. CHAPTER XII.— Illustration from Chess, 126 Known laws of the game somewhat analogous to intuitive knowledge — First moves may he habitual— Subsequently the player deliberately forms precon- ceptions and compares them — Does not examine every possible move, but de- termines how long to examine by an exercise of judgment — Each volition to move the same as if he had never before moved — A more complicated game supposed, more nearly resembling that of real life — The skilful succeed against many opponents ; and Infinite Wisdom would accomplish Its end though op- posed by any number of finite intelligences, all acting as freely as itself— The uninitiated see no order or design in the game— It is a creation having its own laws — Automaton chess-player — But for the uniformity of God's actions, the efforts of finite agents would be impossible — Case in which, by the laws of the game, only one move is possible, and analogous cases in real life— Compliance with the laws of the game, as with the laws of God, may become habitual, but this does not conflict with freedom — Influence of law on individual action — The word law, in such cases, used iu two distinct senses, but the knowledge of the law, in either sense, important in deciding our efforts. CHAPTER XIII. — Of "Want and Effort in Various Orders of Intelli- gence, 136 Want requisite to all but the lowest forms of animated existence— Imputa- tion of want to the Supreme Being — A sole first cause, without want, would im- mediately become inert — Intelligence must have a retaining power and some adaptation to put its retained power in action — If matter is cause, no applica- tion of a self-moving power to it is possible — If the activity of any intelligence ceases, it cannot put itself in action again — No intelligent being can do any- thing unless it makes effort to do something — Want rouses the mind to effort, but does not direct the effort — Effort the condition of cause in the Infinite as in the finite being — Some cause with power to produce change, which it does not of necessity immediately exert, is necessary— Mind and matter in motion the only such causes conceivable — The existence of God cannot, of itself, be the cause of anything which ever began to be — Effort makes the distinction be- tween that condition of a being in which it seeks to produce change and that in which it does not — If in the Supreme Being there is no such distinction, all effects must be independent of His action — Reasons why it is thought Omnipo- tence may produce effects without effort — Omnipotence has its bound in the absolutely.impossible — Want has with it the germ of its own gratification — Man may design change, and make effort to actualize his design, though no other intelligence or power in existence — The mode of connection between vo- litions and their sequences not important to the act of will. CHAPTER XIV.— Of Effort for Internal Change, 145 Question stated — Do we produce the sequences of volition? — The important fact is, that our volitions are necessary to them — Effects of effort for internal Xll CONTENTS. PAGE change as uniform and as inscrutible as for external— "We can induce spiritual as well as physical want, but cannot directly will either into existence — Increas- ing our knowledge the only means for this, and, though it may sometimes have the opposite effect, is still the only mode — Constitutional occurrence and recur- rence of our spiritual wants — Want the source of effort for internal changes in all intelligent beings — General moral evil and individual depravity — Man's knowledge infallible as to what, for him, is morally right— Directs his efforts for internal change by means of his preconceptions — In forming these, need not recognize existing circumstances — An advantage of the purely ideal concep- tions — In the moral nature the willing is the consummation, and hence, hi it, mind is a supreme creative first cause — Distinction between effort in the moral sphere and out of it — A man who does not want to be pure and noble may be- gin with the want to want to be pure and noble — Virtue all lies in the effort, and not in its sequence — Not any present moral wrong in want, or knowledge, and hence all moral right and wrong concentrated in the act of will — Efforts to bo pure and noble may become habitual — We may indirectly discard a want — A being with no want for what is unholy cannot be unholy — Cannot will what is contradictory to its own nature — Though many of our moral wants are in- nate, they may be cultivated, enabling us to influence our moral characteristics at their source — Conclusion from the foregoing, that man in the sphere of his moral nature is a supreme and a sole creative first cause — Man's will infinite, but limited in its range, because his power of conception is finite — This power may forever increase — Man responsible and accountable for his acts of will. CHAPTER XV— Conclusion, * . .161 Recapitulation of the previous results and leading positions — Wants seem- ingly insignificant may be the basis of contests for the mastery of empires — Man bountifully provided with wants— Physical wants temporary — Made less inconstant by the secondary want of acquisition— They are preliminary to the soul's progress, teaching effort ; though this provision is often counteracted by acquisitiveness with a material bias— Spiritual want essential— Early ideal constructions and influence of the romantic passion—" Castle building" — The interest which attaches to the products of our labor — Influence of wants not left to accidental occurrences — Recurrence of both spiritual and bodily wants amply provided for — Each has within himself an inchoate and, to him, a boundless universe, which is his especial sphere of creative action — Construct- ing this universe within himself the principal, if not tho sole end of life. BOOK II. REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. Introduction, . » 173 CHAPTER I.— Edwards's Definition of Will, 177 Edwards's definition of will— He identifies volition with choice and prefer- ence, and willing with choosing and preferring— His definition admits of vari- CONTENTS. Xir PAGK ous constructions— Confounds the process of choosing with the result of the process — Also asserts that an act of choice is a comparative act of the mind — Proof that tho comparative act is not itself the act of choice, and that the choice, "which in some cases is the result of a compai'ative act, is not an act of ■will, but is knowledge— The choice to will preceding the act of will considered — Edwards's definitions of choice as an act of will, and also as the result of a comparative act, involve an absurdity — In making choice an act of will, he makes it the last act of the mind in relation to the effect intended — Cases mentioned by Edwards in which the soul would rather have or do distinguish- able, and the question whether choice is ever an act of will, examined— Ed- wards's use of the word choice confounds the understanding with the will — Further proof that choice is knowledge, and not act of will— Sophism admitted by making choice a synonym for will — Difficulties encountered by Edwards, growing out of his definition — Difference in a man's preferring to walk and preferring to fly — Edwards constrained to admit exertion, but having no space between choice and effect, must crowd it into one or the other— My views ap- plied to explain the difference of the cases of preferring to walk and preferring to fly — Edwards's intention to use the word choice in its popular sense — Reca- pitulation. CHAPTER II.— Liberty as Defined by Edwards, 201 Edwards asserts that the only liberty in man is power " to do as he pleases," or " conducting as he wills" — This places liberty in that in the doing of which we are not conscious of having any agency — In this case the mind has no liberty in willing, and the definition begs the question — The hypothesis that the will- ing is itself a doing considered. CHAPTER III.— Natural and Moral Necessity, 204 Edwards's definitions of these terms — Much confusion from vague use of some of the terms— Every intelligent being with will a distinct cause — Hence our will cannot change the course of nature, except by being an independent cause — God's action or the counter-willing of finite minds may, either of them, control or influence the effect intended by another, without interfering with the freedom of that other in willing — The argument is rather against the free- dom of man in doing than in willing— Edwards's definition admits three dis- tinct intelligent causes, each acting freely — The term " necessity' 1 '' used in dif- ferent -senses in defining natural and moral necessity — Edwards makes " mo- tive" a cause, producing volition, or makes human volitions the direct action of God — The argument from these definitions stated — The hypothesis, that the same causes of necessity produce the same effects, essential to it — It assumes that human volitions are a part of a necessary chain of events — Yet asserts that the mind encounters difficulties in bringing them to pass — The assump- tion that the human will is finite shown to be an error, and especially if it is " choice' 1 ''— Supposed difficulty in willing examined, and found not to be in the -willing, but in finding or knowing what to will — The martyr and the craven equally free in willing — Difference in action indicates difference in character — Modes in which we form our own characters and aid each other in doing it — The difficulty spoken of by Edwards consists in the conflict between present pleasure, and right or future good— That a man may will against such convic- XIV CONTENTS. PAGH tians may prove that he is not pure and wise, but not that he is not free — The particular cases of moral inability Btated by Edwards — Examination of those cases — All analogous to those of inability to will, because there is no want — In- ability to will what we do not want to will is not against freedom — No reason to suppose that a, previous bias or inclination will prevail over the present in the act of will— If it does, it is because the biased or inclined mind itself con- trols the act of will — As in the case of "nature of things,"- Edwards makes "habit" a power, or cause — No certainty and no necessity that habits will continue — Habits of a man influence his act of will only in case he wills freely — Man is said to be a slave to his habits ; reasons why — The argument from moral necessity only proves that a man wills in conformity to what he wills, and natural necessity only implies that he cannot always execute what he wills. CHAPTER IV.— Self-Determination, 233 The argument against the self-determining power of the will irrelevant to my position — Edwards's statement of his argument against the soul's deter- mining its volitions in the exercise of its power of willing— From which it can only be inferred, that whatever is true of acts of will is true of acts of choice — Changing the word "■£«." to "6y" vitiates the argument — Confusion from using choice as the process of choosing, and also as the result of the process, and "mind " and " will" as equivalents — Edwards does not recognize mind as cause — There must be something to move the mind, as it does not act without a reason— Edwards finds this prime mover in his " motives ; " I have ascribed it to "want" — Control, by a previous act of will, fatal to freedom in the pres- ent act — Edwards's favorite reductio ad absurdum that a self-determined or free act admits of no first free act, fallacious. CHAPTER V.— No Event without a Cause, 24C Edwards says he applies the word cause to what has no positive influence — This facilitates his proof, but makes it unavailing for his purpose — Edwards's positions being admitted, if mind is itself cause, they prove its freedom in will- ing — He assumes that the cause of a volition must be not only without the vo- lition, but without the mind that wills — If the act of mind, as cause, must have a cause, for the reason that everything which begins to be must have a cause, there can be no flrst act of cause — The soul itself, being the cause of its voli- tions, is not, in them, the subject of effects which have no cause — The question why the soul exerts such an act and not another considered — Examination of Edwards's position that " activity of nature " cannot be the cause why the mind's action is thus and thus determined— This argument also vitiated by changing in to by, or by assuming that of two terms expressing the same thing one is the cause of the other — Volition cannot be determined by the "past." CHAPTER VI.— Of the Will's Determining in Things Indifferent, . 259 Edwards's statement of the question imperfect, though warranted by ex- tracts from his opponents— As he states it, one thing is indifferent, and another chooses — Other of his arguments founded on his assumption that will and choice are identical — nis use of the phrase " determining power" ambiguous, applying either to mind or will— Auother statement of the argument— Ed- CONTENTS. XV PAQH wards supposes the mind to devise a way of getting itself out of a state of in- difference, and illustrates by the touching of one of the squares of a chesB hoard — His argument denies that the mind can get itself out of a state of indif- ference, yet begins by showing how it can do so — Mind's doing, indirectly by volition, what it cannot do directly, is not against its freedom — In this case such indirection (the giving itself up to accident) does not obviate the suppos- ed difficulty, but increases it — Just as difficult for the mind to determine what accident as what square of the chess board — Edwards might as well have made the movement of the finger as the movement of the eye determine the square to be touched — In either case, the difficulty of indifference may recur- There is the same difficulty of indifference in applying the accident, even if it can be selected — The whole causal efficacy must be, not in the accident, but in the rule which the mind makes to apply it, in doing which it again encounters indifference— The mind can as well make the rule to touch a particular square without the accident as with it — The whole efficacy of the proposed plan is in the mind's governing itself by an arbitrary rule which itself has created — The indirection would not aid the argument for necessity, but these supposed cases of indifference militate against it — If choice, among the objects of effort, is essential to will, a man never could will if there- was only one object — Not necessary to an act of will that we should select, or choose even, among objects which we know to be different — The bearing of the views elicited in Book I. on this question — Similarity of cases of indifference and those of wanting to will— The apparent analogy of Edwards's mode of deciding them to that of de- ciding between parties having equal claims — But this would as well be accom- plished by a direct act of will — If decided by lot, or accident, an arbitrary rule must still be made — Analogy of the cases of indifference to matter kept at rest by equal counter forces. CHAPTER VII. — Relation of Indifference to Freedom in Willing, . 284 Edwards uses the term indifference as directly opposed to preference — His argument against the soul's sovereign power in certain cases, only proves that if the soul wills when it does not will, then its willing is not wholly owing to itself— Much confusion from using the term inclination as identical with will, and yet as something which goes before it — Another of his arguments only proves that the mind is not free in willing when it is not willing at all— And this and the subsequent reasoning only proves that the mind cannot both will and not will at the same time — His statement that a free act of will cannot immediately arise out of a state of indifference, considered — He assumes that choice is a necessary element of free will — Argument thus far avails only on certain inadmissible premises, and has little application to my positions — For the purposes of this argument, Edwards's assumption that choice is a pre- requisite of a free act of will may be admitted — Form in which this admission may be most plausibly used against freedom — The essential element of free ac- tion is not choice, but self-direction — Suspending volition — Edwards assumes that suspending volition must be an act of volition— If so, the mind never can stop willing, for suspending its willing is only another willing — Even then the mind could suspend action in one direction by acting in another — And liberty in every action might still be maintained — What is meant by suspending an act of will— Illustrations from reading aloud— Do we will either to will or not Xvi CONTENTS. TAGS to will ?— Nearest approach to willing to will is when we want exftrciso for the faculty of will and act capriciously — Indifference indicates the point of depart- ure from the passive to the active state ; perfect in the non-active state of pro- found sleep — Vigilance of the mind as to changes about it which may call for effort— Effort to rind what changes are taking place, or what action these ohanges require, is attention — To know these changes does not always re- quire effort — Changes often occurring and requiring no action, as the striking of a clock, are immediately forgotten — Reason why monotonous sounds favor reverie and the concentration of the mind in abstract thought. CHAPTER VIIL— Contingency, 313 Treated by Edwards in Part II. , sections 8 and 9 — If mind is the cause of its acts of will, then Edwards's argument only proves that they are necessarily connected with mind, and not that mind is not free — Edwards absurdly argues that the mind is not free in the act of willing, because the act of will is connect- ed with the mind — His argument also involves the contradiction that mind is not free, because it cannot be otherwise than free — In chapter xiii. applies sim- ilar reasoning to prove that if the will controls itself it cannot be free, because controlled by itself — Fallacy of this and preceding argument — From the posi- tion that every effect is dependent on its cause, Edwards infers, not that the effect, but that the action of the cause is necessitated— Necessary futility of reasoning on his statement, which really only asserts that a man wills what ho wills — The hypothesis that there are other mental faculties which influence the will considered in its relation to the mind's freedom in willing — Edwards's argument denies the possibility of this ; but with more reason it might be said that all cause is of necessity free — Even matter in motion is not constrained or restrained till it comes to the producing of an effect — Any force or power sub- ject to extrinsic control is an implement rather than a cause — Essential differ- ence in the freedom of intelligent and material causes. CHAPTER IX.— Connection of the "Will with the Understanding, . 323 Sometimes the last dictate is neither an act of will nor followed by an act of will— If will is choice, it never follows the last dictate of the understanding— If it does, still not against the mind's freedom or self-determining power in willing — Edwards attempts to prove that the will, as a distinct entity, is not free — Act of will not always necessary to the mind's attention — Mind may be- gin by an effort to obtain the requisite knowledge, or may direct its action by a simple perception of it — Edwards's position in regard to the will's following the last dictate of the understanding really confirms the freedom of mind in willing. CHAPTER X.-Motive, 327 Statement of Edwards's argument on motive — Varies his definition of will to accommodate the argument— His argument, even admitting his definition of will, is still fallacious— His definition of motive amounts only to "that which is a motive is a motive"— As impossible to deduce any new truth from such definition as from the expression " whatever is, is " — The argument, as he states it, does not contravene that of his opponents— The difficulty is radical, arising from defining motivo not by what it is, but by what it must do — To CONTENTS. XV11 PAGE conform to tho definition and admit the deduction of necessity, the motive must control the mind — The motive cannot itself determine that it is the strongest — This must be done by the intelligent being that wills — His positions involve an infinite series with no beginning — That the mind has in itself, or its own view, a motive, no reason why it does not act freely — "Whether motives prove necessity or freedom must depend on their character or influence— Ed- wards uses "motive" sometimes as meaning the mind's view of an object, and at others the object viewed — The assertion that the mind is governed by its own views affirms its freedom— The point that, if the mind determines itself by its own view, the object viewed is still essential to that view, considered — The ex- istence of objects of choice cannot be a reason why the mind does not will free- ly — Freedom does not imply a power to make existing circumstances different from what they are at the time — Classification of objects, which may possibly be motives, under Edwards's definition— These considered in their order — Vague popular notions in regard to the influence of circumstances — Particular cases, as stated by Edwards, make motive the mind's view of the future effects of its own action— Inquiry as to the meaning of "previous tendency"— The ar- gument again leads to an infinite series, and makes the act of (will) choice be- fore that by which the mind chooses has acted — In Edwards's system, motive, or previous tendency of motive, must be an act of choice springing directly out of a state of indifference— Same difficulty in regard to motive which Edwards finds in regard to will — This difficulty attaches to every system which does not recognize a self -moving power or cause. CHAPTER XL— Cause and Effect, 364 The argument of Edwards assumes that the same causes of necessity pro- duce the same effects — If the same cause never acted twice there could be no application of the rule — The law is deduced from observation, and cannot be of metaphysical necessity — No reason to suppose the law goes farther than our observations indicate — That there is no general rule without exceptions, con- flicts with it — No reason to suppose that God may not vary from any law of uniformity which he has established for His o^n government— That He is om- niscient obviates the necessity of trying different modes — In mind, observation does not indicate any such law — To all appearance, different minds act differ- ently, and even the same mind changes its mode in similar circumstances— No case can arise for the application of the rule to mind — Under such rule a sole First Cause never could have produced but one effect — The application of this rule to intelligent cause denies any continuing power to produce changes in the universe— As applied to God, the rule can only mean that He has adopted uni- form rules for His government — The finite mind, after having tried one mode, may, upon the recurrence of the same circumstances, try another — As used by Edwards, the law of cause and effect involves an infinite series with no begin- ning of action — There must be some cause which has power to change itself as cause, or to vary its effects— Changes in matter must be referred to an intelli- gent will — Some things may have been made not uniform, to vary the prob- lems of life, for the development of the finite intelligence— No difficulty in sup- posing that the finite mind maybe a first or originating cause — If mind is cause, the necessity of volition as its effect does not prove that mind is not free —The uniformity of God's action is necessary to and argues the existence of XV111 CONTENTS. PAGH finite free agents— The argument that, if the same circumstances occur a thousand times to mind in the same condition, its action will he the same, ex- amined. CHAPTER XII.— God's Foreknowledge, 384 Edwards argues that the acts of the will must he necessary, because God foreknows them — Unavailing reply to this — An event foreknown by infallible prescience must be as certain in the future as if known by infallible memory in the past, and God's foreknowledge of free volitions is contradictory — The other link in the argument of Edwards, that God must foreknow, denied — Edwards's position that, without foreknowledge of men's volitions, God could not be able properly to govern the universe — His argument goes rather to disprove freedom in executing the volitions than in the volitions themselves — God, foreknowing all the effects of human volition which are possible, can provide in advance for any contingence — That He may do this without deviating from uniform modes of action, illustrated by an automatic chess-board — He may also deviate from such uniformity in miracles — And, in many things, we do not know that He has established any uniformity— Foreknowledge, for the purpose of making sea- sonable provision, not necessary when the power is infinite — Foreknowledge of God has the same relation to His actions that preconceptions of man have to his. CHAPTER XIII.-Conclusion, 401 Recapitulation of the argument — Edwards's erroneous and incompatible definitions of Will and Choice — His favorite reductio ad absurdum and various sophisms founded on these errors — His error in defining Freedom — His argu- ment from Moral Necessity and Moral Inability, and supposed difficulties in willing — His argument from the connection of volition with a prior cause— Mo- tive — Habit as a motive — Assumption that the same causes necessarily produce the same effects — Indifference and Contingence — Last dictate of the under- standing—Willing in cases of indifference— Foreknowledge— Edwards's idea of it would deprive God of the highest%ttributes of creative intelligence. BOOK I. FREEDOM OP MIND IN WILLING BOOK I. / FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. ~ k * CHAPTEE I. OF THE EXISTENCE OP SPIRIT. Evekt argument has its postulates. We cannot reason from the known to the unknown, unless some- thing be first known. Of all that we believe, nothing is more certain than the existence of belief itself, consti- tuting knowledge ; and, of this knowledge the belief that there is some existence which believes, stands in the first rank ; and, next in order, a belief in a plurality of existences, which, of necessity, implies that each of the existences, constituting this plurality, has peculiar and distinguishing characteristics, otherwise it would be identical with some other existence. It would not add to the number of existences ; and, if none possessed dis- tinguishing attributes or conditions, there could be only one existence. In such case, if space is a necessary exist- ence, all other existence would become impossible. Even if space were homogeneously filled, that which fills must, in some way, be different from that which is filled. Time itself would be excluded. It may then reasonably be as- 2 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. sumed not only that the belief in the plurality of exist- ences itself exists, but that it is well founded. In this plu- rality there is nothing of which we have more convincing proof than of the existence of sensation, emotion, want, and of effort to supply want, of all which we are conscious. Perhaps we cannot logically deduce from this any separate existence, which knows, feels and acts, but it is at least certain, that this knowledge, sensation and effort are, in some way, so far associated as to justify us in speaking of them as one combination ; and, in doing this, each individual combination of them is denominated a spirit, an intelligence, mind, or soul, of which the attri- butes of knowing, feeling and acting are distinguishing characteristics. As present with this mind, or soul, yet distinct from it, we associate the idea of a particular form, which, with the soul, constitutes what each ex- presses by the term, " I." This idea of form is not essen- tial to our conception of mind, or spirit, the attributes of which maybe conceived of as entirely independent of such association, or as purely intelligent being, or beings. Among our sensations are some which each indi- vidual finds he can himself produce. He can, by cer- tain efforts, produce the various sensations known as muscular movements, the sound of a bell, &c. ; and hence knows his own power to produce effects. But he finds the sensation is sometimes produced without any effort of his own, and hence he infers a cause, or power without himself; and most naturally attributing the effect to a power similar to that which in himself pro- duces similar effect, — to another finite intelligence, — he gets the idea of the existence of other finite minds. It is, perhaps, hardly necessary here to remark, that although through the sensations of sight we may have OF THE EXISTENCE OF SPIRIT. 3 an immediate perception of other forms like our own, still, the belief that other similar "beings are associated with, or represented by snch forms, is an inference from the visual sensation, in connection with other facts. We draw no snch inference from our image in a mirror, or from any other object known to be lifeless, however nearly resembling the human form. But, among our sensations, are some, which we find we have no power to produce, or very insufficient power ; and hence we infer the existence of a power without ourselves, greatly exceeding our own ; so in- comparably surpassing it, that we term it infinite. Strictly speaking, the evidence as first presented to ns, only proves the existence of a power capable of pro- ducing the sensations of which we are conscious ; but every new observation revealing greater and greater power, and power far beyond what we had previously conceived, lays the foundation for a belief that the power is unlimited, and that any apparent limitation to it is in our own finite powers of observation and con- ception. Or, to put it in another form, the constant effect of the enlargement of our own observations and conceptions having always been to make the limit of this external power appear more remote, there is no reason to suppose that a further enlargement of them, to any finite extent, would bring us nearer to that limit j and hence, so far as our experience goes, we may, if not with strict logical accuracy, yet without danger of its leading ns into philosophical error, apply the term infinite to the Supreme Intelligence. A power, which can accomplish everything conceivable to ns as within the province of power, is, to us, the same as if it were infinite. It has, for us, no conceivable limit. £ FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. The inference, by which the finite intelligence argues the existence of other similar intelligences, is not one of absolute necessity ; for all the phenomena, — the sensa- tions, — which he ascribes to their agency, may be pro- duced in him by the Infinite, — the greater including the less. But the exhibition of weaknesses and imper- fections like his own, and which are incompatible with the Infinite ; and the repeated coincidence, or frequent association of these phenomena with the presence of forms similar to, yet differing more or less from that which he associates with his own being, and in which changes resembling his Own external actions take place, give preponderance to the hypothesis of the existence of other and numerous finite intelligences, distinct from his own. In the absence of any reason to the contrary, it is rational to suppose things really to be as they appear to be. So far, then, we may be said to have arrived at the knowledge of the existence of our own finite intelli- gence ; of other similar finite intelligences ; and of the Supreme, or Infinite Intelligence. We have come to know ourselves, our fellow beings, and God, as powers producing certain effects, as being Cause. CHAPTER II. OF THE EXISTENCE OF MATTEE. We know nothing of matter except by the sensations, which we impute to its agency, mediately, or imme- diately ; and as those sensations can exist in the mind without the intervention of the external, material forms, or forces, to which we impute them, the sensations are not conclusive evidence of any such external existence. In dreams, and especially in nightmare, we have as vivid sensations of what we afterward find had no cor- responding external materiality, as we ever have under any circumstances. If this arises from the excited action of our own memory and imagination, it merely proves that the mind, under certain conditions, has a power of reproducing what has before been impressed upon it by some external power, and at the same time of vary- ing the combinations in which they before existed. This does not conflict with the position that, as the sensations may exist without the intervention of matter, the sensations are not evidence that matter exists. All the sensations which we attribute to matter, are as fully accounted for by the hypothesis that they are the thought, the imagery of God directly imparted, or made palpable to our finite minds, as by the hypothesis of a distinct external substance, in which He has 6 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. moulded this thought and imagery. If God, with design, created or fashioned matter in the forms pre- sented to us, then these forms are but the result of thoughts and conceptions existing, or which existed in His mind ; and the only question is, does He impart or impress them directly and immediately upon our finite minds ; or indirectly and mediately, by first writing, picturing, moulding, or carving them out in a distinct substance called matter ? In either case it is to us equally real / the sensations, by which alone we know these, to us, external phenomena, being the same. The hypothesis that the material forms are but the imagery of the mind of God made palpable to us, is the more simple of the two, and makes creative at- tributes more nearly accord with powers which we are ourselves conscious of exercising. We cannot infer the existence of matter as an en- tity distinct from spirit, from any necessity of spirit for something to act upon ; our conceptions of it serv- ing for this purpose, as well as any such distinct exist- ence could do ; and, indeed, being all that we can employ the faculties and attributes of spirit upon. The whole science of Geometry, which, being the science of quantity, or extension, — one of the attributes of matter, — may be deemed as emphatically a material science, is entirely founded on such conceptions ; and, in fact, on such conceptions as we get no accurate sen- sations of from without ; for, not to insist that no one ever had a sensation of such abstractions as a mathe- matical point, or line, we may assert that no one ever had a sensation from matter of a perfect mathematical form, for instance, of a perfect circle. It is a concep- tion of the mind, and for the purposes of mathematical OF THE EXISTENCE OF MATTER. 7 reasoning, is a creation of the mind, brought into exist- ence by actualizing this conception in a definition ; and for these purposes, whatever conforms to that definition is a circle, and what does not so conform is not a circle. The reasoning is wholly based on the definition of our conceptions of form, and not on any actual existence, or sensation of such forms in matter, which are never sufficiently accurate to rest such reasoning upon ; and hence, mathematics is really a hypothetical science, and would be equally true if there were no material forms even bearing any resemblance to the conceptions of the mind brought out in its definitions. The science of mechanics, too, is founded on our conceptions of resist- ance and forces, as solidity, inertia, momentum ; and does not involve the question as to what these forces really are.* To adopt the hypothesis, that our sensations of what is external are but the conceptions of Grod, made directly palpable to us, and ignore matter entirely, would free the subject of the freedom of intelligence from some apparent, if not real difficulties ; and would, at the same time, avoid much confusion, which I apprehend has been occasioned bv the close and various associa- tions of matter with spirit. We should then have only to consider the action of intelligence in its finite and infinite forms. But as either hypothesis accounts for all the phenomena, the fact that one is more simple and that it makes the process of material creation more com- prehensible to us is not, perhaps, even with our expe- rience in dreams, a sufficient reason for presuming that matter does not exist as an entity distinct from mind * See Appendix, Note I. at the end of the volume. 8 FKEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. and with the properties which our sensations indicate. We may remark, however, that, supposing the In- finite Intelligence to fashion and control this matter, it would make no difference as to the question of our freedom ; for, in that case, the real phenomena would be the same, — the thought and imagery of the mind of God — and the only question would be as to which of the two modes He has adopted in communicating that thought and in making that imagery palpable to us. We may further remark that, with the testimony of our senses on the one hand, and on the other, the considera- tion that the imagery of the mind of God is not in it- self intelligent, but an effect of intelligence in action, we may assume, in either case, that matter is in itself unintelligent and inert. Admitting, then, for the pur- poses of the argument, the existence of matter as dis- tinct from spirit, we will, in a subsequent chapter, in- quire how far it can produce effects, or be cause. I CHAPTEE III. OF MIND. Mind has feeling, knowledge, volition. It is suscep- tible of sensation and emotion ; has a simple perceptive attribute by which it directly acquires knowledge ; and a faculty of will, through which it manifests its power to produce, or to try to produce change. Our sensations and emotions are not dependent upon the will. We hear the sound of a cannon, whether we will to hear it or not ; and can neither avoid, nor pro- duce the emotions of joy or sorrow by merely willing it. "We may, by effort, bring about the conditions pre- cedent to a particular sensation or emotion ; but, the conditions being the same, whether they exist by our own act, or from some other cause, makes no difference as to the effect.* Our knowledge is also independent of the will. We cannot know, or believe anything by simply willing to know, or believe it. If I have a sen- sation of seeing a tree, I cannot by any act of will be- lieve that I have no such sensation, or that I have the sensation of seeing a rock instead. So, too, if in the relations of my ideas, I perceive certain truths, as that 2 + 2 = 4, I cannot at will disbelieve or not know such * See Appendix, Note II. 1* 10 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. truths. By will I can bring about the conditions favor- able to the increase of knowledge, but I cannot thus determine what shall become known. I may, by effort, remove an external obstruction to sight and thus be en- abled to see what was behind it ; but I cannot, by will, determine what it is that I shall then see. So also I may by effort arrange and compare my ideas, so that some truth, which before was hidden, will become ob- vious ; but I cannot will what that truth, when discov- ered, will be. In both of these, and in all other cases, the discovery of the objects, or of the abstract truths, and the consequent addition to our knowledge, is, in the last analysis, a simple mental perception j and all our efforts to acquire knowledge are only to make such external changes in matter, or so to arrange our ideas, as to bring the truth within reach of the simple percep- tive attribute of the mind. From the foregoing it appears that feeling, whether in sensation or emotion, is rather a property, or suscep- tibility ', than a faculty of being. So also the ability to acquire knowledge is a capacity, or a sense, rather than a faculty. Our sensations, emotions, and knowledge, at the time being, are actual present existences, in common with all others now actually existing, — independent of the will. Having become existent, whether by the agency of will, or otherwise, such existence cannot, by will, be changed, in the present, any more than what existed in the past can be so changed. Whenever we seek to pro- duce any change, it must be with reference to the future, and this is always by will. Whenever by the exercise of our own power we try to influence the course of events, we will. When by effort we recall the knowl- OF MIND. 11 edge of the past, the recalling is still an event future to the effort. There are other attributes, or modes of mind, which are often spoken of as if they were distinct faculties, or active agents, having power of themselves to do certain things. In this category we may embrace memory, judgment, reasoning, imagination, conception, and per- haps, also association. These are all names of some form of knowledge, or of some mode of mental action to acquire, or reproduce it. The forms of knowledge, to which they are applied, are actual present existences, not subject to the will. Our memories of the past, our observation of the present, and our anticipations of the future are all, when reached, but present knowledge. When, from any cause, the knowledge of the past, the present, or the future is perceived by the mind, it is a simple mental perception. "When we make effort to produce such changes, internal or external, as will bring any knowledges within the mind's view, it is an act of will, a trying to do something. So that, in all cases, the names of these supposed faculties only indi- cate actual existing knowledge, or its acquisition by simple mental perception, or by acts of will to produce those changes which will bring knowledge within reach of this simple mental perception.' These acts of will differ from each other either in their mode, or in their object. Memory, for instance, is but a condition, and a necessary condition, of knowledge of the past. With- out it such knowledge could not exist. In this sense it is only an expression of one form of our knowledge. To say, I remember an event, is to say, ITcnow an event in the past. If, from any cause, an event of the past comes before the mind it is then a simple mental per- 12 FEEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING ception. When we make effort to bring an event of the past into the mind's view we call it an exercise, or effort of memory ^ and this, of course, is an act of will, a trying to do this thing. So likewise the term judgment may express the mind's conclusion as to the equality, or superiority of one thing, or method as compared with another ; or as to the truth, or error of a proposition. And such con- clusion is a simple mental perception ; while any effort in comparing, examining, &c, by which we seek to bring about the conditions favoring such perception, is called an exercise, or effort of judgment, which, is an- other act of will. The same may be said of reasoning, imagining, con- ceiving, &c. In the sense in which these are spoken of as faculties, or powers, they are but names of varied modes of effort, or of efforts for different objects^ made by the same unit-mind, manifesting its power to pro- duce change by its efforts, or acts of will. Whether these supposed faculties are but names of varied acts of will, or otherwise, does not really affect the question of the mind's freedom in action ; for, whether it act by a faculty called will, or by a faculty called judgment, would not affect its freedom in action so long as the faculty by which it thus acted pertained to its own being. If the question were, whether the will, considered as a distinct entity, were free, it might become important to inquire if there were any coordinate powers of mind by which it could be con- trolled. The introduction of these supposed faculties, as distinct powers, does, however, tend to complicate and confuse the argument as to the mind's freedom. In confirmation of the views already stated, it may be ob- OF MIND. 13 served, that if acts of will are but efforts of the mind, and these faculties are exerted by the mind, it follows that they but indicate, or name different acts of will, or efforts of the same unit power — mind. In further illustration that they are but names of these varied efforts, I would remark, that the immediate object of every act of will is to move some portion of the body, or to influence mental activity. In either case we are conscious only of the effort and the effect, and though we speak of bodily and mental efforts, we still recognize them all as efforts of the mind. In so speaking, we distinguish them not by the active agent, which is the same in all, but by the immediate object of the effort, or by the subjects of it, which, in some cases, are but instruments to accomplish remoter ob- jects. Thus, when movement of the body, or of any portion of it, is the object, we speak of bodily, or mus- cular effort, and subdivide into efforts of the hand, the foot, &c. ; while those efforts, of which the mind is the , subject, we designate as mental efforts ; and, as in these we are not conscious of distinct members as the subjects of our action, we subdivide, or classify by the objects sought, as efforts of memory, of judgment, of imagina- tion, &c* By the phrase bodily effort we cannot mean to as- sert that the body is an active agent, itself making effort, but only that its movement is the object of the mental effort; and, in as close analogy to this as the case permits, the expressions, efforts of memory, of judgment and imagination, &c, only signify that the object of the effort is to remember, to judge, to imagine, * See Appendix, Note III. 14 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. &c. In all, we recognize but varied efforts, or efforts for different objects, by tlie same unit-mind, without the intervention of any other powers ; and all these efforts are but manifestations of the mind's action, va- ried in conformity with the objects, or changes it seeks to produce. It may be objected to this dispensing with these alleged faculties, and considering them merely as names designating different modes of effort, or efforts for dif- ferent objects, that they sometimes seem to act of them- selves. Of this, memory is the most marked example. Our memories seem to rise unbidden before us, and in an order which we do not control. ^N"ow, as a present sensation is known by means of simple mental percep- tion, without effort, it may so happen that the circum- stances, which exist without our agency, may also bring the knowledge of the past within the reach of this same perception. This appears to be effected mainly, if not wholly, by means of association, which is an ar- rangement, or classification of our knowledge in con- formity to some observed relation, as that of cause and effect, or of antecedent and consequent ; or of some re- semblance, in which last may be included similarity as to time, or place ; and, by a slight extension, this will also embrace contiguity in time and space. But what- ever the rule, or principle of association, it seems that through it, an idea, or sensation in the present may suggest others in the past without any effort. The sen- sation I now have of a tree in sight recalls, or causes me to remember a sensation I had last week of a tree then in sight ; and this again suggests the fruit I saw upon it, &c. In this case, through external agencies — agencies not of the mind — the past knowledge has been OF MIND. 15 brought within reach of the simple mental perception. As in the case of simple sensation, the mind has been the recipient of knowledge without any active agency of its own ; and hence the case affords no ground to suppose an active agency in its memory, or in any other of its attributes. These views seem to justify the conclusion that the mind has but one real faculty, or power to do anything, and this faculty is designated by the term will ; that with this power it has a susceptibility to feeling, and also a capacity, or sense of simple mental perception, through which it becomes the recipient of knowledge ; and that all knowledge, whether the result of prelimi- nary effort, or otherwise, in the last analysis is a simple perception of the mind, and that all preliminary effort for its acquisition is only to bring about the conditions essential to such perception. We know that we have certain sensations without effort. "We attribute some of these to the instrumentality of the bodily senses ; but the sensation is in the mind ; and it is not the bodily sense that knows of its existence. Nor does it require any act of will to know it ; on the contrary, we cannot, by will, avoid knowing it. Here then is a faculty, or capacity of knowing ; of simple mental per- ception, or assimilation, as independent of the will as sensation itself. To proceed one step further; it is not the oodily sense which knows the difference between the sensations of black and white ; or of sound and color ; and we still are not conscious that to know this requires any effort. If we regard general and abstract ideas, in- stead of sensations, we may perhaps without previous effort know that what is, is ; that the whole is greater 16 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. than its part ; that two parallel lines cannot cross each other ; but we do not thus know that all the angles of every plane triangle are equal to two right angles ; to ascertain this, requires effort.* There must then some- where be a point at which acts of will become neces- sary to our acquisition of knowledge ; but the mind cannot by such action determine, or vary the facts, or its own conclusions in regard to them. If it could, it would then have no idea of absolute truth. The last result ; the finality of the process — the assimilation — being thus independent of the will, must come by the attribute of knowing, i. e. by simple mental percep- tion ; and the object of the effort of the mind is to re- call and so vary and arrange either its previous knowl- edge, or things external to it, that the truths sought will come within the range and scope of its simple per- ceptive power ; such effort, however, is not always needed, sensation sometimes performing this office, or the truths being in themselves obvious to simple per- ception, without effort. For instance, if an effort to remember is the effort to find some idea, which by as- sociation will recall, or lead through other associations to some particular knowledge of the past, this sugges- tive idea may sometimes be brought to mind by exter- nal events through sensation, without our effort ; or it may arise in some train of thought, which we are pur- suing for another purpose, without any intention or any effort to recall the past knowledge. In both cases the knowledge of the past is brought within reach of the mind's simple perceptive sense without effort for that end ; and the memory appears to act spontaneously as an independent power. The facts, however, do not * See Appendix, Note IV. OF MIND. 17 really conflict with the hypothesis that what we term an effort of memory is but a mode of effort of the mind, and that, in its efforts for recalling the past, prying into the future, or investigating abstract truth, it but exerts its own unit-power in different modes, and does not put other powers in action for that purpose. When, for the purpose of ascertaining truth, or of determining action, we call up and examine other knowledge, we deliberate ; and any conclusion, to which we thus come, is a judgment. This process may involve a secondary one of examining, or comparing various simple perceptions, which have resulted from various views of the subject, or from views of different portions of it. We often, and sometimes from the urgencies of the case, examine very hastily, while at others we do it very thoroughly. This leads us to speak of hasty con- clusions and deliberate judgments, the latter being the result of the more full examination of our knowledge relating to the subject. Though this judgment is a re- sult of an effort in the examination of our knowledge, it is immediately incorporated with and becomes a por- tion of it ; in this respect not differing from facts, or any other addition to our knowledge, acquired by mere observation, or simple mental perception without pre- vious effort. From the nature of the examination, or of the subject itself, these judgments vary from the slightest shade of probability to that of demonstrative certainty; and induce various grades of belief, from that of mere conjecture to confirmed knowledge ; but, such as they are, we are often obliged to act upon them from want of time, or of ability to obtain better. Of knowledge, obviously an important element in all intelligent cause, I will further remark, that I deem 18 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. the term, in strict propriety, applicable only to those ideas, or perceptions of the mind of which, we enter- tain no donbt ; and that it is applicable to snch, even though they are not conformable to truth ; for, if we cannot say that we know that of which we have no doubt, there is nothing to which we can apply the term, and it is useless. This is liable to the objection that we may know what is not true. Knowledge is a certain condition of the mind ; and there is no difference in this condition, whether we have an undoubted belief that 7x6 — 41, or that 2x2 = 4; the knowledge that 2x2 = 4, and -the fact that 2x2 = 4, are distinct ; and to make the latter a condition of the former is to define, or describe one thing, by attributing to it what belongs not to it, but to another distinct thing, which is unphil- osophical, and leads to confusion. When, however, I speak of the use which the mind makes of its knowledge in connection with its faculty of will, it is generally more convenient to embrace, in the one term, all its opinions and beliefs of every grade of probability, which, in the absence of certainty, it is often obliged to make the basis of action ; and, in such cases, I use the term with this latitude. Metaphysical certainty applies to that order of ideas and perceptions, or to that order of expressions, which we perceive to be necessarily true in their own nature, and the denial of which involves an obvious absurdity, or contradiction. CHAPTER IY. LIBEKTY, OR FREEDOM. These terms are, perhaps, as well understood as any by which we conld directly define them. The opposing terms are compulsion, control, con- straint and restraint ; and when the term necessity, as the antithesis of liberty, or freedom, is applied to the action of the mind in willing, it must imply that such action is compelled, controlled, constrained, or restrained. The question may arise, whether that which con- trols itself is free, or whether the fact of its being controlled, even though by itself, renders it not free. This question, in our present inquiry, concerns the action of the mind in willing ; but we may say, generally, that everything, in moving, or in acting ; in motion, or in action, must be directed and con- trolled in its. motion, or in its action, by itself, or by something other than itself; and that, of these two conditions of every thing moving, or acting ; or in motion, or action, the term freedom applies to the former rather than to the latter ; and if the term freedom does not apply to that condition, it can 20 FKEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. have no application to the acting, or the action of anything whatever. And hence, self-control 'is but another expression for the freedom of that which acts, or of the active agent ; and this is in conformity to the customary nse and the popular idea of the term freedom. CHAPTEK Y. OF CAUSE. The word Cause is variously used. I shall use it, in what I deem its most popular sense, as meaning any- thing which produces change. In this sense, four dis- tinct kinds of causes are conceivable : First, such as are both unintelligent and inactive; as a rock, which arrests the motion of a moving body, causing it to stop, or alter its direction. These we will call inert causes. Secondly, unintelligent, but active causes ; as a heavy body in motion, moving others in its course, but which does not intend, or know the effects it produces. These are motor causes. Thirdly, causes which produce changes by their activity, and which are not only conscious of the changes, when produced, but can anticipate the effects of their activity, yet do not plan, or design the means, or modes ofcproducing these effects ; as the lower forms of intelligent agents. These are instinctive causes. Fourthly, causes which produce changes by their activity, and not only anticipate and know the effects of their activity, but design and form plans to produce them. Of these God is the. type. They are originat- ing, or designing causes. 22 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. We might have divided the third class, making two others, one merely knowing the effects after they oc- cur ; the other only anticipating them ; but as we know of none in which the two are un combined, there is no necessity for including them in our classification. I mention the four varieties, just named, as conceiv- able and as embraced in the popular notion of cause. Whether they are all real causes may be a question for further inquiry. "We have then, of material causes, two kinds, inert and motor. The inert becomes cause only by being first acted upon *by the active, or motor cause. Each motor may also be inert cause in relation to other mo- tor causes, as when one motor impinges against another, the effect, in some cases, may not be influenced by the motion of this other, but be the same as if it were inert. We Lave of intelligent causes also two kinds, the instinctive and the designing. The former of these also becomes cause only by being first acted upon by the latter. The instinctive must first be informed by the designing cause, before it can become cause itself. The designing may include, or be associated with the in- stinctive ; and, sometimes acting without exercising the faculties by which it is capable of designing, manifest itself at such times only as instinctive cause. A definition, or statement is sometimes spoken of — I think improperly — as a cause, of which the logical consequence is the effect ; as, for instance, the equality of the four sides of a square causes those opposite each other to be parallel. Such consequences are necessary, self-existent, or co-existent truths ; which are found, or discovered, and not caused. OF CAUSE. 23 When we speak of time's changes, the expression is elliptical. We do not mean that the changes are effected by time itself as a cause ; but by those causes of which the effects are gradual, and percep- tible only after the lapse of some considerable periods of time. CHAPTER VI. OF THE WILL. It is not unusual to speak of the will as a distinct entity, possessing and exercising certain powers. This produces much confusion in the argument on the ." free- dom of the will." It is obviously the rnind that wills, as it is the mind that thinks ; and we might with as much propriety speak of a thought, which thinks, as of a will, that wills. In treating of mind (Chap. III.) I have already stated that there is a passive state, in which, without any active agency of its own, it may be the subject of sensations, and the recipient of knowl- edge. Also, that in another condition it seeks, or en- deavors to produce change by the active exercise of its power. In this the mind is said to will. Of these two conscious states of its existence, that of activity — that in which it strives to produce change — is a state of will- ing. The mind's willing, or its act of will, then, is the mind's effort ; and Will is the power, or faculty of the mind for effort. It is not a distinct thing, or in- strument, which the mind uses, but is only a name for a power, which the mind possesses ; and an act of will is that action, or mode in which intelligence exerts its power to do, or to try to do, and manifests itself as cause. The willing, or act of will, is the condition of OF THE WILL. 25 the mind in effort, and is the only effort of which we are conscious. In each individual the efforts are all by the same active agent — by the intelligent being — by the mind — but are classified as bodily and mental efforts ; the former being subdivided into efforts of the arm, the lungs, &c. ; and the latter into efforts of memory, of judgment, of imagination, &c* Mind — intelligence — has no property, or attribute by which it can be inert cause. It may be the passive subject of change by other active agencies, but can it- self be the cause of change only by the exercise of its power, i. e. by an effort. The existence of any mind with certain powers, may be among the circumstances which other intelligent agents take into consideration in their action, but it is only by its own effort that itself can do anything — that it can of itself produce any change, or be cause, f The mind has two very distinct spheres for the exer- cise of its activity — for its effort. In one it seeks to acquire knowledge ; in the other to mould the future. In the first it analyzes, combines and compares its ideas ; observes the present external ; recalls the past, and, by this use of its present knowledge, acquires more. It can thus not only learn abstract truths, but is enabled, with more or less of certainty, to anticipate the course of events, and to perceive in what it would, by effort, try to alter that course. In both cases it seeks to affect the future ; but in one case the effect is confined to changes in its own knowledge, to ascertain, or find what now is, has been, or will be ; in the other, it seeks to affect the succession of events, to change what now is and influence what will be. * See Appendix, Note V. f See Appendix, Note VI. 2 26 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WDLLINO. By means of its prophetic power, the mind reaches into that future in which by effort it seeks to produce effects. The success, or failure of the effort, however, cannot in any way affect the effort itself, which already has been. To the effects which the mind, by its ac- tivity, or effort, produces, it has the relation of cause, whether these effects were, or were not intended. By its influence upon the future, however proximate, by its active agency in creating that future, mind mani- fests its originating, creative power. In this, its finite sphere, every finite intelligence, of every grade — having the faculty of will — is a finite first cause, as the Su- preme Intelligence is Infinite First Cause, in its sphere of the infinite. The inquiry as to the truth of this po- sition is involved in the question, does the finite intelli- gence will freely ? which we are hereafter to examine. CHAPTEK VII OF WANT. The term want is probably better understood than any word, or phrase, which we conld select to define, or explain it. Nothing is better known to ns than onr wants. We nrast, however, in the use of the term, carefully distinguish between the want and the thing wanted ; between that present feeling, or condition, which is a state of want, and which we already have, and that which will gratify the want, and which, as yet, we have not. It is to the present condition, that I apply the term. We feel a painful sensation, or emo- tion, and want such change as will give relief. "We find that we are ignorant on a point upon which knowl- edge is, or may become useful, and we want to know ; and when, either from past experience, or intuition, we are conscious of the absence of a sensation, we may want that sensation. A sensation, or emotion is not, in itself, a want ; it may exist without any corresponding want. We may be content with it as it is. Nor is the perceived ab- sence of a sensation, or emotion, of itself, a want ; for we may be content with such absence. To get rid of an unpleasant sensation, which we have, or to induce an agreeable one, which we have not, are often the 28 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. things wanted, but are not themselves the want. We have the sensation of hunger, and want food, but nei- ther the sensation, nor the food is itself the want. In this case the food is the thing wanted, and the sensation is one of the conditions which causes us to want. This sensation, or emotion, in this, as in other cases, is to us an extension of knowledge, which requires on our part no effort. That the idea of change is essential to the want is very obvious in cases in which some absent sensation is the thing wanted. "When a present sensation is the subject, the want must either be to continue, to discard, or to modify that sensation ; and even the want to con- tinue requires the knowledge, or idea of possible change. So, too, an emotion is not in itself a want ; a joy, which so satisfies the mind that it neither desires, nor thinks of change, cannot be said to be a want. And there is a grief — a holy and unselfish grief — of the elevating and hallowing influences of which we are so conscious, that we would not banish, or modify it. Our admira- tion may be so pleasurably excited by what appears to us already perfect, that no change is suggested, or wanted in the sensation, or the object. Wonder, of itself, in- volves no idea of change, and no want ; and, under the emotion of awe, we reverently shrink from all thought, or anticipation of change. Want involves an idea of change. We must, at least, be able to conceive that by some change in what exists, the pain we feel will be discarded, or the knowl- edge which we seek, or the pleasure we covet be ac- quired ; though we may not know by what means the desired change is to be effected. The existence then, of this idea of change, seems in OF WANT. 29 all cases to be an essential element of want. A man, entirely satisfied' with things as they are, cannot prop- erly be said to have a want. It is true, we say, that such a man wants things to remain as they are. The expression is really equivalent to saying he wants noth- ing, i. e. does not want — he is content. If it really expresses any want, it is the want of such change as will ensure things remaining as they are, and relieve him of any apprehension that they may not so remain. This can amount to no more than that, to make certain the continuance of some things as they are, he wants change in some other things ; which is to say, he is not satisfied with things as they are. It may be convenient to classify wants into primary, or those the gratification of which is the final object, or end in view ; and secondary, or those which relate only to the intermediate means of such gratification, and to what is not in itself wanted. A man, in imminent dan- ger, to get to a safe place, may want to walk, though every step is painful : to reach the place of safety is the ' primary want ; to walk, in such case, the second- ary. The lust of power is, perhaps, always a second- ary want ; being wanted not for itself, but as a means of gratifying other wants. These secondary wants, however, seem also to belong to the mind's perception of the means of gratifying its primary wants, and, as such, may with as much propriety be classified with its knowledge as with its wants. They are knowledge, or at least belief, that by some act, perhaps not in it- self wanted, that which is wanted may be attained. Again, wants may be divided into natural, acquired and cultivated. Natural wants are those which are innate, constitutional. Hunger, or the want of food is 30 FKEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. a natural want. But we may want to be hungry for the sake of the enjoyment which attends its gratifica- tion ; and this want to be hungry, supposing it to grow out of the acquired knowledge that hunger is a basis of the enjoyment, may be said to be an acquired want. If we take exercise, or adopt other means to induce the want of food, such want may be said to be a cultivated want ; and from this low, material form, our cultivated wants may rise to the most ethereal aspirations of our aesthetic, moral and religious nature. We speak of them merely as cultivated, for they still have their root in the constitution of our being ; and we only use our knowledge of means to bring them out, or give them vitality and force, when they would, otherwise, be dor- mant or sluggish. That which we have spoken of as a secondary want, is a consequence of our perception of what is necessary to gratify, a primary want; and is thus the offspring of the primary want, and the knowledge of the means of gratifying it. As our primary wants and knowledge may exist without our volition, the conse- quent secondary want also may. We cannot, by an act of will, directly change the perceived fact, or our knowledge of the means essential to a particular result. The natural, or innate want is obviously not an effect of volition. An acquired want must result from some increase of knowledge. If w T e made effort, and increased our knowledge for the purpose of acquiring this want, we must have previously wanted it, and the acquired want, in such case, was, before its acquisition, the thing wanted, and not the w 7 ant which we sought to gratify. If we accidentally acquired such want without OF WA2TT. 31 intending it, it has come without our willing it ; and though it may have been a consequence of our efforts for some other purpose, it is such a consequence as we did not foresee, and for which we have made no effort. It may be such a result as, had we foreseen it, we would have opposed ; but not having foreseen it, it is an effect, which we have neither favored, nor opposed. As the influence of an actually existing want upon the will is not varied by the source, or cause of its existence, it will not, in treating of it in this connection, often be necessary to allude to these distinctions. CHAPTER VIII. OP MATTER AS CAUSE. Whatever changes take place in matter must arise from its motion, either massive, or atomic. But matter has no power to move itself ; and hence cannot become cause of such change, except by first being in motion ; and, even if imbued with locomotive powers, would have no knowledge to direct its movements to produce any given effect ; and, if possessing both these attri- butes, being destitute of sensation and emotion, would have no inducement to make effort to produce any ef- fect, supposing it also to have a faculty of will. It is plain then, that matter cannot be an originating cause, even of its own movements ; and hence, if changes in it ever had a beginning, they must have originated with intelligence. I say, if they ever had a beginning ; but we have still to inquire whether matter, even if once put in motion, could produce effects, or change other matter, or be affected, or changed by other matter, from the mere circumstance of its being itself in motion ; in short, whether, in motion, matter becomes cause, origi- nating effects, or prolonging, or extending the effects of any intelligent action, which may have put it in mo- tion. The mere change of place by motion* cannot * See Appendix, Note VII. OF MATTER AS CAUSE. 33 be considered as an effect of motion, but, rather, as the motion itself. If it is an effect of motion, canse and effect are here blended in one. The only reason why matter in motion can become cause of any other effect than that which took place immediately on the com- mencement of its motion, is, that by time and motion the circumstances become changed, though matter can- not intend, or know of this change. If, with motion, it can become cause, then, though it never could have commenced its own motion, yet, as in considering intel- ligence as cause, we are obliged to regard it, in the ab- stract, as a necessary existence, which had no beginning, so we might also suppose that matter had been in mo- tion from eternity, and hence always had in itself caus- ative power. Whether matter in motion, can of itself produce ef- fects, seems to depend mainly on another question, viz.: Does matter in motion, of necessity, have a tendency to continue in motion, or to stop the moment it is relieved from all impelling power ? If I throw a ball, after it leaves my hand I can no longer control it ; I make no effort to control it ; it continues to move even though my attention is wholly withdrawn from it. But whether it does so move, because to stop requires change which, being mere matter, it cannot effect ; or whether it continues to move in conformity to a law, which the Supreme Intelligence has adopted for its own govern- ment, and by which, in certain cases, it uniformly exe- cutes the decree, or causes certain effects to follow the effort of the finite mind, even after that effort has ceased ; in brief, whether it continues to move by its own inherent material force, or by the action upon it of 2* 34: FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. an invisible intelligence, or cause, is a question, which I can find no means of determining. A particle of matter can begin no change in itself. When put in motion does it require change in itself to stop, or to continue its motion ? If the former, then a moving body has in itself the amount of power which is required to stop it ; and when it comes in collision with another body, as the two, by a law of metaphysi- cal necessity, cannot occupy the same space, some effect must be produced ; for instance, if moving in opposite directions, in the same line, one must be stopped, or turned back, or if the forces are equal we may, perhaps, infer that both must of necessity stop. The ball thrown obliquely, after leaving my hand, if in vacuum, moves in a parabolic curve ; or if resisted by the air, in an irregular curve. This, in either case, involves a continued change of direction, and it may be asked how matter, undirected by intelligence, can con- form its changes of direction to these curves, or indeed, how change its direction at all % If, however, matter in motion has power to stop, retard, or change the motion of other bodies ; or is liable to be stopped, retarded, or changed by them, it is conceivable, as has-been sug- gested, that such change may be produced, and the pro- jectile kept in the particular curve by particles of mat- ter moving through space, and impinging on one side of the projectile, while the earth protects the other side from similar influence ; once admit the self-existent, or inherent force, and its application is quite conceivable. The line of motion is changed from the parabolic to the irregular curve by the body itself impinging against the particles of the atmosphere. As any force of matter in motion depends upon its OF MATTER AS CAUSE. 35 supposed tendency to continue in motion ; and it being evident that some of the bodies, coming in direct oppo- sition to each other with equal force, must be stopped ; and that matter has no power to put itself in motion again, it follows that the power of that portion thus stopped is annihilated ; and the power of matter being thus continually diminishing, must, with sufficient time, be eventually destroyed, or, at least, be reduced to an infinitesimal quantity.* But, if matter is an originating cause, or power, in- dependent of intelligence, it must, as we have before shown, be so in virtue of having been in motion from all eternity ; and hence, there having been sufficient time, its power, from the cause just mentioned, must have been destroyed. It follows then, that any power which matter may now have, in consequence of its being in motion — supposing it to have any — must be either the result of its having been put in motion within a finite time by intelligence, or from intelligence subse- quently sustaining and renewing the motion, which may have been from eternity, f If this supposed power of matter in motion were left to act uncontrolled by intel- ligence, its blind activity would accelerate its self-de- struction, and must, in some instances, counteract itself by opposition, while in others its effects would be in- creased by co-operation of the forces. The observed uniformity of material effects is inconsistent with this blind exercise of power ; indicating that, even if matter now has, or has had power of itself, as cause, to produce effects, it has been subjected to an intelligent control — to a designing cause — and that all such effects are now the result of intelligent action. * See Appendix, Note VIII. f See Appendix, Note IX. 36 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. The argument on this point may be thus stated : admitting the existence of matter as a distinct entity ; and that it has always existed, we know, as a fact of observation, that the motion of one portion is always affected and often destroyed in producing effects upon other portions. ISTow, further admitting, that its origi- nal state was that of motion, it must always have been with its present conditions, or the original conditions of its motion must have been changed. If it com- menced with the present conditions, which would con- tinually lessen its motion, then, with sufficient time, and an eternity must be sufficient, its motion would be destroyed, or reduced to an infinitesimal and inappre- ciable quantity ; and hence, on this supposition, the in- terference of some other — of intelligent cause — must have been necessary to sustain any appreciable power in matter, as cause. And if we adopt the other hypothesis, that its mo- tion was originally subject to other conditions than those which are now observed, then this change in its conditions, or mode of action, could not have been effected by matter itself, but must be attributed to in- telligence, as the only other conceivable cause. So that, whether matter in motion was, or was not, origi- nally subject to its present conditions, its present in- fluence, by means of motion, must result either from intelligence sustaining its motion, or from its controll- ing that which is inherent. And, except on the hypo- thesis that the tendency of matter once put in motion is to continue in motion and not to stop, this control by intelligence must be direct and immediate ; for upon no other hypothesis can intelligence make matter a means of producing or even of prolonging effects, after OF MATTER AS CAUSE. 37 its own action upon it is discontinued. The matter would stop when that action left it, and no change would take place in it till farther action of intelligence again moved it. Nor, without the further hypothesis that the effects of matter in motion are necessary, can we either sup- pose that without the power of selection — without pur- pose — these effects would either be uniform, or yet vary in any respect. They must arise from the neces- sities of the case ; as, for instance, the impossibility of two impinging bodies occupying the same space ; and some effect must thus be absolutely necessary, or none would be produced. Still, as in most, if not all con- ceivable cases, more than one effect seems possible, as when two bodies impinge, both may stop, or one turn back ; some power which can select, seems essential to the uniform ordering of the effects. This consideration exposes one difficulty in supposing that which is unin- telligent to be cause at all ; or to be anything more than an instrument used by an intelligent cause. Nor could intelligence make matter cause, or increase its causative power, and make it capable of selecting its own effects, or of beginning a change, or a series of changes, by impressing laws upon it for its govern- ment ; for, to be governed immediately by law, pre- supposes a knowledge of the law, i. e., intelligence on the part of the governed. If all matter were at this moment quiescent, it could not of itself, in virtue of any law, begin a change. To do this it must move itself. But more especially could it not so move itself as to produce a particular effect at a particular time. This would require it not only to have power to move itself, but to know when to move, 38 FKEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. and how to direct its movement ; all which, as matter is inert and unintelligent, is contradictory, and hence impossible even to infinite power. All that can be meant when we refer an event to the " nature of things," or to the " laws of natnre " is, that tl^e intelligence, which causes these events, is itself the subject of laws, under which it acts uniformly in its changes of matter ; and all those changes in matter, which begin to be, must be attributed to the action of spirit ; and, of course, such of them as are not caused by a finite, must be referred to the action of the Infinite Intelligence. And however difficult the conception may at first ap- pear, there seems no way to avoid the necessity of this constant exercise of creative energy to begin change, or produce uniform results ; or the conclusion that every particle which floats in the breeze, or undulates in the wave ; every atom which changes its position in conformity to the laws of electrical attraction and re- pulsion, or of chemical affinities, is moved, not by the energizing, but by the energetic will of God.* From these views we may infer that matter cannot, without the aid of intelligence, be an active cause even of changes in itself. It ,can produce no activity in itself, and any imparted activity is diminished in producing effects ; nor can it, even if in virtue of a derived ac- tivity it becomes an active cause, select and effect such changes as will conform to the will and wants of intelli- gence ; nor yet directly impart activity to it as one body appears to do in regard to another ; though, as desirable, it may be the object, and, as admitting of desirable changes in itself, it may be the subject of intelligent action. Any observed changes of matter * See Appendix, Note X. OF MATTER AS CAUSE. 39 vary the circumstances presented to the intelligence, which, in virtue of its power to judge of and to con- form to these circumstances, varies its action accord- ingly. In this way, one intelligence having the power to produce changes in matter, may, by such changes, influence the action of another intelligence ; but, in such case, matter is but a means, a mere instrument, by which one intelligence communicates with, or produces effects on another, and not a cause of those effects.* It is true that we loosely speak of matter, or of cir- cumstances, as cause ; and to this we have been led by observing the uniformity with which certain phenomena follow certain conditions, or changes of matter. We generalize the facts, deduce the law, and then ascribe directly to that law what we should ascribe to the in- telligence whose uniform action makes, or is the ground of our inferring, the law. Science has now made us so familiar with these generalizations, called secondary causes, that we habitually accept them as the ultimate of our inquiries, without tracing them to a first cause, that can begin a series of effects. Even supposing that matter has been in motion from all eternity ; that the tendency is to continue in motion and not to stop ; and consequently that it has power to produce effects, and that this power continues undiminished through all time ; still, as these effects must be necessary effects, and matter has no power to vary them, they may be of necessity, as they are in fact, uniform, not less so than if produced in conformity ,to the laws, which the Supreme Intelligence, on the other hypothesis, has adopted for his government of matter ; and hence, by observation, we may learn * See Appendix, Note XI. 40 FEEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. equally well to calculate on the certainty, or proba- bility of the effects ; and, as in either case they make but a part of the circumstances on which the finite in- telligence acts, whether the causes of these circum- stances are material or intelligent, can make no differ- ence to the intelligent cause, which is to act in con- junction with such other causes, or in view of the changes by them, which it can anticipate. The change of circumstances actually produced, or expected, will have the same influence on the mind in willing, or upon its freedom in willing, if produced by the one cause as if by the other. If all matter were quiescent, then the action of in- telligent cause to produce change on it would be to move it. If it were in motion, producing changes in an established order, which the acting intelligence could anticipate, then the action of the intelligent cause must be to vary this established order ; and the problem, as to its proper action to produce a given result, becomes more difficult and intricate, requiring the exercise of more contrivance, or of judgment to determine that action ; but whether that established order of external changes arises from the necessary effects of matter in motion, or from the free efforts of some intelligent cause, designing such uniformity as will admit of its effects being anticipated, can make no difference to the intelligence, which makes effort to vary that known established order. Again, if all matter were quiescent, it could not begin motion in itself, and, of course, could not be cause. If it were in motion, it could not determine or select its own effects, and if certain consequences of necessity resulted, it would have no power to vary, or OF MATTER AS CAUSE. 41 to produce changes in those consequences, and so far could not be cause. That which produces effects, which it cannot but produce, must be constrained to produce them by some power which it cannot control ; and, in such case, the power which constrains is more properly the cause, and the subject which is constrained, its in- strument. It appears, then, that matter cannot possibly be cause, except by means of motion ; and whether it can then become cause depends upon the question, as to its tendency to continue in motion, or to stop, which is undetermined. But if, with motion, it has power to effect change, still, every application of that power to an effect, diminishes it ; and as to make matter an inde- pendent cause, and not merely an instrument used by some other cause, we must consider it as having been in motion from all eternity, this diminution by use must have exhausted its causative power ; and further, that in any event, if matter be quiescent, or if it be in motion, producing changes in a necessary estab- lished order, it cannot be a cause of changes either in that quiescent, or yet in the established order of changes ; or begin any new series of changes ; and that, to effect such changes, or to begin any new series of changes, spirit is the only competent power or cause. CHAPTEK IX. OF SPIRIT AS CAUSE. In postulating thought and effort, we have already assumed the inherent activity of spirit, that is, its power to produce changes, or, at least, to endeavor to do so. If we have now shown that matter cannot, in the proper sense of the word, be cause, or have an inherent and inhering power to produce change, or that it could not retain such power ; and that it cannot originate or begin a series of effects, or, of itself, have retained any power to continue an established series, or yet to alter such established series ; we must infer that spirit, if not the only real, is an indispensable cause. The question next arises, whether this causative power of spirit is all concentrated in one Supreme Intelligence, or whether there is a sphere in which the finite intelligence is also an active, originating cause, using its attributes to create, or change, uncontrolled by the Infinite, or any external power. This question is closely connected with the main question which we are to consider, and, at this stage of the argument, we can only state our position, viz. : That one Supreme Intelligence has power, and, if He chose, might exert the power to create and sustain all that exists in the sphere of the infinite. But that, OF SPIRIT AS CAUSE. 43 within this infinite sphere, He has allotted a finite sphere for the action of finite intelligences ; that He has adapted that sphere to the action of such finite in- telligences, by furnishing it with circumstances, and by conforming His own actions to such uniform modes, that the finite intelligence, acting either through the power of the infinite thus uniformly exerted, or with reference to His future action, may be able to anticipate the result of its own efforts, and to direct those efforts, or to will, accordingly. The human intelligence thus acts freely with the assent and co-operation of the in- finite ; unaided by which, though possessed of powers similar to the infinite, its action would be restricted within very narrow limits. Let us more particularly note this similarity of kind and variation in degree. God is omnipotent ; man has finite power. God is omniscient ; man has finite knowledge of the present and past, and can, in some degree, anticipate the future. God is omnipresent ; man has faculties by which he can make everything within his finite sphere of knowledge, past, present, and future, present to himself ; and, therefore, may be said to have a finite presence commensurate with his knowl- edge, i. e., man has a finite presence, which has the same relation to omnipresence, that his knowledge has to omniscience.* God has a creative power, and this seems to be fully embraced in the faculties of thought, imagination, and conception, with the power of fixing the thoughts, imaginings, and conceptions, in His own mind, and making them palpable to others, either im- mediately, by transferring this thought and imagery directly to finite minds, or mediately, by depicting or * See Appendix, Note XII. 44: FREEDOM OF MIND IN WELLING. forming them in matter, and thus making them palpa- ble to other intelligent, percipient beings. If mattei, as a separate substance, exists, and was not created by, bnt is co-eternal with intelligence, then all the creative power of God, as manifested in the material universe, maj be confined to mere changes in matter ; and man has the same power in a finite measure. If there is no such separate existence as matter, then material crea- tion is but the imagery of the mind of God made palpa- ble to us ; and man here, also, has the same creative power in a finite measure. The creation of matter, as a substance distinct from spirit, seems to be entirely beyond the power of man. He has no faculty even to conceive of any possible mode of such creation. But, as all material phenomena can be as well accounted for, without supposing matter to be created, by either of the two modes just suggested, i. e., either by considering matter as co-external with spirit, or as an emanation, or a mere effect of the action of intelligence, we cannot, from its existence or phenomena, infer that it was created. And if we cannot conceive of any possible mode of its creation, nor infer such creation from its existence, nor from any of the phenomena of its exist- ence, we can have no proof that any being possesses the power to create it ; and the phenomena of the material creation furnish no proof of any great attri- bute of the Infinite mind, which is not also found, in some degree, in the finite. Whether, then, we adopt the one or the other of the two hypotheses of creation just alluded to, the creative power of any being, so far as we can have any knowl- edge of it, is all embraced in these two powers, to both of which knowledge is a prerequisite, — first, that of OF SPIRIT AS CAUSE. 45 thinking, imagining, or conceiving the forms, appear- ances, relations, and changes, which constitute creation ; and secondly, that of impressing these forms, and ap- pearances, and relations, and changes upon its own and upon other minds. The finite mind has both these powers in a limited degree, and, we should say, the latter in less proportion than the former. The finite intelligence can collect all within its sphere of knowledge, and, by analyzing and recombining, form for itself such a new creation at will, as, on delibera- tion, its judgment or fancy may dictate. It forms this creation first in idea, in its own mind, and then decides whether or not to make further effort to give perma- nency, or outward actuality, to these internal creations. The limit of its knowledge is the boundary of that finite sphere, in which the finite intelligence, with its co-ordinate finite presence, is creative with its finite power and its fallibility, as the Supreme Intelligence, with its omnipresence, its infinite power and its infalli- bility, is creative in its infinite sphere. Every time a finite intelligence, by an act of will, forms a conception of thought, things, and circumstan- ces, in new combinations, or in new relations ; that is, every time, by effort, he conceives change in the phenomena within his finite sphere of knowledge, it is to him a new creation of his own, which, by other efforts, other exercise of will, other creations, he may, at least in some cases, make palpable or depict to other intelligences. I will add that this creative power is exerted by the finite in the only way in which we can conceive of its exercise by the Infinite Intelligence, and under the same conditions. Either must exert the power from a desire 46 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. to produce some change, from a feeling of want. By meann of its knowledge, or by the exercise of its know- ing faculties, it is enabled to form conceptions of the effects of its contemplated efforts before it puts them forth, and to vary these conceptions till it finds one adapted to the want ; and, in the case of the finite mind, one which it supposes is within the scope of its finite means and power to actualize by its finite efforts. This often makes a very complicated problem, in which all the powers of the mind find an appropriate and im- proving exercise. It is in the mind's preconceptions of the effects of its efforts, in relation to its previous wants, that it finds the reason for its action. It may be said, that the creative power in finite in- telligences is of a secondary character, and limited to producing changes, or new combinations, in the crea- tions of the Supreme Intelligence. In regard to mat- ter, if a distinct entity, this is merely saying that we mould our thoughts, or conceptions in the same mate- rial which God has previously used for a like purpose. Any of us can imagine a landscape, and vary it as we choose. We can even imagine a universe, and one varying from that which is the subject of our observa- tion. We can conceive of one in which all the bodies should be in the form of cubes, cones, double cones, or prisms, &c, &c, and all stationary, or moving in orbits, hexagonal, or epicycloidal, &c, &c. ; and this, for the time being, is, to him who conceives it, a new creation, perhaps distinguishable from that creation which, not resulting from his own efforts, is without him, only by the fact that one is subject to be changed or annihilated by his own effort or will, or by his ceas- ing to will, and the other is not. If the material uni- OF SPIRIT AS CAUSE. 47 verse is but the thought and imagery of the mind of God, made directly palpable, it no doubt is in the same manner subject to change and annihilation by an act of His will, or a suspending of it. So far as the indi- vidual is concerned, the imagery, which he, by his finite powers, has willed into existence, is, while he so wills its existence, a real creation.* But when we at- tempt to transfer this imagery of our own to other minds, we find that our power of doing so is very limit- ed in regard to the amount of imagery we can so trans- fer ; the completeness or precision of the transferred images, and the number of other minds upon which we can impress them. Though we may have created the imagery by a direct act of will, we cannot thus transfer it to other minds, but only by slow, circuitous and ten- tative processes or efforts ; some, however, doing it with much more facility than others. "We can, by effort, change matter with more or less of accuracy, in conformity to certain ideas in our minds ; and the change, under certain conditions, will be im- pressed on the minds of some others. The rudest and least gifted intellect can do something of this ; while superior genius is able, not only to conceive of the grand, the beautiful, the tranquil, or the terrific, but to make these creations recognizable and enduring by so portraying them in language, picturing them on can vas, or carving them in marble, that they will long be palpable to many other minds. But, to make the con- ceptions of a Raphael thus palpable, requires an almost countless number of efforts, before the pre-requisite con- ditions, by which it is perfected and exhibited on the * See Appendix, Note XIII. 48 FKEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. canvas, are completed — before his creation becomes a palpable, tangible reality to other men ; though superior intelligences may have perceived the original forma- tion, as it existed in his mind, without the aid of the external means, by which it penetrates through our ob- tuseness. The finite intelligence may create new forms and new combinations. It can conceive a pleasing land- scape, and therein create not only new combinations, but new thought and new beauty, and exhibit it to others. The poet, through the medium of language, does this. The painter, with his pencil, also. The florist, with his spade, does the same. All create new forms, new combinations, new beauty ; and, by their different modes, impress their creations on other minds. The efforts of the florist are most palpably made in reference to the aid of the Supreme Intelligence, acting by uniform modes, of which he has acquired a knowl- edge, and by which his own designs are executed, — his finite efforts made effective. But the painter is really hardly less dependent upon this same extrinsic aid, for the successful exhibition of his ideal creations, in a tangible form, to others. The poet, though still dependent on this uniformity for the means of making his conceptions palpable, seems to be less so than either of the others. There is less intervening between his conceptions and our percep- tions' of them. He issues the fiat, " let there be light," and his creation flashes upon us. It is in the purest forms of poetry — those in which the words seem to vanish and leave the unalloyed thought and imagery of the poet, as if flowing directly from his mind OF SPIRIT AS CAUSE. 49 to our own — that we can most readily realize that mode of creation in the Supreme Intelligence, which we have supposed to be a direct impression of the creative conceptions of the Infinite upon the finite mind. Whether our mental creations are made palpable by means of some direct, but unperceived connection be- tween our efforts and their outward manifestation, or through the uniform modes of God's action, is not material as to the question of our power to make them manifest. If such manifestation only follows our efforts, it identifies the power to produce the effect, with our power to make the effort. But the finite mind, in its present condition, can thus impart, and give, even a qualified durability to a very small portion of its con- ceptions. Whether, in a farther stage of its progress, this means of imparting to others will be increased, as its present disproportion to our powers of conception would seem to indicate, is a question not within the scope of our present inquiry ; and we content ourselves with the conclusion, that here and now, the finite mind of man, made in the image of God, has finite powers corresponding to omnipotence, omniscience, omnipres- ence, and other creative attributes of the Infinite ; and, so far as we can know, exerts these powers in the same mode and under the same conditions ; that is, it has wants, it has a faculty of effort, or will, by which to endeavor to gratify those wants ; and it has knowledge, which enables it to form preconceptions of the future effects of those efforts, and to judge as to what effort to make, and thus determine that effort and the consequent effect, as in itself a creative first CAUSE.* * See Appendix, Note XIY. 50 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WELLING. Whether the finite mind, in the exercise of these powers, is independent of, or is controlled by the In- finite, or by other powers, or forces, is a question in- volved in that of the freedom of the mind in willing, which we will now proceed to consider. CHAPTER X. FREEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. As the will is very frequently spoken of as a distinct entity, so, as a logical consequence, it is not uncommon to speak of the " freedom of the will." This opens the way for the argument, that the will is dependent upon, and is controlled by the mind ; and, hence, is not free, producing much confusion ; whereas, the real question, and that which involves the important consequences of human responsibility, regards only the freedom of the being that wills — whose responsibility is supposed to be affected by the condition of freedom, or necessity. The inquiry should then be, not is the will free, but, does the mind, the soul, will freely f In reference to this question, it is not material whether the effect we seek to produce when we will, follows our volition, or not. We may not have the power to do what we will, and yet may freely will to do. There may be no such connection as we supposed between the volition and the intended result ; our knowledge may have been deficient, our deductions erroneous. If that result was in any degree dependent on other causes or forces, as the motion of matter, or the action of other intelligences, we may have been mis- taken in our anticipations of those movements or ac- 52 FEEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. / tions ; or have made wrong inferences, as to their in- fluence or effects. However this may be, it is manifest that the subsequent result cannot control the volition, which already is, or has been ; the actual effect cannot control its cause, after that cause has been exerted. Of that mysterious connection between the effort and its consequences, we know nothing beyond the fact that, under certain conditions, the latter more or less uni- formly follow the former. If, in a normal and natural condition of my being, I will to move my hand, it moves. If I will to throw from it a ball, the ball moves and even continues to move after my mind has ceased to act in regard to it. Now, whether the move- ment of my hand, and of the ball, while in it, arises from some direct, but latent connection between my mind and my hand ; and whether the ball continues to move, after my mind has ceased to will in regard to it, in virtue of some power inherent in matter or some necessary principle of motion ; or whether, all beyond my willing is to be ascribed to the action of some other intelligence, ever present and ever active and efficient, are questions which I have already alluded to as unde- termined. The last we know of our own agency in producing change, is our act of will, or effort to effect it. We know that the change follows this willing with more or less of certainty ; but why it so follows we do not know. We may intuitively or experimentally fore- know what effects will probably follow certain efforts, but, beyond the effort, we know nothing of ourselves as the cause of these effects. For every intelligent act, or every act of an intelli- gent being, as such, there must be an object, a reason for its acting, rather than its not acting. To suppose in- FKEEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. 53 telligence to act, and yet not know any object or reason for its acting, is to suppose it to act without intelli- gence, and if there is no intelligence involved, or con- cerned in the act, the action, if any there can be, must be wholly independent of the intelligence ; or, which is the same thing, of any exercise of intelligence by the intelligent agent or being ; which, in the case of its willing, would involve the contradiction of its being passive in its own action. It would also make a case in which that which is unintelligent moves itself. To suppose any being to will any particular act, and yet know no reason or object for that act, is either to suppose a change, or an effect, without any cause ; or that this act of will is directed by some cause, without the being that wills. But, as will hereafter more fully appear, there is no^ possible way in which any power, external to the agent that wills, can affect the direction of this willing, except by causing him to know some reason, or object for such direction. Intelligence in acting, then, must have an object. The object of its action must be an effect which it wants to produce. The mind, acting intelligently, will not make an effort, or will to produce an effect, which it does not want to produce. Every volition, then, must arise from the feeling or perception of some want, bodily, or mental ; otherwise there is no object of effort. This want may be that of food, of knowledge, of muscular movement, or of mental effort, in some of the various modes before indicated, or merely a want of change from the present state of things. But though the want suggests change, it does not indicate the mode of effecting it. A mere sensation, or perception, attended by a 54 FKEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. desire for change, but with no knowledge as to the mode of producing that change, points equally in all directions, furnishing to the mind no indications of the means of effecting the change. It, so far, furnishes no ground or reason to the mind to suppose that effort is the means, or that any particular effort will tend to the desired effect, any more than to the contrary. The mind must have some additional knowledge as to the mode. With the want, which, as before stated, is com- pounded of feeling and the knowledge that some change is desirable, must be associated the further knowledge of what change, and the means of effecting that change. The knowledge that effort is the means by which we must effect change generally, is innate ; as probably also all that knowledge which is essential to existence, and especially that Which is thus essential in the earlier stages of being. If the first want is that of breath, or of food, the knowledge of the means of gratifying it probably accompanies the want. The infant breathes, and knows, at least, how to swallow, if it does not also know how to find the source of its nourishment in its mother's breast, and later in life want is developed, with which, without any agency of our own, is as- sociated the knowledge of the mode of its gratifi- cation. Again, as the circumstances under which the want may exist may be very different, there must be some power of adaptation to them. Suppose, for instance, a man being hungry, knows that by walking a few steps to the north he can find bread to relieve his want ; but he becomes hungry when he is in a different position, requiring him to walk a few steps south to get the bread. The first step, in such cases, when the knowl- FEEEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. 55 edge is not an immediate mental perception, is to ex- amine the circumstances. This is a preliminary effort of the mind to obtain more knowledge with which to direct its final action. But this effort also requires some previous knowledge. We must know something before we will to know more. As preparatory to such effort, we must at least know that more knowledge is desirable, and that to examine is the mode of acquiring it. And this previous knowledge must either be intui- tive, or acquired through the senses without effort. In the latter case its acquisition would be merely acciden- tal, and the mere passive observation of events is so en- tirely different from an effort to examine, that the latter could never be inferred or learned from the former ; and if so, then the knowledge that we must examine the circumstances, in order to know how to adapt our final effort to them, is probably intuitive. If it is not, the infant, in seeking its mother's breast, must do it by knowledge imparted to it in each particular case as it occurs, and adapted to the peculiar circumstances of that case. If we suppose it only to know the mode of muscular movement, and that, under any circum- stances, it may succeed, by moving its head, or turn- ing its eyes, first in one way and then in another, till it finds the right direction, such movements of the head, or of the eye, are but modes of examining the circumstances in regard to which there must have been some pre-existing knowledge, at least, that by such movements there is a possibility of finding the object sought, i. e., must know that an effort to examine is the mode of attaining its ob- ject. If the mind has no knowledge in any degree, — no expectation — that by effort it can accomplish the 56 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. object, it is, to it, the same as if it had no object of its effort. It may be only the knowledge, that we need more knowledge properly to direct the effort to gratify the want, or that, by effort, we may possibly effect some change, which change may possibly be a desirable one. With such certainty, probability, or hope, we make the effort, i. e., we will. We have here, then, in want and knowledge com- bined, the source in which volitions originate, and the means by which mind, in virtue of its intelligence, gives them direction. Without want, the mind would have no object to accomplish by effort ; without knowl- edge, it would have no means of directing its efforts to the accomplishment of that object. Without want and knowledge, the mind would never manifest itself in effort, or self-action ; and hence, if without them it could be cause at all, it would be only blind cause, like matter. Its want furnishing an object of action, and its knowledge, enabling it to determine what action, are all that distinguish the mind from unintelligent cause, or force ; for even if without them it could will at all, it would will blindly, as matter moves, and without any more reference to its effects. As want is compounded of feeling and knowledge, these sources of volition are resolvable into an intelligent or knowing being, with a faculty of will and a susceptibility to feeling ; in other words, into a cause, which itself perceives the effect it would produce, i. e., wliat it would do, or at least try to do ; knows the means, and is conscious of its ability to do, or to try to do it ; and at least believes that its effort may possibly be successful. The want does not, generally, arise from our voli- tion. We may want, we do want, without effort to FKEEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. 57 Want. The mind could not begin its action by willing a want, unless there was first a want of that want. As already shown, without some want to be gratified by its act of will, the mind would not will at all. It would not will for the mere purpose of exercising its will, unless such exercise of will were itself a previous want ; the want must precede the action of the will to gratify it, and must, in the first place, come by the act of God, immediately, or mediately through the constitu- tion of our being. As we may want without effort, so also we may Jcnow that we want without effort, for we cannot want without knowing it. It has before been shown that the want itself involves the knowledge of a desirable change, and that some of our knowledge, and especially some of that which we acquire through the senses, comes to us not only without effort, but could not be prevented by pur direct effort. Any intuitive knowledge which we may have, must also exist in us without effort to obtain it. To these pre-requisites of effort — want and knowl- edge — no antecedent effort, then, is necessary. They may both exist without it. We cannot directly will either ; but may will to use means by which to produce them in us. It is not necessarily, by an act of will, that we see and thus Jcnow that a heavy body is approaching us, or that we Jcnow that we are in danger from it, or that we want to avoid it, or that we know the means of avoiding it, and how to adopt the known means, i. e., to make an effort to move. With such knowledge and want, the first effort of the mind may be to make the bodily movement ; bnt, if we suppose it not yet to know in which direction to move, but to know that the mode of learning this is to examine the circumstances, 3* 58 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. i. e., by further observation or reflection, then its first effort will be to examine. A want may itself be the object wanted ; we may want a want, as we want an apple ; and the want that already is, may be the occasion of our willing in regard to the attainment of the want, which is the ob- ject desired ; as the want of the apple is the occasion of the effort to obtain the apple. For instance, we may want to be hungry, i. e. 9 want to want food, that we may enjoy the pleasure which arises from gratifying hunger. In such case we must distinguish between the secondary want, which, like the apple, is but the object of our effort, and that primary want, which excited us to make the effort, and for the gratification of which the secondary is required. As the apple is not itself flie want, but the thing wanted, so also, in the case just supposed, the hunger, or want of food, is not itself the want, but is the thing wanted. But, though we do not make, or cause, this primary or exciting want, it is our want that we feel, and not the want of another. The same of knowledge ; we do not make the fact, or the truth, or the evidence of it. The most we can do is to seek that which already is ; and the moment we find, or know it, it is our knowledge, let the source from whence derived be what it may. For intuitive knowl- edge we do not even have to seek. The want is, while it lasts, a fixed existence in the mind, demanding effort for its gratification or relief.* The knowledge becomes a portion of the mental appa- ratus, by which the mind directs its efforts ; every in- crease of its knowledge increasing its means of accom- plishing its purposes and enabling it to direct its efforts * See Appendix, Note XV. FREEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. 59 with less of fallibility to the desired results. To make knowledge most available, or useful, often requires thought, reflection, or deliberation in its application. An exciting want may be accompanied with a con- sciousness that our knowledge is insufficient, and, in such case, the secondary want of more knowledge inter- venes. We want to ascertain the circumstances, or the best mode of proceeding under them, and our effort is first directed to obtain this knowledge. We examine, we deliberate, and thereby reach a conclusion or judg- ment. These judgments are but the knowledge, certain or otherwise, as to what is, or what we should do ; ac- quired by preliminary efforts for this object. We ob- serve, we examine, and so arrange our ideas, that the knowledge sought may come within the scope of simple mental perception. As a basis of the whole proceeding, however, there is always a want ; and, of course, with this want as one of its elements, some knowledge (at least the knowledge that by effort more knowledge may be obtained) which required no effort. The feeling, which is one element of the want, is constitutional ; and the knowledge, which is the other element, is in the first instance either innate, or acquired by simple perception, without effort. The preliminary efforts of the mind to obtain knowledge to use in directing its final effort, are but parts of a plan, embracing a series of efforts, to accomplish the final end it has in view. As preliminary to that final act of will, or series of acts, by which the primary exciting want is to be grati- fied, the mind may have to decide — 1. Between its conflicting wants. 2. Between various objects ; the obtaining, or effect- ing some one of which is essential to the gratification 60 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. of its want ; and this is always a change, or effect to be produced in the future. 3. Among various possible, or conceivable, modes of producing this effect in the future. 4. Whether to make the effort to produce the effect, or not ; and then, if the mind so decides, it proceeds to make the effort in conformity to the preferred mode to produce the selected effect, to gratify the chosen want. The preliminaries, as above, may be settled in other order, and may not all of them be requisite to every final act of will. The fourth decision seems to be very closely associated with the final act of will ; and, per- haps, liable to be confounded with it. But a decision or judgment is but a particular form of knowledge, which is often the result of acts of will, but cannot it- self be such act, or effort. The final act of will comes after the decision to do. If the process ends with the decision to do, there is no room for the willing by the mind, to do that which it has thus decided to do ; and the whole matter is as completely ended by a decision to do, as by a decision not to do. The difference in the two cases is, that a decision to do is followed by a fur- ther action of the mind to execute its decision and effect change in the future ; and a decision not to do is a finality, leaving the mind in a state of quiescence, and not of action. If the decision is itself the act of will, we have nothing to mark the difference in the subsequent mental conditions of action in the one case, and of re- pose in the other. We may suppose a being to know that there are, or may be, several modes of gratifying a want, and yet not know that there is, or may be, a choice among FREEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. 61 them. Such a being would, no doubt, on feeling the want, adopt the first means it perceived of gratifying it, as though it knew and could know no other. If, in so doing, it adopted the worst mode, it would have been better not to have known it. We all know that this disadvantage sometimes occurs to us when acting too hastily, without sufficient deliberation, and this expe- rience teaches us the necessity of deliberately examin- ing the facts and the probable results of action, before we act. In the same way, too, we learn that of several wants there may be a choice as to the order in which they shall be gratified, or whether they shall be grati- fied or not. Hence, from experience, or that knowl- edge which comes after effort, we learn the importance of using, before an effort, what knowledge we then have ; and thus, with the want and knowledge which alone were sufficient to enable the mind to will, and to will intelligently, is associated deliberation, which is a preliminary effort of the mind to obtain more knowl- edge to enable it to will better and more intelligently in its final action, i. e., to produce the desired result of gratifying the want more certainly, more fully, or with less collateral, or consequential disadvantages. Delib- eration being thus but the application of our knowl- edge, in an effort to obtain more knowledge, cannot be considered as a new, but as the same element, used in a preliminary, or intermediate effort, induced by the want of more knowledge. In its every act of will not purely instinctive, or habitual, the mind applies its knowledge, or some of its knowledge, in devising, or adopting a mode of gratifying its want ; and must take some time to make the application at all ; * and the ex- * See Appendix, Note XVI. 62 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. tended deliberation is only devoting more time to make that application more perfect, or to obtain more knowl- edge to apply. The deliberation is only an examination of our knowledge, generally resulting in a judgment, but is sometimes fruitless. It may be exhaustive, but more frequently it is not, and the quantity of time which shall thus be devoted, in any case, is also a mat- ter for the mind to judge of and to decide, at any point, by the knowledge which it then already has. If we want food, it will not be advisable to spend a month in considering whether it is best for us to eat beef, mutton, or venison ; and yet, perhaps, less time would not suf- fice for a thorough examination. In such cases, the mind judges for itself, bestowing such time as, under the circumstances, seems to it desirable ; the exercise of a proper judgment, in this respect, combining prudence with decision. That the mind has the power to arrest its impulse to gratify its want by the first means it per- ceives, to consider or examine whether there are not better means ; or whether it is proper that the want be gratified at all, by whatever means it may have at command ; is a very important fact, making, perhaps, the foundation of oue essential difference between in- stinctive and rational action. In turning from the want, knowledge, and the appli- cation of the knowledge, or deliberation, which precede, to that effect, which the mind seeks to accomplish by its effort, constituting its object, we may remark, as an ob- vious fact, we might say, a truism, that we do not make any effort for what already is. Hence, a beginning, or a design to do what might not otherwise be done ; an endeavor, or attempt to bring to pass what before was not ; to originate some change, which otherwise might FREEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. 63 not occur, seems involved in the very idea of effort. In this view, every volition is an exercise of the creative power of the intelligence that wills ; and when success- ful, results in a creation, formed, with more or less skill and wisdom, from the unarranged materials existing in the chaos of circumstances, which this same intelligence perceives, examines, compares, analyzes, and combines in idea, before its final volition is decided upon, — before it determines by what actual construction of these ma- terials it can best effect its purpose, — by what means it can best gratify, or relieve the want, which excited it to action. We have seen that the finite intelligence has all the powers essential to creative action, and also the knowl- edge required to direct these powers. Hence it may of itself use them with intelligent aim. To direct our first efforts, we have sufficient intuitive knowledge, and when this, with any accumulations passively acquired by the knowing sense through external sensation, will not avail, we know that the mode of obtaining more is by an effort to examine. Among the circumstances, the examination of which by the mind may be essential to its proper exercise of these powers, must be included not only the actual present existences around us, but our recollections of past observation and reflection ; our anticipations of the future ; our knowledge of the experience of others and of what others may be doing, or expected to do ; and, especially, of those laws, or uniform modes, by which the Supreme Intelligence regulates His acts of change ; and by, or through, or in conformity to which our own volitions are made effective. Among the circumstances, our opinion as to our ability to execute this or that de- 64: FKEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. sign, will largely influence ns as to the effort we con- clude to make. Whether that opinion is, or is not cor- rect, is not material to its influence on the volition. The mind will, in this respect, be influenced in its ac- tion by the internal existing belief, — the present known — and not by the external future fact, which is unknown, perhaps unanticipated, or even disbelieved. We never will to do, what we know we cannot do. To will an act, I must first ~know what act to will. If no particular act appears to me as better adapted to pro- duce the desired effect than another, there is no reason why I should adopt- one act rather than another ; and, in such case, my knowledge would only indicate trying any act out of the infinite number of conceivable acts. But, if I know that there is no act that will produce that effect, there is no reason why I should will at all. I could just as well will without any want, as to will when I knew the act of will would have no influence on the want. Under such circumstances there can be no decision of the mind to act, and nothing to be executed by an act of will. The decision to will, is a portion of the mind's knowledge ; and to say one cannot decide to will to do what he knows that he cannot do, is merely saying, that he cannot reconcile the contradiction, and know that he will do what at the same time he knows he cannot do. The effort, or trying to do, involves some expectation of doing. If I know the nature of the act, which, if my power were sufficient, would produce the effect, but know that my power is not sufficient, I know that willing such act cannot avail. I, in effect, know that it will no more produce the effect, than any other act, however different its nature. Under strong im- pulse, men sometimes seem to make efforts which they FREEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. 65 know will be insufficient to produce the desired effects. Strong emotion often finds relief by expression in unavailing words ; and a like relief is derived from expression in unavailing action. Such relief may be the end rationally designed, or, perhaps, in such case, action is instinctive. If a friend asks me to push aside a mountain of granite, I say I cannot do it ; and if, in compliance with his request to try, I push against it, I still do not will to move it ; but the whole object of my effort, and what I will, is to push against it to please him, and this I pre-perceive to be possible. A man, who can demonstrate the impossibility of duplicating the cube, or of contriving a perpetual motion, may yet will to exercise his wits upon these problems. His effort, however, is not to solve the problems, but, per- haps, by exercise to improve himself in geometry and mechanics ; or to amuse himself thereby. Sometimes persons, in moments of frenzy or desperation, appear to attempt impossibilities. This appearance may arise from various causes. In a pressing exigency, wheji there is nothing but what is highly improbable, things highly improbable may be attempted. This is ex- pressed in the ancient adage, " A drowning man will catch at a straw." Or, the object sought may have taken such strong hold on the imagination, or may so exclusively absorb the attention, that the obstacle to its attainment, the impossibility, though ever so palpable to others, is overlooked by the actor. A man in battle, surrounded by an army of his enemies, may act as if to cut his way through them, rather than passively meet the fate he knows to be inevitable ; but, in this case, what he really seeks and wills is not to cut his way through the army, but something else ; perhaps to de- 66 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. stroy as many of the enemy as possible ; or to get that relief, which effort gives by its excitement and by with- drawing his thoughts from his impending doom. Again, the habit of resistance, or of effort in similar, though less hopeless cases, may have its influence on the action willed. (Of the influence of habit, I shall have occasion to say more hereafter.) So, too, it seems certain^ that our belief as to the degree of certainty with which we can attain an object, is one of the circumstances gen- erally taken into the view of the mind in forming its judgment as to what it will try to do, or in what mode it will attempt it. The mind may not always adopt the easiest mode of reaching the ultimate object of its effort. It may be indifferent as to the amount of effort, and hence not seek the easiest mode ; or it may prefer to make more effort than is necessary, and adopt the mode which will embrace this intermediate with the ultimate object ; but it must always seek to adopt a mode by which what it wants will be accomplished ; and, in do- ing this, the mind must itself judge of the mode, or modes, which it knows, or which, when not immediately apparent, it finds by a preliminary act of search, and, in view of all the circumstances, including its own power, and the pleasure or pain of exercising that power, decide whether to adopt any one, and, if so, which one. These views show the necessity of want and knowl- edge as pre-requisites to any effort of the mind. It is, perhaps, sufficiently evident that the mind will make no effort to do anything which it does not want done ; also, that it will make no effort to do what it wants done, if it knows that such effort will not produce any desirable result ; or even when, without this negative FKEEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. 67 certainty, it has no affirmative faith, or hope of such a result. But, more fully to explain, let us suppose another case. A man feels a sensation, and with it has certain knowledge, constituting a want, say of food ; the intui- tive knowledge which, in the first stage of his existence, indicated the mode of gratifying this want, no longer avails him, and his acquired knowledge must be brought into requisition. But he knows of no way of minister- ing to the want by a direct act of will. He knows that this is impossible, and he now wants to make such effort as will lead, though indirectly, to the desired result. He knows that, by examining the circumstances, the means may, perhaps, be found ; and he now wants to examine. This he has the power to do, and on doing it, he finds, from immediate perception, or from the memory of previous perceptions, that there is bread in the baker's shop over the way, or, at least, a probability of its being there ; but he knows of no way of obtaining it by a direct act of will, without being first near to it ; and he now wants to be at the baker's shop ; still, he knows no mode of accomplishing this end by a direct act of will ; but he knows that by a direct act of will he can make and govern the movements of his limbs so as to walk there ; and he now wants to walk there. To meet this want, he has the requisite knowledge and power ; he can will and successively continue to will the movements necessary to walk, and commencing with these, he goes through the several stages of mov- ing himself to the baker's shop, obtaining the bread and applying it to relieve his sensation of hunger. At every stage there was a want demanding effort, but no direct effort to relieve or gratify the want, until it was re- 68 FKEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. duced to one in which there was corresponding knowl- edge — knowledge of a means, of a plan, by which a se- ries of acts of will, in proper order, would accomplish it. The wants, which arise in forming this plan, are all sec- ondary wants, and may be embraced in the want of the mind to apply its knowledge, or to obtain more knowl- edge to apply. The contrivance, or design, by which the finite mind finds means to reach indirectly, what it cannot by a di- rect act of will, is one mode in which it manifests its creative power. It is conceivable, that a man with his mind engrossed by some absorbing subject, and at the same time feeling hungry, might have his notions so confused as to move his teeth to chew before he put the food between them. Perhaps most persons have experienced something analogous to this, and all can readily perceive how abortive such efforts must be. Hence we see that, to produce any given effect, it is important that the efforts should be in conformity to some pre-existing plan or design. A single want may thus require not only a number of acts of will, but that they shall be in a certain consecutive order ; and a lit- tle system, as clearly manifesting the orderly arrange- ment of designing cause, as our planetary system, be created before the original want, which induced the effort, is gratified ; these little separate systems, going to form that universe which every man, by the exercise of his creative powers, is gradually constructing, and in which, as in the stellar universe, some of its consti- tuent parts are continually being formed, while others, having fulfilled the purposes of their existence, are oblit- erated. If, in the case just stated, we suppose the man to know, not that there is bread over the way, but that FKEED0M OF INTELLIGENCE. 69 there is a baker's shop a short distance in one direction, where there may be bread ; and another shop, farther off, in another direction, where there is a greater prob- ability of finding it ; also, that in another place beef may be had, and frnit in another, then the judgment must be exercised ; the mind must seek, by examina- tion, to find the best mode of effort to get the bread, or to determine whether, in view of all the circumstances, the effort should not be to obtain the beef, or the fruit instead. In such case there is more extended delib- eration. We have already remarked that we do not make effort, or will as to what now is ; neither do we will as to what is past. The object of our effort is always to influence that which is to be — to produce some effect in the future. What already is, or has been, has no other effect upon our decision as to the effort to be made, than as our memory of the past and perceptions of the present increase the knowledge by which we are better enabled to judge as to what effects we should seek to produce in the future, and add to our power and means to produce them. In other words, this knowledge ena- bles the mind to form those preconceptions of the effect of any contemplated effort, which are essential to its decision, or judgment, as to what effort it should put forth. The object of willing being always to produce some change in the future, this preconception of the effect of the willing on that future is obviously a very important element. If a man could not anticipate some desirable change as the result of his effort, he would not, as a rational and intelligent being, put forth the effort. He could have no object of effort and no reason for making it. To will, then, requires that, by 70 FREEDOM OF MIND IN" WILLING. means of our knowledge of the past and present, intui- tive or acquired, we be able to obtain a prophetic view of the future. This is true of the effort to form these preconceptions. When they are not obvious to simple mental perception, effort is required to form them, and the mind must have some faith, that by effort in exam- ining, it can get the foresight — the knowledge required to form them, or so arrange its knowledge that such preconceptions will become apparent. The knowledge, that by examination we can get the knowledge requi- site for action, as before suggested, is essential to our first actions, and is probably intuitive. As a conception, poetic or logical, of the effects of any contemplated efforts upon the future, is thus essen- tial to the effort, a being, with only sensation and a knowledge of the past and present, would not will. It is only by the God-like power of making the future present, that intelligence, Infinite, or finite, in the exer- cise of its will, becomes creative. By means of this power of anticipating its effects, the mind, in willing, is influenced by the anticipated creations of its own ac- tion, while those creations are still in the future, mak- ing a very broad distinction between intelligent and any conceivable unintelligent cause. It is this fact, that intelligent cause is influenced by its preconceptions of its own effects, that fits it for first cause ; for that which is thus, as it were, drawn forward by the future, needs no propulsion from the past ; that which is moved by inducements before it, does not need a motive influence behind it ; that which acts from its own internal perception of the effects- of its own action upon its own internal, existing want, does not require to be first acted upon by extra- FKEED0M OF INTELLIGENCE. 71 neous, external forces. It is essential that the want ex- ists, bnt not material to the action how it came to exist. If the mind is moved to exert its causal influence in acts of will, by the consideration of the effects which will succeed^ and not by what has preceded its action ; it cannot, up to the point of effort, bnt be a first canse, and, as such, an independent power, freely trying to do its finite part in that creation of the future, which is the object of its effort. In the past it has acquired the knowledge which aids its judgment as to the effect of any contemplated action under the present circum- stances. The problem which the mind has to determine, in such cases, and which the mind alone must determine, is this : given, a certain want, or, which is the same thing, a certain change to be wrought out in the future ; and, with this, certain facts, constituting whatever knowledge the mind has from memory of the past, or observation of the present, including, of course, all in- struction, from any source, human or Divine, up to the moment of* deciding ; to determine by what change in the future the want may be gratified; and then by what effort, or series of efforts, this gratifying change may be effected. If the want and the existing circum- stances, or facts, were not already fixed and determined, and, as such, not subject to the will, we should have, for finding the required volition, only variable and un- known data. There would be nothing fixed, or known as a basis of calculation, and the problem would be as indeterminate as that of constructing a triangle with three unknown sides. If the want were not fixed, the problem would still be indeterminate. The mind, that does not know what it wants, is not prepared to deter- 72 FREEDOM OF MEND 12* WILLING. mine its action. Or, if we suppose the want and the knowledge of it to be fixed, but all other knowledge to be dependent on the will ; then the mind would, by an act of will, have to fix this other knowledge of the past and present before it could make it available in deter- mining its course as to the future. The mind, in such case, would have to assume the facts and truths, by its own creative acts for its present purpose, make them fact and truth in some fixed form ; it would be acting upon an assumed basis, upon mere hypotheses, and the action founded upon such assumptions might prove to have no adaptation to the actual existences. No sane man would, from such process, expect other than im- aginary or hypothetical results, admitting of actual ap- plication only when the actual existences happened to correspond with the assumed hypotheses. He might, in this way, plan action without reference to any actual, existing circumstances, or to any changes, which other causes might be affecting ; but the chance of his plan being applicable to the actual existences, would be in- conceivably small. With the want and knowledge both given, the mind has only to determine their rela- tions to the contemplated acts, to make the problem analogous to that of constructing a triangle, knowing two sides and their relations to the other. It be- comes a determinate problem, but it is the mind's knowledge, including that of its want, which thus makes it determinate ; and the mind itself, by the use of its knowledge, actually determines it. If we do not know the existing facts or circumstances, which relate to our action, we seek by a preliminary act to find them. The mind may be in doubt as to some, or all of the data, or knowledge, upon which it bases its con- FREEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. 73 struetions ; and, so far, the result will be doubtful and the problem be determinate only within the limits of certain probabilities ; or it may be mistaken in the data, either as to the facts, or the relations, and, so far, the result may be erroneous, and the act of will have no tendency to produce the expected result ; or there may be a want of power to produce the effect willed. However this may be, however perfect or imperfect the solution — the mind, with such means as it has, must it- self resolve this problem, growing out of the relations, indicated by its own knowledge, between its own want and the conception which it forms of the future effect of certain of its own acts of will, and determine the re- sult or act of will, or that result, that act of will, will not be determined. No other power, material or intel- ligent, could possibly determine it without knowing both the want, and the perception of the relation between the contemplated action and the want, which exist in the mind of the agent willing. This could be only by one who knows all our wants, u to whom all hearts are open, all desires known." On this point, of the pos- sible control of the finite will by the Supreme Intelli- gence, we have already made some suggestions, and shall consider it more fully in another place. From the views just stated it appears that, if the want and knowledge of the mind were subject to, in- stead of being independent of its will, they would have to be fixed by specific acts of will before any other act of will could be determined ; and the fact that the want and knowledge of the mind are not subject to the control of its will, instead of involving necessity as at first glance one might suspect, is really essential to the freedom of the mind in determining its action ; or, 4 74 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. at least, facilitates the exercise of that freedom. That we have want, know our want, and the means or mode of gratifying that want, cannot militate against our freedom in the use of that knowledge, to gratify the want. The want is the original incentive to that effort, the direction of which the mind determines by means of the relations which it perceives between its wants and its preconceptions of the future effects of this effort ; among such conceptions selecting, or choosing, for ac- tualization, that one which, in its view, is best adapted to its purpose of gratifying, or relieving the want. It is in the forming of such preconceptions, as will prob- ably answer the purpose, in the accuracy of these pre- conceptions, or their conformity to the effects that will actually be produced, and in selecting among them, that the mind manifests its ability in action. Whether or not these preconceptions are realized by the power of the mind in effort, is not material. It is sufficient that its effort is a pre-requisite to such realiza- tion. Up to the point of and including the effort, the finite mind, in its own sphere, so far as we can know, exerts its creative powers in the same way as the Infi- nite, and as freely. It has a want ; forms a preconcep- tion of what changes will gratify the want ; what effort, or succession of efforts, will produce these changes ; and makes the efforts, or wills these changes. The only ne- cessity or restraint, differing from that of the Infinite, which the finite mind is under, arises, not from a differ- ence in the kind, but in the limited quantity of its power. It cannot do what it has not power to do ; it cannot act from considerations, which it does not per- ceive or apprehend ; or upon knowledge which it does not possess ; i. e., the finite mind cannot reconcile con- FREEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. 75 tradictions. But neither can the Infinite. In this re- spect they are, if not on the same, at least on similar footing. The finite mind cannot be infinite, and the In- finite cannot be finite ; and this difference in condition makes a corresponding difference in the contradictions, to reconcile, or to overcome which is, to each, impos- sible. If no intelligence can will to do what it knows that it cannot do, then the Infinite cannot will to do anything which is really impossible to it ; while the finite, being limited in knowledge, may will to do what, to it, is impossible, and even what is absolutely so ; for the very reason that it does not know the impossibility, or the fallacy in its perception of some apparent means ; and hence, the finite mind may will in some cases in which, if omniscient, it could not.* Having now premised that the finite intelligence has the powers essential to creative acts of will, and that it has a finite sphere commensurate with its knowl- edge, in which it has a finite, all-pervading presence ; and in which, so far as we can know, its creative powers are exerted in the same manner as those of the Supreme Intelligence are, in His infinite sphere, let us suppose a commencement of creation. The one first cause — the Supreme Intelligence — ex- ists, and must have power to act, to will to do, or noth- ing would be done, or even attempted. This, in It, must be a fundamental condition of its existence. It must, originally, as a part of the constitution of its Be- ing, know how to exert at least some of its powers, as the same knowledge is constitutional, or innate in the active finite intelligence. This Supreme Intelligence, then, is about to act for the first time. Its object is to * See Appendix, Note XVII. 76 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WELLING. produce some effect, some change. To do this must require action of some kind on its part ; for, if the effect can take place without any such action, it can take place as well without its agency as with it ; and the effect is not the effect of its agency. To produce an effect, even Omnipotence must exert its power — it must put forth effort, it must will. A creative God cannot be an inert Being, wholly passive, and yet mani- fest creative power. Such an idea cannot be conceived without violence to all our notions of power. Power itself does not act, but the being that has power, acts and must exert its power — must put forth effort, or the power will not be exerted, will not produce any effect. Such a Being, then, is about to exert its causative or creative power. If there is no matter — nothing but this one intelligence, there is manifestly nothing extraneous to itself to oppose, to determine, or even to influence its action ; and it must, therefore, be free to exert its power as itself may determine. It must itself determine this first act, or it cannot be determined. Nor is it difficult to see how this may be done. The Supreme Intelli- gence exists with its wants, its knowledge, and power ; its knowledge including the mode of using that power. It wants to create ; it has the knowledge of means ; the wisdom to select and to adopt those means ; and the pow- er to apply them, so as to produce the creation or change wanted. There being no opposing force, the first crea- tion, the first effect of its effort, must be in conformity to its design, if that design be within the province of its power to accomplish. If it could have but one want, and only the knowledge of one way to gratify that want ; if, in intelligence, there was no principle of adaptation to new circumstances, then, even this Su- FREEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. 77 preme Intelligence could produce but this one effect, or, at most, but duplications of it. From the fact that intelligence has a variety of wants ; also a variety of knowledge, or the faculties to acquire it ; and that, from its variable knowledge, it can select for use that which it deems best suited to the occasion, it becomes a variable cause, adapting itself to the want and the cir- cumstances existing in its view ; each new want, with every increase of its knowledge, and every combination of want with knowledge, becoming, in its view, a rea- son for new and different effects by the active intelli- gence, which thus becomes a multiple cause, produc- ing varied effects. Suppose, then, the first want which actuated the Supreme Intelligence to have been grati- fied ; that want can no longer exist ; and, it being a fundamental property of intelligence to want change, or to want to do ; a new want arises. It may be only a want of variety, or of exercise for its faculty, but an- other new creation, or effect in the future, is required to gratify this want. This second creation must have some reference to the first. The first has changed the condi- tions, and a different ^combination of circumstances en- ters into the decision as to the mode in which the sec- ond want is to be gratified. This, however, does not interfere with the, freedom of the active agent, but only varies the circumstances under, or upon which it freely exerts its active power. It contemplates another crea- tion — no less a new creation than the first, but begun or conceived under different circumstances, which the intelligence takes into account as a portion of its knowl- edge, by which it determines as to what is best to be done, and what the best means to do it. It is the same as though it had now to act for the first time, and found 78 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. the" circumstances, as they now are, to act upon, or to consider in its action. That by previous action it has itself made, or contributed to make, the circumstances what they are, has nothing to do with the proper action under them. The date, or the cause of their existence, cannot affect the result, all that enters into -the delibera- tion being their actual present existence ; so that every successive act of the creative intelligence is the same as the beginning, or, we may say, is the beginning of a new creation, made in reference to what already exists. So also if, when intelligence was first to act, it found matter coexisting ; and further, that this matter was in motion and blindly producing changes in itself; this would vary the circumstances under which the intelli- gence would act, but could not affect the freedom of its action. To this uncalculated and uncalculating state of things, it would bring the new element of intelligent action, and, from the chaotic confusion of numerous blind forces, educe the order, the unity of a designing cause. The design must be all its own, for no variety, no quantity of blind causes, or forces, could make a de- sign, jform a preconception, or be in any way influenced by, what, as yet, is not. For a similar reason, the effort to fulfil the design must be its own effort. Blind forces cannot conceive or will at all, much less will in con- formity to, or in the order of a preformed, or preexist- ing design or plan, which it cannot form, or know, but the design may be wisely so formed, that some, or all of such forces, if any such be possible, may cooperate with the effort of the intelligent cause to actualize its designs or conceptions. The effort must, however, be to make the effect different from what it may be obvious that all such forces combined will do ; otherwise it is FREEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. 70 but an effort to accomplish nothing; which is an ab- surdity. When, then, the design is such, that all the blind forces, unchanged, obviously aid in its accomplish- ment, the design must include something in addition to what the designing agent perceives these forces would themselves accomplish. Such forces may be auxiliary to the power of the Supreme Intelligence, or may pre- sent circumstances to be changed and impediments to be overcome ; but evidently, for reasons above stated, do not interfere with His freedom of design or effort^ though, if His power were not infinite, they might pre- vent the actualization of the design, or frustrate the effort. If infinite, this could only occur in case the de- sign were so unwisely formed as to involve contradic- tion, as the making, on a plane surface, of two hills without a hollow. Such contradiction an infinitely wise Being would avoid. We have now supposed the Supreme Intelligence acting as the only cause, and also in connection with any blind causes. If we suppose one of the creations of the Supreme Intelligence to be a subordinate, finite intelligence, and this created intelligence to act freely as cause, pro- ducing its own effects, independent of the Supreme In- telligence, and without Its prescience, then the Supreme Intelligence must, in its subsequent creations, make these new circumstances, this new cause, with its own uncertainty, or ignorance of the effects which this cause may produce, a part of the foundation of its own ac- tion ; as the finite intelligence, in its action, has refer- ence to its own uncertainty and ignorance, as to many events depending on the action of the Infinite, of which it has no certain prescience. Some of these, however, we rely upon with implicit faith ; as the rising of the 80 FKEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. sun ; others, as the changes of the weather, are to tis very uncertain ; and we must sometimes provide, in our de- signs or plans of action, for numerous contingencies, which we cannot certainly foreknow. This very uncer- tainty makes one of the circumstances which we have to consider in determining what, in view of all com- bined, we will try to effect. If there is any such uncer- tainty in the mind of God, as to human actions, it will be but one of the circumstances which He will consider in determining His own action. His designs, His efforts, though they may be made in reference to the existence of this finite cause, are not made, either wholly or in part, by it ; they are still his own designs, his own efforts, freely made. The existing finite intelligence not only has not sufficient power to coerce or control the freedom of the infinite, as to its designs and efforts } but it has no tendency to do so. The mere changing of the circumstances upon, or in view of which the Su- preme Intelligence acts, even though such change could, in some unseen way, frustrate the effort, could not affect the freedom of the design, or of the effort. Among, or upon one set of circumstances, His designs and efforts would be as free as among another set ; though some combination of circumstances may, to any but the infinite, require less, and some admit of less de- liberation, than others. The Supreme Intelligence, then, whether acting as the only activity in the uni- verse, or in connection with matter in motion, or with inferior intelligence, must will without constraint or re- straint — must will freely. Nor can the amount of the power of the intelligence make any difference in regard to the freedom of its efforts. The mind's own estimate of its power, may be FKEEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. 81 one portion of the knowledge by which it judges as to what effort to make. If mistaken in this, it may make efforts which are unavailing. Still, this does not show any want of freedom in its willing, but only a want of power to do what it wills. That it can will to do even what it cannot do, is rather an indication of its freedom in willing than otherwise. If, in conformity to a strin- gent logic, we suppose God to have no more power than is required to do what we see He has done, such limitation could not affect His freedom in the exercise of that power. Neither can the amount of knowledge have any influence on the freedom of the effort, but only upon the wisdom of the design, or of the effect in- tended. With inadequate knowledge we may not form full and correct preconceptions of the effect, or of the mode of producing it, and hence be liable to err in our judgment as to the wisdom or propriety of the contem- plated change, or to mistake the means of producing it, but this does not effect .our freedom in the attempt. It seems to be a self-evident proposition, that the Supreme Intelligence, acting alone as the only existing cause, must act freely ; and the views just stated, in connection with those before presented, in regard to spirit and matter as cause, show that this freedom is not — at least not necessarily — affected by the amount of the power, or of the knowledge of the intelligent cause ; nor by the coexistence of other causes, material or in- telligent. If, then, neither the amount of the power, nor of the knowledge of the willing agent, nor the co- existence of other causes, influence the question of the freedom of the agent in willing ; and man, as we have shown, is creative in that finite sphere, in which, with finite power, he is present to all that he know T s ; as God 4* 82 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WDLLING. is creative in that infinite sphere in which He is om- nipotent and omnipresent, we must infer that man may as freely exercise his finite creative powers in his finite sphere, as God does His infinite powers in His infinite sphere ; and, that every act of will is a new and inde- pendent movement, and, as it were, a fresh beginning of a new creation, evolved by the mind from the new combination of circumstances in view of which it wills. Each individual intelligence wills as in its view of the circumstances it deems best ; and though these circum- stances may be the result, the composition, of the pre- vious action of itself and of all other intelligences, and any other possible causes, still, as no such action can change the present state of things, at the present time, each intelligence acts, so far as external circumstances are concerned, as if, at the moment of its action, all other powers were quiescent and itself the only active power in existence. What the others have already done, or may be expected to do, are but portions of the circumstances upon which the mind acts in judging, or deciding, as to the effort it will make, if any. In re gard to its own efforts, then, the finite mind, so far as external events, circumstances, and coexisting causes are concerned, at the moment of willing, may be as free as if no other intelligence or force existed ; and hence, may will freely, though other forces may frustrate the subsequent execution of what it wills. One intelligence may to the extent of its power, shape the circumstances with a view to influence the will of another ; but this is presuming that the other wills freely. If that other does not, there would seem to be no use in presenting to it the newly adjusted circumstances to influence its will ; no reason to suppose that its will could thus be FREEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. 83 influenced by any change of circumstances produced by other intelligences, or other causes. In connection with the argument that, as the free- dom of the mind in willing is not affected by the amount of its power, or knowledge, the finite mind may will as freely as the infinite, the foregoing views suggest that it makes no difference at what period of creation the finite mind begins to act. Suppose it, first having acquired knowledge, to have been quiescent for ages, and again to begin to act at this moment, and that previous activities, having brought creation to its present state, should all cease to act, except those agen- cies, whatever they may be, which execute the decrees of the human will, leaving nothing but this one finite mind, with its wants, faculties, knowledge, and the sur- rounding circumstances ; these latter all quiescent in the state to which the recent activities brought them. This one finite mind could make effort to change these circumstances, in the absence of all other active influ- ences, as well as with their presence ; and, in their ab- sence, there being nothing else, must itself direct the effort, which must be directed, and is consequently free in making that effort, and especially as there is nothing to oppose, to constrain, or control it in so doing. How- ever small its power to will, that power must be suffi- cient to overcome no obstruction. The circumstances do not make the effort, or any part of it. In order to form a preconception of the effect of any contemplated effort to change the present, the mind must consider what now is, and hence acts in reference to what al- ready is ; but mere circumstances, having in themselves no power, no self-activity, cannot act upon anything, and can only be acted upon. The finite mind, then, 84 FEEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. under such conditions, being, by the hypothesis, the only activity, the only power capable of producing change, or capable of making eifort to produce change, must be wholly unimpeded in such effort, and must de- termine its effort, without extraneous aid or hindrance. Nor can it make any difference, if we suppose the other activities to be reinstated. They cannot alter the past, nor can they in the present moment, alter the present, whatever already is, though its existence commenced in the present instant, is as surely existent as if it com- menced its existence ages before. The reinstating, then, of these other activities, at the instant that this sup- posed one finite mind wills, cannot, at that instant, alter the circumstances, except as their own existence is a fact added to the knowledge of this one mind, and, thus far, may vary its action ; but cannot, as before shown, affect its freedom in acting. From this fact, that no cause can alter what is at the instant, in the same in- stant — or make things as they are, and, at the same time, different from what they are — every act of the in- telligent being, finite or infinite, is the same as a first act of such being, under such circumstances as it might find coexisting, and, in the absence of all other activ- ities, forces, or causes ; and further, as the number of coexisting circumstances does not affect the mind's free- dom in choosing among them, or in combining them, or in considering their relations to its efforts, or in its pre- conceptions of the effects ; and the quantity of the agent's power does not affect its freedom in using what it has ; every effort of the finite mind may be as free as the first creative act of the Infinite, even supposing It to have then been the only existence. These considerations serve to show that the finite FREEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. 85 mind may will freely ; and we shall next inquire as to whether it is controlled in willing by any other power. The only essential elements in willing which are within the mind, and yet are not the mind's action, are want and knowledge. The want does not itself will. It does not direct the will ; for it has not the knowledge by which alone this can be done. The knowledge does not will, nor, itself, direct the will ; for knowledge, if considered as an entity distinct from mind, is not, in it- self, intelligent, and cannot even know the want to the gratification of which the effort moist be adapted. It is also obvious that no want, or combination of want with knowledge, can will. The effort and its direction, or determination, must be by that which is cognizant of both the want and the knowledge, and perceives the relations between them ; that is, by an intelligent being, or agent. In regard to external control, I will further observe that the only conceivable modes in which the mind of any finite intelligent being, as man, can be influenced from without itself, in its act of will, are, First, by some other intelligence, cause, or force act- ing directly upon his will, and, as it were, taking the place of his mind, and using his will to accomplish its own objects ; or, Secondly, by such other intelligence, cause, or force acting directly upon that man's mind and, by control- ling its action, through it control his will ; or, Thirdly, by so changing his knowledge, including the knowledge of those sensations and emotions which are elements of want, that in consequence of this change of knowledge, he comes to a different result, and wills differently. 86 FREEDOM OF MIND LN WILLING. As the power of matter, if it have any, must be lim- ited to changing the circumstances and thus changing the knowledge on which, or in view of which, we act, it can only influence us in the last of the three modes, and hence may be excluded in considering the other two. The first of these involves the absurdity of making the will a distinct entity, separable from the particular mind with which it is usually associated, and liable to be used by any other intelligence, that can get posses- sion of it. If the will is not a distinct entity, but is a mere quality, property, faculty, or attribute of a mind ; or a result or condition of its activity ; then, when we de- stroy its connection with that mind, or with its activity, the will vanishes as completely as the image in a mir- ror, when the object is removed from before it ; and there is no will left to be thus controlled by another in- telligence, or other external force. Upon the hypothe- sis that my will is a distinct entity, or a separate por- tion of my mind, it is, perhaps, conceivable that such will, though controlled by another, may be so connected or associated with my mind, as in some sense to be said to be my will ; but even then, the action of that will, thus controlled by another, cannot be my action ; the effort, the willing through, or by means of, that will, is not my willing, but it is the effort, the willing of that other intelligence, which thus uses my will and acts through it ; and, in such case, my mind makes no effort — I do not will at all. Hence the question, as to wheth- er I will freely or not, cannot arise in this case. In the second case, if another intelligence directly controls my mind, and causes it to will without any FREEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. 87 reference to my own views, my own knowledge, then my intelligence has nothing to do with the willing. I am not then the intelligent being that wills, or the agent that acts, bnt am the mere instrument which some other active agent uses, as it would an axe, or a lever, to accomplish its own purposes. The willing, thus directly controlled by external power, may be in opposition to that which I perceive would accomplish what I want. If the external power perceives in me certain conditions of want and knowledge, and conforms the forced action of my mind to them, it is thus con- formed by the volition of the external power, and not by my action. The extrinsic agent perceives the con- ditions, and their relations to the action, as the sculptor perceives the aptitudes of a block of marble, in which he works out his own designs. So, if my mind is con- strained in its act of will by external power, my own want and knowledge, my perception of means to ends, my preconceptions of the effect, have no more to do with the coerced action, than the form of the block of marble has with the action of the sculptor. The act is not the action of my intelligent being. It is not I who act, but some other being, which, in acting, uses me as its instrument. I am, in such case, no more than an inert something, acted upon by intelligence, which is not of me ; and I in no wise differ from unintelligent sub- stance, except, in being conscious of the changes thus wrought in me by a power without me. In neither of the first two of the three supposed cases of control of the will of any being by the action of extraneous power ; viz. : that directly exerted on the will, or that on the mind, to compel, or constrain its act of will, can there be any willing by that being to be 88 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. thus controlled. In these cases, such being does not it- self act, but is only a passive subject, acted upon by some external power, though still having the capacity to feel, and to know, the changes thus produced in it. There may still be a being with sensation and knowl- edge, but no will.* Hence, the moment we reach the point of controlling the will, in either of these two modes, there is no willing of the being to be controlled. It may further be remarked that, even if such extrinsic control and willing were compatible in themselves, we neither know, nor can conceive of any mode in which extrinsic power could be directly applied either to will or to mind. In regard to the third and the only other conceiv- able mode, there are various ways in which the knowl- edge of one intelligence may be increased or changed by another. In relation to external circumstances, this may be done by adding to or altering the actual exist- ing circumstances, which is an exercise of creative power, finite or infinite, so that other intelligent beings, perceiving this change, will, in virtue of their intelli- gence, their power to adapt their efforts to circum- stances by means of their knowledge, will differently from what they would have done but for such addition, or change of circumstances. Even finite mind may so influence the infinite. In regard to those abstract ideas, and the perceived relations among them, which are not influenced by ex- trinsic changes — in regard to what is true or false — the views and knowledge of one finite mind may be changed through the action of another mind in statement, illus- tration, argument, &c. ; but the finite intelligence can- * See Appendix, Note XVIII. FREEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. 89 not thus influence omniscience. But such change of knowledge in any mind, from any cause, whether by the action of others or by its own efforts, or directly through its own simple perceptive attributes without aid or effort, is not the willing of that mind ; it is not such willing. in any one of these cases of change of knowledge, more than in the others ; and the only rea- son why, in either case, such change in the mind's knowledge has any influence on its willing is because it freely conforms its action to its knowledge — to its perceptions of the fitness of the action to the end sought. If the circumstances themselves be altered, this is not of itself altering the will, and no alteration can take place in it, except as the mind acts upon its perceptions of the altered circumstances, and that, under a different mew of the circumstances, whether produced by an actual change in them, or by argument, or otherwise, the mind may will differently, or make a different effort in consequence of the change in its knowledge, is no evidence that it does not will freely, but, on the contrary, such change of its act of will to conform to its own views, or its own knowledge, indi- cates its own unrestrained control of its own act of will ; and, as already intimated, if it does not will freely, there is no reason to expect any change of its will, by changing its view of the circumstances, either by direct action on the mind, or indirectly, by actual change of the circumstances viewed. If it does not will freely, that which is desirable, if it have any influence at all, may influence it in the same way as that which is unde- sirable ; and if this lack of freedom extends to the inter- nal, as well as the external, even a man's own virtuous emotions, or proper wants, may be the foundation of 90 FEEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. vicious voluntary efforts ; all of which is not only con- trary to observed fact, but is self-contradictory and absurd. These considerations, touching the influence which may be supposed to arise from the mind's view being affected by change of circumstances, are equally appli- cable, if the circumstances change in any other way, or are changed by any other cause than another intelli- gence ; and even if they change themselves — if any such changes, or modes of change, are possible. Even if matter or circumstances are an independent cause, producing effects, it can produce no other effects on the mind's action than may be produced by intelligent cause changing the circumstances in view of which the mind acts ; and hence the reasoning just herein ap- plied to the influence of other intelligent causes on the will, applies also to any which are unintelligent. The mind, in determining its own action, may con- sider what any other cause may be expected to do, and, in willing accordingly, still will freely. The mind, in willing, builds the future upon the present circum- stances, and is thus active in a sphere which circum- stances have not yet reached. It uses the circumstances as means, and in the absence of such means, may not be able to effect what it might effect with them. In regard to this influence of circumstances, we may further observe, that if any future event is necessarily connected with any circumstance, or with any thing in the past or present, and comes to pass of necessity from such connection, then the circumstance, or thing, is itself the cause of that future event, which must thus come to pass in virtue of such connection without any act of will. If it be said that the act of will is it- FREEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. 91 self that event which is thus so connected with the past or present circumstance or thing, that it comes to pass in virtue of such connection, then the circum- stance, or thing, is the cause of such act of will, and is the power which produces it, and the being, to whom the act is attributed, really makes no effort, he acts no act of will, there is no willing by him. Again, the in- stant that, in the past or present, with which such act of will is necessarily connected, comes to pass, the act of will, being of necessity connected with it, also comes to pass, and they are really simultaneous ; and every act of will necessarily dependent on the past or present must, at any subsequent instant of time, have actually taken place, and no new act of will could grow out of this past. If the act of will has no such necessary con- nection, but subsequently becomes so connected, then the new connection is a change, requiring a cause, which did not of necessity produce its effect at the in- stant the past circumstances came into existence ; but this must be a cause which can originate and begin subsequent action, i. e., a cause which is at least so far independent of these past circumstances, that it need not act in immediate connection with, or as a necessary consequence of their existence. But, if the effect of these past circumstances may be deferred for one mo- ment, it can be for another and another, and so may never be, and hence is not a necessary effect. From what has just been said, it is evident that no new effect can come from past existences, till some new cause has connected such effect with such past existence, and hence it follows, that an act of will never can be the necessary effect of anything in the past, or have any connection with it, till the action of some efficient cause 92 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. makes the connection, and, in such case, the cause which makes this connection is really the cause of the act of will. Now the only conceivable modes in which the effects of a cause can be continued in time, after the cause has itself ceased to act, are by means of matter in motion, and by intelligence retaining or recalling the effects by memory, and thus, as to itself, making them still present. But matter in motion cannot will or se- lect, decide or determine, among the various conceiv- able possible volitions ; and though it may be a link in the connection between a past event and a volition, the last and essential link is made by the mind itself. The nature of the circumstances cannot enable them to make a necessary connection, or to decide when and where it shall be ; their nature can have no influence on the mind in willing till it knows their nature, and it is thus only through the cognition of the mind itself, that they have any influence on the act of will ; and the real connecting cause is intelligence, — mind ; — and the past circumstances, including any movements of matter, only furnish the knowledge, or reasons, for its action in willing. These positions confirm the conclu- sion we before reached by another mode, that every act of will is, in itself, a beginning of action. Again, if the past is a necessary cause of volition in a mind, then, as to this mind, there always is a past, it must be constantly willing, which is contrary to the known fact. If it be said that, though the past does not of necessity always produce a volition, yet, whenever a volition does occur, it is, of necessity, so connected with the past as to be controlled by it, then, as the circum- stances cannot themselves select and determine when this connection shall, and when it shall not be, we must FREEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. 93 find some other cause for this connection, and our pre- vious reasoning upon this connecting cause recurs. Even if we suppose this subsequent connection to make the effect, i. e., the act of will, necessary ; it does not follow that the cause, which, by this connecting, pro- duced the act of will, was necessitated in its action by the preexisting past ; but, on the contrary, it has been shown that, if so, all the possible acts of will must be simultaneous with the supposed past existence, which is thus presumed to cause and necessitate them, and no new act of will, or any other effect, could thereafter arise, as the effect of such connection with the past. From this reasoning it also follows, that there must be some cause, which does not, of necessity, produce its effects immediately ; but, as just stated, if the effect of a cause may be deferred one instant, it may be deferred another and another, and so on forever, and hence such cause may never produce its effect ; and this must be a cause, a power, which, so far as the past is concerned, may act, or not act. Mind, intelligence, is such a pow- er, and it is conceivable that matter in motion may be, both admitting the intervening of time between any two extrinsic changes which they may produce by their continuous activity ; and these are not merely the only causes that we know of as admitting of this de- ferred effect of their activity, but the only real causes of any kind, that we can conceive of. If the activity — ■ the motion — of matter ceases, it requires external force, again to put it in motion. If the activity of spirit ceases, it requires some change within, or without it- self, which it feels or perceives — some want — to rouse it to activity. It seems conceivable, that these two kinds of causes may act and react upon each other, at least 94 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. thus far, that intelligence may put matter in motion, and thus make it a cause of change, and that the changes caused by matter in motion may furnish the occasions or the reasons for the action of intelligent cause. It is not, however, conceivable that matter can act directly on the will of any intelligence, but, only by changing the circumstances, occasion it to want, or if listless and inert, remind and call its attention to the conditions of want. And this is only so to alter its knowledge, that its own action, freely conformed to its own knowledge, will be different from what it would have been but for such changes by matter. The same is true of all changes or circumstances external to the mind whose action is thus influenced, and which are produced by any cause extrinsic to it, or even by itself. It is the changed knowledge that the mind uses to de- termine its action, without regarding how it became changed. • If matter in motion, or any other unintelligent cause can change the circumstances, the changes can of them- selves produce only the same subsequent effects as if such changes were the results of intelligent cause. In the one case it would be cause doing without design what, in the other, cause did with design. No such causes of change in circumstances, and no such change of circumstances, can act directly on any will without making that will its own ; and can only influence an- other to will differently by, in some way, changing its knowledge ; and this it may do by actually changing the circumstances which the mind views, or the mind's view of the same circumstances without any change in them. This is the limit of the power of circumstances on the mind in willing, and all their power, as already FREEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. 95 shown, depends on the minors ability to will freely — to direct its own action in conformity with its own knowledge. In many cases, in which the act of will is supposed to be controlled by circumstances, the influence is not ascribed to any existing circumstances, but rather to the fact, that certain circumstances do not exist. When such non-existence is recognized by the mind before its act of will is determined, it makes a portion- of the knowledge by which its effort is influenced or deter- mined, but, when it is not recognized, it may only influ- ence the effect of its effort. In the case of non-existence, it is obvious that the mind is influenced in its effort, not by the non-existent thing, but by its own knowl- edge of such non-existence, and of the consequences at- tending it, and it is also true, in the case of any external existence, that the mind is influenced in its efforts, not by the thing itself, but by its knowledge of the existing thing, and of the consequences attending it. The thing itself, if unknown, would have no effect upon the mind, or upon its effort ; and it is only by changing its knowl- edge, that changes in circumstance have any influence whatever on the mind's action ; and change of effort, upon changed knowledge, as already shown, does not conflict with freedom of effort. If there were no past or present circumstances — nothing external to itself — for the mind to know, or even if there were none known to it, its only act of will or effort would be to create something out of noth- ing — to begin a primary creation. In doing this it would not of course be controlled by existing or past circumstances. And, if we suppose events and circum- stances already existing to be in action and producing 96 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. effects, then, the only reason for the action of an intelli- gent will must be, either to arrest or to vary those effects, or to produce other wholly independent effects. These last must be by the mind acting independently of the existing' circumstances, excepting so far as it per- ceives that they will not produce the effects ; and in this case the mind directs its own action or effort, by means of its own knowledge of the end wanted and of the modes of reaching it ; or, in other words, perceiv- ing that no other causes are producing the desired re- sult, the mind exerts its own causative power to do it. In the other case, when the mind seeks to arrest or to vary the effects of the supposed action of circumstan- ces, its effort must be to resist or control their influence ; which is the reverse of control of the mind by the cir- cumstances. If, however, it be supposed that the effort, or volition, is one of the effects of the action of the cir- cumstances, there being but one effect, and that effect not a thing, in itself, but merely a change in the condi- tion of a thing or being, such change, or such effort, or volition, must be the effect of its cause. And hence, in such case, the effort or volition is the effort or volition of the circumstances, and not of the being with which it is associated, and argues nothing against the freedom of that being when it exerts its power to produce an effect — when it does will. A man may will to give a beggar a shilling, and unexpectedly find he has no shilling to give. He free- ly willed to give. He acted upon his knowledge, — be- lief, — that he had the shilling, the means of producing the future effect which he designed ; but, in the execu- tion of that design he was frustrated by the actual ex- isting circumstance. It is in the doing what he wills, FKEEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. 97 and not in the willing, that a man may be directly con- trolled by the external circumstances. Of the three and only conceivable modes of influ- encing the mind in willing, from without the mind that wills, two of them are inconsistent with any exercise of its will, and the other is effective only in case the mind wills freely. If, then, in willing, it is influenced by something extrinsic, it must, to be so influenced, will freely ; and if, in willing, it is not influenced by any- thing extrinsic, it must, in such act, be wholly nnder its own control, and, of course, be free in snch act of will- ing ; so that, if a mind wills at all, it must will freely. The same result, in terms, is more concisely reached thus. For a man to will and yet not will freely, is to will as he does not will ; is to be willing when he is unwilling, which is a contradiction. Reasoning, then, directly upon the nature of the things involved in the inquiry, or from the logical relations of the terms by which those things are represented in the common dis- course of men, we reach the same conclusions, that the mere act of willing implies a free action, involving the necessity of freedom in the agent willing ; and that to will, and yet not will freely, involves a contradiction ; and hence, the only question left, in regard to the free- dom of the human intelligence in willing, is, does it will? This we assumed as a fundamental premise of our argument, and, if our reasoning is correct, the con- clusion that the mind wills freely is within our pos- tulate. Necessitarians assert that the existence of such free- dom is neither true in fact, nor even possible. I shall notice their arguments in Book II. of this work. 5 CHAPTER XI. INSTINCT AND HABIT. It appears, then, that every being that really wills, must will freely. The sphere of its free activity may be more or less circumscribed, varying with the extent of its intelligence, from the lowest, most sluggish form of sentient life, to that of the most vital and ethereal spirit — from the contracted world of the monad, to the illimitable sphere of the Supreme Intelligence. Through- out this infinite range, each, in its own sphere, is equally free. If I want a piece of metal, and, from deficiency of knowledge, know only tin and lead, I cannot will to have gold ; and yet, as to the obtaining of tin or lead, my efforts may be as free as though I knew all the metals. "Within this limit of my knowledge I am as free to will, as if I were omniscient. If I have knowl- edge of other metals, but also know that I have power to obtain only tin or lead, I will not make the effort to obtain gold ; but as to tin and lead, I may will as freely as if I were omnipotent. Mere matter — unintelligent, having no will — musk be wholly controlled, in its changes, by some power with- out itself; all real changes in it, except the subsidiary effects of the finite, must be referred to the action of the Supreme Intelligence. Or if, in any sense, matter INSTINCT AND HABIT. 99 can be said to produce change, by being itself in mo- tion, such change is, and, as before shown, must "be a necessary consequence of such motion, which the mat- ter has no power to prevent or to vary. It has no knowledge, and, so far as its own movements, indepen- dent of any present action of intelligence, are concerned, is wholly controlled by the past. In short, it has no will, no self-control, and hence no inherent or real lib- erty. And if it had, having no knowledge, it would have no sphere in which to manifest it. If to senseless matter we add only sensation, it could feel, but not will. It might suffer, and yet could not know that any change is either possible or desirable. As yet it Jcnows no want, and must passively suffer or enjoy its sensa- tions. If now, adding want, we suppose a being capable of conceiving that by change its suffering may be di- minished, or its pleasure enhanced, it may then want change ; but if it have no knowledge as to what change will produce the effect desired, or knows no real or sup- posable mode of producing such change, it still cannot will. With the addition of such knowledge, will be- comes possible, though it does not follow of necessity ; otherwise, it would always immediately follow, and there would be no opportunity for the mind to select as to the different wants, or as to the different means of gratifying the same want ; the first want felt, with the first known means, would immediately determine the volition ; and no exercise of the judgment, no delibera- tion as to different wants and modes, would be possible, which is contrary to known facts. To be available for effort, the knowledge must extend to the future. A being which does not perceive enough of the future to conceive that the effect of its action will, or may be, to 100 ~ FEEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. gratify its want ; for instance, that taking food may re- lieve its hunger, cannot be said to act, to eat, from any intelligence of its own ; and, in such case, some power without it must move it to action if it be moved. It lacks an essential element of creative, or first cause ; it does not form a preconception, perfect or im- perfect, true or false, of the effect of its effort. It can have no design, no purpose, no intent, no end in view ; and hence has no inducements to effort. It is evident, that to will to do anything requires an idea, a precon- ception, of the thing, or of something to be done ; to make an effort and have no object of effort ; to will and not will anything is an impossible absurdity. Such a being, though it might still have sensations in the pres- ent and memories of the past, yet, perceiving no rela- tion of these sensations and memories to the future, Would have no means within itself of foreknowing the effects of its efforts on the future, or that there would be any effect whatever ; and would not will as to that future. It would have no will. It has no knowledge except as to the past and present ; it is not, in any sense, in the future, and cannot act in the future ; its whole sphere of thought and activity is confined to the past, bounded and separated from the future by the present. It cannot change the past and any effort in regard to it, as to remember, or to recombine what it remembers, is really an effort to produce a future effect. It cannot will any effect, or change, as to the past or present ; and thus, having no knowledge available for willing, its sphere of free activity, always commensu- rate with that knowledge, is reduced to nothing. All changes in, or of such a being, must still, like those of unintelligent matter, be effected by some power with- INSTINCT AND HABIT. 101 out itself, with only this difference, that the being may feel and recollect the changes, and matter cannot There is no conceivable way in which such a being could manifest its sensations and memories ; and, unless the external power, acting upon it, caused it to exhibit the phenomena we usually attribute to internal power — to will — such being would appear to us the same as senseless matter, moved only by external forces. If all finite intelligences were of this order, any real changes in matter could only be by the will of God. The same also of a being with sensation, but no power of volun- tary action — no will ; and a being with no knowledge of good and evil, — using these terms in a large sense, — would have no choice as to its sensations, no want, and no will. In such beings all change must be either im- mediately or mediately by the act of God. The neces- sity of this control by the Supreme Intelligence, to the preservation of the being, or to any change in it, dimin- ishes as the being derives or acquires power itself to contrive those plans, which are essential to its existence and well being.* The lowest order of intelligence, then, with which will is compatible, is that in which there is only one want ; with the knowledge of only one means of grati- fying it ; and that knowledge wholly intuitive. We say intuitive, because this implies less intelligence than acquired knowledge ; which presupposes an ability to learn by observation, or by rational process. Even to act from knowledge acquired by simple observation, re- quires an inference ; whereas this inference, or rather the idea or fact inferred, may itself be the subject of the intuitive knowledge. For instance, if I have ob- * See Appendix, Note XIX. 102 FREEDOM OF MIND LN WILLING. served that, when at one time I willed to move my hand, it did move ; I may, from association, expect, or, having some previous idea of the uniformity of cause and effect, infer that when again I repeat the effort, the effect may be the same ; whereas, the knowledge that willing the movement of the hand is the way to move it, may be directly imparted intuitively. In the former case I have to devise the plan to reach the end from my own knowledge ; in the latter, the plan of effort is previously devised for me. The sphere of effort, as also of freedom, in a being with only one want and one known means of gratifying it, would be limited to grati- fying its only want in the only mode known to it, or not gratifying it at all. It is still a sphere commensu- rate with knowledge. The gratification of its want would still depend on its own effort, without which its want would not be gratified. To reduce this to its low- est terms, we must suppose the being having only one want and an intuitive perception of only one mode of gratifying it ; also to have no knowledge — no thought — that it may possibly be better not to gratify it. If, in this hypothesis, we increase the number of wants, and suppose that only one of them arises at a time, it makes no material difference. In each case, as it oc- curs, it is still one want, one known mode of change, and no knowledge, or thought that it may be better not to adopt that mode, or to make no effort to produce that change. If more than one want arise at once, or if the being knows of more than one mode applicable to the want, it must select among them ; it must com- pare and judge, requiring that mode of effort, which is known as an exercise- of the rational faculties ; but, under the condition above named, no comparison is in- INSTINCT AND HABIT. 103 stituted ; there is no occasion, no room for the exercise of the rational faculties. Now all animals, so far as we can ascertain, come into existence with wants, and some one known mode of gratifying each want, and no thought that it may be better not to gratify it ; and hence, re- quiring no additional knowledge to direct its effort, and of course no exercise of the rational faculties, no delib- eration to obtain it ; and this is instinct. Instinctive action still involves a free effort of intel- ligence, though it precludes the exercise of the rational faculties in devising the mode of effort, or in selecting from different modes already devised by itself, or by others. Having the want, the requisite knowledge of the means, and the power to use the means, or to make an effort, it makes that effort. The effort in such case is spontaneous ; no deliberation being required ; but there is still an effort. It may, perhaps, be certain, that under those conditions such being will make the one particular effort, the only one known to it ; but this is not because it is constrained to make, but, because it is in no way restrained from making such effort. It feels the want, has the power to gratify it, knows how, and being free to exert its power, does itself exert it. The effort still is the actual, the uncontrolled, the free effort of the being that makes it, and without which effort the effect would not be produced. That it has no knowl- edge of any other effort, does not affect its freedom in making that which it does know. It is not as in the case of matter which some other power has put in mo- tion and directed — the freedom of which, if it can have any, consists in the absence of any obstruction, or coun- teraction — for in instinctive action intelligence still uses and directs its own powers, and, without such self- 104 FKEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. movement, there would be no exercise of its powers. That the knowledge by which it directs such exercise or effort is intuitive and not acquired, cannot affect its freedom in using its knowledge for directing its efforts, or for any other purpose. In either case, once in pos- session, it is equally knowledge, and the mind's own knowledge. An act of will is the primary self-move- ment of the mind, and not an antecedent cause of it. The effect, or sequence which it, as a first cause, produces, is some change of body or mind. In an act of will or effort, the agent, even when he knows only one mode of action, is free in a different and wider sense than that of not being counteracted in an action which some external power has imposed upon him. The agent willing is free to make and to direct the effort which it does itself make. If there be nothing in existence but himself acting through his will, and his want and knowledge, which are independent of his will, the effort may yet be made. The want itself cannot know, or apply the knowledge. The knowledge itself cannot know the want and adapt the effort to it, nor could both combined. This must be done by some- thing which is not only conscious of both the want and the knowledge, but is capable of perceiving the rela- tions between them, — by the intelligent being, — and, as there is no other existing activity (for by our hypothesis there is no other existence of any kind but the one active being, the want, and the knowledge), the act must be wholly its act ; and, there being no other power, it must act without restraint or constraint, it must act freely. Under our theory of instinctive action, the knowledge being reduced to the least quantity with which will is compatible, the spheres of freedom and INSTINCT AND HABIT. 105 of will there reach their least assignable limits, but are still coexistent ; and, like the decreasing quantities of the differential calculus, retain their relations to each other, even in their infinitesimal forms ; and when free- dom vanishes, the will of necessity vanishes also ; and this occurs when the knowledge of the future is reduced to zero, admitting of no preconception of any change to be willed, or made the object of effort. It will be ob- served, then, that the only essential difference between the observable phenomena of mechanical and of instinct- ive action, arises from the incorporation into a vital be- ing of one iota of knowledge, — the knowledge of one means corresponding to one want! Without this, even if a being had sensation and memory, its instinctive movements must be produced without any effort of its own by some external power ; and, whether the subject thus moved be that of being with spirit, bones and muscles, or that of stars and planets, such movements are purely mechanical. The proximity of the two, sep- arated only by this single step, has caused confusion in regard to them, and led some to doubt, whether what we class as instinctive actions are not, really, mechanic- al. And it seems quite conceivable that the first instinct- ive movements, as, for instance, that of the infant in obtaining food, are not preceded by any act of its will, but that all the movements of its muscles to that end are as immediately produced by the Supreme Intelli- gence, without the action, prior or present, of the in- fant's own will, as are the beginning of movements in lifeless matters ; that these first motions of the infant may be but God's teaching ; his mode of practically and directly imparting the knowledge., which is essen- tial to its existence, till, by imitation, or other means, 5* 106 FEEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. it learns to evoke, or to invoke the same effects by ita own efforts ; as a tutor, with his own hand, sometimes guides that of his pupil, to teach him how to write. If it has not the knowledge that it can will, and also how to will, by intuition, it must, in some way, acquire it before it can itself will, either freely or otherwise. It seems quite conceivable that this and other intuitive knowledge may be thus practically taught us, and es- pecially in regard to our bodily movements ; and yet, on closer examination, we may find that this is practi- cally impossible, and that such knowledge must be taught, or must consist in an idea, or conception of the mode directly imparted as such, and not derived from the observation of external movements of our own bodies, or those of others. The moving of the hand by external force is so entirely distinct from the internal effort to move it, that the knowledge of the latter could no more be obtained from the former, than the idea of weight from color. Nor could I ever learn to move my hand by will, from seeing another person move his hand, — for the process of will by which he does it, is not cognizable by the senses through which alone I could learn it in observing the external. All that I could possibly learn from seeing another person move his hand, by will, or from having my own hand moved by a force exerted through the will of another, would be the velocity and direction of its movements, and not the process of will by which it was so moved. Still less could I get this idea of movement by will, from any movement of my hand by an external force, which I did not refer to any act of will whatever. Nor can the mind first get this idea by the application of its reason to such external phenomena ; for no one has ever yet INSTINCT AND HABIT. 107 discovered any rational connection between the effort and the movement. The mind, then, does not get this knowledge of muscular movement at will, by observation, and must get it by intuition ; and by it we know only the fact without any rationale of it. It must be an ultimate idea directly imparted to us, and we may, with the first want of muscular action, be supposed to know the mode as well as at any subsequent recurrence of such want. There is nothing gained by supposing the first muscular movement to be mechanical, or the effect of external power. The facts in regard to a want which comes into existence after we have become capable of observing, confirm the conclusion that such knowledge is direct- ly imparted to us, and that all that is voluntary in sub- sequent action, is voluntary in the first instance ; that it is our effort, and is not the direct effect of the exter- nal power which imparts this knowledge. The change in our knowledge is only a reason for changing our own efforts. By the same mode of reasoning it may be shown, that we must also intuitively know the mode of putting our mental faculties in action ; and as every effort we make is, in the first instance, to affect some portion of either our body or mind, we are justified in regarding all these early actions, which we term instinctive, as the consequence of the effort of the being to gratify its want by a mode intuitively known to it ; and with a preconception, at least, of the proximate effects of that effort ; and hence, as really voluntary and not mere mechanical acts, from which, indeed, they are sufficient- ly distinguished by the existence of the effort and its prerequisites, want and knowledge. 108 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. If there are any such movements of the body pro- duced by external power, as have just been mentioned as conceivable, they are as purely mechanical as those of inert substance. In nature, when God works out his own plan, the action is called mechanical. When he imparts the knowledge of a plan to a finite being that works it out, the action of this being is instinctive. The uniformity and symmetry which we see in crys- tals, are God's perfect work, and rank with the mechan- ical. The bee, in forming its cells, though it executes with less nicety and precision, works from a plan equal- ly uniform and equally symmetrical, which God has furnished to it, and its action is instinctive. It knows the plan, but probably does not know why it is prefer- able to others. Some of its advantages were unknown, even to scientific men, until revealed by the aj)plication of the differential calculus. We have, then, incorporated in our beings, in the first instance, the power to will ; the want, which re- quires the exercise of that power ; and the knowledge which is requisite to its early and very limited exer- cise ; also the knowledge that by will we can put in exercise those mental faculties by which we may come to more perfect knowledge, which sometimes itself gratifies the want and at others reveals the action appo- site to the want. We also thus have the knowledge of the first step into the external by muscular action. The power to will, a want, and corresponding knowl- edge of means to gratify it, are constitutional elements of every creature that wills ; and such creature can at once will, and will freely, because it is constitutionally such a creature as it is. INSTINCT AND HABIT. 109 Instinct may teach the infant only sufficient to en- able it to come within the reach of easy effort to accom- plish its object; and this may be designed to indnct it into a habit of making effort, thus subserving a double purpose. If this be so, it will not materially vary the previous results. The instinctive actions, then, being voluntary, in what respect do they differ from other acts of will ? The whole phenomena of most voluntary actions, as ob- served in the adult man, are embodied in the want, the knowledge, including the preconception of the future, the deliberation, the volition, and the effect. The dis- tinction we are seeking is not in the faculty of will it- self ; we have not two wills. It is not in the want, for the same want may often be equally gratified by the instinctive, or by other modes. It cannot be in the vo- lition, for the same volition may arise in instinctive, as in other modes. It must then be in one or both of the other two elements — deliberation and knowledge, that is, in knowledge itself, or in the mode of obtain- ing, or of applying it. Now, one of the most obvious peculiarities of instinctive action is the absence of de- liberation, or of any exercise of the judgment, or ra- tional faculties, in devising or selecting means ; and this condition of absence, as we have just shown, can be perfect only when the knowledge of the mode of action is intuitive. In further confirmation of this we may remark that if, on any particular occasion for action, we have not the requisite knowledge, we must, in some way, acquire it ; and in its acquisition, or in its application, or in both, must use our rational faculties.* We have also * See Appendix, Note XX. 110 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. shown, that the mode of producing bodily movements by will, must be intuitively known ; and that this knowledge is simply of the fact, without any such ra- tionale of it as will enable us to vary the mode by any mental process. We know but one mode, and this knowledge is intuitive. In the first applications of this knowledge, we do not know that there may be some reason for not making the movement, and such action then is purely instinctive. As, in our efforts to produce external changes, we always begin with bodily move- ments, they form the substratum of our plans of action for such changes. In these plans we subsequently learn rationally to combine muscular movements to produce desired results, for which our intuitive knowledge is insufficient. Our plan may embrace certain particular movements, the order of which we arrange ; but we do not attempt to arrange, or plan the mode of producing these particular movements. When, subsequently, we have learned to look about us to see if there is sufficient reason for not making the contemplated movement, and have decided that there is not, we are in the same con- dition as if we had no knowledge, no thought, that there might possibly be such reason. In the last analysis, the bodily movement itself is always instinctive ; there is no plan, no deliberation, no exercise of judgment, as to the mode of making it ; but only as to the particular movements, or series of movements, to be effected by the known mode ; and the intuitive knowledge that by will we can produce muscular movement, is the starting point of all our efforts for external changes. From this one common point both instinctive and rational actions take their departure. In the instinct- ive, the plan of action, or the successive order of the INSTINCT AND HABIT. Ill series of volitions required to produce the intended re- sult is also intuitively known, is so imparted, either mediately or immediately, that it is the same as if in- corporated in the being, and requires no rational process to ascertain it. The whole plan may be known at once, or only each step, singly, as it is reached. In either case it still requires the exercise of the will to act out the plan thus furnished to it, without which the knowl- edge even of the whole plan, though associated with a want demanding its execution, would not avail. The kid, the moment it is born, can rise upon its feet and go directly to the food its mother supplies. It must not only know that by volition it can produce muscular movement, but it must know what particular movements to make, and the order of their succession. It works from a plan furnished to it, and not designed or contrived by itself. As, by its will, it still produces effects in the future, it is creative, but in an inferior de- gree. It creates, as the most untaught laborer, who re- moves the earth from the bed of a canal, has an agency in creating the canal, though he acts only under the di- rection of the superior intelligence, which designed and comprehends the whole structure. The inferior free agent, while executing all within its own sphere of ac- tion, — all the plan which itself forms, or a/pjprehends — ■ may subserve the purposes of a superior intelligence and help to execute its higher designs. But the intui- tive knowledge of a mode of producing bodily move- ment, except when mere bodily movement is itself the primary want, would answer no purpose unless the knowledge of the particular bodily movement, or series of movements, required to reach the end, is superadded. If this is intuitive also, requiring no exercise of the ra- 112 FREEDOM OF MIND IK WILLING. tional faculties, no deliberation as to the plan, or order of successive efforts, then the action, or series of actions, is purely instinctive. But to shut out all ground for the exercise of the rational faculties, there must, as be- fore stated, be only one want, one known mode of grat- ifying it, and no knowledge or thought that it may pos- sibly be better not to gratify it. If we suppose an intuitive knowledge of two or more modes of gratifying the same want, or that there are conflicting wants, we have a case for the exercise of the judgment. In the former of these cases, the mind may be said to be confined to the two or more modes. It has not designed or planned either of them ; but it may design and plan, and must decide as between them ; and then the subsequent action becomes, so far, a rational one ; and, if the decision is not immediately obvious to the knowing sense, deliberation — effort to examine and obtain more knowledge — with consequent delay, becomes an element in the mental process of de- termining the final effort. The same is obvious in the case of conflicting wants ; and we may remark that any indisposition to the effort, or a disposition to be passive and inert, is a conflicting want. When the plan of action was before unknown, and yet is obvious to simple mental perception, without pre- liminary effort to acquire it, the case approaches very nearly to that of action from a plan intuitively known, if, indeed, it can be practically distinguished from it. Another easy divergence, from the purely instinct- ive, seems to be that in which the knowledge of the required change, or series of changes, instead of being intuitive, is derived from the simple observation of such external changes, or movements as we can see others INSTINCT AND HABIT. 113 make, requiring only to be imitated. This differs from the intuitive, in requiring an effort of attention to ob- serve the movements or their successive order ; and an exercise of the rational faculty to infer, that as we have the power to move our muscles, we may there- fore be able to make similar movements, and that they will lead to similar results. We might thus learn to apply our knowledge of muscular movement by will ; though, as already shown, we never could acquire this knowledge by merely observing others. As distinguishing features of instinctive action, we have, then, the absence of any plan, design, or contri- vance, on the part of the active being, to attain its end ; and, in place of such contrivance of its own, the knowl- edge of a plan directly imparted to it, ready made, re- quiring no contrivance of its own, and no deliberation. The circumstances under which such actions are most conspicuous, perhaps the only cases of purely in- stinctive action in human beings, occur in the infant, when its whole attention is absorbed by the want of the moment, when its knowledge is limited to its intuitive perception of only one mode of gratifying that want, and it has yet no thought that it may be better not to gratify it. In brutes it continues more prominent, be- cause they learn less of other than the intuitive modes. It seems, too, not improbable that, with the deficient ability to plan rational modes of action, the necessities of existence may require an increase of the intuitive modes ; but if our distinction is well founded, we cannot deny rational actions to most of the inferior animals, or even that a large portion of their actions are of this class, though more alloyed with the instinctive, than those of man. The hungry dog, acting instinctively, would not 114: FREEDOM OF MIND LN WILLING. hesitate to seize the joint of meat he sees before him in his master's kitchen ; but he learns that, in the presence of the cook, the effort to get it may be unsuccessful, or be attended with unpleasant consequences, and he gov- erns himself in conformity to this acquired knowledge, including his consequent preconceptions of future effects, and foregoes the effort to appropriate the meat. If, in view of the circumstances, he plans to wait the absence of, or in some way to induce the cook to let him have the meat, he exhibits still more of rational design than by simple forbearance. Though instinctive action is thus less conspicuous, as the acquired knowledge in- creases, it is conceivable that a being with any amount of such acquirement may act without using it to contrive means, and may wholly disregard any plan it may have previously contrived for similar occasions. In man, a want may be so imperative or so absorbing as to ex- clude all others ; and also all comparison of the differ- ent modes of gratifying it ; and all deliberation as to whether to gratify it or not ; and, in such cases, he acts as a being having only one want, one means of gratify- ing it, and no knowledge or thought that it may be bet- ter not to gratify it ; if the one known means has to be found, the action is a rational one ; but if it is intui- tively known, all the conditions of purely instinctive action are fulfilled. Cases in which our rational actions thus approximate more or less nearly to the instinctive, occur when we are under the influence of some absorb- ing passion, as, for instance, of fear excited to terror, in sudden fright, and we yield to the impulse to flee from whatever has terrified us. If, in so doing, the mode is immediately perceived, or if it is a result of our own efforts in searching out and designing a plan of action, INSTINCT AND HABIT. 115 but, under the excitement, so instantaneously formed and applied that the element of deliberation is very minute, the action will be liable to be confounded with the instinctive, though properly belonging to the rational. That we nee from danger, and not toward it, indi- cates the formation of a plan of action founded on our perception of the circumstances. We may intuitively know that to avoid being burned we must move from the fire, and how to so move ; but we must still per- ceive — know — where the fire is, and the combination of the two knowledges may be by^a rational process. In other words, the knowledge of the general facts may be intuitive, and their application to particular cases ra- tional. In running from a fire, we may fall down a precipice of which we well knew, but did not take time to embrace the knowledge in our deliberation, or use it in the preconception of the effects of our action.* When we are conscious of forming the plan of action at the moment, however quickly, we are in no danger of con- founding it with the instinctive. The distinction, how- ever, is practically not always obvious, and especially in those cases in which the plan of action is easily and quickly formed. The movement of the jaw, to relieve the pain occasioned by the pressure of a person's own teeth on his finger, would, no doubt, be deemed by some an instinctive action ; but there have been cases of idiots who did not know enough to do this, though they had all the intuitive knowledge requisite to make the movement, as evinced by their voluntarily making it whenever they ate ; showing that, at least in them, an inference from the peculiar circumstances of the case * See Appendix, Note XXI. 116 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILUNG. — more knowledge — was required to enable them to apply their intuitive knowledge of the mode of moving the jaw, in such way as would relieve the pain of the finger. It may be as difficult for such an idiot to form a plan for extricating bis finger, as for a horse to plan to extricate his foot when it gets entangled in the hal- ter. The pain being in his finger, he, not improbably, seeks to move and thus to effect change in it, as the horse pulls on his entangled foot for relief; in both cases, from not knowing plans adapted to the circum- stances, aggravating the difficulty. In such persons, the intuitive knowledge may be less than in some others ; but the particular \ point at which the intuitive must be aided by the acquired, is not material to the illustra- tion.* Though, in terms, the rational may be clearly de- fined by the formation of a plan of action by the active being ; and the instinctive, by the plan of action being furnished to it by intuition, ready formed ; yet prac- tically we do not always readily perceive the exact boundary between them.f They are often blended, and perhaps the rational always embraces something of the instinctive. We may rationally plan a series of suc- cessive muscular movements in a certain order, but, as before stated, the mode of making each of the move- ments by will is always instinctive. The same rule will also apply to the use of our mental powers by a pre- arranged plan. The mode in which the knowledge of a plan of ac- tion is acquired does not affect the action itself. Once acquired, whether by the teachings of the Infinite, or of a finite intelligence, or by our own rational investiga- * See Appendix, Note XXII. f See Appendix, Note XXIII. INSTINCT AND HABIT. 117 tion, or by simple perception, the acting from it is the same ; and, having memory, we can repeat or reenact the same, by mere association with our wants knowing when to repeat it. The instinctive and the rational both admit of being thus repeated by memory and mere imitation, though neither memory nor imitation could have had any part in our first instinctive actions, for there were then no actions to remember or to imi- tate ; and when ever the young intelligence begins to work by memory of a plan adopted in previous acts, instead of one known by a direct intuition applicable to the case, it begins to be the subject of habit. The same of those actions which we have ourselves designed, how- ever complicated, however much contrivance and inge- nuity they may have originally required, when, after frequent repetition, we perform them in proper order by memory instead of by a reference to the original reasons of that order, they, too, have become habitual. The peculiar characteristic of habit seems to be that we become so familiar with the plan by which the de- sired result is to be reached, that, at every stage of it, we know what to do from what has already been done, and do not have to form a preconception of the future, or, at most, not more of it than the next immediate act, or even recur to any preconception previously formed of it ; we do not have to perceive the connection of the immediate act contemplated with the end sought. We may merely recollect that, on previous like occasions, we did thus or so with satisfactory results ; and that, after such an act, such another act immediately follows. We do it by rote. Suppose a man, who is accustomed to walk in a certain path from one place to another, wishes to go to some other place, requiring him to di- 118 FEEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. verge from the familiar track. If, on reaching the point of divergence, he fails to look at the portion of his plan, which is yet in the future, bnt, as on former occasions, directs himself in each successive act by refer- ence to the preceding one, or by mere association with it, he will take the old path, and will not discover his mistake until he looks to the future and refers to his preconception of the result intended, and of the means of attaining it. This habitually pursuing an old plan when a new one had been designed, is matter of common ex- perience. As a consequence of this working from mem- ory of an old plan, instead of one newly formed for the occasion, there is in habitual action little, if any, need of deliberation, or for the exercise of the rational faculties. As, in the case of instinctive action, there is also in the habitual, a plan ready formed in the mind, and though it may be there, by our own previous efforts, instead of by intuition, it subserves much the same purpose. Perhaps the only essential difference is, that the intui- tive knowledge may embrace that of the occasions for adopting the particular plan ; and in adopting our own previously formed plans, we have always to determine by an exercise of judgment the proper occasions for their application. This, however, as already suggested, may sometimes be necessary also in regard to the appli- cation of a mode, or a series of actions intuitively known as the means of reaching an end ; and in the habitual, after we have decided to adopt the mode, or series, we pursue it without further deliberation, or exercise of the judgment in going through the successive steps. Again, as before observed, the occasion upon which to use a known plan, either intuitive or acquired, may be sug- gested by its mere association with recurring circum- INSTINCT AND HABIT. 119 stances, and, if that examination of onr knowledge, which results in a judgment, is an element of associa- tion, snch examination, or exercise of the rational facul- ties in comparing and judging is often so slight, or so instantaneous as to be almost unnoticeable. We ob- serve, then, how nearly habitual action brings us back from the rational to the instinctive ; and in this we may find the significance of the common saying that " habit is second nature." The instinctive also resembles the habitual in this, that it is not essential in either that we should ever know, at one time, any more of the plan than the connection between the action just done and the one next in order. The bee, when it has construct- ed one side and one angle of its cell, need not know that it will require five more such sides and angles to com- plete it. The most that is essential to its subsequent ac- tion is the knowledge that the next step is to make an- other like side and angle ; and so in the habitual, all that is requisite is the recollection of what action comes next, and then again the next. We find another similarity in the fact that, in re- sorting to an habitual mode, even though originally ac- quired, and especially if then adopted after full deliber- ation, the mind may again use it, as if it were the only one possible ; just, as in the first instinctive action, it adopts the one and only known mode, which it has by intuition. "With these points in common, the instinctive may glide easily into the habitual. By repetition in practice, the memory of the consecutive order of the ac- tions may take the place of the direct knowledge of that order.* Though more unlike, rational actions become habit- * See Appendix, Note XXIV. 120 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. ual by tlie same process — by the repetition, on like oc- casions, of the series of efforts embracing the plan of ac- tion, till we distinctly remember the routine of the suc- cessive efforts, and can go over them in the same order, without reference to the end or the reason of such or- der. In the habitual, as already intimated, the mind may determine each successive action, not by its per- ception of its connection with the future, but by associa- tion with that which is past ; and this analogy of such actions to the movement of a material body by a force behind it, without itself perceiving its course in the fu- ture, has probably favored the popular application of the term mechanical to habitual actions, which was naturally enough suggested by the comparatively small amount of mental effort they require. It is obvious that a very large proportion of the ac- tions of adults are habitual, and that our rational ac- tions, in becoming habitual, approach so nearly to in- stinctive, is probably one cause of that difficulty in distinguishing the instinctive from the rational, which is so general ; a difficulty which may be further in- creased by the instinctive also actually becoming habit- ual, the two thus blending together and becoming un- distinguishable in one common reservoir, from which the main current of our actions subsequently flows, and through which it is often difficult to trace their respect- ive sources. Customary or imitative actions also belong to this group. When we do anything merely because it is customary, we adopt the plans or modes of action which we have seen others adopt, without ourselves contriving, and sometimes without even perceiving the reason why others have adopted them. In regard to in- INSTINCT AND HABIT. 121 stinctive, habitual, and customary actions, the question may arise whether it may or may not be better to class those in which we perceive the reason of the plan at the time of action, with the rational actions. There is evidently, in this, a distinction for which philosophical accuracy requires a corresponding difference in ex- pression. To recapitulate ; mechanical action, or material movements and changes, are either God's action, imme- diate or mediate, upon his own plan — a part of his rational actions ; or, as seems to be conceivable and more in couformity to the popular idea, the necessary consequences of blind causes, as of matter in motion, which can have no plan. Instinctive actions are the efforts of a finite intelli- gent being, conformed by its intelligence to the plan which God has furnished, or furnishes to it, ready formed. Rational actions are the efforts of an intelligent being, finite or infinite, in conformity with a plan, which itself has contrived, by means of those faculties, which make a part of the constitution of its being, de- rived or underived. Customary or imitative action is the action of a finite being in conformity to a plan which it has derived from its observation of the action of others. Habitual action is the action of a finite, intelligent being, in conformity to a plan which it has in its mind, ready formed, with which practice has made it so familiar, that each successive step is associated with, and is suggested by those which precede it, requiring no examination as to its influence, or its connection with the desired end, or effect in the future ; whether 6 122 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. that plan was originally instinctive, rational, or cus- tomary. In regard to habit, I would further remark that it has, in some respects, the same relation to action, that memory has to knowledge. They are both retaining powers. As memory of the results of former investiga- tions, or of former observation, obviates the necessity of repeated investigation or observation to enable us to know, so habit obviates the necessity of examining as to the probable result of the different proposed acts, or of repeating the experiments required in the first action, and which, with the caution then requisite, rendered it slow and tedious, compared with the facility acquired after practice has made us familiar with the order of the successive efforts, and rendered us fearless of any latent consequences, the apprehensions of which, in the first instance, would induce careful examination of our preconceptions of the future effects. Habit seems to be mainly dependent on memory and association. The first time certain circumstances occur, if we have not the knowledge of the mode of action intuitively, we have to examine, compare, judge, and perhaps resort to ex- ■ periments as to how we shall act ; when they recur, we may adopt the former modes implicitly, if the result was then satisfactory, or with such modifications as ex- perience may suggest ; and repeat the experiments, with variations, till we have got what we deem the best. When, from the plan adopted on a former occa- sion, gratification has resulted, a recurrence of similar circumstances suggests, by association, the want of like gratification. This want is also intensified, not only by the recollection of the former pleasure, but the mind, being relieved from the labor of a particular examina- INSTINCT AND HABIT. 123 tion of the means and of devising a plan; and also from apprehension as to unseen consequences, which rendered circumspection necessary in the first instance, may direct its attention to the expected gratification, and be almost exclusively absorbed by it.* In regard to any action requiring several successive efforts, as, for instance, walking, a man with full strength, unless knowing by intuition not only the mode of making the particular muscular movements, but their proper respect- ive order and foree, would, probably, in a first effort to walk, have to proceed very slowly, giving a con- sciousj attentive, tentative effort to each movement, and perhaps then not always succeed in practically doing as he desired ; but, by repeated experiments, he learns the proper order and degree of the movements, and by repetition becomes able to make them without any conscious thought as to the order, degree, or result, each effort suggesting the succeeding one, as a letter of the alphabet, after much repetition, suggests the one which follows it. If, by memory, we retained the knowledge of the letters of the alphabet and of their order of succession only long enough for the occasion, we should have to relearn, every time we had occasion for such knowledge ; and but for the retaining power of habit, we should have either to study or experiment in regard to every particular act, not instinctive, and as to the order of any instinctive series of actions, as often as the same might be required to reach the desired re- sult. Habit is but a substitution of the memory of for- mer results of investigation, and experience for present investigation and trial ; those former results being sug- gested by association with like circumstances. In other * See Appendix, Note XXV. 124: FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. words, it is memory, aided by association, and applied to actions, when like occasions for them recur. In cases to which it is applicable, habit thus relieves the mind of nearly all the mental labor requisite to action — that of investigating the circumstances and forming its creative preconceptions in the future, and thus facili- tates our advancement in action ; making it easy for us to do that which, we are accustomed to do, whether right or wrong. While habit thus facilitates effort, it also enables us readily to select from among passing occurrences those which require attention or effort, and to dismiss others almost without notice. When we have no special occa- sion to know the hour, the striking of a clock, which is constantly repeated within our hearing, makes so little impression, that it is not recollected a moment after- wards. We know from repeated observation that we need not attend to it. It awakens no interest, no want, in us. Ask a man who has just looked at his watch, for the time, and, in a majority of cases, he cannot tell you. He habitually saw the time, as indicated on the dial plate, and inferred that the hour of his engagement had not yet arrived, or found that it suggested nothing to be done, and immediately dismissed the whole mat- ter. He can give no account of what passed in his mind. Perhaps a little more of memory of the pro- cess so instantaneous would reveal to him that he merely saw that a certain hour had not arrived, rather than what the present time was. The want for which he made the effort to look at his watch was satisfied by the former, and he had no interest to know or to retain the latter. That habit especially applies to those actions which INSTINCT AND HABIT. 125 we have most frequent occasion to perform, increases the benefits we derive from it. It seems, however, to be frequently regarded as a vicious element of mind. This, probably, often arises from only looking at its power to perpetuate or facilitate actions which are wrong, overlooking its influence on those which are right, and may be confirmed by the further considera- tion, that retaining the old habit enables us to dispense with new acquisitions and with new efforts, thus foster- ing indolence ; and that which legitimately furnishes the great means of progress in action, thus perverted, enables a man to forego the efforts, which are the very germs of this progress. He has become familiar with one course of action — habit has made it easy to him ; it no longer requires the examination, the experimental efforts, the circumspection, which are necessary to learn and apply new methods. He has also learned the grati- fication arising from the habitual course, and does not know, and does not seek to know, that by pursuing a different course he may obtain a higher, more perma- nent, or more unalloyed gratification, or, at least, has not so brought the knowledge home to his affections, and into such practical form, as to induce a want for such higher gratification. Being slothful, the higher and higher wants, which with efforts for progress are continually evolved in the mind, are undeveloped, and remain in their original chaotic state, without the sphere of his efforts, in a region which he has never at- tempted to penetrate, and, by the exercise of his crea- tive powers, to reduce to order. CHAPTER XII. ILLUSTRATION FROM CHESS. As a partial illustration of some of the foregoing views, let us suppose two persons, A and B, to be en- gaged in playing chess ; and as there is no conceivable necessity for supposing any other intelligence to do, or to have done, anything in relation to the game, we may, so far as the players and their efforts are con- cerned, assume that none others exist. The players have no intuitions of the game ; but the knowledge of its laws, indicating what moves can and what cannot be made, having been taught them by others, without any contrivance of their own, is somewhat analogous to that intuitive knowledge which is the foundation of our early actions ; and the unreflecting spontaneity with which a young player avails himself of an opportunity to take a valuable piece, without reference to future consequences, has some resemblance to instinctive, un- deliberate action. The first move to be made by A is, so far as the position of the pieces is concerned, to be made under precisely the same circumstances as has been every other first move, which he has ever made, and he may now make his habitual move without rein- vestigation, and each player continues to do this until the combinations become such that past experience can no longer avail. Or either may try an entirely new ILLUSTEATION FKOM CHESS. 127 first or subsequent move, and test its advantages. In any case, however, both the players soon come to new or unremembered combinations. A has just moved, and may be supposed to be passively waiting the move of B, who is now the only active intelligence, and is to will his next move in view of the new circumstances which the last move of A has presented, and which cir- cumstances cannot now be changed until after himself wills and makes his move. His primary want is to checkmate his opponent ; but, in view of the circum- stances^ he knows that, in conformity with the laws of the game, he cannot gratify this want by any move now possible. He then wants to make the move which will most tend to checkmate. This secondary want in- duces him to make an effort to ascertain what move will best fulfil this condition. He examines, he delib- erates — that is, he makes an effort to obtain more knowledge, with which to direct his final effort, or move ; and then, by means of his knowledge of the present position of the pieces, and his power of forming an idea of the future, including his conjectures of the subsequent move of his opponent, he compares his pre- conceptions of the possible or probable result of various moves ; and having, by that use of his knowledge which results in a judgment, selected among them, wills, or puts forth the final effort in conformity to that judg- ment. He does not fully examine all the possible re- sults of every possible move. This would make the game insufferably tedious, indeed, impossible to be played in a lifetime ; but the time he will give to de- liberating is also a matter for him to judge of, or decide by his knowing faculty ; and, in fact, he often moves with a consciousness that his examination is very im- 128 FREEDOM OF MIND IN "WILLING. perfect. Of two or more moves, lie may not have de- cided which is best ; but, the fact is, he does decide to adopt one, and as, by the hypothesis, there is no other existing intelligent activity to decide for him, he must, in snch case, himself decide which to adopt. So far as his present volition and act are concerned, it is the same as if he had never before willed or acted. That he has contribnted, by his previous moves, to make the circumstances as they are, does not now affect the con- siderations by which his present move is to be deter- mined. For the purposes of this action, he begins with the circumstances as they now are, and is precisely in the same situation as if he found the game in that con- dition and was (being already possessed of the same knowledge of the past and present, and with the same power of anticipating the future) to move for the first time. Every time he wills, or puts forth an effort, making or planning a move, is a new and distinct exer- cise of his creative energy ; and the effect is a new crea- tion, evolved from the new- circumstances, sometimes getting existence only in the conception of his own mind, and sometimes actualized, or made palpable to others, in the altered position of the piece moved. We might suppose a more complicated game, in which several persons moved at the same time on one side, each having to take into account not only the probable future moves of the several opponents, but, also, the simultaneous moves of his several coadjutors ; and this would more nearly resemble the complicated game of real life. But though, in real life, many may move at once, yet, to each individual, certain circum- stances are presented for him to act upon at the mo- ment of willing ; and whether, at that moment, these ILLTJSTEATION FROM CHESS. 129 circumstances are fixed, or are still flowing by the in- fluence of some other intelligence or force, is but a cir- cumstance to be taken into view in willing, as also the anticipated future action of other intelligences ; as the future possible or probable moves of one party at chess are taken into account by the other in determining his own move. If we look for the cause of the move, we refer it immediately to the will of the mover ; and if we seek the reason why he willed this and not some other move, we may, in most cases, by making such an examination of the circumstances as we suppose he made prior to moving, form a conjecture, in some cases amounting almost to certainty, in others only to the smallest degree of probability ; while, in some instances, we may fail to discover a probable or even a supposable reason. The same thing occurs in real life, showing that we differ in our knowledge, or come to different conclusions from the same premises. One man may better understand the game of life, or see farther or more clearly into the future, than another. Some can successfully compete with several skilful chess players, or can ably direct several distinct games at once ; and so some men are a match for many others in some of the rivalries of active life, and accomplish their ends in competition with numerous opponents. In a game of * diplomacy, a Talleyrand or Metternich would succeed against most men, many men combined, or in separate games with each at the same time. And a Being of in- finite power and wisdom would accomplish His pur- poses, though opposed by any number of finite intelli- gences, all exerting their finite power as freely as He His infinite. To one uninstructed, the chess board with a game 6* 130 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. partly played out, would appear a mere confusion, without any more arrangement than a child discovers in the position of the stars ; and the moves would seem to him as arbitrary and erratic as the motions of planets and comets did to the early pastoral astronomers ; but on ascertaining and applying the laws of the game, the element of design immediately appears, and an harmo- nious system is evolved from the apparent chaos. It is a creation — a very tiny creation — in which the finite intelligence has as freely exerted its creative power in devising and assigning the laws of the movements of the game, and in moving the pieces in conformity to those laws, as the Supreme Intelligence exerts its in- finite power in making laws and moving the universe in conformity with them. The inventor of the game has, in fact, created another sphere for the exercise of human activity ; like the great sphere of God's crea- tion, conditioned by certain laws, which, for the pur- poses of the game, must be regarded as inviolable as if decreed by infinite wisdom, and enforced by infinite power. It is a sphere in which many of the same pro- cesses of mind, which are common in active life, are brought into play, and in which are formed habits of effort, of deliberation, or the investigation of intricate combinations, preparatory to action ; and perseverance in effort under circumstances apparently the most hope- less ; and in which many of the emotions of real life, as hope, fear, despondency, the feeling of disappointment, the sense of superiority, the humiliation of defeat, the pride of victory, also have place.* If we suppose only one intelligent being to be en- gaged in the game, with an automaton chess player so * See Appendix, Note XXVI. ILLTJSTKATION FKOM CHESS. 131 contrived that the automatic moves will be in conform- ity with the laws of the game, we shall have a case analogous to that of the finite intelligence acting with reference to the anticipated action of the infinite, uni- formly conforming to certain laws, the consequences of which can be only partially known, or vaguely antici- pated by the finite. But for this uniformity in the Di- vine action, our position, in the efforts of life, would be that of a person who should attempt to play chess with one who was wholly regardless of the laws of the game. In such case, all effort in investigating, planning, de- signing, and moving would be useless ; the game would be impossible. And so in the affairs of real life ; but for the recognized uniformity in the action of the Su- preme Intelligence, there would be no reason or ground for the efforts of finite free agents. In chess it often happens that, in conformity with the rules, only one move is possible ; for instance, when the king must be put out of check, and there is only one move by which it can be done. This resembles some cases of supposed necessity in the voluntary efforts of real life. By the laws of the game, the player is con- fined to one move, and has no liberty to will any other. But there is no conceivable case in which the mind is, or can be, compelled to will at all, and this apparent want of liberty or analogy to it, in chess, is merely an inability in the agent to conform to laws which he has voluntarily adopted for his own government, and, at the same time, not to conform to them ; which, so far from detracting from a man's freedom in determining his own volitions, is essential to it ; for if, at the same moment that he either decided or willed to conform, he could also decide, or will, not to conform, and the two 132 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. mental efforts were to go forth simultaneously, his power would be completely neutralized. It is a mere inability to work contradictions, and cannot even be re- garded as a deficiency of power, for no increase of pow- er tends to give such ability. In the case supposed, the effort of the player to make a particular move is made to depend on his knowledge of the laws of the game, and any other knowledge which may lead him to want to conform to them ; and such government of himself to gratify this want, by the aid of any knowledge he may have, does not make a case varying from those which we have before considered. The laws of the game are certainly not more obligatory upon him than the just demands of his country, or the laws of God, or his own convictions of right. In all such cases, the ex- istence of such obligation, or of any conclusions, or in- ferences from them, are but circumstances to be consid- ered by the mind in determining its efforts ; but do not affect its freedom in making the efforts, the making, or not making of which still depends on itself. The memory of the conclusions of former examina- tions of the circumstances, of which these laws form a portion, may enable a man to dispense with present ex- amination, and act from habit. In chess, each player tacitly pledges himself to conform to the laws of the game ; and a man, on full deliberation, may resolve al- ways to conform his efforts to the laws of God, and, in both cases, his compliance may become habitual, so that he ceases to deliberate, or to form new plans of ac- tion, spontaneously adopting the old ; but this substitu- tion of the result of a former for a present examination, does not conflict with freedom, but is itself an act of freedom. If the mind's predetermination to be gov- ILLUSTRATION FEOM CHESS. 133 erned by certain laws, or in certain circumstances to act in certain uniform modes, could be regarded as a voluntary curtailment of its liberty, that which was thus abandoned could be voluntarily resumed, and the mind, by its own act, regain its entire freedom ; bat the free- dom of the mind is as apparent in the voluntary curtail- ment, as in the reextension of its sphere of effort. But, in adopting such laws or modes, the mind does not, by its free effort, curtail its freedom, but uses its knowl- edge of general rules to lessen the deliberation required in each particular case as it occurs, or to direct its efforts in cases for which its knowledge, if it did not embrace these laws, or general rules, would be wholly inadequate. That God wills to conform His action to certain laws or uniform modes, does not impair His freedom. In regard to the influence of law on individual ac- tion or effort, we would remark generally, that matter cannot know the law, and, therefore, cannot govern it- self by law ; that an intelligent being, knowing the law, and not willing to be governed by it does not so govern himself ; but that, in both instances, the move- ments or actions of the matter, or of such non-willing being, if made to conform to the law, must be so con- formed by some external power, to which the law is a rule of action. If the intelligence making or promul- gating the law enforces it by an exercise of its own power, then the law is only a law to itself, and the will of a controlled being has no part in it, and has no more to do with the result of a law thus enforced, than a heavy stone has to do with the effects of gravitation. A law made by one being for the government of an- other, and not enforced by direct application of power, 134 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING, must depend for its efficiency upon the will of that other. He may will to obey it, because, having exam- ined the particular law, he deems it good in itself ; or because it is dictated by a being in whose wisdom and beneficence he confides. In the latter case he adopts the rule, because he perceives that it is a particular case of a more general rule, on which he has before decided. In all cases of government by law, we are influ- enced, not by the existence of the law, but by our pre- conceptions of the effects of breaking the law, or of con- forming to it. It may be that we perceive it will grieve or offend one whom we love ; or it may be the consideration of more direct personal consequences, dis- tinctly and directly apprehended, or inferred from the attributes of the law-maker. The knowledge of the law is always such an addition to our knowledge as enables us better to preconceive the future, and especially in regard to what others, in certain contingencies, will do ; but, in the mind's application of this knowledge, to de- termine its own efforts, there is nothing coiJlicting with its freedom in willing. If it wills in conformity to the law, it is just as free as if it wills in opposition to it. The word law, in such connection, seems to be used in two distinct senses ; the one indicating a rule by which causes are governed in producing effects ; the other ex- pressing a mere uniformity of such effects. But the observation of this uniformity of effects is perhaps but a mode in which we learn the law of the cause which produces them ; as, for instance, by our observation of the changes in the material universe, we come to know the laws which God has adopted for His own govern- ment in producing these changes, and the two senses of the term become blended in one. But be this as it ILLUSTRATION FROM CHESS. 135 may, the knowledge of such laws, whether they are the mere uniformity of the effects, or those invariable rules or modes which an intelligent cause adopts in produc- ing them, enables us better to preconceive the effects of our efforts, and, of course, to determine them more wisely ; or, at least, more certainly to produce the effect intended. CHAPTER XIII. OP WANT AND EFFORT IN VARIOUS ORDERS OF INTELLIGENCE. From the foregoing views it follows that want, often regarded as a weakness, or defect, is really requisite to all but the lowest forms of animated existence. It is necessary to all intelligent activity, and hence, essential to all the enjoyment which arises from the exercise of our faculties and from that conscious progress, or that satisfaction in the performance of duty, which attends our proper efforts. It is necessary to elevate us above the condition of mere sensitive and sensuous being ; and, as no intelligent being will make effort to do what he does not want to do, it is thus necessary, with a meta- physical necessity, which even Omnipotence could not obviate. If these views are well founded, God Himself can- not be active, or make any progress, or produce change in anything except by being the subject of want ; and, in every order of intelligent being, to want is as essen- tial to the exercise of a free creative energy, as to know. This imputation of want to the Supreme Being, to some may seem irreverent, and especially to those who habitually regard it as an imperfection. Let such con- sider that we know God only by the attributes which He manifests in action, or by the effects of His action ; Or WANT AND EFFORT. 137 that we cannot conceive of Him as destitute of quali- ties ; and that the simplest and most evident affirma- tion which we can make, touching the exercise of His active power, is that He doeth that which He wants to do. Nothing, by the mere fact of existence, can be a cause of any effect after such existence began ; for all the effects of which its mere existence is the cause would take place the instant it came into existence, and all its causative power would then be exhausted and cease. It could produce no further changes even in itself; and hence, a sole first cause, without any want to excite it to effort, would immediately on com- ing into existence, become inert. Such existence, then, would not act on anything, but would become mere material to be acted upon. It is only by the faculty of effort that intelligence rises above this condition ; and this faculty, to be avail- able for such elevation to us, without direct, extrinsic aid, must either be continuous, or we must have a re- taining, internal power, with some adaptation to put this retained power in action. In mind, one or the other of the required conditions is fulfilled by the con- stant, or by the recurring influences 01 want, which is the only mode known to us, and perhaps the only one which is conceivable, for exciting the voluntary action of an intelligent being, and moving it from a quiescent state. If we ever become quiescent, we cease to be cause, and this want must then become manifest by some change effected by some active cause without us, the effect of which, from the constitution of our being, we may recognize without effort of our own ; and the fact iSj we cannot always prevent such cognition. If 138 FKEED0M OF MIND IN WILLE5TG. our mental activity ever entirely ceases, it must then be as if we had no mind, and we mnst be re-minded before we can again become an active canse ; and this, as before suggested, may be done by want in us, pro- duced by causes to the action of which our own efforts are not essential. If matter in motion is cause, its power, while it has any, is continuous and ready to be exerted whenever the occasion for it occurs. Being unintelligent, no ap- plication of self-moving power to it is possible ; having no mind, it cannot be reminded. It must be true of every intelligence, of whatever order, that if its activity entirely ceases, it cannot, of itself, put itself in action, till some extrinsic activity has, in some way, acted upon it ; and the only condi- tion upon which a sole First Cause could entirely sus- pend activity, without annihilation, would be by its first creating other cause, which would continue to be active independently of the creative cause, and which, by producing some subsequent change, would react upon and arouse the now dormant cause which by previous activity created it. There is, however, no reason to suppose tha*t the supreme First Cause ever becomes quiescent ; and it is even doubtful whether the finite mind ever does. It is only certain that we do not always remember in what we were active, or that we were active in any wise. ~No intelligent being can do anything unless it makes effort to do something. It may try to do one thing and really do something else. A man may attempt to take a flower ; and, for that purpose, by the requisite voli- tion move the hand, but, instead of reaching the flower, may overturn a vase, which he did not observe. His OF WANT AND EFFORT. 139 plan did not embrace all the essential facts, or circum- stances ; his knowledge, at least as applied, was defect- ive, and the effect did not conform to the preconception. Still, but for the effort to reach the flower, he would not have overturned the vase. If his power does it and yet he does not exert his own power, the power must exert itself, or be exerted by something without him and not of him ; and, in either case, it is not his power, and he has no agency either in putting forth the power, or in producing the effect. He does not even make the signal for some other cause to put the power which produces the effect into action. If, then, the power of an intelligent being is put forth at all, it must be by the being to which such power pertains ; arid the con- dition which makes the difference between the non- exercise and the exercise of its power is that of effort ; and hence, its effort is necessary to its doing or being the cause of anything, even of that which it does not intend to do. But, when an intelligent being makes an effort to do something, it is with an intent and design to do it ; and it will not try, endeavor, make effort to do anything which it does not want to do. So that, the want to do something is essential to its doing anything, even that which it does not want to do. But, though the want rouses the mind to effort, it does not make or direct the effort. The intelligent agent that perceives the relation of the anticipated sequences of the effort to the want, must do this ; though, without the want, these sequences would not be sought. If Napoleon, on the morning of the battle of Austerlitz, had not been aroused from his slumber, he would not then have fought that battle ; but the page, the drum-beat, the cannon's roar, or the want of 140 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. food, of activity, or of glory, which aroused him, had nothing to do with the direction or order of the battle. So the want arouses the mind to effort, but does not, and, being unintelligent, cannot direct, or even indicate, what effort. This must be determined by the mind, which uses its knowledge, intuitive or acquired, for that purpose.* But, admitting that want is in all cases a necessary prerequisite to effort, some may suppose that effort is a condition of cause only in a finite being ; and that infinite power accomplishes its ends without effort. Such, however, do not imagine that He produces effects or changes without an act of His will ; and, if our defi- nition of will is correct, this is an effort. To suppose any intelligence to become the cause of any change without some action of its own, is to suppose intelli- gence to be cause and a necessary cause, merely in virtue of its existence. But all the effects of such a cause must be simultaneous with its existence, and its causative power must cease at the moment of its birth. Now, at any given moment of time, all the causes which can influence the immediate succession of events must exist ; and, if the effects of all these causes are necessary consequences of their existence^ then these effects must all be coexistent with such existence ; and, even if we suppose one or more of these effects to be the creation of a new cause, if its effects, too, are neces- sary consequences of its existence, they, also, would be coexistent with, its creation ; and the causative power of the first cause, with that of all subsequent created causes, would be exhausted at the same instant and no effects could be produced in the future. Hence the necessity * See Appendix, Note XXVII. OF WANT AND EFFORT. 141 of some cause, the effects of which do not, of necessity, result from its existence, but which retains a power of producing change that it does not, of necessity, exert at the instant — which is not cause merely in virtue of its existence. Matter, retaining, or extending its power in time by means of motion ; and intelligence, with power which it puts in action when it perceives a reason, or has a want ; are the only such conceivable causes. Of these, we have already shown that intelligence, in its powers of effort and of preconception, has a special adaptation to future effects ; and that matter in motion can now be, at most, only its instrument in producing these effects. That God, with His infinite attributes, exists cannot, as already shown, of itself, be a cause of any changes subsequent to the commencement of such existence ; and hence, if such existence embraces a past eternity, His mere existence cannot, of itself, be, or ever have been, the cause of anything which has had a beginning. If the power exerts itself without any effort of the being of which it is an attribute, then that being has no more agency in producing the effect, than if it took place without any exercise of its power whatever. There must be a distinction between that condition of any being, finite or infinite, in which it actively produces, or endeavors to produce change ; and that condition of repose, in which, satisfied with things as they are, or as it perceives they will be, by the agency of other causes, it remains inactive and has no agency in producing change. The former must be a condition of effort. If, in the Supreme Being, there is no such distinction, then the effects must be independent of His 142 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WDLLING. action and are not cansed by Him, for they come to pass as well without as with His action. Hence, what- ever has its origin in His agency must require His effort. Much of the reasoning which I have just before this applied to show the necessity of effort to the producing of any effect by a finite being, as man, is applicable to any order of intelligent being. The Infinite, however, would never, by its effort, produce effects counter to its intention ; although, through self-active free agents of its own creation, it might be the remote cause, or rather the cause of the cause, of what it did not decree, or even foreknow. The idea that Omnipotence may be creative with- out effort is, perhaps, induced by observing that with every increase of our own power we accomplish any given work with less effort ; and it seems to be a mathe- matical deduction, that when the power becomes infi- nite, the effort must become nothing. But if the mag- nitude of the effect, or the power required to produce it, keeps pace with the magnitude of the power appli- cable to its production, no such consequence is deduci- ble from increase of power. We look upon Newton and Napoleon, each in their respective spheres of action, as having had more power in themselves than most men ; but no one supposes they made less effort. On the contrary, we are apt to consider the efforts of such men as commensurate with the effects of the exercise of their powers. So, also, if the works of a being of infinite power are infinite, there is at least no reason to suppose that His efforts are not as great as those of a being of finite power producing finite effects. Even Omnipotence has its bound in the absolutely impossible ; OF WANT AND EFFORT. 143 and there may be effects, just within the verge of possi- bility, approaching so near the impossible as to task even infinite power to accomplish them. There is, however, in the case supposed, no power at all without the effort. If we should speak of a dormant power, we could only mean, not that there is now power, but that there would be power if exerted ; i. e., in a self-active being, with effort there would be power ; and attribut- ing Omnipotence to any being could only mean that the efforts of such a being may be all-powerful. Effort, then, to which want and knowledge are pre- requisites, is an essential element of a creative being ; and He who governs and controls all the " vast, stu- pendous scheme of things," and reconciles the various and conflicting efforts of numberless free agents in har- monious results, cannot be an inert being, passively looking upon the gradual development of His designs, but must put forth an active energy, must make effort, • — must will these results. We have already remarked that want involves the idea, or knowledge of future change, though not of the means of producing change. Want, then, which, in the system we are asserting, lies at the foundation as a pre- requisite of effort or will, is also the first incipient, chaotic, but still inchoate stage of those preconceptions of the future by which the mind eventually determines these efforts ; and the want thus has with it the germ of the element of its own gratification. In this we may recognize something of that harmony, or unity which usually pertains only to truth and which ever marks the designs of Infinite Wisdom. But, for the gratification of the want, the mere knowledge that change is necessary is not sufficient. We must know what change ; and, however small and 144 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. simple the want, or however easy and obvious the means, a creative preconception of them is required. I am hungry, and seek to gratify the want for food. I see bread before me, and know that, by various move- ments of my hand, mouth, tongue, &c. &c. in a certain consecutive order, and only in that order, the want may be gratified. I may want a house to give me shelter, and for this a more complicated creation must be designed and a more extended creative power must be put forth,, and. with the same regard to the order of the efforts, to actualize the creative conception. Still, the mind could design or form, such creation within itself, and will, or make effort, to actualize it without itself, if there were no other intelligence or power in existence, or if all other existence were entirely passive ; and hence, feel- ing the want and having the knowledge required to de- termine the mode of gratifying it, could by its own in- herent powers, unaided and unrestrained by any other power, determine, or put forth a corresponding volition, could will the creation it has conceived, and, if there is a direct connection between its volitions and their sequences, the mind can thus actualize its conceptions in a real external creation. Nor, so far as relates to the act of will itself, is the mode of that connection im- portant. If the mind only knows that the consequences will, or may follow its volitions, this knowledge is a sufficient basis for its own effort ; for an effort directed by its use of its own knowledge is self-directed and therefore free. Whether there is any direct connection between volition and its final sequences, is a question which we have already considered, though more espe- cially in relation to external phenomena. The same question arises in regard to internal changes, and this will be considered in the next chapter. CHAPTER XIV. OF EFFORT FOR INTERNAL CHANGE. In regard to the relation of effort to internal changes ; as, can we of ourselves put our internal pow- ers in action ? or, can we repent of evil and change our affections and dispositions solely by our own efforts ? we will first remark that, though we may very reason- ably suppose that our own mental efforts are more closely connected with mental than with external ma- terial changes, still, as it appears not improbable that our efforts are made effective in the external by the intermediate agency of the Omnipresent Intelligence, so, in like manner, it may be that the Divine influence is necessary to give efficacy to. our efforts for internal change. The question here raised is whether the se- quences of volition are the immediate effects of our effort to produce them, or if there is some intervening power or cause, to the action of which our own efforts are either necessary, or uniform antecedents. In both cases, however, the important fact that our efforts are necessary antecedents or conditions precedent to the changes is known, and furnishes a good foundation for effort, let the subsequent effects be brought about as they may. If the effort is essential to a desirable result, 7 146 FKEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. the reason for the effort is the same, whether the result be proximate or remote. Though this is all that is strictly within the scope of our present inquiry, yet? as germane to the subject, we may be permitted to re- mark, that the action of those internal faculties by which we do follows our efforts to use them to increase our knowledge, or to effect other internal change, as uniformly as the bodily movements follow our efforts to produce external change ; the connection between the effort and the sequence of it is in both cases equally uniform and equally inscrutable. External circum- stances may affect us both internally and externally, may produce sensation and emotion ; and may, also, move our bodies without our volition and even against it. We cannot directly will a change in our mental affections any more than we can directly will what are termed bodily sensations. We cannot directly will the emotions of hope, or fear, or to be pure and noble, or even to want to become pure and noble, any more than we can directly will to be hungry, or to want to be hungry. If we want to take food we are already hun- gry, and if we want to perform pure and noble actions and to avoid the impure and ignoble, while this want, or disposition prevails, we are already pure and noble. If we want to be hungry, i. e. want to want food, and know that by exercise, or by the use of certain stimulants, or by other means we may become hungry, we may by effort induce this, in such case, a cultivated want ; and if we want to want to be pure and noble and know the means, we may, in like manner, by effort gratify the ex- citing want, and induce the want, which in such case is a cultivated want, to become pure and noble. OF EFFORT FOR INTERNAL CHANGE. 147 If, from seeing the pleasure which admiring a beau- tiful flower affords to others, or from any other cause, we want to admire it, we would readily perceive that some additional knowledge is essential to that end ; and that the first step is to find, by examination, what in it is admirable. To examine, then, becomes a secondary want, and we will to examine. The result of this ex- amination may be, that its before unknown beauties excite our admiration and make it, or the gazing upon it, an object of want ; so we may also will to examine what is pure and noble till its developed loveliness ex- cites in us, or increases, the want to be pure and noble, and induces a corresponding aversion to what is gross and base. It may be that increasing our knowledge of the flower will have an opposite effect, and produce disgust, or confirm our indifference. "We cannot, by will, de- termine what the knowledge, or the effect of the knowl- edge on us will be ; but still, as we cannot by effort directly discard, or lessen, the knowledge we already have, the only way in which we can by effort change our present intelligential relations to the flower is to increase our knowledge ; and hence, herein lies our only chance and hope to come to admire it.* If there is anything really admirable, or lovely in a flower, or in a moral emotion or sentiment, examination may re- veal it, and our admiration follow the discovery. If holiness were something which it were well for us to want and to have, and yet repulsive in its nature, ex- amination could not help the matter. We never could thus make it a primary want ; but, in such case, in- creasing our knowledge might even eradicate such * See Appendix, Note XXVin. 148 FEEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. want if innately existing. If repulsive, it could only be wanted as a means of something else, and then, as a nauseous dose, the less thought of the better. But God has not so ordered it ; on the contrary, by the consti- tution of our being, virtue in all its forms, in itself, ap- pears more harmonious and beautiful, more lovely and attractive, the more it is examined ; and hence, with the power to examine, may be made the object of a cul- tivated want and of consequent effort to attain it. "We said the result of the examination, — the newly discovered beauties of a flower, or of a moral virtue — excites, or increases the want ; for the purely mental wants, as well as those associated with our physical nature, have their roots in the constitution of our being ; and the recurrence of the former, if not so regular in their periods, or so imperative in their demands as the latter, is still amply provided for without any special effort of our own. God has so constituted us that the want of progress — of something better than the present attainment — is an universal want, occurring in our spir- itual, even more certainly than the appropriate wants in our physical constitution. The occurrence of them in both and our providing not only for their immediate gratification, but for their recurrence in the future, make conflicting wants, between which we have to decide ; and though our decisions in such cases may become habitual, and be almost unnoticeable, yet the occasions for such decisions will continue to arise. The occurrence and recurrence of our spiritual wants are as certain as those of hunger. We are continually reminded of them by our own thoughts and acts, by comparison with those of others, and by those external appearances, which result from God's thought and ac- OF EFFORT FOE INTERNAL CHANGE. 149 tion ; and He has placed within us the moral sense, as a sentinel, with its intuitions more certainly warning us of what, in wants, or means, is noxious to our moral nature, than the senses of taste and smell do of what is injurious to our physical. These remarks, with our previous reasoning, lead us to the conclusion that want, constitutional, acquired, or cultivated, is the source of effort for internal, as well as external change, and that this is true of every order of intelligent, active being. God directs His efforts with infinite knowledge, per- fectly considered, or comprehended — perfect wisdom ; man, his with finite knowledge, imperfectly considered, or only partially comprehended — fallible judgment, or imperfect wisdom. Infinite wisdom always reconciles its wants, or the mode of gratifying them, with what is right ; and hence, moral perfection. Man's finite wisdom does not always reconcile his wants, or the mode of gratifying them, with absolute right ; and hence, moral evil, or imperfection, in his general con- dition as exhibited in aggregated social combination ; nor yet with his own conceptions of right ; and hence, individual moral depravity, which can only exist when his efforts are not put forth in conformity to his knowl- edge or sense of right. As a man cannot do any moral wrong in doing what he believes to be right, his knowledge, though finite, is infallible as to what it is morally right for him to do ; * and his fallibility in morals must consist in his liability to act at variance with his knowledge, or conviction of right, and never in deficiency of knowledge, or even in belief. In this view, his knowledge in the sphere of his *See Appendix, Note XXIX. 150 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. morai nature is infallible, and were lie infinitely wise, or certain to act in conformity to his knowledge of the right, he would be infallible in his moral sphere of action. It is also evident that the mind must direct its efforts for internal change by means of those preconcep- tions of the future effects of its efforts, which its knowl- edge enables it to form. Now a preconception is an imaginary construction,* an incipient creation of the mind in the future. In forming it, the mind does not, of necessity, even con- sider, or recognize the already existing external circum- stances. In " castle-building " it often voluntarily dis- cards these circumstances and forms a construction entirely from its own internal being. Retaining its knowledge of the past, and having the power of ab- straction, it could just as well conceive even an external creation, if all external existences, facts, and circum- stances were annihilated. A man thus isolated may imagine a universe in which all is, in his view, beauti- ful and good ; or, confining himself to his own being and prompted by his physical wants, he may, in im- agination, revel in all the luxuries of sense. He may not even intend to make the additional effort to actual- ize these combinations, and make them palpable to others, or permanent within himself. If he makes such effort he, perhaps, finds that it is unavailing, and that he cannot give external reality to his creative concep- tion of such a universe, and that he has not the means to obtain the luxuries he has imagined. Yet he has formed these ideal constructions as freely and as inde- pendently of all other existing causes, as though he had * See Appendix, Note XXX. OF EFFORT FOR INTERNAL CHANGE. 151 omnipotent power to realize the conceptions in an out- ward creation. So, too, if moved by the aspirations of his spiritual being, he may conceive in himself a moral nature, pure and noble, resisting all temptation to evil and conform- ing with energetic and persevering effort to all virtuous impulses and suggestions. Though we may make no effort and not even intend to make any to realize such ideal conceptions, they are not without their influence on our moral nature. They appear sometimes to be formed merely for the exercise of our faculties in con- structing, and sometimes for the pleasure of contem- plating new and varied forms of harmony and beauty ; and, in both cases, they are not without utility. The preconceptions thus sportively made add to our knowl- edge and to our skill in combining, and furnish models which may be available for future practical use. Poetry presents us with such constructions ready formed by others. These purely ideal conceptions have this ad- vantage, that, in forming them, the mind being free from the excitements and selfish inducements, from the temptations of actual affairs, is more disinterested in its judgment of right and wrong and acquires expe- rience and forms habits, which, without its actually en- countering, prepare it for the exigencies of real life. The making of such constructions as harmonize with our conceptions of moral excellence is itself improving ; a determination in advance, by persevering effort to make them manifest in action upon proper occasion, is a greater step in progress ; and the mere willing to ac- tualize them, when the occasion presents, is, so far as the moral nature is concerned, really their final con- summation ; for, whether the effort be exhibited in ex- 152 FKEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. ternal manifestation or not, makes no difference to the condition of the moral natnre. The external act or effect is but the tangible evidence to others of the in- ternal effort, which is the real manifestation of the moral element. This is in harmony with our statement that, producing the intended effect is not material to our freedom in willing it. If a man wills to do an act which is good and noble, it matters not, concerning his virtue, whether his effort be successful or otherwise ; the effort is, itself, the triumph in him of the good and noble over the bad and base. If the object of the effort, instead of external good and noble action, is the direct improvement of his own moral nature, then the perse- vering effort to be good and noble is, itself, being good and noble. It follows from these positions that, as regards the moral nature, there can be no failure except the failure to will, or to make the proper effort. The human mind, with its want, knowledge and power of abstrac- tion, having the power within and from itself to form its creative preconceptions and to will their actual reali- zation independently of any other cause, power, or existence of any kind, up to the point of willing, is, in its own sphere, an independent creative first cause. Exterior to itself it may have no power whatever to execute what it wills, or, having some power, it may be frustrated, or counteracted by other external forces ; and hence, in the external, the contemplated creative consummation of volition may not be reached ; but, as in the moral nature, the willing, the persevering effort is itself the consummation, there can, in it, be no such failure ; and the mind, in it, is therefore not 'only a creative, but a Supreme creative first cause. OF EFFORT FOR INTERNAL CHANGE. 153 We have then, between effort in the sphere of the moral nature and in that sphere which is external to it, this marked difference : that while in the external there must be something beyond the effort ; i. its 7. Its perceptions of the present, knowledge. 8. Its conceptions of the future. J 9. Its imaginings. 10. Its associations. 11. Other mind; representing all intelligences, other than the mind to be determined. 12. The faculties of these other minds. 13. Its emotions. 14. Its sensations. 15. Its knowledge, past, present and future. 16. Material phenomena ; including any circumstances, which are extrinsic to mind. ■ We will consider these in their respective order. 1. If the mind itself is the motive that determines its own act of will, then, as before shown, the mind in such an act of will is free. 2. If the attributes or faculties of the mind are the motives, then, as these attributes or faculties can do nothing except as they are exercised or exerted by the mind, it must be the mind, in the exercise of its facul- ties, that determines the will; which, again, would prove the mind's freedom in willing. 3. An emotion, which is not in itself a want, and * See Appendix, Note XLIV. 15* 346 KEVIEW OF EDWAKDS ON THE WILL. which does not produce want, is not a motive. As we have already suggested that no want arises, so no act of will can spring from that joy, which so satisfies the mind that it desires no change, or from that holy and unselfish grief which it would not banish nor modify ; and, of that anguish which arises from the conscious- ness of error, the cause is in the past, and cannot be reached by any act of will ; while admiration, wonder, and awe compose or still, rather than excite, the active faculty. All these but make a part of the past expe- rience, adding to that present knowledge which aids the mind in determining its course in the future. But with these and other emotions, as love, hope, fear, anger, the mind may have corresponding wants, if only the want to derive pleasure, variety, or excitement from them. These wants, and the sensation or perception of these wants, may induce the mind to act for its own gratifica- tion or relief. But the wants cannot themselves deter- mine that action, for that must depend on the percep- tion by the mind of the means of gratifying the want ; and the perception must include, or be the preconcep- tion of, the relation of the future effect of its own act to its want, which brings it to the case of the mind deter- mining its action by its own view, which we have be- fore considered. If it has no such perception of a means of gratifying the want by an act of will, and that the want may thereby be gratified, there is no act of will put forth ; which shows that the mind, in grati- fying any want which may arise from the emotions, still directs its action by means of its preconception or knowledge of the future effect of its effort, which it only can apply, and hence in such effort acts freely. 4. Sensation, as before stated, may, with knowledge, MOTIVE. 347 produce want, suggesting some change for its gratifica- tion ; or, it may be but a perception of an external fact in the present, involving no want of change in the fu- ture. The effect of want as a motive, and of the inci- dental addition of another fact to our knowledge, have both been already sufficiently considered in their re- spective relations to the determination of the mind in willing, and shown not to militate against its freedom. 5. Innate knowledge is that knowledge which is directly communicated by the Creator to the creature, but, becoming a portion of its own knowledge, in no respect differs in its effects or influence on the will from other or acquired knowledge. That, as suggested in our chapter on instinct, it may be in such a form as not to require any contrivance to adapt it to use, in the act of willing, and thus facilitates the action of the mind in willing, does not conflict with the mind's freedom in the act which is thus facilitated. 6. The mind's memory of the past, including its own thoughts, and embracing, of course, the knowledge of things, events, and abstract truths which it has acquired in that past. The things and events from being in the past, and the abstract truths from their nature, are un- changeable, and hence not subjects for the action of the will, and only make a portion of the knowledge of the mind, by which it is enabled to decide its future course. 7. The result of the mind's perceptions of the present is a knowledge of existing things. These may admit of a succession differing from themselves — of change — and this change be the object of the mind's act of will ; but the mind will not will, or make effort to change them, unless it has some want to be gratified by such change. The things themselves cannot indi- 348 review or edwards on the will. cate what changes will gratify the want, for they cannot even know what the want is. To do this requires intel- ligence. To adapt things, or the changes in things, w T hich are effected by volition, to the simplest want, requires not only knowledge, but contrivance, which things have not. For instance, hunger is the want of food in the stomach : we cannot immediately will the food there, but have to apply our knowledge and power of thought or examination, in adapting and devising means and ways of doing it ; even after it is in the mouth, it is not the food that knows that it must be masticated and swallowed, and the order of these two processes. It is the mind's perception, that by the various acts, from the procuring the food to the swal- lowing of it, and by these acts, in a certain order, 'the sensation of hunger may be relieved, that enables it intelligently to determine its successive efforts to that end ; and this preconception of the effect of its efforts it is enabled to form by its faculty of conceiving of the future — its finite prophetic power — which is aided and rendered less fallible by every increase of its knowledge. In such case, neither the mind's percep- tions nor that which is perceived can determine ; but the perception or knowledge enables the mind to de- termine. 8. The mind's conception of the future is itself a view by the mind, and, as such, embraced in our re- marks on the mind in willing being determined by its own views. We are admitting the largest possible lat- itude to what may be conceived to be motive, but the mind's own view or conception of the future, of some- thing which as yet has no objective reality, but is exclu- sively a view of the mind within itself, seems hardly MOTIVE. 349 such a motive as Edwards speaks of as " standing in the mind's view ; " for the mind's perception of that future is the mind's view itself, and not something which stands in that view. If this be the motive, we need not repeat our reasoning to show that such views of the mind, such motives, are the essential element which enables the mind to determine its own acts of will as an independent, creative,, first cause. The motive cannot be that future which the mind views, for it, as yet, has no actual existence, and can have no influence on the mind except by or through the mind's anticipation of it, which is the mind's view just considered, and makes a portion of its knowledge. 9. The mind's imaginings being such combinations as have no objective existence, past or present, but sup- posed capable of existence, may also be regarded as in the future, and be classed with those conceptions which are incipient creations of the mind. Being palpable and tangible to itself, they gratify some want of the mind, as the love of knowledge, the sentiment of beauty, &c. If, for convenience, we take some circumstances of the past, and in imagination vary them, or add some new feature, the new combination really has no past exist- ence, and, as present, exists only as a view of the mind without any objective existence ; and, whether we locate it in the past, present, or future, or give it no particular place in time, makes no more difference than the loca- ting of a geometrical diagram in time. In both cases they are but constructions, affording pleasure by their harmony, symmetry, and beauty, or aiding the mind to solve some problem and thus to increase its knowledge. 10. The associations of the mind are only other por- tions of its knowledge, suggested by that portion which 350 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. is immediately in its view ; and, though very important in giving the mind a ready nse of its knowledge in the formation of its plans, which are prerequisites of rational action, and yet more especially, in that recalling of former plans, which is the basis of habitual action, still association is but, in this connection, a means by which the mind uses its knowledge in directing its will, and requires here no further comment. 11. Any other mind or intelligence, as a mere object, viewed or apprehended by the mind, can have no influ- ence differing in kind from that of the mind's view of any other extrinsic object, and this we have already considered. If this other mind has in it anything which will gratify a want in the mind that views it, this mind may put forth an effort to obtain that thing. We have before considered in a similar connection the case of the will of one mind being controlled directly or indirectly by another mind by means of the exercise of any of its powers, or otherwise, and need not repeat the reason- ing or the result ; and this, with the consideration that those powers cannot exert themselves or have any influ- ence except as exerted by the mind to which they ap- pertain, disposes, also, of 12. The attributes and faculties of one mind, as a motive, determining the will of another mind. 13. 14, 15. The emotions, sensations, and knowledge of another mind can have no influence, except as they are made manifest to the mind to be influenced in that case, becoming but portions of its own knowledge, and, as such, already shown not to interfere with its freedom in willing. We may, however, further remark that the knowledge which one mind acquires from another co- ordinate or like mind, must be of the same character as MOTIVE. 351 that which it acquires or has from other sources ; and that the knowledge which the finite mind derives from the Infinite when directly imparted is intuitive ; and when indirectly^ by the written expression of His thoughts in nature, they are but the knowledge of material phenomena or that which is extrinsic to the mind, which belongs under our next and last division. 16. Material phenomena, including any circum- stances which are extrinsic to the mind. Material objects cannot, of themselves, be such a motive, for they may have existed from all eternity, and yet never have produced or determined a volition, and even may have been in the mind's view for any length of time and yet never have moved it to will, or determined its will ; but if they are a necessary cause in themselves, then the moment they exist they must produce their effect, or if the additional circumstance that they must be u in the mind's view," makes them the cause of volition in that mind, then, as soon as they are in that mind's view, the volition should follow. That this is not the fact, proves that there is something besides the material object and the fact that it is in the mind's view, which produces the effect, or determines the will. The same is true of extrinsic circumstances. JSTor can any changes in these extrinsic objects and circumstances, whether produced by the motion of matter, or by intelligent action, of itself, move the mind to will. Increase or vary the circumstances ever so much, they could no more produce any volition in themselves or in others — a volition having reference to an effect which as yet is not — than the extension of the multiplication table could make it know itself or feel hungry. However blindly active among themselves, they cannot embrace 352 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. that design, that intention, to produce a preconceived result, which is an essential characteristic of volition, and which distinguishes the action of intelligent from blind causes. For this they avail nothing until the mind uses them as its knowledge to determine its action ; and the mind is itself really the efficient cause of that determination, freely adapting its action to the circum- stances in its view. There is, evidently, no way in which these circumstances can directly produce a voli- tion in the human mind, and if they could, it would be the volition of the circumstances, and not of the human- being. These extrinsic circumstances can influence the mind in willing only as they are perceived or appre- hended by the mind, and, as such, become but a part of the mind's knowledge, and, of course, subject to our previous conclusions, that knowledge, however acquired, is used by the mind to enable it to determine its acts ; and hence, is essential to its freedom in willing ; every increase in knowledge enlarging its sphere for the exer- cise of such freedom. There are vague notions, in the popular mind, in regard to the influence of circumstances upon us, often bordering on fatalism, if not really involving it, and which find expression in such phrases as " man is the sport," or " he is the creature of circumstances." One reason for this is, that we are liable to be frustrated by circumstances in the execution of what we will. This, it will be observed, is such an effect, after the act of willing, as can have no influence backward upon it. I will to walk in a certain direction, but am obstructed by a rushing torrent, which God has caused to flow there, or by a wall erected through human agency. The circumstance prevents my doing what I intended, MOTIVE. 353 and what, from want of sufficient knowledge, I decided to do. The new knowledge thus acquired, leads me to alter my course, and I may never again fall into the same track that I would otherwise have pursued. I go on to produce some change, but what that change will be depends npon the use which my mind makes of this new, combined with its previous knowledge, in directing its subsequent action. Though I cannot, as now ascer- tained, go in the direction intended, there are still an infinite number of ways in which I can go ; and among these my mind, in virtue of its intelligence, judges which Is best. It may do this by a preliminary free act, and then, being free, conform its final action to its judgment ; and hence, this influence of circumstances does not argue that the mind does not act freely in willing, but only that it cannot always execute its de- crees ; not that it does not freely try, or make effort, but that its power is not always adequate to the effect designed, or its knowledge sufficient to direct its efforts most wisely, and the want of freedom, if such this want of power may be termed, is just where Edwards asserts the only freedom of man exists. As the mind's being liable to be frustrated in the execution of what it wills by the existence of circum- stances of which it did not know, is one reason of the popular idea in regard to the influence of circumstances, so, on the other hand, another reason for it may be found in the limitation of the circumstances — in the absence or non-existence of some that are essential to the execution — to the doing what is attempted — or of some which are prerequisites of the effort, which it would or might make, if they were present and avail- able, and for the want of which the mind either does 354: REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. not will, or wills differently from what it would if they were present and available as a portion of its knowl- edge. In their absence, the mind knows no mode of obtaining the object for which such circumstances are prerequisite. This does not affect its freedom in willing as to what, under the circumstances, is attainable, but only lessens the sphere in which it can exercise that freedom. This sphere, as before stated, is always com- mensurate with its knowledge ; and it matters not whether the knowledge requisite to any effort — the knowledge of some mode — is deficient, because such knowledge cannot exist, or simply because it does not exist in the mind. The limitation of the sphere of effort is the same in either case. I may know not only that /cannot now make 2 + 2=5, but that it is an impossi- bility, and hence, will not seek any mode of doing it. I may also know that I have no knowledge of any geo- metrical process by which to trisect an arc, and, as I do not know that this is an impossibility, I may seek to increase my knowledge, and by means of such increase devise some mode in conformity to which I may direct my efforts to trisect the arc. So that, whether the thing to be done be absolutely impossible, from there being no possible mode of doing it, or only relatively to me impossible, because I know of no way, the for- mula heretofore adopted, that the mind's sphere of free activity, or for the exercise of its creative powers by will or effort, is commensurate with its knowledge, covers the whole ground. If the mind of every human being at all times embraced all knowledge, then, all the circum- stances presented to every mind would, of necessity, be the same, but by the limitation of human knowledge different circumstances are presented to different minds. MOTIVE. 355 Of two persons wanting a metal, one may have, within his power, lead, zinc, and gold ; another only lead and zinc ; but the latter chooses and conforms his effort to his choice as freely in regard to the two, as the former in regard to the three. If a man with all the natural endowments of Newton, and with his acquired habits of industrious and persevering study, had always lived in the Sandwich Islands, he would not have had, in the surrounding circumstances, the opportunities essential to such discoveries as Newton made. The requisite books and instruments — the means of knowledge — would not have been there accessible, or to him pos- sible ; but he would have been equally free by effort to avail himself of such means as were there in his power. The mind varies its own action to conform to the relations which it perceives between the circumstances and the preconception of the effect by which it seeks to gratify its want, and it does this in virtue of that intel- ligence, which, perceiving this relation, makes self- control and freedom, or self-action free from extrinsic control, possible to it. We find then, in all this conceivable range, no mo- tive that so determines the will as to warrant the infer- ence of necessity ; none to which the mind itself is subordinated, or which will admit of dispensing with the mind itself as the cause, which determines its own acts of will. Let us now see if Edwards has himself indicated any such actual motive. In the general statement -, already quoted, he affirms that without motive the mind in willing " has no end which it proposes to itself or pur- sues in so doing ; it aims at nothing, and seeks nothing, and, if it seeks nothing, then it does not go after any- 356 REVIEW OF ^EDWARDS ON THE WILL. thing P These expressions indicate that the essence of the motive is in the end which the mind seeks, some- thing which as yet is not, bnt which will be the effect of its volition, and that which is in the view of the mind as the motive to the volition, is the idea of the effect of the volition. But the idea or preconception of the effect of a volition conld have no influence toward a volition, if the mind did not want to produce the effect it preconceived. The want is the incitement to effort ; and the mind's judgment or knowledge as to the adapta- tion of the effect, which it anticipates in the future, to the want and of the effort to the effect, enables it to determine as to the particular effort or volition it will put forth. So, also, in the particular case by which he illus- trates the influence of the strongest motive, ne says : " Thus, when a drunkard has his liquor before him, and he has to choose whether to drink it or no ; the proper and immediate objects, about which his present volition is conversant, and between which his choice now de- cides, are his own acts in drinking the liquor, or letting it alone ; and this will certainly be done according to what, in the present view of his mind taken in the whole of it, is most agreeable to him. If he chooses or wills to drink it, and not to let it alone, then this action, as it stands in the view of his mind, with all that belongs to its appearance there, is more agreeable and pleasing, than letting it alone " (p. 10). The expression " between which his choice now de- cides," must mean, between which he by an act of choice now decides (otherwise he makes choice decide the choice), and, taking this as his meaning, the objects contemplated by the drunkard are his own acts in MOTIVE. 357 " drinking or letting alone," either of which is yet in the future. It is true that Edwards immediately says, " But the objects to which this act of volition may relate more remotely, and between which his choice may determine more indirectly, are the present pleasure the man expects hj drinking, and the future misery which he judges will be the consequence of it ; " but, at the time of this judgment, both the drinking and its consequences are in the future — still expected — and the anticipated con- ception of them is all that u is in the mind's view." The mind by its judgment is to weigh its preconception of the effect of " drinking the liquor," against its pre- conception of the consequences of " letting it alone," which, Edwards has just said, are the acts between which the drunkard's choice now decides ; and though Edwards does not expressly say so, yet, to give the illus- tration any force or meaning, we must suppose that, of the two acts about which he says " the present volition is conversant," that one which, " as it stands in the view of his mind with all that belongs to its appearance there," is most agreeable, or suits it best, is the strong- est motive ; and this is but a preconception of the effects of a certain act, which the mind decides to be in accordance with that want which it seeks to gratify. As already remarked, Edwards does not say. this, nor does he appear to have had any clear thought of it ; but it seems difficult to make the facts he states, or the case he cites, illustrate any other position than that his mo- tive is, in fact, the mind's view of the future effect of its own action, and this is the mind's knowledge by which it perceives a reason for acting and for the partic- ular direction of its action, and not a motive power 358 REVIEW OF EDWAKDS ON THE WILL. putting the mind in action. Snch view is but the rea- son why the mind, as cause, acts in one particular man- ner, instead of another, rather than a cause itself of the action, or of the particular manner of the action. His " motive," however, as illustrated in this instance, corre- sponds to the influence which I have assigned to the mind's preconception of the effects of its effort, and " the mind's view " is but a portion of its knowledge, which it uses to determine its action, as it uses any other knowledge it may have, and which knowledge, as already indicated, by a preliminary effort to examine, or to consider, by deliberation, and sometimes perhaps by an immediate mental perception, becomes the judg- ment of the mind. As he uses a motive " in some other places, it indicates the influence which I have assigned to want j and, in this instance, just quoted, the decision of the mind is really to be between two conflicting wants — the want to enjoy the pleasure of " drinking the liquor," and the want, " by letting it alone," to avoid the unpleasant consequences of drinking it — both of which, under Edwards's view, must be motives ; and that, the gratification of which in the mind's view suits it hest, is the strongest motive. Even admitting, then, that the same causes neces- sarily produce the same effects, which is still an essential link in this argument for necessity, this doctrine of mo- tives, from its inception in the definition and statements of it to its conclusion, reveals nothing which really con- flicts with the results attained in Book First of this" Treatise ; and, on examination, it turns out that the motive which, by a mere hypothesis, is made the cause of the determination of the will, can be in reality noth- ing but the mind itself, or the mind's own views f and, MOTIVE. 359 in either case, as the application of the views must be made by the mind that views, it is the mind which de- termines its own volitions or efforts. And this expres- sion for its freedom is made more emphatic by the de- velopment which comes out in the illustration and in the final summing up of the argument by Edwards, that the mind in willing is not only determined by its own views, but by its view of the future effects of its own action, as yet having no existence except in its own preconception, which is its own creation ; or rather, by the relations which it perceives between its own cre- ated preconception and its own want ; and the consid- eration that these relations do not inhere either in the want or in the preconception, but are in the mind's view wholly by the exercise of its intelligent faculties — its own thought — directed to the examination by means of its own previous knowledge, intuitive or acquired ; that such examination is essential to a wise action ; and that it is by such knowledge that Supreme Intelligence itself must direct its action ; serve at once to illustrate and strengthen our position. It would, indeed, seem that there could be no stronger expression of the free- dom of an intelligent agent in willing, than that it determines its own acts of will, by means of the knowl- edge obtained by the exercise of its own faculties, of the relation between its own creations — the preconcep- tions of the future effects of its efforts — and its own wants. The whole process and all the elements of the act of will in such case are in and of the being that wills. But, supposing all these difficulties and. objections to these positions of Edwards to be, in some way, sur- mounted, we have still to inquire as to the meaning of 360 KEVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. that u previous tendency," which is an all-important element in motive, as applied in his argument for neces- sity. He says : " Everything that is properly called a motive * * * has some sort and degree of tendency, or advantage to move, or excite the will previous to the effect, or to the act of will excited. This previous tend- ency of the motive is what I call the strength of the motive " (p. 7). And again : " Whatever is perceived or apprehended by an intelligent and voluntary agent, which has the nature and influence of a motive to voli- tion or choice, is considered or viewed as good" i. e., the mind perceives or judges it to be good. And, im- mediately after the above, he says : " I use the term good, namely, as of the same import with agreeable ; " and hence, the strongest motive is that which appears most agreeable, as he thus more fully states : " But if it tends to draw the inclination and move the will, it must be under the notion of that which suits the mind. And, therefore, that must have the greatest tendency to at- tract and engage it, which, as it stands in the mind's view, suits it best and pleases it most " (p. 9). The prevailing motive then, is that which, as it stands in the mind's view, suits it best and pleases it most. But, " a being pleased with " is the phrase which he uses (p. 2) as identical with " an act of will," and which he subsequently identifies with choice or preference, by saying, " it will not appear by this and such like in- stances, that there is any difference between volition and preference, or that a man's choosing, liking best, or being best pleased with a thing are not the same with his willing that thing," and by many other expressions of like import. So that this strongest motive, or " that Ivhich appears most inviting, and has, by what appears MOTIVE. 361 concerning it to the understanding or apprehension, the greatest degree of previous tendency to excite and induce the choice," must be that motive for which the mind has a choice or preference over all others, and it is this choice or preference of the mind, which gives it all its influence or tendency to move the will ; but as its tendency to move the will is previous to the act of will, or choice, or preference, we have the choice, or preference, which gives this previous tendency, not only before itself, but under the definition, that " the will " is " that by which the mind chooses anything " (p. 1). We have, in this previous tendency of the motive, a choice before that by which the mind chooses has acted, which is absurd. These results follow from the fact that the terms by which Edwards defines " the previous tendency of mo- tive," are the same as those by which he designates choice or preference ; and if, instead of seeking the re- lation of the things in the substituted terms or defini- tions, we look directly to the things themselves, it seems evident that nothing, whatever, has any influence to move the mind till it has some preference or choice for it. This makes the previous tendency to choice, a choice itself, which, by Edwards's hypothesis, would re- quire a previous tendency or choice to excite it, and so on ad infinitum. This difficulty is not obviated by supposing the pre- vious tendency of the motive to inhere in something which is extrinsic to the mind, for it is not a motive at all until it is in the mind's view, and strongest motive is still that which in the mind's view suits it best ; and, whether it be in the mind's view itself, or in the object viewed, it can exert no influence until the mind has 16 362 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. some choice or preference for it, which still makes the choice previous to the act of will or choice, and before that by which the mind chooses has acted. We here again observe how this, the main argument of Edwards, is made fallacious by being founded on the two incom- patible definitions of choice. In the unsettled state of metaphysical language, it is, perhaps, allowable for a writer to define his own terms, and even in some instances, like the mathema- ticians, to bring the subjects into existence by the defi- nitions. But, in such cases, he must not involve incom- patible conditions. If a mathematician should say, " a triplogon is a plane rectilineal figure included within three sides and with- three right angles ; " or a ma- chinist should plan a flying machine, or a perpetual motion, one element of which should be a revolving wheel with a weight on one side just equal to one on the other, but that on the other a little heavier than it ; though one might reason ingeniously and even correctly upon such hypotheses, yet no practical result, no new reality, could be evolved from it ; and so, if motive, by the definition of it, is that which is before itself, or that which comes into beins; before the existence of that which gives it being, however subtle the reasoning upon it, no practical result, no solution of any question of realities, can be evolved from it. All reasoning from such hypotheses must take this form : " If a triplogon is contained by three sides, and has three right angles, then some quadrilaterals must have four sides and six right angles ; " and, though this should be shown to be a logical consequence, the truth of it would still depend upon the possible existence of such a figure as a " triplo- gon " has been defined to be. MOTIVE. 363 "We before had occasion to show that, in Edwards's system, there is no room for anything between a state of indifference — a not willing or choosing — and the act of choice or will ; and, if that conclusion was correct, there is in his system no room for this motive, or pre- vious tendency of motive, between total indifference, or not choosing, or not willing, and the act of choosing or willing ; but, -as appears by the preceding reasoning, the motive, or the previous tendency of motive, must itself be an act of choice, in his system also an act of will, springing directly out of a state of indifference. Beyond all these, there exists the same difficulty in regard to the determining power of motive, which Edwards finds in regard to the will's self-determining power. In his system, everything must have an ante- cedent cause ; and these motives, and even the previous tendency of motives, must have a cause as much as the volitions of which they are assumed to be the cause. If we pass over intelligence in willing, as a first cause of its own volitions, making it only an intermediate link in the chain of causes, and effects, we never come to a beginning or first cause. This difficulty must attach to every system, which does not recognize some self-moving power, or cause, and which, as it cannot be in matter, must be in spirit. Edwards, in fact, assumes that motive is a first, self- acting cause ; this denies that every act is necessarily controlled by some cause in the past, which is an indis- pensable link in his argument for necessity. If this motive is the intelligence that acts, if the mind itself is the motive, or cause of its volitions, then his argument really asserts the freedom of the mind in willing. CHAPTEE XI, CAUSE AND EFFECT It will be observed that the argument of Edwards, in favor of necessity, rests mainly upon the assumption that the same causes, of necessity, produce the same effects / I say of necessity, for if the relation of effect to cause be not one of necessity, no necessity of the effect can be inferred from the relation. If the motive is the cause of the act of choice or volition, and the particu- lar act of choice or volition, is not a necessary effect of its cause, but some other volition might have ensued ? then, there is nothing in the relation of cause and effect upon which to predicate necessity in the act of choice or volition ; so that the whole force of this argument rests upon the hypothesis, that the relation of effect to cause is one of necessity. That the same causes necessarily produce the same effects must mean that, if the same causes occur, or are repeated in action any number of times, the same cor- responding effect will occur, or be repeated each time. If the same cause never occurred, or acted twice, there could be no occasion for the rule — nothing to which it would apply. It is the same, then, as a case of uniform- CAUSE AND EFFECT. 365 \ ity of cause and effect. Now, this law of the uniform- ity of cause and effect is known to us only as an em- pirical law growing out of our observation of the suc- cession of changes in matter, and these changes, as we have already shown, must be controlled wholly, or mostly, by a creative intelligence — by the will of an in- telligent being. The law of uniformity in these changes of matter,* then, must depend upon the will of this in- telligent being. The acts of the finite intelligence in producing these changes are but infinitesimal, and hence, even if there w T ere no other reason, may be left out of view, and the control of the changes in the mate- rial universe be ascribed directlv to the will of the Su- preme Intelligence. We do not even know that the movement of our own hand, as a sequent of our voli- tion, is not a uniform mode of God's action, and not by our own direct agency. The law, then, that in the material world the same causes produce the same effects, is deduced from our observations of the uniform- ity of God's action. It cannot be a law of metaphys- ical necessity, for it is just as conceivable that He should will that the same set of circumstances should be followed by different consequences every time they oc- curred, as that He should w T ill the same consequences with every such recurrence. There is no causal power in the fact that the cause has before acted, or that the same circumstances have before occurred. Excluding such cases as involve contradiction, and which, of course, even Infinite Power cannot control or affect, there is no reason to presume that the law goes any far- ther than is indicated by our observations of the facts. We do not know that the changes in winds or weather, are subject to any such uniformity ; they may, in every * See Appendix, Note XLV. 366 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. individual case, be effected by the will of God acting without reference to any uniformity. Even if in such cases we find that an effect is uniformly preceded by a limited series of antecedents, it does not follow that this series is a part of one which is infinite. It may be iso- lated, and be in fact but God's uniform mode of doing that particular thing, and may have no uniform con- nection with any prior antecedents. To suppose all the events to be either necessary terms of an infinite series following each other in a necessary order, or even in a pre-ordained order, would leave no room for the con- tinued exercise of God's designing power, and, as we shall have occasion to note more particularly hereafter, would deprive Him of the highest attribute of Creative Intelligence. In regard to matter, then, this uniformity of cause and effect, so far as it goes, is not a necessary but an arbitrary law, which the Supreme Intelligence has adopted for His own government in the management of matter, and which our observation of His modes of action in the material world has revealed to us. There is no reason to suppose that He makes such laws for His own action in all cases — as in changes of the weather, for instance — or, that He may not vary from the law of uniformity, which appears to us to be estab- lished, and thus produce what we call miracles. That He is all-wise and omniscient obviates the ne- cessity of trying experiments to which finite intelli- gences are subject, for he must be able to preconceive the results, and, by a comparison of these preconcep- tions, to determine the best modes of action in any cir- cumstances without continually trying different modes ; and knowing the best mode, will, of course, adopt it in CAUSE AND EFFECT. 367 a recurrence of the same circumstances, unless from some cause, the gain of variety makes the new mode of action, with such variety, better than the old one without it. When in natural phenomena we seek to general- ize existing facts, or the succession of events, we do not really seek the consequences of any necessity in the same causes to produce the same effects, but the consequences of God's uniform action. If we find in the premises no evidence of such uniformity in His action, our knowledge will be limited to particular facts in the past. In regard to the finite mind, observation does not indicate any such law of uniformity, or necessity of cause and effect, for, it is impossible to predict, with certainty, what the action of mind under any cir- cumstances will be ; nor, from the act, can we deter- mine the cause or reason of the act, which, in one man, may be the gratification of his want to do good to others, while another man, under the same apparent circumstances, does the same act because he perceives that he will eventually thereby be enabled to inflict great injury on others. The fact that we cannot, with certainty, predict what the future action of any mind will be under any antecedents, and conversely, from the action cannot, with certainty, tell the antecedents, shows that there is no observable or known uniformity in the relation of this action of the mind to whatever the antecedents of its action may be. It may be said, that this is because we cannot take into view all the circumstances ; but, if so, this not only proves that we have no experience proving the rule, but that we can- not have any such experience, and such assertion would 368 KEVIEW OF EDWAKDS ON THE WILL. thus weaken the position it is intended to support. So far as we have opportunities for observing the action of mind under similar circumstances, the fact seems to be that, not only do different minds act very differently, but that the same mind sometimes changes even its habits and modes of action very suddenly and unex- pectedly ; and hence observation reveals no rule of uniformity of cause and effect which is of necessity ap- plicable to mind. Edwards says : " I might further observe, the state of the mind that views a proposed object of choice, is another thing that contributes to the agreeableness, or disagreeable- ness of that object; the particular temper which the mind has by nature, or that has been introduced and established by education, example, custom, or some other means ; or the frame or state that the mind is in on a particular occasion. That object which appears agreeable to one, does not so to another. And the same object does not always appear alike agreeable to the same person at different times. It is most agreeable to some men to follow their reason, and to others to follow their appetites ; to some men it is more agreeable to deny a vicious inclination, than to gratify it ; others it suits best to gratify the vilest appetites. It is more disagreeable to some men than others to counteract a former resolution. In these respects, and many others which might be mentioned, different things will be most agreeable to different persons ; and not only so, but to the same persons at different times " (p. 14). But, if these " objects of choice " in " the mind that views," and which he treats as motives, produce such different effects on different minds, and, also, on the same mind at different times, where is the evidence of CAUSE AND EFFECT. 369 this uniformity, or of this necessity of the effect of these motives as cause of the volitions \ which is the very foundation of his argument upon motives, as already shown in the quotation from him (p. 116). It may be said that, in such cases, though all extrin- sic circumstances are the same, some change in the mind varies it as a cause. I will consider this point of identity, in its effect on the argument, hereafter, and, for the present, will only remark that in such cases it must be the changed mind, which is really the efficient cause of the variation in the effect, and that, if the rule does not apply to two minds acting under the same circumstances because they are not the same cause, nor yet to the same mind, acting a second time with all other circumstances the same, except such as of neces- sity arise from its being a second -and not a first time, no possible case can arise for the application of the rule to mind. If, as at least appears probable, spirit is the only real cause, and postulating that the finite mind is not co-eternal with the Infinite, there was a time when only one cause existed ; and if the same causes necessarily produce the same effects, this one cause never could have produced but one effect, or, at farthest, but duplications of the same effect. If it be said that the fact of this cause having once acted and produced one effect, makes such a variation of the circumstances under which it acts, that its subsequent action may differ from the first merely from the fact that it is the second, and not the first causative action ; then, we say that this en- tirely destroys the rule and makes it a nullity ; for the same cause cannot act a second time, without having acted a first ; and if, from the fact of its having acted 16* 370 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. once, the effect of the second act may be different, there can be no such necessary uniformity of effect as the law supposes. There must be something to determine if there shall be a difference between the effect of the first and second action, and, if so, what difference. That differ- ence in circumstances, which has arisen from the cause having once acted, cannot itself determine the different action the second time. We have already shown that the mere existence of the thing created cannot influence the mind that created it, except as a circumstance to be considered by it in determining its next creative act, and as, by the hy- pothesis, there is nothing else in existence when this second action is to be determined, it must be deter- mined by the causey-by the Infinite Hind — in view of the result of its first action, and of what it wants to do in the future ; and hence, as before shown, the Infinite Intelligence is not only an originating creative cause, but, in virtue of its intelligence, can produce different effects by successive acts of volition, and determine what the difference in each of these successive acts shall be. If we suppose all material creation to be the one effect of the first action of the First Cause, then, under this rule of uniformity of cause and effect, that cause must have then become dormant ; and as, whether that creation be the imagery — the conceptions — of the mind of God made directly palpable, or His ordering of mat- ter conformably to His conceptions, it cannot change itself, or be governed or changed by law impressed upon it, it must, so far as Creator and creation are con- cerned, remain fixed without change ; for any subse- CAUSE AND EFFECT. 371 quent change would be another and different effect pro- duced by the same cause, which is contrary to the as- sumed law, that the same causes necessarily produce the same effects, and hence, if this law be true, the first effort of the First Cause would destroy itself as cause, leaving no room or possibility for its future activity in new and different creations, or in changing what it had first created. But there is change — change in our sensations, if in nothing else ; changes we do not produce by any action of our own, and hence, we must infer the continued ex- istence of some other power as cause, producing these changes. If the same cause must necessarily produce the same effects, the effects must be co-existent with the cause ; for if the cause can exist without immediately producing the effect, it may exist any length of time, and even forever, without the effect, and the effect would not be a necessary effect of such a cause ; and, in this view, the First Cause, if the subject of such a necessity of effect, must have immediately exhausted its creative or causative power in a necessary effect. If, to obtain a continuing causative power, and yet retain the law of necessity in cause and effect, we sup- pose the effect of the first cause to have been the crea- tion of other cause, then, this other cause, too, must have immediately produced all its necessary effects ; and so of any number of duplicate causes, and there would be an end of the power to produce changes, all, being simultaneous, would have no existence in time, and no subsequent changes could be produced. So that the application of this rule to intelligence as cause 5 denies any continuing power to produce changes in the 372 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. universe ; which, being contrary to the fact, proves the rule untrue, and shows the necessity and the fact of the existence of a cause which is not subject to this law of necessity, or of uniformity of effects, but which has a faculty of producing different effects, or, at least, so far adapting itself to circumstances, that, from the fact that it has once exerted its causative power, and pro- duced an effect, it may, by a subsequent exertion, pro- duce a different effect. This freedom must be an at- tribute of the Infinite Intelligence, and u uniformity of cause and effect " in regard to It, means nothing more than the uniform modes of willing, or the modes which It voluntarily adopts for Its own government ; which is but an expression of Its freedom ; for this is controlling Its own action ; and that It does this in conformity to a law of Its own creation, or which It voluntarily adopts, cannot lessen this freedom. With regard to the finite mind, experience indicates that, after having, under any given circumstances, acted in one way, it may, on a recurrence of them, elect, and frequently does elect, to try another way ; the fact that it has already tried one way with certain effects, having, by increasing its knowledge, led to a belief that some other way may be productive of more desira- ble effects, or, at least, again add to its knowledge by practical experience in the new mode. It is enabled to design or conceive these new modes of action, to ex- amine and judge of their expediency, and to execute them in virtue of its being intelligent, originating cause, with a faculty of adapting its action to its view of the circumstances in which it is placed, and by which it is surrounded, which itself only can do. It may be said, that t^is change in the view, or CAUSE AND EFFECT. 373 knowledge and want of the mind, makes it, in fact, a different cause. This is merely a question of identity, w^hich it is useless now to discuss, further than to say that, if it be the same cause, producing different effects, it disproves the rule ; and if it be a different cause, it cannot logically be inferred from different causes pro- ducing different effects, that the same causes must pro- duce the same effects. I may, however, further ob- serve, that this difference in the mind's knowledge in the second case, grows directly out of its experience in the firsthand if, as a consequence of intelligent cause or causes having once acted, their recurring action may be different, the rule as to them becomes a nullity ; for there is then no necessity that the subsequent action of the same causes shall produce the same effect as they did when they first acted. If it be said, in asserting this necessary uniformity, the phrase " same causes " in- cludes not only the efficient, or active power, but all the co-existing objects and circumstances having any relation whatever to the action of this power, still the rule can then never have any application to intelligent beings acting as cause, for in mind the same circum- stances cannot thus occur twice, because, to it, the fact of having occurred a first time, itself makes a differ- ence in the second. It varies the knowledge, which is one of its essential elements as cause. The nearest ap- proach to it is when the mind has forgotten that they have before occurred. In such cases we determine as if they never had before occurred, and the common ex- perience is that we sometimes realize afterward that, from not recalling their previous occurrence, we, in the second case, acted differently without being aware of it, and when, but for this forgetting, we probably would have repeated the first action. 374 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. This cause and effect, as used by Edwards, involves the infinite series, which he so often introduces into his arguments. If the same causes necessarily produce the same effects, and everything which begins to be must have a cause, then this new event, this beginning to be, must arise from some change in the operating causes, otherwise no new effect could be produced ; but this change in the operating causes is an event which must also have a cause, and which, in its begin- ning, must have arisen from some change in the operat- ing cause of it, which change, again, must have had a cause ; and so we have a series, which can have no be- ginning unless there was either an event without a cause, or a different effect from the same unchanged cause. If, to avoid this dilemma, we suppose the series traced back to a necessary self-existent cause, which had no beginning, it may be replied, that such cause, existing from eternity, if acting from necessity, must, of necessity, have produced its proper effect an eternity ago, and could produce no other and new effect, except by some subsequent changes in itself, which it would have no power to produce ; for this would be a different effect of the same cause, and hence, we are compelled to infer a cause which has either the power of changing it- self as cause, or of varying its effects while it remains the same cause. It may be said that, before this cause produces a different effect, it changes itself, either by direct action, or by producing an effect, which reacts and becomes cause of change in its own cause ; but even then, as the changed cause would be a different cause, one, as before observed, could not argue from different causes producing different effects that the same causes must produce the same effects ; and, even CAUSE AND EFFECT. 375 if we could, if the creative and created cause act only from necessity, all their effects must be coexistent with their existence, and all their causative power be in- stantaneously exhausted ; so that, to continue effects in time, there must be some cause which does not, of necessity, produce only one particular effect, but can delay action, and when it does act can produce different effects. We have no reason, then, either from experience or from the nature of things, to suppose that any such law of uniformity is applicable to spirit causes, but, on the contrary, as already stated, actual existences, or changes, in them, at least, in our own sensations, prove that there is now, or must have been some cause, which did not of necessity produce the same effect ; and the existence of such a cause, either in the past or present, would disprove the rule of necessary uniformity. I have endeavored to show that we have such causes in intelligent beings, — infinite and finite — with origi- nating, creative power ; causes, which, from the very fact of having already produced one effect, are better prepared to go on to produce other and different effects, and that, but for this versatility, only one effect ever could have been produced. An effect cannot be till its cause exists ; but it does not follow that cause must be before its effect. That which may become cause may, and, as in the case of intelligent being, generally does exist, before by activi- ty it becomes cause. If matter exists in a state of rest, it too must have activity, motion, imparted to it before it becomes cause. At the same instant, however, that a sufficient cause begins to act, its effect must al£o begin to be, and if that which may be cause, or in which 376 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. power may be said to subsist, begins to act at the in- stant in which it comes into existence, its effect must be simultaneous with its existence ; for, as before observed, if the effect can be delayed one instant, it may another, and another, and so may never be, which is to say that the sufficient cause is not a sufficient cause. As used in my argument, however, it is only essential to predicate this co-existence of effect with a necessary cause. If we suppose matter, in the first instance, to have been quiescent, then all changes in it must be traceable to an intelligent will ; and, if we suppose matter to have been in motion from eternity, and, as a conse- quence, to have been producing, in a certain order of succession, such necessary effects as arise from the im- possibility of two bodies occupying the same space ; or, which is the same thing, of one space being two spaces ; then, all changes from this certain order must, also, be referred to an intelligent will. In tracing the connection we are but tracing the last effect back to. an intelligent cause — in most, in- stances to the will of God as a first cause. We cannot often, if ever, tell how many terms there may be in the series. For aught we know, gravitation may be the immediate will of God, acting in conformity to a uni- form law, which He has voluntarily adopted, and which we have ascertained, while the changes in the weather may be immediately determined by His will, acting either without uniformity, or in conformity to some law which we have not ascertained. The present conditions may be different from any which ever before existed, and hence different from any which ever before attended or preceded either a clear CAUSE AND EFFECT. 377. or a cloudy sky, and yet either a clear or a cloudy sky will attend or follow them. Some of these things may have been made not uniform to vary the problems of life, and develop the finite intelligence in their solution, as the concealment of his plans, by one player at chess, makes a necessity for more thought, care and vigilance in the other, to provide for an unascertained amount of variability in his move. It is true, that the same intention might be fulfilled by concealing the law ; but greater variety in the problems is obtained by using both means, stimu- lating the human intellect to discover'the law and thus get power to foreknow events arising under it ; and, also, forever tasking it to provide for certain contingen- cies, which it never can thus learn certainly to an- ticipate. There is no more difficulty in supposing the finite intelligence to be a first, or originating cause of change in its finite sphere of action, than in supposing the Su- preme Intelligence to be first cause in the sphere of the Infinite. Intelligence, in all degrees, may possess the faculty of adapting itself to that change of circumstan- ces, which itself has produced by causing an effect, and go on to produce another and different effect ; and this entirely , destroys the rule of necessary uniformity of cause and effect as applicable to intelligent cause ; for, if such cause, in consequence of having produced one effect, may, from that very circumstance, produce a different effect, no case can possibly arise in which the same intelligent cause must produce the same effect. "Without such power of adaptation to the changes which itself has wrought, the First Intelligent Cause must forever have thought the same thought, or per- 378 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. formed the same action over and over ; and, if the effect of that action was the creation of a finite intelli- gence with one or more thoughts, then, every other effect must also have been the creation of a finite intel- ligence, like the first, with only the same thought. But, if it be a characteristic of intelligence that, through its constitutional want for activity, or more directly, its want for knowledge and its intuitive knowledge of the means of acquiring it, one idea is but the precursor of another and different idea, and that these ideas, singly or accumulated, are the means by which the mind adapts its action to the want, both thoughts and muscu- lar movements, internal and external action, may be varied without any other effective cause than the intel- ligence itself, which wants, thinks and acts, and which is thus, in itself, a creative first cause. I have already alluded to the fact, that this uni- formity of the action of Supreme Intelligence, as ob- served in many cases, may arise in part from the perfect wisdom by which it determines its acts without the necessity of experiment. The same remark applies in some degree to the action of the finite will, which, with finite wisdom, knowing, or ascertaining by experience, or otherwise, the best modes in certain cases, will adopt them, whenever such cases arise ; and this gives some appearance of reason for the application of the law of uniformity and necessity in cause and effect to mind. It appears then, that a certain uniformity of the effect of intelligent action, on which the argument for necessity is based, is, or at least may be caused by the free action of intelligence, infinite or finite ; and, there- fore, from the existence of such uniformity, it cannot be inferred that no such free action exists. The existence CAUSE AND EFFECT. 3 79 of an effect cannot be a reason against the existence of that which may be its cause. This uniformity could not have produced itself, nor could it have been pro- duced by blind, undesigning forces, except in cases when some effect must be, and only one effect is possible ; i. e.) when non-effect and also any other than one par- ticular effect involve a contradiction.* We must refer this uniformity, in all other cases, to the action of intel- ligence, and to infer from it necessity in the action of intelligence is to make the effect necessitate its own cause. If the action of the mind is the cause of the volition, then, as before observed, that the volition, as an effect of such action, is necessary, does not prove that the ause — the action of the mind — is necessary, but only proves an infallible power in mind, as such cause, to determine its volitions. But there may be another reason for this uniformity in the mode of God's action, for, as the finite mind acts more or less through His modes, or is influenced in its action by what it presumes His action under certain cir- cumstances will be, this uniformity of action in Him is essential to the action of finite intelligence — to the exist- ence of finite free agents — for, without this uniformity in God's action, a finite agent could have no knowledge as to what would be the effect of his effort, and would have no inducement to make any effort. If, for in- stance, an effort to move a heavy body one way was just as likely to move it in a way not intended and counter to the want of the agent, the effort would never be made. We cannot conceive that the Supreme Intelligence * See Appendix, Note XLYI. 380 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. acts, except from a want of change of some kind — a desire for variety — and this desire, of itself, would seem to be best gratified or accomplished by making every act a new variety, rather than in conformity to some previous act. That God has not done so, but, in many cases, adopted the rule of uniformity of action, seems to indicate a design, which was incompatible with the variety just suggested, and which is not only consistent with, but necessary to, the existence of finite agents freely exercising the finite creative power of will ; and in this uniformity, then, instead of the argument which Edwards deduces from it in favor of necessity, we have an argument from final causes in favor of the freedom of the finite mind in its acting or willing. Before closing this chapter, I will notice an argu- ment derived from the supposed law of uniformity in cause and effect, in connection with the influence of cir- cumstances, which has been thus stated. If the same circumstances occur a thousand times, and the state of the mind is the same, its action will be the same, and hence, necessary under the circum- stances. This is but a particular application of the general rule, that the same causes necessarily produce the same effects ; which, we have already shown, is not a law of metaphysical necessity, and that there is no reason to presume that it applies to mind. The fact that all the circumstances have before occurred, including the con- dition of the mind, is involved in the statement ; and this fact making itself an alteration in the repetition of them, the mind may, from that circumstance, elect to vary its action. If so, as before shown, this destroys the rule, and the inference which is based upon it. CAUSE AND EFFECT. 381 But admit, for the sake of the argument, that this law does apply to mind, and further, that in every one of the thousand cases, one of the conditions of the mind is that of necessity / then, the same causes necessarily producing the same effects, the action of the mind is the same. Again, suppose that, in every one of the thou- sand cases, the condition of the mind is that of freedom / then, under the same law of the uniformity of causes and effects, the action of the mind would still be the same in each of these thousand cases ; and, as we may thus change this condition of the mind from necessity to freedom, without changing the result, the result can- not possibly indicate which of the two elements was involved ; or, in other words, admitting the fact and the application of the law, it applies just as well to mind controlling and directing its own volitions, as to mind in which the volitions are controlled and directed by some external power. If, in every one of the thousand cases, the action of the mind is the same, it can, so far as this case is concerned, just as well be so because it acts freely as because it acts from necessity ; and hence, even admitting the law on which the argument is wholly based, and that it does apply to mind, it has no force whatever, and cannot even indicate whether, in each of the thousand cases, the condition of the mind's action is that of necessity or freedom. Admitting that, in every one of the thousand cases, the mind, even by preliminary effort, or by immediate perception, comes to the same conclusion as to what to do — that, the truth being palpable, it cannot but per- ceive it — still this perception is not the act of will, but knowledge preparatory to it ; and if, with this conclu- sion or knowledge as to what to do, it were found try- 382 EEVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. ing to do something else, this would indicate that the mind was not free, but constrained by some extrinsic power ; while, on the other hand, its trying to do that which is in conformity with its knowledge indicates self- direction of its power and consequently freedom in the effort or act of will. It would be a strange and contra- dictory idea of freedom, which would require, for its realization, that a man might try to do what he de- cided not to do, and might not try to do that which he decided to do, and thus act contrary to his own views. The fallacy of the argument from the " thousand cases " lies in supposing that, after the mind has, by a decision or judgment, directed its volition or effort, freedom still requires that some other volition or effort should be possible ; which, were it so, would really show that the mind might not be free ; that is, that it might not direct its own action. The assertion " if the same circumstances occur a thousand times," &c, must in- clude all the circumstances ; if we stop short of the knowledge or final decision of the mind as to its own action, the rule will be found to have no application, or to be untrue ; and, admitting the assertion, it then really shows only that the willing by the mind is al- ways in conformity to its own decision or knowledge as to what to do. If there is, of necessity, a connection between this decision and effort, this only proves that the mind is of necessity free in such effort ; and to assert the contrary, is again like saying that freedom is not free because it is of necessity free. This view brings the argument home to our defini- tion of freedom, as that condition in which a being directs its own action or movement ; while that argu- CAUSE AND EFFECT. 383 ment, which, from this necessity of connection between the decision and the volition of a being, would infer necessity, must assume that freedom requires that a being may act counter to itself — to its own directing power. CHAPTER XII. god's foreknowledge. Another argument of Edwards is, that the acts of the will are necessary because God certainly foreknows them ; and that, what is foreknown by Omniscience must as certainly happen as though it were decreed by Omnipotence, and, therefore, such acts cannot be free. Against this it has been contended that, even though God foreknows every event, such prescience does not cause that event, or control the act of will which is foreknown. It may be asserted, with some show of reason, that freedom of the human will is one of the elements of God's foreknowledge ; that He knows that such or such an event will happen, because it depends on the foreseen free action of some being, without which it would not happen. On this I would remark, that it does not fulfil the intention of those who urge it. It does not avoid the practical difficulties of fatalism. A man with this belief might say : " I need not trouble myself with regard to the future. Everything in that future, even my own agency upon it, is already as certainly determined as the past. No effort of mine god's fokeknowledge. 385 can change it ; or, if effort or volition of mine is to change it, that effort, that volition, will inevitably take place, and no care or thought of mine will prevent it." The position still admits that necessity which it is in- tended to exclude. With such "belief he would make no effort. When a man wills he always intends, as already shown, to produce some effect in the future, to produce some change, or to make that future — internal or exter- nal — in some respects different from what it would be without such effort. But, if the fact is that no effort of his can in any way change that future, and he knows it, he will not will at all, freely or otherwise. As just suggested, it may be said that his free act of will is itself one of the events infallibly foreknown, and hence must happen. This, it will be perceived, in the last analysis, involves the contradiction of supposing a free will to be a necessitated will, so that the position, as- sumed, even if it would obviate the difficulty, is unten- able, and cannot be urged by the advocates of freedom against this argument for necessity. An event fore- known by infallible prescience must be as certain in the future, as if known by infallible memory in the past, and to say that God foreknows an event, which depends upon the action of an agent, which, acting without His control, may, of itself, freely and independently produce any one of several different results, or none at all, in- volves a contradiction. I am disposed to yield to the argument of Edwards all the benefit of any doubt on these points, and, waiving any replication which might be founded on the power of God to influence the future free action of a finite agent by imparting or withhold- ing knowledge, to admit that what is certainly fore- known by Omniscience must certainly happen, and 17 386 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. that, if God foreknows the volitions of men, then they cannot will freely, and for a refutation of his argument for necessity, founded on prescience, rely only upon other considerations.* One essential link in his argument is that, God does foreknow all the future, and, especially, all human voli- tions ; and this Edwards attempts to prove by showing that such knowledge is absolutely necessary to God's proper government of the world. On the point that God does foreknow,' I would remark that, as in regard to the argument from canse and effect, it appeared that God, having the power to produce infinite variety, had yet chosen to lessen that variety by establishing a cer- tain uniformity between antecedents and consequents, and that the apparent object of this was to make the existence of finite free agents possible ; so, also, though God, having the power to determine, could foreknow all events, He may forego the exercise of such power, and neither control nor foreknow the particular events, which are thus left to be determined by the action of the human mind. That God may certainly foreknow any event, which He has the power to bring to pass, will not, however, militate against the argument in favor of freedom ; for, if God, by the direct exercise of His power, produces a volition, it is not the volition of any other being than Himself; and if He indirectly influ- ences the volition by changing the knowledge of a being, then this change of knowledge avails only on the hypothesis that this \>o,mg freely conforms its action to its knowledge. If a being does not will freely, there is no reason to suppose that any inducements to a cer- tain act will avail to produce that act any more than * See Appendix, Note XL VII. god's foreknowledge. . 387 the contrary. But, as we have already suggested, even supposing God to have this power over every future event, and that either directly or indirectly He can con- trol every volition, and deny freedom to every other being, He may forego the exercise of such power, and thus make the existence of finite free agents possible. This is not only conceivable, but we are conscious of having and of exercising such power ourselves — that we can refrain from doing and from knowing what we might do and know, in order that another may act freely. For instance, a child is in a room with two doors to it. I know that, by using my superior strength, I can put the child out of the room by a certain one of them, and hence, may foreknow that the child will go out by that door ; but I decide not to use my strength for that purpose, and leave the child to its own free action — to go out by either door, or to remain in the room. I may alter the circumstances, as, for instance, by placing some attractive object just without one of the doors in the view of the child, and thus, make it probable that the child will leave by that door ; and this probability is founded on the presumption that the child, with the knowledge of this attractive object, will want to move to that object and freely will to do so. I may, however, will not to exert any influence — not to change the circumstances, or increase the knowledge of the child — but leave it by its own knowledge freely to determine what to do. In this case I do not even seek to change its final action by imparting knowledge. Edwards argues that God must foreknow the voli- tions of finite moral agents, for, otherwise, His knowl- edge of the future would become so imperfect that He could not govern the universe. He says : 388 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. " So that, according to this notion of God's not fore- seeing the volitions and free actions of men, God could foresee nothing appertaining to the state of the world of mankind in future ages ; not so much as the being of one person that should live in it ; and could foreknow no events, but only such as He would bring to pass Him- self by the extraordinary interposition of His immediate power ; or things which should come to pass in the nat- ural material world, by the laws of motion and course of nature, wherein that is independent on the actions, or works of mankind ; that is, as He might, like a very able mathematician and astronomer, with great exact- ness, calculate the revolutions of the heavenly bodies and the greater wheels of the machine of the external creation. " And if we closely consider the matter, there will appear reason to convince us, that He could not, with any absolute certainty, foresee even these. As to the first, namely, things done by the immediate and extra- ordinary interposition of God's power, these cannot be foreseen, unless it can be foreseen when there shall be occasion for such extraordinary interposition. And that cannot be foreseen unless the state of the moral world can be foreseen. For whenever God thus inter- poses, it is with regard to the state of the moral world, requiring such divine interposition. Thus, God could not certainly foresee the universal deluge, the calling of Abraham, the destruction of Sodom and Gomorrah, the plagues on Egypt and Israel's redemption out of it, the expelling the seven nations of Canaan, and the bringing Israel into that land ; for these all are repre- sented as connected with things belonging to the state of the moral world. Nor can God foreknow the most god's fokeknowledge. 389 proper and convenient time of the day of judgment and general conflagration ; for that chiefly depends on the course and state of things in the moral world " (pp. 144-5). " It will also follow from this notion that, as God is liable to be continually repenting what He has done ; so He must be exposed to be constantly changing His mind and intentions as to His future conduct ; altering His measures, relinquishing His old designs, and forming new schemes and projections. For His purposes, even as to the main parts of His scheme, namely, such as belong to the state of His moral kingdom, must be always liable to be broken, through want of foresight ; and He must be continually putting His system to rights, as it gets out of order through the contingence of the actions of moral agents. He must be a Being, who, instead of being absolutely immutable, must neces- sarily be the subject of infinitely the most numerous acts of repentance and changes of intention of any being whatsoever ; for this plain reason, that His vastly extensive charge comprehends an infinitely greater number of those things, which are to Him contingent and uncertain. In such a situation, He must have little else to do, but to mend broken links as well as He can, and be rectifying His disjointed frame and disordered movements, in the best manner the case will allow. The Supreme Lord of all things must needs be under great and miserable disadvantages, in governing the world, which He has made, and has the care of, through His being utterly unable to find out things of chief importance, which hereafter shall befall His system ; which, if Pie did but know, He might make seasonable provision for. In many cases, there may be very great 390 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. / necessity that He should make provision, in the man ner of His ordering and disposing things, for some great events which are to happen, of vast and extensive influ- ence, and endless consequence to the universe ; which He may see afterward when it is too late, and may wish in vain that He had known beforehand, that He might have ordered His affairs accordingly. And it is in the power of man, on these principles, by his devices, pur- poses, and actions, thus to disappoint God, break His measures, make Him continually to change His mind, subject Him to vexation and bring Him into confusion " (pp. 149-50). We v might, perhaps, argue that these statements rather tend to show that God does not foreknow the volitions and actions of men, or, at least, that if He does, He generally chooses not to interfere with them, but, for long periods of time, leaves them to their own free actions ; for it does appear from the record, that " it is in the power of man * * * by his devices, purposes, and actions, thus to disappoint God, break His measures, and make Him continually to change His mind," and that He does not " make seasonable provision " to prevent the necessity of His " rectifying His disjointed frame and disordered movements," as evinced in the necessity of a general destruction by the flood to get rid of a corruption which had arisen from agencies which He did not control, and which, a resort to such a measure by Omnipotence would seem to argue, could not possibly be directly controlled by ex- trinsic power. We propose, however, to discuss the question on philosophical and not on theological ground, and to treat inferences from Biblical quotations as we would deductions or illustrations from any other state- ment of fact or belief. GOD S FOREKNOWLEDGE. 391 The foregoing reasoning of Edwards asserts, that it is necessary that God should foreknow the volitions of men, because of the influence of those volitions on the affairs of the world. But, it is evident that the sup- posed difficulty relates less to the volitions than to the effects, or actual doings in which the volitions are ex- ecuted ; and, if the foreknowledge of a volition is thus necessary, the foreknowledge of the sequent effects must, " a fortiori," he, also, necessary ; and if the fore- knowledge of the volition proves it to he not free, the foreknowledge of the doing must prove it not free, and this would take from man the liberty which Edwards grants him, in doing what he wills. If to this it be re- plied that, if the volition is controlled, there is no ne- cessity for controlling the consequent effect, or doing, for the volition itself controls it ; it would still appear that there is no liberty in the sequent doing, for the reply asserts, that it is controlled by the will, which is, also, controlled, and, of course, whatever controls the will, also controls the doing ; so that, if there is no liberty in willing, there can really be none in the conse- quent doing, and all human liberty is denied. But, even supposing there may be freedom in doing what we will, when there is no freedom in willing, the foregoing difficulty, in respect to God's government, as Edwards states it, is equally obviated, either by suppos- ing that God controls the volition and constrains it to be in conformity to His preordained plan ; or that, leaving man to will freely, He frustrates the execution — the doing — making the result different from what the agent willing intended, whenever that intention conflicts with that foreordained plan. Of these two positions, it seems most reasonable to adopt the latter, 302 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. as it is a fact, well attested by our daily experience, that in the doing we are often thus frustrated and over- ruled, while our consciousness reveals no such inter- ference with our willing to do. For aught that appears, the sequences of the volitions may be determined in that inscrutable process, by which our volitions are made efficient, and of which, Edwards truly says, we know nothing. Giving to the argument, then, all the scope which Edwards assigns to it, it disproves the free- dom in doing, which he asserts, rather than the freedom in willing, which he denies. But, perhaps, the urgencies of the argument do not require that even the freedom in doing should be abandoned ; and, even supposing man's volitions to be always executed, I still think that Edwards overrates their influence on the ability of God to control and direct the universe and its affairs. The child's remaining in the room, or going out of it by one door, or the other, does not materially affect that knowledge by which I judge of what I shall do in rela- tion to the future. Knowing all the results possible in the case, viz., that the child will remain in the room, or go out by one door, or by the other, I may use what wisdom I have, in so ordering my own actions, as to insure the most good, or the least possible evil from their combination with any one of the three possible contingent events. Now, the acts of any finite number of finite free agents, must bear a less ratio to the power and wisdom of the Supreme Intelligence, than the act of the child does to even the most wise and powerful of finite intelligences, and as God may know all the acts or effects possible by such finite intelligences, singly or combined, He may, in His infinite wisdom, provide for every possible event which to Him, either by the neces- god's foreknowledge. 393 cities of the case, or by His own free will, is thus made contingent. Of an arrangement so vast, it is difficult for us to form a conception to reason upon, and I will, therefore, endeavor to illustrate the views just expressed by supposing a case, which, though perfectly conceiv- able, is beyond the reach of any human calculation, and beyond any human power. Suppose, then, a chessboard — an automaton chess- board — in which each piece differing in functions, or color, has a different weight, and that each square is separately supported by a spring, so that the different weights will depress each to a different point. If we suppose any one given position of the pieces, it is con- ceivable that the different degrees of depression may act upon machinery devised for the purpose (say ma- chinery moved by a weight like a clock), so that the best move which the position admits of will be made ; and though, even for one movement, it would require very complicated machinery, there is nothing inconceiv- • able or impossible in it ; and, as this is conceivable of any one combination of the pieces, it is conceivable that it may be applied to every possible combination. Sup- pose then, such a chessboard, the moves, on one side, made by the automatic machinery, and on the other by an intelligent finite free agent. We will suppose there is nothing else in existence but the board so constructed — (of course, with whatever is requisite to sustain at- traction, gravitative and cohesive), — and this free agent playing the other side of the game. The agent moves freely ; what particular move he would make, the mech- anist who devised the machine did not and "could not anticipate, but knowing every possible move which the position admitted of, he has devised the machine in refer- 17*- 394: REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. ence to every such possible move ; and though no partic- ular move is foreknown, yet, if the mechanist, with full knowledge of every possible combination, has so con- trived the machine, that in its turn the best possible move will be made, the result, supposing the mechanist to have his choice in regard to the first move, will certainly be checkmate to the agent, who moves freely, but without this comprehensive knowledge of the whole possibilities of the game. And to effect this result does not require any departure from uniform modes of action^ but, on the contrary, is produced by the intelligent application of one of the most uniform of what we term laws of matter, — that of attraction. The attraction of gravita- tion, acting through the weight attached to the ma- chinery, imparts the force to move the pieces, and through the difference in the weights and the conse- quent unequal depression of the squares by the pieces on them, giving direction to that force ; while the attraction of cohesion gives the requisite resistance to the springs which support the squares. The combina- tions on the chessboard, though vast in number, are finite, and may all be comprehended by a finite intelli- gence. Though no human being could in a lifetime accomplish any large part of the calculations and work- manship essential to such a machine as we have de- scribed, still, power and intelligence short of the infinite could accomplish it ; and, if a mechanist of finite pow- ers could, by modes as uniform as the laws of attrac- tion, thus cause to be made all the moves essential to the skilful playing of this complicated game, and that, too, without being able to anticipate a single move on the other side, there can be nothing unreasonable in supposing that God, with a perfect knowledge of all the god's foreknowledge. 395 possible combinations and changes, which His own sys- tem will admit of, including all the possible effects of the action of finite free agents, may, without knowing by anticipation the particular acts of those finite agents, so contrive His uniform modes of action, that, without varying from such uniformity, every possible contin- gence will be provided for, " without altering His meas- ures, relinquishing His old designs and forming new schemes and projections." If it be true, or even con- ceivable, that man, with his finite powers and limited knowledge of the future acts of God and of his fellow beings, which does not include all possible acts, can yet, in his finite sphere, with finite wisdom, adapt his acts with some degree of effectiveness to that future, it is certainly conceivable, that God, with His infinite powers and full knowledge of all that is possible from other causes in the future, may, with infinite wisdom, adapt His acts to all the possibilities of that future, so that He will not be liable to be " frustrated of His end." We have explained how this may be done consist- ently with uniformity in His modes of action, but He has still in reserve the power of deviating from that uniformity, in miracles, and it appears that the acts of men, in the exercise of their free agency, became so generally perverse and corrupt, that Supreme Wisdom demanded their almost total extinction, and a special act or miraculous interference for that end. Besides miracles, which are deviations from the established uni- form modes of God's action, we do not know but that many things are the result of His special actions in regard to which He has established no law of uniformity. We do not know that these things are not dependent, 396 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. in each case, on His immediate will, without reference to any conformity with acts performed in the past, or contemplated in the future. We do not know but that the storm, which destroyed the Spanish Armada — the winds, which delayed the landing of William of Orange — or the unusually early commencement of cold weather, which frustrated the plans of Napoleon and destroyed his army in Russia, were all as much special acts as the miraculous opening of the waters of the Bed Sea, which favored the escape of the Israelites from Egyptian bondage. With these ample means there would seem to be no danger that God, with in- finite power and wisdom, could be " frustrated of His end," or, that He would not be able, even without fore- knowledge of the particular acts of finite free agents, to bring to pass all that He might deem essential to the proper government of the universe, and to such care or control as He chooses to take of all that He has cre- ated.* We will add that the necessity of knowing events in advance, in order to " make seasonable pro- vision for them," arises from the weakness of the agent on whom the making of such provision devolves, and the time required will be somewhat and inversely pro- portioned to the power and wisdom of the agent. When that power and wisdom become infinite, the time required becomes nought, and God would there- fore require less time to consider the most intricate and complicated affairs conceivable, than we would to de- termine the simplest possible case that could be pre- sented to us. The foreknowledge of God has the same relation to His action, that the preconceptions of man have to his. * See Appendix, Note XL VIII. god's fokeknowledge. 397 God perceives what, without His own effort, the course of things in the future may be, and by what effort he can change that course. A finite being may exert all his ability to know the future, and may also exert all his power to influence the course of events, and thus increase the probability that the future will conform to his anticipations : or he may, as in the case of the child just mentioned, forego the exercise of his own power that another may act freely. There is certainly no impossibility that God may do the same. A being of limited powers may know all the effects bearing upon his future action, which such single or combined efforts can produce, even if the modes in which they can be produced are infinite, and hence beyond his prescience. For instance, the ways in which a friend may reach a place at which I am to meet him at a given time, may be infinite in number, and yet, the fact that he does reach the place at the appointed time, be all that is materia] to my plan of future action. In certain states of a game of chess, a man can foresee every possible move, which his antagonist may next make, that can affect the result of the game, and make his own plans accordingly. A man of ordinary skill and discernment may, sometimes, do this even for each of a few moves in advance, and, if he had sufficient capacity, he could do it for the whole game. To one who did this, the game would lose its interest, and he would play it only as a benevolent man plays the sim- ple game of Fox and Geese with a child for its amuse- ment. Suppose, for instance, that at the commencement of the game, one player, A, having the requisite capacity, perceives that his antagonist, B, has his choice of the 398 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. twenty different moves. A may plan his play so that he will be ready to move in any one of the twenty cases which can arise, and B, at the commencement, if looking forward, and providing in advance for the whole game, must, for his second move, take into view the four hundred possible contingencies growing out of the two moves to be previously made ; and the number of possible combinations in a game of ordinary length would be almost innumerable. But even to provide in advance for all these, though far beyond the reach of human faculties, would still be within the scope of even a finite comprehension ; and when we contemplate the Supreme Intelligence, as anticipating and providing, or making immediate provision as they occur, for all the possible contingencies which can arise from the free volitions of myriads of free agents, and all their com- binations ; although we know that, being still finite in number, they cannot exhaust the power, or fill the com- prehension, which is infinite ; yet, we may perceive that they may furnish ample occasion for the effort — that they may call out the energies of a being, capable of producing all the sublimely vast and minutely per- fect combinations, which creative power has exhibited to us ; and, perhaps, can hardly avoid the thought that they must, even in such a being, excite that interest, which arises from the necessity of thought, skill, and contrivance, to accomplish its object and avoid being frustrated by the action of other powers. If, on the other hand, God foreknows, and, as an attribute of Divinity has ever foreknown all the future, then that portion of His creative power which relates to designing that future, and which is the highest at- tribute of Creative Power, has no sphere for its exer- GOD S FOREKNOWLEDGE. 399 cise, and never could have had any ; it is virtually- annihilated, and God becomes a mere executive causal- ity working out plans preformed, and requiring in their accomplishment no higher order of intelligence, no more exalted creative talent than is required to copy a paint- ing. On such hypothesis, indeed, still less than this, for, as on it God's own volitions must be foreknown and be manifest to Himself, He does not even have by a present exercise of intelligent power to adapt his effort to the effect, as the copyist must do, and this per- fect prescience would degrade the Supreme Power to the same rank as that of one who turns the crank of a mill, knowing that thereby the corn is ground, but also knowing each required volition without any present effort for that object. A prescience which has always included the whole future must be innate, and never have been the occasion for any exercise of intelligent power, which the knowledge required to turn the crank may have been. The acting of a being from the knowl- edge of a mode which has ever existed ready formed in its own mind is purely instinctive, and action merely from the innate knowledge of its own volitions and of the order of their succession, requiring no exercise of intelligence in applying the known mode to the occa- sion for it, would be below the ordinary forms of in stinctive action. It is not my purpose now to follow Edwards in his attempt to prove that his system of necessity is consist- ent with moral agency, with virtue, and with common sense. This, if I have succeeded in showing that his arguments in support of that system are fallacious, and 4:00 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WDLL. that it is in fact untrue, would be needless ; and, if I have failed to do this, there would be little ground to hope that my examination of the subsequent portions of his work would be attended with any better result. CHAPTEK XIII. C ONCLTTSION. Ve have now shown that the Will, instead of being as defined by Edwards " that by which the mind chooses anything," is the mind's faculty or power of making effort, and that, in relation to choice, we make effort to ascertain which of two or more things is preferable only as we do to ascertain any other fact which we want to know ; that Edwards also defines choice to be a com- parative act, or the result of such act, and yet makes choice and will synonymous. He also makes will the last agency of the mind in producing an effect, and as- sumes that choice is a necessary prerequisite and the distinguishing condition of free acts of will. From these various and incompatible definitions of the same terms, and these unfounded assumptions, he argues that as a free act of will must be preceded by a choice, which is itself also an act of will, and hence, if a free act, must have also been preceded by a choice, and this choice as a free act of will again thus preceded, and so on without limit, there could have been no first free act of will, and, if the first act was not free, then the whole subsequent train is not free. But the foundation of this, his favorite reductio ad absurdum^ which he ap- 402 EEVIEW OF EDWAKDS ON THE WILL. plies in a variety of modes, is wholly destroyed by cor- recting the definitions and assumptions as above stated. In regard to this reasoning I have also remarked that self-direction, and not choice, is the distinguishing characteristic of freedom. The mind thus directs its efforts by means of the knowledge which it has at the moment it makes the effort, including its preconcep- tions of the effect it seeks to produce. "Whether this knowledge has been acquired by previous efforts of comparison resulting in choice, or otherwise, it is, at the time of applying it, but the mind's perception, and the mode of its prior acquisition can make no difference to the freedom of the act which the mind directs by means of the knowledge which it now actually possesses. I have further observed that this confounding will with choice, which as one form of knowledge is not subject to the will, but, as a result of certain comparisons, is as necessarily and passively recognized by the knowing sense as sound is through the ear, opens the way for the argument, that as choice is, in this sense, necessary, will, being the same as choice, must also be necessary, and this confounding as identical two things so very distinct as will and knowledge leads to intricate confusion and various sophisms, pervading, as already shown, a large portion of Edwards's argument. In regard to that somewhat simpler form of his re- ductio ad dbsurdum to prove that the will (free or not free) cannot determine itself, because, if it does, it must determine each act by a prior act of will, admit- ting of no first act, and which, taken in the view most favorable for Edwards, only proves that the mind can- not always direct its act of will by a prior act of will, it has already been remarked that this does not conflict with the position that the mind determines its act of CONCLUSION". 403 will by means of its knowledge, in which act, being thus self-directed, it acts freely. Edwards applies this reasoning to choice, evidently, however, here as else- where, using it as a synonym for will, and will, with him, meaning u the soul willing," his inference really is, that the soul willing or choosing cannot "determine its act of will or choice. But it is evident that the essence of a choice must be the determining among ob- jects of choice, and if the soul cannot do this it cannot choose at all, but something else must choose for it. From the same position it also follows that as the mind cannot will generally r , bnt can only will particular acts which must be determined or decided irpon before ft can will, i. e., make effort in regard to them, it cannot will until the act of will is elected and determined or decided upon, and if the mind cannot make this elec- tion it cannot will till some other power has deter- mined its act for it, and hence cannot of itself make effort or will without this extrinsic aid. As bearing on this point I have shown that the mind need not and does not will either to will or not to will, nor yet to suspend willing, but that it directly wills or makes effort to do that which it wants done, and remains or becomes passive when it has no want or perceives no reason to be active, and hence a prior act of will is not necessary either to our willing or non- willing. This denies the premise on which the argu- ments of Edwards just treated of are founded. Edwards also assumes that freedom means power to do as one wills, which, as it can only come after, either does not apply to or denies freedom in the act of willing. In his Part II. Section 13, he asserts that even if the will determines its own act it is not free, because it is • s 404: REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. still controlled, which, as applied to the argument, as before intimated, is equivalent to saying, the mind in its acts of willing is not free,. because in them it must control its own action, and hence is constrained, or is under a necessity, to be free. I need not repeat the rea- soning showing that Edwards's definition of freedom, and this assumption that whatever is controlled even by itself is not free, in which the above sophisms have their root, are wholly erroneous, and that self-control or self-direction is the distinguishing characteristic of freedom. Correct these errors, and -those before men- tioned in regard to will, and a large portion of his rea- soning becomes either entirely futile or affirms the free- dom, not of the will, but of the mind in willing. Edwards's remarks upon " moral necessity " only tend to show that a man must will in conformity to his inclination ; but, as he makes inclination synonymous with choice, preference, and will, this only tends to prove that a man must will in conformity to his will : or, if he uses this term inclination as designating a choice, and a prior choice, as I think would be proper, then, the argument proves that these acts of will have the condition of previous choice which Edwards as- sumes to be the essential condition of free acts ; while his remarks on " Moral Inability," going to show that there can be no act of will when this inclination is wanting, merely tend to prove that there can be no act of will without this essential condition of freedom ; the two arguments thus going to prove that every act of will which is possible must of necessity be free. In regard to the difficulties which Edwards treats of in connection with " moral necessity " and " moral inability," and which he asserts the will may be unable CONCLUSION. 405 to surmount, I have shown that the faculty of will is not in itself limited, but that we can will or make effort to do anything which we can conceive any mode of doing, and further, that these difficulties relate not to our willing, but to our obtaining the knowledge by which to direct our efforts or decide what we will try to do, which, as we are not, and cannot be, omniscient, we cannot always acquire. From u ^Natural Necessity," as Edwards treats it, he can only infer that a man can- not always execute what he wills, or do what he tries to do, which, coming after, cannot affect the freedom of the mind's previous act in willing. I have also observed, that the existence of difficul- ties which the mind in its act of will is unable to sur- mount, goes to prove that the mind is the real agent in such willing, and that if its volitions are necessitated, it could have no difficulty in regard to them : and further, that in all the cases cited by Edwards the supposed difficulty really is the absence of any want to do, and if it were possible for the mind to overcome this diffi- culty, and will what it did not want to will, this would rather indicate that it did not act freely, while the im- possibility of its doing so proves that in such cases it cannot possibly be unfree. After having thus sought to prove that the will, or the soul in willing, cannot determine its own action because of the impossibility of doing it by prior acts of will, or because in the attempt it encounters difficulties which it cannot surmount, Edwards seeks to show that it is determined by some extrinsic cause or power. He argues that every event which begins to be must have a cause, i. e., as he says, a ground or reason why it is, and that this cause must be prior to the event ; that 406 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. volition is such an event, and hence must be connected with some cause in the past on which its existence de- pends, and as the same causes must produce the same effects, the volition is determined by this cause to be one particular volition and can be no other. Against this I have urged that the past cannot will — put forth or produce a volition ; that mind has an inherent abil- ity to act or make effort, and that this action or effort is its volition, of which itself is the cause, and hence that the necessary connection of the effect with its cause only establishes the mind's power to control its volitions, and thus confirms its freedom in willing. And further, that the volition is in no wise dependent on the past any further than that the mind may have acquired knowledge in that past, which knowledge, however, is now present to it, and that if, from any being having power to act, and in present possession of knowledge to direct its action, the past were entirely cut off, or even if to such being there never had been any past, it could still direct its own action, or make effort to affect the future, which is always the de- sign of effort, and hence such volition is not of necessity controlled by the extrinsic events of the past. I have further observed that, so far as we know, every intel- ligent being comes into existence with an object of effort — with want — and the knowledge of a means of gratifying this want, and can thus direct its effort with- out reference to any past. On this point I have also argued that if the past is a cause of which volition is a necessary effect, then, as to every being there always is a past, every being must of necessity w T ill without any cessation ; and fur- ther, that if this cause is the whole past, then, as this CONCLUSION". 407 whole past is at every instant the same to all, and the same causes necessarily produce the same effects (as perhaps any blind causes must do), the same voli- tion must be produced in all at the same time. And if it be said that the volition in each mind is produced only by that portion of the past of which this particular mind is cognizant, then there must be some intelligent power to adapt this volition to the varying circum- stances of each mind, which a blind past could not do. To this controlling cause of volition in the past, Ed- wards subsequently gives the name of " motive," upon his vague definition of which I have commented. He treats inclination as a motive, but he also makes inclina- tion synonymous with choice and will, which would make the will — the soul willing — the cause of its own act. He also treats habit as a motive ; but, as I have shown (in Book I, Chap, xi), habit is but the mind's acting in conformity to a plan before known to it, rather than, to form a new one, and this conforming its action to a mode previously known, being still self- direction, does not militate against its freedom in such action. I have also shown that on analyzing the par- ticular cases cited by Edwards, it appears that motive is but the mind's own view of some desirable effect of its contemplated effort, so that even the " ground or reason " for the act is not found in the past, but in the future, of which the mind has a present preconception. This shows that in these cases, especially selected to prote necessity, the mind directs its acts of will by its own view, i. e., by its own knowledge, thus really affirming its freedom. As touching this influence of the past, I have further 4:08 EEVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. argued that though that, which by activity may be- come cause, may and generally does have a prior ex- istence, yet an effect is always simultaneous with the action of its cause, for if the effect can be delayed for an instant, it may be for another and another, and so may never be. This would dissolve the connection which must exist between any effect actually produced and its cause, though the terms or things connected may not of necessity be uniform. In regard to the uniformity of cause and effect, or the rule that the same causes necessarily produce the same effects, which is assumed by Edwards, and makes an essential link in some of his arguments for necessity, I have contended that it is not a law of metaphysical necessity, but an empirical result of our observations of material phenomena, and that even in them there is no sufficient ground for assuming that it is universal, and no reason to suppose that it applies to mind. That in things material it but indicates that the Supreme Intelligence has voluntarily adopted certain uniform rules for governing or directing His own actions, and that it is quite conceivable that He could have varied this plan so as to have produced a perfect variety or want of uniformity. That even infinite power must be presumed to put forth creative effort from a want of variety, and that the only conceivable reason why such variety is partially sacrificed to uniformity, is the abso- lute necessity of such uniformity to the existence of finite free agents. This uniformity in the material uni- verse, then, instead of favoring the argument for neces- sity in the action of such agents, as Edwards supposes, really becomes, as a final cause, an argument that they act freely. It is conceivable that this result might have CONCLUSION. 409 been reached by other modes, as, for instance, by estab- lishing a law of variability, and making this law known to finite agents, but this does not conflict with the argu- ment just deduced from the fact of uniformity, and need not be here dwelt upon. I have also suggested that this uniformity, in things material, may arise from an infinitely wise being always knowing what is best under certain circumstances and conforming its action in each recurrence of them to this knowledge. Finite mind, too, may freely adopt gen- eral rules for its action under certain circumstances, or at each recurrence of the like circumstances may per- ceive the same action to be best, and freely conforming its action to its knowledge of the general rule, or of the particular fact, produce a certain degree of uniformity in its. efforts and in the consequent effects. In none of these cases does the uniformity conflict with the mind's freedom, but such freedom is rather an element in pro- ducing the uniformity. I have further urged that even admitting the rule of uniform causation, and that it applies to mind, we could only infer from it that the volitions as effects are necessary, and not that mind, as their cause, is neces- sitated or not free in its action. Such necessity of the effect is proof only of the sufficient power of mind as cause to produce it. Hence, though this assumed rule is much relied upon in the argument for necessity, its disproof is not absolutely essential either to the refuta- tion of that argument or to the proof of freedom, and especially if it is established that mind is a first cause, acting from considerations of the future and not moved by power in the past. Throughout his " Treatise " Edwards ignores mind 18 410 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. as cause, making such unintelligent things as past events, motives, and habits control and direct the course of events in the future, including human volitions. I have urged that such unintelligent things have no power or tendency to will themselves, or to produce a volition in anything else, and even if they had such power, their causative action and effects must form an infinite series running backward into the past, each link or term requiring a preceding one as its cause without the possibility of ever reaching a first cause ; and if the Supreme Intelligence is admitted to be a first cause ca- pable of beginning a series' of events without reference to a past, then the assumption in regard to the necessity of past causality is destroyed, and cannot be urged against the position that finite intelligence in its finite sphere may act and produce effects in the future with- out any causative power being exerted by the past. It appears that some of the advocates of freedom have admitted that will and choice are the same, and also that liberty implies the absence not only of ex- trinsic, but of self control, and hence were driven to certain positions in regard to " indifference " and " con- tingence " against which Edwards directs his arguments on these subjects. They are not material to the system I have advanced, and I have remarked upon them only because they afforded opportunity to elucidate my own views, and to expose some of the fallacies opposed to them. Nearly all of Edwards's reasoning upon them rests upon the erroneous definitions and assumptions already mentioned. Another argument for necessity, adduced by Ed- wards, is, that the volition always follows the last dic- tate of the understanding, or is so connected with the CONCLUSION". 411 understanding, as an antecedent cause, that the volition, as its effect, must be one particular volition, and can be no other. But the last dictate of the understanding is often itself a choice, which in Edwards's system is a volition and cannot follow itself. And if the under- standing is a portion, power, faculty, or attribute of the mind, then, that the volition is certainly determined by the understanding only proves the mind's perfect con- trol, and consequent freedom, in its act of willing. The last dictate of the understanding always is a conclusion as to truths or facts in regard to the subject presented, and may be the result of effort in examining by comparison or otherwise, or may be an immediate perception of the knowing sense. In all cases it is the view or knowledge of the mind, which it can use to direct its action. This last dictate, however, is not always followed by an act of will, but in mauy cases, as when we compare two triangles merely to ascertain their relative size, the knowledge is itself the end sought, and leads to no subsequent effort — no act of will follows. It appears, also, that the advocates for freedom have relied much upon the asserted ability of the mind to will in cases of indifference, i. e., in cases in which there can be no ground of choice as between two things or two acts, and no motive to choose or do one rather than the other. Edwards attempts to show that in such cases the mind makes for itself a rule of action which becomes to it a motive to choose one rather than the other. I have endeavored to prove that the plan he suggests really involves the very difficulties he seeks by it to avoid, and in a greater degree, and that the mind in such cases, instead of doing something additional to 412 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. construct this motive, really omits the preliminary com- parison and judgment as to the things or acts which it already perceives to be equal, or ends its effort to com- pare with such perception of their equality, as readily as it would do with a perception that one thing is de- cidedly better than some other, and, in fact, comes to no choice among them. The argument on " choosing in things indifferent " derives much of its supposed importance from the assumption that to choose and to will are the same thing. Under the views I have put forth, choice, even between acting and not acting, may not be of necessity essential to an act of will, much less choice as between different acts or objects. An oyster having the faculty of will and the feeling of hunger, with only an innate knowledge of the mode of opening its bivalves, and that opening them is required to sat- isfy its hunger, could will to open them without com- paring the . act of opening with any other act. If it acts at all it must be without such comparison or conse- quent choice, for it knows no other act with which to compare. It could thus act even though there were no other power in existence, and of course in so doing would then be both uncontrolled and unaided, and hence the act must be wholly its own self-directed act, and, consequently, a free though but an instinctive act. Such an oyster having a faculty of will, and knowledge to direct its effort or act of will to e*ffect what it wants, is in itself complete as a self-acting and self-directing power or cause, is a complete free agent, though with a very limited agency. Its agency is limited like that of every other order of intelligence to the sphere of its knowledge. With the knowledge of one mode of action, preliminary efforts to obtain more knowledge by com- CONCLUSION. 413 parison and consequent choice, are not essential to ac- tion, but only to better or to varied action, and if such preliminary efforts are unsuccessful and no choice is reached, it leaves the mind to the mode of action pre- viously known to it. As by its own unaided efforts the oyster can to the extent of opening and shutting its bivalves influence the future, it is so far a creative first cause. It can originate action and produce effects — begin and complete a series of effects — for which there is no cause anterior to itself. Besides the attempts to prove necessity in the mind's acts of will, by showing in the first place that it cannot determine its own action, and in the second, that its action is determined by something extrinsic to itself, Edwards has a third mode of argument seeking to prove that in point of fact volitions must be necessary because God certainly foreknows them. Admitting, for the argument, that foreknowledge of a volition, by an infal- lible being, involves its necessity, I have contended that for such foreknowledge there is no such necessity as Edwards asserts : that as it appeared probable that God had limited variety, as the object of His action, for the reason that uniformity in it is essential to the existence of finite free agents, so He might for a like reason limit His prescience. Edwards asserts that foreknowledge, and especially foreknowledge of human volitions, is absolutely neces- sary to enable the Supreme Intelligence to govern the universe — that without it He could not provide in sea- son for the contingencies which would arise from the unknown volitions. In opposition to this, I have urged that a being of infinite wisdom could, without knowing a single future volition of any finite being, provide in 414: REVIEW OF EDWAEDS ON THE WILL. advance for every contingency which conld possibly arise from free and independent finite action ; and further that a being infinite in wisdom and power has no need thus to provide in advance, as He could both form and execute His plan at the instant that the emergency for it arose ; that He could do this and yet conform all His acts to uniform modes, and still have in reserve, for any possible requirement, the power to depart from these uniform modes and work by miracles. I have also argued that the actual foreknowledge of all future events, including the volitions of Himself and of all other intelligent beings, would deprive God of the highest attributes of creative intelligence, and, in fact, deny that He ever possessed them — that, though still infinite, His creative power would thereby be reduced in rank beneath that of the mere copyist and His voluntary action to the level of the lowest form of the instinctive. As between these two hypotheses, the one attributing to Deity full actual prescience and thereby, as a logical necessity, depriving Him of the highest attribute of creative power, and the other in which a self-imposed limit to His prescience still makes the continued exercise of free creative efforts with intel- ligent design and adaptation possible both to the finite and the Infinite Intelligence, the reader will judge which is the more reverent, which attributes the greater wis- dom, and which most honors the Omniscient. In here ending my review of this remarkable argu- ment of Edwards, I may be permitted to say that in my efforts to expose its fallacies, as also in the direct argument which I have presented in favor of freedom, I have been actuated by a desire to find truth and to eradicate error, and though I have sought to meet the CONCLUSION. 41 5 subtle reasoning of the great advocate for necessity with his own weapons, I am not conscious that either the ardor incident to polemical discussion, the pride of opinion, or any vain ambition for victory has ever diverted me from these objects. On one other point I would make a suggestion. It is in the domain of the spiritual that the highest attributes of Deity are most especially manifested. In entering it, we pass, as it were, from the material workmanship, the magnificent — the stupendous and harmonious grandeur of which so exalts our conceptions and so fills us with wonder, to that inner sanctuary of thought in which all this gran- deur is designed, and there find that it is but the massive base of an ethereal superstructure still more admirable and sublime. To explore this domain is the province of the metaphysician, and however reverently he may perform his office, he is often subjected to the imputation of profanely entering the Holy of Holies, and of being rudely familiar with sacred things. How far I have avoided what would justify such imputation, and how far my efforts to advance truth have been suc- cessful, that portion of a small class of readers still attracted by the subject, of whtom it may be my good fortune to obtain audience, will decide, and they will perhaps indulge me in closing this work with the ex- pression of an earnest hope that it will be conducive to the progress and elevation of man, and a sincere belief that nothing in it will be found to lessen the love, rev- erence, and homage, which even the most abstract con- templation of the Character of the Most High tends to inspire. APPENDIX. 18* APPENDIX. NOTES TO BOOK I. NOTE I. P. 7. These views may explain the difficulty of applying mathemati- cal reasoning to other subjects. In these we have to apply our definitions to something that exists independent of the definitions, and there is great difficulty in doing this accurately. Another difficulty is in comparing the relations of things not homogeneous in their nature. In mathematics we deal with nothing but quanti- ty, and the whole scope of the comparison is as to its equality, or inequality, under different forms. The"' definitions must be perfect, for they determine the thing defined ; and all the truths of Geom- etry are really involved in these definitions ; the demonstrations under them being mere logical processes, showing that they are so involved, or that what is true, when stated in one way in the definitions, is also true when stated in another way in the propositions. NOTE II. P. 9. "We may also, in some cases, avoid or discard sensations by acts of will. In regard to objects of vision, we may shut our eyes, or direct them to other objects, and may, at least in some degree, modify many other sensations by directing the attention to or from them by direct acts of will. By will we may select from among external objects the subjects of our attention. Though we and other intelligences may be at work altering, at each moment we recognize by the senses only what is and not what will be. What 420 APPENDIX. we have now observed of those sensations, which we refer to ex- ternal objects, is also true of those physical sensations, which arise from our own material organism. Those, too, are external to the mind and independent of the will. "We cannot, by will, feel, or avoid feeling hungry ; and most persons in a normal condition can very faintly even recall or imagine the sensation of bodily pain. In sleep, that state in which the soul seems most independent of the external senses, it has this power; and in some conditions almost perfectly ; indicating that we have undeveloped spiritual faculties by which we may retain the physical sensations, without the material organs of sense. NOTE III. P. 13. In the bodily movements we are conscious of acting upon dis- tinct members occupying distinct positions in space, and that when we move the hand and when we move the foot there is a differ- ence both in the object and in the effort. There is generally some remoter object of an effort for bodily movement, as to move from one place to another by walking, using our limbs as the instru- ment for this purpose. In the efforts for mental change we may perhaps be conscious of using the material organism of the brain as an instrument, but if so, as this occurs in every kind of effort, it furnishes no means of distinguishing the efforts from each other. Perhaps we only resort to the organic brain as a means of exciting sensations in the mind, which we use, as we use language, symbols, or counters, to condense and to mark the progress, positions, or relations of our ideas. If, as the phrenologists assert, we use different portions of the brain for different processes or objects, still these portions have been named from these processes or objects, and have not fur- nished the name for the corresponding efforts, and what they assert, if established, would not indicate different active agents or powers, but only that the same active agent in its different efforts uses dif- ferent organic instruments. NOTE IV. P. 16. In the first class of these cases, any effort of which we are con- scious is to comprehend the meaning of the terms, rather than to judge as to the truth they express when understood; but in the APPENDIX. 421 last case, the truth is no less really involved in the terms than in the others, but being less obviously so, effort is required to dis- cover it. If, instead of seeking to know the truth of the expression, that the angles of a plane triangle are equal to two right angles, we seek to find the measure of those angles, the case will more widely differ from the first class. The limit of simple perception, or of the capacity for perceiving truth without previous effort in arrang- ing our knowledge of the subject, varies not only in different individuals, but in the same individual at different times. If this capacity were infinite, the acquisition of any knowledge whatever would require no other effort than that of directing attention to the subject, and if the attention of a being of such capacity could also embrace all objects, every truth would be immediately appre- hended by it. Such a being would be, or at least could be, om- niscient. NOTE Y. P. 25. In regard to processes of thought, a question arises somewhat analogous to that hereafter suggested in regard to matter in motion, viz. : — Does it require an effort, an exercise of power, to continue or to stop them ? The mind is pursuing a logical train, does it require. the exercise of the will at each step to advance it? or can it, by simple perception of the relations of the terms, anticipate the successive steps, and going on without any exercise of the will, re- quire such exercise to stop it at any point short of the final result of the argument, or of the mind's non-perception of any further results ? It is obvious that the simple perceptions of the mind at every stage of the logical process, whether such perceptions have or have not required a preliminary effort, have a determinate limit beyond which the mind has not progressed, and that it is here for the instant arrested till, either by its own effort or by some extrinsic power, the obstruction to its mental vision is removed, or such arrangements made of its ideas as will enable it to get another perception reaching farther into the subject. The perception is always immediate and instantaneous ; there is no momentum car- rying it beyond the point to which the mind actually sees. A gleam from truth may flash upon us and be immediately lost, requir- ing further search to find the gem ; and when found we may deem closer examination requisite to ascertain if it is pure and genuine. 422 APPENDIX. However this may be, it seems certain that the mind cannot direct- ly determine the successive steps by a mere act, or exercise of its will ; for these must depend upon the absolute relations which the mind perceives among the terms of the argument ; and hence, the result is not a product of the will, though the process by which the result is reached, or made palpable to simple mental perceptions may be, and generally is. So of those other processes of thought in which the mind examines and searches for truth without the intervention of words ; directly analyzing, combining and comparing the objects of its thoughts, as originally perceived or apprehended, in- stead of first putting them in words. The observed relations here, too, control the progress of the thoughts, and the final result is not dependent on the will. The only difference between the two cases is, that in pursuing the one, the logical train, the mind is directed to its conclusions by the relations it perceives among the terms, while in the other, it is directed by the relations it perceives among the things themselves. If we happen to see two fragile bodies moving rapidly toward each other in the same right line, we, — -with our past experience, may perceive, without any effort of will, that one or both will be broken ; and if we have in view the ex- pression x — 1 = 5, we may in like manner perceive that x = 6 ; and so of more complicated forms of expression. Though we may will to seek out the relations, we cannot by will change our per- ceptions of the relations which we perceive whether sought or unsought. They are real and immutable existences or truths which we cannot alter by will or exclude from our belief any more than on examining the subject we can by will exclude the results that 2 + 2=4, or that all the angles of a plane triangle are equal to two right angles. So far then as our knowledge is derived from sensation and from thought, the influence of our exercise of will is limited to the quantity of time and the amount of effort we apply to its acquisition ; and to a selection from among the various subjects suggested by external or internal agencies, to which this time and effort shall be directed. These questions as to whether an effort of the mind is required to continue or to stop its train of thought, or whether it can recognize certain consequences of its observations or certain relations of its thoughts without such effort, are really questions as to the limits of simple mental perception, and are APPENDIX. 423 still more analogous to those relating to sensation than to matter in motion. I see a tree and a stone before me without any effort. How far I perceive the relations of the two without effort maybe a question ; and so, also, it may not be ascertained how far the mind perceives the relations of its ideas or of its 'various knowledge without effort, and this is not essential to our inquiry. For this, the facts that we have some knowledge, intuitive or acquired, without effort, and that by proper effort our knowledge may be increased, are sufficient. We cannot by will vary the facts or truths as they appear to the mind, nor even wholly exclude them. To be able to vary them by will, would be but an ability to destroy our power to find truth. Mind cannot banish any thought or thing from it by direct effort or will, for to will not to think of or not to attend to anything is still to think of or to attend to it, and it is only by directing its thoughts to something else, that it can by effort get rid of its present thoughts or images. It cannot always avoid them. Other intelligences, infinite and finite, have, to some extent the power to impress their thoughts, their creations, upon us, whether we will or not. In regard to the power of the mind to control the results of its investigations, it may, perhaps, be urged that we will to examine only those facts and arguments which lead to the particular result which we wish to establish, avoiding those on the other side. But, in such case, a man con- scious of this cannot be said to have acquired any knowledge. He may be prepared to assume and defend a position, but the fact that he has intentionally made his examination a partial one for the very purpose of arriving at the particular result, and done so from apprehension that an impartial examination would not lead to it, is conclusive upon himself that he knows the result is not to be relied upon ; and hence, he must be in doubt as to the result,* or rather, just so far as he has interfered by his will, he has entirely failed to obtain any knowledge ; and, of course, the result cannot affect the "conclusion we have just arrived at in regard to the relations of will * This is probably the foundation of a not uncommon religious belief that, beforo we can know anything aright, the will must be brought into a state of subjection to God", that we must, in contemplating His manifestations become passive — become as a little child — which having formed no theory, and having no interest to pervert truth, pas- sively perceives and accepts the conclusions from observation and reflection, without any inclination or effort to mould them to its prejudices, pride of opinion, or interest. 424 APPENDIX. to our knowledge. What we have said on this subject is equally applicable to all our beliefs and opinions, of every degree of cer tainty or probability. "We cannot control them in the process of acquisition ; aud once acquired, they cannot be changed by our merely willing such' change. The opposite view that belief is de- pendent on the will seems to have led to honest persecution for opinions deemed heretical. NOTE VI. P. 25. As the mind cannot act except by exercising some of its powers? every act of mind is an effort or act of will ; and the phrases, acts of will, acts of mind, and mental action are really synonymous. If the mind is moved, except in or by the exercise of its own power, it must be by some extrinsic power, and so far is as passive in such movement as is the stone which is so moved. It is not itself then active, but is the passive subject of action. We may be moved by external agencies and in this be passive ; when we move ourselves we must be active and we have no means of moving ourselves ex- cept by act of will or effort. We are moved by distress to pity, without our own action ; the emotion springs directly from knowl- edge, which may have required no effort ; but when we would relieve that distress by any act of our own, we must will — make effort. In acquiring knowledge, — in learning what is — by simple mental perception, either of things or ideas, the mind may make no effort. But when it seeks by the exercise of its own powers to know something which it does not now know, or to do anything whatever to change the existing state of things — to influence the future — it must make effort, it must will ; and conversely, whatever is done without its effort is not done by it, but must be by some other power of which it can at most be but an instrument. The deciding and the willing of the mind are sometimes con- founded. The phrases decided to do and willed to do are frequently used as equivalent. This arises from a decision being, at least very generally, preliminary to an act of will ; but there are many decisions of the mind which involve no coexisting or subsequent act of will, as its conclusions in regard to abstract truths, or when it decides not to attempt any change, not to interfere by any exer- cise of its power with the course of events. In this last case, as the willing is the means by which we effect change, if the decision APPENDIX. 425 is the willing, we should have to say we willed not to will. There is a manifest distinction between the cases in which the decision is not, and those in which it is, attended or followed by some action to effect change. In the latter we are conscious that the decision is followed by a mental affection, which we term effort, and without which the effect, though we may conceive of it and view it as in itself desirable, would not follow. The decision is the final conclusion or judgment of the mind as to doing ; and when it has decided to do, it executes its decision, so far as it has power, by an effort. It does or tries to do what it decided to do. A decision or final judgment is but an addition to our knowl- edge, in some cases as to what already is or will be, and in others as to what is best for us to do. This decision or judgment may have been* an immediate perception, or it may have required a preliminary effort, but this does not conflict with the assertion that the decision is not the willing, but tends to confirm it, as knowl- edge, whether a simple perception or acquired by effort, is not an act of will. NOTE VII. P. 32. Professor Bowen, in his very able " Lowell Lectures," gives a negative reply to all these positions. He rests his conclusions on the premise that matter cannot move itself or direct its own mo- tion, which is also the basis of my reasoning, and I do not perceive that his reaches farther than mine, or proves that matter in motion may not be an independent cause or that it could not be used as an instrument to prolong and extend the effects of intelligent action. I much desired to make such proof, but found no way to do it. I desired it not ooly to simplify the question of free agency, but also to facilitate the proof that God still exists ; which we both treat as deducible from the proposition that matter has no causa- tive power. I may here further observe that the views I have advanced in Book IL, in regard to the law of cause and effect, and my inference, from the observed uniformity of things external to us, of a design in the Supreme Intelligence to provide for finite free agents, also closely resemble those put forth by Professor Bowen. My conclu- sions on all these topics having been reached, written, and dis- cussed with my friends, before his lectures were delivered, could 426 APPENDIX. not have been influenced even by the infusion and circulation of his views in the common atmosphere of thought, and hence are entitled to that greater consideration and credence, which are properly accorded to the concurrent results of independent mental action. NOTE VIII. P. 35. If bodies in motion produce effects on other bodies by imping- ing against them, it must be by giving motion to those at rest, or by stopping, retarding, accelerating, or changing the direction of those in motion ; and if moving bodies strike on opposite sides of a body at rest, it cannot move both ways at the same time ; and hence, a loss of some of the power of matter in motion. If bodies impinge with equal aggregate force on opposite sides of the same body, then the motive power of all such impinging bodies may be destroyed and no new force is communicated to the inter- vening body. If the bodies thus impinging either on an interven- ing body or directly against each other, are perfectly elastic, then so far as our observation informs us, they would acquire equal force in the opposite directions, and the result would be the same as though no body had intervened and no direct collision occurred except that the impinging particles would have exchanged with each other and each turned back on the lines on which, but for the collision, the other would have moved. But in case of such elasticity it is demonstrable that the impinging bodies must come to a state of rest, and being but inert matter, they could not put themselves in motion again. If, as is now asserted, the force of the impinging bodies, when they are arrested, is converted into heat, still that heat often as- sumes a passive form, as in coal, requiring some active cause to develope and make it efficient, and in this view the heat which is stored in the coal is but an instrument by which this cause makes itself effective. It matters little to our argument whether the active cause produces force by means of the heat reserved in the coal or by putting quiescent matter in motion. NOTE IX. P. 35. The apparent power of matter in motion to produce effects, of course without design in the matter, is probably the foundation of those notions of a blind chance in the succession of events, which, APPENDIX. 427 in some form or other, seem always to have had a place in the popular mind. Matter once put in motion by intelligence might, after it had produced all the effects intended, go on to produce other effects ; or before the completion of the intended effects, it might produce other effects which were not intended. These are said to come to pass by chance or accident, and though frequently used interchangeably, I think that in common discourse the former is more generally applied to effects without or beyond the scope of the design, and the latter to such as incidentally happen within it, and are either unexpected or counter to the design. NOTE X. P. 38. It is not necessary to suppose that this energy is really con- stant everywhere. If all changes in matter, and all activity within the universe of our knowledge, were suddenly suspended and to remain so for millions of years, as measured by something without that universe, and all simultaneously put in motion again, begin- ning where, or as, it left off, we never could know it. The suc- cession would be the same to us as if there had been no interruption. NOTE XI. P. 39. It is only by a figure of speech or, perhaps a contraction of language, that matter is said to do anything ; and the recent change of expression from " moving " to " being moved " is, so far, more strictly philosophical. NOTE XII. P. 43. This finite presence, or presence co-extensive with knowledge, answers all the purposes of spirit, for, if we exclude the phenome- na of the bodily sensations and muscular action, nothing is gained by our being actually moved in space ; and hence, so far as our spiritual nature is concerned, this finite presence of man within the sphere of what he actually knows is as perfect as the omnipresence of the Supreme Being in His infinite sphere of knowledge. Our limited, incomplete and fading knowledge in many things requires to be renewed and augmented by means of the senses which, for this purpose, must be brought within sensible distance of their objects. 428 APPENDIX. NOTE XIII. P. 47. It seems that by long dwelling on an idea, or from some excited or abnormal sensitiveness of the mind, it sometimes loses the power to change or annihilate its own creations, and they become to it as external realities, producing, if partial, monomania, or, if general, causing one species of insanity. NOTE XIV. P. 49. It may be apprehended by some that this ascribing all the crea- tive powers of Deity to man, in however small degree, may unduly arouse his pride and excite his presumption. If there be such a one, let him essay any comparison, even the most trifling. Let him observe yonder towering elm mirthfully rustling .its foliage as if titillated by the awkward attempts of its neighboring spire to appear graceful. Or first looking upon nature, — the great picture which God exhibits to us as His own creation, — turn from it to the most exquisite painting of a Claude Lorraine or a Salvator Kosa, perhaps grouping a few trees, a glimpse of water, a speck of green sward, floating clouds and dubious rays of sunshine, &c, &c, and in the comparison, the works of man, even those which, as the highest efforts of his creative genius, excite our profoundest admi- ration, will appear sufficiently Lilliputian, sufficiently paltry and insignificant, not to say mean and even ludicrous, to induce a be- coming modesty, to attemper his pride and humble all that is haughty and arrogant in his nature ; and in the comparison he may realize that there is something more than a mere abstraction in the mathematical dogma that no increase of the finite can alter its ratio to the infinite. He may here observe, too, what we have before intimated, that the conceptions of the human mind are more perfect, more Godlike, than the expression. For ourselves, we apprehend no evil tendency in the exaltation of man to the conscious dignity and responsibility of a being endowed with crea- tive power. We believe he is too apt to take debasing views of himself, to consider meanness and wrong as appropriate or necessary to his condition and attributable to the natural weakness and imper- fections of his being, rather than to his own agency, or his own neglect properly to exercise the powers he has at command. "We be- lieve, too, that it is essential to even an imperfect conception of any one of God's attributes, that we should ourselves possess it in some APPENDIX. 429 measure. "Without this, we have no means of estimating the vast difference, and can no more form even a remote conception of how much greater God is than His creatures, than we can tell the pro- portion between seven acres and three hours. The proper effect then of the finite mind having the same attributes, is to enable it to form more adequate conceptions of the Infinite and make itself more sensible of its inferiority; and if, as we have supposed may be the case, its efforts are made effective through the uniform modes of God's action, the finite becomes wholly dependent on the Infinite for the execution of its designs and for the effectiveness of its efforts; and these considerations, in this connection, are eminently calculated to inspire gratitude and imbue us with humility. NOTE XY. P. 58. As already remarked, a being, satisfied with things as they are, cannot be said to feel a want, and he makes no effort, he does not will any change. If he perceives that causes external to him are doing what he wants done without his agency, then, if his want is only to have it done or to know that it will be done, his want is gratified by perceiving that it will be done. But perhaps he wants to know that it is actually done by these external causes ; and to this end an effort of attention is still required to gratify his want. NOTE XVI. P. 61. Even in cases of instinctive action, though, for reasons hereafter stated, we do not have to seek for knowledge to apply, or even to arrange the order of successive efforts, still it seems impossible that we should conform our action to the perceived circumstances — to the occasion demanding such action — without some intermediate effort, however instantaneous it may be, the need of which effort, as already suggested, may be intuitively known. However this may be, we early learn the importance of considering the cir- cumstances before we yield to instinctive impulses, and of adapt- ing our actions to them, and thus are led to introduce conscious deliberation, either as a wholly new element or as an increase of one already existing, thereby changing the features or character of the action. 430 APPENDIX. NOTE XVII. P. 75. Conflicting Wants. — There may be conflicting wants between which the mind must decide. If, for instance, a man with only bread and water at command is both hungry and thirsty, he must decide which want he will first make effort to relieve. Or if, with the want to move out of some apprehended danger, there is co-existing the conflicting want of bodily repose, then he must decide between them by a comparison of his preconceptions of the future effects of his conduct. No matter how short the plan of action, or of how few steps it may be composed, he may make the comparison. Even if the conflict is merely between effort and repose, one of the preconceptions being then limited to the mere making of effort, if we perceive in advance that effort will be pain- ful or pleasurable, it furnishes a subject of comparison with the painful or pleasurable effects of not making the effort. It is conceivable that wem&y want not to make any effort, and that, under the influence of this want, we would not examine as to any effort required by any other conflicting want. This is equivalent to supposing that there is no want of change, or that the want of repose is a conflicting and, in the view of the mind, a permanent want. If, with this supposed and eventually paramount want not to act, there is a co-existing, conflicting want, the mind must recognize it, for that which is not recognized by the mind cannot be its want. It cannot then shut out the presentation of the question, or the petition of its other want ; * and its subsequent non-action is proof that it has decided upon it. It is, however, doubtful whether we can ever properly be said to have a want not to act. We may want to make effort, but there are distinctions between the want to make effort, or the want of effort, and the effort itself. In the first place, the distinction be- tween the want and the thing wanted ; and in the second place, that between the want of effort generally and a particular effort ; we may be disposed to effort and yet some particular efforts be undesirable, and even with this want of effort generally, any par- ticular effort not yet made or determined must be a preconception * The popular idea that the right of petition should be utterly inviolable seems thus to have its origin in the lowest depths of the constitution of our spiritual being. It might be curious to trace out the analogy of its association with the idea of liberty, in its metaphysical and in Its political relations. APPENDIX. 431 and not a want. Hence, it can never in the first instance be a con* flicting want, bnt only one of the modes of gratifying our want of effort, and as such, as just intimated, may come into comparison with other preconceived modes. In other words, what may be represented in terms as negatively a want not to make effort, gen- erally is either the absence of all want, or the presence of the positive want of repose. In the one case there is no disposition or indisposition to effort, and in the other, any such indisposition arises from a preconception that the effort if made will conflict with the want of repose ; and hence, is not the means to be adopted to gratify that want, and is subject to comparison with other preconceptions of the effects of not acting. The forming of the preconceptions of the effect of acting or not acting is itself, for the time being, action ; and if with the want of repose a con- flicting want is actually presented to the mind, it must decide upon it, at least so far as to dispose of it by considering its merits, or deciding not to consider them. In the wants of activity and repose we have the last analysis of wants, and here find elements which enter into all our precon- ceptions for the gratification of other wants. The pleasure or pain of the particular effort,with its anticipated consequences, enters into the comparison of different modes of action. If, when wanting re- pose, the pain of effort itself, as perceived in advance, either from its proximity or other circumstance, appears greater than the anticipa- ted or apprehended painful results of not acting, or even just equal to them, no further effort than that required to ascertain this fact will be made. So, too, if, when wanting activity, the pleasure of effort itself appears to be just balanced by the anticipated conse- quent pain of acting, or by the pleasure expected from not acting, no effort will be made. It is then as if the mind had no want to do, and it will not do. In such cases, though it may still know and enjoy or suffer, it is but the_passive subject of changes in its own sensations, produced by other and extrinsic causes in which itself had no agency. From this inert or passive state the mind is aroused to effort by want, which may occur and recur without any antecedent effort ; and then by means of its knowledge, which also may exist without antecedent effort to obtain it, can direct its effort intelligently. 4:32 APPENDIX. NOTE XVIII. P. 88. By memory of a continuity of those changes in our sensations, the sense of identity might still be preserved, even though the will and all its pre-requisite processes of thought were annihilated. "Without will, we might still know ourselves as the subjects acted upon, but could never know ourselves as cause. If this view is correct, the personal identity does not of necessity inhere solely in the will. NOTE XIX. P. 101. If our first parents had no knowledge of good and evil, in any sense, 1 they must have been in constant communication with God, and as immediately directed and governed by His will as mere matter is. NOTE XX. P. 109. These views are in harmony with one indicated in the last chapter, that deliberation is superinduced upon some more primi- tive mental processes. NOTE XXI. P. 115. Many brute animals do not know enough to flee from a fire. The horse will not leave his stall, though the stable is burning about him. "We might suppose him palsied by terror ; but if forced away he runs back again. It seems to be a voluntary act, founded on the association of safety with his stall. Children, when frightened, will in like manner run into danger to seek refuse in their mother's arms. 'o v NOTE XXII. P. 116. There is no doubt that the intuitive knowledge varies very materially in different animals ; and there is, at least, some ground for supposing that it varies also in the individuals of the same species. It seems, however, certain that in all not higher in the scale of intelligence than man, voluntary action has always its base in the instinctive, though the superstructure which constitutes the plan of action may be wholly rational. This appears from the consideration that the immediate object of every act of will is to produce muscular or mental activity, for which we APPENDIX. 433 only know one mode, and that intuitively, and hence such action is always in itself instinctive. The difference between the instinctive and the rational is not in the knowledge of the mode of acting, but in the mode by which we came to know the order of the suc- cession of our acts to reach the end sought. In regard to the difference in the intuitive knowledge of indi- viduals of the same species it may be remarked that it is not only conceivable, but is matter of common belief, that the natural cal- culators, as the term implies, have an intuitive perception of the relations of numbers, or, at least, an intuitive knowledge of some mode of ascertaining such relation, through which they instinctive- ly reach results which others obtain in rational modes only by much time and labor. It is worthy of remark that those who exhibit this knowledge can give no more account of its origin, or even of their mode of obtaining their results, than others can give of their knowledge and modes in regard to muscular movements. If the natural calculator has only such intuitions as enable him easily to form plans by which, with very little effort, he reaches his results, his action is still rational. The amount of his knowl- edge, though it may enable him to make his plans more perfect and in less time, does not affect the nature of the act, which is still in conformity to a plan of his own contriving, using his supe- rior knowledge for that purpose. If he only adopts rules or plans which he finds ready formed in his mind, without any investiga- tion of his own, his action is instinctive. If he knows that, by looking for it in his mind, he will there perceive the result as a man perceives it in a table, without going through any process by any rule or plan, the action approaches as nearly as possible to that produced by an external power, — to mere mechanical action. But, as the action still requires an effort to apply the knowledge of this mode of obtaining the result, it is still voluntary and instinctive. So, also, of the natural bone setter. If he has by intuition such knowledge of anatomy as to enable him thereby to form Ms own plans, his action is as rational as if he had learned the same at a medical college. I speak of these phenomena as they exist in popular belief, and have not given to them the examination required to form an intelligent opinion as to their nature or existence. I will, however, observe that it only requires a modified form of one 19 4:34 APPENDIX. of our senses, an introverted sense of bodily feeling, to enable one to obtain through it, all, and perhaps more than all, the knowledge of the anatomical structure of the system, which can be derived through the sense of sight from dissection, or from the observation of prepared specimens ; and that it does not seem more surprising that some men should intuitively have a knowledge of the relations of numbers and the results of their combinations, than that an ani- mal, blindfolded and carried by circuitous and zigzag routes, should know the direct course back to the point from whence it started. NOTE XXIII. P. 116. Winking the eye when it needs to be moistened is probably in- stinctive. The infant knows when and how to do it as well as the adult, and apparently does it with as much facility. In the adult the attention and the effort required to do it being almost imper- ceptible, it is liable to be confounded with the involuntary and mechanical on the one hand, while to the more careful analyst it may appear not certain that it does not belong to the rational on the other. If we do not know that moving the lid will relieve the unpleasant feeling in the eye, we will not will to wink for such purpose, and if under such circumstances the lid moves, its move- ments must be attributed to some cause not of us ; and in such case, is as purely mechanical as the movements of the planetary system.* * The difficulty in applying conventional language to metaphysical inquiries is, perhaps, well illustrated by the fact that the distinction, apparently so broad and palpable as that between mechanical and voluntary, is really not well defined. In some connections the term voluntary would apply only to the volitions. But it has been transferred to the sequences of volitions ; and hence, we say the muscu- lar movement which we will is voluntary ; but, in cases of cramp, or convulsion, it is involuntary or not willed. If we conceive of matter as having been in motion from eternity, and as continuing and producing movements and changes of itself, then these movements and changes are undoubtedly mechanical ; but when such changes in matter are produced or directed by a voluntary agent, acting mediately or immediately, their character is more or less changed— we name them from ap- pearances generally — and when we do not recognize the immediate or present acting of a voluntary agent, we call them mechanical. But how close and how apparent the connection must be before the term voluntary is applicable, does not seem to be well settled. But all movements of matter must probably be referred to the will of an intelligent being ;. and if the universe is the material form with which the Infinite Spirit is associated, as the human frame with its finite spirit, the movement of a planet would, in this view, seem to be as much a voluntary movement, as the movements of our feet, when we will to walk. APPENDIX. 435 On the other hand, it may be said that if a finger is suddenly thrust toward the eye the mind may immediately perceive or judge that there may not he time to consider whether it will reach the eye or not. The injury might be done during the time re- quired to consider this ; and hence, it is at once obvious that to insure safety the act of winking must be immediate, without con- sidering any other plan, the future consequences of the action, or even the present necessity for it. Any confidence which we might on reflection have that the finger would not be thrust upon the eye, cannot avail, for the mind has not time to consider this fact. The danger appears imminent and the mind decides almost instant- aneously, but its decision may still be a result of the exercise of its rational powers in comparing, &c, or in seeking a mode adapted to the end sought, and, if so, its action by a plan founded upon knowledge thus acquired, or even upon knowledge now acquired by immediate simple perception, and not upon an innate knowl- edge of the mode, is a rational action. In further confirmation of this view, it may be said that if the finger approaches the eye slowly, it is not immediately closed ; but the mind then judging that there is time to adopt the usual precaution of examining the circumstances preparatory to action, does examine ; it deliberates as to whether it will be necessary to make any effort to avoid the finger, and if so, what effort. The action must then be in con- formity to its own plan, even though its knowledge of the mode it adopts is intuitive ; for the adopting of that mode is an exercise of its rational faculties, using the intuitive knowledge of the mode with other knowledge to form its plan of action with reference to a certain future result; and if, when the finger moves slowly, the action is a rational one, it may be difficult to determine at what particular velocity of the finger the action to avoid it becomes instinctive, if it ever does. But our previous reasoning would go to show that if an external object with the velocity of lightning flashes upon the eye, produc- ing pain or apprehension of injury, and we wink for its relief or protection, this may still be a rational action, though it may not be in time for the purpose intended. Whether the action be instinctive or rational, it may become habitual ; but if the former, nothing is perhaps gained by the 436 APPENDIX. transition to the latter, as it may be as easy for the mind to act from the original intuitive knowledge, the innate conception of the mode of relieving or protecting the eye by moving the lid over it, as from memory of the practice under the same mode, even after any number of repetitions. It is when we know of various modes of action adapted to the same occasions that habit lessens the time and labor of deciding by furnishing a mode before decided upon under similar circumstances. I have stated what appears to me to be the general rule of dis- tinction between instinctive and rational action. To remove some of the difficulties in applying this rule, to determine to which class certain actions belong, is perhaps rather in the province of the naturalist than of the metaphysician ; and by actual observation they may, perhaps, be able to determine whether the movement of the lid to moisten the eye, or to protect it from external violence, is, in either or both cases, instinctive. I would, further, here sug- gest the question, whether the intuitive knowledge of animals leads them to examine the surrounding circumstances before acting, and to conform their instinctive actions to them before they have learned by experience to do so ? Whether, for instance, if a kid's first want is to walk to its mother's breast, and water intervenes, it will walk into it, or around it, or not walk at all ? That there is an adaptation of the intuitive knowledge of the modes of instinct- ive action to the peculiar wants of the animal is obvious from numerous facts already observed, as that a chicken will not go into water, while a duckling will immediately embrace the first oppor- tunity of doing so. NOTE XXIV. P. 119. Though this distinction can be conceived of and expressed in terms, it is yet so slight as to raise a doubt as to whether it prac- tically amounts to anything. The difference in working from direct knowledge, or from the memory of that knowledge, may amount to nothing ; though working from a direct knowledge, or from memory of previous actions, conformed to that knowledge, may. NOTE XXV. P. 123. The influence of this saving of labor in the plan is evinced in the fact that when we have a plan ready formed, which may be APPENDIX. 437 worked in and made a part of the one now required, we will often use it, though we may know that in all probability less labor will be required to execute one entirely new. NOTE XXVI. P. 130. Some persons prefer to have these emotions excited without intellectual effort, as in games of mere chance; and those, who are absorbed by the labor of providing for physical subsistence, and who have no intellectual or moral wants demanding effort, may yet want a quasi exercise of those powers, which such wants would call into action, or want the excitement which usually attends such exercise. They may want to be aroused by effort, but, degraded by grovelling pursuits, or enervated by luxury, idleness, or dissipa- tion, do not want to make the effort. To such, if not controlled by humane feelings, exhibitions of bullbaits, cockfights, and gladi- atorial conflicts afford the required gratification without taxing their own powers. These views indicate that a popular passion for what we call the barbarous sports is not so much the result of that savage state in which the activities have full play in providing for personal defence or security and for the absolute wants of life, as of that highly artificial condition of society in which large portions of the community are overtasked in mere drudgery, and other large portions . relieved from the necessity of laboring for physical existence, without the substitution of intellectual or moral objects of effort. It is only one phase of sensualism. The Eomans, supported in luxury by their slaves and their conquered provinces, with the love of the coarse and intense excitement engendered in war, would, in times of repose, naturally resort to such exhibitions of effort, intensified to the sanguinary and violent. The rude Indian tortures his captive to increase his own security, or to re- venge the wrongs of himself or tribe, and not from that mere wan- tonness which is the product of a highly artificial and sensual con- dition of society. NOTE XXVII. P. 140. When the knowledge of means is intuitive, it is so closely asso- ciated with the want, that it is liable to be taken either for a part or for a necessary consequence of it, and thus the knowledge be confounded with, or attributed to, the want. 438 APPENDIX. NOTE XXVIII. P. 147. Logic. — The knowledge of abstract truth does not necessarily produce any want. It may itself be the object of an effort, which may end in gratifying the want which induced it — the want for some particular knowledge or truth. Hence, as a want is essential to voluntary action, a mere conviction of truth does not directly demand such action. A man does not will because he is convinced by demonstrative argument that the angles of a plane triangle are equal to two right angles. The fact may gratify a previous want to know, but does not of necessity awaken any new want. A pleasurable emotion attending the discovery of the fact, or the ex- ercise of his powers in making it, may induce a want for the repe- tition of such emotion, and corresponding efforts of the mind to produce it. A perception of some prospective application of such knowledge may also do this. So, too, if he is convinced that a certain act is right and proper, it does not influence his will, unless he wants to do what is right and proper. Touch his sensibilities by presenting to him distress, or so portraying it that in imagina- tion it becomes present ; enable him to participate in and to antici- pate the pleasurable emotions of relieving it, and a want to relieve is induced.* Hence it is that mere logical results, however high and holy the truths demonstrated, do not touch the springs of voluntary action. In following the demonstrative argument we but perceive the relations between the terms ; and before they influence effort, we must make an application of such results to actual existence and dwell upon the new relations evolved by the new results, till they take hold of our affections and assume some form of want. The logic which merely demonstrates, however clearly and forci- bly, the advantages of holiness, does not of itself move us to effort. * The high morality, the generosity of the act, in such cases, consist in his deriving pleasure from making others happy, or perhaps a higher morality, a purer disinterest- edness are evinced in his yielding to an instinctive or innate want to relieve distress without any conscious reference to himself, showing that he has not depraved his morel nature, but that its delicate sympathies make the sufferings of others his own ; and re- lieving it in others, a relief or gratification to himself; while the man who seeks out occasions for the exercise of such beneficent feelings, shows that he has cultivated this innate want and has come to want the occasions for exercising his generosity, or by vigi- lant examination to relieve himself even from the apprehension that there is some as yet undiscovered suffering requiring his action to relieve. APPENDIX. 439 For this there must he a want, and to excite such want in our moral nature, one magnanimous act, one exhibition of tenderness, one manifestation of self-sacrificing devotion to principle, one delineation of true, unselfish love, one image of a Eedeemer by pure and sublime ideas, so elevated above all vulgar passions and resentments as to look down with a divine love and compassion upon those who reviled and tortured Him, maybe more efficacious than all the calculations of utility which selfishness has ever sug- gested, or all the verbal arguments, which human ingenuity has ever devised. Hence religion, though she may stoop to meet the attacks of the sceptical logician on his own ground, has a more congenial ally in taste, which, in the moral as well as in the physical, is often a precursor and incentive to want; in the former generally applied to the more refined and cultivated wants of our spiritual being ; and the propagandist finds in the beauties of eloquent expression ; in the graces, or the sublimity of poetry ; in architectural gran- deur ; in lifelike delineations of reality, or of ideal conceptions on canvas ; in sculptured marble, cold and inflexible as logic itself, but still embodying some lofty conception, or some form of beauty ; a more direct and ready emotive influence to arouse the soul with a sense of its own sublime nature and inspire it with devotional feeling, than it can command from the most towering and most successful efforts of the intellect to demonstrate, in terms, the loftiest problems of humanity. Even in the concord of evanescent sounds, the soul finds an analogy, a moulding or shadowing to the senses, of its own har- monious variety, of its own aspirations, swelling into ecstasy in effort and smoothly subsiding into the luxury of contemplative repose. All these manifestations of art may fitly introduce and induce a want for the development and cultivation of those pure and elevated sentiments of which they but give the first suggestive taste ; * and those who have consecrated the power of genius to * I trust that I shall not be suspected of intending lightly to use this word — taste — in a double sense. To my mind there is a profound significance in such relations of a term as I have here attempted to shadow, showing how deep, in the common reason of man, the roots of his form of expression may lie ; and suggesting that, even if a merely arbitrary term is used, it is gradually fitted and jostled, by this common reason, into harmonious relations with a whole range of ideas, with only one of which, in its first 440 APPENDIX. the service of truth and virtue, have ever been assigned a high place among the benefactors of their race, while those who per- vert it to make vice fascinating and seductive, are justly regarded as vilely treacherous to God and man. "When, instead of the logical or prosaic mode of examining things by means of the relations of the terms by which we repre- sent those things, we look at the actual existences themselves as recognized by the senses, or as made present to the mind by the exercise of its poetic powers, the things are present, or by a scenic illusion appear so, and, in either case, any fact or relation, which does not harmonize with our views or feelings, presents a want of change to the mind for its action. We may remark that, as it is mainly by means of these same poetic faculties that the future effect of an effort in gratifying the want is made present, we here find the wants and the means of their gratification growing side by side in the same common soil. As before remarked, it is in the accuracy of the preconceptions of the future and a proper selection among them, that the mind manifests its ability in action; and hence, the poetic faculty, not only by its power to examine the relation of things as they pri- marily and naturally exist, instead of the relation of the artificial terms by which those things are represented ; but by its prophetic power of imagining, or conceiving of what does not yet exist, is really the basis of that common sense, which is so useful in the conduct of the affairs of life. He, who most clearly imagines, con- ceives, foresees the future, is, so far, best prepared to act wisely and sagaciously ; and, in this respect, the man who perceives has the advantage of him who reasons. The logician is proverbially liable to great mistakes in practical affairs, to exhibitions of a want of common sense ; but it is not so generally admitted that the poetic faculty corrects, or avoids the errors of the reasoning. It seems a desecration to put such noble endowments as our poetic and prophetic faculties to the vulgar, practical uses of daily life. It is taking the lightning from the skies to be the drudge of our workshops ; but this is analogous to the influence of electricity, much diluted, in many of the most common and sluggish changes of matter. adaptation, it had any perceptible affinity ; that this common reason perceives and marks in expression those delicate similitudes of thought, which the reasoning of the philosopher is Blow in developing APPENDIX. 441 NOTE XXIX. P. 149. I use the phrases u morally right " and " morally wrong." as applicable to the intelligent being that wills, and not to the good or evil effects of his action generally. Such effects may be injurious when the int-entions were most beneficent and morally right and good. NOTE XXX. P. 150. On forming Preconceptions and acquiring Ideas. — The forming of a preconception preparatory to action is generally a tentative process ; the mind noting what will be the effect of one plan of action, and then varying the plan to obviate some defect, or to ascertain if some other is not better. It may, however, some- times happen that the first plan so completely fulfils all the con- ditions required, that no further investigation seems necessary. When the same want has repeatedly existed under the same circumstances, the mind adopts a previous plan from memory and association and acts from habit, saving itself the labor of re- investigation. The investigation, by which the mind determines its preconception, is only one of the cases in which it applies the knowledge it already has to acquire other knowledge. In doing this, it adopts one of two modes. It may examine the facts pre- sented until it is enabled to determine the truth ; or, after a partial examination, it may form an hypothesis, which appears probable, or, at least, possible, and then examine whether such hypothesis is compatible with all the facts. In the former case, the mind does not seek to arrive at a particular idea, but to arrive at truth. In the latter, it seeks to ascertain whether the idea it has formed is true. If the object were merely to get a particular idea into the mind without reference to its fulfilling the conditions required in that idea, as, for instance, its being true, no effort for such object could be made ; for the idea must then be in the mind before the want of it could be determined, and the whole object of the effort would already be accomplished. The want of a particular, definite idea must be a want that is already gratified, and of course is no longer a want. No such want then can exist, and no effort found- ed on such want is possible. "We may have an idea, which we perceive is incomplete and not well defined, and want and make 19* 442 APPENDIX. effort to complete it, or to define it more accurately, that is, to get a more full, or more clear and definite idea of the subject. The mind cannot seek a particular, definite idea, or a particular, de- finite preconception ; but it may seek an idea, or a preconception, which will fulfil certain conditions. A man may want to -know what the truth is, without forming any definite idea as to what that truth is ; or having formed a definite idea of what it may be — an hypothesis — may want to know if his hypothesis corresponds with the truth. One, who can only count, will know that the product of 7 multiplied by 9 must be some particular number, as yet unknown to him. He wants to know, and, on a partial examination of the facts, he perceives that by the use of his knowledge of counting he can gratify this want to know the product of 7 by 9. He can count out seven piles, each containing nine pebbles ; or nine piles, each containing seven pebbles ; and then, counting the whole, arrive at a result without having formed any previous hypothesis as to that result. Here, however, are two preconceptions of the mode to be pursued, making seven piles of nine, or nine piles of seven, so obviously equal, that no one could anticipate which another mind would adopt, or which would be first perceived. The man may, however, — say for the purpose of forming some idea of the number of pebbles required, — prefer to carry his pre- liminary examination farther. In doing this, he may bring in his knowledge that, in counting, he advances by tens and goes over seven of these divisions of ten each in arriving at seventy ; and hence infer that 7x9, being less than 7 x 10, must be less than seventy, and that sixty-nine pebbles will be sufficient ; and, com- mencing now with this hypothesis, that sixty-nine may be the product of 7 x 9, he counts out sixty-nine and then makes the experiment to ascertain if he can get just seven piles, of nine each, out of sixty -nine ; and varies the number until he can do so. Though this is not one of them, there are cases in arithmetic and even in geometry, in which the best mode is to begin with an hypothesis and test its truth, or the degree of its variation ; and, in the affairs of life, it is generally prudent to test any plan or preconception, as we would a mere hypothesis. They admit of so great variety and the combinations are so numerous, that the application of general rules is not practically reliable. They more APPENDIX. 443 nearly resemble the variety and combination of the chessboard, in which it is frequently necessary to consider each of several possible moves and compare the preconceptions of the effects which we perceive would result. It is not unusual to aid these preconceptions by actually changing the place of the piece as pro- posed, and thus get, by immediate perception, what, without such move, is but imagined, or conceived. Persons sometimes, having a vivid conception of the object desired, act hastily to attain it, without having fully matured the plan of the successive efforts required ; and are liable to fail in consequence. Some requisite effort may not have been made at the right time, or in proper order, or may have been overlooked entirely. NOTE. XXXI. P. 155. There is no selfishness surpassing that of those who, having through life used all their means to obtain for themselves as much as possible of this world, at the last moment seek, by some judi- cious investment, to make them still available to obtain as much as possible of the next. NOTE XXXII. P. 155. Perhaps these views show the metaphysical root of the theo- logical and popular discussions as to.the influence of works. NOTE XXXIII. P. 158. These truths, vaguely existing in the popular mind, or applied with too much latitude, may have furnished a metaphysical origin for the doctrine of "perseverance"; and the same views, applied to the extermination of the wants morally good, seem to furnish a similar foundation for the belief that a finite moral being may sink to a condition of degradation from which he has no power to rise ; and from which nothing but a miraculous intervention of Divine power can elevate him. As above intimated, however, there seems to be good reason to suppose that these wants, especially those more elevated, are so rooted in our being, that they can be actually eradicated only with its annihilation ; that even in the lowest stages of depravity, the inferior wants may ever supply temptation and give occasion, on the one hand, for vicious action, or submissive indulgence ; and, on the other, for virtuous effort in 4:4:4: APPENDIX. resistance ; thus furnishing the means and inducement for still lower depths of debasement and for more hopeless habitual degra- dation ; and, at the same time, affording the opportunity for re- form, or for progress in virtue, to which all the higher aspirations of our nature will be incentives. To these, the Infinite Intelligence ever present and ever palpable in its effects ; and ever mediately, or immediately in communion with the finite, may add its Divine influence ; and even the aid of one finite being to another be not wholly unavailing in imparting knowledge and exhibiting moral beauty in action, and thus making it a want. NOTE XXXIV. P. 159. Intervals of such calm thought — of repose from the engross- ments and excitements of active temporal pursuits — have ever been deemed conducive to moral well-being, and, when occurring at stated times and places, and especially places set apart for this object, their influence may be enhanced by association and habit. We have stated times to gratify the want of food. NOTE XXXV. P. 165. Man, being constituted as he is, — being what our observation of his earliest existence shows him to be, — has the powers and faculties of a first cause. How he became such a being is not within the scope of our inquiry and is probably entirely beyond the reach of the human intellect. Our object is to show what he is, and what capable of, as he is, rather than how he came to be so. NOTE XXXVI. P. 171. I know a man, living on a very sterile tract, which to the most unremitted toil yields only a very meagre subsistence, but who, after considering a proposal of his friends to remove to a productive farm upon which much less labor would have given him abundance, said, " When I think how much work I have done on these gravel hills and stone walls, I cannot bear the thought of leaving them." He but expressed a common sentiment of man- kind, which is as potential in regard to the results of moral culture as of physical labor, and which has a specific influence in produc- ing consistent and persistent effort, and, of course, upon stability of character, giving to that which amidst adversity and temptation APPENDIX. 445 has been built up by effort, an additional advantage over that which, has resulted from opportune circumstances. NOTES TO BOOK II. NOTE XXXVII.* P. 201. Edwards adds, in a note, "I say not only doing, but conducting, because a voluntary forbearing to do, sitting still, keeping silence, &c, are instances of persons' conduct, about which liberty is ex- ercised, though they are not so properly called doing.' 1 '' NOTE XXXVIII. P. 241. This assertion and the necessary connection of effect with cause make everything necessary; for everything must be em- braced in what is necessary in itself, and what is not necessary in itself; and what is not necessary in itself must have a cause, and hence, as an effect of its cause, becomes necessary, so that what is necessary in itself and what is not, being both necessary, every- thing is necessary. NOTE XXXIX. P. 251. In the same way, there may be things relatively impossible to the finite intelligence, which impossibility, when perceived, pre- vents its efforts to do such things ; but when not perceived, has no such influence whatever, though the effort will still be unavailing and the expected effect will not follow it. NOTE XL. P. 255. It is, perhaps, worthy of remark that the existence and the nature of a finite line are co-existing and self-existing truths (knowledge), which the mind perceives as the reasons of the deter- mination or end ; as the preconception which the mind forms of the effect of its action is rather a reason, which it perceives for the determination of its act of will, than a cause of it. * The foot note on p. 201 refers to Note I. ; it should read Note XXXVil. 4:4t6 APPENDIX. NOTE XLI. P. 278. The wise, the prudent, the industrious, especially do this;— the foolish, rash, and indolent decide by virtue of their absolute power so to do, without examination. Most men, however, by experience, knowing its importance, do more or less examine, and the results of such examination form the reasons for further action or an addi- tion to those reasons, which were immediately obvious. NOTE XLII. P. If it could be shown that cause, or power to produce change, could thus be extended in time, only in the case of matter in mo- tion, and that it, by the changes which it produced, called on the active powers of intelligence as a dormant power, which must wait such opportunity to become cause ; then, matter in motion would become essential to the activity of spirit, not merely as something to be acted upon, but to enable intelligence to begin to act and to sustain its action even for a single moment ; and, in such case, the existence of matter as a distinct entity would be demon- strated, as also, that it must have existed and been in motion from eternity. NOTE XLIII. P. 332. If, as some suppose, the mind has other faculties, as reason, im- agination, judgment, &c, which act independently of the will, then, if such action influences the action of the mind, it is still the mind influencing itself. In the view which I have presented in Book I., Chap, iii., these supposed faculties are but varied modes of effort, or effort for varied objects ; and any exercise of them bear- ing on subsequent acts of will are but preliminary acts of will, de- termining the final act, which would be the mind's determin- ing the final act by its own preliminary act. In tracing back the series of such acts, we must eventually come to an act which was induced by a want and directed by the mind's knowledge, in the form of an immediate perception of the means of gratifying it. Such immediate perceptions, in the first instance, must be, and in most subsequent cases probably are, of intuitive knowledge, but may be of knowledge acquired previously, or at the instant. The known fact, most frequently, thus perceived and applied to direct an action, is that the first effort must be to examine the circum- APPENDIX. 447 stances which, as before intimated, is probably intuitively known. The application of this note to other similar arguments, in which the " other faculties of the mind " are an element, will be obvious without reiterating it. NOTE XLIV. P. 345. In the relation of knowledge to acts of will, it is not often ne- cessary to distinguish the innate from the intuitive, the important distinction generally being only between that which requires effort to obtain it and that which does not. In Book I., Chap, xi., I have argued that our knowledge that the mode of effecting movement in our own being is by act of will, must be innate. NOTE XLV. P. 365. It is not intended to assert that this knowledge of the fact of uniformity in many cases, may not be intuitive as well as acquired. It is certainly not an idea of universal application, for there are many cases of a frequent recurrence of the same thing, to which we never learn to apply it ; and the intuitive knowledge of the fact that in some cases there is a certain uniformity of antecedents and consequences, might be only an innate faith, that God had in such cases established, and would maintain such uniformity, which would be very different from an intuitive conviction that such uni- formity must exist as a condition of metaphysical necessity. NOTE XLYI. P. 379. Though this may be expressed in terms, it does not seem cer- tain that any such case can be conceived of as practically arising. It cannot occur in regard to the mind in willing, for there is always the alternative of willing or not willing any action. If one body impinges directly against another, there must be some effect (as the two bodies cannot occupy the same space, or one extension cannot possibly be two extensions) — non-effect, in this case, involves contradiction ; but there are still various conceivable effects, no one of which has been ascertained to be the one necessary effect to the exclusion of the others. The observed effect does in fact vary very materially. It is true, it varies only with varied circum- stances, as hardness, inertia, momentum of the impinging body or bodies, &c. ; and then, in reference to these circumstances, with a 448 APPENDIX. uniformity which has been well ascertained. But, that this or any other uniformity is of metaphysical necessity, that no power could have made it otherwise, has not yet been demonstrated. NOTE XLYII. P. 386. I have here intended to give all the scope and weight to the positions of Edwards which could possibly be accorded to them. Nor do I perceive that the admissions here made require any ma- terial modification. It may, however, be observed that, in the views I have presented in Book I., any intelligence may influence the volition of another by imparting knowledge ; but, as before shown, such influence is possible only because the volition of this other is free. This suggestion can have no place in Edwards's system, because he makes knowledge itself the volition, and we thus find that even this argument on the foreknowledge of God is obscured by the confounding of choice and will. If, however, a being has any intelligence of its own — any knowing sense — even its knowledge cannot be wholly controlled by extrinsic power. A man, with eyes to see and ears to hear, must of himself get some knowledge of the external, and with powers of thought must learn some relations of ideas, and cannot be made by extrinsic power to know or believe that 2 + 2=5. In virtue of his intelligence he is so far an independent power ; and though he may be indirectly in- fluenced by knowledge imparted to him, yet even in this he can- not be coerced or constrained. He may be convinced by skilful presentation of truth ; he may be deceived by ingenious falsehood ; and freely acting upon the knowledge thus acquired, his action may be different from what it would be if it had not been inculca- ted. "We may suppose the Supreme Intelligence to resort to the first mode, and by imparting truth influence the action of men, or, perhaps, justly withholding divine illumination, permit the perverse to believe a lie. The element of want seems to present another possible mode of influencing the human will. These, as we have before observed, are in the first instance constitutional, and can be cultivated only through the medium of knowledge, which would bring this mode in the same class of influences as that of knowl- edge itself; and if the constitutional w r ants are themselves altered by a direct application of power, this would be to change one of the constitutional elements of the being ; and either to partially APPENDIX. 449 annihilate the being, or add to it by a new creation, making a dif- ferent being, another free agent, whose acts might, in virtue of being free, be different from those of the former agent. In none of these modes, then, can the wills of finite intelligent beings be directly controlled even by infinite power or infinite knowledge ; and the prescience of God furnishes no reason to suppose they can be thus controlled. NOTE XL VIII. P. 396. "Without entering generally upon a subject for which I am wholly unprepared, I would here merely note the bearing which these views, and some others which I have before stated, appear to have upon the " Science of History." Such a science must have its basis either upon the idea that the events of the future are con- nected with those in the past, as effects dependent on antecedent causes which must produce such effects and no other; or on the supposition that the Supreme Intelligence brings about results in conformity to certain uniform modes or laws which He has estab- lished ; by the exercise of His power either making all other effort as nought, or so combining the element of His own action with other causes that the composition of the forces will produce cer- tain uniform results, or at least results which may be anticipated. In regard to the idea that the events of the future are a neces- sary consequence of those in the past, our previous reasoning would go to show that, if we eliminate the mere mechanical effects which may result from matter in motion, there is no such connection, and that to produce any such requires the action of intelligent cause. The events of the past have no present existence. They may be remembered by an intelligent being, but such memories are but knowledge of the past, which, like any other knowledge, enables such being to direct its efforts upon the future intelligently. The whole influence of such past is, then, through the volition of an intelligent being. Excluding at any moment the mechanical effects of matter in motion, the whole future must depend on these voli- tions, and the events and circumstances which have already trans- pired have no more tendency to extend themselves into the future than the wall, which the mason, by his own efforts, is raising brick by brick, has to build itself upward. The uniformity of the effects of matter in motion, whether as 450 APPENDIX. necessary consequences of motion, or a3 uniform modes of God's action, is established, and furnishes a means of determining from the past something of the future ; but this is limited to the mechan- ical conditions of the material universe, enabling us to anticipate the alternations of day and night and of the seasons — to foreknow the future positions of the planets, and thus to predict eclipses, transits, &c, and so far there is, and has long been, a Science of History. In regard to thus foreknowing the course of events, which, upon the principles I have stated, is the composite result of all intelli- gent activity, or of such results combined with the effects of mat- ter in motion as a distinct cause, grave difficulties present them- selves. If, as I have argued, God, as a necessity in providing for the existence of finite free agents, foregoes the use of His own power to control every event, and even forms no plan of particu- lars in the future, but is ever ready by His own action to modify the effects of the free and independent action of all other intelli- gent beings, then He not only does not foreknow the acts of these finite free agents, but He foregoes the prescience of His own actions, and the student who from past history should seek to deduce these particular future acts, either of the finite or Infinite Intelligence, would be seeking a knowledge which God has pro- scribed even to Himself. In any attempt to solve the problem of these particular future events, our data must involve the variable elements of innumerable free wills, each of which may be acted upon and affected by every other, leaving little hope of any solution as to the particular events of volition and their immediate consequences. If it be said that, amidst this almost infinite variety, God yet, by His paramount power, reconciles the divers influences so as to bring about a har- monious result, in conformity to some design which He has pre- formed, still the particular elements of the* combination, including His own agency in it, cannot be foreknown ; and in regard to those final or cyclical events, which make a part of this supposed pre- ordained plan, there is manifestly great difficulty. From examina- tion of the past we may learn such very general facts as that God is just, that He will punish iniquity, &c, &c, and hence draw very general conclusions as to His future action ; but this still gives APPENDIX. 451 little indication of the particular acts by which these ends will be reached, the time when, or even of the cyclical events by which His justice will be manifested, for there may be many events which so far as we can see, will equally answer the purpose. In this use of His power to do justice or punish iniquity we might expect, not a necessary repetition of former events, but the exhibition of action reaching the same end, making perhaps historic parallels, of which the events now transpiring in our country, compared with those which attended the exodus of the Israelites, when the Egyptians were afflicted with plague after plague, till they were made willing to let the bondsman go free, seem to be a striking illustration. Even in this case it is hardly conceivable that the events could have been inferred, with any particularity, from the past. Perhaps the nearest particular coincidence in this case is, that among those most immediately implicated in the wrong of slavery, it is now asserted that there is hardly a family in which the strife has not brought a death, and then " there was not a house in which there was not one dead." The plague of the locusts devouring the pro- ducts of labor, is easily typified among either of the belligerents and perhaps the rod — the law intended to preserve peace and maintain order and justice — was cast down upon the ground and converted into a venomous reptile, in that opinion of our highest judicial tribunal in which it was asserted that, by our fundamental law, as originally intended by its framers, and as it must still be construed, a whole race of men and women had no rights which others were bound to respect. Yerily, if such had become our settled principles, there was little reason to expect that the aveng- ing arm of Him whose ears are open to the moan and the prayer of the weak and the oppressed would long be stayed. Such events may indicate general rules or uniformity in God's action; as that the violence and injustice of a people shall react upon themselves, but still throws little* light upon the particular modes by which the uniform results will be accomplished. Take for instance, as recorded, the most notable event of His special action since the creation of the world — the destruction of our race because of their sorruption. Even supposing that, on a recurrence of such corrup- tion, God would, as an act required by perfect justice, again depopulate the earth, He might still do it by other modes, as fire, 452 APPENDIX. famine, pestilence or war. So far, indeed, from our being able from the past to infer that the recurrence of such corruption would be followed by another destroying flood, we cannot even infer that destruction in any form would be resorted to. If there is no change in God, there may be such change in His creatures as will be to Him a reason for a different course of action. Once, among us, the scourge and the gallows were deemed the proper antidotes for depravity ; now milder means, with the school and the lyceum, are relied upon, and this change in our views — in our appreciation of means — may be a reason with God for adopting another mode in which He may correct moral evil by imparting more knowledge to the transgressors, and, in case of a resort to miracle, instead of flood or flame, increase the knowledge of our race, either by His own immediate revelations to all, or by inspir- ing some portion to teach new and elevating truth ; or by sending a special agent with extraordinary or even miraculous power to perform this office. On the grounds I have before suggested, such resort to miracle can seldom if ever become a necessity. Among the prominent difficulties which, in the views I have presented, would appear to impede the Science of History, we have the great variety of events which may intervene between the great general results which mark the footsteps of the Deity in time, and which are perhaps required by His attributes ; the uncer- tainty as to the periods between such events ; and that there may be many such results which will fulfil the same intention. In a game of chess it may be pretty confidently predicted that a very skilful player will eventually checkmate one unskilled ; but through what particular moves, or how many of them, it will be done, no human being can prognosticate. If now we suppose that, instead of only one result, the object or end in view of the player is to produce either checkmate or stalemate, or some one of a thousand other conditions, the difficulty of foreknowing the final result is vastly increased. In chess the possible combinations are limited ; but by repetitions of them the moves possible in a single game are infinite. If we suppose the possible combinations of the position of the pieces to number a billion, then when a billion and one moves have been made we know that at least some one combi- nation has been repeated. If we assume an arbitrary limit to the APPENDIX. 453 number of moves in any game, then the variations which arise from changes in the order of the succession of the billion possible com- binations will also be limited ; and assuming this to be a trillion, we will know that when a trillion and one games have been played some one of the games has been an exact repetition of one of the others ; but who would essay the task to tell, in the first case, what move, and in the second what game, had been repeated ; and yet the attempt to conceive or to state the greater difficulty in foreseeing the results of the acts of innumerable free agents would in itself be bewildering. This main difficulty, arising from the variable element of free volitions, may be thus stated : Excluding, as before, the mechani- cal effects of matter in motion, the events of the past have no power to generate the future ; but that future is the result of in- telligent power manifested in efforts or acts of will. Intelligence} thus acting, is a cause which does not, on a repetition of the same circumstances, of necessity produce the same effect, or repeat its own action, but may, in such recurrence, try a new mode, produc- ing a different effect. The influence of this variable element of will is further complicated by each individual acting in reference to what he perceives others are doing, or are expected to do, so that the action even of the Supreme Intelligence may be modified by the action of inferior intelligences, down to the lowest in the scale, and may thus be influenced to elect one rather than another of divers cyclical events, any one of which will fulfil His main design. It must also be borne in mind that the object of every effort is to produce an effect in the future, and change that course of events which, but for such effort, would be established by the influence of other causes ; and that efforts which at the time ap- pear to be of little moment often lead to very important consequen- ces. These difficulties appear formidable, leaving little hope that the study of the history of the past will enable us to indicate even any great results by which God, in the exercise of His overruling power, at periods to us uncertain, corrects the aberrations pro- duced by finite efforts, and in the main conforms the course of events and the government of the world to His own attributes. On the other hand, there is encouragement for the prosecution of this lofty science in the fact that every being that wills must have 454 APPENDIX. some perception of the future in which there is at least sufficient probability of truth to be the foundation of its action, affording a hope that this prophetic power may be largely increased by study and cultivation. It must not, however, be overlooked, that the probability that the future will conform to our anticipations of it decreases so rapidly, as we increase the distance in time, that our prophetic vision can reach only a very little way into futurity. As favoring the pursuit of this science, I may also refer to the posi- tion which (in the text) I have just attempted to illustrate, that God may govern the world and provide compensation for all the aberrations of finite wills without departing from general rules or uniform modes of action ; and to the previous positions, that, being * perfect in wisdom, His actions, under the same circumstances, will be free from the mutations which attend the experimental efforts of less intelligent beings, and that even the imperfect wisdom of finite free agents leads to a partial uniformity in the actions of the individual, while similarity in the natural wants and intuitive knowledge, and identity in the absolute truths from which we de- rive our acquired knowledge, tend to produce a corresponding similarity in the actions of different individuals. These tenden- cies to uniformity encourage the hope that some law or mode of God's action, analogous to that which assures the stability of the material universe, may, within certain limits, regulate the succession of events in the moral. We may also note, that though, in some aspects, the ability which each one has to influence the action of others complicates and obscures the future, in another view it aids us to anticipate it. Our power to influence a future event is so far a power to foreknow it. When the efforts of a large number of persons are directed to the same end, the probability that this end will be accomplished is increased. When these efforts are intend- ed to influence the volition of numerous individuals, though no one can foreknow the effect upon any particular one of them, the probabilities are that, for reasons just stated, a large number will be similarly influenced, and, if the efforts have been wisely directed, that the desired result will be reached. In individual action each adopts the mode which his own knowledge, derived in great meas- ure from past experience, suggests. This leads to diversity of action ; and combined action requires a common reason, or at least a common APPENDIX. 455 ground for action, and this can often be fonnd in that common or general experience of which history is the record. Hence the ob- vious application of this science to the enacting of public laws. In those efforts by which we do our part in creating the future, what we most immediately and pressingly want to know is, what next to do, and the farther we can clearly trace the consequences of our efforts, the better are we prepared to decide what to do. It is evident, however, that in tracing out the consequences of an action in all its subsequent ramifications, the problem as to what is best to be done soon becomes so complicated that the time for action would pass before we could thus decide what to do. -^ It seems, however, at least probable, that the more systematic study of the past may enable us better to perform our parts in cre- ating the proximate future, may expand our knowledge of the ways of God, and increase our faith in His attributes, and at the same time lead us to some very generic ideas of the modes in which He manifests these attributes in His government of the world ; and these are objects well worthy of our highest efforts. In nearly all our efforts to acquire knowledge, our aim is to find out God's ways, and read His character in His works. The ideas above alluded to, and inculcated, in various parts of this work, that in our humblest efforts we are co-workers with God, taking part with Him in the creation of the future, and that our ways change His ways, may to some appear irreverent, and even arrogant, but they seem to me to furnish the only rational ground for hope in effort, or trust in prayer, and that by exclud- ing them we would make our noblest efforts and holiest aspira- tions the merest mockery. However hallowing and consoling the reflex influences of devout prayer may be, the belief in a system which would exclude us from all influence upon the future, either by our own direct efforts or by petition to the Sovereign power, making us but the subjects of a rigid and inexorable despotism, frould degrade humanity and involve all the evils of fatalism. 1*77 6 1 Deacidified using the Bookkeeper process. Neutralizing agent: Magnesium Oxide Treatment Date: Nov. 2004 PreservationTechnologies A WORLD LEADER IN PAPER PRESERVATION 1 1 1 Thomson Park Drive Cranberry Township, PA 16066 (724)779-2111 LIBRARY OF CONGRESS 013 410 298 6