■ ■Kstfii una Bfi MM mm WB8SS899IA Hi HA Copyright N?_iil/ COPYRIGHT DEPOSIT. *J THE ELEMENTS or INTELLECTUAL SCIENCE. A MANUAL FOR SCHOOLS AND COLLEGES. ABRIDGED FROM "THE HUMAN INTELLECT." By NOAH PORTER, D.D.,LL.D. PBESIDEJCT OP YALK COLLEGE NEW YORK: CHARLES SCRIBNER & COMPANY. 1871. ^ Entered according to Act of Congress, in the year 1871, by CHAS. SCRIBNER & CO., In the office of the Librarian of Congress, at "Washington. JAS. B. RODGERS CO., JOSEPII J. LITTLE, ELECTBOTYPEBS, PBIHTl B, PHILADELPHIA. los to 114 booster St., N V PEEFAOE. In accordance with the wishes of many instructors and friends of education, the author has prepared an abridged edition of his work entitled, The Human Intellect, which was first published in 1868. In doing this, he has retained all the leading positions of the original work, with many of the illustrations, occasionally condensing the language, and not infrequently changing the order and method of the argument. Many important topics, less adapted to an elementary work, have been omitted altogether. The con- troversial and critical observations, have to a large extent been dropped, or greatly abridged. The historical matter has been in part retained, so far as seemed appropriate to a strictly elementary manual. In order, however, to meet the wants of schools, as well as of colleges, some of the matter which is less adapted to beginners, has been printed in smaller type. This may be reserved for a review, or omitted altogether. The author did not feel at liberty, however, to forego for the sake of beginners, a thorough discussion of the important speculative questions which occupy the concluding part of the treatise. For the con- venience of those teachers and pupils who may wish to IV PREFACE. consult the larger work the leading divisions and titles in both volumes are the same. With many thanks for the favor with which the previous treatise has been received, this manual is now offered to the public, and especially to teachers and pupils in schools and colleges. K P. Yale College, July, 1871. TABLE OF CONTENTS. INTRODUCTION. PSYCHOLOGY AND THE SOUL. PAGE I.- -Psychology Defined and Vindicated 1 § 1. Psychology and kindred terms. § 2. Psychology is a science. § 3. Its relations to physiology and anthropology. § 4. Its phenomena known by con- sciousness. § 5. Its phenomena impel to scientific study. £ 6. Value of Psy- chology. It promotes self-knowledge and moral culture — Disciplines to moral reflection. § 7. Trains to the knowledge of human nature. § 8. Is indispensable to educators, g 9. Disciplines for the study of literature. § 10. Psychology the mother of the sciences which relate to man. § 11. Its special relation to logic and metaphysics. § 12. Is a discipline to method. II. — The Eelations of the Soul to Matter. . . 11 § 13. Psychology is a branch of physics. § 14. Reasons why its facts are at first distrusted by the student, § 15. Material phenomena are the earliest known. § 16. Materialistic misgivings and impressions. § 17. These should be set aside. In what way. § 18. The arguments of the materialist. (1). The soul is con- nected with a body — 2. The soul is developed with the body — 3. Is dependent on the body for its knowledge and enjoyment — 4. Also for its energy and activity — 5. It terminates a series of material existences — The conclusion of the materialist. § 19. Counter arguments. (1). Its phenomena are unlike material phenomena — 2. The soul distinguishes itself from matter — 3. The soul is self-active — 4. Is not dependent on matter in its highest activities — 5. Gradation of existence does not prove the soul to be material. \ 20. The phenomena of the soul real. § 21. Phe- nomena of one sort cannot be judged by those of another. § 22. The phenomena, and language in which they are described. § 23. Misleading influence of lan- guage. III. — The Faculties of the Soul 24 § 24. Question concerning the faculties. § 25. Faculties not parts or organs — Each faculty does not act at a separate time. £ 26. States of the soul are like and unlike one another — Their elements are like and unlike in quality — They are V VI CONTENTS. dependent on one another — One element is preponderant in each state. § 27. Faculty defined. General authority — Special authority. § 28. These faculties common to all men. § 29. The faculties not independent of one another. § 30. The unity of the soul — Different kinds of unity — Psychical unity is the highest of all. § 31. Unity does not exclude complexness. $ 32. Powers of the soul, threefold. § 33. Faculty, power, capacity. § 34. Function, state, phenomenon. IV. — Is Psychology a Science, and what are its Prin- ciples and Methods? 34 § 35. Materials of psychology; It is an inductive science, and the science of induction. § 36. Some hold psychology too vague to be a science. § 37. The materialistic view of psychology. § 38. The cerebralist theory, g 39. The phrenological theory. § 40. The Associationalist theory — Usually materialistic. \ 41. Metaphysical or a priori Psychology. THE HUMAN INTELLECT: ITS FUNCTION, DEVELOPMENT, AND FACULTIES. A preliminary chapter 42 § 42. Knowledge defined. What is it to know ? § 43. The process which pre- pares objects of knowledge. § 44. To know, implies the certainty of being. § 45. Also the reality of relations, $ 46. When is the process of knowledge com- plete ? § 47. The act of knowing is diverse in its energy. Attention. § 48. The psychological and logical relation of processes and products — The critical, or speculative, application of knowledge. § 49. Order of intellectual develop- ment, growth and studies. § 50. Principles of classifying the powers of the in- tellect. § 51. The presentative faculty. § 52. The representative faculty. § 53. Thought, or intelligence — Two aspects or forms of thought. CONTENTS. Vll THE HUMAN INTELLECT. PAKT FIRST. PRESENTATION AND PRESENTATIVE KNOWLEDGE. PAGE I.— Consciousness — Natural Consciousness. . . 61 § 54. Consciousness denned. Variously applied. § 55. Two forms of con- sciousness. § 56. Natural consciousness as an act. § 57. Consciousness the ob- ject. \ 58. Relation of consciousness to each of the elements of a psychical state. g 59. The activity may be chiefly noticed. § 60. Consciousness of the ego. $ 61. The relation of consciousness to the objects of psychical activity. $ 62. The object of consciousness is a state of being — Special sense of cogito, ergo sum. § 63. The validity of relations is also established. § 64. The development and growth of consciousness. § 65. Latent modifications of consciousness. II. — The Reflective, or Philosophical Consciousness. . 78 § 66. The reflective consciousness defined — The abnormal consciousness in children and adults — The ethical consciousness. § 67. The scientific reflective consciousness. Characterized by persistent attention. § 68. It attends to all the psychical phenomena. § 69. Compares and classifies them. § 70. Interprets and explains them by powers and laws. § 71. Relations of the philosophical to the natural consciousness. § 72. Office of language in respect to each — The language of common life sometimes the most trustworthy. § 73. The actions of men also an important test of truth. § 74. Conditions of reaching the decisions of con- sciousness. § 75. Uncertainty and slow progress of psychology explained. § 76. Peculiar difficulties in the study of the soul. III. — Sense-Perception: The Conditions and the Process. 93 § 77. Sense-perception defined and distinguished — Is developed earliest of all the powers — Seems to be the most familiar. Is not the most easily understood — Distinguished from other mental acts — Knowledge of matter not gained by sense- perception — What are acts of sense-perception ? — Knowledge that is gained by sense-perception — Results of analysis. Eight topics proposed. § 78. The con- ditions enumerated. The first condition — The nervous system. The sensorium — The reflex action of the nerves. § 78 a. The second condition is an object or ex- citant. § 79. The third condition. Its action on the sensorium. g 80. The process of sense-perception in the simplest form; what is it? — It is psychical, not physiological — It is complex of two elements — The elements unequal in energy; in the same, and the different senses, g 81. Sensation proper pertains to the soul. # 82. Yet experienced by the soul connected with an organism. § 83. The sensa- tions localized. § 84. Differ from one another in quality and definiteness. § 85. Vlll CONTENTS. Perception proper, an act of pure knowledge. § 86. Its object a non-e^o. What kind of a non-ego. £ 87. An extended non-e^o. § 88. Perception attends all the sensations — The extension and externality of all objects not given with equal clearness, g 89. The varying relations of sensation and perception proper — In different sensations of the same sense — In the different senses. IV. — Classes of Sense-Perceptions 109 § 90. Three classes of sense-perceptions. The muscular. § 91. The organic. § 92. The special sense-perceptions. Smell; its organ, conditions, and objects. § 93. Taste: organs and objects. Variety of the sensations. § 94 Hearing; its organ and objects — The sensations various. In what respects distinguishable — Sounds in succession and combination. Melody and harmony — The condition of oral language. Expressive of feeling. \ 95. The sense of touch. Its organ — Essential condition of touch. § 96. Variety of sensations involved in touch. Sensations of gentle touch — Sensations involving violence or injury — Sensations of temperature — Sensations of pressure and weight — The muscular sensations — Sensations localized. § 97. Perceptions proper of touch — Extension perceived by touch. Not explicable by extension in the organism. \ 98. The perception of externality by touch — Two meanings of externality — Externality in the first sig- nification — Objection answered. $ 99. Sense of touch the leading sense — Fur- nishes intellectual terms. § 100. Sight; its organ and the conditions of vision — Function of the image on the retina — Sensations proper of vision. § 101. Per- ception proper in vision. The object of vision — Is always extended — Visible ex- tension superficial only — A single object seen with two eyes — Original place of the visible percept, g 102. Dignity of the eye. V. — The acquired Sense-Perceptions 132 § 103. The sense-perceptions, as original and acquired — Importance and time of gaining the acquired perceptions. § 104. The acquired perceptions of smell and hearing. § 105. Acquired perceptions of sight. Distance judged by size — Judgments of magnitudes by distance — Judgments of distance by color, outline, clearness, etc. — Judgments of size by other equidistant objects — Influence of In- termediate objects. § 106. Judgments of form, etc., by sight. $ 107. Acquired sense-perceptions of place, motion and expression within the body — The provi- sions of nature for these ends — The control by the intellect of these arrangements — How we learn to talk and to walk — Feats of dexterity. Expressional effects. § 108. The errors of the senses explained. $ 109. The acquired perceptions as forms of knowledge — They involve induction — Objections from the cases of ani- mals — Reasons why the perceptions of animals and of man should differ. VI. — Development and Growth of Sense-Perception. . 150 g 110. Nature, interest, and difficulty of the problem. # 111. The intellect, condition of the, before sense-perception begins — The beginnings and development of attention. § 112. The order in which the perceptions are developed. § 113. The development of touch — Hamilton's theory of the perception of the extra- organic. § 114. Development of vision, g 115. Combination of touch and vision — Observations upon infants. # 116. The blind from birth, upon the recovery of sight. CONTENTS. IX PAGE VII. — The Products of Sense-Perception; or, The Per- ception of Material Things 165 § 117. Material things and sense-percepts. $ 117 a. The first stage of percep- tion j limited to coincidence in space and time. $ 118. The second stage : The relation of substance and attribute — This relation supposes reflex and indirect knowledge. $ 119. The conditions of complete perception. § 120. Can we attend to more than one thing at a time ? VIII. — Activity of the Soul in Sense-Perception . . 180 § 121. Sense-perception held by many to be passive only — Grounds on which the theory rests. § 122. Evidence that the soul is active. § 123. Different modes of this activity — Is elementary, and easily exercised. Sense-Perception: Summary and Review. . . .187 IX. — Theories of Sense-Perception 189 § 125. Interest of the theories and their history. § 126. The early Greek phil- osophers — Aristotle. \ 127. The schoolmen. Their doctrine of species. $ 128. Descartes, Malebranche, and Arnauld. g 129. John Locke. £ 130. Bishop George Berkeley, David Hume. $ 131. T. Reid, Dugald Stewart, Dr. T. Brown. § 132. Sir William Hamilton. § 133. Immanuel Kant, and the German school. PART SECOND. representation and representative knowledge. I. — The Representative Power Defined and Explained. 206 $ 134. Representation defined and illustrated. § 135. Appellations for the power. § 136. Objects of the representative power. § 137. These objects involve relations. § 138. Conditions and laws of representation considered. $ 139. Representation divided into several varieties. $ 140. Interest and importance of the representative power. * • II.— The Representative Object — Its Nature and Im- portance. 215 £ 141. Why the object of representation needs special discussion. § 142. It is a pyschical object. § 143. It is a transient and short-lived object. § 144. It is an intellectual object. § 145. The relation can be compared to no other. £ 146. Representative ideas of objects of consciousness and sense-perception do not re- semble them. Memory. § 147. Positive characteristics of mental pictures. § 148. In thought, we prefer ideas to realities. $ 149. Ideas especially useful in com- parison and generalization. $ 150. Images prepare for and aid to action. X CONTENTS. PAG 9 III. — The Conditions and Laws of Eepkesentation — The Association of Ideas , 225 § 151. Association of ideas. Importance and interest of the subject. g 152. Laws of association. $ 153. Association not explained by bodily organization. § 154. The laws of association cannot be referred to any attractive power in ideas as such. § 155. Nor into the force of relations as such — Are not other relations supposable? $156. The law of redintegration. $157. The real expla- nation. How enounced — Associations with home. § 158. The secondary laws defined — How far reducible to the same principle with the primary. $ 159. Apparent exceptions to the law of association. $ 160. Representation unceas- ingly active. How it can be interrupted. § 161. Law of association and law of habit. § 162. Higher and lower laws of association. IV. — Representation. — (1.) The Memory, or Recognizing Faculty 254 $ 163. The elements essential to an act of memory. $ 164. Memory techni- cally defined. Relation of memory to representation. § 165. The spontaneous memory. $ 165 a. The intentional memory. § 166. Memory as the power to retain, and to lose. $ 167. Dependence on the body. § 168. Varieties of mem- ory; how explained — Development of memory. Its characteristics in the several periods of life. $ 169. The education of the memory. $ 170. The cultivation of the memory; mnemonics. V. — Representation. — (2.) The Phantasy, or imaging Power. . . . . . . . . . 278 \ 171. Phantasy defined and illustrated. § 172. The interest of its problems — The power of association is operative in them all — Deviations accounted for. (1.) By changes in the relative proportion of the powers. § 173. Sleep physiolog- ically considered. $ 174. Sleep considered psychologically. $ 175. Somnambu- lism, or abnormal sleep. $ 176. Hallucinations, apparitions, etc. § 177. Insanity. VI. — Representation. — (3.) The Imagination or Creative Power 295 $ 178. Conditions and materials common to the imagination. £ 179. Tho power of the imagination to create new products. § 180. The combining and arranging office of the imagination. $ 181. The idealization of tho relations of space and time in art, and mathematical science. § 1S2. 3. The formation of an ideal standard for psychical acts and states. $ 183. The imagination is capable of growth and culture. # 184. Is developed from the earliest till the latest periods in life. § 185. Special applications of the imagination. The poetic imagination. § 186. Its medium is language. £ 187. Tho philosophic imagina- tion. $ 188. The practical and ethical imagination. $ 1S9. Relation of the im- agination to religious faith. CONTENTS. XI PART THIRD. THOUGHT AND THOUGHT-KNOWLEDGE. PAGE I. — Thought-knowledge Defined and Explained. . .319 £ 190. Thinking and the thought power defined. § 191. Appellations for the power of thinking, etc. £ 192. Relation of thought to the lower powers. § 193. Concrete and abstract thinking. § 194. Relations of thought to language. II. — The Formation of the Concept or Notion. . . 327 § 195. The processes involved in forming the concept. § 196. The product, its nature and appellation, § 197. Concepts as concrete and abstract, as simple and complex; their content and extent. £ 198. Classification, its origin and different species. £ 199. How much do we gain by knowing by concepts. § 200. Relation of knowledge by concepts and by intuitions. III. — The Nature of the Concept.— Sketch of Theories. 339 § 201. The doctrines of Socrates and Plato, and Aristotle. § 202. Porphyry's questions and the scholastics. £ 203. Modern Philosophers — G. W. Leibnitz. § 204. G. W. F. Hegel. IV. — The Nature of the Concept. — General Names. — Language 45 § 205. Essential characteristics of the concept. § 206. How far the concep- tualist and nominalist are both right, £ 207. The imaging of concepts — Differ- ent images illustrate the same concept. £ 208. The truth represented by realism — The classifications of Botany. £ 209. Value of naming and of language. £ 210. The relation of symbolic to intuitive knowledge. V. — Judgment, and the Proposition 358 I 211. Judgment implied in the formation and use of the concept. £ 212. Judg- ments are psychological and logical — How the subject of a judgment is expressed in language. § 213. The Signification of the copula. § 214. Classes of judg- ments. Judgments of content. § 215. Judgments of extent. § 216. Scientific and common knowledge. VI. — Reasoning. — Deduction of Mediate Judgment. . 366 § 217. Nature and importance of reasoning. £ 218. Reasoning, inductive and deductive. § 219. The forms of deduction, g 220. The syllogism not a but the form of deduction. §221. The dicta or formula of the syllogism. §222. Deduc- tion rests on the relation of reason to consequent. § 223. The relation of logical reasons to cause and laws. § 224. Geometrical reasons. VII. — Reasoning. — Varieties of Deduction. . . 378 I 225. The varieties are three ; these subdivided. § 226. Probable reasoning. § 227. Mathematical reasoning, materials of. § 228. Definitions and axioms. § 229. The construction of geometrical figures. Auxiliary linos, etc. § 230. Xll CONTENTS. Geometrical reasoning explained by an example. § 231. Immediate syllogisms. § 232. Two elements in most acts of deduction. § 233. Deduction adds to our knowledge. In what sense ? VIII. — Inductive Seasoning or Induction. . . .391 § 234. Inductions properly and improperly so-called. \ 235. Inductions of common life and inductions of science. § 236. Why are the indications of science more difficult? g 237. The a priori relations assumed in induction. § 238. The three rules of induction. § 239. The conditions of a successful hypothesis and discovery. § 240. The choice between hypotheses. § 241. The place of experi- ment. IX. — Scientific Arrangement. — The System. . . 416 § 242. Scientific arrangement. System in its lower import. § 243. System in its higher significance. PART FOURTH. INTUITION. THE CATEGORIES. — FIRST PRINCIPLES. I. — The Intuitions Defined and Enumerated. . .419 § 244. The critical and speculative stage of our studies — They have been re- ferred to a separate faculty — The appellations by which they are known. $ 245. Not first in the order of time, but in logical importance — They are, in fact at- tained last in the order of time. § 246. Various significations of a principle. § 247. The relation of intuition to experience. £ 248. The Three Criteria of First Truths. $ 249. They are independent of one another — Hegel's development of the categories. \ 250. Divided into three classes. II. — Theories of Intuitive Knowledge. . . . 433 § 251. The theory of a direct mental vision of first truths. g 252. The theory that they are discerned by the light of nature. § 253. That they are innate or connate. £ 254. The views of Locke and his school. § 255. Dr. Reid and the Scottish School. § 256. Kant and his School, g 257. Hamilton's Positive and Negative Necessity. $ 258. The theory of Faith as contrasted with knowledge. I 259. J. G. Fichte. \ 260. Schilling's view of the categories. § 261. Hegel's theory of pure thought. § 262. Herbart's theory. HI. — Formal Relations or Categories. . . . 446 § 263. The category of being. — In what sense fundamental. § 264. The most abstract of all the categories. § 265. Is indefinable and indeterminate. § 266. Relationship. Diversity and similarity. — Relative notions. Negative notions. § 267. Substance and attribute formally conceived. £ 268. The logical axioms of idqntity, etc. CONTENTS. Xlii PAGE IV. — Mathematical Eelations: Time and Space. . 454 § 269. Development of the several relations of extension. $ 270. Duration, how related to the acts of the soul. $ 271. The mind discerns extended and en- during objects together. § 272. Limitations of sense-perception. $ 273. Beyond these we use the imagination. § 274. Measures of time-objects are imaginary. — Different capacities in different men. — Differences in the estimates of time. — Whence standards for both space and time are derived. § 275. How the relations of space and time objects are generalized. $ 276. Two classes of mathematical concepts. The geometrical. — Postulates of geometrical quantity. § 277. The concepts of number. § 278. The application of number to magnitude. $ 279. "Why, and how mathematical concepts are applicable to material objects. $ 280. Time and space relations can be still further generalized. § 281. Extended and enduring objects are limited. £ 282. Extension and duration distinguished from, but related to space and time. £ 283. They limit objects and events. £ 284. In what sense space and time are unlimited. £ 285. Space and Time cannot be generalized under higher concepts. $ 286. They are known as the conditions of their limited correlates. § 287. What are space and time ? Conclusion. V. — Causation and the Eelation of Causality. . 480 $ 289. Causation as a law, and as a principle. § 290. Event denned. \ 291. Cause distinguished from conditions. $ 292. The relation cannot be resolved into a time-relation. $ 293. The principle of causality intuitively evident. $ 294. Counter theories. The belief not acquired by induction or association. $ 295. Not resolvable into outward or inner experience, or both. Locke and De Biran. § 296. The theory which resolves causality into a relation of concepts. $ 297. Hamilton's theory of causation. — Conclusion. Our position re-affirmed. VI. — Design of Final Cause 498 § 298. Terms explained. Formal, material, efficient, and final causes. $ 299. Design and adaptation, how related. § 300. The relation assumed as necessary and a priori. \ 301. Reasons. The mind impelled to connect objects by this relation. £ 302. The relation is higher than that of efficient causation. $ 303. The principle has been of essential service in scientific discovery. $ 304. The foundation of the inductive philosophy. $ 305. Required to explain the pheno- mena of organic existences. $ 306. Relation of final to efficient causes in the higher orders of being. $ 307. Objections: (1.) Men mistake in their judgments about final causes. § 308. (2.) Our interpretations can neither be tested nor con- firmed. $ 309. (3.) This relation derived from conscious experience. — The rela- tion unquestioned in some applications. § 310. (4.) Two principles introduced into philosophy which may possibly conflict. § 311. (5.) The search after final causes has hindered discovery. $ 312. (6.) The adaptations of nature are only the conditions of existence. § 313. (7.) Adaptation is limited to organic exist- ence. § 314. (8.) We are not warranted in affirming it of all kinds of existence. § 315. (9.) Adaptation cannot be affirmed of an unlimited Being. $ 316. The principle is illustrated and confirmed by its application to metaphysics. § 317. Applied in geometrical construction and deduction. $ 318. Applied in geology, etc. £ 319. Applied in geography and history ; # 320. Also in comparative an XIV CONTENTS. to my and physiology. § 321. Applied in anthropology; — In the provisions for and the capacities of language, g 322. Application to psychology. $ 323. Ap- plied and assuumed in ethics. § 324. Application to theology. — The common argument for the Divine existence. VII. — Substance and Attribute: Mind and Matter. . 524 § 325. Uses and etymology of the terms. § 326. Substance and attribute in the abstract. § 327. Spiritual or mental substance. $ 328. Material substance defined. $ 329. Space occupation and identity of matter, g 330. The produc- tion of new substances. — The real Essence or Thing in itself. \ 33 1. A material substance not necessarily independent. — Dogmas that seem to deny permanence. § 332. The reciprocal relations of material and spiritual substance. — Mind and matter directly and indirectly known. $ 333. The qualities of matter as primary and secondary. £ 335. Real and phenomenal or relative knowledge. VIII. — The Finite and Conditioned. — The Infinite and Abso- lute 541 § 336. To know, a limiting process. $ 337. The finite universe ; how con- ceived, g 338. The import of the terms infinite and absolute. $ 339. The un- conditioned is the non-conditioned. — Applied to quality and quantity. £ 340. The absolute, several causes of. The Hegelian sense. § 341. What is not truo of the absolute, etc. g 342. The absolute, etc., are knowable. — Views of Kant, Hamilton, and Mansel. — Herbert Spencer dissents in part. $ 343. The absolute apprehended by the intellect. § 344. Not know exhaustively or adequately. — The finite universe infinite to our knowledge. — The absolute a thinking agent. § 345. Must be assumed to explain thought and science. INTRODUCTION. PSYCHOLOGY AND THE SOUL. I. PSYCHOLOGY DEFINED AND VINDICATED. § 1. Psychology is the science of the human soul. pg cholo The appellation is of comparatively recent use by and kindred English writers, but is now generally accepted as the most appropriate term to denote the scientific knowledge of the whole soul, as distinguished from a single class of its endow- ments or functions. The terms in frequent use — mental philoso- phy, the philosophy of the mind, intellectual philosophy, etc. — should be strictly limited to a single power of the soul, i. e., its pou hnoiv, and should never be extended to its capacity to fee and to will, or to all its endowments collectively. The terms metaphysics and philosophy, when used without an adjunct, can- not designate any special science, but only one which is general and fundamental to all the sciences, both material and psychical. § 2. Psychology is a science. It professes to exhi- bit what is actually known or may be learned con- Ps a 3 £en? e y IS cerning the soul, in the forms of science — i. e., in the forms of exact observation, precise definition, fixed terminology, classified arrangement, and rational explanation. It is the science of the soul; i. e., the science which has the soul for its subject-matter. Soul differs from spirit as the species from the genus ; soul being limited to a spirit that either is orlias been connected with a body or material organization ; while spirit may also be applied to a being that has at present no such connec- tion, or is believed never to have had any. The term soul originally signified the principle of life or mo- il 2 INTRODUCTION. § 3. tion in a material organism. It was especially appropriated to the vital principle which was supposed to animate the body, whether in man or the lower animals. This signification is appa- rent in the threefold division of man into body, soul, and spirit, in which the soul occupies the place between the corporeal ele- ment, and the spiritual. This intermediate part was sometimes called the animal soul, and was believed to perish with the body. Hence, the term spirit was applied to a nature that had never been fixed in a body, or soiled and degraded by connection with it. But in the New Testament, ' in general, and of the intellect in particular, as inconsistent with the essential unity of the soul, and as self-contradictory in both conception and statement. But Herbart insists most earnestly that the soul pos- sesses a capacity for self-assertion, and that these self-assertions vary both in kind and degree with the conditions which call them forth. His doctrine is not unlike that of Leibnitz respecting monads of all classes, and preeminently of tho conscious monads, that they represent or reflect all other objects, and that in this individual capacity lies their individual being. But diverse capacities for theso varying self-assertions, or, in modern terminology, for 'reactions,' involves all that is essential, and wo may add, all that is objected to in the doctrino of 'faculties;' the one being no more incompatible with tho soul's unity than is tho other. Herbart, moreover, affirms of the ideas — ' Vorstellungen' — all that ho denies to faculties, giving them the power to act and react on each other in such a variety of ways, and with independent energies, as to explain all tho varying psychical phenomena. While ho contends most earnestly that the soul is one — a monad without relations to space — ho makes it the theatre, literally the 'show-place/ of all manner of active and antagonistic agents, which arc evolved from its own being by tho objects that excito them. The associational and ccrobral psychologists reject tho doctrine of faculties as commonly received, and resolve all the operations and products of the soul into tho single power of association between its ideas, this being in their view the singlo function either of tho soul or its ideas, and that into which all its remain- ing powers and activities may bo resolved. § 34. THE FACULTIES OF THE SOUL. 33 § 33. We call these endowments of the soul facul- ties, powers, capacities, with some difference of mean- J C acif ' P ° wer ' ing and application for each. Faculty is properly limited to the endowments which are natu- ral to man and universal with the race. We also limit the term, by a sense of natural propriety, to those endowments which are especially spiritual, and which manifest the independent and higher energy of the soul. The word power is applied to the active properties of material objects, as well as to those which pertain to spirit. Originally it was employed by Aristotle in contradistinction to act. Hence, power and action are always contrasted, and beings are always contemplated by him as h duvdfj.sc and & htpyia. Force is quite as frequently used as power, of material objects and agents, and in the collective sense, the forces of nature are more frequently spoken of than its powers. When power is applied to the soul, it is used in a larger signification than faculty ; for by it we designate the capacities which are acquired, as well as those which are original. All men are said to be endowed with the faculty of memory. A few are said to have, or to have attained to, the power of remembering with surprising reach and accu- racy. All men have the faculty of sense-perception, but seamen gain the power of seeing objects at a very great distance. Capacity signifies greater passiveness or receptivity than either of the others. Hence it is more usually applied to that in the soul by which it does or can suffer, or to dormant and inert possi- bilities of being aroused to exertions of strength or skill, or of making striking advances through education and habit. § 34. The normal operations of each of these ,,,.'-. ,-,, . Function, faculties are called its functions. The term is taken state, pheno- from the action of the bodily organs. From these it is transferred to organs in the metaphorical sense, as the ' organs of government,' and the ' functions ' which they perform. In both these applications it has come to mean, first, the appro- priate operations of each, and then the activities to which they are appointed, or destined. This signification appears when the term is applied to the activities of the powers of the soul. In this use it is assumed that there are activities for which the soul is designed — modes of operations which are adapted, or conduce . l o, 2* 34 INTRODUCTION. § 35. the end of its being. Hence the normal activities of these powers are called functions. States of the soul are often spoken of. The phrase has passed into current if not into technical use. Strictly interpreted, it would designate the more permanent or enduring, as contrasted with the more transient phenomena. It has come, however, to mean any conditions of the soul whatever. Phenomenon is used as properly of spiritual as of material beings or agents. Literally, it means that which appears to, or is known directly by the senses : next that which is known as a fact by the mind. In science, it signifies more precisely that which is known as a fact, in distinction from its explanation by a force, principle, or law. Whether this explanation has or has not yet been attained, makes no difference. Whatever is or is not yet explained, when viewed solely as a fact, is called a phe- nomenon. The English word appearance carries with it the meaning, or at least the suggestion, of unreality. It often means and is understood as a mere appearance, a possible illusion. No such signification belongs to phenomenon, as a technical term that has become established in psychical as well as in material science, to signify an observed fact or event. IV. IS PSYCHOLOGY A SCIENCE, AND WHAT ARE ITS PRINCIPLES AND METHODS? § 35. In the preceding chapters we have impliedly psfcho^gy; if answered these questions. In the subsequent ex- science^fh amination of consciousness they will be discussed inauction M ° f more full y> and also the nature aud authority of psychological science. Our own theory may be briefly stated, thus: The facts or materials with which psychology has to do are derived primarily from consciousness. These materials psychology seeks to ar- range in a scientific method, and to explain by scientific princi- ples. At the same time physiology comes to the aid of con- sciousness, by furnishing a knowledge of the functions and States of the body which prepare the objects of the sense-perception*, and are the essential conditions of the development and the §36. IS PSYCHOLOGY A SCIENCE? 35 activities of the soul. Both these classes of facts must be con- sidered in conjunction, must be observed with attention, must be analyzed into their ultimate elements, must be compared, classed, and interpreted according to the methods which are common to all the inductive sciences. So far it would seem that psychology is truly an inductive science. It is distinguished however by two striking peculiari- ties. First. Its subject-matter is attested by consciousness to be sui generis, consisting of phenomena which cannot be resolved into material entities or agents, and cannot always be subjected to or judged by analogies furnished by material agents, pheno- mena, or laws. Second. This subject-matter is in part the function of knowledge itself, the very agency by which all scientific knowledge is produced, whether of matter or of the mind. This special and fundamental function, psychology must examine, in its various processes, and their products. By this peculiar feature, the science of the human soul involves the scientific study of the principles and laws of all knowledge whatsoever, and of each one of the sciences. In every other feature except this, psychology takes rank with the other induc- tive sciences, and is co-ordinate with them in its subjection to a common method. But by this last feature it becomes in a sense the arbiter of them all, as it tries and tests the methods and principles common to them all, itself included. While, then, psychology is an inductive science, with a subject-matter of its own, it is also in a certain sense, the science of induction itself. It requires us to find, and in a sense to justify the fundamental principles of all the sciences, by showing that such principles exist, and demand verification. So far as psychology concerns itself with the explanation of these principles, it is the science of sciences, the Prima Philosophia. These views are very generally received in respect to the nature of psychology as a science, in answer to the question whether such a science is possible. The opinions of those who dissent from them may be classed as follows : $ 3G. A very large number of persons deny that psychology can ever become a science, because of the vagueness and uncertainty Some hold psy- of its subject-matter. Science, they allege, knows nothing of vaguiPto be powers, either in matter or in spirit. It does not concern itself a science, with the constituents of things, or with the essence and ultimate properties of matter or spirit. It has to do with phenomena only, and it seeks to learn the order and laws of their occurrence by definite statements concerning 36 INTRODUCTION. § 38. their mathematical relations. Force is measured by number; so is the quantity of matter; so are pressure, motion, attraction, and repulsion, in short, every thing with which science, as such, has to do. The range of science proper, they contend, is limited within the domain where mathematical relations apply, and cannot include the facts of psychology to any effective or valuable result. It is sufficient to say in reply, that this view of scientific knowledge, would exclude the science of life in all its forms as truly as the science of the soul. It proves too much, and therefore cannot be true. Science does inquire after the powers, the conditions, and causes of phenomena, as truly as it concerns itself with the mathematical relations of either. Besides, it is always pertinent to ob- serve, that the power by which we are impelled to seek, and by which we attain scientific knowledge, is the only authority for our confidence in science itself. To distrust the possibility of exact and determinate knowledge of the conditions and laws of this power, is to distrust the authority of science. ■ If the soul, as the agent of science, cannot itself be known in its processes and their results, then the processes have no value, and the products no binding force. £ 37. The materialists of every sort contend that a science of The material- the soul is possible and real, because the substance of the soul is psyc'ioloo-y material, and its phenomena can therefore all be explained by the laws and relations of matter. Their cardinal axiom is: there is nothing substantially existent in the universe except what has extension and sen- sible properties. The phenomena of the soul must therefore be the manifestations or actings of an existence of this kind, and can be resolved by scientific methods just so far as they can be referred to changes in the constitution or the actings of an extended and material substratum. We pass over the grosser and cruder theories of the ancient schools, which resolved the soul into some form of refined but unorganized matter, as now universally outgrown and rejected, and observe and notice only that form of modern materialism which passes current with not a few scientific men. This theory makes the brain and nervous system the proper sub- stance of the soul, and explains its phenomena by the peculiar activity of this highly organized material substance. It has this in common with the material- ism of the grosser sort, that it holds it to be impossible that there should be any agent of psychical phenomena except matter. § 38. The materialises of the present day are properly called theory! 613 ™ 118 * Cerebral Psychologists, and plant themselves on the more recent discoveries of physiology in respect to the brain and nervous sys- tem. These discoveries are those of the reflex nervous action by the agency of the afferent and efferent nerves, made by Sir Charles Bell; the discovery of tho independent activity of the several systems of nerves, made by Marshall Hall ; of the capacity for increased nervous energy, and the flow of a more effective nervous stimulus, which is induced by the repeated action of any organ, whether internal or external, whether muscle or brain ; of the changes in the substance of tho brain attendant upon a high mental development — a change in bulk and complexity ; and, last of all, tho discovery of the provision for the consentient or consilient action of different organs of the body, by the coordinating agency of the great nervo centres, which tendency can be greatly augmented and modified by culture and habit. Thcso physiological facts, combined with the doctrine of the association of ideas, which is resolved by ninny into the physical coaction and coalescence of brain movements and brain cells, arc the data or materials § 39. IS PSYCHOLOGY A SCIENCE ? 37 out of which the Cerebral Psychologists construct their science of the human soul. Some cerebralists venture to avail themselves of the as yet partially estab- lished doctrine of the correlation of physical forces, in support of the conclusion that mind, or soul-energy, is but the spiritual correlate or metamorphose of so much brain or nervous energy. Many of these views are ably represented in the works of Professor Alexander Bain, of Aberdeen, entitled The Senses and the In- tellect, and The Emotions and the Will, also, Mental and Moral Science, etc. The facts and phenomena recognized by the cerebralists are true and impor- tant. The most of them should be treated of in anthropology, or the science which treats of the relations of the soul to the body. We may even admit that they all deserve to be considered among the conditions of the purely psychical activities. But they are only the invariable antecedents or the essential condi- tions of these phenomena. There is no evidence that they produce these pheno- mena ; they do not appear among the constituent elements of any psychical state or act; they cannot be found in them by analysis; they do not explain in the least the original capacity to produce them ; they do not account for the depen- dence of one of these classes of states upon another, as of memory upon percep- tion, or of reasoning upon both. These cerebral conditions might be supposed to exist, without the occurrence of any of the phenomena in question, without perception, memory, or reasoning. Moreover, these professed explanations have neither meaning nor application except as they suppose the mind already to possess a knowledge of psychical phenomena as known by consciousness, and as connected by certain scientific relations which are purely psychical in their origin and authority. The cere- bralist talks, like every other man, of perceiving, of being conscious, of re- membering, of induction, and of reasoning. He proposes, as problems to be ex- plained, these phenomena as dependent on and connected with one another in the experience of human consciousness. Of these facts of consciousness he con- tinually avails himself, to give meaning and significance to his cerebral analysis. In short, he supposes a science of the mind's inner experiences which he pro- poses to supplement by facts or laws of sense-observation, using the facts to be explained to interpret the facts which explain them. Should he attempt to use the nomenclature of his own science in place of that given by the science founded on consciousness, he would fail to be understood. The one cannot be a substitute or an equivalent for the other. A science supposes a knowing agent, and a knowing agent is something other than a throbbing brain : and to know even the functions of the brain, especially after a scientific method, must surely be something more than for the brain to exercise a function in respect to itself and its own functions. Such a conception is more incredible and incon- ceivable than the conception, which is so often stigmatized, of the soul as con- scious of its own operations. A soul that is self-conscious would not be so singular as a brain functionizing about itself. § 39. The so-called phrenologists constitute a distinct branch of the cerebral school, if, indeed, their doctrines have not been i o-i C al theory, superseded by the more exaet and comprehensive knowledge of the brain on which the cerebralists build. To the claims of the phrenologists to have established a science of the soul, the following objections may be urged : 1. They have not proved that the protuberances of the brain, or the cranium, on which their science is founded, correspond to the psychical powers or func- 38 INTRODUCTION. § 40. tions which it is claimed they decisively indicate. 2. The classification of these very psychical powers which they adopt is illogical, inasmuch as it is chargeable with not a few cross divisions. 3. The classifications and arrangements of the whole science rest for their verification on the knowledge of the soul which is given by consciousness. It even requires this knowledge to supplement its obser- vations of the cranium. It is consciousness which furnishes all the facts which are to be explained, and which is the test of the correctness of the classifications. Were phrenology established, it would not be a science of psychical facts : it would serve only as a guide in the use of certain external indications as explain- ing the psychical characteristics of individuals. The question may here properly be raised, whether the brain is not the organ of the soul. We reply, that there is an important difference between asserting that the brain is the substance of which psychical processes are the functions, and the very general statement that the brain is the organ of the soul. This last would seem of itself to imply that the brain is one substance and the soul is another, each having proper features and functions of its own. To say that the soul, so long as it exists with its present corporeal environments, uses and depends upon the brain as its organ of communication with the material world, and sympathizes with the physical condition of the brain in its capacity to act with effect, is to say no more than the truth. This dependence and sympathy may hereafter be established in a multitude of particulars which have not yet been discovered. The brain might itself be subdivided into special organs, and for each of these a separate and as yet unknown function might be ascertained. The relations of these organs and their functions to the powers and acts of the soul might be traced out with surprising minuteness, and still the brain would not be proved to be identical with the soul itself. § 40. The Associational Psychology represents still another tionalist theory, theory of the science of the soul. It is founded, as its name imports, upon the fact or law recognized by all psychologists, that the ideas or acts of the soul which are often united tend to recall one another more readily. This law is applied by this school to take the place of every other law or condition of psychical activity, and to exclude every other power or capacity. It is made to stand in the place of the so-called faculties, and even to explain the origin of all necessary and intuitive truths. The school numbers many adherents, among whom are conspicuous Hobbes, Hume, Hartley, Bonnet, James Mill, John Stuart Mill, Bain, and Herbert Spencer. Some of these are more consistent and extreme in their conclusions than others, but all may be fairly said to adopt the associationalist theory in its principal features. These common features are the following. They hold, 1. That a psychical state is analogous to a change or effect in a material object as being a simple impression, or changed condition which is simple — not complex, as is claimed by those who find in every such state a conscious relation to the ggo. They also, hold, that it is necessarily produced by its cause, condition, or object. They deny, distinctly or impliedly, the truth that every state of the soul must be performed by the con- scious ego, and that in many of these states this ego is active, and in no sense passive. 2. They teach that every such state thus necessarily produced and pas- sively experienced, tends to be reproduced with its attendant*. 3. A repro- duced state, unless in some way reinforced, as by similar conditions, of itself tends to be and is reproduced with an energy that is weaker than that of the § 40. IS PSYCHOLOGY A SCIENCE ? 39 original. (Cf. Hume, Bain, and Spencer.) 4. If it is often reproduced and is reinforced in every act, its energy is greatly increased. This increased energy is manifested subjectively by its stronger tendency to recur again, and objectively by the greater vividness with which the object is represented. Herbert Spencer in- sists that the facility thus acquired becomes literally mechanical, and that the acts in question pass entirely out of the domain of consciousness, and are taken up by the passive energies, first of the associational faculty, and then of the brain and nerve-cells. In this way they become the material for propagation, through transformations of the nervous substance which are transmitted from one generation to another. A few physiologists, who are not so extreme, account for the phenomena in question by what they call processes of 'unconscious cerebration/ Every activity of the mind not occasioned by some new or original impression, is the action or product of this tendency to recurrent action, thus weakened or strengthened in whole or in part. Imagination is a weak- ened impression. An act of memory is a somewhat stronger and recurring ac- tivity, bringing up a more perfect reproduction of the past. Generalization is a more vigorous revival of some part of many original impressions, which is capable of being suggested by each of these originals or their parts, and made common to them all. Judgment and induction are similar experiences of partial elements of more widely ramified impressions. All these processes are reduced to the more vivid experiences which result from many similar impressions; never to the discernment and affirmation of similarity in the parts of each of the objects to which they belong. Similarity itself, as the ground and motive to the classification and interpretation of nature, is only the result of two or more passive impressions, and never an intelligent cognition or judgment. It is not an objective fact of relation knowable by the intellect, but a subjective sensa- tion or impression more or less frequently recurring. The belief of necessary truths or fundamental relations, is the result of the frequent conjunction of similar expei'iences made inseparable by repetition. Thus, the relation of causation is resolved by Hume into the customary connec- tion of ideas or objects. Thus, J. Stuart Mill resolves the belief in any neces- sary truths, even the simplest mathematical postulates or axioms, into " insepa- rable association," and gravely suggests that their opposites might be and ap- pear just as axiomatic to a community, trained under different associations. Thus, Herbert Spencer, in his Principles of Psychology, resolves our a priori con- victions concerning the reality of space and time, and the relations which they involve (for the necessity of which, as realities, he contends, against Kant and Hamilton), into the invariable conjunctions which first created a persistent ten- dency to recurrence, which tendency has been fixed by being propagated through countless generations of human beings. It is necessarily implied in this theory that it dispenses with what it calls the scholastic doctrine of separate faculties of the soul. This, indeed, is its pride and boast, that it makes these several faculties to be but varied results of the sin- gle tendency or law of association. The fundamental defect of the associational school, consists in this, that it does not distinguish between those activities of the soul by which, so to speak, objects are prepared for and presented to the soul for its varied activities, pre- eminently that of knowledge, and the activities which the soul performs with re- spect to them when so prepared and presented. An impression on the sensorium, 40 INTRODUCTION. § 41. even when responded to by reflex nervous activity, is not the act of knowledge by which the mind distinguishes the object from itself and from other objects; nor does the tendency thereby created to its repetition explain the act of imagi- nation or memory with respect to it when represented a second time. A similar impression, in whole or in part, is a very different thing from that apprehension of a whole or part as similar which is essential to generalization and reasoning as acts of knowledge. The constant conjunction of two ideas, in consequence of wbich the one will always suggest the other, does not explain the relation under which the mind connects them in an act of judgment; least of all the rela- tion by which it joins them in those beliefs which are necessary and intuitive, as are those which concern the relations of space, time, causation, and design. It is worthy of notice, that though the associational school is plausibly suc- cessful in its explanations of the lower activities and products of the intellect, they fail most signally in explaining the higher operations. J. S. Mill supple- ments the functions of the associational power in his theory of reasoning and in- duction by resorting to an ' expectation concerning the uniformity of nature/ which neither association nor induction can account for. Bain resorts to the emotional nature to explain belief, and Herbert Spencer must fall back upon the growth o£ two nerve-cells into one, propagated indefinitely through successive generations, to account for a priori and necessary beliefs. The associational school can only explain the higher processes and products of the mind by explaining them away — by causing them, under the pressure of its theory, to become something else than what they are. Its theories and ex- planations are plausible, because the single principle on which they rest is so nearly allied to the pervasive law of attraction, which is so potent in mechanical and chemical philosophy. The extensive and ready favor with which they are received as the only truly scientific theory of the mind, is but a single cxamplo of the power of materialistic analogies and prepossessions in the judgments of spiritual facts and relations. The associational theory, though in its fundamental principle not riah^tic. necessarily materialistic, has been uniformly received by tho cerc- bralists, especially by the cerebralists of tho modern school. Tho doctrine that every mental process is the result of the association and blending of ideas, when united with the principle which explains association by the conjunc- tion of nerve-cells into nerve-growths, and the consilience of nerve activities by the increased energy of nervous stimuli, commends itself as demonstrable, rea- sonable, and true to all those who find in tho movements and growths of tho brain the scientific explanation of psychical processes. Bonnet, Hartley, Bain, and Herbert Spencer impliedly, are eminent examples of the union of both ccre- bralism and associationalism in tho same scientific theory. g 41. The Metaphysical, or, as it is called by some, tho Con- Metaphysical structivc theory of the science, remains to be noticed. This as- chology°. ,i y suincs that psychology can become a science only as it is ox- pounded in the spirit of a system of speculative philosophy which is first assumed or proved to bo true, and which. must be established as true, bo- fore tho study of the mind can bo made truly scientific, or even before it can begin. 'There is a truth in tho assumption, that every special science is only so far scientific as it rests upon true metaphysics. But there is an important differ- ence between the correct and adjusted statement of this underlying philosophy §41. IS PSYCHOLOGY A SCIENCE? 41 in a perfected system, and the investigation of these truths in their concrete appli- cations without the aid of such a system. In psychological studies the tempta- tion is particularly strong to view the facts in the light of some preconceived and half-learned philosophy; hut it ought for this very reason to be more vigor- ously resisted. It is in the order of nature that the study of metaphysics should follow after the study of the mind, inasmuch as it is by the analysis of the power to know, that we are supposed first to discover what it is to know, and especially what are the objects and relations which are essential to science; in other words, what conceptions and relations are philosophically valid as the axioms and pos- tulates of scientific knowledge. To pursue the reversed order, is to weaken the certainty of knowledge, as well as to confuse and embarrass the mind of the student. Such an error of method is certain to be revenged on speculative philosophy itself. It opens the way for fantastic dogmatism on the part of the teacher; for, as soon as he is emancipated from the necessity of justifying his speculative system to the consciousness of his learners by the facts of inner experience, he will be tempted to be positive when he is not certain, and to be fantastic when he is neither logical nor clear. It breeds haziness and pretension on the part of the student. In attempting to fol- low a guide who deviates from the order of nature, his steps cease to be confident and firm. The want of clear insight he will supply by pretension and conceit, which are both parent and offspring of credulity and dependence. No maxim deserves to be recorded by the student of philosophy in letters more clear and bright than this : ' The man who seeks to enter the temple of philoso-' phy by any other approach than the vestibule of psychology, can never penetrate into its inner sanctuary; for psychology alone leads to and evolves philosophical truth, even though it is itself subordinate to philosophy.' The investigator who attempts to construct psychology by the aid and under the direction of a meta- physical system, contradicts the order by which both psychology and philosophy are developed and acquired. Knowledge de- THE HUMAN INTELLECT: ITS FUNCTION, DEVELOPMENT, AND FACULTIES. A PRELIMINARY CHAPTER. § 42. We have considered the soul as capable of fined, what is various functions or operations, which are manifested it to know ? . r . to consciousness as psychical facts or phenomena. TIw intellect has been defined : — the soul as endowed with and exercising the power to know. We now proceed to make the intellect the special object of our study, that is, we enter upon that special division of psychology which is concerned with the capacities, operations, and laws of the human intellect. The distinctive function of the intellect being to know, we at once inquire, ' What is it, for the soul to know ? ' The fact that we exercise the function of knowing is attested by consciousness and also that it differs from feeling and willing. For this conscious experience there can be no substitute. All definitions and de" scriptions presuppose that the person to whom they are addressed can understand their import and verify their truth by referring to his own conscious acts. What consciousness apprehends and distinguishes may be more exactly defined as follows : 1. To know, is an operation of the soul acting as the intellect — an operation in which it is preeminently active. In knowing, we are not so much recipients as actors. We do not merely sub- mit to the impressions made upon the senses from without. Nor are we the passive subjects of the mechanical operations of ideas already acquired, acting upon us by an independent force and movement of their own. But in all states of knowledge the soul knows itself to be active. 2. The intellect exercises its capacity to know under certain 42 § 42. ITS FUNCTION, DEVELOPMENT, AND FACULTIES. 43 conditions. Like every other agent in nature, it is limited in respect to the mode, energy, and results of its action, by the occasions and circumstances under which it acts. Thus the intellect cannot perceive a color, a taste, a tree, a house, unless these objects are presented to the mind, for it to act concerning or upon. So, too, it cannot remember unless an event has occurred which it may proceed to recall and recog- nize. Nor can it imagine or believe, without certain materials or data, by means of which it creates or infers. These conditions are objective only. There are also conditions which are subjective, as the mind's capacity to know, which is always implied; its disposition for present activity, its bodily conditions of health and reason ; also certain favoring circum- stances, as absence of preoccupation ; and, last of all, the direc- tion and fixing of the attention to the so-called objects. 3. The objects which condition the acts of the intellect are diverse in their character. Some are presented from the world without : as the objects of sense, for the existence and nature of which, the soul itself may be in no way responsible. Others are presented from within, as the operations of the soul itself, in the various forms and the endless variety of the states of know- ledge, feeling, and will, all of which are apprehended as objects by consciousness. Others still are the products or results of precedent acts or energies of the soul — residua from objects once perceived, waiting to be re-awakened — the so-called images or pictures once present, now absent, yet capable of being revived. It is manifest from this enumeration that the word object is used in two widely divergent senses — either as the external or material object, the object-object, as it is often called, and which may be explained as the object eminently objective ; or as the subject-object, i. e., the mental object, or the object created by the mind's own energy. The adjectives objective and subjective, also, follow the import of the nouns. Objective is applied to whatever the mind contemplates as an object, whether it be a subject-object or an object-object Every relation which such an object holds is called objective. On the other hand, subjective is applied to the knowing mind, whether it is conceived as apprehending a subject- object or an object-object Subjective is also applied to all the 44 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 44. psychical experiences and acts ; to the feeling and willing, as well as the knowing soul. § 43. 4. If the soul can create objects for itself to which prepares know — as in the cases already referred to of con- kuowfedge. sciousness and memory, — we ought carefully to dis- tinguish those of its activities by which objects are, so to speak, prepared for the mind's cognition, from the special ac- tivity of the intellect in knowing these objects when prepared or presented for its apprehension. For example, the energy of the soul in what is called the association of ideas — by which, on occa- sion of the presence of an object known, another object presents itself in order to be known — is clearly distinguishable from the act of the intellect in apprehending that object when presented. In like manner, all the antecedent preparation by which material things are made ready to be known through the joint action of body and spirit in the sensorium, is plainly diverse, and ought to be distinguished from the act of the mind in perceiving the object when thus made ready. We observe also, that these acts or functions of preparation, are generally not conscious acts, in the sense in which the acts of knowledge are. Some of them may be wholly removed from consciousness, as is the activity by which the soul preserves and suggests objects once known, even though this very activity largely depends on previous conscious operations. Some of these may be entirely removed from consciousness, as the physiological or psycho-physical operations which conditionate sense-perception. Others may be entirely within the range of conscious observation, though performed with rapid,spontaneous and uncontrolled exertion. They are all properly psychical acts, and are appropriately treated in connection with those activities with which conscious- ness has to do. We cannot understand the one class of activities without constant reference to the other. § 44. 5. To know — the conditions of knowledge To know, lm- . ° plies the cer- being fulfilled — is to be certain that something is. tainty of being. si- ■, . , Knowledge and being are correlative to one another. There must be being, in order that there may be knowledge. But it belongs to the very essence of knowledge to apprehend or cognize its object to be. Subjectively viewed, to know, involves certainty ; objectively it requires reality. § 45. ITS FUNCTION, DEVELOPMENT, AND FACULTIES. 45 We distinguish different kinds of objects and different kinds of reality. Objects may be psychical or material. Their reality may be mental and internal, or material and external, but in either case it is equally a reality. The spectrum which the camera paints on the screen, the reddened landscape seen through a colored lens ; the illusion that crosses the brain of the lunatic, the vision that frightens the ghost-seer; the thought that darts into the fancy and is gone as soon, each as really exists as does the matter of the solid earth, or the external forces of the cosmical system. It is true, one kind of existence and reality is not as important to us as is the other ; we dignify one class as real, and call the other unreal. We name some of these objects realities, and others shadows and unreal ; but, philosophically speaking, and so far as the act of knowledge is concerned, they are alike real and are alike known to be. The word being is sometimes contrasted with phenomenon. It is obvious that in that case being is not used in the sense in which we have defined it ; i. e., as equivalent to a hnowable object. When used in such a contrast, we oppose permanent, or independent being, to transient, or dependent being. We often err in making one kind of reality indicate another. We do not err in not knowing that something is, but in mistaking it for something which it is not. We do not err as to that the being is, but as to what it is. We do not err as to its beingness or entity, but as to its relations. This leads us to observe : § 45. 6. In knowing, we apprehend not only that objects exist, but also that they exist in certain rela- "of re'iatTous! 7 tions. It is essential to the definition of knowledge, not only that we know objects as existing, but that we know them as reined. We cannot even know two thought-objects as existing without also knowing that the one is not the other. Yv r e cannot notice two leaves, without knowing that they are alike or unlike in form, surface, or color. We cannot observe two oc- currences without referring them to the same or different causes, etc., etc. It may be objected that, although it may be true that when- ever two objects are known by a single act, they must be known in relation, yet it is not so when the object is single. To this we 46 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 46. reply, that it is impossible that an object should be known singly and apart from every other. A single object must be known by some agent, and it cannot be known by that agent unless the object is distinguished from the agent, and from his act in know- ing : but to be distinguished is to be known in the relation of diversity. The attention may not be strongly fixed on the rela- tion — it may seem to be engrossed by either of the two objects ; but their diversity cannot be unknown. But there is scarcely such a thing supposable as a single object. No single object actually exists in the world of matter or of mind. Every so-called object or event in nature, every single state of mind, will readily resolve itself before the attentive eye into many separable elements existing in relations to each other, and held together as one thing by the cementing force of these bonds. An apple, an orange, a pebble, nay, even a grain of sand, consists of parts not a few, united into one perceived whole. A mental state, however simple, is in its essential nature complex, to say nothing of the special relations of time and quality which distinguish it from every other. This prepares us to assert that to know, always involves two comprehensive acts, each of which corresponds to the other — the act of separation, or resolving objects as wholes into their parts or distinguishable elements, and the act of uniting or combining these parts into their wholes. These acts are technically termed analysis and synthesis, and they are present in every form and variety of knowledge. In sense-perception the different parts of material objects and the objects themselves, are first distin- guished and then united under relations of space and time. In consciousness they are connected as coexistent, successive, or pro- duced by the active ego. In imagination they are again sepa- rated and reunited. In thought or intelligence, they are again divided, to be re-combined as constituents of general notions or concepts, of judgments, arguments, inferences, and systems. Thought, indeed, tends to bring all knowledge into the unity of common properties, powers, laws, and ends. § 46. 7. The process or act of knowledge is com- cess of know- plete when it is matured into a product and this comp e c product itself becomes an object to the mind's future knowing. At one time the whole of a mental state becomes § 47. ITS FUNCTION, DEVELOPMENT, AND FACULTIES. 47 such an object ; at another, some one element of a single mental state is detached from the act that produced it, and becomes en- dowed, so to speak, with a separate life. This product, so far as it exists, exists as a mental transcript or representation of the original, whether that original were a subject-object or an object- object It is also capable of being recalled, and of itself recalling its original. The power of producing such permanent and reproducible results is essential to the perfection and the utility of the act of knowing. It is so essential, that upon it depend the simplest acts of the memory and the imagination, without which the mind would be limited to the present, and could neither gather instruction from the past, nor apply wisdom to the future. The higher processes by which man explains the powers and laws of nature would otherwise be impossible, and the capacity to use these powers and to apply these laws in any practical service would be excluded altogether. The knowledge which is thus separated from the original ac- tivity is called representative knowledge, with reference to the original act of acquiring, and mediate or represented knowledge, with reference to the original objects known. The products thus preserved are called acquired or positive knowledge. § 47. 8. The same act of knowledge, with similar The act of objective conditions, may be performed with greater knowing is di- n rm ■ i • verse in its or less energy. Tnis greater or less energy m tne energy. Atten- operation of knowing is called attention; which word, as its etymology suggests, is another term for tension or effort, and was doubtless first transferred to the spiritual opera- tion from the strained condition of the part or whole of the bodily organism, which accompanies or follows such effort. This effort is manifested in the more or less exclusive and complete occupation of the knowing power by the object or relation that is apprehended. This greater or less effort of attention is fol- lowed by the greater or less distinctness, vividness, and complete- ness in the objects apprehended, and in the objects retained among the mind's permanent possessions, as also by a greater or less facility in exercising a similar activity a second time. Some of these beings and relations are discerned by the mind with far greater ease than others. To hold the mind to certain 48 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 48. classes of objects and relations, is comparatively easy, requires little or no exertion, and is accomplished with spontaneous facility. To know so as to master an unfamiliar object, always involves effort at the first ; and a ready facility can only be at- tained by frequent repetition. "Why or how this is so, we need not here explain. The fact is attested by universal observation. It is natural and soon becomes easy to all men "to attend to material objects, up to a certain degree of minuteness. It is comparatively difficult and unnatural to consider closely the ex- periences and processes of the soul. It is easy to decide upon the comparative length and breath of two corporeal objects. It is not so easy to apprehend the parts and relations of a ma- thematical theorem or of a logical argument. The easier and more natural processes are performed by all men. The more difficult and less natural are reserved for the few. For facility in the one, that education which nature furnishes to all, is amply sufficient. For skill and readiness in the other, special discipline and culture, — literally great pains-taking, — are requisite. The easier and spontaneous processes are first performed, and are therefore the earliest perfected and matured. The more diffi- cult and artificial are exercised next in order ; and readiness and skill in using them is reached at a later period. The powers of sense and outward observation are first developed, next those of memory and imagination, and last of all, those of reflection, thought, and reason. As it is with the intellectual processes, so is it with their pro- ducts. We have seen how the products are related to the pro- cesses ; that as the mental processes are employed and perfected with energetic attention, so the mental products are evolved in completed perfection, as naturally and as certainly as the ripe fruit or perfected seed drops from the plant or tree which has rightly elaborated its organic processes. § 48. 9. In this wav there comes to be an organic The psycholo- ° J . ° gicai and logical connection among the products of the intellect, cor- relation of pro- ° • i .• <* -i i cesses and pro- responding to the organic relations 01 the several processes out of which they grow. This relation, as it depends on the development of the soul itself, is called psy- chological; as it implies antecedence and subsequence of time, it is called chronological. §48. ITS FUNCTION, DEVELOPMENT, AND FACULTIES. 49 Besides the psychological or chronological relation of the powers and products to one another, there is still another, which is more important and fundamental, and that is their philosophi- cal or logical relation. We use one of these kinds of knowing to supplement the other, and often not only to supplement, but even to correct its operations and results. Thus we reason to conclusions which we cannot observe by the senses or experience in consciousness. We infer results which we cannot try by experiment, and we predict them before it is time for them to occur. We correct rash con- clusions, by looking at principles and laws. We deny assertions, however confident, by employing arguments. We question so-, called facts because they do not square with an established theory. Corresponding to the relation between these processes of know- ing, there is the relation of logical dependence or of rational con- neclion between their products. One conception is subordinate to another, as a species to a genus ; or one is a property or at- tribute of another, as a quality of a substance; or one is con- tained in another, as an element in its definition ; or is given as a reason for another, as a proof for an assertion, a premise for a conclusion, a datum for an induction, or a means to an end. Many conceptions and truths are also capable of being united in mutual relations of classification and explanation, as constituents of a system. All these are examples of logical relations in mental products. The logical relations of the products grow out of the philoso- phical dependence of the processes from which the products are evolved. But inasmuch as the products are expressed in language, and are made objective to the mind, their logical and objective relations are more striking and prominent than the subordination of the acts of knowledge to one another when psychologically considered. The rational faculty asserts for itself intellectual authority over the lower powers, by asserting for its products, the place of criteria, rules, reasons, and princi- ples in respect to the products of the lower. Hence the objec- tive or logical relations are more conspicuous than the psycho- logical and subjective. We therefore set up a broad distinction between two kinds of knowledge, calling the one empirical and the other philosophical, 50 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 48. the one, knowledge by observation, and the other, knowledge by principles or reasons. We should remember, when we make this distinction, that the same mind uses two ways or processes of knowing, and that these supplement one another. There must, then, be a relation of dependence between the two. The one must be subject to the other, in the mind's own judgment, and according to the ordinances of the mind's own constitution. The mind that observes and acquires, knows that, by thinking, it can correct and aid its own observing, and that the one method of knowing has a certain authority over the other. Thus, when we analyze a substance, we determine the qualities that are common to its class, and so are enabled to define a general conception, by resolving it into its constituent or neces- sary elements. We account for or explain a phenomenon which we observe, or a fact of which we hear, by referring to the causes or forces by which it was produced ; and these very causes or forces we interpret still further by the laws according to which they act; or we round off and complete the explanation by stating the adaptations to an end or assumed design. The psychological and logical relations of knowledge do not always coincide. The order of intellectual growth and of psy- chological development does not agree with the order of logical dependence and of philosophical arrangement. That which is last in actual attainment, is first in logical importance. The truths and relations which the mind is the latest and the slowest to develop and assent to, may be those which are fundamental to its rational knowledge. It may even be taken as a maxim, that what is psychologically last, is first in logic and in reason. Another and still higher activity of the intellect is or speculative,' the critical or speculative. It reaches this when knowledge 1 . ot having attained the command of its higher faculties, and developed the familiar principles and rules which they involve, it applies them in judging the mind itself, and preeminently its higher powers, for the purpose of testing their trustworthiness and examining their authority. After questioning every other agent in the universe, and judging of its workings, it turns its scrutiny in upon itself, to test the processes by which it knows, and even the very rules and principles which it imposes upon every thing besides ; itself included. § 49. ITS FUNCTION, DEVELOPMENT, AND FACULTIES. 51 § 49. The consideration of these facts and relations, enables us to trace the growth of the mind through the stages of its normal i e ctual develop- development. This development begins with the beginnings of men t, growth . and studies, attention. Before this, its activities are, as it were, rudimental only. From this condition the mind awakes when some object attracts and holds its attention. The infant's power to know begins to be developed when it begins to attend. As soon as the infant begins to notice, its vacant countenance for the first time assumes the expression of intelligence, and is lighted with the dawn of intellectual activity. Attention gives discrimination, and discrimination im- plies objects discriminated. The first objects distinguished are objects of sense. The sensible objects that are first mastered are those which relate to its wants, and generally, so far only as they are related to these wants; first to its appetites, then to its affections and desires. With the discernment of these objects, in their relations to these sensibilities and desires, begins also the direction of the active powers by intelligence. But though the attention is at first chiefly occupied with sensible objects, and these prominently in their relations to the sensibilities and the practical wants, it is not wholly neglectful of the psychical operations and the psychical self. At a very early period the body is distinguished from the material world of which it forms a part. The soul also begins to be apprehended as diverse from the body, as soon as the purely psychical emotions, as the love of power and sympathy, or the irascible passions, are vividly experienced. As fast as the attention masters distinct objects, it must separate th*em into separable ideas or images, which are henceforth at the service of the imagina- tion and the memory. These reappear in the occasional dream-life that begins to disturb what was hitherto the animal sleep of the infant. Memory begins to recall past experiences of knowledge and feeling. Recognition finds old and familiar acquaintances in the objects seen a second time. At a later period, ima- gination begins to imitate the actions and occupations of older persons, and furnishes endless and varied playwork for childhood in the busy constructions of the never- wearied fancy ; while it irradiates the emotional life with perpetual and inextinguishable sunshine. Slowly, the rudiments of thinking, or the rational processes, begin to be learned and practised. The attention not only discriminates, but compares. As it com- pares, it discerns likenesses and differences in qualities and relations. These it thinks, apart from the individual objects to which they pertain. It groups and arranges, under the general conceptions thus formed, the individuals and species to which they belong. To these activities language furnishes its stimulus and lends its aid. Inasmuch as there can be but a limited language without generali- zation, the infant or child is forced to think, by the multitude of words which catch its ear and force themselves upon its attention; each representing the pre- vious thinking of other men, and even of other generations. With classifying, are intimately allied the higher acts of tracing effects to causes and illustrating causes by effects. Then, inductions are made by interpre- ting similar qualities and causes, as exhibited in experience and elicited by experiments. The mind becomes possessed of principles and rules, which it applies in deductions both to prove and explain. The powers and forces of matter and spirit begin to be discerned, as the result of induction and deduc- tion combined. The relations of these powers to their conditions, and to one 52 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 49. another, as well as to motion, time, and space, begin to be fixed and definitely- stated and the laws of matter and of spirit are ascertained in a wider or more limited range and application. Science arranges all beings and all events into the order of completed systems, by means of the processes of thought; the world of nature is recast into a new spiritual structure, under the relations by which thought decomposes and recombines its individual beings and events, as presented to observation under the relations of space and time. Adaptation and design shoot golden threads of light and order through that otherwise pale and lifeless system of nature, which science reconstructs out of blind forces and fixed mechanical laws. The originating and intelligent intellect of the Eternal Creator and Designer is reached, as the first assumption and the last result of scientific thought. Last of all, thought turns back upon itself, and critically analyzes all its knowledge, and its very power to know. It inquires into and scrutinizes its acquisitions and its assumptions, and challenges its own confidence in its most familiar processes and beliefs. It seeks to justify to itself its acquired knowledge, its science, and its faith, by retracing, under the guidance of logical relations, every step it has taken, and every stage through which it has passed in its de- velopment and growth. It lays bare the necessary assumptions, the primary and universal relations, which are acknowledged and acted upon in all observation, in all science, and in all faith. It returns again from the course of its speculative criticism, to confide a second time in this knowledge and the faith which it could not but acquire and apply in its progressive synthesis, and which it now has learned to vindicate by its retrogressive analysis. These critical and speculative processes of thought are reserved for but a few of the race to prosecute. They are, however, the normal and the necessary con- summation of the completed growth of the fully developed man. The consideration of the development and growth of the intellect furnishes the principles by which to regulate the culture of the intellect, and to arrange the order of its studies. The studies which should be first pursued are those which require and disci- pline the powers of observation and acquisition, and which involve imagination and memory, in contrast with those which demand severe efforts and trained habits of thought. In early life, objective and material studies should have almost the exclusive precedence. The capacity of exact and discriminating per- ception, and of clear and retentive memory, should be developed as largely as possible. The imagination, in all its forms, should be directed and elevated — we do not say stimulated, because, in the case of most children, its activity is never-tiring, whether they be at study, work or play. We do not say, cultivate perception, memory, and fancy, to the exclusion or repression of thought, for this is impossible. These powers, if exercised by human beings, must be interpenetrated by thought. If wisely cultivated by studies properly arranged, they will necessarily involve discrimination, compari- son, and explanation. To teach pure observation, or the mastery of objects or words, without classification and interpretation, is to commit the error of simple stupidity. But, on the other hand, to stimulate the thought-processes to unnatu- ral and prematurely painful efforts, is to do violence to the laws which nature has written in the constitution of the intellect. Even thought and reflection teach us that, before the processes of thought can be applied, materials must be § 50. ITS FUNCTIONS, DEVELOPMENT, AND FACULTIES. 53 gathered in large abundance; and to provide for these, nature has made acquisi- tion and memory easy and spontaneous for childhood, and reasoning and science difficult and unnatural. The study of language should be prosecuted in childhood, as it is, in fact, in the acquisition of the mother-tongue. In the acquisition of other languages the methods by which the vernacular is learned should be followed so far as is possi- ble. Grammar, so far as it is required, should be simple, plain, and practical. Its theories should be kept in the background, its terminology and principles should be the reverse of the abstract. The contrasts and comparisons involved between the strange and the familiar, will stimulate and guide to the first begin- nings of reflective grammar. The memory for words should be exercised and stimulated. Choice tales and poems — narrative and lyric, — should be learned for recitation. Natural history in all its branches, as contrasted with the sciences of nature or scientific physics, should be pursued with the objects before the eye — flowers, minerals, shells, birds, and beasts. These studies should all be mastered in the spring-time of life, when the tastes are simple, the heart is fresh, and the eye is sharp and clear. The facts of history and geography should be fixed by repetition and stored away in order. But science of every kind, whether of language, of nature, of the soul, or of God, as science, should not be prematurely taught. For the consequence is, either disgust and hostility to all study on the one hand, or, on the other, super- ficial thinking, presumptuous conceit, and, worst of all, sated curiosity. The law of intellectual progress involves effort and discipline severely imposed and constantly maintained, but the effort and discipline should follow the gui- dance of nature. § 50. The consideration of the nature and the de- velopment of knowledge teaches on what principles ciSfying^e we may divide and classify the powers of the in- £32*! tellect. In assigning different faculties to the intellect, we do not divide it into separable parts or organs. When we say that the intel- lect has faculties, we mean only that the soul, as the intellect, acts under certain conditions in clearly distinguishable operations which terminate in definite and determinable results or products. The consideration of the soul's development gives the conditions of these faculties. The consideration of the logical relations of the products assigns to these faculties their relative authority and importance. In tracing the development of the intellectual powers in their succession, we do not exclude the co-action of the other so-called faculties of the soul, as of feeling and will. Their presence and agency have already been recognized with sufficient prominence. Nor do we deny or overlook the truth, that the several powers of the intellect act together in the earlier stages of its growth, 54 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 50. and in all the periods of its history aid and direct one another. The action of a single power of the intellect does not exclude the co-action of the other powers. On the other hand, it is to be re- membered, that as the energy of the whole soul is so far limited that one psychical state is preeminently a state of feeling, another intellectual, and another voluntary, so, of the intellectual activi- ties, one is likely to be predominantly an act of sense rather than of memory, and another an act of the imagination rather than of intelligence. When it is said that one power, as denned, is, in the order of time and growth, developed sooner than another, it is not in- tended that each lower power is completely matured before the other and higher is used at all, or that distinctly traced boundary lines mark off the several stages of the mind's development. This would involve the absurdity of teaching that the child perceives with the senses for a long time before it begins to remember, and that it remembers and imagines for another long period, before it generalizes and explains. What is asserted is, that sense must begin before memory and thought are possible, and that, as a power, it is perfected before thought has reached its consumma- tion. Conversely, it will be found to be true in fact, that many acts which we call acts of sense-perception are largely intermin- gled with acts of representation and thought ; also that acts of memory recall past objects under the laws of association which thought makes possible ; while imagination, in which thought is not largely conspicuous, is scarcely worthy the name. These cautions being premised, we observe that the powers of the intellect are clearly distinguishable by the order of their devel- opment and application, as manifested in the character and rela- tions of their products. The leading faculties of the intellect are three : The pre- SENTATIVE, OR OBSERVING FACULTY ; THE REPRESENTATIVE, OR CREATIVE FACULTY; THE THINKING, OR THE GENERALIZING faculty ; or, more briefly, the faculty of experience, the FACULTY OF REPRESENTATION, and the FACULTY OF INTELLI- GENCE. Each of these has its place in the order of intellectual grovvth and development. Each has its appropriate products or objects. Each acts under certain conditions or laws. Each of these leading faculties is subdivided into subordinate powers, § 51. ■ ITS FUNCTION, DEVELOPMENT AND FACULTIES. 55 which are distinguishable from one another in like manner with their primaries. § 51. I. The presentative faculty, or the faculty of acquisition and experience, is subdivided into sense- ,'. -, , ,-■ The presenta- perception and consciousness; or, as tney are some- tive faculty. times called, the outer and the inner sense. In the order of the mind's development these are exercised first and earliest of all. The intellect begins its activity with observing objects of sense. Closely connected with this is the consciousness of the soul's inner experiences, prominent among which are its sensations of pleasure and pain. Not only does this order actually occur, but it is impossible for us to conceive of any other as possible. The mind must observe before it re- members; unless it had previously observed and acquired, it would have nothing to remember or imagine. The objects or products with which this power is concerned, or which it evolves, are individual objects. In this respect they are distinguished from the objects of thought, which are always general. But this feature they share with those of memory and imagination, which are also individual. From these last they are still further distinguished by being presented for the first time ; hence the epithet presentative is applied to the faculty by which they are known. This feature is made still more precise by their individual relations in space and in time. The objects of sense are known in space, as being here, and the objects of con- sciousness are known as now in time. These two relations they share with the objects of no other power. They are also mutually related to one another, the one being an individualized non-ego, the other being a determinate state of the ego. The conditions of the acts of sense-hioivledge are the existence of the living body in connection with a sentient spirit, and the excitement of the same by material agents. Some of these are bodily, some are psychical. Some of these are known to physiology, others are wholly unknown, but so far as they are knowable, they are appropriately considered in explaining the power of sense-knowledge. The condition which furnishes or constitutes the object for the act of consciousness, is that the soul should in fact act or suffer in a present and individual state. Consciousness takes heed of 56 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 52. the fact, i. e., of the operation, and cognizes that it is. Whence or how it is that the soul furnishes this material, or how the soul is able to act in these varied forms, it can do little to explain. These operations lie out of the range of consciousness ; they are presupposed by it. But these objective conditions are not alone. There are also subjective conditions of the presentative power in both conscious- ness and perception. Let the external world and the quick sen- sibility both conjoin to furnish ample material through eye and ear ; let the active and eager soul exercise the most varied forms of act or affection ; if the perceiving or conscious spirit does not attend, it will fail to notice, and of course will fail to know. § 52. II. Next to the presentative comes the The repre- ° J: . . .. - sentativ© fa- faculty of representation. That this is developed second in order of growth and of time to the soul's power to acquire and observe, is obvious. The objects or products of this power are individual objects, like the objects of sense and of consciousness. They differ from them in this, that they are representative of them. They are therefore not real, but mental objects. They are wrought or created by the mind itself, but always with respect to some real object actually experienced. This is their common characteristic, that they represent observed and experienced objects. They are representative ; i. e., they present a second time, and so take the place of objects previously known. In representing these objects, the mind acts in two ways— as the memory ; and as the imagination or phantasy : and hence the representative power is divided into these two. In memory it knows that the mental object represents an object previously known. In imagination it changes the representative object into another, such as it has never actually experienced. Ac- cording as it changes the object in more or fewer particulars, and with special applications, does the imagination receive dif- ferent names. The conditions of the representing power arc, that the soul should retain and reproduce past objects for the memory to re- cognize and the imagination to modify. If the soul refuses to furnish these appropriate objects, neither the memory nor the imagination can know their objects. For this reason, the pmer § 53. ITS FUNCTION, DEVELOPMENT, AND FACULTIES. 57 of the soul to retain and recall is essential to the power to know these mental objects when represented. Concerning the actings of the capacity of the soul to retain and reproduce we know little directly, but indirectly we know very much : that is, we know how we can affect its actings by our own conscious energies in acquiring. The relations and laws by which acquired objects can be reproduced are more obvious and better established than almost any other psychological truths. These are all compre- hended under the familiar title of the association of ideas, and they very properly enter largely into the consideration of the re- presentative power. § 53. III. The power of thought is developed last of all in the order of the soul's evolution or growth, temg?nce.° rm " It is also called the intelligence, and the rational faculty. This power requires for its possible exercise some range of ob- servation, some acquisitions of memory, and some creative activ- ity of imagination. For its effective energy and its actual appli- cation it must be preceded by many separate exercises of all these functions. To the thorough and persistent use and the complete development of this power, the soul is most of all disinclined ; and therefore it is perfected and developed later in the order of time. But ^hough this power is last and reluctantly developed, it sur- passes all the others in dignity and importance. It explains facts and events by powers and laws. It enforces conclusions by premises. It accounts for inferences by data. It lifts observa- tion up to the dignity of science, and establishes it on the firm foundation of principles. It enables us to interpret the past and to predict the future. The products or objects of this power are always generalized objects. They are universals, as contrasted with individuals. This difference distinguishes this power of the intellect widely from the two others. These products are known by various names, as the concept, the class, the judgment, the argument, the induction, the interpretation, and the system. In accordance with these distinguishable products, the intellect is said to perform all the acts which require the several powers or faculties of generalizing, classifying, judging, reasoning, infer- ring, explaining, and methodizing the individual objects give^ : y 3* 58 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 53. experience. Hence the intellect is sometimes said to be endowed with as many subordinate faculties. The most obvious aid or instrument provided by Nature for furthering these processes and retaining their products, is lan- guage. For this reason the existence of language is regarded as a necessary result of the power of thought, and the use of language is regarded as the indication of its presence and exercise. The conditions of thought, as distinguished from the materials or occasions of thought which experience furnishes, are certain relations discerned and generalized by the power of thought itself. The reality of these relations is an assumed condition of these peculiar operations ; and when the mind comes to appre- hend them, it must proceed upon the belief that they are uni- versally present and incontestably valid. In this sense the mind itself prepares for itself these objects of its own apprehension. For the service of thought, all individual objects must be be- lieved to be connected or bound together under universal and ne- cessary relations or categories. Such are the relations of sub- stance and attribute, cause and effect, means and end. Thus the relation of substance and attribute is assumed as real in order to the possibility and truth of the acts of generalizing and of judg- ment. The relation of cause and effect must be presupposed to give meaning and force to acts of reasoning and explanation. The relations of design are the prefatory conditions of acts of in- duction. But universal or generalized objects presuppose the ex- istence of individual concepts and their relations. To individual beings and events, space and time relations are presupposed. Therefore, in order to the products of thought, the intuitions of space and time are presupposed. These relations are said to be a priori, for the reason that they are presupposed in these processes. They are called intuitions, categories, primitive cognitions, etc., etc. They are said to be universal, because applicable to every indi- vidual object in the way explained. They are necessary notions, because they are necessarily applied by the mind in all its thought-activities, and to all thought-objects. They are, however, no more necesary to thought than they are to presentation and representation. We imply and suppose them as truly, though not as conspicuously, in perception and § 53. ITS FUNCTION, DEVELOPMENT, AND FACULTIES. 59 consciousness, in memory and imagination, as we do in classifica- tion and reasoning. But it is by means of thought that we discern and define these categories. It is only as we use thought-processes critically — i. e., as we generalize and analyze our own mental processes — that we discover these relations as everywhere and necessarily present. Though they are actually present as the conditions and elements of all our knowing, it is only by thought that we discover and demonstrate their presence and their application, as the conditions of all knowledge. In view of the two methods in which the thought power is employed, the power itself has been sub- foJms oPthought! divided by many writers into two: the elabora- tive faculty, as performing the processes, and the regulative, as furnishing the rules — or more properly as prescribing the sphere and possibility — of thought. These are named also the dianoetic and the noetic faculty. By some writers they are distinguished as the understanding and reason, in a usage suggested by Kant, but deviating materially from his own. Milton and others call them the discursive and intuitive reason. We prefer to say that the analysis of the thinking power involves two heads of inquiry : (1.) What are the several processes of thought of which the intellect is capable in the order of their development, the man- ner of their action, their conditions, and their products ? So far as psychology prosecutes these inquiries, it considers them sub- jectively as processes of the soul. When we go further, and proceed to define their products as expressed in language, to derive rules to direct the knowing processes or to test what is known, psychology passes over into the service of logic. (2.) What are the ultimate relations or categories which thought brings to light, and, which, all knowledge presupposes ? What is their authority and trustworthiness ? What is their re- lation to special acts of knowledge? What application can be made of them to the discovery of truth and the detection of error? Last of all, how can they be applied to vindicate man's confidence in his own knowledge, and in his very power to know ? All these questions when prosecuted with reference to the sub- 60 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 53. jective power of the soul to evolve and apply these intuitions, belong legitimately and necessarily to psychology. So far as the intuitions themselves, objectively considered, are made the subjects of analysis and discussion; so far as their relations to one another, and the structure of human knowledge, are examined : so far, in short, as they are made the subject of critical or speculative discussion, they lead us within the field of metaphysics, ontology, or speculative philosophy, for which, as has been already explained, psychology is the direct and neces- sary preparation. We divide therefore, our treatise into Four parts, with the following titles : I. Presentation ; II. Kepresentation ; III. Thought; IV. Intuition; the last two being devoted to Thought proper and Thought critically applied to the analysis of knowledge and the discovery of the categories or ultimate rela- tions which are the conditions of its processes and products. For the explanation and justification of this division we must refer to the foregoing remarks, and the subsequent treatment of the topics themselves. THE HUMAN INTELLECT. PART FIRST. PRESENTATION AND PRESENTATIVE KNOWLEDGE. CHAPTER I. CONSCIOUSNESS — NATURAL CONSCIOUSNESS. § 54. We begin with presentative knowledge. „ ° e Consciousness Of objects presented to the mind there are two classes : defi n ned - Vari- . „ °usly applied. objects of matter, and objects of spirit. Corresponding to these two classes of objects, two powers or faculties are distin- guished, viz., consciousness and sense-perception. We shall first treat of consciousness. It is briefly defined as the power by which the soul knows its own acts and states. The soul is aware of the fleeting and transitory acts which it performs ; as when it perceives, remembers, feels, and decides. It also knows its own states ; as when it is conscious of a continued condition of intellec- tual activity, a gay or melancholy mood of feeling, or a fixed and enduring preference. Whether the state is in such cases in fact prolonged, or only repeated by successive renewals, we need not here inquire ; it is sufficient that states of the soul are distin- guished from acts by their seeming continuance. Again, the terms conscious and consciousness are often applied to any act whatever of direct cognition, whether its object be in- ternal or external. In other words, they are used as equivalent to knowing, perceiving, etc., or to knowledge in any form. Thus we say, ' I was not conscious that you were in the room ;' or, ' I was not conscious that he was speaking ;' as well as, ' I was not conscious of being angry.' In cases like these the terms designate an act of simple perception and knowledge. The rea- 61 62 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 54. son why they come to do so is, that every act of knowledge, what- ever be its nature or object, is attended by consciousness. Tne phrase, ' I was not conscious that you were in the room/ is ex" plained as meaning, ' I was not conscious of seeing you in the room.' Consciousness is also employed as a collective term for all the psychical states. In the words of Sir William Hamilton, " it is a comprehensive term for the complement of our cognitive ener- gies." Every such state or energy is attended by consciousness ; it is an act or state of which we are conscious, or, as we some- times say, it is a conscious act or state. The sum-total of all such acts is therefore expressively described as the consciousness of an individual. It is equally true that we are conscious of our states of feeling, and these may also be designated by the same general and comprehensive term, though with somewhat less pro- priety. Consciousness is often figuratively described as the ' witness ' of the states of the soul, as though it were an observer separate from the soul itself, inspecting and beholding its processes. It is called the 'inner light/ 'an inner illumination/ as though a sudden flash or steady radiance could be thrown within the spirit, revealing objects that would otherwise be indistinct, or causing those to appear which would otherwise not be seen at all. Appellations like these are so obviously figurative, that it is surprising that any philosopher should use them for scientific purposes, or should reason upon, or apply them with scientific rigor. The terms, conscious and consciousness explain their own meaning, and confirm the truth of the assumption and belief that the fact is true which this language implies. They de- scribe a knowing with, or within the knowing agent, and they imply that the states of the human soul may be known by the soul to which they pertain. The power of the soul thus to know itself is often called the internal, or the inner sense. This term is suggested by analogy. As the soul, by the external sense or senses, apprehends the pro- perties and qualities of matter, so it is said to know its own states and powers by another, i. e., an inner sense. Consciousness has also, for the same reason, been called by many philosophers, as Leibnitz, ad- or ap-perception, by which § 55. CONSCIOUSNESS. C3 term the same fact is recognized that the word consciousness im- plies, viz., a perception of the mind's own activities, in addition to the perception of the objects of those activities. The term Beicusstseyn, and its cognates in the Teutonic languages, recognizes the distinct — rather than the accompanying — knowledge which consciousness always involves. It describes a be-, rather than a co?i-knowing ; i. e., the clear and completed knowledge which the mind usually attains by a second and more attentive look. Hence it is with eminent propriety applied to that knowledge which the soul has of its inner states, as this, to be of any service, must be earnest and attentive. The word in German, however, is not so closely limited to this internal knowledge, as is consciousness, in English. It is supplemented by self-consciousness — Selbst-beicusstseyn. Hence sometimes, when we should use consciousness only, the Germans would say self-consciousness. Their more usual technical appellation for the power is the inner or internal sense. Reflection is the appellation used by Locke for this power ; or, more exactly, it is under this appellation that he discusses its nature and authority. Hence, among many English writers re- flection is freely used as the exact equivalent of consciousness. It is the great and distinctive merit of Locke to have called at- tention to this as a separate source of knowledge, and to have claimed for the knowledge which it furnishes equal authority and certainty with that which is received through the senses. We quote a passage memorable in the history of psychology. 6< The other fountain from which experience furnisheth the understanding with ideas, is the perception of the operations of our own minds within us, as it is employed about the ideas which it has got ; which operations, when the soul comes to reflect on and consider, do furnish the understanding with another set of ideas, which could not be had from things without ; and such are perception, thinking, doubting, believing, reasoning, knowing, tcilling, and all the different actiDgs of our own minds; which we, being conscious of, and observing in our- selves, do from these receive into our understandings as distinct ideas as we do from bodies affecting our senses. This source of ideas every man has wholly in himself; and though it be not sense, as having nothing to do with external ob- jects, yet it is very like it, and might properly enough be called internal sense. But as I call the other, sensation, so I call this reflection, the ideas it affords being such only as the mind gets by reflecting on its own operations within itself/' — Essay, Book ii. chap. i. § 4. § 55. Consciousness is exercised in two forms, or species of activity, viz., the natural or spontaneous Two . foms of r J ' ■*■ consciousness. and the artificial or reflective. They are also called by some writers the primary and the secondary consciousness. The one form is employed by all men ; the other is attained by few. 64 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §56. The first is a gift of nature and the product of spontaneous growth ; the second is an accomplishment of art and the reward of special discipline. The natural precedes the reflective iu the order of time and of actual development. But it does not differ from it in kind, only in an accidental element, which brings its results within our reach and retains them for our service. This is the general conception which we form of both, as preliminary to the special consideratiou of each. The capacity to attend to the psychical states in the lowest appreciable degree — i. e., with that energy which leaves any per- manent product or result for the memory or imagination — is matured by the slow education of infancy and childhood (§ 64) During this period, even under the most favorable circumstances the growth and development of consciousness is steady, but slow. Where consciousness is energized by attention, and applied to psychical phenomena for scientific purposes in the interest of psychological science, it is called the secondary, the artificial, the philosophical or reflective consciousness, or simply, reflection. As such, it is distinguished from and contrasted with the primary the natural, the common, the unreflecting consciousness, or simply, consciousness. The division indicated by these con- trasted terms is convenient and important. It should always be remembered, however, that the two so-called species of conscious- ness do not differ from one another in kind, but in degree, and that there is no well-defined and sharp line of distinction that divides off the one from the other. § 56. We notice first the natural, or primary con- Natural con- , . . J sciousness as sciousness. Natural consciousness is the power which an act. . the mind naturally and necessarily possesses of know- ing its own acts and states. It may be further described by considering it in its operation and its objects, or as consciousness the act, and consciousness the object. We begin with consciousness the act. As an act, it is a neces- sary and essential constituent of many active conditions of the soul. The soul cannot know, without knowing that it knows. It cannot feel, without knowing that it feels ; nor can it desire, will, and act, without knowing that it desires, wills, and acts. Consciousness is an act of knowledge, and is therefore an act purely and simply intellectual. The states observed may be § 56. CONSCIOUSNESS. 65 psychical, in any form, i. e., states of intellect, sensibility, or will — but the act by which they are known is intellectual only. It is an act of direct or intuitive knowledge. To attain it, neither memory nor reasoning are required, nor any indirect process or succession of acts, but the soul immediately knows . its present condition or act. It confronts it face to face. It knows it as now existing. It is eminently presentative knowledge. Consciousness, as an act of knowledge, is matured into, or results in a peculiar product. When it is complete, it furnishes for the mind's recall an idea of the object known. This is a purely intellectual result. What the mind is conscious of may be a state of knowledge, feeling, or choice, but the feeling and choice which we reproduce in memory is not a feeling or choice, but our idea or image of a feeling or choice, and this is purely intellectual. As an act of knowledge, it involves the discern- ment of relations (§ 45). We know the state to be our own; i. e., we discern its relation to the ego. We know that the present is not the past state of the soul ; i. e., we know the two under the relations of contrast and of time. Again, the know- ing agent distinguishes itself as the conscious observer from itself and its own states as the object observed. Like every act of knowledge it is at once an act of analytic separation and synthe- tic union. The act of consciousness is a peculiar intellectual act — an act that is preeminently sui generis. Especially is it peculiar in the conditions of its exercise. To most of the other acts of know- ledge it is required that their objects should exist before they are known. But in this peculiar process the object and act are blended in one. Thus, the landscape on which I gaze is a per- manent object, to which I can bring and from which I can with- draw my mind. The thought or feeling which I remember must have been experienced in order that it may be known a second time. It is rashly concluded by many that this is a necessary and universal condition of all knowledge. What is as- serted of consciousness violates, as is objected, the first and essential requirement, that something should have existed, in order to be known. ' How can I know that I know/ it is urged, 1 unless I have first known, in order to furnish an object for me to know ?' Or it is concluded that consciousness is, at best, but a 6Q THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 57. kind of memory, an act that immediately follows the act or state of which we are said to be conscious. " No one," says Herbert Spencer, " is conscious of what he is, but of what he was sl moment before. That which thinks, can never be the object of direct contemplation ; seeing that, to be this, it must become that which is thought of, not that which thinks. It is impossible to be at the same time that which regards and that which is re- garded." {Principles of Psychology, Part i. chap, i.) The force of this objection lies in the assumption, that every thing which is known must have already existed. But this assumption is unauthorized. It is founded on a supposed analogy between this and other acts of knowledge. It by no means follows, because the landscape must have existed before we see it, or the mental state must have occurred before we remember it, that a perception or feeling must be past before we can be conscious of it. Besides, how can one remember that which he did not know at the time when it occurred ? How can one recall the state in which he was a moment before, and know that he had been in that state, if he was not conscious of it at the precise instant in which it occurred ? Those that resolve acts of consciousness into acts of memory, make an act of memory itself impossible. The remembering act necessarily follows the act which is re- membered however closely. We cannot recall the act itself, nor that it was our own act, unless we knew both, when the act occurred. § 57. From the consideration of consciousness the consciousness ac ^ we pass to consciousness the object. The object of consciousness has already been defined to be an act or state of the soul ; more exactly, the soul acting and suf- fering in an individual state. That such an object should be peculiar and unlike any other, we are prepared to believe, by what we have already noticed under consciousness as an act. Other peculiarities will reveal themselves to a closer inspection. We observe, in general, that objects of consciousness are unlike the phenomena of matter in this, that they are given to observation a3 essentially complex even in their greatest simplicity. Every state or condition of the spirit in actual experience and as known by the soul, is complex, even in its extremest simplicity. The object is threefold in its elements, every one of which must § 58. CONSCIOUSNESS. 67 be recognized by the conscious spirit. The elements are, the identical ego, either agent or patient according as the case may be ; the object with respect to which it acts or suffers ; and the pre- sent state or action in which it exists or acts. Every psychical state of which we are conscious implies an acting or existing ego, to which the state pertains. A condition of the soul without an in- dividual person acting or feeling, is impossible as a conception, and is never experienced as a fact. Again, this ego is known to be in a definite form or condition of action or suffering. The states are transient, the agent remains. The states are as fleeting and as transitory as the flying moments ; indeed, they come and go more swiftly than any instants which we can count ; the indi- vidual self remains unchanged, referring all these changes to itself. Again, the ego, in its acting and suffering, is concerned with some object. It must have some object to be employed upon, either material or mental. One state is as often distin- guished from another by its object, as by any thing besides. These are the elements which make up that complex whole which we call the object of consciousness. § 58. It is a natural question, What is the relation of consciousness to each of these essential constituents, nt I^}° n ^l ' consciousness either as combined together in a general view, or as each dements* of a calls forth special and separate attention ? To this ^ t c e hical question we give this general preliminary answer: -The soul, in consciousness, is directly cognizant of all these ele- ments, as entering into every one of its states. It knows them as distinguishable from one another, and yet as, in their union, con- stituting a single whole. Here we observe that, in an act of direct or intuitive knowledge like consciousness, it is as essential that the connecting relations should be apprehended, as the parts which they bind or connect. In logical analysis, the parts are considered separately, and to each we assign a separate word or phrase ; but in the synthesis of real knowledge the parts are viewed together. The verbal ex- pression of a mental state is not a single word, as I, perceive [or] love, this apple, each apprehended apart, and then somehow aggre- gated into a phrase or proposition ; but it is a finished proposi- tion, in all its parts and relations, as, I perceive [or love] this apple. In other words, we can analyze or separate only 68 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §§ 59, 60. what is given as united in the concrete or real. If the parts and connecting relations ane not discerned together by an intuitive act, they can neither be separated nor united by any other act or process. The objects known by consciousness are intuitively known. All the materials which mediate or abstract knowledge evolves from these objects, the objects must be known already to involve. But though these elements are always recognized in every object of which we are conscious — i. e., in every conscious mental state — they are not regarded with equal attention. According as one or other of these elements receives the chief attention and is most absorbing, so is each state of consciousness definitely and peculiarly marked. We will consider the predominance of each of these elements siugly and apart. § 59. First let the sours own activity be the special The activity may be chiefly object of its own conscious observation. The states come and go, they rise and fall, they are varying and restless as the waves of the ocean, each pushing forward the one that went before. Moreover, these states are the products of the soul's own energy, or the sufferings or joyful experiences of its own sensibility. What can it be conscious of, if it knows not these ? For these reasons no one has ever doubted that the operation or state of the soul is the appropriate object of consciousness — is the central element, the element par eminence, if the object is believed to be complex ; the sole object, if the ob- ject is conceded to be simple. § 60. Second. Of the ego itself we are also di- oftiie 8 ?© 11811683 rect ty conscious. Not only are we conscious of the varying states and conditions, but we know them to be our oivn states ; i. e., each individual observer knows his changing individual states to belong to his individual self, or to himself, the individual. The states we know as varying and transitory. The self we know as unchanged and permanent. It is of the very nature and essence of a psychical ytate to be the act or experience of an individual ego. We are not first con- scious of the state or operation, and then forced to look around for a something to which it is to be referred, or to which it may belong. A mental state which is not produced or felt by an indi- vidual self, is as inconceivable as a triangle without three angles, § 60. CONSCIOUSNESS. 69 or a square without four sides. This relation of the act to the self is not inferred, but is directly known. The fact of memory proves this beyond dispute. In every act of memory we know or believe that the object now recalled was formerly before the mind ; in other words, I, the person remember- ing, did previously know or experience that which I now recall. But how could this be possible, if the first act or state was not known, when it occurred, to belong to the same ego which now recalls it? This truth has been extensively overlooked or denied. Thus Hume says : " For my part, when I enter most intimately into what I call myself I always stumble on some particular per- ception .or other, of heat or cold, light or shade, love or hatred, pain or pleasure. I can never catch myself at any time without a perception, and never can observe anything but the percep- tion." "If any one, upon serious and unprejudiced reflection, thinks he has a different notion of himself, I must confess I can no longer reason with him. . . . He may, perhaps, perceive some- thing simple and continued, which he calls himself, though I am certain there is no such principle in me." — Human Nature, Part iv. sec. 2. Dr. Thomas Reid says : " I am conscious of perception, but not of the object I perceive ; I am conscious of memory, but not of the object I remember." But he guards himself against the conclusion drawn by Hume from their common assumption, by insisting that, though consciousness does not give us the intuition of self, yet we have a firm belief of the reality of the self, through a native and necessary suggestion, for " our sensations and thoughts do also suggest the notion of a mind, and the belief of its existence and of its relation to our thoughts." — Inquiry, chap, ii, § 7. Dugald Stewart says : " We are conscious of sensation, thought, desire, volition, but we are not conscious of the existence of the mind itself. This is made known to us by a suggestion of the understanding consequent on the sensation, but so intimately connected with it that it is not surprising that our belief of both should be generally referred to the same origin." — Phil. Essays, p. i, c. i. Dr. Thomas Brown says of a special sensation, as of fragrance : " There will be, in the first momentary state, no separation of self and the sensation, no little proposition formed in the mind — I feel, or I am con- scious of a feeling, but the feeling and the sentient I, will for the 70 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 60. moment be the same. If the remembrance of the former feeling arise, and the two different feelings be considered by the mind at once, it will now, by that irresistible law of our nature which impresses us with the conviction of our identity, conceive the two sensations which it recognizes as different in themselves, to have belonged to the same human being — that being to which, when it has the use of language, it gives the name of self, and in rela- tion ' to which it speaks as often as it uses the pronoun I." — Lecture xi. Hamilton says : " On the other hand, as there exists no intuitive or immediate knowledge of self as the absolute subject of thought, feeling and desire, but, on the contrary, there is only possible a deduced, relative and secondary knowledge of self as the permanent basis of these transient modifications of which we are directly conscious, it follows," etc. — Notes on Reid, (jff.,) p. 29, b.— Cf. Met. Lee. 19, on Mental Unity. Mansel dissents from Hamilton on this point. (Prolegom. Log., c. v.) " I am immediately conscious of myself, seeing and hearing, willing and thinking." James Mill agrees with Brown, etc.: " To say that I am conscious of a feeling, is merely to say that I feel it. To have a feeling is to be conscious, and to be conscious is to have a feeling. To be conscious of the prick of a pin, is merely to have the seusation." — {Analysis of the Human Mind, Chap, v.) But he corrects himself in another passage, as follows : " The consciousness of the present moment is not absolutely simple, for whether I have a sensation or an idea, the idea of what I call myself is always inseparably combined with it. The conscious- ness, then, of the second of the two moments in the case supposed, [the case of remembering a preceding state,] is the sensation combined with the idea of myself, which compound I call ' myself sentient,' " etc. — {Id. Chap, x.) John Stuart Mill says, in the same strain : " My mind is but a series of feelings," and defines it as, " a thread of consciousness," " a series of feelings with a back- ground of possibilities of feeling." — (Exam, of the Phil, of Hamilton, c. 12; ef. McCosh, Fundamental Truth, etc., c. 5.) It will be found, moreover, that all those writers who deny or doubt this, do yet incidentally betray their faith in the reality which they by words or reasonings oppose. Dr. Brown, who is so earnest in opposing it, cannot thread together the several ex- periences of the soul's life, without resorting to " the irresistible §61. NATURAL CONSCIOUSNESS. 71 law of our nature which impresses us with the conviction of our identity," and James Mill himself is forced in one sentence to confess what he stoutly denies in another, " for whether I have a sensation or an idea, the idea of what I call myself, is always inseparably combined with it." These are more or less distinct acknowledgments of that direct knowledge of the ego which enters as an essential constituent into every conscious state of the soul. § 61. Third, we inquire still further, What are the relations of consciousness to the objects of the consciousness psychical acts and states? Is the soul conscious of psychical of the objects as truly as it is of the states them- selves ? When I gaze upon a landscape, and am delighted, am I conscious of the landscape which I see, as truly as I am con- scious of the act of seeing and of the delight which it gives? It is maintained that it is a gross impropriety to say that we are conscious of the landscape, except in the general sense in which we use conscious as the equivalent of knowing. Thus Reid -says in the words already cited : " I am conscious of perception but not of the object I perceive, I am conscious of memory, but not of the object I remember." The truth is, that we are conscious of the object somewhat as we are conscious of the ego. The state or operation is the central object of apprehension ; but as the state can neither occur nor be known except as haviDg a relation to the unchanging ego, so each separate state is distinguished in part by its object. This is especially true if it is preeminently a state of knowledge. We distinguish one such state from another by what we know ; e. g., in one moment I perceive a tree, in another a house, etc., i. e., I can- not be conscious that I perceive a house or a tree, unless I notice the relation of the act itself to the house or tree. We do not say that two states of knowledge cannot be dis- tinguished subjectively as well as by their objects. We know that an act of knowledge never can occur by itself without some feeling, desire and will. So, far as it is a state of feeling and will it is purely subjective. These subjective elements attract the notice of consciousness preeminently, and these mark and individualize the state to the soul's memory. But when such states are described in language or recalled to the thoughts by an explicit statement, they are described by their objects. Even a state 72 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 62. of the most absorbed feeling is indicated by the object or event which excited the emotion. We cannot conceive it possible that we should know that we know, enjoy, or choose, without knowing what we know, enjoy or choose. In other words, in being con- scious of an a*et or state, we must be conscious of the state or act in relation to, and as therefore including the object. We recapitulate thus : The object of consciousness is a state or act of the soul ; this state or act must occur or exist in order that it may be known • but it does not exist before it is known in the order of time, but only in the order of dependence, or of logical necessity. So far as the order of time is concerned, it exists while it is known. What is known of this object must depend on the nature of the matter to be known, and also on the reach or capacity of consciousness to observe it. A psychical act or state, as we have seen, is in its nature complex, consisting of three elements in intimate relation to each other: the ego; the object; the acting or suffering of the passing moment. But the act or suffering is inconceivable, except as belonging to the ego and defined by the object. Of this double relation consciousness must take notice. It must, therefore, also take notice of the terms or elements which are related. The object of § 62. We observe still further, that consciousness SsTstateo? 8 tne object, as contradistinguished from consciousness being - the act, is a state or condition of being, as contrasted with an act of knowledge. Knowledge of every kind as has been shown, supposes and requires being as its objective correlate. The being, known by consciousness, is a spiritual being, a perma- nent identical agent or producer of the states and acts which are known ; i. J remaining and the most important class. All these its organ.'coni are distinguished by this marked peculiarity, that objects'. and ^ ie V are experienced through organs specially con. structed for the sole function cf sense-perception. They are the so-called five senses : Smell, taste, hearing, touch, and sight. Each of these is clearly distinguished from every other, and to each of them is assigned its own organ or organs. The organ of smell is the nostrils, which open into the two § 92. CLASSES OF SENSE-PERCEPTIONS. Ill nasal fossae, the plates of which are overlaid by a mucous mem- brane called the pituitary membrane. The passages between these plates are somewhat tortuous, giving extent of surface for the expanse of membrane, and the ramifications of the olfactory nerve. This organ is in immediate contiguity with the organs of taste, with which it acts in ready sympathy. Offensive smells occasion nausea and disinclination to food. Savory odors, on the other hand, stimulate the appetite. It is generally believed that smell is excited only by the con- tact of the interior surface of the organ with minute portions of matter, or gases diffused through the atmosphere. But what- ever uncertainty there may be in respect to the occasions of these sensations, with the sensations themselves we are all familiar. Their varieties are almost endless. The odors from flowers, from food, from perfumes, from woods, from earths, from metals, and from many other objects, are too numerous to be classed or named except in a very general way. We class them in a few general and obvious groups, as quickening, refreshing, depressing, sicken- ing, aromatic, spicy, etc., etc. "We name them usually from the objects which excite them, as the odor of the violet and the lilac, of the rose and the tuberose, of the peach and the apple, of cedar and camphor-wood. It is to be remembered that the so-called sensations are in truth sense-perceptions — i. e., they involve apprehended relations of externality and extension. The experience of every odor t according to the explanation already given, must be referred to some part of the sensorium. These sensations are, however, very undefined in their places and limits, and hence it has been sup- posed they are purely psychical. They cannot be distinctly recalled in the imagination or memory. Hence,' in our actual perceptions of objects, they are referred directly to the object as seen or handled. That is, the object seen or touched occupies the attention and engrosses the memory, and not the object smelled. The language and terms taken from this sense are transferred to supersensual objects, especially to the moral and the religious. The odor of incense, the offense that is rank, -and smells to hea- ven, and the like, are examples of such an application. 112 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 93. § 93. The organs of taste are the tongue, the palate, aad S o e bje°c| ans and a portion of the pharynx. These are also truly, Jensa e tk.ns f . the though imperfectly, organs of touch ; but they are coated with a membrane which is organized in such a manner as to yield a variety of special sensations called tastes. The tasting organ, so far as it can be traced, consists of minute papillae, which cover the upper surface of the tongue and the inner cavity of the mouth. Sapid substances to be prepared for tasting, must be made liquid. Those which are hard and compact, must be broken by mastication and dissolved in the saliva. The harder the sub- stance and the slower the process of dissolving, the longer does the taste continue. The sensations of taste are various in kind and almost count- less in number. They are capable of being so combined as to produce singular modifications and striking contrasts. They can thus, to some extent, be changed by custom and formed by art. Tastes that are at first positively disagreeable, become pleasant by being connected with a stimulant effect upon the nervous sys- tem — as the pungent and fiery taste of strong liquors, and the nauseating taste of tobacco. Or the sense-organ itself becomes less sensitive- in its energy, and of course less offended by the sen- sations which were at first more intense, and therefore positively disagreeable. Tastes, like smells, are designated by a few general epithets, as pungent, bitter, sweet, spicy, acrid, sharp ; more precisely by the objects which occasion them, as the taste of pepper or alum, of the peach or the plum, of different vegetables and meats. Of this language or vocabulary of taste we may say in general, that it is taken originally from the sense of touch, as the obvious meaning of some of the terms, and the less obvious roots of others, both indicate. The reason is obvious. The organ of taste is also an organ of touch. The tongue touches as well as tastes. Cer- tain tastes are attended with certain touches. It ought not to escape our notice in this connection, that the sense of the beautiful and the .sublime in nature, art, and litera- ture, and the capacity for judging rightly of its occasions or sources, is called taste in many languages ; a singular transfer of a term from one of the grossest of the animal capacities to one §94. CLASSES OF SENSE-PERCEPTIONS. 113 of the highest of the psychical endowments. It is explained by the fact that the corporeal sense of taste is susceptible of fine and delicate discriminations. The question is never mooted, whether the sensations of taste are purely subjective, or independent of all relations of exter- nality and extension. Taste, as a sensation, is inconceivable ex- cept as an affection of that part of the sensorium which pervades the surface of the tongue-and palate. § 94. The sense of hearing comes next in order. Hearing . ita Its organ is a complicated and convoluted bony tube ? e r c g t a s n an ^ b " or chamber, resembling somewhat the interior of a snail-shell, and furnished externally with an expanded append- age, the surface of which is corrugated very much after the man- ner of the bony passage within. The object of the external ear (which with the internal constitutes the organ), is to receive, con- vey, and quicken the vibratory action of the air till it reaches the tympanum. This is a parchment-like substance, which, by the aid of a chain of bones, bears upon a liquid within. The arrange- ment of this entire structure, when judged by mechanical prin- ciples, is obviously adapted and designed to carry and increase vibratory action. But the vibrating tympanum is not itself hear- ing. Though we seek for the spirit of sound in all these narrow and winding chambers, we cannot find it there ; but it flees from our search like a shadow or a mocking spirit. It is the soul which lives in the sensorium that hears. "When the tympanum is made to vibrate with the requisite intensity and rapidity, and the nervous apparatus is unharmed, the soul, if attent, experiences the sense-perceptions which we call the sensations of sound. Every body which emits or conveys sound is susceptible of vibration. The sonorous body with which we are most familiar, is the atmosphere, which, by being everywhere present, is the constant and the pervading medium of sound. Many solid bodies are, however, capable of more delicate vibrations, and hence are more perfect conductors of sound ; or perhaps they owe their effect on the sensorium in part to the vibrations which touch conveys through the bony structure. A stick of timber will con- vey to the ear in contact with it, a whisper or the scratch of a pin, scores or hundreds of feet. If the ear is brought into con- 114 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 94. tact with a musical instrument, either directly or through the medium of some intervening substance, the intensity of the sound is greatly increased. Of these sensations there is a great variety. What The sensations ... various, in deserves especial notice is, that each one of this end- what respects .. ,.,,.. . distinguisna- less variety is readily distinguished from every other, and very many of them can be recalled and re- cognized. A single human voice is capable of emitting a great variety in respect to quality, tone, and pitch. The voice of each individual has its distinguishable characteristic in each of these particulars. The wind sighs and whistles and groans in the forest, or beats and rolls among the clouds like resounding waves. Almost every substance has a sound of its own when it strikes or falls upon another, and this sound can be varied in quantity and quality. Single sensations of sound are distinguished by quality, by in- tensity or loudness, and by volume or quantity. Besides these obvious differences, there are others less discernible to common apprehension, which are observed and named by elocutionists and musicians. The epithets which we commonly hear are such as low and high, feeble and loud, soft and harsh, smooth and rough — sweet, gentle, clear, piercing, light, heavy, etc., etc. All these epithets were originally appropriated to the other senses, especially to those of touch. Some few are derived from taste and sight. To a limited extent, sounds are named from, the objects which excite them : as the bell and glass, like the wooden, the metallic, etc., etc. Besides these distinguishing differences in single Sounds in sue- . ° ° i • i i i cession and sensations of sound, there are others which oelong to combination. , . .. , . . o i Melody and souuds when in succession and combination, bounas of almost any quality become pleasing when uttered in any regular succession ; especially when a series is made to repeat and to return upon itself, and its measures or intervals are marked by accent or beat. Examples of these are the beating of a drum to a tune, the rhythmical measure of well-sounding prose, or the more regular and marked repetitions of poetic verse. If the sounds possess musical quality, these repetitions constitute melody, giving exquisite sensuous pleasure to the ear, and, by expression, speaking movingly to the soul. To this is § 94. CLASSES OF SEX3E-PERCEPTIONS. 115 superadded the more refined attribute of harmony, when sounds of different musical quality are given in concord, greatly enlarg- ing, enriching, and elevating both the sensuous and expressional resources of music. Melody and harmony combined, when added to what culture has done for the voice, and art for the improvement of instruments, are the grounds of the elevated en- joyment that music affords. The sensations of sound are invested with even a higher interest, and applied to a still more elevated of oral ian- use. Without the sense of hearing, vocal utterances presaive of do not become sounds ; and without vocal utterances as heard, there could be no language. As addressed to and af- fecting the senses, sounds are pleasing or displeasing, musical and melodious or the contrary, harmonious or discordant ; as significant of human thought and feeling, they are endowed with a wondrous and almost a sublime power. When we listen to a foreign language of which we are ignorant, or when we cannot catch the sense of our mother-tongue, it is to our ears a jargon or a chatter, or, at best, but a pleasing now of insignificant sense-perceptions. But as soon as these sounds are understood, they become the audible expressions of thought, in its most subtle distinctions and its most complicated connections. Not only are sounds significant of thought ; they also express feeling. Even simple and inarticulate tones do this, especially if the tones are musical, or partake of musical quality. The whine of the beggar, the command of the master, and the threat of the enraged, are expressive as tones, even when no words are uttered, or when the uttered words fail to be understood. A plaintive or a triumphant strain of music is easily interpreted, though no thoughts are uttered in words. But when thought and feeling are both conveyed, the one by clear and well-chosen words, and the other by an expressive elocution, and the soul is enraptured and elevated by eloquent speech, then the resources of sound and the importance of hearing begin to be appreciated. When, again, poetry and music lend both grace and expression to thought and feeling, we have a stiil higher example of the dignity of a single sense, and the wondrous uses to which it may be. applied in the service of the soul. In view of these relations, the sense of hearing has been 116 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 95. ranked higher than any other. It effects a connection between one soul and another ; it enables the spirit to breathe out feelings which even articulate speech cannot utter. Its dignity and: worth are especially illustrated in the case of the blind. It is to them the subtle interpreter of those emotions, which are ex- pressed to others by the eye, the countenance, the attitude, and the gesture all combined. To the blind the voice softens in tender- ness, thrills with love, is harsh from anger, and lingers in entreaty. To them every tone breathes some shade of emotion. An intelligent and educated blind man once remarked with great energy, " The human voice is to me the divinest endowment of man." § 95. The sense of touch comes next in order. The The sense of ° J m touch, its organ of this sense is the skin. The skin is the ex- ternal covering of the body, and the lining of certain internal cavities, as the mouth. Its sensations depend on the action of certain minute papillce, which are placed beneath the external cuticle, each one of which encloses the termination of some nerve, or nervous branch or branchlet. Different portions of the skin are more or less sensitive, and the perceptions which are gained through them are more or less delicate, accord- ing to the number of the nerves and the fineness and frequency of the nervous terminations. The thickness or thinness of the external covering or cuticle is also an important circum- stance. In general, those portions of the body in which the perceptions are least acute and discriminating are the most scantily supplied with nerves, and their branches extend over a very large surface — in some cases over several square inches. In the more sensitive parts of the body, on the other hand, there are very many distinct nerves and nervous branches and branchlets. The distinguished physiologist, E. H. Weber, was the first who instituted a series of careful experiments, in order definitely to ascertain the different degrees of sensitiveness in touch of differ- ent parts of the body. He applied for this purpose the points of a pair of dividers, which were separated more or less widely. Pie ascertained that in some parts of the body these points could not be perceived as separate, unless the dividers were opened as widely as three inches ; while in others the extremities needed to be only the thirty-sixth of an inch apart in order to be distinctly § 96. CLASSES OF SENSE-PERCEPTIONS. 117 perceived. Similar experiments have been made by other physi- ologists. The tip of the tongue, the lips, and the ends of the fingers, are the most sensitive and discriminating portions. The human hand, inasmuch as it is lined with a sensitive covering, and — through its connection with the arm and shoulder, and its division into thumb and fingers — is provided with an apparatus especially adapted to regulate and direct the application of touch and pressure, is preeminently the organ of touch. It is an essential condition of a sense-perception of touch, that the object should be actually applied dE^touch" to or brought in contact with the organ — i. e., with some portion of the surface of the body. According as this application is made with greater or less force, the sensation varies in intensity and the perception in distinctness, and sometimes the quality of the sensation is changed. A light pressure or gentle touch, is usually favorable to distinct or delicate perception. If the pressure is increased, the sensation may become excessive and unpleasant, and even positively painful; while the per- ception is less acute, owing, probably, to the compression of the nerve or nerves. In some cases, the very slightest contact that is possible, with a careful avoidance of pressure, as in the touch of a feather, is attended with the greatest sensibility and the acutest discernment. But the force of the application of the organ to the object of touch depends usually on muscular effort. It scarcely ever can happen that muscular effort is not called into requisition, either in positive and direct pressure, as of the hand or finger, or in withholding from pressure beyond a certain degree, or in resisting pressure when it is imposed from without. § 96. Hence it is that the muscular sensations always attend and often seem to be blended with the J^fJ^i 6eu " perceptions that are appropriate to touch. In the ac- touch ed slia. quired or complex perceptions of touch, these muscu- £° u n c s h ° f gentle lar sensations play a conspicuous part. In the classi- fications of common life and in those of the earlier philosophers, — both psychologists and physiologists, — the muscular sensations were assigned to the sense of touch. So were the sensations of temperature, many of which arise from contact with a body warmer or colder than the touching organ, and hence were referred to touch proper. Inasmuch as these various classes of 118 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 96. sensations are all concerned in many of the perceptions of touch, it is necessary to consider each apart. The first class are the sensations of gentle touch, or of touch proper. These sensations are occasioned more frequently by feeling an extended surface, but they may, and often do, arise from gentle contact with the extremity of a pointed body. Sen- sations thus arising are neither pleasurable nor painful, and one is scarcely distinguishable from another. Hence none of them can be readily reproduced in the memory. Pressure against a surface, or motion over it, each involving muscular sensations, seems to be required as the condition of sensations sufficiently positive and energetic to enable us to distinguish the objects themselves, and to recall to memory the sensations which they occasion. The second class are the acute and often painful Sensations in- . . , voMngvio- sensations that come from any affection that does lence or injury. . violence to the organ, as the prick of a pointed sub- stance, the cut of a knife, the stroke of a whip, the bruise from a stick. These sensations are all distinct and energetic, and occa- sion a shock to the nervous system which is more or less violent. They are more definitely localized than the sensations of touch proper, and more distinctly revived and recalled. The sensitiveness of the skin to affections of this kind is not proportioned to the sensitiveness of its touch. It has been proved by the experiments of Weber and others, that those parts of the surface of the body which are furnished with the fewest and the most sparsely ramified nerves and branches of nerves, and are the most incapable of sensations of touch proper, are none the less susceptible to exqui- site sensations of this sort. These sensations are not confined to the surface of the body, its interior portions being capable of ex- quisite suffering from pricking, cutting, and laceration. Sensa- tions of this class seem to be more nearly allied to those which we have called organic, and which are most conspicuous when an organ is injured or diseased. The third class are sensations of temperature. sensations of These arise usually from contact of the body with temperature. J some material .object differing m temperature from itself. They are also experienced, by what is called radiation, from an object not in contact with the body. In such cases the §96. CLASSES OF SENSE-PERCEPTIONS. 119 body may be said to be in direct communication or contact with the heated atmosphere, or the vibrating medium of heat. The sensations of temperature are, in many particulars, like the pain- ful sensations which we have just described. They are like them in not being confined to the surface. In case of scalding from water or steam, or of a severe burn from fire, or of violent internal inflam- mation, or of febrile excitement, their causes are purely internal, and the affections are organic. The sensitiveness of the body to heat and cold is not proportioned to its susceptibility to touch. The fourth class are the sensations of pressure or . Sensations of weight. These, so far as they are definite and pecu- pressure and liar, are the slightly benumbed and painful feeling which a weight occasions when laid upon the hand or arm, when there is no muscular effort to sustain or resist the pressure. In such a case slight additions may be made to the bulk of the body imposed, without being perceived. If the same experiments are made upon the parts of the body which are more mobile — as upon the lips, when resistance and muscular effort is provoked and made necessary — minute differences will be perceived and appreciated. Accurate experiments of this kind were made by Weber, eliciting surprising results. Hence the so-called sensa- tions of weight are very largely complex in their nature, consisting largely of muscular sensations. The fifth class are the muscular sensations, which have been already sufficiently characterized. Not sensatTon^" ar only do they enter very largely into the sensations of weight, but into all those sensations which require motion upon, and application to, the surface of the body which is touched. The sensations of the rough and smooth, of the adhesive and slippery, of the elastic and non-elastic, are of this character. According to the nicety with which these sensations are distinguished, is the delicacy of perception. Success in any manual art depends upon this sort of delicacy. Skill in sewing, engraving, and drawing, in the handling of tools, in driving, rowing, and playing on musical instruments, depends on the natural capacity for and the nice attention to these muscular sensations. They are equally, if not more important, to our judgments of form, size, distance, and the various relations of extension, as we shall see in consid- ering the acquired perceptions. 120 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 97. One feature all these sensations share in common. caSzed.° ns °" Though sufficiently alike to be classed together as tactual, muscular, etc., etc., yet they differ in quality according to the part of the body which is their seat. The tactual sensations on the palm are different from those on the back of the hand ; those on the hand are different from those on the different parts of the arm, and so on through every portion of the surface of the body. The same is true of the different muscular sensations. The muscular sensations which attend the opening and closing of one finger, differ from those which are experienced in opening and shutting the hand. Those which we feel in managing the arm differ from those which are used in controlling the position of the head. The same is true of the other classes of sensations which are appropriate to the interior of the trunk or the vital organs. This fact is of great import- ance in the explanation of the acquired perceptions. § 97. From considering the sensational element peTo? ToS™ in touch, we pass to the perceptional. By percep- tion proper, in touch, as in the other senses, we ap- prehend objects as extended and external. To touch has been assigned especial superiority in these discriminations. Many limit them exclusively to touch, making it the only agent through which we perceive, and assigning to all the other senses the sensational function only. Others, as we have already said, limit perception proper to touch and sight. We have given our reasons for holding that through every sensation, and of course in connection with every one of the senses, we perceive — i. e., we apprehend objects as extended and external. The perceptions of touch, however, differ from those of the other senses not- only in being more definite and minute, in consequence of the greater energy of the sensations, but also (with the exception of sight) in their immeasurably superior variety. For this reason they deserve special consideration. Let it be observed as a preliminary, that we do rSl'lity toK not, by touch alone, know mathematical extension, by* SKSum n( > r mathematical qualities, nor the relations of pure !?m. the ° rgan " mathematical quantities to one another, nor to the pure or abstract space or time which we conceive to exist. We simply perceive extended and external somethings. § 97. CLASSES OF SENSE-PERCEPTIONS. 121 It is contended by many that the reason why we perceive ex- tension by touch, either exclusively, or in common with sight, is, that the organism itself is extended. We find, they say, that in those parts of the skin in which our perception of extension is the most definite and acute, the nerves and the nervous endings are most frequent ; while in those portions in which its dimen- sions are most vaguely perceived, these are more sparse. Hence it is concluded that two nervous terminations at least are re- quired for the apprehension of superficial extension. Moreover, it is urged that, as the remaining organs, except those of sight and touch, are each furnished with a single nerve only, or, at most, with a single pair, that is -the sufficient reason why, by means of these, we have no perception of extension. In touch and sight, it is said, the soul being affected by sensations through nerves placed side by side, must necessarily perceive objects as extended. This view is held chiefly by physiologists, and, among them, by the distinguished John Muller, with whom many others agree. Of this theory we observe, that it overlooks entirely the dif- ferences between the physical conditions of perception and the act of perception. It may be, and probably is, a necessary con- dition to the perception of extension by touch and sight, that many nerves should terminate side by side or be spread over an extended expanse in the organs. But it is one thing for the nervous apparatus to occupy an extended organ, and entirely another for the mind, by means, or on occasion of the sensations which follow the excitement of these nerves, to perceive an ex- tended object. The soul is not aware that it has nerves at all, or that one or more are called into action. Nor is it aware that separate parts of the skin, or other organs, are thus affected. It knows neither nerves nor extended organs as organs. The spatial arrangement of the nervous endings may be a physiologi- cal fact, but this fact does not in the least explain the apprehen- sion of extension as a psychical process. Moreover, this theory, and many others adopted by physiologists, involve the absurdity of making the soul first to know extension physiologically, in order to know extension psychologically — i. e., they require it to know the nerves as side by side, in order to know that very pro- perty which is essential to knowing one object as side by side with another. 6 122 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 98. The correct analysis of the psychical process is that as the tactual and muscular and other more subjective sensations, are called into action, they are known to pertain to the soul, as con- nected with an extended sensorium. This sensorium is known to the soul not as a collection of nerve-endings or nerve-expan- sions, but as found in various conditions of activity, involving the soul's own active sympathy of either suffering or enjoyment. All these sensations involve some relation of extension and place, very vague at first, but sure to be more positive and de- finite as soon as the soul fixes its attention upon each. The soul, as it were, occupies and pervades the sensorium as extended in all directions. Its attention is first fixed upon certain of the sensations that are most positive or energetic, both the muscular and the tactual. Then the local diversities and likenesses are noticed, and the relations of place within and upon the surface of the body become fixed. Differences in direction, form, size, etc., are known, by processes which we shall explain under the acquired perceptions. But in order to any one of these dis- criminations it must be assumed that in the original perceptions of touch, extension, the sensorium as extended in three dimen- sions, is directly perceived. Unless such knowledge is gained directly in connection with touch, it cannot afterwards be ac- quired. But tangible objects are not only known as extended ; they are also known as external. This brings us to our next division : § 98. Externality, or outness, is involved in the of %xternaiity extension which is known by the sensations of touch. Externality differs from simple diversity, or differ- ence. Diversity may pertain to objects that are purely spiritual, as a series of mental activities or mental entities. But externality as apprehended in j^erception, as ^externality! has already been explained, is the diversity or dis- tinguishability of an extended object from the spirit as non-spatial and non-extended ; and again, it is the separatc- ness or separableness of the surrounding material universe from the animated body. Both these relations are apprehended in sense-perception, and pre-eminently by the sense of touch. It is not only important, but essential, that these two meanings be not confounded. § 98. CLASSES OF SENSE-PERCEPTIONS. 123 It is also important to observe, that the externality which we perceive, is, like the extension, not abstract, but concrete; or, in more familiar terms, an external object, or an object as external. We will consider the two senses of externality in Externalit in their order. As to the first, we ask, How does the * he first si s ni ~ ' fication. soul, m touch, perceive its own body to be external to itself? We answer, — as we have done already, (§ 86), — Precisely as through the other senses, by an immediate and inexpli- cable act of its own. It perceives directly its own body as a not- self or a non-ego ; originally its own sensorium excited to sensation. We open this question a second time in connection with the sense of touch, because it has been often urged that its sensations are peculiar in revealing outness, or externality. Some — as Reid — contend that the simple sense of resistance or hardness, or that affection of the sensorium which every solid body occasions, directly suggests outness. Dr. Thomas Brown teaches that all proper tactual sensations, like other sensations proper, are purely subjective and spiritual, without the suggestions of externality and extension, and that it is only through the muscular sensations that the knowledge of the non-ego is gained. " We open the hand or the arm, as we have done in a score of previous instances, without striking against an object. All that we experience is a succession of purely subjective affections — affections simply and solely spiritual. But we strike against a wall, or other resisting medium, and we ask, What has caused this new sensation? We answer, it is not myself, for I have previously had, or rather pro- duced, only a succession of spiritual states, in a series of muscu- lar sensations. But here is a change. I have a sensation un- caused by myself, but caused by a being different from myself. There exists, therefore, a being not myself, and so I reach the non-ego, or externality." To this solution or explanation there is this fatal objection, that allowing that the order of sensations has been previously the same, and that the order is for the first time changed by some resisting object, the change would consist simply in a new subjective experience. The resisting object would give a novel sensation, but it would still be subjective. However unusual this may be, it is only subjective and psychi- 124 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 99. cal, and, according to Brown's theory, can give no relation of extension, and therefore no relation of externality. Even if in the way supposed, a cause other than the agent could be reached, it might be purely spiritual, and not necessarily spatial. All these, and every other theory of the sort, have one common weakness — that they require us, by some arrangement or series or combination of sensations purely subjective, to account for or develop an objective, i. e., an external non-ego. But it is obvious that it is not the greater or less positiveness of a subjective sensa- tion, nor any change in the order of such sensations, which would elicit a non-ego, unless this were immediately discerned by the mind itself. But what ! it may be asked, when I grasp a pebble, answered? 11 or an ivory ball, or a stick, is that which I perceive as external to myself simply the sensorium excited by the object grasped? Is this the non-ego which I perceive, and this only ? We reply, that this is the only non-ego, which we reach by direct and original perception. The question is not what is in fact first noticed in the order of time, but what is first and ultimate in the analysis of thought. But do we not perceive also the object which produces these sensations? Do we not directly perceive the surface of the pebble, the ball, or the stick, as diverse from the sensorium, and the body which it pervades ? Not by immediate perception. If we did, it would involve the inference that we perceive a non-ego, viz., the surface of the pebble as touched, and producing a sensation, viz., the felt sensa- tion, which is also non-ego. That is, we should have immediate perception of two non-egos — the sensorium excited, and the object exciting it to a sensation. This is possible, but it must be shown to be necessary. We shall show in its place (§ 113), that exter- nality in the second sense — i. e., the distinction of the not-body from the body — is discerned not by an original, but by an acquired perception. If this is true, it is the result, not of a single act, but of a series of processes. § 99. The sense of touch is the most positive of all touch the lead- the senses in the character of its sensations. In many respects it is worthy to be called the leading sense. The sense-perceptions which it gives, and those which are called into action in connection with it, are felt on every part of §99. CLASSES OF SENSE-PERCEPTIONS. 125 the surface, and throughout the interior of the body and all its members. The sensations themselves are the most energetic of any that we experience. Moreover, the organ of every other sense is also an organ of touch, and, as such, is more or less sensitive. We touch the food which we taste, and unless we touch it, we cannot taste it. Though the eye does not literally touch the undulating light — i. e., in response to the touch of light, gives no tactual sensa- tions — yet when the surface of the eye is pressed by the finger, or strikes against any solid object, it feels and is pained. It is also acutely sensitive at times as a touching organ. The inner surfaces of the nostril and of the ear, like the outer surface of the body, are susceptible of tactual sensations. All of these organs are more or less completely provided with a muscular apparatus, by which they are moved, directed, accommodated, and made more ready for and subservient to their appropriate sensations. Hence the tactual and muscular sensations are very intimately connected with seeing, hearing, smelling, and tasting. In view of these considerations, it was said long ago by Demo- critus, that 'all the senses are modifications of the sense of touch.' In view of these facts, touch has been called, by some physiolo- gists, general sensibility, or the power of general sensibility ; and the four remaining senses have been called the special senses. It ought not to surprise us to learn that the sense of touch furnishes most of the terms for the intel- kctuaUermsf 1 " lectual acts and states. Sight itself is indebted to touch for many of its terms. We take or apprehend a meaning ; we hold an opinion ; we comprehend or grasp a train of thought or a course of reasoning ; we accept a proposition. Especially does touch furnish the words for those acts of the intellect in which the feelings and the will have a share. The reason is obvious. We touch and handle objects in order familiarly to understand their properties and laws. The objects which we touch, and the ways we touch or handle them, are determined very largely by our feelings, whether of curiosity or indifference, of love or dislike, of caution or boldness. All these feelings are expressed through acts appropriate to the sense of touch, or by the modes of using its principal organs. Hence the spiritual 126 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 100. acts or states generally, are expressed by terms and phrases primarily applied to this class of bodily activities. § 100. The sense of sight is the last which we are Sight; its organ . ... and the condi- to consider. The organ of vision is the eye. The eye is in a structure like an optical instrument, and adapted to the retraction of light by a combination of lenses, and to the production, by this means, of a distinct miniature image of the objects seen upon the retina, i. e., the dark network of nerves which lines the inner chamber. This image can be seen in the eye of some animals if separated carefully from its socket, and divested of the sclerotic coating behind. The surface of the eye is small compared with that of the organ of touch, but it is susceptible of the readiest and most rapid motions, and of ad- justments of position and direction with little muscular effort, and as little muscular sensation as is sufficient for the discrimina- tion and regulation of its motions. This susceptibility of easy and swift motion and adjustment is one of its most remarkable physical features, and is the condition of its marvellous superiority. The conditions of distinct vision are a proper quantity of light, and the formation of a well-refracted image upon the retina. If the light is deficient or excessive in quantity or intensity, there can be no distinct vision. There is a particular distance for every eye, at which the most perfect vision of a near object can be attained. This distance varies considerably, from that of the so-called near-sighted, to that of the far-sighted. This variety is occasioned by a difference in the degree of the convexity in the lenses of the eyes of different persons, requiring a different distance of the object in order to bring the rays to a focus upon the retina. There is in every case, however, a certain range within which dis- tinct vision may be had by a more or less constrained adjustment of the retina and one or both lenses, through certain muscles provided for the purpose. The muscular sensations experienced by the adjustments of the eye in order to discern objects dis- tinctly, are important media in forming and applying tho acquired perceptions. In order that the vision by both eyes may be single — and it must be single to be distinct — the two axes must be steadily fixed upon the same point ; and in order that they may be fixed, they must be inclined together. The muscu- lar sensations, varying with the different adjustments of the two § 100. CLASSES OF SENSE-PERCEPTIONS. 127 axes are important in the acquired perceptions or judgments of vision. These conditions are completed or finished when a distinct picture on the retina is formed. This leads the image on us to consider the function of the image on the retina, or its relations to the act and the object of vision. Concerning this there is confusion and error of opinion. The mind can not see the image on the retina. If it could, it must see it by means of another image, and so on ad infinitum. Nor does it perceive the image by any direct act, knowing it to be an image on the retina. It does not know that there is a retina, till the anatomist or the optician brings this fact to its notice, nor does it know of nerves, or nerve endings, or nerve expansions, in the act of seeing, nor can it in any other way be aware of the image as an image. That its formation is essential to the act of vision, we know by physiological researches, but not in psychical ex- perience. Physiologically, we know that the one is necessary to the other. Psychically, we are not only not conscious of using it as a known means of the act of seeing, but we are conscious that we do not employ it as such an aid or means. If this fact were kept in mind, serious difficulties in the explanation of the process of vision would be set aside. For example, it has been often asked, How can we see objects upright, of which the images on the retina are inverted ? How can we see objects as single, whose images are double? The answer to questions like these, and the difficulties which they involve, is, that the mind neither knows nor uses the image in the psychical act. It is by a purely physiological analysis that it subsequently discovers such an image as the last member or link in the series of physical conditions. The act of vision as a sense-perception includes two elements, the sensational and the perceptional. The sensations proper from light and colors are g ensat i ons scarcely marked in our conscious experience as plea- p. r °P er of vi ~ surable or painful. Hence they are feebly obtrusive. They rarely if ever attract the attention except when they are painful through disease, or an excess of energy which induces abnormal action. Some colors, however, seem to give a positive sensuous pleasure, as rich violet or purple ; and a series of such colors, finely blended, occasions extreme satisfaction. So far as 128 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 101. this is aesthetic, it is not sensuous at all. The pleasure from form and outline, as distinguished from color, is still less sensuous. These facts explain why it is that the sensations of vision are less definitely located in the sensorium, and why, when the eye is known as their subject, the percepts are so readily detached from the eye and projected before it. The equally unobtrusive character of the muscular sensations which are experienced in using the eye contributes to the same result. § 101. Vision as perception proper apprehends il- P roper e ?n°vi- luminated, shaded, and colored visibilia. When we jeS'ofv^sion." ca ^ t nem objects, we do not intend that they are objects in the sense that they can be felt or handled, but that they are illuminated and colored percepts, set over against the soul by itself, and distinguished from itself by its own act of perception. The spectrum, as of a color refracted by the prism, or of a flame depicted on a screen, is a real object of vision. So is the image that seems to lurk behind a mirror, or to lie in the depth of a glassy pool. The colored network that is projected when the eyes are closed is an object. The visible percept is always colored. When we say it is colored, we include, under color, light and shade. Darkness even, is discerned by the eye only as the intensest and gravest of positive colors. This visual object is always extended. The tendedf ys eX ~ colored percept is an extended object, and it cannot be apprehended as colored without being perceived as extended also. Brown (Lectures, 28, 9) insists most earnestly that the extension is not originally given in the sense-percep- tion of color, and that we connect the two only because of an oft-experienced and inveterate association from touch. Dugald Stewart (Elements) sanctions this view. James Mill, and all the associationalists, must of necessity adopt this solution. The following suppositions refute the doctrine : If two or more bands of color are beheld by the infant which has never exercised touch, it must see them both at once ; and, if it sees them both, it must see them as expanded or extended ; otherwise it could not see them at all, nor the lines of transition or separation be- tween them. Or if a disc of red were presented in the midst of, and surrounded by, a field of yellow or blue, or if a bright baud of red were painted so as to return as a circle upon itself on § 101. CLASSES OF SENSE-PERCEPTIONS. 129 a field of black, the band could not be traced by the eye without requiring that the eye should contemplate as an extended percept the included surface or disc of red. The object of vision is, however, an extended „ ... ° 7 ' Visible exten- superfieies only. By vision only, a sphere is per- aon superficial ceived simply as a delicately-shaded circular disc. A cube is a flat surface with abruptly-shaded portions, bounded by converging lines. If we draw or paint from nature, we do it on a surface perfectly flat or even. In order to do this with truth, we must first see the object as without obtruding or receding portions. " The whole technical power of painting, says Kuskin, depends on our recovery of what may be called the innocence of the eye ; that is to say, of a sort of a childish per- ception of these flat stains of color merely as such, without con- sciousness of what they signify, as a blind man would see them if suddenly gifted with sight." (Elements of Drawing.*) Indeed, in some visible objects certain of these original aspects are apparent and obtrusive, and we cannot substitute the reality for the appearance. When, for example, we stand at the end of a long street, the lines of houses, or of trees, or posts, approach one another till they nearly meet in a point. But they do not con- verge in fact ; they are exactly parallel. It has been insisted by some that the eye perceives more than superficial extension — that we discern by vision, depth, or the third dimension ; that the eye, as it were, sees around a sphere, or along the receding sides of a cube. An appeal is confidently made to "Wheatstone's discoveries in respect to binocular vision, and the application of the same in the stereoscope. The conclu- sion very far outruns the data from which it is derived. The objects seen through the stereoscope are not in relief, but are in a superficies or plane. No third dimension exists, but the usual signs of its presence are so striking, that the mind leaps for the instant to the conclusion that it is there in fact. The experiment of the stereoscope is so far from confirming the view that the third dimension is actually seen, that it shows most decisively that it cannot be, by effecting an illusion, which is well-nigh per- fect, by means of objects drawn and actually seen upon a plane. The question has been very frequently and very ^ ' ,y J A single object earnestly discussed, " How is it possible that the seen with two mind should apprehend but a single object by means 6* 130 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 101. of two eyes ?" The question has been variously answered by physiologists. Some have insisted that one eye only is in fact used in the act of vision, the office of the second being to strengthen or reinforce the nervous or physiological action of the first. Others teach that the mind beholds two objects in fact, but passes so readily from the one to the other, as in effect to ap- prehend only one. Others have sought to solve the problem by tracing the impressions made upon the corresponding parts of each retina, through the corresponding nerves of each, to a com- mon blending or meeting-place in the organism, where the two are fused into one. So far as these facts are purely physiologi- cal, if they are to throw any light on the psychical act or object, they must assume that the mind performs the act by a conscious recognition of the retina, or the nervous apparatus, which cannot be admitted as true. The psychical act is occupied with a visible object, which, as has been explained, is colored extension. It sometimes hap- pens that, in consequence of a diseased or abnormal condition of the eye or its nervous apparatus, the mind perceives two objects, when it ought to perceive but one. How is this to be explained, and what light does the fact shed upon the relation of vision with one eye, to vision with two ? We answer : In double vision the mind beholds two similar objects in two situations. In single vision two percepts are perceived in the same part of the field of view. They must necessarily coincide. If the one overlaps the other, the one must strengthen the other. The question also suggests itself, WJiere, in rela- Original place . ^ . °° . '■ . M , . . of the visible tion to the retina or the eye, is the visible object [i. e., the variously-colored plane or disc first appre- hended] placed in the original act of vision : is it in the retina itself, or in the front of the eye? or is it projected in space — say at the proper focal distance before the eye? The question, in all its forms, supposes a more extensive or a more matured knowledge of space, distance, and position than the mind can possess when it begins to see. Position, or place, as applied to perceived objects, is relative. It supposes some objects to be fixed as starting-points, and others as standards of measuring or estimating distance from them. None such can be definitely fixed and familiar before the not-body § 102. CLASSES OF SENSE-PERCEPTIONS. 131 is distinguished from the body, and before the hand, the eye, and the parts of the external body have been fixed in their relative positions. The vague knowledge of extended matter which the sensorium gives must first be made definite by a bounding out- line; and the most familiar extra-organic objects must first be placed apart from one another, before the eye or the retina can be known as the instrument of vision, or either can be distin- guished as the place or the seat of the sense-percept. Long before these cognitions are attained, the sense-percept seen by the eye will have been carried by the hand into the space without the body, and irrecoverably connected with its correspondent touch-percepts, in the way hereafter to be described. § 102. The superiority of the eye to the other senses is owing in part to the unobtrusive delicacy of §g£™ n of a the its sensations. They do not occupy the attention and eye ' detain it from the object itself and its relations. The force and "tension of the soul's activity are given to these. Vision is capa- ble of far finer discriminations than touch. A hair of the diameter of .002 of an inch can be distinctly seen. The eye can also pass from one object to another with a swift- ness which none of the other organs can imitate. In so doing, it can place data at the service of the intellect as quickly as the intellect can use them, however rapid may be its move- ments. By its swift and wide-reaching motions it can imitate the slower and limited motions of the hand, drawing outlines, constructing figures, measuring distances, combining groups and elements, with surprising rapidity and precision. The cultivated eye sweeps across a landscape, and in an instant the mind computes the size and distance of its principal objects, and unites them together within a frame-work of mathematical relations. The minuteness of the observed distinctions, the vividness of the contrasts, the cheerfulness of the colors, the stimulus of the light, the sharpness of the outlines, enable the mind to hold fast its perceptions, to recall them vividly and at will, and to employ them for science, art, or practical life. The eye has always been estimated as the noblest of the senses; and many of the words which describe the actions of the pure intellect, as to see, to per- ceive, to discern, are taken apparently from this sense, though perhaps all are finally to be traced to the sense of touch. 132 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §103. CHAPTER V. THE ACQUIRED SENSE-PERCEPTIONS. § 103. Thus far in our inquiries we have considered cep e tio e ns! e ar r " each of the senses singly. We have seen that by acqm"rek and eacn °f these we gain peculiar knowledge. We per- ceive sights only by the eye, and sounds only by the ear. In connection with these diverse objects, we apprehend certain relations common to all, viz., externality and extension. In other words, by each of the organs we experience a determinate sensation, and apprehend an object that is both extended, and also distinguishable from the sentient and perceiving mind. But the range of our sense-perceptions is far wider than this.* We early learn to use one sense in place of another, or of several, and to apply the knowledge which is given by one, in place of that which belongs to one or more of those which are unused. Thus, if I go into a darkened room and perceive a peculiar fragrance, I know and say there is a rose or a tuberose in the apartment — though I can see or handle neither. If I hear a sound, I know it is from a piano, a guitar, or the human voice, and I know the direction from which it comes, and from how great a distance. If I look at an iron that is at glowing white heat, I say, It looks hot ; though heat- is properly felt. The two classes of sense-perceptions thus characterized are the original and the acquired. They are thus defined . An original perception is one that is gained by a single sense, when exercised alone; of an object, or in respect to its relations. An acquired perception is gained by using the knowledge given directly by one sense, as the sign or evidence of the knowledge which we might gain by another. The importance of the acquired perceptions is Importance . ■* x • ■, \ and time of manifest from the greater frequency with winch we acquired per- bring them into use, and the confidence with which ceptions. . , n « i we rely on them, as well as irom their greater con- venience. Thus, a man strikes with a hammer upon the head of § 104. THE ACQUIRED SENSE-PERCEPTIONS. 133 a barrel, and knows in an instant whether it is full or empty, without the trouble of opening it. A surgeon applies his ear to the breast of his patient, and determines whether the lungs or heart are diseased, where, and how far. An architect, by a glance of the eye, sees whether the framing of a bridge or roof is safe ; or he measures off the dimensions of its parts by the eye as accurately as he could by his hand, or an instrument. The time when many of the acquired perceptions are gained, is very early. The most important, and those which are uni- versally applied, are made in infancy, at a period earlier than the memory can recall, and by processes which the memory can- not untwine, nor any subtle analysis easily resolve. Others, which are commenced in infancy, are perfected in youth and early manhood. Many are not complete till the senses through age begin to fail, and the attention becomes less energetic and agile. We begin the education of the senses in the earliest mo- ments of infancy. The artist, the mechanic, the musician, and the observer of nature, never finish it till the organs refuse to aid and to serve the observing mind. Many of these acquisitions are made so early, that they cannot be distinguished from the original teachings of nature. In very many, the process is performed so rapidly that it is difficult for us to believe that the mind goes through any process at all, the knowledge comes so simply and directly. It is more convenient to begin with those which have been made within our memory, of which the stages and the means are within our view and at our command. We may afterward ven- ture to unravel the more delicate tissues that have been wrought by the finer and more dexterous arts of infancy, in that early yet mysterious period when Heaven lies close about us, and seems to direct the movements of the soul. § 104. The acquired perceptions of smell and of hearing invite our first attention, because they can p |!Jvepn q nTof be most readily explained. Oar first examples are 1 '^l ag . and of odors. We experience the sensations of smell, as from a lily or tuberose, from camphor or musk. We ascribe them to certain objects of given appearance and structure, with- out the use of the sight or the touch by which the appearance or structure is directly 'discerned. The ground of this confident 134 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 105. knowledge is experience. There is no reason a priori, why the fragrance of the tuberose should not proceed from the lily, and the fragrance of the lily from the tuberose ; no known cause why camphor and musk should not interchange their odors. We have simply learned by experience, that in all cases where the sensation is experienced, a certain object is present. We do the same with sounds. We hear a sound, and believe that it comes from a bell. We hear another, and know it is from a drum ; another still, and say, There goes a cart, or a coach. Each of these sounds we ascribe to its appropriate object with positive certainty, on the ground of simple experience. We not only learn in this way the objects which occasion smells and sounds, but we learn the place and direction of both. This is especially true of sounds. We know whether a ringing bell is on our right, or on our left ; whether it is high, or low : whether a military band is far, or near ; whether it approaches or recedes. That knowledge of this kind is founded on experi- ence only, is obvious from the fact, that when the usual or the assumed conditions or occasions of our knowledge are chauged, we are mistaken in respect to the place, direction, and distance of a sound, and that mistakes in respect to these lead to error in regard to the object which occasions it. The beating of our own hearts may be mistaken for a knocking at the door ; the tramp- ling of horses in a neighboring stable, and the cutting of wood in a neighboring cellar, may be thought to be within our own dwelling. The rattling of a cart on a bridge may be mistaken for distant thunder ; the humming of a mosquito, for a distant cry of alarm, or the sound of a trumpet. § 105. The acquired perceptions of sight are still ciptTons e of Per ~ more numerous and interesting. These divide them- jidged^JE selves into several classes. The first of these are the judgments of distance by size. If we know the real magnitude of an object, we judge how far distant it is by means of its apparent magnitude. If we hold any familiar object, as a globe two feet in diameter, near the eye, and then remove it slowly, it will dwindle away first to an inconsiderable ball, and then to a mere speck. If we know its real size, we judge by its apparent magnitude how far it is actually removed. So true is this, that from a magnitude that is falsely assumed, we mistake § 105. THE ACQUIRED SENSE-PERCEPTIONS. 135 as to the real distance, and are as confident and as prompt in our mistaken perception as though the data and the inference were both correct. Let a person look over the coping of a wall, or the ridge of an intervening building, and see only the spire of a miniature church — say of a bird-house — and believe it to be attached to a real church, and he will at once see it as a very distant spire. Second : We judge of magnitude by the assumed _ 1T1 J & * . ■* - Judgments of distance. When we have a correct impression of the magnitude by distance of objects, we perceive them in full size. We every day see men and other objects at long distances greatly diminished and dwarfed, and yet we do not perceive or judge them to be smaller than they really are. A lofty building viewed at a very great distance, or a tall ship far off at sea, will even seem loftier than when viewed from a position very near, from which the beholder looks upward, without distance and other aids by which to judge of their height. The most impress- ive judgments of the height of the loftiest mountains and edifices are gained by seeing them at a great distance over an intervening plain. Third: If the magnitude is unknown, or not con- sidered, we judge of distance by means of the intensity distaSTy 8 ° of the color t the sharpness of the outline, and the rela- ckarnessfetcf' tive clearness or confusion of the distinguishable parts. For example, should we view, through a tube, several trees of the same species, as the elm, the maple, or the oak, re- moved at different distances from one another, the nearest would be known by its brighter green, its more sharply defined outline, and its more clearly distinguished leaves and branches. By these circumstances, designated technically as " atmosphere" painters produce the effect of nearness or distance, with accesso- ries of relative magnitude and of more or fewer intervening objects. The traveler in Italy, especially when he goes directly from England, judges the mountains to be far nearer than they are in fact. The atmosphere is so much more transparent than that to which he is accustomed, as to reveal the outlines and face of the mountains so distinctly that he cannot believe them to be as distant as thev are. 136 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 105. Fourth: We judge also of the size of objects, by- size g by e other comparing them with other objects which are or seem e jects!° an to be at equal distance from ourselves. If the size or distance of our standard of comparison is incor- rectly taken, we misjudge altogether. Dr. Abercrombie (Intel- lectual Powers) tells us that, on going up Ludgate Hill toward the great door of St. Paul's which was open, he took several persons who were standing under the opening to be children, whom he found, on coming up to them, to be full-grown men. The reason was, that he assumed the height of the door to be less than it really was, and, by this false standard, he misjudged the size of the persons who stood under it. Fifth: Our judgments of distance vary according intermediate as there are more or fewer intermediate objects. Ob- jects seen across the land seem further than objects at the same distance seen across the water. A given expanse of the sea is greatly enlarged to the eye when a score or two of vessels are anchored at different distances along its surface. A level meadow or prairie, with copses, trees, and dwellings inter- spersed, seems far more extended than without them. A salt marsh, when dotted with haystacks, seems wider than at the season when they are removed. Sixth: Intermediate objects, by affecting our judgments of dis- tance, affect our judgments of size. The sun and moon appear larger when near the horizon than when toward the zenith. Through the influence of intervening objects and the dimming influence of the atmosphere, they are removed to a greater distance, and then judged to be larger. The sky itself, for this reason, is not the half of a sphere, but a section of which the height is shorter than half the base. When the ordinary standards of judgment are withdrawn, and our accustomed processes cannot be applied, we are either greatly embarrassed, and even bewildered, or we fall into serious and amusing errors. Captain Parry says : " We jiad frequent occa- sion, in our walks on shore, to remark the deception which takes place in estimating the distance and magnitude of objects over an unvaried surface of snow. It was not uncommon for us to direct our steps toward what we took to be a large mass of stone at the distance of half a mile from us, but which we were able § 106. THE ACQUIRED SEXSE-PERCEPTIOX3. 137 to take up in our hands after one minute's walk. This was more particularly the case when ascending the brow of the hill." § 106. By means of sight we acquire perceptions ' appropriate to the touch. When we look at a sphere, form, etc., by we see by the eye only a circular disc on which the transitions of color or of light and shade blend so finely with one another, that we know if we grasp it with our hands we shall feel it to be spherical in form. A sphere may be so skilfully painted in fresco on a^flat surface, that we actually take it to be a sphere in fact. We often seem to see projecting statues, gradu- ated mouldings, depressed panels, receding corridors, vaulted domes ; and yet as we approach, we find only a plane surface. When the blind from birth are restored to sight, they come into a new world, of the percepts of which, and their relations to the percepts already familiar to their touch, they have had no previous knowledge. They must therefore go through a special discipline in order to connect the well known objects of touch with the newly acquired experiences of the eye. Thus the blind boy whose sight was restored by Cheselden could not call the cat and dog by their right names, or could not tell which was the cat and which was the dog. He could not avoid distinguishing them by the eye, but he had not learned to connect the dog and cat as handled — to the appropriate forms of which he had attached the names — with the dog and cat which he saw, so as to be able to feel them by means of his eyes. Finding himself one day at fault, he carefully felt of the cat with his hands, his eyes being shut, and set her down, exclaiming, " So, puss, I shall know you another time." The question has been often asked (cf. Locke, Essay, B. ii. c. ix. § 8), whether a blind man, on being restored to sight, would know a cube from a sphere. It is obvious that, so far as mere vision is concerned, he could not but distinguish the two objects as soon as he attended to them with the eye. What he would need to acquire would be the capacity readily to connect the visible with the tangible cube and sphere. In the examples which have been cited, we translate the per- ceptions given by sight into those which are derived from touch. The proposition is sometimes broadly and positively laid down, 138 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 106. that from the touch is derived all perception whatever of form, distance, and magnitude ; inasmuch as in all cases, we must come back to the touch as furnishing the ultimate standard. The position is sometimes stated thus : All visible extension must be reduced to that which is tangible. These propositions need to be somewhat qualified, if we hold that we can perceive superficial extension by the sight. They are true to the letter of all those perceptions which involve the relation of depth, or the third dimension of space ; but to all judgments of superficial form and dimensions they cannot literally apply. To the blind, how- ever, touch furnishes the only possible standard of definite form, distance and size. The blind man applies his finger, his hand, or his arm, to every object which he encounters, and measures its size by any of these standards. But those who see, perceive objects extended superficially. Why, then, may they also not apply any of these objects as units of measurement, and as standards by which to judge of form and size? We reply, they may, and would do so always, if what is called the apparent magnitude of the standard, and of the object to which it is applied, did not constantly change as the two are near or remote. A yard-stick or a foot- rule may be so far removed from the eye, as to measure to the eye no more than a foot or an inch respectively. Even though the standard is unaltered in its position, the object measured may, by being itself carried near or far, measure a foot, a yard, or a rod. We can only be satisfied that the standard and its objects coincide, when we bring the standard in actual contact with the object by the hand. But even then we use the eye, in order to be certain that the two coincide. The hand of the blind, however surprising may be its delicacy of touch, can never attain the fineness of the eye in discerning exact adjustments. Give the practiced eye an assurance that its distances are correctly taken, and it will measure and judge with marvellous accuracy. It is a circumstance which is worthy of attention, and certainly ought not in this connection to be overlooked, that the point of distance from the eye at which vision is usually most satisfac- tory, coincides with that at which the hand can most conve- niently handle and hold an object. § 107. THE ACQUIRED SENSE-PERCEPTIONS. 139 § 107. It is by the acquired perceptions that we definitely assign the places of our sensations to the ^^^^t different parts of the body. ft^ n All the sense-perceptions must be known to have JJ*2-- H the some place in the sensorium, though the limits of the place may not be definitely drawn, and the relative positions of each perception may not be exactly fixed. Whatever is in- volved in such a perception taken singly, is an original percep- tion. Whatever is added or superinduced by combining several perceptions, is acquired by experience. For example : an adult person has a pain in one of his teeth, he does not know which — or a cut in a part of his arm, he does not know exactly where. If he touches the tooth with his tongue, or if he discovers in a mirror which tooth is defective, he ascertains which is the one affected ; he learns as we say, where the pain is. That much of this knowledge is acquired, is evident from some cases of lesion in different parts of the body, and of the loss of a limb by amputation. A man who has no foot, will feel pain in the foot. Why ? Because he experiences precisely the same sensations which he suffered when he had the foot, and knew it was the seat of the pain. But if he had never had a foot, he would never have assigned pain to it; for he would never have had the means by eye or hand or muscular sensations, of connecting these sense-perceptions with it. It is also by the acquired perceptions that we learn to regulate and control the movements of the body. Man was made to move. When the soul, so to speak, finds the body, it finds it in motion. Not only is this true, but the body is, by its very structure, adapted to certain specific motions, as of walking, speaking, and singing, all having definite relation either to its present or its future wants or enjoyments. These bodily capacities the soul acquires the power to use in definite ways for special ends. The motions to which nature prompts, the intellect learns to control and regulate, so as to bring to pass determinate results. A more particular consideration of this subject presents two separate questions : What does nature provide f and How does the intellect apply these provisions of nature f We ask, first : What does nature provide f 140 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §107. We have already adverted to the fact, that with The provisions J of nature for the sentient nerves which conditionate sensation, there these ends. are provided the reflex motor which impel to motion. In obedience to the stimulus furnished by the one, there is awakened in the other an unbidden and often an uncontrollable tendency to motion. Consciousness need not, and often does, not intervene. Thus, we wink in response to the stimulus of light ; the flesh quivers and withdraws itself from the knife; the muscles knit themselves into convulsions and cramps. Under the same law, the excitements being diverse, the heart beats, the lungs expand, and other involuntary motions are performed. These functions and operations relate to the body, and their effects terminate in its well-being. There are other movements that are connatural and at first in- voluntary, which the intellect has the power to apprehend and the will to control. Such are the muscular efforts that are involved in speaking, singing, and walking, and in feats of skill or dexterity. Many of these relate to the soul as well as to the body, in the way of use or enjoyment. Some of them are made ready for the spirit against the time when it shall be sufficiently developed to apply them with intelligence and design. To all these movements the stimulant comes not from without, but from within. When the infant weeps from pain, and laughs and shouts from delight, it is under an excitement proceeding directly from the soul, that the muscles are moved to laughter and to tears. In the same way, every emotion seeks and finds expression by attitudes, looks, and gestures. In the same way man is prompted to speech : first to inarticu- late cries expressing emotion only, and then to articulate lan- guage and words significant of definite thought. Nature pro- vides for all this, by making man capable of a limited range of vocal sounds, through the action of those muscles that move the larynx ; and nature prompts to the use of these muscles in various ways, according to the varying excitements of feeling and thought. To very many, if not to all of these effects, the consentient action of many muscles is required. For this nature provides, by so arranging the structure of the nerves through which these consentient muscles are excited, that, under the stimulus of feeling or thought, those needed, and those alone, § 107. THE ACQUIRED SENSE-PERCEPTIONS. 141 shall be aroused to the united activities which conspire to the single effect which is required. Not only does nature provide for the conspiring action of sev- eral muscles to one effect, but she even arranges for and prompts to the combined action of different parts of the body in obedience to a single impulse. In order to make progress by walking, each leg must alternately advance and wait for the other. To these al- ternate motions there is an original impulse. These are movements which the infant makes long before it begins to walk. The arms, on the other hand, tend to move together. So do the fingers. It is difficult, and sometimes impossible, by any effort to bring certain of the fingers to a separate action. But it is in the eyes that this tendency to joint action is most conspicuous. The eyes will persistently move together in the same direction. They cannot be forced to act apart. One eye cannot by any violence be made to look upward while the other is directed downward. Nor will one tend to the right, and the other to the left. Even more than this is true. There seems to be, so to speak, a natural aptitude for the joint action of organs that are not paired together, but which yet are fitted to aid one another in important uses. This is preeminently, true of the eye and the hand. The eye must lead the hand, and the hand follow the eye, in a multitude of actions. When we would touch or grasp a small object at the first trial, the eye must guide. When we would strike it with a stick which we hold, or with a projectile, the eye must conspire with a fixed and earnest gaze. There must be some physiological reason for this concurrent action of nerves and muscles connected with two organs, though it has not yet been discovered. We ask, second : How does the intellect apply what nahwe pro- vides. The intellect finds itself furnished with this cor- poreal instrument, and actually using it under the th^inteUect of promptings of nature ; it finds it laughing, or weep- rSs? nangc ~ ing, speaking, and walking, under the promptings of nature, and it acquires the power of directing these activities in particular methods and to certain definite results, and of doing this so readily, that-it does not notice its own processes, or advert to the elements of which these processes consist. First, it 142 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 107. observes the muscular sensations which are employed when certain effects occur, and the effects it observes by the appropri- ate sense-perceptions. It experiments upon these, and notices how the sensations which are connected with the varying use of its muscles are connected with varying effects. Then it tentatively and designedly repeats the effect which it has chanced to produce, or it seeks to imitate the effect which another has ac- complished ; e. g., to utter a sound, to refrain from laughter or from weeping, to walk slowly or rapidly, or with a particular gait. By repetition of the effort, the effect is produced with little attention to the means, till at last the effect seems to occur without the use of these means at all. When the mind would accomplish an object, as utter a sound, hold a book, or let it fall, walk, run, or leap, it thinks only of the effect, and wills.it, and it is accomplished. In learning the unfamiliar sounds or combinations How we learn . ° to talk aud to oi a foreign language, we try one experiment after another, till at last we succeed. When the ear is satisfied that the result is reached, we repeat the muscular effort required, guided by the muscular sensations, till our com- mand over the organs is complete, and we can produce at will the sounds which we seek for. The infant pursues the same method in learning to talk. It is awakened from its purposeless lispings by the desire to produce a sound, as to pronounce a word, or a brief sentence. It succeeds imperfectly at first, but well enough to guide its efforts in the direction toward complete success. It triumphs at last, and it attentively observes the sensations which are connected with the word which it has learned to speak. Guided by these sensations, it can repeat the word or sentence a second time. The deaf-mute cannot learn to speak, not because he is mute by reason of any defect in the organs of speech, but because lie is deaf, and cannot regulate these organs. He has the vocal appa- ratus in complete perfection and he can make all the varieties of vocal utterances which are required in speech, but not having the ear by which to direct his efforts, he can neither form his own efforts to definite results, nor can he retain the acquisitions which he has made. In a few cases, the deaf and dumb have been taught to articulate by a discipline specially directed to the § 107. THE ACQUIRED SENSE-PERCEPTIONS. 143 management of the vocal apparatus; but the articulation is imperfect, and easily lost. The infant learns to walk as it learns to talk. It notices the sensations which attend those adjustments of the muscles which are necessary to quick or slow progress, to rising or sitting, to running or leaping. In all these effects we are usually guided by the eye. But sometimes we have not the eye to guide us. We ascend a flight of stairs to which we are accustomed, by a vague remembrance of the height and width of the steps. The blind depend on the direction of others, both in their first essays and in many of the subsequent uses which they make of their limbs. By similar processes, facility is acquired in those Sty. ° f Ex- ex ~ uses of the limbs which are required in feats of dex- f e r c e ts S . 10naI ef " terity, as in sleight of hand, or in playing on a musi- cal instrument. It is to be observed, however, that whatever movements nature fails to provide for, she gracefully accepts as a second or an acquired endowment. The effort to con- strain the organs or limbs to an unnatural position or adjustment, may at first be painful, and it may cost constant and severe application. But if it is persevered in, and especially if the intervals in which it is remitted are short, these new adjustments of the muscles are secured, and they even shape themselves to new forms. 'While the mind is renewing its efforts at brief inter- vals for a succcession of months or years, the substance of the body, in obedience to the laws of life, is continually changing ; and as it changes in its material, it is also changed in form, under the moulding pressure of psychical tension. In infancy and early childhood the merely physical capacity of receiving directions and impressions from within is incompara- bly more ready and quick than in later years. In early life, every single distinct effort in the use of any bodily organ seems to initiate a definite physical predisposition toward a permanent physical effect, either in the force or direction of the nervous stimulus, or in a new combination of muscles, or in fixing some form or attitude. A few repetitions, a brief perseverance, and the body is permanently moulded or fixed to the special service of the soul, in some new aptitude or habit. Hence it is that the bodily habits acquired in early life are so readily contracted and 144 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 108. so inveterately retained. But whether the law acts with greater or less efficiency at an early or a later period, the principle is the same. § 108. What are called the errors of the senses lie The errors of ° m J the senses ex- wholly within the sphere of the acquired perceptions. A person needs only to fall into a few such mistakes to be convinced that they are mistakes of judgment only, and that, as in the cases when he judges correctly, the process is a processs of judgment or induction. When a man sees, as he says, a heat * stick in the water, he judges that it is bent by what he sees ; or, in other words, he judges by what he sees, that, if the stick is handled or otherwise tested by the sense of touch, it will be found to be crooked. And yet he seems to perceive by the eye that it is bent. So, when he looks into a kaleidoscope, and sees scores of brilliant objects arranged in symmetrical groups, he perceives them all by the eye, and can count their number, and does not doubt that he can grasp them all by the hand. It is common in such cases for a person to say that his senses deceive him. But the senses are not treacherous : they cannot deceive. It is the man who is deceived in the judgments which he pro- nounces on the evidence which the senses furnish. He is simply hasty and premature in judging by the eye. He rashly connects, with what he sees by the eye, something which he believes with his mind. The bent stick is perceived when out of the water just as is a bent stick in the water ; in either case a judgment is pronounced — in the one case a judgment which is right, in the other a judgment which is wrong. The muscular sensations of the fingers may also be disturbed. We cross the fingers, and at the points of both a single pea is felt as two. The reason is that the convex surfaces, which as they are usually touched are interpreted as looking inward form- ing a single sphere, seem to look outward, and by the imagina- tion are interpreted as requiring two to complete them. This class of the so-called errors and deceptions of the senses ought to be sharply distinguished from another, which is caused by the physical conditions of the sensations themselves. Some men, for example, are color-blind — i. e., they see every object in one uniform, dingy hue, instead of under the bright and diversified colors which are granted to the majority of men. Some men, § 109. THE ACQUIRED SENSE-PERCEPTIONS. 145 through a disease of the stomach or liver, see every object tinged with yellow. It occasionally happens that a man is afflicted with double vision — seeing two objects where other men see only one. Others see spectra, or visible images which have no tangible reality, and no reality at all except to the individual who beholds them. Others hear sounds, as of ringing in the ears, when there is no sonorous body, and no vibration of the atmos- phere. Cases of this kind are never deceptions of the senses, for the objects perceived are the natural and legitimate product of the physical conditions that are present; these conditions being the physical excitants or stimuli and the sensorium excited, whether to normal or abnormal activity. § 109. The acquired perceptions differ from the original as forms of knowledge. Acts of original per- perceptions ception are acts of direct or immediate knowledge. fed^e.° fknow " In such acts the objects are present to the intellect, and the intellect knows directly that they are, and that they exist in certain relations. Acts of acquired perception are acts of mediate knowledge. In such acts it is by the medium of another act of original perception, that the object is said to be perceived. Thus, when I know the place of an object, the size or distance of an object seen, I use a direct or immediate percep- tion as the medium through which I reach what I know indirectly. Again : an act of acquired perception requires for its fulfilment the representative power, in the form of phantasy or memory. When the mind, on occasion of a direct perception, supplies that which it does not directly feel, or see, or measure, it must reproduce its object from something previously experienced, either in the form of a perception precisely like what is reproduced, or else similar or analogous. But the original perception apprehends its object directly. Again : if the act of acquired perception rests upon the repre- senting power or agency, it must involve the action of the asso- ciative power. At the experience cf one odor, we think of a lily; at the experience of another, of a tuberose. At the sight of a distant moving object, no larger than a mote, we think of a man or a horse. "What brings the form of a rose or a tuberose, the picture of a man or a horse, before my mind's eye on occasion of these direct perceptions? We must anticipate 7 146 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 109. our knowledge of the laws which govern the representative power, in order to answer — The laws of association. Every act of acquired perception is an act of in- iSictionJ Ve duction. The mind does more than represent some picture or remembrance out of the stores of its past experience; it believes there is a real object corresponding to this picture. In so doing, it performs a process of induction. It judges, by the signs or indications which the original perceptions furnish, that there are existing objects which the other senses would find to exist should they make the trial. The process by which this belief is attained is variously named inference, induc- tion, judgment, interpretation, etc. It is peculiar in this, that it knows by media or signs. It also assumes that these signs always indicate the same accompaniments, and that the laws and operations of nature are uniform in respect to the connections which are indicated. It may surprise many to learn that the processes employed in the acquired perceptions are processes of induction. Induction is usually conceived and described as a process which is appro- priated to philosophical discovery, which requires wide generali- zation and profound reflection, and issues only in comprehensive principles and laws. A little reflection will satisfy any one, however, that the act of mind is the same with that performed in every one of the acquired perceptions. The difference between the two kinds of induction is not in the process, but in the materials upon which the mind performs them. But the acts, the fundamental assumptions, and the liabilities to error in both, are essentially the same. But it cannot be possible, it will be urged, that the perceptions which the infant so rapidly acquires, and which the most igno- rant and unreflecting so skilfully apply, are in their nature similar to those profound and daring acts by which the astrono- mer scales the heavens, and the naturalist penetrates and resolves the mysteries of the universe. The difficulties and objections which are expressed in this language can be most effectually set aside, if we notice the differences in the circumstances and con- ditions of the acts performed by the infant and the philosopher. We notice 1. that the infant employs its perceptions upon a very limited number of objects. § 109. THE ACQUIRED SENSE-PERCEFTIOXS. 147 2. The few objects which the infant mind distinguishes are constantly recurring to view. 3. All the objects and parts of objects with which the infant has to do — in other words, all its sense-perceptions — have an immediate relation to its appetites and desires. 4. When any experiment has been successfully made in the way of connecting the known and the untried, the gratification at success will stimulate to repetition : and this again holds the attention to every element and step in the process, till the whole is fixed in the memoiy. The infant repeats all its lessons as fast as it learns them, because it rejoices over its acquisitions. 5. The associating power unites what observation notices. So few are the combinations which it has made as yet, and so closely were they connected by the original acts which first bound them together, that the one cannot be perceived or thought of without its companion. 6. The resemblances which the infant apprehends are few, and discerned with little effort. It might better be said that similar objects are at first recognized as the same, rather than discerned as similar. Hence the inductions of the infant are at first simple acts of spontaneous memory, rather than beliefs founded on similar instances. In induction proper, the similarities are remote — not obvious, not directly discerned, but indirectly surmised ; the data them- selves are the results of previous research and reflection, instead of being forced upon the attention. 7. The infant cares for the result, and, in its eagerness to reach it, slights or disregards the means. What it finds to be true, occupies its attention, and not the evidence or data by which it has discovered it. 8. The freshness and energy of the activity of the human soul in the earliest periods of its life continually surprise and astonish us. The activity of the intellect, the freshness of interest, the energy of will, the eagerness of the desires, the variety of the experiments upon itself, upon nature, and man, are ceaseless occa- sions of interest and surprise to older persons whose powers are torpid or overwrought, and whose curiosity is partially sated. Whatever objections may be urged against the possibility that acquisitions like these should be made in infancy and early life, 148 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 109. are satisfactorily met by the unquestioned fact, that the infant is constantly making experiments and falling into errors in this very sphere of induction and acquired knowledge. It makes awkward attempts to grasp, to reach, to stand, and to walk ; it misjudges in respect to the distance, form, size, and nature of the objects beyond its reach ; it is taught by experience, and it applies the lessons which experience imparts, whether painful or pleasant. It is never so busy as in the earliest years of its life. All this time it is chiefly occupied with experiments upon the material world and its own bodily powers, its energy being employed in the very directions, and being busied with the very objects, with which the acquired perceptions are concerned. It ought also to be remembered that, during the same period, it makes the surprising acquisition of language ; always of the mother-tongue, and, if circumstances favor, of one or two lan- guages more. To acquire a new language so as to speak it well, costs an adult whose powers are well disciplined many months, if not years of labor. With how much greater ease, rapidity, and perfection, is the same task achieved by the infant ! Surely it is not surprising that at an age as* early; or even earlier, it should master the acquired perceptions. ^ . A . , It might be urged in objection still further, that Objections from ° to J the cases of ani- there is no evidence that animals have what are mals. properly acquired perceptions. On the contrary, observation shows decisively that they perceive directly the dis- tance, size, and properties of the objects with which they are concerned. The chicken, with the young of certain birds, strikes its beak with precision and success at the food brought within its reach, even before it is released from the shell. The young of the partridge and the grouse run swiftly through the stubble, avoiding projecting objects as if with practiced skill. The young of quadrupeds run and leap with little previous discipline or train-, ing. In view of these facts, it is confidently urged that, if these animals are taught by instinct to perceive correctly, it is not to be supposed that man would be left to the slow and uncertain processes of feeling his way along to certain "beliefs. Surely nature would do as much for its noblest work, as for the inferior species. To this objection is to be opposed the indisputable fact that § 109. THE ACQUIRED SENSE-PERCEPTIONS. 149 the human species is slowly disciplined to feel its way on to matured and trustworthy acquisitions. The reason why, is ob- vious. The animal has not the capacity to judge by signs, to that extent and with that discrimination which would qualify it to build up the power of perception. This deficiency is supplemented by instinct, about which we know but little, but enough to be cer- tain that it effects by blind and unintelligent impulse what reason discerns and performs with discriminating judgment. Some facts are observed in infants which are supposed to be inconsistent with these conclusions, and to prove decisively that the infant, as well as the animal, has a so-called instinctive per- ception of distance. Thus, for example, Adam Smith reasons: " A child that is scarcely a month old, stretches out its hands to feel any little plaything that is presented toward it." It is more than possible that in infancy the eye cannot be excited by a visible object, especially if the object gives pleasure, without a consentient movement of the hands, and of both hands and eyes, in the same direction. That some provision should be made for such a conspiring movement or impulse to motion of two members of the body that perform many functions in common, may be received as probable, and believed to be true. But this would not prove that the eye, in the proper sense of the term, discerns distance. All the movements with both hand and eye show that this is judged or inferred by indications or signs. Important reasons suggest themselves, however, ii i • -i -i • -.1 -i -i » • Reasons why why the animal is taught and impelled by instinct to the perceptions , ,.-,?.-, „ M of animals and do at once, and with little exposure to failure, what of man should . , , , . fl , ... differ. man can only attain by slow and painful acquisition, and at the risk of many failures and sufferings. The discipline to which man is subjected has respect to his moral culture as well as to his intellectual discipline. He needs to learn patience, caution, foresight, and circumspection, as well as the higher virtues. All ox these are furthered by the disciplinary processes through which he gains the acquired perceptions. It is by the adaptation of this discipline to high moral uses, that we explain the law of nature by which man is born the most ignorant and helpless of all the animals, and forced, as it were, to make his acquisitions by his own sagacity, as fast as he is impelled by his awakened appetites, desires, and affections. 150 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §110. We conclude, then, that the processes of the acquired percep- tions are processes of induction, and that they involve the powers of representation, and judgment by indications. In other words, in the very act of perception, usually considered as the lowest and the most elementary of all the acts of the intellect, there is required the presence of the higher powers with the intuitions and relations which they involve. This is a striking instance of the principle already enounced, that no faculty of the intellect can act apart from the rest. For we have found that, in the very lowest of all, the rudimentary action of the very highest must be present, in order that its perceptions may be human and rational. CHAPTER VI. DEVELOPMENT AND GROWTH OF SENSE-PERCEPTION. § 110. We propose next to trace the growth and S^and^ffi- development of the sense-perceptions in earliest in- p?ibiem. the fancy. We take our guidance from what we have observed of those processes which we are certain that we acquire, and, going back to that period of which memory brings no report, we ask, From what beginnings, in what order, and by what steps does the infant mind develop and mature the power of sense-perception of which it finds itself in possession when it awa'kes to distinct and remembered consciousness ? The question is full of interest. It seems like a proposal to revive the experience of our earliest years, and restore, as it were, the forgotten past of our lives. There is a mystery about those months and* years which we would fain unravel, while the diffi- culty and apparent insuperableness of the problem incite and challenge us to the effort. The difficulty which attends the effort arises from the fact that it is impossible, by memory, to bring back a single fragment of our infant life. We cannot penetrate the darkness and obscurity which overhang the whole of this period of our existence. § 110. DEVELOPMENT AND GROWTH OF SENSE-PERCEPTION. 151 We can not recall to the memory any single perception in which all visible objects were depicted on an extended plane, without distance or depth. Nor can we by imagination feign such an experience. The effort to do either must be fruitless. The new elements which we have incorporated into our constant habitudes of perception and knowledge we can never throw off. We can not lay off the new growth which has overgrown the original germ. But the problem, though difficult, is not insolya- ble. To the judgment only is it explicable, but not to the imagi- nation. We can demonstrate what our infant life must have been, but we cannot imagine how this infant life must have seemed. To attempt to retrace and thus to reconstruct the processes of the earliest perceptions of childhood, is not irrational. We have at our command the materials with which to prosecute our analysis and to construct our synthesis. These are the known facts of experience and observation within our conscious experi- ence, the facts observed of infants and very young children, and the probable conclusions which analogy warrants us in deriving from both. Who can tell what a baby thinks ? Who can follow the gossamer links By which the manikin feels his way Out from the shore of the great unknown, Blind, and wailing, and alone, Into the light of day ? ***** What does he think of his mother's eyes ? What does he think of his mother's hair? What of the cradle-roof, that flies Forward and backward through the air? etc. J. G. Holland. — Bitter- Sweet. All that we observe of the actions of infants and young children is entirely consistent with the theory, that they develop the power of perception by many experiments and many mis- takes. The known methods and laws of nature in the education of men and of animals give the strongest confirmation to these con- clusions. We rely with confidence upon the view that, so far as it is possible to account for the acquired perceptions by the 152 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §111. theory of intelligent activity rather than by that of blind instinct, so far we are bound to go. Where intelligent activity cannot be presumed or proved, there instinct and intuition must be assumed. Synthesis or combination, however, cannot account for every process or solve every problem. There must be original elements with which to begin, or else there would be nothing with which to. combine, or which could be added when it was sought for. There must be capacities or powers of original knowledge, beyond or behind which we cannot go in our analysis ; which capacities, indeed, give the elements which we evolve by such analysis. § 111. These things being premised, we observe: The condition ? . , . , •, • of the intei- The first condition m which the soul exists before the lect before . ... , sense-percep- beginnings of conscious activity, is nearly allied to the tionbegins. „" , i , •, , „ -, -. state 01 sleep undisturbed by dreams, or 01 a dead fainting, in which the most indistinct and feeblest sensations possible are experienced without distinct perception. The unde- veloped condition of man is not dreamlike in the sense of being confused, or bewildered ; it is rather such a vague and low condi- tion of sense-perception as would attend the activity of those muscular and vital sensations which belong to the processes of the animal life. These sensations, when closely attended to in later knowledge, are at best but vague and indefinite ; and when they fill up the whole world of our conscious life, they must be obscure indeed. From this condition the soul is aroused when it anddeveiop- gs begins to attend either to a sensational excitement, or ment of atten- tQ ^ reg p 0ns i ve perceptional act. The soul scarcely can be said to have sensations even, till it is con- scious of some sharp or positive experience of pain or pleasure. Much less can it be said to perceive, till its attention is aroused, repeated, and fixed upon some single sensible percept. We are not to suppose that the attention, in either of these directions, is developed at a single bound, or that its energy is attained by one spasm of effort ; nor that the soul maintains itself always in the attent condition which at first it attains only now and then. All analogies from the states of our mature ex- perience would lead us to believe that the soul now rises for a § 112. DEVELOPMENT AND GROWTH OF SENSE-PERCEPTION. 153 moment into fixed attention, and then sinks again into blank inanity. Nor, again, are we to believe that the attention can only be aroused or occupied by a single sense at once, but rather that two or more of the senses may be exercised at the same time upon their appropriate objects, and thus the development of one of the senses may aid that of the others. This view is altogether con- sistent with nature and experience, and with the observations which we are able to make of the successive efforts which the infant makes to correct his mistakes and to perfect the training of his powers. As it is true with the adult, so is it with the infant; the several capacities are developed together and aid one another. § 112. The sense-perceptions which we should expect would be developed first are the muscular and vital. If, W h iC h thepe™ however, we perceive only so far as we attend, we Siopld^ 6 ought not to call these sense-perceptions till they are connected with other perceptions which are more positive and objective, as the perceptions of sight and touch. We should also suppose that the three senses of hearing, taste, and smell, would spring into activity next in order. Observa- tion does not, however, confirm these anticipations. The sense of hearing is used, in some feeble degree, a few days after birth, scarcely in such a manner or degree as to be called attentive or discriminating. The sense of taste is still later. At first, the infant swallows medicine as readily as milk. It is not till some four weeks have elapsed that it distinguishes the one from the other. The sense of smell is exercised still later. Others say taste and smell are active from the first. Hearing, though feebly developed at first, remains the longest, as death comes on. It is with the eye and the hand that the soul begins fixedly to attend, and of course, effectively to perceive. But with which does it first begin — with the eye, or with the hand? It is impos- sible to answer. Perhaps it were safer and more exact to say that it begins with neither alone, but with both, each aiding the other. In our analysis we begin with the hand. Whatever may be true of the eye, we are certain that intelligent perception by touch must be acquired very early for those who can see. 7* 154 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 113. § 113. We begin, then, with touch. Our problem ment e o d f7ouch" is, to show by what steps of touch we acquire the perception of extension and of outness or externality — by which we mean separableness from the body — or the not- body. "We assume that by original perception the non-ego proper is distinguished from the sentient ego, or the ego which animates the sensorium. We do not ask at what time this distinction is consciously developed; we only contend that it can not be acquired. Our present inquiry is by what process the knowledge of the non- ego as the not-body, is attained. The first step is for the soul to know familiarly its own body as bounded by a limiting surface. This knowledge it acquires by contrasting the muscular and tactual perceptions. The muscular and tactual perceptions we suppose to be familiarly known. By means of the distinguished muscular sensations we perceive the interior of the body which the spirit inhabits and controls. Upon contact of the sensorium with what are afterwards discovered to be material objects, we have only certain affections upon its own surface. When an infant lays its hand on anything flat and smooth, it perceives a portion of its own body in a given state of activity. If this surface is triangular, a corresponding portion of the sensorium is similarly excited, and so on. As soon as the two classes of sense-perceptions are familiar by attention, the muscular sensations give us the knowledge of the interior space that the sensorium occupies, and the tactual sensations give the knowledge of its bounding or limiting enclosure. The infant is constantly made aware of this limit, by contact with the sur- rounding objects that excite it to sentient activity. In the warm surroundings of a bath, bed, or heated apartment, the surface of the body is defined by a gentle glow. If the temperature is cool, it is revealed by the rough and comfortless chill, that creeps over and pinches the sensitive wrapping. The second step is to distinguish the two descrijitions of tactual sense-perceptions which are experienced as the hand is applied to any part of the body as the arm, or to the non-sentient table. In the one case the surface that is touched, also gives the sense- perceptions of being touched; in the other it gives or so to speak experiences none. The absence of capacities for sensation distin- guishes a certain class of objects as unlike all those which have § 113. DEVELOPMENT AND GROWTH OF SENSE-PERCEPTION. 155 them. This is the distinguishing mark of extra-corporeal objects. It is not, however, enough that objects are distinguished as extra- corporeal. They must be also known as separated in space — i. e., they must be known as extended, and thereby involving a space which is beyond or without the body. This suggests the next acquisition. Third, Objects corporeal and extra-corporeal can be grasped by the hand, and in this way can be known as occupying space. When a blind man grasps his own arm or wrist, he knows cer- tain muscular sensations as extended through and posited in the space that lies within the surfaces that he touches. If his wrist is withdrawn from the enclosing grasp, and an extra-corporeal object is inserted in its place, the adjustments of the grasping hand are the same as before, and the dim knowledge of the space which these adjustments involve is also the same. All is the same, except the sensations located within the wrist. The wrist is known by direct perception as space-filling. The enclosing hand is a measure of the space enclosed. The same enclosing or grasping hand measures the surface of another body, whether it is applied to a sentient or a non-sentient object. The last is mea- sured by the first, by means of the extension of the enclosing hand. It occupies, however, precisely the space which the other filled. It is known, therefore, as space-filling, and as filling other space than that occupied by any part of the body. In this way it is possible for the mind, by touch alone to reach the extra-corporeal world, and to know that all its objects, like the body with which it is directly connected, occupy space. These processes are all acquired, and that which is acquired in them all is the facility of using one percept as the sign of another, or of some relation which is indicated by the percept as its invariable attendant — e. g., outness, extension, direction, dis- tance, size, and the like. The theory of sense-perception, taught in this volume, coin- cides with the theories of John Miiller and Sir William Hamilton, theory of the so far as they agree, viz., that we have a direct or intuitive per- perception of „ . ' , 1 . , . ,. f , the extra or- ception of the extended organism, and an indirect or acquired ganic. perception of extra-organic matter. Miiller explains the last pro- cess, substantially as we have done, though with less detail. Hamilton explains it thus : " The existence of an extra-organic world is apprehended * * * in the consciousness that our locomotive energy is resisted, and not resisted by aught 156 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 114. in our organism itself. For in the consciousness of being thus resisted is in- volved as a correlative, the consciousness of a resisting something." (Appendix to Works o/Reid, Note D* 28; cf. 20, 23, 24, 25, 26; cf. 864, Note D.) This explanation of the process supposes the application of the relation of causation. For it represents the locomotive energy as a causative energy which, unresisted, would produce certain effects, which effects are overborne or set aside by an agent which is known to be neither the ego nor the organism with which the ego is connected. From the presence of this new and strange effect, the ex- istence of an extra-organic agent is inferred. The theory is in principle the same with that of Dr. Thomas Brown which we have already noticed, with this dif- ference, that Brown supposes the cause and its activities to be both spiritual and non-extended, while Hamilton supposes the locomotive energy to be known directly as extended. The distinction of body and not-body is better explained by the presence and absence of certain tactual and muscular sense-perceptions. When the reflective consciousness has been developed and the relation of causa- tion is familiarly handled by the mind, this relation would confirm and make de- finite the belief in extra-organic beings and agents. A more serious difficulty is involved in Hamilton's theory — the same, indeed, which in another way is fatal to that of Brown's, viz., it seems not to explain how with the necessity of finding for this effect an extra-organic cause, this " correla- tive "" resisting something " must also be proved to be extended. The agent, the ego, as a percipient and actor is not extended ; then why may not the extra- organic agent and non-ego be non-extended, or why must it be extended ? How is it shown to be correlative so far as to be extended, except it is taken to be the analogon of the extended organism, i. c, like it in being spatial in many per- cepts, etc., etc., but unlike it in respect to other sense-percepts, as we have, ex- plained. § 114. We consider next the development of the O f^ e ilfo2 pment eye. Vision seems to begin at that early period when the bright and steady light attracts and holds the infant's eye, or when it carries the eye with itself wherever it leads. Certain objects that glisten with reflected rays., or that are brilliant with intense color, are soon separated from the background of undistinguished things against which they are projected, or athwart which they are moved. It is not easy to decide how much of intellectual perception attends this early moving and fixing of the eyes, and how much is an unconscious and reflex response of the nervous organism to the stimulating light. The eye is so constructed that only a single portion of the retina can give a perfect image of an object that comes within the field of view ; so that when a bright object comes before the eye at all, it will hold or draw the eye to or after it, by the reflex action of the nerves which its brightness excites. Whenever the mind perceives such an object as a distinct and § 114. DEVELOPMENT AND GROWTH OF SENSE-PERCEPTIONS. 157 definite percept, then vision begins. Such a percept, as has already been explained, is known as a non-ego, and is known to be extended in two dimensions. We have already given the reasons why, in the beginnings of vision, the percept should not be located in the eye (§ 101). It remains for us to show why it should be projected in space. With this projection of visible objects afront of the eye, begins the development, or education of the sense of vision, if the act of location is acquired, and not intuitive. It is not easy to explain the steps of the process, or the grounds why the percepts are carried forward into space, even if they are not located in the eye. Some contend that no explanation can be given, because none is re- quired ; that there is no problem, because there is no process, it being, in their view, by an ordinance of nature that the object seen should first be seen at the eye's focal distance forward, and thus here is fixed the original starting-point from which all the acquired judgments of distance proceed. They insist that all objects, as viewed by the act of original vision, are seen in a hollow sphere — forward, above, below, on this side and that — whose radius is this focal distance. Such must of necessity hold that the act of projection is original, and not in any sense ac- quired. Those who hold that it is acquired, give various explanations of the process ; in all of which they must call in the aid of the hand. The most plausible is the following: The eye, though, like the hand, it is moved by muscles which are directed by the aid of the appropriate sensations, does not, when in its normal or healthy state, give any tactual sensations by the felt contact of its surface with the objects which affect it, nor do the muscular sensations themselves attract the attention. We may assume that, in the way explained, space and spatial objects external to the body have become familiar through the sense of touch and the use of the hand. At the surface of the eye such tactual experi- ences are wanting, and of course no outer limits can be defined. So soon as the lids are raised and the experiences of color are made, the eye gropes after these strange objects, but cannot touch them. It reaches after them, as it were, but they are beyond its reach. But still they exist. If they draw near, 158 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §114. while the eye regards them, they fill more of its field of view ; if they withdraw, they occupy a less extensive plane. Mean- while, as they draw near or remove, the eye is adjusted to perfect vision, and its adjustments and motions are known by changing sensations ; but still the objects cannot be touched, nor can they be reached. By all these criteria, visible percepts are strikingly contrasted with those which are tangible — they exist, but they cannot be touched by the eye, nor can the eye reach them. They are in space somewhere without the body. This somewhere is definitely fixed as soon as the seen object is also touched. The where of the percept after which the eye inquires, is answered as soon as the hand touches the object seen. The limited distance which is measured by the sensations proper to the extended hand, becomes fixed and clear, and the object held by the hand and gazed at by the eye is distinctly projected in space. Hence- forward the eye and the hand go together beyond the limited range which is at first allotted to them, into the unexplored infinitude that awaits their labors. Then comes the power to set up a field of vision. This sup- poses some knowledge of place, of relative distance and size, in gaining which the eye is aided greatly by the hand. First, the mind must construct certain definite objects of vision out of the bewildering multitude of colors and outlines which present them- selves to the unpracticed eye. Next, it must select a few of these objects for its observation at a single look. These it must place in a plane more or less distant, leaving out of distinct vision objects near and remote, estimating distance and judging size in the ways already explained. These acts and judgments of the quick and sensitive eye, aided by the slower and cooler hand, must be repeated again and again, till any required field of vision can be selected and constructed with ease and precision, so that we seem to see space, distance, and dimensions by the simple glance of the eye. These space relations, when once learned, are so few, so simple, so easily indicated, and so permanently established, that they seem never to have been learned at all. They become en- twined in all our associations ; they leap at once to the imagina- tion ; they preoccupy it so completely as to shut out the possi- bility of the opposite ; their suggestions are accepted by the in- tellect with a rapidity that often leads to illusion and error. § 115. DEVELOPMENT AND GROWTH OF SENSE-PERCEPTION. 159 Hence is it that all the so-called subjective sensations are at once projected into space. Hence, when the veins of the retina them- selves become the objects of vision, they are seen afront of the eye, a dark arborescence projected on an illuminated background. Hence, when we look into a mirror, either natural or artificial, we see all its reflected objects in the depths of space. Hence the spectra of the imagination, the visions which haunt the phantasy of the diseased and insane, are all distributed in space. § 115. We are next to show how the infant learns . n l-Ti n Combination to combine the perceptions of touch with those of of touch and vision. "We may do this by considering how the infant learns to connect the hands as seen with the hands as directly felt. Before this is possible, the hands as seen must become familiar as definite and separated objects, with forms that are easily recognized. The muscular sensations must also have become definite and distinct to the attentive intellect. This knowledge being given, the mind must learn to connect the hands as seen, with the hands as moved and touched. To unite these two percepts is one -of the first and most important of the acquired perceptions which the infant masters. How this can be effected, seems not difficult to explain. It should be con- sidered, for the reason already given, that these two classes of objects are the only objects with which the infant is conver- sant. These occupy its chief attention. They constitute and com- plete its universe. Let one hand lie upon another, or let the hand rest upon a material object that does not belong to its body. The eye watches the process, and as the hand holds the surface with its sentient touch, so the eye holds it with its gaze ; it observes that what was still is now in motion ; that what was seen is now covered, and by the interposing hand. Or, if the process be described in terms taken from the language of vision only, one patch of color or shade or light is obscured by another which moves before it and hides it from the view. Or, one is moved behind another, and is hidden from sight. In this way the two percepts coincide in place, and one is made the sign of the other ; when one is seen, it is expected that the other will be felt ; when one is felt, the mind expects that the other will be seen. As the mind proceeds and masters the other relations of form, place, size, and dis- 160 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §115. tance, etc., the import of either percept as a sign of the other becomes to the same extent enlarged. It is a sign not only of the other as a percept simply, but of all the relations which it signifies. These acquisitions are in fact achieved by every person born blind, to whom sight is given in later years. In infancy, the eye performs a service similar to that which it renders to the blind who learn to see in mature life ; with this difference, that the eye does not wait to furnish its aid till the hand has done all that can possibly be accomplished without it. "When the eye and the hand are developed together, by their mutual aid they greatly shorten the processes of acquisition, and of making the results more sure. What each can do apart, we have already con- sidered. It is fair to infer that in the processes by which infancy makes its acquisitions, whatever each can do best it will perform for the other. If the touch gives the first distinct knowledge of the third dimension of space, it places this knowledge at the ser- vice of the eye. The eye, if it can not directly discern distance, can yet observe and interpret the signs of distance. The hand can determine the relative distances of objects only within its reach ; or the foot must measure off distance by counting the steps, carrying the body as it goes. But the eye can, by a glance, reach for rods and furlongs and miles, and measure with sufficient ac- curacy for the common occasions of life. That the eye and the hand must conspire in iu- uiwn^Sants!* fancy, is not only fairly to be inferred, but it is evi- dent from observation of the experiments w T hich the infant is continually making with both. The infant learns to touch ; by which we mean not merely that it learns to use its hands, but that it learns to use them with intelligence, and to in- terpret its touch-perceptions. It is equally evident that it learns by practice not only to use its eyes in seeing, and to judge what its sight-perceptions signify, but also to combine its sight and touch-perceptions together, and thus makes the one serve as the signs of the other. As the eye of the infant rolls or rests in the socket, or is caught for an instant by the excitement of the stimulating light, so the hands and arms, at first, hang uselessly from the shoulders, or dangle hither and thither, resting on whatever may sustain § 115. DEVELOPMENT AND GROWTH OF SENSE-PERCEPTION. 161 them. They can neither grasp nor hold, much less can they be carried to a point on which desire fixes the eye ; nor can they, in obedience to desire, hold and carry an object, — as food to the mouth, — or release it when brought to its destined place. All these uses of the hand must be learned by attention. That they are learned, is evident from the aimless use of the hands at first, from the many experiments and failures and final successes which follow, and from the gratification that is manifested at success. The earliest objects which attract the persistent attention of th*e infant's eye are the hands. As these are to be the instru- ments of its activity and the arbiters of its earthly destiny, it is natural and appropriate that they should occupy the largest share of its earliest notice. It is impossible that it should be otherwise for two or three reasons. They are always before its eyes, ever flitting to and fro in aimless and convulsive move- ments, and challenging its notice as they are passing across its limited field of vision. As if to concentrate the whole energy of the attention upon the action of the hands, the infant is short- sighted, and, till it is four months old, observes only the nearest objects, and then objects somewhat more remote, till, by gradual advances, the whole spectacle of the universe is unveiled and opened to its view. It is manifest that the explanation of the process by which the infant learns to connect and unite the visual and tactual per- cepts of its hands, applies equally well to those acts by which it learns to connect the percepts of all material objects, so as to view them as single things. That this power is acquired, and neither innate nor connate, is obvious. That it is acquired by observation and experiment, is equally clear. The world of the eye and the world of the hand are at first diverse and apart. How to bring them together, is the first problem of infancy. Upon this problem it tasks its earliest powers. When it is achieved these two worlds rush together, coinciding so completely that it seems inconceivable that they should ever have been per- ceived apart. We need not pursue our synthesis further. We need not ask further how' the infant builds up the rest of its knowledge, or acquires its infant skill. We need not ask how the infant 162 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 115. learns to use its hands, to grasp, to hold, and to handle a spoon, a fork, or a knife, or how it learns to walk or talk ; for all these processes can be explained by analogous activities which occur within our recollection. Still less need we ask how it learns to connect the percepts of smell, of taste, and of sound, with their appropriate sight or touch objects. These problems present no difficulty and require no solution. It is instructive to watch the timid yet adventurous experiments which an in- fant makes, especially with its hands. First, it strikes about in aimless efforts, or makes a play for its eyes with the half convulsive motions of its little fists. By a gradual progress it learns to reach after the few objects which the eye has separated from the background — the infinite unknown which lies beyond nts reach and beyond its aims. Soon it endeavors to lay hold of objects which the eye rests upon, though quite beyond its reach. It clutches after the distant lamp, the fire-blaze, or the polished fire-iron. By slow but sure progress it masters the objects within its own apartment, and learns to apply its rude standards of size and distance to the world within its vision, the finite universe which its four walls enclose. All beyond is infinitude. During this time, as has been said, the infant is short-sighted, till many months of its life have elapsed, with the manifest design that it should be forced to master all near objects before it is tempted beyond. If we would conceive how the world out of doors may appear to an infant brought to the window, after it is somewhat familiar with the form, size, and re- lative positions of the objects within, we may read what is told of Caspar Hauser, who is said to have been confined, till the age of seventeen, in a darkened apartment, without communication with nature by the senses, or with man by language. The story, whether true or false, meets the case. " I directed him," says his teacher, "to look out of the window, pointing to the wide and extensive prospect of a beautiful landscape that presented itself in all the glory of sum- mer, and asked him whether what he saw was not very beautiful. He obeyed, but instantly drew back with visible horror, exclaiming, ' ugly, ugly !' and then pointing to the white wall of his chamber, he said, ' there not ugly.' Several years after, his friend asked him if he recalled the remembrance of the scene, and of his own feelings, and he said : ' What I then saw was very ugly ; for when I looked at the window, it always appeared to me as if a window-shutter had been placed before my eyes, upon which a wall-painter had spattered the con- tents of his different brushes, filled with white, blue, green, yellow, and red paint, all mingled together. Single things, as I now see things, I could not at that time recognize and distinguish from each other. That what I then saw wcro fields, hills, and houses ; that many things which at that timo appeared much larger were in reality much smaller, while many other things which appeared smaller wero in reality larger than other things, is a fact of which I was after- ward convinced in the experience gained in my walks.' Ho also said, ' that in the beginning, ho could not distinguish between what was really round and what was only painted as round or triangular. The men and horses represented on sheets of pictures appeared to be precisely as men and horses carved on wood.' " — Caspar Hauser : An Account, etc. (translated from the German"), pp. SS, 89. 2d edition. Boston, 1833. § 116. DEVELOPMENT AND GROWTH OP SENSE-PERCEPTION. 163 § 116. The phenomena attendant upon the acquisi- tion of sight by persons who had been blind from birth bKupontS have already been referred to as illustrating and sfght. ery ° f establishing some of these positions. They deserve a separate and more particular notice. The cases which are most easily accessible to the English reader — which are, indeed, the most satisfactory and decisive of any on record — are those reported in the Philosophical Trans- actions of the Royal Society of London for the years respectively, 1728, 1801, 1807, 1826, and 1841. The persons operated upon differed greatly in respect to age, mental capacity, and the degree of their previous blindness. The observations and experiments with all of them may be accepted as having established the fol- lowing facts and truths : — The patients, as soon as they began to see, saw objects not only as colored, but as extended. Their experiences gave no counte- nance whatever to the views of Stuart and Brown, that color can be perceived without extension, and that the two are united by inseparable association. It is true that in almost every case the patients, previously to their recovery of sight, had some experience of light, and of course of light superficially extended or diffused. But this experience of light was so obviously dependent upon the affection of the retina, as to indicate, if not to prove, that any ex- perience of light whatever involves the perception of extension. The extension which they perceived by sight was in two di- mensions only. This was made evident from a few experiments instituted with express reference to this point in the case of one of the most intelligent. A solid cube and a solid sphere were both taken by him to be simply discs or planes. A solid cube and a flat projection of the same were both taken to be flat and in every respect alike. A pyramid, when turned toward him so as to present one of its sides only, was called a triangle. When the pyramid was turned so as to expose a part of another side, he could not make out what it was. As to distance from the eye, or the place where objects are located in original perception, the testimony is unanimous and decisive that objects at first seem very near — how near, could not be exactly known — and that the relative distance of each object beyond this indeterminate limit is learned by experience. Most 164 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 116. of the patients were afraid to move, lest they should hit against objects that were comparatively remote. Two or three of the patients, in attempting to reach objects extended to them, clutched behind the objects when held near before them, and when more remote, only succeeded in grasping them after re- peated efforts. Cheselden's boy said, at first, that all objects touched his eye. The boy reported by Sir Edward Home (1807) said the sun and the candle touched his eye, even before the cataracts were removed ; and, just after the first operation, said the head of the surgeon did the same. But after a second opera- tion, he said the sun and the candle did not touch his eye. It is probable that the objects which were said to touch the eyes, in these two cases, stimulated them so actively as to present some analogy to the muscular sensations accompanying the touch, with which, in every possible form, the patient was so familiar. Hence they interpreted and called these experiences perceptions of touch. All these persons were forced to learn by experience to com- bine the percepts of sight with the familiar impressions of touch, so as to translate the one into the other. All experienced a difficulty similar to that of Cheselden's boy with the dog and cat. When they saw objects a second time, and were not certain that they could recall them, they reached for them with the hand, and could not be content till they handled them a second time. Their judgments of size and form all needed to be acquired. Visible mathematical figures, as a square, a circle, and rectangle, could not be recognized till the fingers were re- sorted to. One patient did make out one or two of these figures, by drawing the outline with her finger in the air, and, as it were, constructing the figure with the finger after the lines presented to the eye. Another could not understand how drawings of objects could represent the objects, till he revived the percepts of the objects by his fingers. Most of them were embarrassed by drawings and pictures, not being able to see likenesses or to understand perspective, or to perceive that light and shade repre- sented form and distance. Their judgments of the comparative size of objects were embarrassing to them. Cheselden's boy knew that his own room was a part of the house, but could not easily believe the house was so much larger than the apartment. The testimony is uniform, also, that, in learning to see objects § 117. THE PRODUCTS OF SENSE-PERCEPTION. 165 as separate things, the constructive power is brought into play, requiring intelligent attention and constant memory on the part of the percipient, and that it is only slowly, at best, that the mind learns to separate material objects, to construct its field of vision, and to locate objects as near and remote by the various signs which it learns to interpret. In short, these observations and experiments confirm and illustrate all that has been said in this chapter in respect to the early development and growth of sense-perception. CHAPTER VII. THE PRODUCT3 OF SENSE-PERCEPTION; OR, THE PERCEPTION OF MATERIAL THINGS. § 117. Thus far we have considered sense-percep- „ . . ,„. *- x Material tuing3 tion as a process, and in its growth. We proceed and sense-per- * ' ° x cepts. next to discuss its products as the permanent pos- sessions of the mind. We have already explained of knowledge in general, that, as an activity of the intellect, it is brought to its appropriate termination when its objects can, so to speak, be detached from the process by which they were so matured as afterward to be retained, recalled, and recognized. This is eminently true of sense-perception, which is only complete when it results in the knowledge of material things. A material thing or object, as known by sense-perception ,is a completed whole made up of separate percepts. We distinguish the knowledge of things from the knowledge of percepts. A percept, as has been ex- plained, is the appropriate object of the mind's knowledge through a single organ of sense. A thing is the product of the mind's knowledge in apprehending several percepts as united into a finished whole, with the relations which such a combination involves. As an example of the difference, take an apple. The apple seen, touched, smelled, tasted, and heard, are separate percepts. The object perceived by the combination of all these percepts is the apple, as a material thing. The separate original perceptions 166 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 117 a. give as many percepts. The original and acquired perceptions, when united, give material objects or things. Two questions now present themselves for consideration : By what means, and under what relations, does the mind unite separate percepts into things or objects? Under what conditions does the mind so complete its knowledge of percepts and of things, as to be able to retain and recall them as permanent objects of knowledge ? We begin with the first of these questions : By what steps, and under what relations, does the mind unite percepts into things or material objects? We answer: — Percepts are united into things by two successive steps or stages, to each of which there is an appropriate product. By the first the mind unites these percepts into a material thing or whole, under the relations of space and time. By the second, it connects the parts of the whole under the relation of substance and attributed quality. The several percepts united in both these relations constitute what is commonly known as a material thing. It has already been shown how the percepts of sight and the percepts of touch are referred by the mind to the same portion of space. The seen hand and the touched hand are found to lie in the same direction, and to be at the same distance from any and every part of the body. In like manner the apple or the egg, the chair or the table, which is seen and that which is touched are found to coincide in the same por- tion of space. They are in the same place. By a similar process the sentient body itself must have been previously perceived to be one material thing. § 117 a. This coincidence in place is the product of The first stage B . / . r . of perception; the first constructive or synthetic act by which the limited to co- . , . . incidence in mmd, in sense-perception, unites percepts into a thing. space and time. ~ , ., ,.. .,,. buch an act is complete when it givesa material object or whole, in this lower sense, viz., a combination of the percepts that are appropriate to different organs of sense, by means of the relations of space and time. The percepts of sight and touch are inseparably united in space, and this is. the earliest combination made by the intellect which may properly be called a material thing. With these two are connected the percepts of taste, smell, and sound, at first under the relation of simulta- neous occurrence in time. § 117«. THE PRODUCTS OF SENSE-PERCEPTION. 167 It is obvious that the several percepts, when viewed as con- nected into a whole under these relations, have a very unequal relative importance. The percepts of sight and touch, to those who can see and feel, as they are denned in place and eminently objective, constitute the material object as it is usually conceived and named. The percepts of smell, sound and taste, are its invariable attendants in time, until they are connected with it by another relation. To those who see, even though they can also feel, the leading percepts are those of sight. The name of an object suggests its visible form and color, etc., rather than the object as touched; a certain and decisive evidence that the object as seen is that which is most prominent and attractive to the mind, and therefore is most readily recalled to the imagination. To the blind, on the other hand, it is the object as touched, or the tangible percept, which is suggested by the name, and is re- presented to his imagination as the thing perceived. The other percepts, of taste, smell, and sound, are connected with the com- bined percepts of touch and sight less readily, and by a looser bond. As at first experienced, they are referred to the sentient organism, and are less readily separated from it. They are more sensational and subjective, less perceptional and objective. As to the man- ner and the relations by which they are first connected with the percepts of sight and touch, philosophers are not agreed. It must at least be true, that whatever other relations unite them to material things, they must at the very earliest period be their constant attendants in place and time. The conception of a material thing or whole, made up of ex- tended parts or single percepts, is, however, very equivocal in its import and varied in its application. To an infant with limited experience, the greater part of an apartment may be perceived as a single object or thing; the only separable objects in it being the chair, table, and a few utensils, the position of which is often changed. To a child, a horse and vehicle, seen together for the first time, may be a whole, or a single object. The savage per- ceives a ship or stea,mer as one huge animal. Many observations and experiments, much information from others, repeated lessons inferred from words and names properly applied, are required to enable the child to distinguish things as wholes and parts ; to hold apart objects that should not be united ; and to unite objects 168 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §118. that should not be divided. The point of view from which objects are observed, and the purpose or use to which they are to be applied, direct in the formation and application of names, and determine whether this or that object shall be regarded as a whole or part of a thing. A house with its grounds, the house alone, an apartment, a door, a window, the smallest perceived portion of either, each and all, are things or parts of things, according to the principle or use which regulates the application of the respective terms. But whether a perceived whole is greater or smaller in its spatial dimensions, it must have defined spatial dimensions and be capable of being perceived by one of the leading senses. Whatever the thing may be, the percepts of which it consists must at least be capable of being perceived as occupying the same space, and of occurring together in time. § 118. By the second stage or step of the percep- stage : The re- tive process, the several percepts or parts are con- lation of sab- * x x . x stance and at- nected with one another, or with the whole which they constitute, as substance and attribute. Thus the objects of the sense of touch are known as hard or soft, rough or smooth, elastic or non-elastic, etc., etc. Those of sight are red, yellow, orange, violet, and green; those of hearing are sharp, smooth, harsh, and sweet ; those of smell are pungent, exhilarant, fetid ; and all these qualities are ascribed to an object to which they belong, and of which they are affirmed to be attributes. Certain relations of time and extension, as long and short, square and round, are in like manner treated as properties or attributes. They are more than parts of the wholes which they help to consti- tute; they are connected with a being or agent, the nature of which they define, the presence of which they signify, and the powers of which they manifest. It is not here in place to discuss the nature of this special relation which has occasioned so much speculation and disjmte among metaphysicians (P. iv. c. vii). It is sufficient to say here, that as we have already shown that knowledge of every kind necessarily gives beings and relations, or beings as related, we are prepared to understand the definition of a substance as a being that is capable of being distinguished by relations; and of attributes, qualities, and properties, as relations used to distinguish and describe or define beings. That the objects of perception, § 118. THE PRODUCTS OF SENSE -PEE CEPTION. 169 both wholes and parts — i. e., combined and single percepts — are in fact connected in this way, is too obvious to require illustra- tion and proof. The relations most frequently employed as attributes are the relations of time, space, and causality. As soon as beings are known as enduring for a longer or shorter period, or having this or that size or form, and these relations are used to designate or distinguish them from other beings, these relations are attributed to them as distinguishing characteristics. As soon as the sense- object is known — i. e., thought of as the producer of sensations, as of smell, taste, or sound, it would be known as endowed with distinguishable capacities to produce these effects. The sensations would, in their turn, be referred to these beings as their causes or originators. No illustration is needed to prove that the sense- element in these three percepts is very early regarded as an effect. So far as the mind is passive in sensation, it must always be so regarded. The sensation is experienced when the object or being is near ; it is felt less intensely when the object is remote ; its quality or intensity vary with the varying conditions of the object. An object with a certain form, feel, or color, when brought into contact with the tongue or palate, causes a certain taste. Touched by the hand, no special sensation follows ; but touched by the tongue and palate, there ensues the specific sensa- tion of taste. The object touched might have been regarded simply as a being or thing; but the object tasted is known as also occasioning a sensation. It is conceivable, as has been already suggested, that before these coexistent and successive percepts and sensations are known as substance and attribute, they should be known as con- stant attendants, and that, simply as conjoined, the presence or the thought of the one should, under the laws of association, suggest the thought of the other. Under this relation sense- objects are known to animals, which can not and do not distin- guish the relation of conjunction from that of causation. If one sensation has been experienced in connection with another, the repetition of the one brings up the image of the other, and the pain and pleasure, the hope and fear which are appropriate to it. The dog connects with the whip in the hand of his master the thought of chastisement and pain; with the sight of his gun or 170 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 118. his walking stick, the excitement of sport or of a ramble. It is not easy to assert when and how the two relations are distin- guished by man ; that they are distinguished, is obvious, for reasons which this is not the place to give. That it is not till the second or advanced stage suppose r s e reflex of the perceptive process that percepts are connected knowledge. ' under the relation of substance and attribute, is still further evident from the fact that the knowledge in- volved is indirect and reflex, as distinguished from that which is direct and objective. It supposes the objects related — the subject of sensations, and the object which occasions them — to be more or less familiar, and that both subject and object are projected in the view of the mind upon the same plane, so that both become objects to its thought. A thing cannot be known as capable of producing sensations as effects, unless the body or the soul, one or both, are known as the conditions or subjects of its action ; and this requires that they should be placed afront the reflecting mind by a special effort, which involves a maturity of discipline which time alone can develop. Moreover, it supposes some progress in generalization, and some sort of induction. Many objects must have been touched and seen, before they are so far recognized as similar, as to be taken for the same in their causal efficiency. Many experiences must be had with the sensations of smell, taste, and sound, before these could be invariably referred to the same substances, because dependent on their pro- perties or attributes. • In one sense it is true, that an act of sense-perception is not complete, and its product is not perfected, until the soul's higher energies are awakened, and the object of them has been viewed in the higher relations. The human being can scarcely be said truly to have perceived even a pebble as a man, till he has brought into action all the powers with which he is endowed as a man. The infant's eye may not glisten with the penetrating sharpness of the eye of the young eagle, and yet may wear the softer lustre which betokens the dawning intelligence. The soul leaps into no single form of activity, least of all into the full development of its higher powers. Thus far we have conceived the substance as an object seen and touched, and its attributes a3 capacities to occasion the sensations of smell, taste, and sound. § 119. THE PRODUCTS OF SENSE-PERCEPTION. 171 We have connected a percept with a percept as substance and attribute — a lead- ing percept, as of sight, with a sensational percept a3 of smell — and called the one a thing, and the other its quality. If we push our inquiries a step back- ward, and inquire, "Which is the substance and which the attribute when the object consists solely of a percept of touch and a percept of sight conjoined? we answer, That sense-percept is made the substance, which is regarded in tbe relation of cause to the sense-element involved in the other. The object as touched and the object as seen, may respectively be substances, in their respective relations to the sensations of sight and of touch. We say, it is white — i. e., the object which I touch; and again, it is hard — i. e., the object I see — the touch- percept and sight-percept being each in their turn taken as beings. We may narrow our view still more, and inquire which is the being or sub- stance, and which the attribute or quality, when we have a single percept only, and view it in relation to the sentient mind? We reply, The object, perceived by sense to be, is known as a substance when considered as the producer of the sensation which is the condition of the perception. The tangible or visible object, as a being, is distinguishable as a space-occupying or extended something. As- causing or producing the sensations of sight or touch, it is known as possess- ing the attributes of color or touch. The elements involved in every act of sense- perception provide for the possibility of this relation. But the relation is not, in fact, discerned until the mind projects and brings up the perceived non-ego and the sentient ego into the same field of vision, by a reflex and comparing act. The sensation — i. e., the effect — is not the property or quality which produces it, though the two are called by the same name. Sweetness means one thing when it is said to be in the sugar, and another when it is experienced by the sentient soul. The heat, in one sense, is, and in another is not, in the fire. § 119. Our second question is, Under what condi- . , , . t 7 t n • -i The conditions tions does the mind attain a definite, permanent know- of complete ledge of the objects of sense-perception, whether per- cepts or things, so that they can be readily recalled and recog- nized ? It is only when they are placed so completely in the pos- session of the mind as to be at its disposal, that the process of per- ception can be said to be complete. When this is done, the object of perception is converted into an idea or image. The real object apprehended by the mind becomes an intellectual object, having a purely ideal or psychical existence. By some writers the spe- cial term ideation is appropriated to this process. Sense-percep- tion is said to be complete in the highest sense when its object is ideated, or becomes an idea. But as every perceived object is composed of parts, it follows that the perception of a thing can only be complete when the mind separates by distinct analysis the parts or percepts of which the thing is composed, and unites them by perfected synthesis. In other words, the mind must distinguish the constituent per- 172" THE HUMAN INTELLECT, § 119. cepts by completed acts of original perception, and combine these percepts into things, by finished acts of acquired perception. We are naturally led to consider the conditions of complete per- ception of the parts and relations of material things. (1.) Objects are most easily distinguished which are appre- hended with special energy — which are very strikingly contrasted with, or which are similar to other objects. A lively color, a loud sound, a positive taste, etc., are more readily apprehended than a color which is faint, a sound which is feeble, or a taste which is not positive. Things are more or less readily per- ceived with effect and permanence according as the per- cepts of which they are constituted are more or less readily known. The definiteness with which objects are perceived depends in part also on their likeness or unlikeness to other objects in con- nection with which they are presented to the mind. Of two per- cepts and two things that are very similar, and of two that are very unlike, those are more likely to be perceived which are in striking contrast to each other, than those which closely resemble one another. Two colors, two sounds, etc., as well as two apples or two paintings, are each more readily perceived and retained if they are strikingly contrasted, than if they are very similar. The ground of the likeness or unlikeness, the resemblance or contrast, is in part objective, — pertaining solely to the object per- ceived. In part it is subjective, and arises from the natural or acquired capability of the individual to feel and know. Thus, one class of persons are physically incapable of distinguishing different colors, i. e., those who are color-blind. Others, who can discern the colors which are commonly named, can with difficulty distinguish shades of color that are nearly allied. Some persons are very insensible to differences and similarities of sounds to which others are keenly alive. Even when the original sensi- bilities of the senses and aptitudes of the intellect present no diver- sity, there are the greatest possible differences of susceptibility, arising from differences of habit and attention. (2.) Motion heightens the contrasts of perceived objects, and gives definiteness to the outline and limits, especially of visible percepts. To the infant's eye, moving objects are the first which, so to speak, are separated from the undistinguished mass of § 119. THE PRODUCTS OF SENSE-PERCEPTION. 173 blended color, in which the world of matter is at first arrayed. From this extended surface of color certain objects are detached, as the moving lamp, the walking person, the portable furniture and utensils. They pass to and fro athwart the background upon which they are projected, and are brought into contrast with its unbroken surface, till they take their place in the memory, as the first distinct objects with which it is provided. By degrees this undistinguished mass of blended light and shade, of form and color, is broken up, as one and another separate percept and dis- tinguished thing is detached by the mind's observation and is set apart in the mind's storehouse as a distinct idea. The influence of motion is not limited to visible objects. It is most important in giving distinct percepts to the sense of touch. The hand must move over the surface felt, or the surface must move over the hand, to leave distinct percepts of its limits and qualities. (3.) Repetition is an efficient and often an indispensable condi- tion to the completion of an act of perception. Even the simple percept, as a sound, a color, a taste, is more perfectly mastered by being apprehended in successive acts of attention. If several percepts are to be united as a single and separate thing, it is still more requisite that they be often apprehended by the same or continuously connected acts, in order that the object may be brought completely into possession and placed entirely at com- mand. This is especially necessary if the percept, or object, by reason of its spatial extent or the complexity of its elements, is beyond the power of the mind to master in a single act. In some cases, repetition serves to make the impression more vivid and definite. In others, it is required in order that there be any im- pression at all. (a.) Kepetition often excites and gratifies the interest of the soul in the objects perceived, and thus arouses greater energy of attention. This is illustrated by the example of many single percepts. A color or sound gives pleasure when once perceived. Let it solicit the mind's notice a second time, and the remembrance of the gratification which it gave, will arouse the mind to attend with in- creased energy to the object which had previously imparted sq pleasant an experience. In the recollection of that experience, and with the hope of its renewal, it summons again all its energy of 174 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 119. perception. The result is a definite remembrance of every thing which the man is competent or prepared to know in respect to it. When the attention is solicited again, the mind at once responds to the call, withdraws its divided or distracted activity, and, ac- cording to its sense of the value of the good to be enjoyed, re- sponds with an energetic and attentive gaze. (6.) Eepetition is still more essential to enable the mind to unite into a whole the separate parts of objects which cannot be grasped by a single act of perception. The examples already cited, belong to those objects which require but a single act of attention in order to be completely possessed by the mind. There is a very large class of objects, however, which consist of too many parts to be known by a single effort of perception. These must be combined together into one, by successive acts. For example, if we perceive a mathematical figure with a very irre- gular and complicated outline, it is necessary that we view it in separate portions, in order to master the whole. Not only is this true, but we often need to review each portion which we have already perceived, in order to connect it with the part which was perceived previously. After we have followed the outline by repeated acts of observation, we need often to review the whole as a whole by a rapid succession of acts, or by a single glance of the eye to unite the several parts. If we look at a painting, we study its several parts, perhaps for hours together, in order to gain and carry away a distinct and satisfactory impression of the whole. If we look at the front of an edifice that is elaborately adorned, we follow the several features one by one in their order, often returning upon our course, that we may retain the per- ceptions which we have gained. The first efforts of the eye upon such an object are like voyages of discovery or movements of military reconnoissance. They serve the same purpose as the use of the finding-glass of a telescope. The eye runs hither and there with a vague and quickly-shifting gaze. It finds one feature after another which excites its interest and attracts its attention, and thus learns in a general way what material is present for it to work upon. After this preliminary work, a second and still another look may be required, that the mind may determine which of these parts it is worth while to unite together into a continuous and connected § 119. THE PRODUCTS OF SENSE-PERCEPTION. 175 whole, by successive acts of attentive perception. That this theory is correct, is manifest from the difference which we notice between observing a complex object when seen for the first time, and when it has become familiar by repeated acts of perception. If the object is new and strange, we must view it again and again in order to bring away any distinct perception. If it is familiar, or like a familiar object, a single and hasty look is often enough to secure a clear and permanent knowledge. In such a case we know beforehand what we expect to find, and to what points we need to direct the eye in order to assure ourselves. When the object contains a greater number of parts than we can grasp at a single view, there is need of repetition for another reason. Let the outline of a mathematical figure be made up flf many sides, or the face of an edifice consist of a very great number of salient features, and it is impossible — let either be ever so familiar — that they should be perceived distinctly by any single effort of perception. The eye must pass around the outline, or sweep across the face by successive acts, and master each portion in detail, in order to perceive the whole so as to recall it. Here again we notice a striking difference between objects that are regular and uniform, aad those which are irregular and mul- tiform. Of two figures of fifty sides, let one be a regular and an- other an irregular polygon. Let the facade of a building be made up of similar parts combined after a uniform law of recurrence and symmetry; or let the parts have no relation of likeness, order, or correspondence. A few repetitions of attention enable us to master the one ; very many are required to put us in posses- sion of the other. (4.) Familiar objects are readily and rapidly perceived. Novel or unfamiliar objects are slowly and painfully mastered. The fact is unquestioned. The explanation of it is furnished by the principles which have been already laid down. To familiar shades of color, sounds, forms, touches, tastes, and smells, the mind is ready to attend, being guided by its remem- brance of what it had perceived before, and incited to attention by remembered pleasure. If the combination is also familiar — i. e., the union of the taste or smell with the color, or of the touch with the form — the same law holds good. In looking at an indi- vidual chair or table which I have often perceived, or the aspect 176 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 119. of which is familiar, one percept prepares the way for another — the color for the form, the form for the weight ; one part for an- other, as the leg of the chair or the table for the back of the one or the bed of the other ; so that the mind is at once prepared for what it expects and readily apprehends what it is wait- ing for. But let the object be unfamiliar, we are detained upon its parts in the way already explained, in order that we may discover what they are, so far as to decide which, if any, shall receive our attention. If a novel piece of furniture is seen, or a new imple- ment, or an edifice singularly planned, or a work of art executed after peculiar principles, or if an animal or plant of an unfami- liar species or a dress of a new fashion is presented for our in- spection, we find it necessary to look again and again at the ob- ject. We must feel our way step by step and part by part, to find the parts of which it consists, so that we can recall them. The acts of repeated perception which are required in such cases, are not to be confounded with acts of recognition, or with acts of comparison for the purpose of dis- cerning similarities or other relations. Acts of recognition and of comparison do indeed usually accompany these efforts of perception. But though they often facilitate, they do not constitute the acts. This is manifest from the analysis of the acts. A single percept, or an object consisting of several percepts, must first be perceived in order to be re- cognized. It must be known the first time, or by a first act, in order to be known the second time, or by a subsequent act. So, two objects must be perceived, before they can be compared and discerned to be similar or alike. Some psychologists distinguish perception from sensation thus : " a sensation, when recognized as similar to one previously experienced, becomes a perception." So Herbert Spencer: "As there can be no classification or recognition of objects without perception of them; so there can be no perception of them without classi- fication or recognition." " A perception of it [an object] can arise only when tho group of sensations is consciously coordinated, and their meaning understood." " The perception of any object therefore, is impossible, save under the form of re- cognition or classification." (Principles of Psychology, $ 46.) Morell says: "To perceive a thing, means, first of all, to recognize it j" and again : "When we come to perceive special objects, then it is implied that we not only recognize, but that we also begin to classify them."— (Introduction to Mental Philosophy, pp. 85, 86. London, 1S62.) That this is really impossible and logi- cally self-contradictory, is obvious from what has been said. Recognition and classification attend and assist perception, but they do not constitute tho act. It is obvious that this definition would exclude from tho act of perception-proper, all that is material to it, or by which it is distinguished from sensation-proper, viz., tho apprehension of spatial relations and of externality. Neither of thai necessarily involved in the recognition or comparison of sensations. The view would shut us up to a purely idealistic theory. § 119. THE PRODUCTS OP SENSE-PERCEPTION. 177 (5.) To complete and successful perception, some continuance of time is necessary. This necessity for time is partly physical or organic, and partly mental or psychical. The organic necessity lies in the unexplained and ultimate fact, that in order to a complete and definite physical impression upon the organ, there must be a continued action of its excitant or stimulus for a brief but appreciable period. The eye and the ear, and the other organs, with their connected nervous apparatus, must be occupied with that which excites them, in order to give a sensation of which the mind can avail itself to distinct percep- tion. Indeed, after the stimulant has ceased to affect the organ, the impression, and with it the perception, remains ; as is evident from the experiment by which we revolve a burning coal so swiftly as to perceive a circle of fire. The psychical necessity is obvious from the fact that the mind can remit or increase the energy of the organ by its own volun- tary agency, and that, to exert this energy also requires time, if for no other reason, because the mind acts through and under the laws of its physical organism. An increase of energy in a part or the whole of the organism is an affair of time, and is often a measure of its lapse. Jugglers, prestidigitators, etc., perform many of their feats by having acquired a capacity of rapid movement which does not allow time enough for the sense-perceptions of lookers-on to respond to the objects. Often they do not furnish time enough for the requisite impressions to be made upon the sense-organs. Still more frequently they do not furnish time in which percep- tion or intelligence may perceive the objects in their relations, so as to discriminate, construct, and interpret what the sense-organs respond to. Quickness of movement and quickness of thought are the prime requisites for a successful juggler. To this should be added the capacity to divert the attention by lively sallies, by sudden gestures, rapid speech, exciting tones, and a bold address, as well as skill in inventing the physical appliances of illusion. A man endowed by nature with aptitudes like these, who has learned to make them efficient by art, can almost cheat the eyes and ears of the soberest and most practiced observer. 8* 178 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 120. § 120. It is in place here to consider the doctrine Can we attend i • i_ • • ■ . j \ov, or image, being detached from its surface, reaches the soul by passing through the pores of an organ of sense. The eiStx>\ov and the airoppo-q were nearly the same, unless the ciTroppot] was used to emphasize the material element, and the eZ&oAof that which is subjective and spiritual. The nature and signification of either do not seem to have been held with greater intelligence and precision in earlier times than the corresponding terms [as image, representation, species] and conceptions are employed and understood in modern philosophy. At one time they were used in a signification simply and grossly material; at another, as the product of the combined activity of the spiritual and material. (Cf. Eitter, vol. i. B. vi. c. ii., note.) Erom Democritus, Epicurus borrowed the notion of effluxes, simulacra rerum, which he conceived in the grossest form — viz., that they " are like pellicles flying off from objects ; and that these material likenesses, diffusing themselves every- where " in the air, are propagated to the perceptive organs. In the words of Lucretius: " Quse, quasi membrane, surnmo de corpore rerum Dereptse volitant ultro citroque per auras." The philosophers of the Socratic school [Plato and Aristotle] recognized the doctrines of their predecessors to some extent, either to expand or refute them. They also made important additions to the philosophy of the previous times in respect to the theory of sense-perception. The doctrines of Aristotle and Plato, and even the terms which they employed, can be traced among philosophers of every age since their time ; and they still reappear and exert their influence among the most recent schools, Aristotle especially gave the law to the school- men, from whose teachings the modern theories have retained many traditions. Plato is still appealed to and quoted by his admirers for his eloquent and just psychological discriminations, even in respect to the theory of sense-perception. Plato taught very distinctly and emphatically, especially in his Theatetus, that sensation [proper] is an effect jointly produced by the force, motion, or action ( heing startled by the consequences which Berkeley Dr. T. Brown, and Hume derived from their construction of Locke's theory of sense-perception, was led to review not only the doctrine of re- presentative perception, but also some other principles which Locke was understood .to advocate in respect to the origin and elements of knowledge. The features of his system are as follows : 1. He successfully exposed the groundlessness, inconsistency, and contradictions of the ancient and modern theories of representative perception, and cleared the way for a theory more accordant with experience and common sense. 2. Reid vindicated the general principle, that no theory of perception is enti- tled to confidence as truly philosophical, which contradicts the universal convic- tions and the common sense of mankind, when they apply their understandings to the judgment of truths which they are competent to decide upon. This was a special inference from the general axioms of Reid's philosophy. 3. Reid insisted that the mind is active in sense-perception j and did this with an earnestness rare among philosophers, not only of the English, but of any school whatever. The ancients, and the moderns before him, did indeed assert that the mind is active in its higher functions ; but they as distinctly denied that it is active in the lower. It has been nearly the uniform doctrine of all the schools that, in sense-perception, objects act upon the mind so as to impress ideas, and that, in the reception of these ideas, the mind is chiefly or wholly passive. Against this doctrine Reid occasionally protests, in language like the following : " An object, in being perceived, does not act at all. I perceive the walls of the room where I sit : but they are perfectly inactive, and therefore act not upon the mind. To be perceived is what logicians call an external denomina- tion, which implies neither action nor quality in the object perceived. Nor could men have ever gone into this notion that perception is owing to some action of the object upon the mind, were it not that"we are so prone to form our notions of the mind from some similitude we conceive between it and body." 4. As intimately connected with the preceding, Reid asserts that the faculty and act of judgment are present in connection with the perceptions of sense. 5. Reid recognized and enforced the distinction between sensation and percep- tion ; and thus prepared the way for the correct and complete determination of these two elements in the process of sense-perception. Dugalcl Stewart, the successor of Reid in the school of Scotch philosophers, followed closely and almost timidly in the footsteps of his predecessor, whom ho greatly admired and revered. 1. He discriminated more carefully between sensation and perception than Reid. He limited perception to the act of apprehending the objects appropriate to each separate sense, and escaped the confusion and ambiguity which Reid committed, of confounding the original with the acquired perceptions. Of three of the senses — smell, taste, and hearing— ho denied perception alto- gether, in fact though not in form. Ho expressly asserted that these, by them- selves, givo no information of external objects (Outlines of Moral Philosophy, $ 15). lie asserts that the sensation of color, even as given in vision, can reside, in the mind only, and is purely subjective; giving no relation of extension, and in our early experience clearly separable from it. 2. Stewart apprehended, far more clearly than Reid, tho true character of what §132. THEORIES OF SENSE-PERCEPTION. 199 he calls the mathematical affections of matter, and the relation of these affections to space and to our belief in space as a necessary existence. These mathemati- cal affections are extension and figure, and are distinguished from the other primary qualities, such as hardness or solidity, and are thus characterized:—!. They presuppose the existence of our external senses. 2. The notion of them involves an irresistible conviction of the external existence of their objects — viz., of space. 3. This conviction is neither the result of reasoning, nor of experi- ence, but must be considered as an ultimate and essential law of human thought. {Phil. Essays.) 3. Stewart adds to the doctrine of Reid, that we believe in the existence of the material world, by a necessary suggestion. The explanation of our belief in its permanence, he finds in our more comprehensive belief in the permanence of the laws of nature. Dr. Thomas Brown followed in the same school with Reid and Stewart. The analysis which he has given of the processes and the products of the sense-per- ceptions, is one of the boldest and the most subtle which is to be found in the whole compass of English psychology. 1. Dr. Brown attached great importance to the muscular sensations. He was one of the earliest of English psychologists to recognize and to distinguish them from the sensations as usually accepted. This distinction is now almost univer- sally adopted. Dr. Brown made so much of these sensations, as to derive from them the notions of extension and of externality. 2. He scarcely recognizes £he distinction adopted by Reid between sensation and perception. So far as the original perceptions are concerned, he rejects it altogether. The only acts of perception which he acknowledges or describes are acts of acquired perception. He refers our belief in the external and material world to the principle of cau- sation. We know our sensations as subjective states of the soul. "We believe that they must be produced by a cause. We know that they are not caused by ourselves. There must be causes other than ourselves. These causes are material non-egos. The existence of these non-egos is not suggested directly, as Reid teaches, but it is inferred. " Perception, then, even in that class of feelings by which we learn to consider ourselves as surrounded by substances extended and resisting, is only another name, as I have said, for the result of certain associa- tions and inferences that flow from other more general principles of the mind." (Lee. 26.) Cf. $ 40. 3. It is equally clear that Brown, to be consistent, would reject nearly or alto- gether the distinction between the primary and the secondary qualities of matter as explained by Reid, and in part adopted by Stewart. § 132. Sir W. Hamilton, the deservedly eminent Professor of Logic and Metaphysics in the University of Edinburrgb, was one of the j^Kon™ greatest philosophers of Great Britain. He devoted his researches to two leading topics : Formal Logic, and the Theories of Sense-perception. He had studied the history of these theories with greater care than any one of his own time, and had gathered from his historical researches the most valuable re- sults in the way of observation and analysis. His contributions are important in respect to all the points which have been noticed. 1. Sensation and perception were more carefully discriminated by him, as to their nature and material relations, than by any philosopher before his time. 200 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 132. They are viewed by him as inseparable elements of a single mental state, and are called sensation and perception proper. 2. Hamilton asserts that sense-perception involves the action of the intelligence in the form of judgment, or the discrimination of relations. It follows of neces- sity that, in perception, man is active, and not simply receptive or passive. These important truths Hamilton enforces on every occasion. 3. In respect to extension and space, Hamilton teaches, with Kant and others, that while the spatial relations of every material body are known by sense-per- ception, yet space itself is pre-supposed by the intuition of the intellect, in order that it may be possible for any of these relations to be perceived as actual. Space must be known a priori, in order that extension may be known a posteriori. 4. In respect to externality, Hamilton teaches positively, though not with so great clearness as is desirable, that the term is used in two senses: (1) as de- noting the diversity of the sentient organism from the perceiving intellect ; and (2) the diversity of material objects from the material organism which the soul animates, and by which it apprehends. In respect to the first of these relations, he asserts that it is directly appre- hended in every act of sense-perception. In respect to the second, he teaches that it is gained by the exercise of the locomotive power in the form of muscular effort. This effort is resisted, and with the resistance is gained the correlative of a resisting something, external to the body or sentient organism. " When I am conscious of the exertion of an enorganic volition to move, and aware that the muscles are obedient to my will, but at the same time aware that my limb is arrested in its motion by some external impediment, in this case I cannot be conscious of myself as the resisted relative, without at the same time being conscious, being immediately percipient of a not-self as the resisting correlative." 5. The qualities of material objects are treated by Hamilton as though, as qualities, they were the direct object of immediate sense-perception. Thi3 view is certainly implied in the whole of his doctrine, and his history of the sensible qualities of matter. This is a consequence of his failure occasionally to discriminate between sense-perception as direct and reflex. He does not always distinctly hold to the fact that if in original sense-perception, we can in any sense apprehend the qualities of matter, we can only apprehend those which pertain to the animated organism. We hold that the qualities oi matter are only known by Required perception in reflex action. 6. Hamilton sometimes confounds the conditions of perception with percep- tion itself. He falls into this error in applying the doctrines of latent modifications of the mind to the phenomena of vision and hearing. He argues that, because two portions of extension, or two parts of an extended substance, each of which by itself is invisible, become visible when annexed so as to form one continuum, that therefore each of them, by itself, must obscurely affect the sensorium or the mind. So, two separate sound?, each one of which might be too fceblo to be heard alone, when uttered together, cannot fail to be heard. In both these cases the distinction is overlooked between the action of physical or physiological stimuli upon the sensorium, and their effect on the sensorium as the appropriate and indeed the only condition of the responses of conscious scntiency or perception. § 132. THEORIES OF SENSE-PERCEPTION. 201 7. Hamilton attaches too great importance to the subjective sensations, or the idiopathic affections of the nervous system, which are excited by electrical ac- tion, indigestion, or a blow. The sparks which are elicited by a blow over the eyes, the light, the sound, the taste, the ringing of the ears which electric or other agencies occasion, are doubtless owing to a special stimulus of the sensorium, and to this only. 8. Hamilton's theory of perception is vitiated still further by the metaphysical assumption that we know directly only phenomena, whether of matter or of mind. We hold that neither phenomena nor qualities, as such, are perceived, but objects, percepts, or beings; and that it is by an after-thought, or reflex process, that these are connected as qualities, and are referred to substances. 9. The most eminent service which Hamilton has rendered to the theory of sense-perception, is his criticism of all the possible forms of the doctrine of repre- sentative or mediate perception, and his demonstration that every such theory is untenable. We give the substance of his criticism in our own language, for the sake of brevity, interposing such qualifications and explanations as may serve to illus- trate and explain it. In respect to the act of sense-perception, one of two positions may be taken: the mind is endowed with the power of perceiving material objects by a direct and intuitive energy, without the intervention of any intermediate object; or, the mind can perceive material objects only throxigh the medium of some inter- vening object. It will here be observed, that the alternative does not relate to the conditions of such perception whether material or physiological. It is simply a question whether there are or are not intermediate objects to the psychological act. If the first position be taken, then the only obligation which rests upon the philosopher, is to state the conditions which are essential to the act, and to analyze the act into its elementary constituents, as given in, or inferred from, our conscious experience and careful observation. The person who takes the second position is bound to show why this hypothesis is necessary. The natural and universal belief of mankind is, that objects are perceived directly. He who asserts that this is impossible, ought to give some reason for deviating from this belief. The several reasons that are to be found in the whole history of philosophy, are by Hamilton reduced to five groups, under- lying each of which is a single fundamental principle. The first of them is, that an act of cognition is an act of the mind; and to suppose that the mind should know that which is not itself, is to suppose that it can go out of itself. To this it is replied : 1. That if we cannot explain how it is possible that the mind should act on that which is not itself, it does not follow that it cannot be a fact. The fact may be ultimate, and for this reason inexplicable. 2. The principle proves too much, for it would involve the inference that the mind cannot act upon matter, as it manifestly does in volition. 3. Moreover, it would carry with itself the con- sequence that matter cannot act out of itself upon the mind, and of course cannot produce a representative image of its object. The second reason is, that mind and matter are substances not only of a differ- ent, but of the most opposite nature. That which knows immediately, must be of a nature corresponding or analogous to that which is known ;-the mind cannot, therefore, know matter directly ; an intermediate something must ba interpos-d. 9* 202 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 132. This assumption is of the widest prevalence, and underlies almost every theory of representative perception. It accounts for the variety of the views of the nature of the interposed media held hy both ancients and moderns. When this medium was conceived akin to the mind, it gave the intentional species of the schoolmen, or the ideas of Malebranche and Berkeley. When it was supposed to be iden- tical with the mind,, it gave the gnostic reasons of the Platonists, the pre-existing species of Avicenna, the ideas of Descartes, Arnauld, Leibnitz, Buffon, and Condillac, the phenomena of Kant, the external states of Dr. Brown. To the influence of this assumption, are to be traced the systems of the absolute iden- tity of mind and matter in the opposite theories of exclusive materialism and of spiritual idealism. This grand assumption should be rejected as arbitrary, unphilosophical, and contradictory to our plain experience. The third reason for this hypothesis is, that the mind can only know that to which it is immediately present. External objects can hence be brought within reach of the mind only by means of some intermediate representative. The pro- per answer to this reason is, that the mind is present in every part of the body so far as to act and to be acted upon, and that the real object of immediate per- ception is some part of the body as excited to a specific sensation. The corrected view of the relation of the soul to the body, and of what is the real object of the mind's external perception, sets aside this third reason. Reid and Stewart attempt to set this aside by a failure to conceive these points rightly, and they require some agency of the Deity, and an inexplicable con- nection between the sensation and perception, which is unphilosophical and un- satisfactory. The fourth ground is stated by Hume, that the same object, as a table, at differ- ent distances changes its dimensions, but the object itself does not change ; there- fore the object must be apprehended by an intermediate and changing representa- tion. To this it is answered, that the same table is not perceived, so far as vision is concerned, when near and remote, but a different object in each case is the im- mediate object of sense-perception. The fifth reason is stated by the elder Fichte, that, as the will must act in view of intelligent objects, these must be within the mind; so far then as it acts in re- spect to material objects, these must be represented in the mind. To this it may be replied, that the act of intelligence is in the mind, and this is all that is required as the condition of the act of will. Besides, the act of tho will respects future results, which must necessarily be mediately represented. It is not denied that the mind is capable of mediate knowledge. The question at issue is, whether the act of sense-perception is an act of this kind. After having shown that this hypothesis of a representative perception is unne- cessary, Hamilton shows at length that it does not stand the tests by which every legitimate hypothesis may properly be tried. These conditions are : (1.) That it bo necessary, and be more intelligible than tho fact which it explains. (2.) That it shall not subvert that which it proposes to explain, or the ground on which it rests. (3.) That tho facts in explanation of which it is devised really exist, and arc not themselves hypothetical. (4.) That it does not subvert the phenomena which it seeks to account for. (5.) That it works naturally and simply. Tho hypothesis of representative perception fails to answer to any of these conditions, and must therefore be rejected by every true philosopher. (Met., Lee. xxv. and xxvi.) §133. THEORIES OP SENSE-PERCEPTION. 203 § 133. Immanuel Kant, the great metaphysician of Germany, has treated of sense-perception only indirectly. He has given no Immanuel .r i j.-u v\ -u \ -l. j. ■, . « , , . Kant > and the formal theory of its processes, but has metaphysically analyzed its German school. results, and thus has indirectly taught a partial theory of the power itself and its functions. First of all, he implies that the soul, in its sense- perceptions, is passive or receptive only. He contrasts the receptivity of the soul in sense with its activity or spontaneity in the understanding. He indirectly teaches, by the assumptions that underlie his whole system, that the process of sense-perception is not complete until the understanding, by the judging power, conceives under some of its forms the matter given by sense. Had he distin- guished between the natural judgments which concern individual things and their relations, and the secondary judgments that contemplate general conceptions, there could be little to object to in his theory ; but this omission is fatal to its completeness and its truth. Sense stands on the one side as a purely passive re- ceptivity of individual objects, and the understanding, on the other, as active, but as concerned solely with generalized concepts alone. Of the relation of sensation to perception, Kant teaches that sensation give3 the matter, and perception — i. e., — intuition — furnishes the form. The form es- sential to any and every act of external intuition is space. All material objects, so far as they are perceived at all, are perceived in some relation to space — that is, they are perceived as extended objects. Kant recognizes this as a fact of actual experience. But the fact he subjects to no farther analysis, least of all does he examine farther the process by which the product is reached. Instead of studying the fact in its conditions and elements, he seeks to account for its possibility and the trustworthiness of its results, on grounds of speculative philosophy. For this reason, his discussion of space has an intimate relation to his theory of sense-perception, and the conclusion which he reached has explained the discussions of all physiologists and psychologists since his time. This conclusion was, that space and time must be assumed as the ne- cessary conditions of our subjective experience in both consciousness and perception, but we are not thereby authorized to believe in their objective reality. We cannot, indeed, perceive any material object by means of the senses without involving necessary relations to space directly, and indirectly to time. It does not, however, follow that space is a reality. It is supposa- ble, though not to us conceivable, that to minds constituted differently from our own, these forms, with the relations which they involve, should not be ne- cessarily assumed. (Kritik der reinen Vernunft. EL Lehre, ii Th., 1 Abth. ; ii Buch, 2 Hauptst. 3 Abschn.) In respect to the reality of external objects, Kant recognizes the fact in our psychical experience, that material objects are not only perceived as extended and spatial, but also as external; or in other words, as non-egos. In sense- perception this distinction is necessarily involved. Indeed, it is included as an essential element in the process and its result. But it does not foilow, be- cause the mind makes this distinction, that there is a reality corresponding to this non-ego. For (1.) The non-ego, as a being, is transcendental to all phe- nomena. (2.) It is posited in space, which is necessary as a form of sense, but which may be only an illusion. Kant would however demonstrate, on the ground of speculative necessity, that this is impossible. He contends that we must assume that there is something permanent and real without, in order to 204 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 133. account for the changing modifications within. Of the existence of an external world, we can he rationally assured, hut of it, we can have no direct perception. Even the self, or ego, is not apprehended as a permanent something. It is only concluded to exist as the thought-conception of a spiritual substance with capacities for spiritual acts. All that we are conscious of, are our changing modifications in time. But these can only be rationally explained by a per- manent reality which causes them. The theory of sense-perception was discussed by the successors of Kant chiefly in its purely metaphysical relations. In the writings of Fichte, Schell- ing, and Hegel, still less attention is given to psychological analysis, meta- physical principles and relations being almost exclusively considered. He lb t J F J. F. Herbart'8 theory of sense-perception may be briefly stated as follows : The soul, though a simple substance, is capable of being excited by the action of various material stimuli to various reactions of its own. Certain classes of these, when experienced, are sensations. A sensation is the soul's reception of, or its reaction against, this material stimulus. The sensations differ from one another in quality or kind on the one hand and in energy or intensity on the other. As the several sensations are experienced, each continues to exist in the soul, with a force or tendency to be reproduced. As soon as favoring conditions present themselves, past sensations reappear in the order of the soul's original experience of them. When such a series is viewed [experienced?] from one sensation regarded as fixed, it has time-relations ; and by means of the mutual struggles or tendencies of several series of experienced sensations to gain possession a second time of the soul without success, there is generated the idea of pure or simple time. The apprehension of time prepares the body for that of space. Sensations experienced and recalled in the time series, are disputed by other sensations and series of sensations that struggle to occupy the soul. To provide for the possi- bility of these mutual struggles, and under the experience of the pressure which they create, the mind constructs a conception of space first as occupied, and then as empty or void. Thus, time and space result to the mind as the effects of mutually blended or mutually repelling series of sensations. When space and time are produced, that which is next developed is the appre- hension of the difference between bodily affections and material objects. This results from an experience of certain positive sensations, particularly those of touch joined with those of the muscular sense. A certain portion of space within the body is measured in every direction by various time-series of sensations, terminated by those appropriate to supei-ficial touch. Other sensations wc pro- ject beyond the surface of the body, at greater or less distances, all of which are measured by successive time-series of sensations, in experience or imagination. Sensations which do not occur within the space of the body, nor on its sur- face as explained, are projected beyond — i. e., are apprehended as not within its space. This constitutes perception in tho lowest, or the elementary stage. After- wards are developed apperception, or the knowledge of mental states by a secondary act of knowledge; then tho knowledge of substance and its attri- butes ; then a knowledge of material things, or of material substances with ma- terial attributes and space-relations. § 133. THEORIES OP SENSE-PERCEPTION. 205 Schleiermacher, the distinguished philosopher and theologian, deserves also to be named for the very important contributions which he made to the theory of sense-perception. These were partly indirect, as he opposed so decidedly the current of the great leaders of metaphysical speculation in Germany, by rejecting many of the assumptions which are fundamental to their systems. In part, also, they were direct, in the positive doctrines which he taught in respect to the condi- tions and nature of sense-perception as a process. The relations of space, time, substance, and cause, he held, as against Kant, to be real forms of things, and not merely the forms of our apprehension of things. The reality of time and space must be assumed without misgivings or questionings. Being is directly appre- hended, as well as phenomena and relations. To all the combinations and con- structions which we make in knowledge, we attribute actual reality. Thought which, in Hegel, is the all in all, the originator of the relations and products of knowledge, according to Schleiermacher, is psychologically dependent upon sense-perception. In sense-perception there are two essential elements : the receptive, styled by Schleiermacher "the organic function," and the a priori or spontaneous, called " the intellectual function. " This last is an act of knowing by relations, and, as so defined, is an important improvement upon Kant, and Reid, and even upon Hamilton. Schleiermacher, moreover, teaches that the two elements, the organic and in- tellectual, are present in different proportions in the different faculties and acts of sense-perception, anticipating in this the law of Hamilton respecting the in- verse proportion of sensation and perception proper. Important contributions have been made to the physiological and psychological theories of sense-percep- tion by many distinguished German and English writers, whom it is not im- portant that we should notice. 206 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 134. PART SECOND. REPRESENTATION AND REPRESENTATIVE KNOWLEDGE. CHAPTER I. THE REPRESENTATIVE POWER DEFINED AND EXPLAINED. § 134. Representation or the representative potver Representation n n -, . ■• .-, . ■., denned and ii- is denned in general, as the power to recall, represent, and reknow objects which have been previously known or experienced. More briefly, it is the power to represent objects previously presented to the mind. Thus, I gaze upon a tree, a house, or a mountain. The object perceived is the tree, the house, or mountain, before my eyes. I close my eyes, and " my mind makes pictures when my eyes are shut." I at once re- present or see with "my mind's eye" that which I saw just before with the eyes of the body. My eyes make pictures when they are shut. I see a fountain, large and fair, A willow, and a ruined hut. Coleridge. Hamlet. — My father — methinka I see ray father ! Horatio. — Oh, where, my lord ? Hamlet. — In my mind's eye, Horatio. ShakspeareJ. In like manner we hear a sound, either singly, as the solitary note of the pigeon, or several sounds in succession, as the caw, caw, of the crow, the roll of a drum, or the notes of a musical air. Let the sounds cease. We can still distinctly recall them, and seem to hear them again with the mind, though the mind makes for itself all the sounds which it seems to hear. In a similar way we can represent the percepts that are appropriate to the senses of touch, of taste and of smell ; reviving the touch, taste, and smell by and for the mind alone. Music, when soft voices die, Vibrates in the memory. Odors, when sweet violets sicken, Live within the sense they quicken. — Shelley. We are not limited to sensible objects, or to sense-percepts, in the exercise of this power. We can as truly represent the acts § 135. REPRESENTATIVE POWER DEFINED AND EXPLAINED. 207 and the affections of the soul itself. Not only can we with the mind's eye behold the tree and the mountain previously seen, but we can represent the act of the mind by which we beheld it, as also the delight which the sight occasioned. We not only hear a musical air the second time, but we revive again the idea of the accompanying pleasure. So is it with the relations in which the objects were presented at first. The objects themselves can not only be recalled as objects, but they can be recalled as related, or as totals made up of the objects connected by the several relations under which they were originally known. Whether these are relations of space or time, of self or not-self; whether necessary and permanent, or casual and changing ; whether intellectual or emotional — whether objective or subjec- tive ; — whatever we apprehend in presentation, can be recalled in representation. But the activity of the mind in this general function is not limited to the power of representing objects previously present. It can so far modify the objects of the past experience, as to transform them into new creations. It becomes in this way, in an eminent sense, a creative power. The mind not only can depict a man, a tree, or a mountain as actually witnessed, but it can alter the form, the dimensions, and the appendages or ac- cidents of each, taking parts from the one and attaching them to parts belonging to the other. So, also, it can create or imagine a Lilliputian, a Centaur, a Parnassus, an Abdiel. The representative power in this higher form is called, the fancy or the imagination. § 135. The power thus to act is called the repre- sentative, in distinction from, and in contrast with the fortSepoweS 8 presentative power. In sense-perception and con- sciousness, the mind presents to itself for the first time the objects of its direct and original knowledge. In representation, it presents these objects a second time, or represents them. It is also called reproduction, or the reproductive power, because the mind, by its own energy, under appropriate circum- stances and in obedience to certain laws, reproduces objects pre- viously known. It also involves the pow r er to retain and conserve, in a certain sense, that which has been acquired by the mind. To this 208 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 136. capacity the name cf retention has been given, or the retentive power. To these three distinguishable relations of this power, Hamil- ton has not only assigned separate appellations, but has treated them as separate faculties, viz., the conservative, reproductive, and representative faculties (Met, Lee. xx). But inasmuch as it is implied in the power to represent, that there is a power to reproduce ; and in the power to reproduce, that the mind can retain or conserve, it seems more philosophical to consider and treat retention and reproduction as the essential conditions of representation, rather than as distinct faculties. It is also called the creative power, the constructive or productive imagination, when it evolves new products. This exercise of the representative power has rarely received a technical appellation. § 136. The objects of the representative power are. Objects of the , J f , . -. , , . representative as has already been implied, mental objects. They are not real things or real percepts, but the mind's creations after real things. They are spiritual or psychical, not material entities, although in many cases they concern material things, being psychical transcripts of them, either as believed to be real or as conceived to be possible. When they concern the soul only, they are not the real soul, or its present acts, but psychical transcripts of the real soul in a past or possible condition of action. They are in no sense object-objects, but are preeminently subject-objects. As objects, they are distinguished from the acts of the mind which apprehend them : as subject-objects, they are created by that very mind, and exist only for that mind. As represented subject-objects, they always indicate another reality, whether spiritual or mental. But though the object of the representative power is a mental object, it is an individual object. By this characteristic it is distin- guished from a thought-object, or an object of the intelligence. Thought-objects are both mental objects and subject objects, and, in an important sense, representative-objects : but they are also generalized objects or universals. Objects of representation are like them in that they are purely mental objects, yet are unlike them in being individual. Whether we recall these objects, or create them — whether we copy, as exactly as we can, from an original in nature, or create constructions the most fantastic, grotesque, or § 137. REPRESENTATIVE POWER DEFINED AND EXPLAINED. 209 unnatural, they are all individual. Falstaff, Hamlet, Ivanlioe, Jeannie Deans, Don Quixote," Tarn O'Shanter, the Eden of Milton, the Faery Land of Spenser, were all individual beings in the imagination that originated, and are such in the imagination that reconstructs them as delineated by their originators. § 137. The presented object was known by the .,,.,.'„ These objects mind not only as a being, but m its relations, as of involve rcia- . 77. 7 tions. diversity, space, time, etc. ; so the object as represented, ■may be known again in all these relations, with all those in addi- tion which are implied in its being represented. It should be remembered, however, that a relation as such — i. e., a relation as separate from an object — as it cannot be apprehended by sense- perception or consciousness, so it cannot be recalled by represen- tation. A relation, as such, cannot become an image to the rep- resentative power, but the object in its relations can be imaged. The representative power, not only by its representative act recalls the object in the relations in which it was originally known, but the existence and exercise of this power involves rela- tions that are peculiar to itself. Thus, in recalling a tree or a horse previously perceived, or a mental act of knowledge or state of feeling, I not only bring back the tree or horse as extended and external, and the psychical state as subjective and in time, but, in recalling it, I must know it as a subject-object, and as having been previously perceived or experienced by myself. These relations are necessary and peculiar to the representative power. For the objects of this power we have no appropriate technical name. The words image and picture might be properly applied to the represented percepts of vision ; but to speak of the image of a sound, smell, or touch, would be incongruous, if not offensive. Still less tolerable would it be to speak of the image of an act of knowledge or feeling. Conception cannot be ac- cepted, as was proposed by Stewart, for it is too frequently applied to other and very different objects. Idea would be more significant, if it could be forced back to its original and etymo- logical import ; but idea has, since the time of Locke, been compelled to do all manner of service. In the earlier days of the English language the representative power was called imagi- nation, ox phantasy, and images and phantasms were appropriately and literally applied to its objects. 210 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 139. § 138. The conditions and laws of the representing liwfof'rep?^ power should next be considered. The mind, in Biden!d? n c ° n " representation, as in the exercise of all its powers, acts under limitations and according to laws. In representation, man does not, like the great Originator, create by his own fiat, his world of mental objects. What he reproduces or constructs anew, is in some way dependent upon what he has previously experienced. Not only must every thing which is represented be reproduced from, or by the means of some past experience, but what is represented at any moment depends upon what was present the instant before. The fact that one object or image brings up another to the mind, is called the association of ideas. The conditions or laws under which the mind recalls one object by means of another, are usually called the laws of association. The term is open to exception, because both percepts and experiences are connected with images, as truly as images (or ideas) with images. The phrase is, however, too firmly established in general acceptance and use to be set aside. § 139. The representative power, though marked Represents- i i , • . • i i • tion divided by common characteristics and obeying common rieties. veralva " laws, is divided into several varieties, or species. These are distinguished by the completeness or in- completeness of the pictures which they make of the objects once presented ; by the fidelity with which they adhere to, or the liberty with which they deviate from their originals; by the laws of association which predominate in each variety; and by the ends for which the pow r er is exercised, and the uses to which it is applied. The most perfect exemplification of the exercise of the repre- sentative power is an act of perfect memory. Such an act is always complex, involving the object, the action, and the agent, united by their mutual relations into one indivisible state. If the object is material, it involves certain relations of space ; the action, being one of a continuous series, involves relations of time ; the agent, being the body and soul united, must exist in every act under relations of both space and time. When a single act of presentative knowledge is recalled in all these elements of object and relation, the representation is complete, § 139. REPRESENTATIVE POWER DEFINED AND EXPLAINED. 211 and the act is an act of perfect memory. For example, yes- terday I took a walk to the top of a neighboring eminence. To-day I recall distinctly the landscape which I saw, in its minutest features — re-creating, as I do, a distinct and vivid picture of the scene ; and not only of the scene, but of myself as beholding it, with the actions before and after, with my feelings also in viewing it, and the very accidents of the place where I sat or stood during the view. This is an act of perfect memory ; it includes every element of the original. As time goes on, it is possible that one or another of these ele- ments should be recalled less distinctly, or should be omitted altogether. It is possible that I should be able to bring back the landscape only as an object, and be certain, as I see or think of it, only that I once saw it before ; but how or when, or with what feelings or from what point, I do not recall. Or possibly the object may be lost, and the subjective feelings may alone be revived and recognized as having been before experienced. Re- lations of time and accessories of place may both be lost. Thus, when I see the face of a person in a crowd, I know that I have seen it before ; but when, or where, or with what feelings I can- not recall. I remember a familiar passage of prose or poetry ; I know that I have read or heard it ; but when, or with wliat feelings or attendant circumstances, I cannot tell. All these are acts of what may be called imperfect memory. But memory, whether perfect or imperfect, is clearly distin- guishable from phantasy, or the imaging power. This is repre- sentation without the recognition that the objects recalled have ever been perceived or experienced before. Examples of this are such as the following : I look distinctly at the front of a dwelling, the form of a horse, or the outline of a tree, each of which I wish to retain and make wholly my own. I close my eyes and picture each distinctly to my mind. The undivided force of my attention is expended upon the object, and so suc- cessfully, that it becomes a permanent possession as an object, with few or no accessories of either place or time. In all cases of disturbed fancy, often called phantasy, visions of objects seen before, but not remembered or recognized, throng in upon the soul. There may be no recognition, no knowledge that the object is familiar or has been seen or felt before. These acts are more 212 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 139. likely to occur in those conditions of the soul in which the action of the reason is nearly suspended, or permanently set aside, as in reverie, dreaming, monomania, and partial or complete insanity. But the mind can do more than simply represent the past with greater or less perfection, with or without the act of recognition. It can recombine or construct anew the materials which the past furnishes for it to work with or upon. In such acts it becomes the creative imagination. Of imagination as thus defined, there are several forms or varieties. 1. The mind may neglect or leave out of view all things ex- isting in space, and all events occurring in time, and form to itself pictures of void space, and of time more or less extended or limited. Within these voids it can construct geometrical figures, and arrange series of numbered objects, and thus provide for itself the materials of mathematical science. This is the mathematical imagination. 2. It can separate and unite the parts and attributes of objects and existences, both spiritual and material, in divisions and com- binations which never actually occur, but are grotesque and irra- tional. These separations and unions may be made in obedience only to the more obvious and the lower laws of association. Thus, the chimney of a house can be set upon the hump of a camel, and the ears or head of a donkey upon the body of a man. Or horses may be colored red or yellow. This is phantasy proper ; the products of which are simply grotesque, or as we say, fantastic. 3. Objects may be recalled in wholes or in parts, and recom- bined and reconstructed under the obvious and more natural laws of association, for the ends of wit, humor, or amusement. This is fancy proper, which, as exemplified in literature and some of the fine arts has been thus distinguished from the higher imagina- tion. 4. When the higher objects of nature and spirit are recalled, recombined, and created, with the aid of the nobler laws of asso- ciation, for the higher ends of ideal elevation and improvement — when the more elevated feelings are addressed and excited, and the nobler capacities of man are called into action, then the power becomes poetic iniauinat ion. The sphere of this power is not poetry alone, but eloquence, music, painting, sculpture, archi- § 140. REPRESENTATIVE POWER DEFINED AND EXPLAINED. 213 tecture, and landscape gardening ; inasmuch as all afford oppor- tunities for these higher sentiments and suggestions. This is imagination as contrasted with fancy. 5. When the combinations and creations are effected for the purposes of research, invention, and instruction, and under laws of association which are grounded on scientific or thought-rela- tions, and directed to some definite result or product, we have the philosophic imagination. When the philosophic or the poetic imagination are employed in the service of ethical improvement and religious incitement, they constitute an important element in ethical ideality and religious faith. § 140. The interest and the importance of the re- presentative power is enforced by the following con- importance*!* . -, ,. the representa- siderations : tive power. 1. First of all, the exercise of this power ministers pleasure of a high order and in great variety, which is indejDsn- dent of the accidents of fortune and circumstances. Whether these acts are exercised by the infant in its endless combinations of play and sport, as in the simple story which it constructs out of two or three incidents, or whether they are employed by the novelist or poet in the fiction on which he lavishes all the re- sources of culture, the pleasure of creating is the same. 2. Man often flies to the unreal world of the fancy, to find rest and relief from the highly- wrought excitements of the too earnest and engrossing real world. Ideal objects and conditions furnish associations more pleasing and emotions more satisfying than any which the experience of reality can awaken. The sick man forgets for a brief moment his actual weariness and pain in the scenes of health and action which he imagines. The prisoner is enlarged from his cell. The oppressed forgets his wrong. The homeless dwells under the shelter of his own roof. 3. This power is the necessary condition of the higher functions of the intellect, and of every description of intellectual achieve- ment and progress. The truth is common-place, that memory is the servant of thought and the conservator of our acquisitions. It was not in idle fancy that Mnemosyne was called by the ancients the mother of the Muses. Were the mind limited to the objects and the activities of the present, it could make little 214 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 140. progress of any kind. Thought would be almost impossible. Generalization, by which many objects are viewed as one, would be restricted to the few present objects that could be brought within the range of a single act of comparison. When such an act was finished, its product would be lost forever. It could never be reapplied to a new object, or be enlarged in its sphere. The new individual objects of sense and of consciousness would also be isolated. They could not even be named, for each would stand apart in the loneliness of its own individuality. Language would be impossible. The induction of principles and of laws would be excluded, for, however surely the mind might infer that a common law controlled the objects perceived at a single gaze, neither the objects nor the principles learned through them, could present themselves a second time, the one to be exemplified or the other to be explained. There could be neither invention nor discovery. Even in mathematical science both would be impossible. The creations of art would be excluded. The inventor in mechanics, the composer in poetry or music, the thinker in morals, philosophy, and letters, the deviser of beneficent schemes for human well- being, are each and all dependent on the resources of the imagi- nation for every possible conjunction of cause and effect, of tendency and result. No more manifest or more serious error can be committed, than for the philosopher to decry the imagina- tion as injurious to, or inconsistent with, eminent scientific activity and achievement. The practical uses of the imagination are not to be overlooked. It creates ideals of what we might be and do, which are fir higher and nobler than any thing which we are, or which we perform. It lifts us above ourselves and the examples we observe in real life, furnishing loftier standards toward which we may aspire. A pure and elevated imagination is in many ways allied to a noble ethical nature, and favors an ardent and a sustained religious faith. § 143. THE REPRESENTATIVE OBJECT. 215 CHAPTER II. THE REPRESENTATIVE OBJECT — ITS NATURE AND IMPORTANCE. § 141. The product of the representative power, or the object which the raind creates and apprehends J h reprLenta- in memory and imagination, has been the occasion of cia?discussion] much confusion of thought, and not a little contro- versy. Scarcely any single topic has been more vexed in ancient or mediaeval philosophy, than the nature of representative images. In the discussion of this topic, three topics or heads of inquiry present themselves : I. The nature and mode of existence of the object which the mind remembers and imagines. II. Its relation to the original from which it is derived and to which it is referred. III. The special service which it renders in thought and action. I. The nature and mode of existence of the representative object. § 142. These objects or products, as has already been stated (§ 136), are psychical existences. They cMcafobject?" exist in and for the soul only. They are at once the products of the mind which brings them into being, and objects for the same mind to cognize or contemplate. Whether they are transcribed from real beings and real acts, or whether they are created out of the materials or upon suggestions which real objects furnish, they are in all cases purely psychical and spiritual. It makes no difference whether the original is material, or spiritual ; the idea or image of each is simply psychical. § 143. The mental object is as transient and evanescent as the act by which it is brought into S ient IS a tT &nd being. In this respect the mental object is strikingly JS** 1 *^ ° L " contrasted with objects that are real. The acts by which we know both psychical and actual objects, are for a moment. They cease to be at the instant in which they begin. So is it with the psychical as contrasted with the real object. The re'al object alone is fixed and permanent. To it we can come and from it we can go, and find it still the same. But the psychical trans- cript or creation is as short-lived and evanescent as the act by which we behold it. 216 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 144. These psychical objects of the representative power are to be distinguished from those spectra or hallucinations which result from an abnormal or morbid condition of the sensorium or the nervous organism. The first are psychical, the second are psycho- physical. The first are spiritual in their nature, the second are dependent upon the soul as connected with the sensorium. The hallucinations or spectra, are intimately related to those sub- jective sensations, which, as we have seen, are caused by any excitement of the sensorium by means of subjective agencies as distinguished from material objects (cf. § 78). They are not properly representative images or ideas, which are purely psy- chical creations and objects, being created by a psychical power under psychical conditions, and having only a psychical ex- istence. if is an mtei- ' § 1^4. These representative objects, are not only lectuai object, psychical, but they are intellectual objects. It has been held by some that when memory recalls past psychical expe- riences of feeling and of will it recalls the experiences themselves, and not our ideas of them. " It is not ideas, notions, cogni- tions only, but feelings and conations, which are held fast, and which can, therefore, be again awakened." "Memory does not belong alone to the cognitive faculties, but the law extends in like manner over all the three primary classes of the mental phenom- ena." {Ham. Met., Lee. xxx). This opinion of H. Schmid is ap- parently sanctioned by Hamilton. It is a logical inference from one of the doctrines which he seems to advance concerning con- sciousness. But if consciousness is an act of knowledge, and know- ledge, when matured, gives, as its products, intellectual objects which we can recall ; then, as when we feel we know that we feel, so, when we remember that we have felt, we remember our past feeling as an object known — i. e., we recall our idea of it (§ 56). The pleasure which I enjoy is not the original pleasure revived, but a fresh pleasure from the object recalled by the intellect, and perhaps a reflex pleasure from the fact that it is* revived. But whatever it be which excites the pleasure, whether the exciting object or the pleasure excited, it is the object, or the pleasure as remembered — that is, it is an intellectual object which it apprehended by the mind. The representative object is not only a psychical, but it is also an intellectual object. § 146. THE REPRESENTATIVE OBJECT. 217 II. The relation of the representative idea to its original. § 145. The relation which the represented object 1 . . The relation can holds to the real or presented object, is sui generis, be compared to and can neither be resolved into, nor explained by any other, It is important to distinguish it from those relations with which it is so often confounded, and thus to clear away many errors into which philosophy has often been betrayed. § 146. In doing so, we observe: (1.) That the Representative ideas which we acquire by consciousness or perception ideas of objects ., , 7 7i« • • 7 • i of conscious- cannot possibly resemble their originals, either as parts ness and sense- to parts or as wholes to wholes. Neither the single nTt^sembie features nor the combined wholes of any mental em ' emory ' transcripts can by any possibility resemble the single features or united wholes of any material or spiritual being or act. A mental object is wholly incapable of being confronted or com- pared with an existing reality. One material thing can be like another material thing as a whole and as a part ; one spiritual being, or a single spiritual act, can be like another spiritual being or act ; one tree can be like another tree ; one mental state can be like another ; one act of perception can be like another act ; but the mental image of a tree cannot be like a tree, nor can the mental remembrance of a mental experience resemble or be like the original act or state. It is true, one of these may be loosely and vaguely said to resemble or be like the other ; but that this language is only employed in the way of analogy, is evident from the contradic- tions and absurdities into which those philosophers have involved themselves who have understood it literally. "We have seen (§ 129) to what contradictory and impossible conclusions Locke's definitions of knowledge, as the discernment of a conformity or resemblance of ideas with their objects, ex- posed himself, and actually conducted Berkeley and Hume. The representative idea is not known to consciousness as resem- bling any original. We observe still further : (2.) When we remember or recognize objects which we have previously known, we do not discern any proper resemblance between the original and its mental tran- script. For example, we look upon an object, as a house, a tree, a portrait, the page of a book ; or we hear a sound, we perform 10 218 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 146. some mental act, or experience some feeling ; and when the object is removed, we recall it in our memory. It were simply absurd to say that we recall the material object by its mental object, or that we remember the object by its likeness to the mental picture which we revive to our minds. A discerned re- semblance supposes two objects between which the likeness is seen ; but in an act of simple memory it is plain that only one object is before the mind. It is therefore clearly impossible that any resemblance should be discerned; for that two objects would be necessarily required. In recalling or remembering a past object, event, or mental experience, we simply picture it as having been before discerned or experienced in fact, and we do this by a direct act of knowledge. When it is said that this mental image is transcribed from the original, or represents it, the language describes an act and objects which are emphatically sui generis, and incomparable with any other. The relation of these mental transcripts to their originals can only be understood by considering the acts of the mind by which we acquire and recall them. The nature of mental products can only be understood by the mental acts which give them birth. To understand the relation of a transcript to its original, we must consider the nature of the act by which we acquire it, as related to the act by which we recall and revive the same. To bring these acts together, in order to compare them, let them be employed alternately upon the same object. As the eye opens and shuts upon the landscape seen and the landscape imaged, the real landscape is alternately remembered and perceived. When the eye is shut, it is remembered as having been seen. When it is recognized, it is recognized as the same that we saw before, and which we had remembered during the in- terval ; but in neither case is any resemblance discerned. It is involved in the act of memory, that the object perceived should be recreated by the mind and recalled as real, and also that, when the object is remembered, it should be recognized as the same which was perceived. Moreover, there is also involved the knowledge that the object as perceived was real, and that the ob- ject as reproduced in memory is mental only. § 147. THE REPRESENTATIVE OBJECT. 219 § 147. The nature of any product or object is de- Positive de- termined by the mind's capacity to originate it ; and mental pic- the authority of the mind to trust it and accept the objects which its own activities involve, is to be found in the fact that it finds itself, so to speak, spontaneously exercising the power. Concerning this peculiar object and its relation to its original, we affirm positively: — (1.) The mental picture affects the sensibilities less powerfully than the perception or experience of the reality. By the supposition, if the original be a sense or material object, it must move or excite the senses; and this class of experiences are in their essential nature absorbing and vivid. If the experience be of a mental act or state, no recollection or transcript can match the reality in its power to interest and excite the soul. Different persons differ greatly in the power vividly to repro- duce and make real the past, and as greatly in the capacity to be moved by it in their sensibilities. Some persons cannot revive a scene of pleasure or pain without ecstasy or horror ; the very picture or remembrance of any thing which they have en- joyed or suffered seems to revive much of the delight or pain which the original experience occasioned. But even the sensi- bility of such persons to the pictures which their memory re- vives, is usually in direct ratio to their susceptibility to the pre- sent and the real. That the real object excites more feeling than the same object remembered, is assented to by common ex- perience and confirmed by universal testimony. Segnitis irritant animos demissa per aurem Quam quse sunt oculis subjeeta fidelibus, et quse Ipse sibi tradit spectator. — Hor. De, Art, Poet. 0, who can hold a fire in his hand, By thinking on the frosty Caucasus ? Or cloy the hungry edge of appetite, By hare imagination of a feast ?— Shakspeare, Rich. II. (2.) The mental picture consists of fewer elements than the original. It is but a scanty outline, as contrasted with its fullness — a skeleton as compared with its roundness and life. We look at a real tree, and in the background there is the con- fused or vague perception of the as yet undistinguished mass of form and color, while from it is projected in bold relief a few promi- 220 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §147. nent parts that attract and hold the attention. If we test by the reality the best picture that we can frame in the fancy, we are surprised at the poverty of the one and the richness of the other. (3.) The mental picture is recalled in parts under the laws by which one suggests another, and is constructed with comparative slowness. The reality displays its wealth of detail as coexistent and at a single view. Or, if we study its details with attentive ana- lysis, we do this with inconceivable rapidity, under the guidance and suggestion of the object itself. The object, when re-created in memory, is re-created in the several parts of which it is com- posed : if a material object, in the several sense-percepts which make it a thing or whole. If it is extended in space, or mani- fold or irregular in outline, the parts of the surface and outline must be recovered one by one, under the laws of association, and by acts that are successive to one another in time. To illustrate these contrasted features, we need select but a single example. It is a precipice up which we gaze. First it im- presses us as a whole, diversified by its varied features. Foremost are the broad faces of perpendicular or impending rock. These are buttressed by slopes strewn with accumulated fragments. Here and there are bushy crags and scattered boulders. The whole cuts against the sky with a notched outline, fringed here and there with nodding herbage, or broken by some daring tree, that, stayed upon its uncertain footing, reaches out and up toward heaven. If all this is apprehended by sense-perception, the quick eye first surveys the whole with a rapid sweep, then runs hither and thither, as it is caught and led by some salient feature, the rock itself bringing out new material faster than the mind can appropriate it, impressing the feelings with new emotions of wonder the longer we strive to master its wealth. Let us seek to image that rock in the mind, at evening, when we are just returned from a fresh gaze upon its front. In place of the exhaustless confusion of the vaguely-seen whole to guide and excite the eye, there is slowly revived the scanty frame- work of the few parts which can be recalled by the mind. These parts are recovered one by one, as the mind resting upon what is already present brings back in fragments, and by repeated efforts, that which each present object suggests. However exciting § 148. THE REPRESENTATIVE OBJECT. 221 the effort to recall and reconstruct, and however pleasing the picture that is recalled, the impressiveness and exciting power of the reality are wholly wanting. The objects which the creative fancy or imagination in any way combines or constructs do not differ greatly from those which the memory transcribes, in their relation to the real existences of matter or spirit. The only material difference between the two can be expressed in a word — the one represents real, the other possible existences : the originals of the one in fact exist, and have in fact been perceived or experienced ; realities correspond- ing to the other might exist. In every other respect the two classes of objects coincide. III. The usefulness of ideas in thought and action. § 148. The special service of the products of the , . . In thought, we representative power for thought and action remain prefer ideas to to be considered. It has already been observed (§ § 48, 56), that the process of perception, or consciousness, is normal and complete when it results in an idea or image — i. e., when a transcript of the individual object is prepared for future recall. The usefulness of these acquired facts and of these ideas of possibilities of nature will be accepted by every one. That they are absolutely indispensable to secure the past, and to give range and reach to invention, is obvious to every mind. But it is not clearly, certainly it is not generally acknowledged, that, for the purposes of thought, remembrances are often better than percepts, and that the pale and scanty images which the mind creates are often superior to the fresh experiences which life presents. We often even prefer to employ mental images, when we might avail ourselves of actual observations. We often turn a fact into a mental picture or recollection, even while our eyes, our ears, and our attent consciousness seem to be occupied with a present reality. The reason is, that the image, (supposed to be correct) presents to- the mind fewer elements than the reality, and therefore does not distract, but aids the attention in the activities of thought. Moreover, the elements which it includes are usually the very elements or features with which thought concerns itself. For this reason recollection often guides thinking, and aids it in its work. 222 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 149. When we change our perceptions into ideas, or ideate our perceptions, we retain only what we attend to ; hence the image presents fewer points or elements than the original. We are likely to attend to what is most important, especially if we bring to our observations an eye instructed by the previous training of thought, or the experiences of scientific inquiry. A disciplined mind will of necessity direct the observations of things to those features with which thought is concerned ; and these points will remain recorded in the memory for thought to classify, or be recombined in the imagination for thought to invent and to explain. In a certain sense, representation abstracts while it revives ; as it omits much of what it perceives or feels, and retains only what it cares for. Hence, in observations of things which are accompanied with any comparative analysis of judgment, we close and open the senses by alternate acts. We close the sense, that we may with undistracted thought think or judge of the image which it gives. We open and use it again, that we may correct or fix the image by or upon which we think. § 149. As the mind widens its range of materials Ideas especial- « , , -, i • i t • ly useful in lor thought, and rises to higher generalizations, its and generaii- images of things will need to consist of still fewer features — viz., those only which it needs to use in classification or reasoning. So far as it brings before its view concrete realities or individual examples, these need only contain those parts or elements which come into use in generalization, induction, or argument. The plastic power of representation here comes into play, which can readily omit all that is not necessary to be considered and can easily supply every thing that illustration or discovery may need. Kepresentation can go so far in its abstractions as to leave but a meagre outline, a mere skeleton of a concrete thing or group of objects. Such a skeleton has been called a schema. Such a schema or outline-image has been held not only to be the ne- cessary condition for the formation and use of concepts, but it has been also contended that it is like the concept in being general and equally applicable to every individual thing to which the concept can be referred. For example, when we speak § 149. THE REPRESENTATIVE OBJECT. 223 or think of such terms or things as horse, dog, or flower, it is urged that the mind frames a schema, or outline-image of the form or other relations of each subject, which is equally suitable to every individual horse, dog, or flower. This schema, it is urged, differs from the concept, in that it is not divided or severed into constituent elements, each one of which is regarded as an attri- bute of a substance, but it remains as an extremely abstracted whole, which may be applied to every individual horse, dog, or flower. This view contradicts the doctrine which we have laid down, that the object in representation is always individual, and never general. The image of a horse or dog need not be general because it is very scanty or meagre in its constituent elements, having to do only with a few that are characteristic, as the form, the head, the limbs, etc. ; but so far as the object is imaged at all it must be individual. The reason why it seems to be general is, that being a creation of the imagination, it can readily be changed by addition or omission, so as to conform to the horse or dog before us. It is more exact to say that the schema is conformable rather than general ; i. e., it is capable of being readily adjusted to every object of its class, and hence its preeminent utility. Whatever form or features the individual image may take which we happen to construct, it can be easily shaped and adjusted to the individual example before us. The nature of the outline image, or schema, and its relation to the concept, will be still further considered under the concept. (§107.) We observe, however, in passing, that it is more than a mere conceit to say, that, as we rise from perception to thought, we in- terpose the image or idea as an intermediate object which is less gross and entangling than matter, and yet more substantial, de- finite, and concrete than thought. The image directs and aids the concept, standing, as it does, midway between it and the percept. On the other hand, the idea, especially when directed by thought, reacts upon perception itself, making it more intelli- gent and productive, as it directs the senses to what features it should attend, and often anticipates what they will find. In this way aimless efforts are spared, fruitless voyages of discovery are avoided, and the energies of the mind are expended upon pro- ductive objects. 224 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 150. § 150. Not only do images assist in perception and Images pre- x x , pare for and thought, but they prepare for and so prompt to action. aid to action. _„ & ' .. , . . . . „ , ^ li we recall an object which formerly moved us to excited feeling and impelled us to prompt and energetic action, the thought of the same object is fitted to excite us again in a similar manner, in real or mimic activity, in body and in soul. If an action is soon to be performed — if we are to sling a stone, or point a rifle, or throw a quoit, the image of the act and object held before the mind brings all the muscles into position, and makes ready for the act required, the instant the act is called for. Hence, in any discipline for feats of bodily dexterity, a vivid and concentrated fancy, a strong and kindling imagination, are of essential service, as they bring the powers into that position which effective activity requires. The same is true of discipline to mental exertion, so far as any purely spiritual activity de- pends on the distinct conception of its object. The thought of an enemy to be assailed, or of a wrong to be avenged, knits the muscles, braces the limbs, and convulses the features. The sensitive idealist is convulsed with horror at the pictures which his imagination draws of the scenes of cruelty which he reads of or conceives. He acts over, in fancy, the part which he himself would be ready to take in any depicted scene. When men are to act in concert ; as to row, or pull, or shout, in unison, or to repel an assault, or to storm a battery, or in any way to use their united strength, their imagination must be brought into active service in anticipating beforehand the objects which will soon present themselves, or the kind of activities in which they are to engage. The ideal is far better than the real scene for the purposes of discipline and anticipation. The real object may distract and bewilder as well as arouse and hold the attention. It may over-excite, and so unman. It may bring up unexpected objects, as well as those which are looked and hoped for. The reality, as compared with the idea, may hinder action, as it hinders thought. While, then, the idea cannot take the place of the reality, and discipline by means of the idea is of little avail unless it actually prepares for action, it is essential to such preparation. Nature has provided for this discipline by the strong impulse which she awakens toward it : she secures great deeds by first awakening grand pictures in the excited fancy. § 151. THE CONDITIONS AND LAWS OF REPRESENTATION. 225 CHAPTER III. THE CONDITIONS AND LAWS OP REPRESENTATION — THE ASSO- CIATION OP IDEAS. § 151. We have noticed already that the soul, in Association of , ,• • n •■ ±_ r> ,• • v •. j ideas, impor- representation, as in all its acts or functions, is limited terestoTthe 111 " to fixed conditions, and acts according to established subject laws. What is recalled at any moment, though re- called by the soul's proper activity, is always recalled by means of the cognitions and feelings which the soul possessed the moment previous. The general fact or truth that ideas are rep- resented by means of ideas now present, is usually designated under the general title or phrase ; " the association of ideas." The term suggestion has, by some writers, been preferred to association. They prefer to say, one idea suggests another idea, rather than, one idea is associated with another. This preference is partly a matter of taste in words, and in part is grounded on the philosophical theory which one of these terms is supposed to designate better than the other. Some object to the phrase, The suggestion or association of ideas, because ideas are not the only objects or elements that are concerned-; real or existing objects or phenomena being as truly capable of exciting representations as the ideas or remembrances of things. But, the phrase is too well established in general use to be easily set aside, even though the reasons for so doing were vastly stronger than they are found to be in fact. To seek to determine what are the conditions and laws of repre- sentation, is to propose an inquiry to which we are impelled by the intrinsic interest and even mystery with which the power itself and its actings are invested to all thoughtful minds. Ham- ilton observes (Mei.,Lec. xxxi.), that " the scholastic psychologists seem to have regarded the succession in the train of thought, or, as they called it, the excitation of the species, with peculiar wonder, as one of the most inscrutable mysteries of Nature." " The younger Scaliger says : 'My father declared that of the causes of three things in particular he was wholly ignorant — of 10* 226 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 151. the intervals of fevers, of the ebb and flow of the sea, and of reminiscence.' " " The excitation of species is declared by Poncius ' to be one of the most difficult secrets of Nature (ex difficilioribus natural arcanis);' and Oviedo, a Jesuit schoolman, says, ' Therein lies the very greatest mystery of all philosophy (maximum totius philosophies sacramentum).' " This impression of mystery and the wonder which it excites are not at all surprising. Thoughts and images come and go with the apparent caprice and lawlessness of wizards and fairies — now obtruding themselves when they are not wanted, and then hiding themselves most provokingly, not- withstanding the most earnest desires and the loudest calls for their return. To explain these phenomena by certain definite prin- ciples is an essential prerequisite to an enlightened theory of each of the special forms of this power, as the memory, the fancy, and the imagination, in all their varieties. All these so-called powers of the soul are, as has been explained, but special forms of the general power mentally to represent the actual past, and they must all depend upon common conditions, and obey common laws. A just and well founded theory of the association of ideas lies at the foundation of any satisfactory theory of all these several powers. Representations are also always employed in the actings of the other leading powers, viz., sense-perception and thought ; and for this reason the consideration of the laws which regulate their presence or absence is essential to a com- plete elucidation of the powers with which, at first, they seem to have little concern. On the other hand, when the movements of representation are explained, this explanation is taken to ex- plain almost every thing beside ; so largely do the coming and going of represented objects enter into the other phenomena of the soul. A very considerable number of psychologists, as we have already remarked, have accordingly resolved all the psychical powers into the operation of the laws of association — viz., reasoning, induction, the belief in causality and adaptation, and even in time and space. The association of ideas has played a most conspicuous role in the modern theories of the soul and its operations, and its influence upon such theories was perhaps never so great as at present. Next to false or inadequate theories of sense-perception, have incorrect theories of the association of ideas exercised the most mischievous influence upon the § 153. THE CONDITIONS AND LAWS OF REPRESENTATION. 227 scientific views of the soul, and indirectly on philosophical, ethical, and theological theories (cf. § 40). § 152. To form a correct theory, it is necessary, as in similar cases, to state at some length the defective or erroneous theories which have been accepted to explain these operations and laws. This will enable us to pronounce a critical judgment upon their error, as well as to recognize the truth which they include, and will prepare us to develop a theory that is true and satisfactory. It will be observed, that the laws of association pertain to what Hamilton calls the reproductive, as distinguished from the representative power; in other words, to those operations of the soul which prepare objects for the soul's appre- hension, as distinguished from the soul's acts in cognizing them when prepared and presented ( $43). In representation in all its forms, these functions must necessarily be very prominent and important. In representation, the soul pre- pares and furnishes its own objects of cognition. The capacity to do this, and the laws under which the operation is performed, are analogous to the psycho- physiological capacities and acts of the soul by which sense-objects are pre- pared for the soul's sense-perceptions. (§ 135.) The laws of association have been divided into two leading classes, the primary and secondary, which otherwise may be de- nominated general and special. They are distinguished thus : the primary or general are those which act or tend to act at all times and in all persons, while the secondary and special are those which determine the associations of different persons or of the same persons at different times. The theories which we shall notice apply to both these classes, though more eminently to the primary. We begin with I. The primary laws of association. § 153. We observe, (1.) that the theory is unten- Association not able which explains the phenomena of associations j^Jff" 1 ^ a ^_ by the mechanical or physiological laws of a bodily Ka *ion. organ which is assumed to be the instrument of the soul in representation. It has been held by not a few writers, among whom Bonnet was conspicuous, that the brain, or nervous system, is such an organ. As what we know in sense-perception was thought to be or depend upon certain vibrations, undulations, or oscillations of the brain and nerves, so it was held that the objects thus 228 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 153. apprehended for the first time can be re-presented to the imagi- nation or the memory, whenever these same oscillations or vibra- tions are resumed or repeated. Others maintained that every act of perception results in a permanent condition or disposition of certain of these fibres, which is active again in represen- tation. Some held that, in addition to the oscillating fibres of the brain, there is also present a very delicate and sensitive fluid, intermediate between the brain and the soul. Those who held that the soul is immaterial, insisted that the brain and nervous system are its organs in representation, on the action of which the mind as completely depends for its images and remembrances in representation, as it does on the organs of sense for its objects in perception. Still greater plausibility was sought for this theory by the attempt to show that the soul itself has a special seat or organ in the brain, by the sympathy of which with the vibrations of the remaining portions all its phenomena can be explained. In view of the theory that the senses and the imagination were thus dependent upon the sensorium, i. e., the brain and nervous sys- tem, etc., these powers were formerly ascribed to the lower or inferior energy, which was called the animal soul, or the soul in contrast with the spirit or higher and rational soul, to which the nobler and more spiritual functions were allotted. In modern times, since the various sensible qualities have been resolved into modes of motion, and many physiologists and some psychologists have resolved the capacities of the sensorium for different sensa- tions into simple susceptibilities for more rapid vibrations, there has been a renewed disposition to make the representative power to depend on revived vibrations of the nervous energy. Such theories have, however, been usually carried out to the bald materialism with which they have a strong affinity. We have already explained sufficiently how earnestly the cere- bralists and associationalists of recent times reassert the same views, and seek to enforce them by the aid of the results of modern physiology. (§40.) All these theories fail to be supported, by reason of a common defect. The structure of the brain and nervous system in no way indicates that they are capable of the vibrations or oscilla- tions which are postulated of them. This structure is not en- tirely fibrous. What seem to be fibres, are not capable of the § 153. THE CONDITIONS AND LAWS OF REPRESENTATION. 229 tension and relaxation which vibrations, whether rapid and forcible, or slow and feeble, would require. They are not suffi- ciently numerous to answer to the myriads of millions of states of thought and feeling which are represented in memory and the fancy. Not a single change of the kind alleged has ever been known to occur in connection with a represented object. We call the eye and the ear organs of sight and hearing, because, with the observed conditions and the varying states of these organs, sensations are present or absent, or vary in quality and force ; but never has a nerve- movement been observed, or even conjectured, to which might be referred the remembered face of an absent friend, or the vivid picture of a once-visited scene. Nor has any vibration of fibres or nerves ever been known to be connected with any picture or remembrance what- ever. No nerve-cell has been known to be formed in connection with a picture fixed in the memory, or a purpose decisively taken. Again, the theory, if satisfactory in every other par- ticular, would fail entirely to account for the creative energy of the imagination. Eepresentations of this sort are very abundant, and often very vivid and forcible ; but how the most of these fantastic and gorgeous scenes could be provided for by any dis- position of fibres or vibration of nerves, it is impossible to see. What makes the theory plausible is the fact that certain conditions of the body are connected with a special activity of the representative power. In some of these states this activity is excessive, irregular, and even uncontrollable. When ^the body is in health and in a normal condition, memory both acquires and gives up its treasures with the ease and exactness of instinct; and imagination combines and creates, as if by the spell of an enchanter, so skilfully as to be herself surprised at her own work. Under the excitement of delirium, the eleva- tion of enthusiasm, or the brief madness of passion, the power to recall and create seems almost to be used by another self; now mocking the vain efforts of the man to control the rush of his too affluent fancy, and now suggesting for his service or his delight unexpected stores of facts and" fancies. It is vain, at times, that the soul essays to retard or to still the throng of unwelcome images that break in upon it like a succession of stormy waves. In sleeplessness induced by an elation of the 230 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 153. nervous system, the rational soul seems to be separated from the imagination, and to become the passive spectator of its wayward caprices. We are wearied to exhaustion by the force and per- sistence with which these fancies at once bewilder and overmaster us. In delirium, the fancy seems to have completely overmas- tered the intelligence, paralyzed its functions, or frightened it from asserting its rightful supremacy. These phenomena can be accounted for by two considerations : First, there is the general truth, that the soul is dependent for the measure of force which it has at command, on the force and normal activity of the powers which maintain the corporeal life. When the bodily force is weakened, the force of the mind is often weakened in every one of its functions — in sense, represen- tation and thought. Second, a disturbance of the functions and activities of the body is attended with an unequal action of the powers of the soul. This can in part be accounted for by the obtrusive influ- ence of the sensations and other mental experiences which are the consequence of irregular bodily action. The soul seems to have at its command only a certain quantum of psychical energy, which may be evenly distributed among the various activities of which it is capable — as sense, consciousness, repre- sentation, and thought ; or, if concentrated into one, it is in so far withdrawn from the rest. It has already been noticed, that we cannot exert the utmost energy in hearing and seeing at the same instant ; still less can we employ sense-perception and the reasoning powers at the same moment and with the highest energy and effect. In extreme hunger or active pain, the sen- sations are so absorbing as to exclude all energetic spiritual activities, whether of thought or feeling. In still other con- ditions, the generally dormant vital and muscular sensations may be so positively obtrusive as to weaken the soul's capacity to fix the attention upon any other objects with steadiness and effect. And yet these muscular or vital sense-perceptions, though obtrusive and unpleasant as sensations, may be so vague and indefinite as perceptions, as to serve chiefly as the suggestors — under the laws of mental association — of other images. We ought never to forget that, in all conditions of our existence, so long as we exist as soul and body, these vague sensations of § 154. CONDITIONS AND LAWS OF REPRESENTATION. 231 which the body in all its parts is the occasion, form the constant background on which are projected the more definite and dis- tinctly remembered of our experiences. When these sensations become more than usually active, through an excited or a diseased condition of the body, they can suggest every image with which they have been connected in the past ; and thus preoccupy the whole force of the soul's activity. The condition of the body may affect the whole activity of the soul, by simply introducing unusual psychical experiences, which operate according to purely psychical laws, both in withdrawing the attention from the rational functions, and in obtruding a throng of associated images. These considerations explain many cases of the singular and almost capricious dependence of the memory upon the varying condi- tions of the body. § 154. (2.) The phenomena of association cannot be resolved into any attractive force in the ideas sociatkm °can- themselves, by which they suggest or revive one an- to raVattaTc- other. This theory differs from the one just discussed, idlas^uch. n in making the ideas, as psychical agents, to exert a force similar to that which was ascribed to brain cells or brain fibres. Many of the explanations given of the phenomena of associa- tion, represent ideas as attracting one another somewhat as two drops of water, or two globules of quicksilver rush into one ; or as if, when the larger drop or globule is divided, the one divi- sion draws the other after itself. Thus Hobbes writes : " All fancies [phantasms] are notions within us, relics of those made in the sense; and those notions that immediately succeeded one another in the sense continue also together after sense; in so much as the former, coming again to take place, and be predominant, the latter followeth, by cohe- rence of the matter moved, in such manner as water upon a plane table is drawn which way any one part of it is guided by the finger." (Lev.,-p. i. ch. iii. ; cf. Hum. Nat., ch. iii., § 2; and Elem. Phil., ch. xxv. Locke says : "Some of our ideas have a natural correspondence and connection one with another : Ideas that in themselves are not at all of kin, come to be so united in some men's minds that 'tis very hard to separate them ; they always keep in company, and the one no sooner at any time comes into the understanding, but its associate appears with it, and if they are more than two which are thus united, the whole gang always inseparable, show themselves together." {Essay. B. ii., c. xxxiii., $ 5). Hume says : " These are, therefore, the principles of union or cohesion among our simple ideas, and in the imagination supply tbe place of that inseparable 232 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 155. connection by which they are united in our memory. Here is a kind of attraction, which in the mental world will be found to have as extraordinary effects as in the natural, and to show itself in as many and as various forms. Its effects are every- where conspicuous ; but as to its causes, they are mostly unknown, and must be resolved into original qualities of human nature, which I pretend not to explain." {Hum. Nat., B. i.,p. i.,Sec. iv.) James "MiM (Analysis of the Human Mind, chap, iii.) says: "When two or more ideas have been often repeated together, and the association has become very strong, they sometimes spring up in such close com- bination as not to be distinguishable. Some cases of sensation are analogous. For example : when a wheel, on the seven parts of which the seven prismatic colors are respectively painted, is made to revolve rapidly, it appears not of seven colors, but of one uniform color — white. By the rapidity of the succession the several sensations cease to be distinguishable ; they run, as it were, together, and a new sensation, compounded of all the seven, but apparently a single one, is the result. Ideas, also, which have been so often conjoined, that whenever one exists in the mind the others immediately exist along with it, seem to run into one another — to coalesce, as it were, and out of many to form one idea ; which idea, however in reality complex, appears to be no less simple than any of those of which it is compounded," etc., etc. This view is accepted by J. Stuart Mill, and the doctrine of " inseparable associations," thus enounced, is with him the axiom, which is the "open sesame" of all metaphysical and psychological problems. The most consistent and thorough-going advocate of this theory of the attrac- tive force of ideas, as ideas, either in ancient or modern times, is Herbart. All the mental phenomena, and even the several powers of the mind, he accounts for by the actions and reactions of these ideas. Ideas are strengthened when they recur often enough to gather the force which blends them into one or arranges them in a permanent series. After being experienced, they remain in a condition of constant tension, ready on the slightest occasion to rush back into the posses- sion or rather the presence of the soul; and again pressing hard to return as soon as a kindred object of perception or representation shall attract them back. This theory is open to similar objections with the one which follows, with which it is intimately allied. We observe next, that • . . M S 155. (3.) The conditions and laws of representa- Nor into the ° > J ... force of reia- tion cannot be referred solely, or even primarily, to tious as such. , i»»«i»i_*« the force of certain classes of relations which exist between ideas. This theory is, in its principle, not superior to that which ascribes attractive force to the ideas themselves. Aristotle enumerates three of the relations which are said to constitute the laws of representation, viz. : Contiguity in time and space, resemblance, and contrariety (De Mem. et Rem.,c. ii.,§ viii.). Hume asserts the three laws of association to be resemblance, con- tiguity in time and place, and cause and effect. Others increase this number to seven, viz. : Coexistence or consecution in time; contiguity in space; dependence as cause and effect, means and end, whole and part ; resemblance or contrast ; the being produced by § 155. CONDITIONS AND LAWS OF REPRESENTATION. 233 the same power or conversant about the same object; signified and signifying ; designated by the same sound. Others, as Hamilton, contract them to two: Simultaneity and affinity. All these laws are founded in truth. They all describe facts of conscious- ness, although they fail as we shall see to recognize the ultimate principle or law of the mind's activity, in such cases. Examples can easily be adduced of the representation of ideas under all of these relations. We begin with those of 'place. "When I recall a single building upon a familiar street, I think at once of the building adjoining, and so on, of each that is next. Contiguity of time is illustrated by the following: When a single event is thought of, which occurred upon some day of my life made memorable by joy or sorrow, that event suggests the others which occurred in connection with itself — either before or after — till the whole history of the day has passed in review before the eye of the mind. Inasmuch as all objects adjacent in space must, if perceived with attention, be originally perceived by acts successive to one another in time, it may and generally will happen that when they are recalled as contiguous, they may also be recalled as suc- cessively perceived ; and thus often the relations of time and place act conjointly. Thus, if I examine the interior of a large public hall or church, I may walk around it on my feet, drawing near to every part which I inspect ; or, standing in one place, I may survey every object by successive applications of the eye, fixing the objects in memory by the relations of time. But these objects are also contiguous in place, and form together a whole of space. The relations of similarity and of contrast serve to recall objects. If I see a house like the one in which I lived when a child — it is of no consequence when or where — it causes me to think of my early home. If I see a face that resembles the face of a dear but absent friend, it brings that friend to mind. The likeness may be of the whole to the whole, or of a part to a part ; as of a door or roof (the part of a house) to a door or roof; or of a single feature in the face to another feature. So, objects that are unlike, especially such as are strikingly con- trasted, recall one another. Cold makes us think of heat, light 234 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §156. reminds us of darkness, joy of sorrow and sorrow* of joy, sweet of bitter and bitter of sweet. The relation of cause and effect is constantly recognized in our experience. The cause may recall the effect, or the effect the cause. Fire makes me think of heat, and ice of cold. The wound under which I suffer, recalls the blow which caused it. Under cause and effect, and dependent upon it, is the relation of means and ends. Any instrument or contrivance suggests the use for which it was devised. Thus, a fire-engine makes us think of a conflagration ; a locomotive, of the drawing of a railway train ; a thumbscrew, or a case of surgical instruments, of torture or amputation. The thought of an end suggests the possible or necessary means. If a weight is to be raised, or a building is to be moved, we think of a lever, or a combination of screws and rollers. To these relations three -others have been added. Operations or objects of the same power or faculty, suggest one another, and the faculty concerned. The sign suggests the thing signified, and the thing signified the sign. Objects accidentally denoted by the same sound are associated. A little attention will convince any one that all these may find a place -either under the law of cause and effect, or under the very comprehensive relation of con- tiguity of space and time. The attempt to increase the number of the rela- Are not other . relations sup- tions that are conceived to operate as laws of asso- posable? . .. _. . _ ciation and conditions of representation, most natu- rally suggests the inquiry, whether there is any special charm in the three or four relations of resemblance, contrast, contiguity of space and time, and causation, which invests these alone with efficacy in the production of ideas. We ask at once, Why may not any other relations serve as well as these ? Why, of the two objects that are connected by any relations whatever, may not each suggest its correlate ? We find, in point of fact, that this is so — that objects connected by many special relations, as of premise and conclusion, evidence and inference, do recall each other. § 156. (4.) Philosophers have with greater plau- Stegration? d " sibility united all these relations under what they have called the law of redintegration, which is thus § 156. CONDITIONS AND LAWS OF REPKESENTATION. 235 announced : Objects that have been previously united as parts of a single mental state, tend to recall or suggest one another. Redinte- gration, as here used, is equivalent to the complete restoration of the whole, on condition of the presence of one or more of its parts. This law was announced by St. Augustine, by Wolff, by Malebranche, by J. G. E. Maass, and is accepted with some qualification by Hamilton. It is an interesting question, whether this law will meet and explain all the special cases of representation. If we concede that the three or four laws or relations enumerated by Hume and others comprehend every supposable in- stance, and attempt to resolve all these into the law of redintegration, we shall find the following results : (a.) Objects contiguous in time present no difficulty. Indeed, the law of red- integration might be viewed as only another expression for the law that objects conjoined in time tend to restore or suggest one another. (b.) Objects adjacent in space, as has already been observed, usually come under the relation and law of contiguity in time, and are therefore easily ac- commodated to the law of redintegration. (c.) The most of the cases in which objects are recalled under the relation of cause and effect, will readily be solved by the law of redintegration. For in order to be connected as cause and effect so as to be recalled ' the one by the other, they must first have been united under this relation in a previous mental act ; and if so, they come at once under the law of redintegration. What is true of causes and effects, is still more obvious of means and ends. The same is true of premises and conclusions, data and inferences, or the so- called logical relations. (d.) The relations of similarity and contrast present some difficulty. When I see a face never seen before, at once the thought flashes upon me, il The face is like the face of a friend long absent or dead;" or when I see a horse which stri- kingly resembles in color, form, or action, another horse which I formerly owned, and the image of that horse is called to mind, the objects that recall and those which are recalled, were never conjoined in fact. This seems to be in- solvable by the law of redintegration. Maass ( Versuch uber die Einbildnngshraft), and others have sought to bring it under the same by the following solution : What we see in the resembling face, or the resembling horse, is some special and separable feature or peculiarity, one or more. Let this be called a, and let the remaining features or peculiarities be called b. Let all the observed features or characteristics of the same, both the resembling and the non-resembling, be called A. Let the face or the horse never seen before be designated by B. When B is seen, the part a is seen as a separa- ble constituent, for by the supposition it attracts special attention. The first act is to perceive B ; the next act, to notice a, the resembling feature ; but a has before been conjoined with b, giving the total A. As soon as the past a is appre- hended, it brings back its associate 6, and, A is therefore recalled. When, for example, I look at a portrait of Sir Philip Sidney, I am reminded of its like- ness to the portrait of Queen Elizabeth, because of the ruff which is about the neck of each, which in this case is the only common feature and attracts at once 236 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 156. the attention. The ruff — which is the same in both — brings back every thing besides in her Majesty's portrait — the head-dress, the features, the sceptre, the robes, etc., etc., till the whole is restored. If this solution is accepted, the law of redintegration is established as the one comprehensive and sufficient law of representation. And this would be, " objects which have been previously united as parts of a single mental state, tend to recall or suggest one another." The law of redintegration cannot be accepted for the reason that : The part of a mental state which is said to recall or tend to recall the whole, is not literally the same which has previously been an object to the mind. Every time the mind apprehends either a part or the whole, it has a new percept or image, whether partial or total. If, having seen two resembling horses together, I afterward see one, I am impelled at once to think of the other ; or if the sight of a third resembling horse makes me think of one or both, there is to the mind in every instance a new object pre- sented and pictured. The percept of the same horse taken in successive moments, or at long intervals, is mentally conceived not as the same, but as a similar mental entity or object. All its force to attract, or suggest, or recall another object, comes not from the sameness of the part or the whole objectively viewed, but from the similarity of the two or more mental percepts or mental images regarded subjectively, or as the products of the mind's similar activities. Whatever this tendency, or readiness, or force may be, it is derived entirely from the mind's own activity, and not at all from the sameness of the objects as parts or wholes. The mind thinks, or tends to think of a when it perceives or thinks of b, because it has previously acted in a similar activity, in whole or in part. When a occurs to it, whether in perception or thought, a certain form of partial subjective activity begins, which involves, by reason of the fact that the like activity has been previously experienced, a greater facility of completion. The law of redintegration, as ordinarily phrased or enounced, is liable to the qualification which was noticed in § 154, viz., that no attractive force can be affirmed or conceived to pertain to ideas as such. Objects or ideas have of themselves no greater force or tendency to restore those which with themselves made up a mental state, than they have to attract one, another. The force in the final analysis must come from and reside in the mind whose products they are. . § 157. CONDITIONS AND LAWS OF REPRESENTATION. 237 § 157. (5.) The real principle that explains all the phenomena and laws of association is to be found in nation. How i enounced. the comprehensive general iact or law, that the mind tends to act again more readily in a manner or form which is simi- lar to any in which it has acted before, in any defined exertion of its energy. As the result of our analysis, we accept this as the principle Which comprehends the so-called laws of association. We have seen that these laws are not physiological, but psychical ; that the attractive force by which one idea is said to be able to recall another, does not lie in the ideas as such, viewed as separate from the mind's energy in producing or beholding them : nor does it lie in the relations as such under which the objects were connected in the mind's previous act of uniting them, nor in the power of a part of the mental state to reproduce its fellow-part or whole, but in the ultimate truth that, in whatever way the mind may act, it thereby is enabled to act in a similar manner a second time. Every ori- ginal act is always complex, including objects separated and united, as parts and as a whole, by definable relations. If the mind cognizes a part of any of these wholes, it begins to act in a way similar to that in which it has acted before. The tendency to finish the whole of" the act thus begun explains the principle that underlies the laws of association. This comprehensive law enables us to explain not only the re- currence of two objects that have previously been connected in the same instant of time, but the return of those also which have followed one another in a consecutive order ; as the words that form a sentence suggest each other, or the names that have been learned in a series, or the letters of the alphabet, etc., etc. The reference of the laws of the representative power to the subjective force or energy of the mind, explains the influence of states of feeling, as well as acts of the intellect, upon the repre- sentative activities. The state of feeling in which I perceive or think of an object — e. g., a glorious sunset or an interesting story — is often as distinct to my apprehension as the object itself. It should follow that a similar feeling excited a second time ought as truly to tend to recall a similar object, as a similar object the feeling. That the feelings are potent instruments of memory, is confirmed by the experience of every one. It often happens that 238 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 157. a feeling of disgust once occasioned by some object, can never be experienced again without recalling the object itself. This is often observed of the bodily sensations, as those of sea-sickness or headache. It is scarcely less conspicuous in the experience of purely psychical emotions when these are perfectly defined or are traceable to some determinate cause ; like home-sickness or sudden fright. In such cases the experience of a feeling which is at all similar to the feeling in question, however dissimilar may be the occasion or exciting cause, will bring back the intellectual cogni- tion with which it was originally connected. We have already explained that in such cases the feeling operates through the agency of the intellect. This principle also serves to explain the predominance of certain associations over the intellect and character of different persons. If the tendency to reproduction and recall is an original force or law, then it is natural that the energy with which any individual act or state of the soul tends to be revived, should be proportioned to the relative force of the original act ; in other words, to the attention which is bestowed upon its ob- jects or parts, whether these are objective or subjective. An excited interest is the condition of concentrated attention ; for, as has already been observed, aroused feeling awakens the in- tellect, detains its gaze, and excludes distracting objects. Hence, the intimate dependence of the memory and imagination of different persons upon the character and strength of the emo- tions, the buoyancy and depression of their spirits, etc. Hence, preeminently, the influence of those commanding purposes and prevailing habits which make and mark the individual man, upon the objects which he most frequently recalls and recombines, under his prevailing and dominant associations. That every man has his dominant associations is universally observed and con- fessed. The reason is, with the one person, that the favorite ob- jects of the soul's activity are certain classes of objects with their relations ; and with the other, objects that are very unlike them. But in every case, the associations by which each recalls objects, follow the energy with which he cognizes them. One man recalls objects and relations which never occur to another, chiefly because the one contemplates these objects and relations, and with intense energy, while they scarcely catch the notice or at- § 157. CONDITIONS AND LAWS OF REPRESENTATION. 239 tention of the other. Open before two men the same landscape, the same picture, the same architectural design ; tell them the same narrative, introduce them to the same companion, let them listen to the same poem, lecture, or sermon, and the active intel- lect of each will be busy in selecting objects from each, dis- cerning them in special relations and fixing them for future recall. It also explains why our associations with objects perceived are more energetic and permanent than those connected with objects remembered or imagined. That which is seen with the eye or heard with the ear, other things being equal, holds the attention more closely and longer than that which is merely remembered, or painted to the fancy. It is constantly present, firmly fixed, and held closely before the mind for it to return to as often as it will. The associations with home are a good illustration with S home. lonB of this principle. "When we merely think of the home of our childhood, it brings back a throng of recollections associated with its places and persons ; but when we visit our home, we cannot repress them. They are connected with every apartment ; they start up from every corner ; they attend upon all our walks ; there is not a tree, or rock, or stream, but thrusts into our very faces, and forces upon our attention, its throng of associate memories. Objects of imagination have this advantage over objects of sense, that they are more free from unwelcome and unpleasant elements, and are subject more entirely to the creative power. But objects of sense stimulate the associative tendency to greater energy, and furnish it with the greatest variety of material. Our principle also explains why certain conditions of the body affect the power to recall, both favorably and unfavorably. Disease may both hinder and quicken the energies of the soul to acquire, and, of course, to reproduce its acquisitions ; for, in all cases, the tendency to reproduce is measured by the energy of the original activity ; and this varies, as the body helps or hinders the mind to detain and concentrate its attention (cf. § 153). The principle which refers the tendency to be reproduced to the original energy of apprehension euables us to understand why the mind represents only a portion, and often but a single 240 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §158. element, of an object presented. We perceive a complex ma- terial object ; we read a written page ; we examine a fine draw- ing, engraving, or painting; we hear and understand an elaborate and convincing argument ; we enjoy a succession of pleasurable sensations or emotions. But we bring away, or possess the power to recall, only a few parts or elements of each, but those are invariably the parts or features which we have energetically presented to our cognition. If we revive these speedily, we unite and preserve them by an act of greater energy. It is essential to an act of knowledge that its objects be discerned in some relation. States of feeling even are moved and excited by the discerned relations of objects, as truly as by the apprehension of their unrelated existence. The relation is often quite as much an occasion of intellectual or emotional activity as the parts related. Sometimes it attracts the exclusive attention, and the entities concerned are set aside and overlooked. I may listen to several similar sounds from different musical instruments, or human voices ; the sounds compared may scarcely be noticed, only the circumstance that they are siniila: Twenty effects may be produced by a common agent or cause. The individual effects are scarcely observed, for the attention is oc- cupied by the common relation by which they are connected. In hearing a person read, or in reading ourselves, we often do not notice the words ; the mind takes up only the relations which constitute their meaning. These facts explain why the relations of objects, and especially why three or four more prominent relations, figure so conspicu- ously as laws of association. The relations named are none other, as we shall see, than the comprehensive or general cate- gories which connect and conditionate all our knowledge (§ 515). These relations are the laws of association, inasmuch as they are the instant and universal conditions of original cognition. What- ever we know energetically under these relations, we know a second time under and by means of one or more of these cate- gories. II. The secondary laws of association. § 158. The theories which we have considered thus S^Snelf 7 far chiefly relate to what are called the primary laws of association. Other laws have also been proposed. § 158. CONDITIONS AND LAWS OF REPRESENTATION. 241 which are called secondary. The primary laws are* conceived as explaining the tendency of certain classes of objects to recur to the mind. The secondary laws are conceived to regulate the recur- rence of one individual object in any of these classes rather than another. They might with propriety be called laws of the pre- ference or precedence of particular objects. The secondary laws have been enumerated and propounded as follows : (1.) Those objects are more likely to be recalled, other things being equal, which occupy the mind for the longest period of time ; (2.) those also which are apprehended most vividly ; (3.) those ivhich are brought most frequently before the mind ; (4.) those which were most recently present; (5.) those which are the most free from entangling relations; (6.) those which are contemplated with the greatest strength of emotion ; (7.) those which are viewed with favoring circumstances of bodily health ; (8.) those which are coincident with prevalent habits ; (9.) those to which the original constitution of body or mind furnishes a special aptitude, (cf. Dr. Thomas Brown, Lecture 37.) A critica 1 examination of these laws 'will enable us to reduce them to some general expression. Perhaps it will show that both ci ™ e to the the secondary and primary rest upon the same general principle, same principle The first, concerning length of time, has already been shown to m &TY e P " be necessarily involved in the operation of the general law for which we have contended, that an attentive or energetic apprehension of objects in their relations is a ground of their tendency to be recalled. The second is nearly coincident with -the same fundamental principle. The third presents ground for inquiry. Why does simple repetition give any advantage? We answer: A second look, especially if it follows that which pre- ceded after a considerable interval of time, presents the object as divested of the distracting influences which novelty furnishes. Each new or repeated vieY7, whether near or remote, also reveals some fresh relation either to a familiar or a novel object, and thus increases the chance of its being suggested to the mind a second time. For example, by one act the diamond is apprehended as the bright- est, or the hardest, or the most costly of the gems ; and so, when the gems are thought of, the diamond is suggested. At another view, its relation to carbon is discerned, and then the diamond will be recalled when charcoal, or marble, or carbonic acid are present to the thoughts. The fourth law is, that an object contemplated recently, is, if other things are equal, more likely to be recalled than the same object if viewed longer ago. A countenance casually and hastily seen an hour since, may be recollected or re- called by another similar face within this short interval of time, but may be lost forever if the occasion which suggests it does not soon present itself. The fact is unquestioned, and it may perhaps be inexplicable. But obviously, it rather con- cerns loss or waste of power, than any positive force or tendency. If expressed in 242 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 158. the language or terms taken from the general principle which we have laid down as fundamental, it would be thus phrased : "the tendency of any act of the mind to be recalled or repeated is weakened by disuse, till, finally, it wholly ceases.'' Whether it is properly said to be weakened, or superseded, is an open question. This is true of the kindred question, whether any acquisition of the mind can be irrecoverably lost. One palpable and prominent exception to this general tendency to weakness or loss may be urged, in the frequent cases of persons who in old age remember nothing so vividly as the scenes and events which occurred longest ago. Often the whole of the intervening life is entirely effaced from the soul, while the memories of youth and childhood are still vivid and distinct. Several reasons may be given for this plain exception to the operation of the laws already con- sidered. Many of the remembrances of childhood have been recalled again and again through a long life. Though the events of childhood, as realities, were present to the mind longest ago, yet, as thought- objects, they may be the most fresh and recent. Nor should it be forgotten that the objects and events of child- hood were contemplated by the mind at first with an almost exclusive and ab- sorbing attention. The memorable occurrences of childhood were the absorbing subjects of thought for days before they occurred. They were reviewed with the fondest reflection after they were past. The learning to count ten or one hun- dred, the wearing of a certain dress ; the beginning of school-life ; the long antici- pated, the often-reviewed and recited visit to some relative, the first considerable journey, the first party, the first composition — were most important occurrences in their time, and spread themselves along a large portion of the horizon of the infant life. The fifth law (which relates to entangling relations) has already been pro- vided for. If the points or features to which these relations, — and the thereby related objects, — are attached, are very numerous, the greater is the probability that the objects will be recalled, provided the relations, and the related objects, be discerned with equal energy of attention and ardor of interest. But if the multiplicity of relations divides and thus weakens the interest, the influence of their number is distracting and entangling. In illustration of the operation of this law, Dr. Brown observes: "The song which we have never heard but from one person, can scarcely be heard again by us without recalling that person to our memory ; but there is obviously much less chance of this particular sug- gestion, if we have heard the same air and words frequently sung by others" {Lecture 31). Upon this we remark : If the frequent repetition of the song has the effect to withdraw the attention from the first impression, and to exclude its being often repeated and revived, then it becomes less likely that the person who sung it for the first time will be suggested by the air; but if, every time it is sung by any one, that person is recalled, then the song will be more ineffaceably associated with him the more frequently it is sung. The * ixth and seventh have already been noticed and explained (v? 152.3). The eighth needs but a word. So far as facility of association depends on repe- tition, and so far as particular habits facilitate repetition, so far is this general fact resolved by the law concerning repetition. So far as habit, or easy repetition by habit, enables us to concentrate tho attention with greater energy and interest, § 159. CONDITIONS AND LAWS OF REPRESENTATION. 243 so far is its power explained by the strength of the single or repeated apprehen- sions for which habit provides. The ninth law supposes that there are original differences and aptitudes in different individuals for certain classes of associations. This is doubtless true. But it should never be forgotten that these original aptitudes do not pertain to the faculty of representation or the so-called faculty of association as such, but that it extends equally to the power of presentation and intuition. Whatever we energetically observe or connect by relations, in original intuition, we revive by association. There is no special aptness for special associations, or for vari- ous and ready suggestion, separate from a readiness to discern special classes of objects and relations, and to discern them with interest and energy. § 159. There are what seem, on the first aspect, exceptions to the universal application of the law ce^ions^o the of association. There are many cases when a [ a ^ of associa - thought seems all at once to dart into the mind, which has no apparent connection with any thought or thing that is present. We cite the familiar example recorded by Hob- bes : " In a company in which the conversation turned upon the late civil war, what could be conceived more impertinent than for a person to ask abruptly, What was the value of a Roman denarius ? On a little reflection, however, I was able to trace the train of thought which suggested the question ; for the original subject of discourse introduced the history of the king, and of the treachery of those who surrendered his person to his enemies ; this again introduced the treachery of Judas Iscariot, and the sum of money which he received for his reward " {Levia- than, p. i. c. 3). This case is no more singular nor striking than the experience of any lively mind could furnish in every half-hour. If any person not absorbed with the objects of sense, or bent upon some present achievement, will break in upon his movements of reverie with the question, How did this or that thought occur to my mind? he will be surprised, and perhaps amused, at the series of strangely connected thoughts which introduced it to his notice. In many cases, the thought, though apparently abrupt and strange, will be found to have a real connection with the thought which it seemed to jostle and displace. There are thoughts, however, the connections of which we cannot follow. What ought we to believe in respect to these ? Should we still hold that the laws of association govern their movement, though we cannot trace their presence or furnish the proof of their working ? 244 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 159. In answer to this question, two opposite views have been main- tained. The first is held by Dugald Stewart and others — that the mind is momentarily conscious of the presence of these in- tervening objects, though it cannot recall them in memory ; that they are present long enough to act as media of association, but not long enough to leave any trace of their presence. The second theory is urged by Hamilton, following a sugges- tion of Leibnitz, and agreeing with the school of Herbart.. These all contend that, " though these intermediate objects may be present long enough to influence the train of consciously as- sociated thoughts, yet the mind is in no sense aware of their pre- sence ; for it is unphilosophical to suppose an object present to consciousness without leaving some impression upon the memory. No analogous cases can be adduced, and the hypothesis must be rejected as groundless." Besides, it is urged, " another principle can be adduced to explain the phenomena — that of latent or un- conscious modifications of the mind. In this we have a re- cognized and actually existing law, which is sufficient to account for all the facts." (Met, Lee. xviii.) Upon this argument we observe, that it is not true, as is repre- sented, that there are no grounds on which to rest the first hypo- thesis. In the very case supposed, when one idea suddenly and strangely follows upon another, if we bethink ourselves at once, we can recall some intervening links. We say, if we bethink ourselves at once ; for if the effort is made a few instants later, the clue will fall from our hands. At other times, when it seem3 to have totally escaped and eluded us, it can be recovered by persistent effort and determination. Now, the fact that in some apparently desperate cases we can succeed, demonstrates that the objects might have been — nay, that they actually were, present to the consciousness, though they seemed not to have been. We have a right to infer, then, on grounds of analogy, that they are so in all cases. The analogy of acknowledged and similar phenomena is wholly with the first theory. Moreover, analogy would seem to suggest and confirm the principle, that where there is a feeble activity of consciousness, there is a feeble hold upon the memory ; and we conclude conversely, that where there is the slenderest hold upon the memory, there must have been the feeblest possible energy of consciousness. What is in- § 160. CONDITIONS AND LAWS OF REPRESENTATION. 245 tended by the phrase latent modification of consciousness, is not altogether clear. If it be explained as only a very low degree of conscious activity, the two theories are in principle the same. § 160. The representative power tends to unceasing Representation activity. The mind, if given up to the operation of ^^How a ?t the laws of association, would never cease to furnish can , } 6 inter * ' rupted. itself with new objects. Each object last discerned would suggest another. This would call up its fellow, and the series of successive objects would suffer no interruption and would come to no end. It has been said with great effect — that, were the senses excited to action only long enough to furnish the soul with requisite material and fully to develop all its powers, and then to be sealed up forever, the spirit would have acquired material enough for its endless activity in simple representation. (Bishop Butler, Analogy, p. i., c. i.) We know from observa- tion, that when the other activities are as nearly suspended as is possible, as in dreaming and reverie, the train of associated objects still rushes past the eye of fancy with a rapidity that cannot be measured. But strong as this activity is, and difficult of control as at times it may be, it does not often assume exclu- sive or supreme possession. There are two methods by which this activity is interrupted and turned aside. The one is objec- tive, the other is subjective. We consider, first, the objective interruption. Every new object of sense-perception introduces a foreign and diverting ele- ment. In such cases representation gives way to presentation or acquisition. We do not deny that both these activities may be exerted together, and that presentation and representation, may go forward side by side. It would seem from experience that this often happens. In waking gently from sleep, the images of the dream-world blend with the realities of the sense-world. Even in our waking hours, the hard world which the senses give us, is beset by the spirit-world in which we dream. The soberest world of the most prosaic and practical thinker sparkles with the images which the fancy interweaves into its homely fabric. Let this be admitted, and still it is true that the two species of activity cannot occupy the attention at the same moment with equal energy ; and that the sense-world and sense-objects will 246 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 160. break in upon the activity of the fancy. Let but a single object do this for a single instant, and a starting-point is furnished for a new train of thought in an entirely new direction. The subjective interruption, diversion, and control of the repre- sentative activity of the soul, are still more important. The ego which at times may seem to be the helpless victim or the amused spectator of this moving diorama, is not always an idle or pas- sive looker-on.' It has but to detain any single object, and the object detained suggests new objects, to each of which it sustains many relations. By simply arresting the course of representation, its independent activity is as truly controlled and newly directed as if some object of sense had obtruded itself upon the attention. But the mind can do that which is far more effective and im- portant than to detain an object before its attention from impulse or passive excitement. It can exert upon every such object its higher activities of thought. If it cognizes the existence of the object, it discerns it as present, and as diverse from itself. It may remember it as having before been present. It may compare it with other objects, bring it into a new or a familiar class, name it, reason about it, make from it some induction, mould it into some imaginative creation, apply it in illustration and analogy, discern in it relations of beauty, learn from it some moral lesson, or find in it some manifestation of the divine. Each one of these activities will evolve a new product, which product may serve as a starting-point for a new series of representations. These activi- ties are far more potent and effective than the merely passive services of the representing power, though they blend with them so intimately as not easily to be distinguished from them. As the mind mingles the thinking power with the activity of per- ception, when it seems only to see and hear with the organs of sense, so does it elevate and transform its acts of memory and fancy by the penetrating analysis and combining synthesis of rational judgment. That is a most superficial and limited conception of the representative power and the laws of association, which resolves into them all the nobler and more important operations and pro- ducts of the human soul. Such a view excludes individuality and self-respect— as well as the capacity for the higher achieve- ments of science, duty and faith, (cf. § 40). § 160. CONDITIONS AND LAWS OF REPRESENTATION. 247 Besides this direct action upon the representative faculty, there is another which is exerted indirectly, if possible with greater effect. The action is direct vrhen, in the ways described, the ego arrests and modifies the onward current of what would otherwise be pas- sive tendencies. It is indirect so far as, by every such action, a greater facility or force is given to such tendencies for the future. Every present energy of attention, every special effort of creation or thought, gives additional strength to certain bonds of associa- tion, and imparts special facility to the mind in reviving their objects. This very circumstance enables us to apply the mind to similar objects with less effort and greater pleasure, till at last the mind has created for itself almost a new medium of life, a second atmosphere for its own easy and familiar action, which is purely the product of its own previous activities. The feelings provide for their own perpetuation and increased force as they direct to this or that intellectual activity. Hence, preeminently, every controlling or commanding purpose, whether morally good or bad, tends to perpetuate itself, and to secure the execution of its own behests. Under the constant presence, and guiding con- trol of such a purpose, all the trains of associated objects become its " ready servitors," which bring to mind, when needed, the facts and suggestions, the illustrations and arguments, the happy phrases and expressive words, which are required for thought, expression, and act. Various familiar phenomena illustrate the force of these indirect influences upon the representative faculty. The same material object suggests to different persons associations that are entirely unlike and even opposite to one another. The scene, the house, the apartment, which to one man is full of the \ deepest interest, is to another indifferent. To one person it recalls suggestions fraught with peace, affection, and joy ; to another, memories of hatred, remorse, and terror. To the same man, on different occasions and in different moods, the same object will suggest different associations, according to the feelings of the hour or the purpose for which he is thinking. We may almost say without exaggeration, that in every present activity of the mind there is revived and indirectly made to reappear the whole of the man's previous history, as each of its acts and events have been taken up by the force of the soul's purely passive tendencies, and so incorporated into its very essence. 248 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 161. § 161. The law of association, according to the Law of associa- . * 1 . . tion and law of views oi its nature and energy which have been en- forced, rests upon the same original principle usually known as the law of habit. One object suggests another, because one mental state which is similar in part to another tends to be like it in every particular. This principle, when expressed in other language, is equivalent to, Any mental activity or experi- ence, when it is repeated, is more readily performed. Habit, Lat. habitus, Gr. £&?, is literally a way of being held, or of holding one's self. Thus defined, it must denote a perma- nent state of rest which has been reached as the result of action or growth, or a permanent form of activity, or of readiness or facility for any kind of activity. As such facility for action is universally observed to result from repetition of action, this last element is taken up into the conception or definition of habit. The acquisition of facility by repetition, supposes that some diffi- culty or hindrance has been overcome, whether the habits are purely psychical or corporeal, or whether they are both physical and mental conjoined; whether they are emotional or moral, or whether, as is often true, they are all three together. Examples of bodily habits are furnished by a particular gait ; the dexterous management of the hand in the use of a saw, a chisel, a hatchet, or a plane, in driving or in drawing ; and the control of the limbs in dancing or gymnastic feats. The acquisi- tion of such habits does indeed usually involve some psychical activity, and the gain of facility by repetition. But we may consider apart the formation of the body only to a new habitude, and for the moment have to do only with the changes in the states and functions of the body which our senses observe to be more and more readily made. We suppose, that at the outset the special use required is difficult, either because some habitual and unde- sirable adjustment or predisposition of the muscles has been attained, or because they are imperfectly or wrongly adjusted by nature. An effort is required involving physical tension or phy- sical pain ; as when we would bring the organs to utter the unused sounds of a strange language, or would bring the fingers or the limbs to painful or constrained positions. We may explain the obstacle or hindrance by a certain power or tendency of the reflex activities of the nervous system. The conquest may con- § 161. CONDITIONS AND LAWS OF REPRESENTATION. 249 sist in the facility which it is possible to acquire, by a gradual assumption in the reflex motors of new forms of muscular adjust- ment. We pass next to mental habits— first, those which are devel- oped in connection with such bodily adjustments as we have sup- posed ; and second, those which concern functions that are simply and purely mental. Side by side with the new adjustments to which the muscles are constrained with a more and more ready obedience, there must proceed a constantly increased facility in the mind's connection and control of the appropriate sensations, according to the ends which it intends to accomplish ; i. e., the mind in such cases furnishing the real beginnings of the new ad- justments and growths of the body. The juggler and the gym- nast, the mechanic and the artist, the dancer and the player on the violin or the organ, do not simply train the bodily organs to the requisite suppleness and aptitudes, but they acquire a sur- prising readiness of the mind to connect with every movement those sensations which indicate and regulate the activities to which the body is physically trained. If a mental facility supposes a mental difficulty, what is the nature of the difficulty ? It is an original difficulty of mental application to certain mental objects, and, consequently in the ready mental combination of the objects which are concerned. This intellectual obstacle is usually in- creased, and in some cases wholly occasioned, by one that is emotional or moral. In habits that are purely mental, as in the greater facility that is acquired by study in general ; or the surprising progress which may be made in any special science, as the mathematics or the languages; or the still more unlooked-for dexterity which maybe gained in certain intellectual feats, as of punning, rhyming, etc., etc., the difficulty lies in a reluctant or unwonted attention, and the dexterity pertains to the subjective tendency toward similar activities which is acquired by exercise. The difficulty and the capacity for facility are both assumed to be unquestioned and original facts. When the Imbits are purely emotional or moral, so far as they can be conceived as such, the difficulty to be encountered is a natural or acquired tendency to excessive and abnormal activity in any emotion. This tendency can be overcome only by the 11* 250 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §162. frequent exercise of other emotions, till they act with normal readiness and strength. Leaving out of account the voluntary element, or rather supposing that this is rightly adjusted, it may be assumed that this original hindrance to the natural tendencies remains when the new habits are to be acquired. The completion of moral or emotional habits ordinarily involves also the training of the intellectual habits to the ready suggestion of new thoughts and very often of the body itself to readiness in appropriate actions. § 162. The laws of association are again divided Higher and ° lower laws of into higher and lower. The lower are those which association. . ... are presented to us in the acquisitions 01 sense aud consciousness, and which are reproduced by the representative imagination and the uncultured memory. These are the relations of time and space. As they are more obvious and natural, they require little of higher culture or discipline. They are also developed earliest in the order of time, and are common to the whole race. The relations of likeness and of contrast form an intermediate class between the natural and the philosophical ; being now present in the one, and then largely represented in the other. The higher are the relations of cause and effect ; in- volving means and end, premise and conclusion, datum and infer- ence, genus and species, law and example — all, in short, of the so-called philosophical or logical relations. All these are present in and control the higher imagination and the more developed processes of thought. The higher relations of thought and of the creative imagination are so diverse from the lower relations of sense, that they often supersede and displace, and sometimes even cross and contradict them. In sense-perception and con- sciousness, objects are conjoined, just as they happen to present themselves in space or in time. The mechanical memory or imagination servilely reproduces them under precisely the same relations in which they were originally presented and known. But thought and the higher imagination take the objects thus accidentally conjoined, and recombine and reproduce them under relations that are higher. Whenever objects are habitually con- joined under such relations, they will be persistently associa- ted with and represented by them, so far even as to exclude the combinations presented to sense-perception. By such excess, § 162. CONDITIONS AND LAWS OF REPRESENTATION. 251 those striking idiosyncracies of imagination and memory can be accounted for which are designated by the vaguely-used term, absent-mindedness. The absent-minded person is one who has become so habitually indifferent and inattentive to the objects which address his senses, through preoccupation from a roving imagination or abstracted thought, that his senses seem often to be unused, and his memory to be utterly untrustworthy. He becomes sublimely, or perhaps ridiculously, indifferent to the common relations of common objects and events. As the higher may take the place of the lower relations, so the lower may exclude or displace the higher. The constant or even the frequent conjunction of objects and phenomena may in consequence be mistaken for their necessary relations or essential conditions or constituents. A savage, who should see gunpowder exploded by an electric spark, would associate the whole of the electric apparatus, and perhaps even the words and dress of the operator, with the occurrence of the explosion, and take the combination to be made by a necessary connection of things. The ignoramus who sees a conjurer perform certain ma- nipulations, or hears him repeat the words of some incantation in connection with a surprising feat, unites the two by an associa- tion so inveterate as to believe the one is the cause of the other. The manifold and inveterate superstitions that have been so readily accepted and so tenaciously retained, are in this way to be explained. Startling or noticeable events have occurred together by a merely casual connection, which have been hence- forward associated under the relations of cause and effect ; as in the case of success in battle, the healing of disease, the removal of an epidemic, the termination of drought, the cessation of an eclipse, or the acceptable performance of some religious rite. Eor are errors of this sort confined to uncultured and ignorant races or uneducated men. Men of quick association and ready suggestion, even if they attain the highest culture in many di- rections, often scorn that discipline to philosophical thinking of which they stand in special need, because, from the very quick- ness of their power to combine, they are most liable to mistake the suggestions of their various and ready wit for the sober and oolid relations of thought. The lower associations — those of constant or frequent conjunc- 252 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §162. tion — are most observable when they strongly affect our feelings. Objects which are in themselves indifferent, or which ought to be and would otherwise be positively offensive, excite the intensest liking or misliking, simply because they have been connected with objects which in their essential nature are fitted to please or displease us. The remembrance of a journey, or some other event of our personal history, is always unwelcome, because it was connected in our experience, and is therefore associated in our thoughts, with some serious disappointment or calamity. The sight of the surgeon who saved our life by performing a painful operation, is not always agreeable, however sincere may be our gratitude. Certain persons are very pleasing or very displeasing, because they bring to mind memories or thoughts which we cherish or reject. A dress of the newest fashion may at first be singular and un- attractive. But soon it is generally worn by those who are attractive in appearance, graceful and refined in manners, and high in social position. It is thereupon regarded as highly graceful and agreeable in itself, and no other is tolerable. It is not long before it becomes common, and this detracts somewhat from its factitious attractions. "When it is worn obtrusively by the filthy and vulgar, and becomes conspicuous in connection with persons who are rightfully disagreeable, it is time that the fashion should change, or that some other novelty should appear, in order to relieve the associations of the fashionable world from the offen- sive taint of commonness and vulgarity. The moral influence of accidental associations is still more worthy of attention, for their power for evil as well as their capacity for good. Pleasing manners, high intellectual culture, the attractions of wealth and position, may be and often are connected with libertine principles and easy morals, and thus become powerful aids and instruments of vice and corruption. The drunken revel may, by the force of associations of this kind, not only be endured as less disgusting, but it may be gloried in by the aspirant after high society, as the sign of gentlemanly breeding and fashionable life. The horrors of the first cigar and the first debauch are greatly alleviated by manifold sugges- tions that the experience of both are necessary to constitute the gentleman. § 162. CONDITIONS AND LAWS OF REPRESENTATION. 253 The force of casual associations is in no particular more con- spicuous than in its influence upon language. A deed that is abhorrent to the conscience and offensive to the judgment and feelings of right-minded and plain-speaking men, is more than half reconciled to the moral feelings, and perhaps is installed among the virtues, by softening or dignifying the appellations by which it is named — that is, by designating it by words that suggest associations of respectability and honor. Men seek to keep down or to avoid associations of disgust or abhorrence by the device of euphemistic terminology. It is not always true that ' vice loses half its evil by losing all its grossness ; ' for the very gross- ness which is its natural manifestation and result, is sometimes the best defence of society against the corruption to which it tends. The power of epithets and names to awaken pleasant or un- pleasant associations is well illustrated in the history of parties and the practice of partisans. A party that is encumbered by an epithet or appellation of odious associations or disagreeable origination, hastens to disencumber itself of an appendage that is more fatal than the shirt of Nessus ; while its opponents are as eager and determined that it shall retain the damaging reproach. The skillful application of epithets like Whig and Tory, Malig- nant and Roundhead, Girondists and the Mountain, Conservative and Radical, is often more efficient with the populace than the most convincing arguments or the most persuasive eloquence. Agreeable associations, through the subtle reaction of language, have not only palliated — they have even recommended the most contemptible follies, the most outrageous violence, and the most abominable crimes. Even philosophy herself, though professing to be subject to thought-relations only, is by no means exempt from the influence of casual associations operating through this same medium of words. It is often more effective, even in the schools, to apply an epithet, as sensuous or spiritual, empirical or rational, unsel- fish or utilitarian, than it is to disprove an analysis or answer an argument: to give an opinion an odious name, or apply a contemptuous epithet, than to con- sider its evidence or refute its reasons. The soberest and best-governed men are more or less affected by individual associations in their tastes, their preferences, their manners, their reading, their companions, their politics, and their faith. We could not be wholly aloof or exempt from their influence if we would. We would not if we could; for, in so doing, we should forego much of our individu- ality, and of that which makes our individuality dear. But it is the interest and 254 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 163. duty of every man so far to regulate the influence of such associations, that he do not become the easy victim or the abject slave of chance and arbitrary cir- cumstances. "Whatever is right and true cannot be disagreeable, when it is sus- tained, adorned, and hallowed by associations that are only attractive. Indeed, it is not till the reason and conscience rule so completely over the whole man as to transform and elevate even his individual and casual associations, that the education of the man is complete, and his character has attained that harmony and perfection of which it is capable. CHAPTER IV. REPRESENTATION. (1.) THE MEMORY, OR RECOGNIZING FAC- ULTY. Having considered the conditions and laws of the representa- tive power, we proceed to apply the results of our inquiries to the explanation of the principal modes in which its activity is ex- erted — to the so-called faculties of memory, phantasy, and imagi- nation. The memory comes first in order. § 163. An act or state of memory has already been The elements . . essential to an denned to be that m which the essential elements of act of memory. _ . . , an act 01 previous cognition are more or less per- fectly re-known, with the relations essential to each. These elements are not all recalled with the same distinctness, and hence there are varieties of memory ; but it is essential to an act of memory that some portion of each of these elements and relations should be recalled and re-known. The total complex of object and relations may be recalled more or less perfectly, or each of the constituent elements may be more or less vividly represented. First : The object of the original act may be recalled with a greater or less completeness of its elements or parts, and this whether it be a thought-object, or a sense-object. Completeness or incompleteness in this particular usually attracts the attention, and marks the memory as strong or weak. Second: The original act of the mind in the first apprehension may also be more or less perfectly recalled. I see a face in a crowd. I recall it perfectly, and know that I have seen it before ; but I cannot revive a single vestige of myself as viewing it, only § 163. REPRESENTATION. — THE MEMORY. 255 that I did thus view it I am certain by direct knowledge. And yet we must have this recollection of our previous psychical activity, or we cannot be said to remember it at all. This certain knowledge may vary from the vaguest possible impressions of our subjective state, to the most vivid and circumstantial review of each one of its constituent elements. Third : The time when the object was previously known may be more or less perfectly recalled. If I remember an object viewed or experienced half an hour ago, I may recall the leading events which have happened to me from the present moment backward to the original act of acquiring this knowledge. If it was yesterday, or a month since, I can generally recall the events that were just before and after it, can connect it with the present by more or fewer intervening occurrences, and can fix the date so far as to know that it was in a certain month of a certain year ; the attendants of which dates I can recover with more or less fulness. In some cases, the event stands isolated in the dim and unde- termined past. In others, it may not be wholly isolated from the events which preceded, accompanied, or followed, but yet it can scarcely be said to be united with the present by any connecting series of events that intervene. Fourth : The place where, may be more or less perfectly re- called and recognized. The place where, is a phrase which de- notes the adjacent and surrounding physical objects in their spa- tial relations, which form the background and the setting of every object perceived or every act of the person who remembers. Every object previously observed, every act of my own in ob- serving it, when itself recalled, will bring back this accompany- ing setting more or less perfectly. Fifth : The knowledge of the real existence or of the previous perception of remembered objects may also vary in the degree of accuracy or confidence with which it is held. For this simple knowledge no other explanation can be given, than that the mind is competent to its exercise. The question is sometimes asked, Why do we trust our memory ? To this philosophers have sought to give an answer by enumerating certain grounds or cri- teria — as that the object must be clear, or that the image recalled must represent or agree with the reality. But all these criteria, 256 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §164. or grounds, are merely other words or phrases, which express no more than the act of knowledge itself. But does the mind always know, i. e., remember, with equal certainty ? Does it not sometimes distrust its own act in remem- bering ? We answer : When we distrust our own act of memory, it is we ourselves who are not certain. We seek to be certain ; sometimes we succeed, and pass from the condition of painful doubt into that of confident knowledge. The object which was vaguely recalled nov^ stands vividly and distinctly before the eye of the mind. But the clearness and distinctness of the objects are not the real causes which effect, or the logical grounds on which we rest our positive knowledge. The term distinct and distinctly, objectively describe the subjective certainty, but do not account for or justify it. " But do we not sometimes offer reasons to satisfy or prove to ourselves that what we remember must have been a fact ?" We do often enumerate the circumstances which assure us that we cannot be mistaken, but not as logical reasons to justify the con- clusion that we are in the right. We bring them up as particu- lars on which we dwell with attention, for the purpose of re- creating a more complete and vivid picture of the past. In this sense we are said to refresh our memory — as a witness in court is asked or urged to do, when one or another circumstance is repeated in his hearing, or he is left to his own associations to revive the past. We may indeed urge this number of remem- bered particulars as reasons why others should trust our accuracy because our own remembrance is so full and detailed, but not as grounds or criteria for our own confidence. For this confidence we can give no other reason than that we find ourselves pos- sessed of and using the power for this very function, which is to remember. And yet this act is exercised, as is every other act of the soul, with varying and unequal energy. § 164. An exact and technical description of mem- nicaiiydcfined. ory would be the following. Memory is a modifica- Jlelatiou of me- . „, . mory to repre- tion oi representation. Ine representative power fur- nishes the materials for the memory, according to the laws of association. These objects being furnished, the mind in memory knows them by an act of recognition. More briefly, representation recalls, memory recognizes. The soul, in represen- § 164. REPRESENTATION. — THE MEMORY. 257 tation, is passive, blind, and mechanical, proceeding according to fixed and inevitable laws, by methods or processes which occur beyond or out of consciousness. The soul, in memory, on the other hand, is active, intelligent, and rational. The distinction between representation and memory, so far as our actual expe- rience is concerned, is rather ideal than real, for representation passes into memory by an inevitable certainty, through the easi- est, the most natural, and usually the most unnoticed transitions. The psychologists of the associational school provide for only half the process — that of representation. The recognition they attempt to explain, but unsuccessfully, by the chemistry of asso- ciation — i. e., by the union or blending of a present with a past mental state. Representation and memory may, however, with propriety and advantage, be ideally considered apart. Repre- sentation conceived apart from memory, may begin with a mental image, and by the laws of its own activity call up another, and still another, till all at once the intelligence asserts, "The object now pictured I have known before as a reality." Or the object may be material, and perceived by the senses. In such a case, representation at once supplies a completing image or thought, concerning which memory pronounces, " This real object I have perceived before." Memory, on the other hand, as distinguished from representa- tion, is an act of knowledge. To know, requires objects, and the discernment of their relations. The objects of memory are peculiar, in that, as has just been explained, representation pre- sents or suggests more or fewer of them. The relations under which they are known are, as we have shown at length, those of previous apprehension by myself in some determinate state of knowledge or feeling, at some previous time, and in some par- ticular place. Bnt while we thus distinguish in an ideal way the passive and the active element in memory, both must be taken into con- sideration in order to explain its phenomena; for, in these phenomena, each of these elements modifies the other, and both must be present. The two are related in memory somewhat as sensation proper and perception proper are combined in the acts of sense-perception — the one is inversely as the other. In certain acts and powers of memory, the passive or representa- 258 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 165. tional element is prominent and conspicuous; in others, the active and rational is most apparent. In the two cases, we dis- tinguish the memory as spontaneous and intentional. In sponta- neous memory, tlie object remembered, spontaneously occurs to the mind. In intentional memory it is distinctly sought after until it is found. In spontaneous memory, the representative faculty is prominent, while the intelligence waits only to give its recognition to what is presented to its attention. In intentional memory, the intelligence is active, being aware that some object has been previously known, to recall which, it summons the energies of the representative power. The distinction of these two kinds of memory is so obvious, and is so readily observed, that separate terms for the two have been employed in common life, and are found in many lan- guages. The Greeks have fivijfii) and avdfiviQGtq ; the Latins, memoria and recordaiio (cf. Cic. de Prov. 43) ; the English, memory and recollection. § 165. In the spontaneous memory, there are ousniemory? 6 " natural aptitudes and disabilities, which can only be referred to some original differences of the mental constitution. That such differences exist, is an unquestioned fact. For example : one person hears a series of unconnected names recited, and can repeat them all in the precise order in which they were uttered, while another can recall only now and the a one. The eye of another runs down a column of figures, and he can copy the whole from memory, while his companion can scarcely recall a single one of the whole. One individual can learn a page of prose or poetry simply by reading or hearing it read but once, while another can with difficulty repeat correctly a single line or sentence. That these differences are natural, is manifest from this, that they cannot be remedied by any effort or art. No discipline of the attention, and no determination of the will, can enable one who is strikingly deficient, to acquire the power of this simple and effortless memory. That the defect lies in some original incapacity to fix the attention with interest upon the objects to be recalled, and not in the power of representation, is confirmed by observation as well as by the general law of the workings of the representative power. That the strength or weakness of this kind of memory is not owing to the physical § 165. REPRESENTATION.— THE MEMORY. 259 strength or weakness of the organs of sense, but to the mental energy and the moral direction with which these physical instru- ments are applied, is abundantly manifest. Analogous to differ- ences in the spontaneous memory — if, indeed, they are not ex- amples of it — are the varying capacities to recall a musical air so as to repeat it, or to revive the image of the voice or manners of another so as to imitate them. The relations which are employed in the natural memory are most conspicuously those of simple contiguity and succession. All memory begins with these relations, because our earliest en- ergies and acquisitions commence with objects of this kind. In other words, there is a natural memory of space and of time, or, as we may say in a somewhat narrow sense, there is a natural memory of the eye and of the ear. In some persons the memory of the eye, while in others the memory of the ear, is conspicuous. Those who are remarkable for the memory of the eye, are such as can readily and vividly picture in the mind the details of the front or fag ade of a building, the outline and filling in of some remarkable tree, the features of the face of an acquaintance or friend, the page of a book as presented to the eye. Those distinguished for the memory of the ear, can recall successions of sounds — if they have a musical ear, of musical notes — strings of names, or words when connected in significant sentences. They can repeat dates of uninteresting events, and retail long stories whether tedious or amusing. Superiority in the one kind of memory is not necessarily accompanied by superiority in the other. A good spontaneous memory, or, as it is often called, a good memory for facts and dates, is generally and correctly regarded as a great intellectual convenience, rather than as a decisive indi- cation of intellectual power. It is doubtless true, that many per- sons are distinguished by natural memory, who are inferior in ca- pacity for discrimination and reasoning. It has become a com- mon observation, Great memory, little common sense. In such cases, the power of discerning the higher relations may be either originally deficient, or it may be neglected in consequence of the predominant use of the power of apprehending, and, of course, of recalling objects in the relations that are most obvious. A very energetic mind may be very limited in its apprehensions, and will, of course, be energetic though limited in its memory. It is 260 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 1G5 a. noticeable, also, that persons who become eminent in those achievements which are proper to the higher intellectual powers and relations, are in early life usually distinguished for the strength and reach of their memory of both eye and ear. There are not a few men who carry into the maturity of age, and into the most striking efforts' of judgment and reasoning, a memory that is always clear j vivid, prompt, exact, and universal — a memory that never forgets a name, or loses a date, or is at fault in its recital of facts. Such are the men of universal knowledge, at least in some special department of study and re- search, like Scaliger in ancient learning and criticism; Pascal, " that prodigy of parts ;" Niebuhr in history and statistics; A. von Humboldt in physics both celestial and terrestrial ; Bitter in geo- graphy ; Goethe in literature and art. The reason that in these exempt cases the higher or intellectual memory does not displace the lower, is that the employments or studies of the individual require him to be conversaut with details as well as with their thought-relations, with facts as well as with principles. Hence, the higher memory aids rather than hinders the lower ; the ac- quisitions of the quick eye and ear being fastened and fixed by the secondary processes of reflex thought. The intentional § 165 «. The phenomena of the so-called intentional memory. or vo i un t arv memory next require attention. They are characterized by the single feature, that the objects remem- bered, are sought for by a conscious effort or act. * But how can this be possible? The very statement involves a contra- diction in language and an impossibility in fact. If the mind seeks, intending to find or recover an object lost, then it already knows what it seeks for. In other words, the mind must already have remembered, in order to be put upon the act of endeavor- ing to recall.' In reply, we observe that, if every object re- membered were in all cases remembered with equal fulness and vividness, theu the objection would hold. If, in order to re- member at all, the mind must recall with equal energy and success all which, in the nature of the case, is capable of being reproduced, then ' to intend to remember ' would be plainly precluded by our ' having already remembered.' But this is by no means true. The object remembered may be con- sidered as an object — whether object-object or subject-object is § 165 a. REPRESENTATION. — THE MEMORY. 261 immaterial — out of all conscious relation to the mjnd viewing or caring for it, or as an object in such relation. Taken in the first sense, the object is capable of being recalled vaguely in its general outlines, and confusedly in its details, or it can stand out before the eye of the mind with the sharpest out- line, and inclose a perfect picture of distinct minutiae. But the object of memory is more appropriately the object in some rela- tion to the previous activity of the soul in some given place and at some given time. This more complex object admits also of every variety and degree, from the lowest up to the highest conceivable fulness and freshness. This, of course, provides for the possibility that the mind should, in its acts of recovery, go through all the intermediate steps of effort and intention, till the whole object, as objective and subjective, is fully represented and recognized. In recovering the whole, we may begin with that which is eminently objective. We may set off with some object which we are sure, in our previous knowledge, had some relation to that which we seek — as the dates of some events that occurred before or after the one which we look for, the names which we have learned in connection with the one required ; and we may dwell upon these till the date or name required occurs to the mind, and we recognize it with welcome. Or we may begin with the sub- jective element. We may recall ourselves in the act of being charged with certain duties or commissions — where we were, what we were doing, of what ice were thinking, how we were feeling, — till by this means, the missing element reappears to make the recognition complete. It has already been asserted, that in the intentional memo- ry the active element is most prominent. This is true. But it happens, from this very circumstance, that the passive element is thereby brought into more conspicuous and striking contrast. It would seem to delight to tantalize us by the wantonness of its caprices, as now it flashes those very thoughts upon our mental vision which we are most desirous to hide out of sight, and then as provokingly hides those which we a*e most desirous to un- cover. At one time we are disappointed by a strange and unaccountable forgetfulness of the most familiar objects; at another, we are surprised by the appositenoss and the affluence of unexpected remembrances. 262 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §166. The sole and single function which the mind, as active, can exert, is to apply the force of its attention to the object or objects which it is certain have reference to that which is sought for. To these only have we access. These only we have at our com- mand. Energetic and prolonged attention is all that the mind can do at the moment of remembering. § 166. Memory is sometimes defined as exclusively powSretaint the power to retain, or the conservative faculty. So o lose. Hamilton treats it, and exalts this supposed power into a separate faculty co-ordinate with the power to reproduce and the power to represent. But when we inquire for the defini- tion or statement of the function which this so-called retentive faculty performs, we find that no function of the sort is known to consciousness. Indeed, it is conceded by Hamilton, that what- ever is done by this faculty is performed unconsciously. No one holds that, during the interval, the mind acts upon the object, or with respect to it. It does not exert itself to hold it, or concern itself with it in the least. The expression to re- tain is purely metaphorical, and simply carries the thoughts over the period that intervenes between the moment when it was first apprehended, and the moment when it is known a second time. As Locke pertinently and truly observes, " This laying up of our ideas in the repository of the memory signifies no more than this, that the mind has a power, in many cases, to revive perceptions which it has once had, with this additional perception annexed to them, that it has had them before.' And in this sense it is that our ideas are said to be in our memories, when, indeed, they are actually nowhere ; but only there is an ability in the mind, when it will, to revive them again,'' etc. (Es- say B. ii., c. x., § 2). It is only by a metaphor that objects remembered can be spoken of as preserved in some repository or hiding-place, in drawers, pigeon-holes, or other compartments. Nor can the doctrine be maintained, that in the act of original acquisition the fibres of the brain are disposed in a certain position, which they retain, or at least retain the tendency to reassume. Nor can it be proved, as the followers of Herbart contend, that each object as appre- hended, or the state of mind as excited to action by the object, is retained ever afterward in a condition of tension, which, on a § 166. REPRESENTATION. — THE MEMORY. 263 fit occasion, springs forth into the presence of the conscious spirit. Now, if all these representations are figurative or metaphorical, the power to retain, or the doctrine of a retentive faculty, must be purely figurative also ; the fact which it describes being merely that under certain conditions, and in obedience to certain laws, the mind can represent and recognize its previous know- ledge. The mind that can do this in regard to the greatest number of objects, after the lapse of the longest time, is said to have the most retentive memory. Cicero (De Oratore, i., 5), Plato and others, have compared the mind in pre- serving what it had known, to a tablet on which characters were impressed or engraved. Notwithstanding the cautious and accurate definition of Locke which we have cited, we find him, in the same chapter, indulging in such language as this : , " The pictures drawn in our minds are laid in fading colors, and, if not sometimes refreshed, vanish and disappear." .... "In some, it [the mind] re- tains the characters drawn on it like marble; in others like freestone; and in others, little better than sand." . . . . " We oftentimes find a disease quite strip the mind of all its ideas, and the flames of a fever in a few clays calcine all those images to dust and confusion, which seemed to be as lasting as if graved in marble." Again, the ideas are, "very often roused and tumbled out of their dark cells into open daylight by some turbulent and tempestuous passion." Hamilton justly observes, that, "of all these sensible resemblances, none is so ingenious as that of Gasssndi to the folds of a piece of paper or cloth." But Hamilton does not notice wherein the truth and ingenuity of the resemblance mainly lies, viz., the circumstance that the mind, like the cloth, retains nothing but the capacity to assume the same folds and in the same combination and order which they had originally taken. We observe here, that as the goodness of the memory may respect it as spontaneous or intentional ; so we describe it in the one case as ready, and in the other as tenacious. The one does not exclude the other. If a person is able to recall every object that is required, at once, without effort or delay, his memory is called ready ; but it is not necessarily implied thereby that he is deficient in the capacity to retain, but only that he is quick and apt to recall. On the other hand, when one is slow to recall, and yet sure to do so by the application of energetic attention if sufficient time is allowed, his memory is tenacious ; by which is intended only that the object is certain to be recovered — not that there is a special capacity to retain, which may be possessed in eminent measure, to which may or may not be added another special capacity to recall. The power to retain, in the sense explained, implies the power 264 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 166. to lose, in the same sense; the capacity to remember, suggests that there is the liability to forget. The fact that we do forget, most men will not venture to question or deny. It is not, how- ever, easy to explain why we forget, or to detail the process by which we lose an acquisition beyond recall. In one aspect of the case, it would seem that we ought never to remember — that the mind might be supposed to be limited to the contemplation of the new objects which the presentative power can bring before it. But when we have become acquainted with the possibility and the conditions of representation, it would seem that we ought to forget nothing, but that it must always be within the reach of every related thought to bring back all its correlates. A moment's reflection, however, must convince us that, were it possible for us to recall every object, the recall could never in fact take place simply for want of time. To recall the acquisi- tions of a few years, would require as long a time as to make the original acquirement, even if to represent were our sole occupa- tion. But it is not solely for lack of time or opportunity that we do not recall. Often, when both are furnished, the related thoughts do not spontaneously present themselves. The phrase to forget is variously employed — sometimes posi- tively, at others comparatively ; now absolutely, and then rela- tively; or, as JStiedenroth has it, " Forgetting admits of several degrees, or stadia. The first is a momentary displacement of an object apprehended which is yet certain to spring back as soon as the object displacing it is withdrawn. The second is a com- parative withdrawal of the attention, as when we divert our mind from a painful sensation, or, as we say, forget it, in labor or play. The third is when an object will not present itself spontaneously, but we must bethink ourselves in order to recover it. The fourth is when we bethink ourselves in vain. The fifth is when it has vanished for so long a time that we question whether we can by any effort bring it back. The sixth, when we conclude that it is absolutely certain that we shall never recall it again." (Psychologie, Berlin, 1824, p. 82). It is questioned by many whether this absolute forgetfulness is possible — whether, at least, we are authorized to affirm that the soul can lose beyond recovery any thing which it has known. It is certain that knowledge which has remained out of sight for a § 167. REPRESENTATION. THE MEMORY. 265 long period has often been suddenly recovered. Even acquisi- tions that were the least likely to be remembered, and which, previously, were never known or suspected to have been made, come up as though the soul were inspired to receive strange re- velations of its capacities and acquirements. Numerous examples have occurred within the observation of the curious, and not a few are recorded in history. The well- known and often quoted story, which was originally published by Coleridge in his Biographia Literaria, is in substance as follows : A servant-girl in Germany was very ill of nervous fever accom- panied with violent delirium. In her excited ravings, she re- cited long passages from classical and rabbinical writers, which excited the wonder and even terror of all who heard them, the most of whom thought her inspired by a good or evil spirit. Some of the passages which were written down were found to correspond with literal extracts from learned books. When in- quiries were made concerning the history of her life, it was found that, several years before, she had lived in the family of an old and learned pastor in the country, who was in the habit of reading aloud favorite passages from the very writers in whose works these extracts were discovered. These sounds, to her unintelligible, were so distinctly impressed upon her memory, that, under the excitement of delirious fever, they were repro- duced to her mind and uttered by her tongue. Rev. Timothy Flint, in his Recollections, records of himself, that, when prostrated by malarial fever, he repeated aloud long passages from Virgil and Homer which he had never formally committed to memory, and of which, both before and after his illness, he could repeat scarcely a line. Dr. Rush, in his Medical Inquiries, says that he once attended an Italian, who died in New York of yellow fever, who at first spoke English, at a later period of his illness French, and, when near his end, Italian only. He records also that he was in- formed by a Lutheran clergyman, that old German immigrants whom he attended in their last illness, often prayed in their native tongue, though some of them, he was certain, had not spoken it for many years. § 167. Such facts illustrate the connection of the ?he P Sy Uceon bodily condition with the phenomena of memory, of which a l L • 266 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 167. partial explanation has already been given (§ 153). They con- firm two positions, to which daily experience and observation both testify. The first is, that the extent and reach of our memory is greatly affected by our bodily condition at the time when we acquire. Every object which we apprehend, when in a certain condition of health, we can afterward recall, and this we can do as readily and as easily as we breathe. On other occa- sions, if we are wearied by labor, exhausted by watching, or prostrated by pain, the book which we read, the conversation in which we take part, the incidents which happen, become almost a blank to us when we seek to recover them. It is in place here to notice the circumstance, that certain parts of the day, and, with some persons, certain seasons of the year, are most favorable to the successful acquisition of possessions for the memory. In the evening, and especially late at night, the attention may seem to be as intently fixed upon the objects which are to be»retained, as in the morning, and the intellectual force may appear to* be more energetic. But it not infrequently hap- pens that the acquisitions of the previous evening, which seemed to be so distinct and promised to be so permanent, have well-nigh vanished in the morning, and require to be reviewed to be made useful or sure. It is easy to see how, after the analogies furnished by these phenomena, can be explained the frequently evanescent character of the acquisitions which are made under the influence of wine or opium, as also the fact that the men of the strongest memories have often been either water-drinkers, or men of strong heads, not easily disturbed by stimulants. The second position is, that, whether we can recall what we may be said to have acquired, depends also very largely — at times altogether — upon the bodily condition at the moment of our de- sire or effort to remember. Under the inspiration of joyous health or the stimulus of exciting disease, all that we have ever experienced, witnessed, or learned, comes back to us as if a good genius were pouring forth at our bidding all that we need or de- sire to recall. Again, in seasons of extreme weakness, we can- not recover the most familiar names, incidents, or dates, and our most common knowledge refuses to serve us. It is pertinent here to refer to the many cases of the sudden and almost entire loss of memory, some of which are as striking § 167. REPRESENTATION. — THE MEMORY. 267 as those of its development to unwonted energy. A lady of su- perior endowments and culture was for several days exposed to suffering and fear, in a storm at sea which terminated in the wreck of the vessel. A severe and protracted illness was the consequence, from which she slowly recovered. After her ap- parent restoration to complete health, it was found that the best part of her acquired knowledge was gone, and it was never af- terward recovered. An attack of apoplexy has been said to ef- face all remembrance of the events of some definite period of the life. Both classes of facts — those which illustrate the dependence on certain bodily conditions of both the power to acquire with effect the materials for the memory, and the power to recall them with ease — can be accounted for by the general views al- ready expressed. The varying condition of the body through the several sensations of which it is the occasion, enters into the experiences of consciousness, and furnishes a most important ele- ment in them all. It is the constant background on which all the mental activities are projected, the never-failing setting with which every one of them must be accompauied. When these sensations are of a certain description, they are the normal and favoring accessories of the other actings of the soul. If they are abnormal, disturbed, or unpleasant, the mind is so absorbed or distracted by the presence of these obtrusive sensations, that it has little energy to spare for other objects, and no capacity to steady the attention upon them. Again, the bodily condition may also present sensations which so far disturb and distract the attention, as to allow no time for the passive memory to respond to any call ; may so hurry the mind from one object of present sense-experience to another, as to leave no opportunity for the representing power to thrust in a single mental image ; or, again, these sensations may be so utterly dissimilar to any which have been before experienced, as to sug- gest no image of the past. Or, on the other hand, this com- plex of sensations may be most favorable to the easy and almost exclusive action of the passive or spontaneous memory, and may be so akin to the states which we would recall, as to be all lu- minous and living with objects that suggest those which we wel- come or seek after. • 268 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 168. To the question, whether the circumstances of the soul can ever so far be changed as to empower it to recover all the past, the analogies suggested by these facts would lead us to reply : (1.) Under no circumstances whatever can it be supposed that the soul shall recover what it has not in some sense made its own by the energetic action of its attentive consideration. That is not a proper object of memory to the soul, which has not been taken up into its life by its efficient acquisition. (2.) It is supposable that the conditions might be furnished of recalling all the past thus defined, under the actings of laws which are well known to us. We have only to suppose that a vehicle or subject of the required psychical experiences — call them sensations, if you will, and the occasion of them a new body — should be furnished, and these would of themselves give back every element of past ac- quisition or experience to which they might be analogous. § 168. With the progress and development of the memory 1 - 5 how powers and activities of the soul, the memory itself explained. advances through separate stages, each of which pre- pares the way for that which follows, and becomes its natural and logical condition. The memory of the infant differs from the memory of the child ; the memory of the child differs from that of the youth ; the memory of the man, in each of the several stages of active life, differs from that in the stage which succeeds it. In general, the memory of the person in active life differs from the memory of old age. The memory of the artist is very unlike the memory of the mathematician. The memory of the erudite and disciplined thinker differs greatly in its objects and its laws, from the memory of the person who has had little cul- ture from reading or thought. Hence, there exist many clearly distinguishable varieties of memory ; if we make nothing of the fact that every individual must have a type of memory which arises from those individual habits of thought and feeling which he can share with no other person. Besides those varieties of memory whicb are common to all men in the successive periods of their life, there are the special peculiarities which result from one's pursuit or profession. The historian remembers facts and dates ; the philosopher, principles and laws. The artist remembers landscapes and faces ; the wit and the story-teller, never forget a successful jest or a capital § 168. REPRESENTATION. — THE MEMORY. 269 anecdote. These habits of memory, as they are called, often grow stronger till they become fixed beyond the power of change. Persons distinguished for great intellectual power in certain directions, very often complain of a serious defect of memory which they cannot account for. Such one-sided habits and de- fects are not peculiar to the memory only, but pertain equally to all the activities of the soul : the condition of memory is energy in the original activities ; these involve attention to the objects to be remembered ; attention springs from an active interest in these objects ; this prevailing interest follows the habits which constitute and express the character. We return again to the fact that these varieties of memory are not only distinguished by the character of the objects remem- bered, but also by the method and relations under which they are recalled. The things which the child remembers not only differ from those which an older person recalls, but they are re- called in a child's order,, and by the relations which are proper to a child. The same is true of the devotee to any study or pur- suit so far as special intellectual habits are induced by such a study or employment. When the child recalls to itself or recites to others a series of incidents of which it has had experience, it depicts the whole, generally in the order of time, with little selec- tion of materials according to their importance or their relation to any principle or purpose. The spontaneous memory of the eye or the ear, reproduces the past solely after the relations of time or place, with no rearrangement or selection of the same, such as would be suggested by the desire for the clearer appre- hension of the hearer, or by the bearings of the story upon his intellect or hie feelings. This is very conspicuous in the memories, and especially in the narratives of uneducated persons. Thus, Dame Quickly recites the story of her wrongs in the following fashion : " Thou didst swear to me upon a parcel-gilt goblet, sitting in my dolphin chamber, at the round table, by a sea-coal fire, upon Wednesday in Whitsun-week, when the prince broke thy head for liking his father to a singing-man of Windsor; thou didst swear to me then, as I was washing thy wound, to marry me, and make me my lady thy wife." (Henry IV., 2d part, Act ii., scene i. ; cf. S. T. Coleridge, The Friend, Sec. ii., Essay iv.) No finer opportunity 270 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 168. is furnished for observing this variety in the order and method which characterize the memories of different persons, than in lis- tening to the testimony of different witnesses in a court of jus- tice, concerning the same transaction. The memory of the young is usually more ready ; that of the adult is more tenacious. This is, in part, owing to the greater physical vivacity of youth, which affects the actings of the soul. The vivacious old man is as quick to remember as he is to appre- hend or judge ; while the torpid and phlegmatic child is as slow in his memory as he is in his reasonings and inferences. The difference, however, is not merely a difference of temperament or animal spirits, but has its ground in the character of the relations which usually predominate at each of these periods of life. Ob- jects that are recalled by the relations of space and time and of obvious resemblance, present themselves promptly, if they are remembered at all; but these relations are, from their very nature, limited to but few individual objects. Hence, the groups which are connected by such relations are sooner set aside and forgotten, and are displaced by others. The relations of thought, however, especially those which are founded on wide-reaching principles or laws, are in their very nature less obvious. But, on the other hand, the principles themselves are few, and are constantly before the mind. When these are once mastered, they are illustrated in every fact; they are exemplified in every instance. By means of them we can prophesy and construct the future as well as explain and interpret the past. These few bonds of association, when they control the memory, give to it perfect security in and command over its possessions. The men of universal memory are those who combine most happily the ready memory of facts and events with the te- nacious memory of truths and laws. They are those whose spontaneous memory is not displaced, but rather aided, by the development of the rational memory which sees in facts the illustrations of the higher relations of philosophic truth. They hold fast the acquisitions of youth and of old age by the perma- nence of principles which are as old as the universe and as new as the latest experiment by which they are verified. The memory of the ancients, if we may believe all the stories which are told of the achievements of some of their more dis- § 168. REPRESENTATION. — THE MEMORY. 271 tinguished men, surpassed, in some respects, the average attain- ments of the moderns. It is not difficult to believe this to have been true, from what we know of the memory of those who most resemble them in the circumstances of their lives, and the disci- pline of their intellects. Their attention was far less distracted by a variety of objects than is the case with the moderns. The facts in science, literature, chronology, and history, which they were required to remember were far fewer than those which burden the memory of the modern scholar. More than all, they relied far less than we do upon writing, memoranda, and books, to preserve what they desired to retain. They committed their acquisitions to their own power to recall them. Conversation and repetition were practiced far more generally by them than by us. What was heard by the ear from the living teacher, was repeated and discoursed of by his interested scholars, till it became a part of their very being. The attention of the infant is at first occupied with the sensible ■world. It sees colors which delight the eye, it hears sounds which of^Jmorv^ts captivate the ear. It is long before it unites these separate per- characteristics cepts into individual objects, and still longer before it discrimi- periods oTlife. nates, by special attention, one object from another. Later still, it learns to notice with any effect its own inner experiences and activities. The relations of before and now are of still later evolution. But all these separate elements must be familiarized by attention before an act of memory can be at all definite and complete, inasmuch as, whatever suggestions of representation there may be, there ean be no proper act of memory till all these elements are recognized. The germinant memory of the infant must be exceedingly limited, because its materials are very scanty ; the chief force of its intellectual life being expended in acquiring rather than in recalling. So far as it remembers at all, its memory is passive ; intentional memory being as yet undeveloped, for the infant is the passive child of nature, and the stream of its memory runs side by side with the course of its objective life. The infant remembers, as animals remember, just that, and only that, which the objects of sense-perception recall to their thoughts. The acquisition and the use of language opens the way for the higher memory, though obviously in its first beginnings. The right use of words, and of short sentences, requires that the child should connect names with distinctly discerned objects, and should express its wishes and thoughts by short sentences. But by-and-by the child finds that it forgets — that it has not the knowledge which it once possessed. It cannot recall the right name or phrase which it wishes to use, and which it knows it has previously spoken. It is impelled by its wishes to re- call the forgotten object, and begins to practice the arts of the intellectual, or ac- tive memory. But these occasions and efforts are at best so infrequent, and of so little importance, that they train the intentional memory in a slight degree only. 272 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 169. It is by tasks imposed by others directly and indirectly, that the soul is disciplined to the exercise of this higher memory, and its various activities are developed. The child is taught written language. It learns the alphabet and spelling by the eye, or brief sentences or verses by the ear. Children are charged also with com- missions to execute, with services of labor or courtesy which may not be forgot- ten, and with endless lessons from books to prepare and repeat. By degrees, this pupil of others becomes his own taskmaster : he passes from the lower discipline of the memory, which others enforce, to the higher, which he imposes upon himself. The intentional memory, which has been trained by others, he cultivates for himself. He makes his own purposes ; he proposes his own ideals; he knows what he must learn in order to accomplish these purposes and to realize these ideals; he appoints to himself his own lessons; tasks his own intellect to consider, and his own efforts to retain what he foresees he shall have occasion to know and to have at command. According as this training of the attention is more or less complete, so does his memory become more or less per- fectly subject to his control, and from the passive spontaneity of early life, passes into the active energy of maturer years. This memory of manhood is also char- acterized by the predominance of thought-relations and of rational purposes. The spontaneous memory of early life is not thereby displaced ; the original apti- tudes of the memory of both eye and ear are not necessarily set aside. But just so far as one thinks and acts like a man, just so far will he remember as a man, and not merely as a child — that is, by the aid of those higher relations which thought requires, and which definite aims and rational activities necessarily in- volve. The memory of the man is not only intentional, but it is also rational. When the man advances from the busy noon toward the quiet evening of life, his exclusive interest in the objects which have absorbed his manhood is relaxed, either through physical infirmity, or the success which satiates, and perhaps the disappointment which wearies a man with life. In place of an intent and ab- sorbed devotedness to the present, there is a more frequent review of the past. Old scenes are described, old books are read, old companions are talked of, old stories are repeated. For this reason, recent objects are so readily forgotten, and the singular contrast is furnished in the memory peculiar to the aged — most tena- cious of objects and events that occurred longest ago, and readily forgetful, if te- nacious at all, of those that were most recent. The education § 169. The methods of education should recognise of the memory. ^ e w j ge arran g e ments of Dature in developing and maturing the memory. In the earlier periods of life the spontaneous memory should be stimulated and enriched by appropriate studies. The child should learn stories, verses, poems, facts, and dates, as freely and as accurately as it can be made to respond to such tasks. During this early and objective period, it should learn as many languages as is possible in the circumstances, or as is desirable for its future pursuits. Espe- cially should it learn those languages which can be taught in conversation, or acquired by contact with those who speak them § 170. REPRESENTATION. — THE MEMORY. 273 freely and well. If the elements of the ancient languages are taught so early in life, they should be taught, as far as in the nature of the case is possible, by similar methods. But as the higher and rational powers awake to action, every acquisition that has been made by the lower and more obvious associations, should be secured against loss by recasting it and relearning it as it were, after the relations which are higher and more philo- sophical. English children who learn to speak French, German, or Italian fluently in early life, may lose their acquisitions almost entirely, unless these are fixed by a grammatical study of the same languages at a later period of life. The large accumulations of facts and dates, as in geography and history, which are made very early by many carefully-trained children, and with the greatest ease on their part, are liable to be effaced, and, as it were, swept clean oufr from the memory, unless they are secured against loss by reviewing and rearranging them under the new and higher relations which the development of the reason makes possible. On the other hand, to anticipate the development of the re- flecting powers, by forcing upon the intellect studies which imply and require these capacities, is to commit the double error of misusing the time which is especially appropriate to simple acquisition, and of constraining the intellect to efforts which are untimely and unnatural. The modern practice of occupying the minds of children with the reasons of things, i. e., with laws, principles, etc., in the form of compends of astronomy, natural or mental philosophy, natural theology, etc. — is one that cannot be too earnestly deprecated, or too soon abandoned by those who would train the mind according to the methods of nature. § 170. The cultivation of the memory is a subject which has been earnestly discussed by many writers, tion e of ' the and is of practical interest to all those who are bent Sonicsf' mne " on self-improvement, or are devoted to the education of others. Many complain of a general defect of memory. Others are especially sensible of painful failures in respect to certain classes of objects, as names, dates, facts of history, sentences or passages from authors familiarly read. The question is often anxiously propounded, How can these general or special defects be overcome ? 12* 274 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §170. The conclusions which we have reached in respect to the nature and laws of memory, suggest the only practical rules which can be attained. These rules may be summed up in the directions : ■ To remember any thing, you must attend to it ; and in order to attend, you must either find or create an interest in the objects to be attended to. This interest must, if possible, be felt in the objects themselves, as directly related to your own wishes, feel- ings, and purposes, and not to some remote end on account of which you desire to make the acquisition/ It should never be forgotten, that in memory, the soul can recall no more than it makes its own — no more than, in acquiring, it constructs or creates as a spiritual product by its own activity. The late Sir Thomas Fowell Buxton advised his sons in the following golden words : " What you do know, know thoroughly. There are few instances in modern times of a rise equal to that of Sir Edward Sugden. After one of the Weymouth elections, I was shut up with him in a carriage for twenty-four hours. I ventured to ask him, What was the secret of his success ; his answer was : ' I resolved, when beginning to read law, to make every thing I acquired perfectly my own, and never to go to a second thing till I had entirely accomplished the first. Many of my competitors read as much in a day as I read in a week ; but, at the end of twelve months, my knowledge was as fresh as on the day it was acquired, while theirs had glided away from their recollection.' " (Memoirs of Sir Thomas F. Buxton, chap, xxiv.) Numerous devices have been contrived in order to aid the mind so to make its acquisitions as to secure them against loss, and to bring them readily to hand when required. They were not unknown to the ancients, as is evident from Cicero, De Or, ii., 86-88; Ad Herenn., iii., 16-24 ; Quinct., Instil, x., 1, 11-26. They all rest upon a common assumption or principle, viz., that it is possible, by means of"arbitrary associations, so to connect what one desires to remember with a series or scheme of objects, artificially arranged or actually existing, that they can be readily and certainly suggested to the mind. Some teachers of mnemon- ics employ a scheme of geometrical figures, as squares or tri- angles, For example : if a person, in listening to a discourse or lecture, should, as the speaker proceeds, connect the leading thoughts or divisions with the panes of glass in a window-sash, §170. REPRESENTATION. THE MEMORY. 275 or with the panels of a door, he would avail himself of the geome- trical method, which addresses the eye, through the space-relations of visible objects. Often these systems have sought to aid the memory of dates by the letters of the alphabet; each pre- senting some number, and being employed in forming artificial syllables, such as could be readily attached to names of persons or places distinguished in history. Mnemonic verses and tables have been furnished for many of the important objects with which every student is expected to be familiar, as the names of the sovereigns of the great kingdoms and empires, grammatical paradigms and rules, logical formulae, etc., etc. A correct estimate of the value of all artificial memory may be summed up as follows : The natural, as opposed to the artifi- cial memory, depends on the relations of sense and the relations of thought, — the spontaneous memory of the eye and the ear availing itself of the obvious conjunctions of objects which are furnished by space and time ; and the rational memory, of those higher combinations which the rational faculties superinduce upon thesg lower. The artificial memory proposes to substitute for the natural and necessary relations under which all objects must present and arrange themselves, an entirely new set of relations that are purely arbitrary and mechanical, which excite little or no other interest than that they are to aid us in remembering. It follows, that if the mind tasks itself to the special effort of considering objects under these artificial relations, it will give less attention to those which have a direct and legitimate interest for itself. Its energies, instead of following in easy obedience the leadings of nature, will be forced to efforts that are constrained and artificial. Whatever dexterity is acquired by these intellec- tual gymnastics, must be gained at the expense of that rhythmical power which always rewards those activities in which art follows nature. The wonderful feats of memory which are occasionally adduced as resulting from the latest new device in mnemonics, are the fruits of much time, labor, and enthusiasm. Had the same time, labor, and enthusiasm been expended in acquiring knowledge by means of the ordinary appliances, the acquisitions would have been many times more valuable for the culture of the powers and the uses of life. Perhaps even the number of facts recorded in the memory would have been as numerous. 276 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 170. There are occasions when the artificial memory is unquestion- ably useful. It may serve a good purpose in holding before the mind facts which it is important to remember, when neither the facts themselves, nor their relations, present attractions which are strong enough to fix or hold the attention. For the man whose intellectual force and interest are preoccupied, it is often difficult to apply the memory with success to such objects, unless they are arranged in some novel relations. The artificial memory comes to his aid, and offers the service and assistance of art to supplement the failing forces of nature ; to reenforce, and as it were, to renew the spontaneous memory by novel appliances. But while we concede a certain advantage to the artificial memory under circumstances like these, we must still hold, with Coleridge (Biog. Liieraria, chap, vii.), that, for the ordinary uses of the student, sound logic, a healthy digestion, and a quiet conscience are the proper conditions or arts of memory. By sound logic, is, of course, intended a well-balanced and well-trained intellect, which by original structure and discipline, is capable of fixed attention, clear apprehension, and excited interest. Without these conditions, a strong and trustworthy memory is impossible. A healthy digestion is also requisite ; for if the digestion is dis- turbed, the action of the mind will be distracted by those vague sensations of depression and discomfort which are inconsistent with that harmonious interaction of the powers of the whole man, which is indispensable to a good memory. Even though it happens that persons in this condition are capable of extra- ordinary energy in their mental efforts, these occasions are yet certain to be followed by longer periods of listlessness and de- pression which exclude that repetition and review of the know- ledge which are quite as essential as energy and interest at the time of the original acquisition. A clear or quiet conscience is also a prime requisite, for a simi- lar reason. Indigestion and intoxication of any kind disturb the memory by intrusive, uncomfortable, and exciting sensa- tions. But the consciousness of guilt haunts the spirit with disquieting self-reproach, and fear of deserved punishment. Feelings of this sort do indeed often stamp upon the memory a few impressions that are ineffaceable. But for this very § 170. REPRESENTATION. — THE MEMORY. 277 reason it is the more unfitted to attend with interest or enthu- siasm to other objects, and its movements in all directions are enfeebled or depressed by distraction or constraint. It is natural, in this connection, to notice the moral conditions of a good memory. The man who would have a strong and trustworthy memory, must always be true to it in his dealings with himself and with other men. He must paint to his own im- agination, with scrupulous fidelity, whatever he has witnessed or experienced. He must never so yield to the bias of interest or passion, as to strive to persuade himself, even for a moment, that events were different from what he knows they actually were. He must seek to repeat to others the precise words of what he has heard or read, whenever he makes communications by lan- guage. Such a moral discipline to internal and external honesty, both implies and enforces a mental discipline to earnest and wide-reaching attention — an attention which does complete justice to every object that comes before it, and which neither slights nor omits any thing which ought to be brought to view. An intellect that is regulated and held to its duties by the tension of such a purpose, will act with the precision and cer- tainty of clock-work. Its recollections will be- trusted by others, because they are trusted by the person himself, and for the best of reasons — because he is true to what he remembers. On the other hand, a person who is false to his fellow-men, will often weaken his confidence in his own intellect, and may end with an incapacity to distinguish falsehood from the truth. What he does not like to remember, he will persuade himself did not actually happen, or, at least, not in every particular as it spontaneously presents itself to his view. Then follows, by natural consequence, distrust of his own memory, because he is not sure that the materials are at hand with which he can cor- rect his own omissions. The next step is, under the excitement of strong passion, to persuade himself that what he desires should be true, did really occur, or was really written or said. If he asserts this by his own word, he is the more strongly com- mitted to believe it. At last, he becomes so false to the work- ings of his own memory, that he dares not trust it himself. It is well to remember, that, while the liar has more pressing need of a good memory than any other man, he is of all men the least likely to possess it. 278 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 171. CHAPTER V. REPRESENTATION. — (2.) THE PHANTASY, OR IMAGING POWER. From perfect memory, we pass through the several forms and degrees of imperfect memory till we come to the phantasy. Phantasy de- § 17L The Phantasy, or imaging power, is that ?rated. ndillus " form of representation which brings before the mind's apprehension objects, or, more exactly, images, as such, severed from all relations of place, time, or previous cogni- tion. The best example of the exercise of this power is furnished in dreaming. In what are called the abnormal or disordered states of the soul — as somnambulism, and the various types and degrees of insanity — the phantasy has a more or less complete control. Among the wakeful and normal states of the soul, reverie is the purest and the most perfect example of phantasy. The fewer the relations to the past or the present which the objects suggest, the more complete is the working of the phantasy. In earliest infancy this power may be supposed to be active, for the reason that the mind has not yet reached a condition in which memory proper is possible. In extreme old age also, when the incapacity to attend to single objects for a long continuance pre- cludes intelligent and effective perception, memory, or thought, the phantasy may still survive, and actively call up the pictures of the past, simply as pictures, each recalling the next, according to the conditions and laws already explained. In the wakeful and earnest periods of the mind's activity, the exercise of simple phantasy is precluded, for the obvious reason, that at such times the mind is intent upon some rational object, which lifts it above the condition of the passive recipience or contemplation of pic- tures. And yet, with the higher activities, there are not infre- quently mingled those approaching to pure phantasy. When one object suggests another in a train of associations, many may be recalled without a single distinct act of remembrance, and yet every one may be a transcript from some reality experienced in the past. Each is recalled, however, not as a remembered or recognized object, but simply as an image. When the higher §172. REPRESENTATION. — THE PHANTASY. 279 functions of the soul are wholly, or in part, put in abeyance, as in fainting, fatigue, or sleep, or when there is bodily weakness, or any disturbance of the nervous equilibrium, as in fever, delirium or excitement from liquor or narcotics, or even in protracted sleeplessness, the phantasy asserts a more or less complete dominion. The mind is visited with throngs of pictures, which rush so rapidly by as to confuse it by their very swiftness, and to oppress it by a sense of its own impotence to arrest or direct their course. When this condition is permanent, the mind is said to be the victim of phantasy. Such a state is also called a state of distraction — which term describes the mind's incapacity to fix the attention or detain its flitting images long enough to allow the exercise of the functions of rational memory, in- vention or thought. §172. These conditions of the soul are grave prob- The interest of lems to the psychologist. Three suppositions may be lts P roblems - made in respect to them all: — (1.) These states may be said to be simply abnormal or irregular, recognizing and obeying no law. (2.) They may be set down as simply inexplicable; suggesting the existence of laws which cannot be discovered. (3.) They may be explained in great part by the usually recognized laws of the soul in its normal and wakeful condition. The probability is immensely in favor of the last. If the laws which govern the recurrence and representation of ideas have been fully and cor- rectly set forth, they ought to explain the phenomena of the sleeping and disordered conditions of the soul. That they do so, is probable for the following reasons : — I. The power of association operates very efficiently in all these states. In dreaming, somnambulism, The power of insanity, etc., etc., its presence and powers are often JJJSSSSeto * most apparent. When we ask ourselves, Why did it them a11 ' happen that I had such or such a dream? it is often very easy to answer by a reference to the usually recognized laws of associa- tion. The strange and unexpected sallies of the insane, however wild and preposterous they may be, follow some law of associa- tion, though it often leads to the most fantastic result. There is always some method in their madness. 280 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. ' § 172. II. The deviations from the ordinary working of couSedfor,- tnese laws can also ^ to some extent, be satisfactorily IHSlSSSfe? accounted for. in the relative the OP p°ower n s . of C 1 -) The P owers of the . soul ordinarily act in a certain conjunction with and proportion to one another. It is not surprising, that, when a single power acts alone, the phenomena should differ very greatly from those which result from the combined activity of them all. In the cases supposed, self-consciousness, rational activity, and the voluntary control of the bodily movements and the mental states, are all set aside ; and the associative power asserts, to a very large ex- tent, the possession of the soul. We ought not to be surprised, that a power ordinarily acting in connection with the wakeful reason and under its control, should manifest results unlike those which appear when these regulating elements are present. (2.) Certain bodily states are known greatly to modify the actings of the soul, when the soul is wakeful and in health. It is according to the law of its being, that its action should be modified still more when the bodily affections become more effi- cient and obtrusive. It should not be surprising then, that under such physical conditions as sleep and cerebral excitement, even stranger psychical phenomena should be manifest. (3.) The comprehensive law under which past mental states are reproduced, should be distinguished from the materials upon which it operates. While the laws of representation remain the same, the conditions under which they act, may vary enough to account for every variety of phenomena. To the actual reproduction of an image, two conditions are necessary, viz., its actual previous presence to the mind, and the existence of an exciting occasion in something united with it as an element of the mind's previous knowledge or feeling. In dreaming, insanity, etc., these conditions are peculiar. First, in the states of distinct and easily-remembered conscious- ness, are present many elements which are less distinctly noticed, because they are accessory and subordinate. In the states under consideration, those may be brought forward either as the materials of phantasy, or as the mediate suggestors of other materials. In every act of distinct perception, there is an ex- tended background of such objects, standing out in the field of § 172. REPRESENTATION. — THE PHANTASY. 281 view with more or less prominence, but engrossing some share of the soul's energy. Any one of these objects, under possible exciting occasions, is capable of being recalled. In the normal states of the soul, the prominent or central object is usually re- called. In an abnormal state, one or more of the accessories may be represented. Under the feelings and purposes of wakefulness, a certain class of pictures and thoughts only may be certain to be thought of. In dreaming, another set may present them- selves ; in insanity, still another ; and yet all of these may have been gathered from the mind's own experience. Again : there are many conditions of the soul marked by little energy of attention, as well as by the feeble influence of rational purpose, in which the phantasy greatly prevails. In walking, in driving for relaxation, in extreme fatigue, in the transitions from wake- fulness to sleep and from sleep to wakefulness, in the many listless hours or seasons of reverie, there are multitudes of acts and objects which leave little impression, and are rarely, if ever, distinctly brought back to the rational and wakeful memory or imagination, but of which any one may be recalled under novel circumstances. Again: there are activities that have been ex- perienced previously to the soul's conscious action. Some of these acts tend to be reproduced, and, under varying circum- stances, may return either as a principal or accessory element. Again: the undefined bodily sense-perceptions, or sensations which are accessory in every mental experience, and are promi- nent in not a few — which form the background of many, and come into the foreground of many also, all tend to recur again. The occasions which control the presentation and suggestion of images in these abnormal states of the soul are also peculiar. In sleep, all the organs of sense-perception are more or less quiescent, while the vital organs are active. In insanity, etc., the bodily condition and activities are irregular. In both, they are greatly unlike those which are present in wakefulness and health. These peculiar and morbid bodily states are manifest to the soul in the form of peculiar sensations, both vital and organic. Sleep, from the beginning to the end, is attended by a series of sense-perceptions unlike those experienced in wake- fulness. Insanity, in all its forms and degrees, is attended by a nervous excitement or depression, which is revealed to conscious- 282 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 173. ness by irritating and uncomfortable sensations. The sensations thus excited, become themselves, in turn, the excitants of images and thoughts kindred to themselves. A third consideration should also be noticed. The creative power of the phantasy may have especial activity in dreaming and insanity. Whatever that power may be in its functions and products — if it be allowed that the phantasy is in any sense creative — if, in the waking and rational states, it is not tied to a simple reproduction of the past ; if it has any liberty of origina- tion, then it might be natural and credible that it should exercise this freedom more fully when unlimited by sense, reason, or will, than when constrained by these in the earnest activities of the wakeful and rational hours. That the creations of the phantasy of the dreamer and the madman have no correspondent realities, is obvious to all. The fantasies of " a madman's dream " are conceived by us as the most unnatural and the wildest of all unrealities. If the phantasy is, in its very nature, a creative as well as representative power, it is not surprising that it should create in madness and in sleep. If its creations are free in the one state, when reason is wakeful and the will is attent, and earnest purposes control, it is not surprising that, in those con- ditions of activity in which these influences are feeble, its pro- ducts should be irrational and unnatural. These considerations may serve as the foundations of a general theory of those various conditions of the soul's activity known as faintness, dreaming, somnambulism, and delirium. They are designed only to prepare for a more particular consideration of each. We consider, first of all, sleep, in the two following aspects : — (1.) Sleep as a condition of the body, l e., sleep in its physio- logical phenomena ; (2.) Sleep in its psychological experiences. g 173. We cannot understand sleep as a state of the soul, Sleep physio- -without considering the corporeal conditions which attend it. In logically con- , ... . ~ , .. sidered. order to interpret it psychologically, we must first examine it physiologically. In sleep, physiologically viewed, the organs of perception, and the nerves connected with them, are comparatively inactive, and seem incapable of performing their accustomed functions. Conversely, also, the soul can no longer control the organs of sense and of locomotion; or, more ex- actly, the soul loses, in a very great degree, its power to direct these organs. §174. REPRESENTATION. — THE PHANTASY. 283 On the other hand, the functions of the vegetative, circulatory, and respiratory- organs, go on as usual, though in the case of some with a somewhat diminished energy. That in all these functions the whole tone of life is lowered, is manifest directly from observation, and is inferred from the greater sensitiveness of the body in sleep, to all those agencies which weaken or endanger the life. On the other hand, it is certain that the nutrition of the brain and the whole nervous organism, is greatly augmented in sleep, and that sleep is even essential to re- store that waste of their material which wakefulness occasions. If wakefulness is protracted too long, by nervous restlessness, or excessive mental occupation or anxiety, it terminates in fever, delirium, or dementia, through a temporary disease or permanent lesion of the nervous organism itself. Hence, sleep is, if possible, more absolutely indispensaMe to the restoration of mental activity, than to that of any other human function. The incapacity of the organs of sense to be affected by impressions from without, as well as to yield to influences or directions from within, varies at different times. The want of control of the soul over its organs, also varies from the momentary loss of power which can suddenly be resumed, to that permanent impotence to speak or move, which is experienced in the most distressing nightmare. In falling to sleep, the soul passes through many of these conditions, begin- ning with the slightest unconsciousness, and proceeding more or less gradually through more or fewer intervening stages. In awaking from sleep, it emerges from a condition of more or less complete insensibility to one in which the senses are fully refreshed and active ; and more or less gradually, according as the occa- sion and manner of its waking is more or less gentle or violent. The same is true of the processes by which it loses and regains its command over the organs. The different senses, as has already been intimated, fall asleep at different times in various degrees, and awake also in unlike proportions. Thus, the sense of sight may be very obtuse when the sense of hearing is active, as is the case when a per- son watches by the bed of one who is ill, or in the instance of men who can find refreshment in sleep when reading or conversation is going on, and are able to re- cite when awake what has been read or spoken while they were sleeping. The miller sleeps while his mill is grinding, but wakes if it stops. Another person )s while it is still, but wakes when it moves. The watchman, when wearied, with all his senses, except the senses of touch and muscular direction. Sol- diers sleep in every sense and organ of motion, except the legs with which they march continuously. 174. The activity of the soul continues during sleep. It is not Sleep consi- dered psycho- logically. entirely suspended at any time, though its energy may now and then be exceedingly feeble. That it often acts during sleep, is confessed by all. Every dream involves some form of this activity. There is some diversity of opinion in respect to the question, whether this activity is constant, or whether it is not infrequently interrupted. Many have argued that this activity often ceases, from the circumstance that we are not conscious, and do not remember that we dream all the while that we are asleep ; that we know that we dream more frequently when sleep is less complete, as soon after we fall asleep, or just before we wake; that in our deepest slumber it often happens that no signs of conscious activity are indicated to a looker-on ; and that it is not necessary to the continued existence of the soul that it be constantly active. On the other hand it is urged that the soul is always active, because, on awaking, it is at once 284 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 174. aware of its own identity, which involves the belief of continued existence during the interval of sleep ; and when it wakes, it may recall or review a continued series of sensational experiences, if it cannot bring back an uninterrupted course of con- scious activities. Moreover, it is urged that the fact that the soul does not recall all its dreams does not disprove that it dreams, for there are many waking states during the progress of a single hour, much more during a day, which cannot be recalled. There are also many dreams which we do not recall ; as is obvious from the circumstance, that if, on awaking, we lay hold at once of the thread which is in our hands, we can trace our way backwards through the maze of even a succes- sion of dreams. That the soul acts with feebler energy when asleep than when awake, is obvious from the circumstance that in some of its powers it scarcely acts at all. This may be fairly inferred from that general dependence of the tone of its action upon the force of the body which is observed in wakefulness, which dependence, as may be fairly inferred from analogy, extends to its sleeping states. The only possible ex- ception to this conclusion would be suggested by the fact that some of the powers — e. g. } the phantasy — may seem to act in sleep with greater energy than in wake- fulness. With this exception, observation confirms what analogy suggests, that, in sleep, the general activity of the soul is greatly lowered. The powers and capacities of the soul act with unequal and varying energy in different persons and in differing conditions of sleep. The representative power of the soul, as has already been said, is that which is especially prominent in sleep. The law or force under which it acts has already been explained as the tendency of the soul to act more readily a second time in forms and with objects which have previously occupied its energies. This tendency or force needs only to be supposed to be exerted without the regulating presence of the other faculties, in order to account for its greater apparent energy. All the so-called laws of associa- tion control the production and presence of the objects which make up the image- world of the dreamer. These objects are sometimes recalled under the relations of time and space, in succession or co-existence. Sometimes the relations of like- ness or unlikeness control: at others, those of cause and effect. Very often, all these relations must be resorted to, to account for the presence of the various ob- jects of which a single dream is composed. This comparative irregularity and capriciousness pertains to the order in which these objects are presented to the mind. When the wakeful soul is intent on re- calling some object to memory, all the operations of the representative power are controlled by this prevailing pui-pose. The multitude of varied objects which are presented by the associating power, are entertained or thrust aside by the judging and reasoning intellect, and so an order of their relative value is secured to the objects themselves by the mind's reaction upon them. Even if the mind gives itself up to reverie, it is constantly awake, or read}' to be awake, to the sugges- tions of reason, of use, of beauty, or of rectitude. There is also the rationalizing and sobering presence of the material world, with its obtrusive realities that cannot be mistaken; its permanent attributes, that cannot be changed ; its eternal and superior laws, that can neither be resisted nor set aside. The perpetual presence of this fixed and orderly body of facts and truths, of itself gives reason and order to the fancies which it must in part con- trol and regulate. But in dreams thcro is an absence of judgment, or the judgments are partial, and §174. REPRESENTATION. — THE PHANTASY. 285 the stream of images flows on, under the joint impulses given it by the energies of the mind's previous activity and the force of casual mental or bodily sugges- tions. The material world is withdrawn from the mind's cognizance as an ap- prehended fact ; it is as though it were not, and never had existed. The mind's interpretations of the images of fancy, and even of its bodily sensa- tions, are often false and irrational. First of all, it judges the image-world to be a real world. How this is possible, it is not so easy to explain ; that it is a fact, cannot be doubted. The mind is preoccupied by the action of the representative power. The first impulse, when a picture is presented of an absent reality, is to be- lieve it to be real when there is no ground for the opposite belief. This is wisely provided in the constitution of man, to secure all those actions for which the know- ledge or the thought of any reality is given. The mind, in dreaming, yields to this impulse. The mind, apprehending no real world with which to contrast and judge the imaginary, uses the little force which remains, to infer that the products of its shifting phantasy are themselves realities. They are believed to be real, for they ex- cite all the emotions which such realities are fitted to produce. Delight is experi- enced at ths image of a friend believed to be present, who is perhaps far distant, or long removed by death. Grief is felt at some distressing event which is simply pictured by the phantasy. The mind is not only incapable of discriminating the real from the fantastic, but it interprets the real to be itself a part of its fantastic world. It misinterprets the bodily sensations which it experiences, the sensations of cold or heat, of oppression in the stomach or the heart, and of pain or pleasure in any part of the body. Thus Dr. Gregory relates that, having occasion to apply a bottle of hot water to his feet, he dreamed that he was walking on Mount Etna, and found the heat insupportable. A person suffering from a blister applied to his head, imagined that he was scalped by a party of Indians. A person sleeping in damp sheets, dreamed that he was dragged through a stream. By leaving the knees uncovered, as an experiment, the dream was produced that the person was traveling by night in a diligence. Leaving the back part of the head uncov- ered, the same person dreamed he was present at a religjous ceremony performed in the open air. The smell of a smoky chamber has occasioned frightful dreams of being involved in conflagration. The scent of flowers may transport the dreamer to some enchanted garden, or the tones of music may surround him with the excitements of a well-appointed concert. The exercise of this judgment in respect to the higher relations of thought varies very greatly in the energy of its action, and the perfection of its results. There are many cases in dreams in which single steps, or parts of a series of steps in reasoning, are taken surely and correctly, while these processes are entirely dis- connected with what went before or followed after, as if the rational powers had resumed for a single instant their full energy of function. In other cases, the reasoning may be correct and the data may be false, and yet the falseness of the data may not be perceived. In still other cases, the data may be correctly dis- cerned, and the conclusions correctly derived, so that both premises and reasoning combine to a true and valid conclusion. Even the more difficult feats of the in- vention and arrangement of the materials of an argument, have been successfully performed in dreams. The creations of poetry, even to the selection of rhythmi- cal words, and the composition of sermons and addresses, have been often effected. Difficult problems in mathematics have been solved and remembered ; new and ingenious theories have been devised. Happy expedients of deliverance from 286 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 175. practical difficulties have presented themselves, and brought relief from serious embarrassments. Consciousness is ordinarily but feebly exercised by the soul in its dreams. It is often said to be absent altogether. By consciousness is understood the distinct apprehension of the psychical states, as the states of the individual ego, and not that transient knowledge of them which is essential to any intellectual activity. It is when consciousness acts as judgment, and recognizes the relations of psychical states, that its results remain in the memory. This form or degree of conscious- ness is usually entirely absent, or feebly exercised in dreams. The reason why it is thus feebly put forth, may be the same which accounts for the absence of correct interpretations of the semblances of the material world. For the same reason the estimates of time are so extravagantly and even ludi- crously erroneous. In our dreams, we occupy a year in making a voyage ; we per- form a journey, we witness a long procession, we climb a mountain, and yet the time actually expended is inconceivably short. These erroneous judgments of time are the natural and necessary consequences of mistaking the phantasms of our dreams for real substances and events. We picture to ourselves the incidents of a voyage or a journey. "We turn these pic- tures into realities, and they carry with themselves the estimates of time which would be required if they existed or occurred in fact. The weakening of the con- sciousness of the accompanying psychical states, withdraws any corrective in- fluences which would be furnished by the more distinct apprehension of the time required for the experience of them. The activity of the sensibilities in the dreaming state requires a moment's con- sideration. That we feel in our dreams, or seem to feel, will not be disputed. If we believe we are in danger, we experience terror ; if we dream that we are safe or successful, we rejoice. In some cases, but not usually, the fear and happiness are as intense and as real as when we are awake. In other cases, we feel, but on the review are surprised that we felt no more. Our joy and sorrow are but the pale counterfeits of waking emotions. The intensity of the emotions depends on the strength of our belief and the time of its continuance. Is the will properly active at all during our dreams? That we act, as well as know and feel, is obvious from experience. We seem to resist, to struggle, to speak, to sing, to walk, to run, etc. We strive to attend, to remember, to contrive, to compose, etc. ; in other words, we seem to use our mental powers under some directive force for definite objects. It follows that the conative, or impulsive part of our nature — the capacities which fit for action, are employed in the dreaming state. If these capacities are properly called the will, then we use the will in dreaming. But if we mean by the will, the capacity to direct the impulses by a rational or a moral purpose, it is equally clear that the will is entirely dormant, or, at best, is only occasionally or feebly active. It is and must be inactive, because the appropriate conditions for its exercise are absent. The reason does not pro- pose a distinct end which the mind retains in view. The reflective consciousness neither forms rules nor imposes them. The will cannot act as a rational or moral director when these essential conditions are withdrawn. 8 17"). Somnambulism assumes three forms, which have Certain Somnambulism, - , . . , . . or abnormal features or phenomena in common, but which, in certain respects, sleep, are unlike. These forms are the natural, the morbid, and the artificial. The natural, is that which may occur in ordinary sleep. The morbid, is §175. REPRESENTATION. — THE PHANTASY. 287 an incident or phase of active disease of body or mind. The artificial, is induced by the instrumentality of another person. Each of these forms or manifestations is subdivided into varieties, which pass into one another by scarcely distinguishable shades of difference. Natural somnambulism is distinguished from normal sleep by the special sensi- bility of some — generally some one — of the organs of sense, and by special ac- tivity in the use of some of the organs of bodily motion. The appellation, sleep, walking, is derived from the act of walking in sleep, which for obvious reasons oc- curs more frequently than any other bodily activity. A multitude of examples of natural somnambulism are recorded. One only will serve. "A young nobleman mentioned by Horstius, living in the citadel of Breslau, was observed by his brother, who occupied the same room, to rise in his sleep, wrap himself in his cloak, and escape by a window to the roof of a building. He there tore in pieces a magpie's nest, wrapped the young birds in his cloak, re- turned to his apartment, and went to bed. In the morning he mentioned the cir- cumstances as having occurred in a dream, and could not be persuaded that there had been any thing more than a dream, till he was shown the magpies in his cloak." — Dr. Abercrombie. The activities required in this case, were the sense-perceptions of sight to direct the movements and the active control of the legs and arms. Sometimes the sense of smell, or of hearing, or of taste, are observed to be unusually acute. The use of the voice is often observed. The mental powers are often excited with great energy, continuity, and success. Persons in the somnambulic state will recite passages from authors even in a foreign language, which they could not repeat when awake. Persons who are imperfectly proficient in a language, converse with far greater ease and correctness than they have ever been known to do in the normal condition. Some remarkable compositions have been written, and eloquent discourses have been spoken, which were quite beyond the ordinary capacities of the individuals from whom they came. In the magnetic, or morbid somnambulism, such extraordinary mental power has often been observed as to be ascribed to inspiration from another mind, or to some miraculous deviation from the laws of nature. The ordinary and the magnetic or ecstatic somnambulism, differ from each other, in that the ordinary is preceded and followed by ordinary slumber, while the ecstatic comes upon the patient and leaves him at once, usually in a condition of extreme disease. In their psychological features, the two forms of this affec- tion may be considered as alike, differing only in the greater intensity of some of their manifestations. Both are also exaltations of phenomena which are occa- sionally exhibited in common dreaming and sleep. In all forms of somnambulism, the representative power is the one most promi- nently and conspicuously active. The leading objects of cognition and feeling are the mind's own creations. The man lives and moves, he feels and acts, in and for a dream. Dream-objects are taken to be real existences, and these engross and absorb the chief energies, and direct to many of the actions. But the dream of the somnambulist is far more methodical and continuous than the dream of ordinary sleep. The mind apparently rests upon its objects for a longer time, and gives to them a more fixed attention than it does to the phantasmagoria of the common dream. Certainly it must do both of these, when it adapts speech and 288 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 175. motion to its dream-world, as it does whenever it is prompted to speak, and walk, and lift, and write, at the rate required by its phantasms. Its sense-perceptions do indeed direct the motions and regulate the rate of many of its bodily acts ; but it were a serious error to suppose that what it seems to see, or to hear by the ear, makes up the entire world, or the principal part of the world in which the mind has its being and performs its acts. Besides these sense-objects, there is a multi- tude besides, which make up the background, and the foreground even, of its field of view. In the case of the nobleman cited, in all his movements to and from the nest of magpies, his thoughts were occupied with many phantasms which he con- sidered real, and with reference to which he performed the actions recited. These formed the connecting and the accompanying scenery of the sense-objects which he perceived. The fact that sense-objects were blended with them, served to steady and retard the progress of the dream, and thus to make it regular and me- thodical. The feats which the fancy performs, its powers of memory, its skill in invention, and its resources of creation, are only the natural results of concen- trated attention upon a few, and these connected objects. But this exaltation of the fancy is purchased at the cost of its being limited to but few objects — to single and spontaneous trains of thought running in the courses started and traced by the muscular and vital sensations, or the few sense-objects to which the excited senses are awake. The powers of sense-perception, so far as they are exerted at all, act with sur- prising energy and effect. It is not only a surprising thing that they should act at all in so profound a sleep ; but that the organ should be more sensitive and the mind more acute than in the normal condition, is still more remarkable. But this is often observed in the somnambulist. The objects seen are often seen by the faintest light, and yet they are seen most clearly, because actions requiring acute vision of these objects are performed with precision and success. The touch must be acute, or the somnambulist could not walk so confidently in difficult and dan- gerous places, nor avoid obstacles so dexterously, nor perform so many nice opera- tions, as in skilfully writing and playing on a musical instrument. The senses of smell and hearing are often unusually sensitive to odors and sounds. The question has sometimes been raised, Whether the somnambulist really per- ceives with the senses ? It has been argued that 'he does not, because he also dreams, and because his dreams furnish the greater number of the objects of his knowledge and feeling. It has been inferred that, when he seems to perceive, he only dreams, and that what seem to be the objects of his sense-perceptions, serve, through his interpretations, to form a part of the dreams in which alone he knows and feels. To this it is sufficient to reply that he certainly acts with reference to the real world, and that he really acts — i. e., directs the motions of his legs and arms, and uses and modulates his voice. So far at least as he acts he must have real sensations. • But while his senses are often surprisingly acute, they arc both limited and un- certain in their operation and in their results. He does not sec everything in the apartment in which he is present, but only the table, or chairs, or the paper on which he writes, or the candle which he holds. It is only to those objects which have some relation to his thoughts and actions that he is sensitively alive. The various observations that have been made, warrant the induction that the phantasy stimulates and awakens tho organ of sense, and determines the mind to § 175. REPRESENTATION. — THE PHANTASY. 289 use it with wakeful attention. It is the soul itself that quickens the organ thus made ready by disease or weakness for this extraordinary activity, to that momen- tary excitement which is required to fasten the mind to its monitions. This extraordinary exaltation of single senses is not without its analogy in the wakeful and normal conditions of the soul. The vision of the sailor, the lace- maker, the horo'ogist, the hearing of the sentinel and the hunter, the touch of the blind, the machinist, and the musician, seem to the stranger to be something al- most supernatural. The still higher exaltation of these sense-powers, in the case of the somnambulist, is on the same ascending line with these natural variations. It is only extraordinary in degree. Wo come next to a subject still more interesting, and, at first sight, more puz- zling, viz., the apparent increased excitement of intellectual power as manifested in achievements performed by the somnambulist, particularly when in the mesmeric or ecstatic condition. The first which we shall consider is the claim for him of the ability to perceive material qualities and objects without the medium of the organs of sense. For example : it is asserted that he can see near objects through the thickest bandage, and with the back of the head; that he can hear by the epigastrium, etc., etc. In respect to the first claim, that near objects can be seen or heard independently of the ear and the eye, we need only observe that, provided many of the stories are neither false nor exaggerated, not one of them proves that the mind can have sense-perceptions independently of the nervous organism. If the story be re- ceived as true, that the person has seen (not remembered nor conjectured) through an interposed bandage or by the back of the head, it would still be true that the optic nerve and the retina might be so morbidly sensitive as to be affected by the light, even if the eyelids were closed or thickly covered. No fact is more clearly established than that, within certain limits, one part of the sensorium, or portion of a single system of nerves, can, under extraordinary excitement, perform the functions of another. The second claim is of a power to see distant objects which no sense-power can reach, as objects immured in total darkness behind thick and solid walls. Such a power, or its exercise, can be explained by no known powers or laws of nature. There is nothing analogous to its possession or its exercise, in any thing which we know in the normal actings of the soul. Whatever the poWer may be which acts in this way, it is not vision. The person does not see the object, but if he discerns any thing, it is a phantasm, an image, or series of images which are purely mental. If there be any thing which he apprehends, it is a mental object, the production of his own soul. It exists while he beholds it, within and for his soul alone. If the object or scene has never been the object of his personal inspection, the pictures which he forms of it must be taken from materials within his own ob- servation, or imparted by description. If it be the city of Pekin, or the Himalaya mountains, the picture is composed either of fragments of what he has seen of New York or Boston, of London or Paris, of the mountains of America, or Europe, or from some drawing or painting of the cities or mountains themselves. The third claim for the soul, of a power to understand its own bodily disorders, as to their seat or cure, may be explained in part by the fact that the sufferer in the somnambulic state is far more keenly alive than when awake, to his own bodily sensations. If an organ is diseased, the disease will often be manifest by means of sensations which are prominent and unmistakable in the soul's experi- 13 290 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 175. ence. These are the data for its interpretations or inferences. The disease may- have been an object of intense anxiety and earnest inquiry. «The person affected may have more or less knowledge of the anatomical structure and of the func- tions of many of the organs. It will always be found to be true, in such cases, that the insight of the somnambulist in respect to the names of the organs and their functions, does not go beyond what he has learned by conversation or read- ing. Let him be ever so gifted, he will not learn the nature or the name of a single organ, or its office, or a single remedy, which has not been the subject of thought in wakefulness and health. If this is so, the case is reduced to extra- ordinary sagacity exercised upon data or knowledge communicated or impressed in an extraordinary manner. Fourth, the exaltation of the higher intellect to the capacity to perform some very extraordinary achievements, remains to be considered. This is much more remarkable in the morbid than in the natural somnambulism. The somnambulist sometimes displays great acuteness of judgment. He sees resemblances and differ- ences which had not occurred to him in his waking states, and which astonish lookers-on. He is quick in repartee ; he solves difficult problems ; he composes and speaks with method and effect ; he reasons acutely ; he interprets character with rare subtlety ; he understands passing events with unusual insight ; he pre- dicts those which are to come by skilful forecast. How are all these phenomena to be explained ? We reply : By the excitement of the intellect from an intense interest in the subject-matter with which it is occupied, the concentration of the attention for a long time upon a few objects only and a few of their relations, and the pre- vious familiarity of the mind with these objects and relations. That the mind occasionally acts with energy when in the dream-state, even in its highest func- tions, has already been noticed. That, when it thinks and reasons in somnam- bulism, it is animated by strong excitement arising from a strong interest in the subject-matter, is obvious to all, and will not be questioned. Next, the attention is concentrated upon objects for a sufficient length of time to secure entire familiarity with them and their relations. The attention of the somnambulist is limited, as we have seen, to but few sense-objects. To all other objects except those which excite this or that sense, it is deaf and blind. Last of all, his sense-objects and his dream-objects are ordinarily very familiar. They have previously been the frequent object of thought and speculation. The questions for which the person finds new answers, the problems for which he devises new solutions, the events or characters upon which he casts a new light, are not for the first time before his mind. The operations of his in- tellect are also all in the line of his previous efforts and training. The som- nambulist does not for the first time appear as a mathematician, poet, orator, politician, or divine ; nor does he display activities which have not been in their quality and kind, if not in degree, familiar to his use. The gift of divination, or prophecy, which is claimed for the somnambulist, when- ever it deserves consideration, is explained in part by the extraordinary sagacity which is developed in respect to subjects that are interesting and familiar to tho mind. The somnambulist forecasts or prophesies, by reasoning upon the evidenco before him. His attention being fixed and his interest being aroused, he applies his intellectual force to tho subjects before him, and shows the same sagacity in §175. REPRESENTATION. — THE PHANTASY. 291 foreseeing future results that he exhibits in interpreting events that are present, by the causes, the laws, and principles that are concerned in bringing them to pass. One or two other features common to all the varieties of somnambulism remain to be noticed. First, the somnambulist, when he wakes, usually, though not invariably, forgets his actions, perceptions, and thoughts during sleep. His dream, with all that it involves, is to him an empty blank. To many, this seems incredible ; to others, it is an insoluble mystery. That it is not incredible, is established by the amount of decisive evidence which is adduced of its actual occurrence. That it is not in- explicable, appears from analogous phenomena in dream-life, as well as from the dissimilarity of the conditions of mental activity in the waking and the somnam- bulic state. The dreams of the profoundest sleep are rarely remembered, for the reason that the bodily condition, with ail the sensations which it involves, is, in many respects, very unlike that which attends our lighter slumbers and our waking states. The sensations which accompany these varying conditions, as has been shown, are an essential element in our mental experiences. If the phantasy is active, they are the essential conditions of its activity in any determinate direc- tion. For this reason, these bodily sensations direct the course and furnish the occasions for many of our dreams. But in somnambulism these sensations are more controlling and more unique than in any other dreaming or in any other sleep. "Whatever else there may be which awakens and directs the phantasy is, if possible, still more unlike any other experiences of wakefulness or sleep. If the transition from ordinary sleep and ordinary dreams to wakefulness is often so ab- rupt and complete as to involve entire oblivion of all which we have thought, or felt, or done, it is less surprising that, when we awake from the sleep of som- nambulism, whether the transition be sudden or gradual, it is so complete that the present presents few or no relations to the past. These considerations both explain and confirm the second fact that has some- times been observed, viz. : that the somnambulist, when he passes into a suc- ceeding condition of abnormal activity, remembers the experiences, and, as it were, remembers the self of similar previous states. How this should be possible, most clearly appears from the principles already laid down: The objects of thought and memory, the motives and directors of action which were present in the previous condition, return to him a second time, and they bring with them their attendant experiences. When the soul passes a second time into the sur- roundings of his abnormal being, they are no longer strange, but he recognizes them as familiar, and, taking up new threads of memory, he recalls the pre- ceding dream. Some remarkable instances are recorded of alternating states, in each of which the acquisitions, the capacities, and the employments were unlike those in the other, and yet, as the similar states recurred at intervals, they were connected by continuity of memory. The artificial somnambulism is peculiar, in that it is induced by the interven- tion of another person, who, by means of passes or other appliances, brings the subject into a sleep and dream, the processes and objects of which he directs, and from which he awakes him at his own will. Hence it is called artificial, as effected by another, in distinction from the natural, which is induced by ordi- nary sleep, and the morbid, which is the incident of active disease. It is also 292 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 175. called the magnetic sleep. It originally received this appellation, because it was supposed to be produced by a magnetic influence, generated by or attendant upon all the animal functions. There is still another condition called hypnotism, or the hypnotic state, which may be properly called the artificial sleep as distinguished from the artificial somnambulism — i. e., the artificial dream. It is like somnambulism, as pro- duced by the agency of another, and as being under the control of the pro- ducing agent. The connection of the mind of the operator with the mind and the actions of the subject, is not so manifest, or is not always carried so far as is claimed for artificial somnambulism. It is however so like it in every essential feature, as to deserve to be considered as at least a lower degree of its exercise. For the purposes which we have in view, hypnotism and artificial somnam- bulism or mesmerism, may be considered as one. The states so designated have the following features : Artificial sleep; entire or total insensibility of some of the sense-organs; an unnatural excitement and acuteness of others; the capacity to maintain some relation with the operator, so that the sleep and the dreams of the subject are under his exclusive direction and control. All these phenomena, with one apparent exception, are analogous to those of the forms of somnam- bulism already considered. The production of the sleep is the result of an ex- citement of some of the sense-organs or parts of the nervous system, initiated by exciting and fixing the attention of a susceptible patient, by the aid of a strong will and the energetic activity of the operator. The physical and imme- diate cause of the sleep is common to all the cases. It is the congestion of the brain. The occasions or causes of the congestion are diverse. In natural somnambulism, it is an incident of ordinary sleep in a person of sensitive organism. In morbid somnambulism, it is an attendant of active nervous disease. In the artificial, the congestion is the result of the attention of the patient leading to excessive physical excitement of some part of the sen- sorium. In artificial somnambulism, the feature which is at once the most dis- tinctive and the most difficult to explain is the control of one mind by an- other. While the patient is inaccessible to communications from every other person, he is open both to communications and impressions from the operator. Not only is he open to communications from him, but he is also in a considerable degree subject to his control. If, however, we consider the phenomena of natural somnambulism, or even those of the common dream, we shall find some striking points of resemblance. In both these conditions, great insensibility of certain powers is conjoined with extreme sensitiveness of others. The dreamer and the somnambulist are dead in some of their senses, and comparatively alert and active in others. The phantasy of both is active. To ordinary persons any approach into their inner life is en- tirely precluded. But to the observer who understands the habits, or can inter- pret the dream of another, it is not difficult to gain the attention, to institute and maintain conversation, to effect a communication with the thoughts, to give posi- tive direction and control to the thoughts, and, through the thoughts, to the feel- ings. No feature of a person in this condition is so striking as tho entire and helpless dependence of some of his powers on other persons for stimulus and guid- ance, and tho passiveness with which both the senses and tho fancy respond to their suggestions, and arc controlled by their direction. §176. REPRESENTATION. — THE PHANTASY. 293 In the artificial somnambulism these conditions are intensified. The natural equilibrium is more effectually disturbed than in the state just described. The insensibility of some of the powers, and the sensitiveness of others, are height- ened. This condition is induced by processes that bring the operator prominently before the attention of the subject, and connect him with the trains of thought which his phantasy pursues. The subject falls asleep with his eye fixed upon the operator, by obeying directions which fell from his lips, and following motions and signs which engrossed his own attention. When the sleep is effected, it is in its nature but partial. A portion only of his powers are awake, and, by concession, are morbidly and sensitively alive to their appropriate impressions. It is not unnatural, rather it is most natural and reasonable, to expect that these powers so sensitive would respond to the voice and even to the tones of the one person to whom the patient had passively surrendered in the beginning of the process; that indications which escape the notice of ordinary observers, should bo intelligible and patent for him, and that, when these indications are conveyed they should control all his movements of thought and feeling. It is credible that the pictures before the fancy of the operator should be awakened in his own, and that his positive assertion should not only be taken as proof of their real existence, but should cause the subject to believe that his own senses perceive them, so that he should think he sees a mountain, a house, brilliant colors, smoke, flame, etc., etc., at the will of the operator who dominates over his fancy. £ 176. Our discussion of the phantasy would not be complete, if we omitted to notice the phenomena of hallucinations, and Hallucinations, r ' apparitions, etc. spectral apparitions or illusions. A distinction should be made between the proper images of the phantasy, when mistaken for or believed to be realities, as by the dreamer and the somnambulist, and the actual vision of images in the formation of which the senses cooperate, such as occur to persons in a morbid condition when they are broadly awake, as also to those attacked by fever, or to such as suffer from the effects of certain narcotics or intoxicating drugs. One of the most remarkable cases of continued exposure to such visita- tions, is that recorded of himself by the celebrated Nicolai of Berlin in the Transactions of the Royal Society of Berlin, for 1799. The case of Nicolai is by no means solitary. There are not a few persons of sensitive organization who occasionally see distinct images, visions, and phantasms of real objects, which have distinct form, distinguishable color, and a certain permanent endurance like objects actually existing. These phantasms, moreover, assume relations of place and motion to real objects. They are seated in chairs, they stand by the bedside, they look through the window, and have the dimensions which are suitable to their place and their distance from tho observer. If the judgment of the subject of them is clear, and his self-com- mand complete, he knows they are not real objects, even though he cannot remove them. (Cf. Hallucinations, or the Rational History of Apparitions, Visions, etc., etc., by A. Brierre de Boismont, Phil. 1853.) Tbese phantasms are much more frequent in transient delirium from fever, or permanent insanity. They are the almost invariable result of a variety of drugs, as opium, hasheesh [Cannabis Indica), and stramonium. They are the fearful attendants of that irregularity of nervous action which is the consequence of excess in the use of intoxicating liquors. It is noticeable that the excitement occasioned by each of these drugs, as also that delirium tremens is 294 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 177. attended by phantasms of its own. These phantasms are not confined to vision alone. The other senses have their appropriate phantasms ; the ear has sounds, the touch various feelings, and the nostrils distinguishable odors. None of these, however, are as definite, or as permanent, or as clearly distin- guishable as the phantasms of vision. It is important to distinguish these phantasms or apparitions from the images of the phantasy proper. Unless we do, we cannot clearly understand or interpret the phenomena of delirium, and certain other forms of mental aberration. Two agencies concur in their production — the action of the phantasy by means of the spiritual image, and that of the sense-organ which is appropriately concerned. It has already been observed, that when even a sense-object is imaged, especially if it be vividly and continuously pictured by the phantasy, as a sound or sight, the mind's attention to it tends to awaken a sympathetic activity of the sense-organ by which the object was ori- ginally perceived. Again, in the sense-organism psychologically considered, there is a tendency to be excited or impressed a second time without a sense-object, in a manner similar to that which the presence of the object originally occasioned. Sometimes, in conditions of the system not known to be abnormal, this excitement goes so far as to produce in the mind all the effects of transient sense-perception. As a con- sequence, the mind has actual percepts without material objects, especially on waking from sleep. The mind sees colored spectra, and hears sounds when there are no material things or objects to be seen or heard. These occasional phe- nomena clearly establish the truth that the sense-organism, without the stimulus of an object, can be brought into a condition nearly allied to that to which it is excited by that object. Whether the excitement is mental or physical, is of little import, provided the excitement is furnished. Let, now, the sense-organism bo in a condition of morbid sensibility, and let the phantasy be also morbidly aroused, and it is not unnatural that phantasms should take material forms or bo invested with material qualities. But let the judgment itself be disturbed by more serious disarrangements of the nervous system ; and tho raving madness which sees nothing but phantasms where it ought to see realities, or which in- vests the real objects of sense with fantastic shapes and attributes, are fully ex- plained (cf. H 78, 143, 150). £ 177. It is no part of our duty to give a scientific theory of in- Insanity. sanity. We have only attempted to explain the part which the phantasy has in the mental operations, under this condition of ir- regular psychical activity. We ought also to add, that it is by no means uni- versally the case that the insane are haunted with phantasms. It often happens that insanity is the result of mere mental confusion or distraction, such as may result from the excessive rapidity or the excessive preponderance of certain or- ganic or vital sense-perceptions. These may so distract or preoccupy the atten- tion, as to preclude the possibility of a cool judgment or a controlled activity in respect to any matter whatever. In such cases, tho phantasy, as well as tho per- ceptions, are either so hurried and flighty, or so fixed and recurring, that the ac- tivities of memory, comparison, and judgment are all untrustworthy. Or, again, the mind, and not the body, under some overmastering passion, has given to the phantasy such complete control over tho other powers, as to disturb the equili- brium of spiritual activity. In these cases tho phenomena are purely mental. § 178. REPRESENTATION. — THE IMAGINATION. 295 The sense-perceptions are correctly made. The vision is disturbed by no spectrum. There are no special disturbances of the bodily sensations. But the mind is oc- cupied with inferences incorrectly derived from its past experiences or its present condition. It is haunted with depressing images, or gloomy forebodings. Its distracted phantasy is so overpowered as to set at naught the testimony of the senses, the asseverations of trusted friends, the conclusions of its own better judg- ment, the principles, the faith, and the hopes which had been the soul's support and guide. CHAPTER VI. REPRESENTATION. — (3.) THE IMAGINATION OR CREATIVE POWER. From the phantasij, the most passive form and exercise of representation, we proceed to the imagination, its most active and elevated energy. § 178. In treating of the creative imagination, we shall first consider the general characteristics, condi- materials com- tions, and laws, which are common to this power in imagination. all its phases and degrees of activity, and then the special forms in which it is manifested. Our first duty is, to consider the conditions, laws, and charac- teristics which are common to the creative imagination. "We ask, first of all, what are the materials which are furnished to this power from nature and experience, and which it is forced to make use of in all its creations? In answer to this general question, we would say : — 1. Space and time are always employed in these processes, and always appear in their products. The objects that are conceived, whether by the poet, the dramatist, or the inventor, as forming the scenes in which their personages, materials, or machinery are introduced, or within which they are conceived, are invariably subjected to the laws and relations of space. The acts and events which are described or imagined, all take place under the conditions of time. They precede and follow one another. They are either present, past, or future. The world of the imagi- 296 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 179. nation is always a world of imagined space and imagined time, as the world of reality is a world of real space and real time. 2. The necessary and universal thought-conceptions, and re- lations under which we cognize real beings, are always supposed and employed. Every being and thing which we imagine, we imagine more or less distinctly, as substance with attributes, as cause and effect under proper conditions, and as means and ends. It is not intended that the imagination pictures those in their abstract form. They cannot be imaged, any more than they can be perceived by sense or consciousness. But as concrete objects can be perceived only under these relations, so when they are imaged, they can and must be imaged as connected by means of them. 3. The imagination is limited to the material qualities which nature furnishes. We cannot create or conceive of new colors by any exertion of creative energy. Hume and Tetens both suggest, that if the imagination were furnished with the colors blue and yellow, it could, by combining the two, image the color green, without ever having seen it. The mistake is twofold. The eye does not see the blue and yellow in the green, but the product which results from the combination of the two. The imagination cannot go beyond what the bodily eye furnishes. In a similar way, the imagination is limited with respect to all the simple qualities of sense, to tastes, and sounds, and odors, and tactual feels. 4. In like manner, the imagination is limited to the spiritual phenomena and processes which consciousness reveals, as well as to the powers which these processes suppose. What it is to know, and feel, and will, we know by the varieties of our own experience ; and what a being is who can exert these activities, we are taught by consciousness. In this way we learn what are the acts, and products, and capacities of spirit. The power of § 179. We inquire, second, What new products tion tTcreate can be evolved and created out of these materials by new products. ^ j mag i nat i on proper ? Tff e follow the order of the topics already adopted. (1.) In respect to space and time, though we cannot imagine objects to exist nor events to occur out of relation to each or to §179. REPRESENTATION. — THE IMAGINATION. 297 both, yet we can imagine them to bear relations to each, to which there is no type of reality. The imagination can make changes in the size of objects. The types of animals actually existing, as of the horse, the man, the elephant, and the mouse, lie within certain extremes, the greatest and least of their kind ever known. The imagination scorns these limits, and it can give us horses of every size, from the ponies of Queen Mab up to steeds large enough for the uses of a giant. It can create men smaller than Lilliputians, and larger than the contrasted Brobdignags. It can make elephants smaller than mice, and mice larger than elephants. Again, the position or situation of objects is determined by the character of their material and the laws of nature. Mountains hold a certain relation to vallies, streams to meadows, groves to lawns, houses to gardens, cities to harbors, roads, and rivers ; "so that, where we find the one, we expect to find the other. But the imagination acknowledges none of these relations or laws. While it must imagine all these objects as spatial, it can place them as it will in space. It can plant a garden in a desert a thousand leagues from a dwelling of man. It can build and people a city, without harbor, river, or road. There are fixed forms of objects in nature, as the drooping elm, the aspiring pine, the umbrageous beech, the massive and gnarled oak. In rock and mountain, certain types are ever re- curring. The same is true of the form of the horse, the deer, the dog, and of man himself. But the imagination can draw more graceful lines than nature has ever shaped, the material with which she works being more intractable, and the action of staining and decomposing elements being inevitable. Following her idealizing images, art has given us the Egyptian tomb and pyramid, the Chinese pagoda, the Grecian temple, and the Gothic cathedral, none of which are copied from nature, though all have been suggested by her forms. In one aspect they surpass nature, for their lines are more con- summately drawn, and their forms are moulded more perfectly. We even measure nature by what art has done, and commend her by epithets taken from art. We say of the stem of the pine or the elm, It shoots up like a pillar. We call the forest a " pillared shade." We say of a man, He stands like a statue ; 13* 298 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §179. or, He is an Apollo, for graceful strength ; She is a Venus, for beauty. In time, also, the imagination has boundless range. It must represent all actions and events, as either now, before, or after, yet it can do as it pleases as to which shall be now, before or after. Nature, in respect to time relations, acts after its own laws and within its own limits. The imagination can override them all, and accordingly she can make Puck "put a girdle roundabout the earth in forty minutes," and Uriel "glide on a sunbeam," " swift as a shooting star." There are also special creations which the imagination forms and coDstructs, of which space and time are assumed as the only required conditions. Let all material existences be conceived to cease to be, leaving only an empty void within any limits which may be supposed, and in that void which is feigned, the imagi- nation can construct the surface with its ever-varied outlines, and the solid of every conceivable form. These are purely mental constructions, and exist only for the mind and by the mind which forms them. Their form may be suggested by certain material things with which we are conversant. But the line, the surface, and the solid constructed by the mind, are far more perfectly drawn and moulded than any that nature has ever furnished in material objects, or than art has imitated with material instruments. The imagination can also sweep all actual events and pheno- mena from the line of time, and then plant along its course the shadows of events that shall only symbolize or represent its suc- cessive intervals or instants. It can also group and combine these as it will. Real events, as they precede and follow one another, may incite to these acts of pure construction ; but the acts and the products which they excite and suggest are to be referred to the creative energy of the imagination. What relations these hold to the distinctions of number, will be discussed in the proper place (§ 280). (2.) In the world of matter, the imagination can create no new material, but it can divide and combine the parts of the material things with which it is familiar, so as to form new existences. The head and trunk of a man it can fit to the shoulders and body of a horse. It can form a mermaid — part woman, part § 179. REPRESENTATION. — THE IMAGINATION. 299 fish. It can provide men, women, and children with wings, and turn them into angels and cherubs. It can represent any animal with a human head. It can add to the head of a man the ears of an ass, and give to another the mouth and nose of a puppy. It can connect the part or the whole of any plant with the part or the whole of any animal, making a cabbage to sprout from the hump of a camel, or a rose-branch to nod from the head of a horse, as we see delineated in some quaint pictures and engrav- ings. It can recombine and rearrange the parts of inorganic things as it will, making a rock to be balanced upon a roof-ridge, and a bridge to stand dry in a desert. There is no limit to the grotesque and fantastic combinations which can be made with the parts and the wholes of material objects. Though the ima- gination cannot invent a single new sensible or material quality, it can connect such qualities as nature has never combined, making flaming red dogs, bright yellow oxen, woolly horses, talk- ing mules, musical jackasses, golden mountains, rivers of wine, ponds of beer, and fountains of hot coffee. (3.) In respect to spiritual beings, the imagination is limited by similar, constraints and invested with a similar freedom. A spirit has no visible or extended parts ; therefore, as a spirit, it cannot be divided and recombined ; but a spirit may be connected with any kind or form of matter, may be imprisoned in trees, may animate a cloud, may dwell in an animal form, or " leap like Minerva from the head of Jupiter !" Not a single new spiritual capacity can be invented or ima- gined. The loftiest and the purest of spirit-creations, simply feel, desire, and will. The humblest and the most degraded can do no less. We cannot invest the highest archangel with any endowment other than these. We canuot refuse to the lowliest animal some poor analoga to some of these functions. In respect to the limitations and the conditions of the exercise of the intellect, the imagination has the widest range of creative power. It can conceive the intellect of a God that creates all that it discerns, and discerns whatever it creates, without condi- tion or process, by an all-penetrating and all-comprehending in- tuition. It can also imagine the intellect of an idiot, struggling to free itself from the gross obstructions of a diseased body, and fixing its painful attention in the first beginnings of knowledge. 300 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 179. In respect of feeling, it can, on the one hand, imagine pure love glowing with the energy of seraphic fervor, or simple hatred raging with fiendish malignity ; and, on the other, the most im- perfect and feeblest actings of either. There is no limit to the variety of spiritual beings with which the imaginary world can be peopled, nor to the variety of the conditions of being and acting to which they can be subjected. The graceful Titania, with her frolicsome and mischief-making fairies ; the hideous Caliban, in body and spirit the very contrast of the wonderful Miranda ; Satan and Abdiel ; are examples of the variety of spiritual creations which the imagination can con- struct out of its limited materials. (4.) We have seen that the imagination cannot step without the charmed circle of thought-conceptions and relations. Some of the examples of what it can do within that circle by newly conjoining attributes of material and spiritual beings, have already been given. It cannot conceive of beings, except as substances and attributes, but it can join any attribute, of any intensity and compass, to any substance. It cannot break them from that connection which binds all real beings and events as causes and effects ; but it can make any existence to serve as the cause of any other as its effect, and thus can reverse the whole order of actual being by its capricious and fantastic combina- tions ; or it can enlarge the bounds of science by its happy sug- gestions of undiscovered powers and laws, and the appliances of art by applications, before unimagined, of familiar agencies to new results. All things in the world of fancy must be conceived as fitted for some end, but the adaptations may be imagined as wildly as the caprices of a madman's dream, or as wisely as the perfect fitness which we believe has been arranged by the all- wise God. With this view before us of the materials to which the imagi- nation is limited, and of the products into which it transforms them, we are prepared to inquire, third, How does the imagina- tion effect these changes ; or what is the precise work which the imagination performs in its creative function ? We observe, in answer to these inquiries, There are three different methods in which its creative power is shown. (1.) The imagination can re- combine and arrange the constituents of nature in new forms § 181. REPRESENTATION. — THE IMAGINATION. 301 and products. (2.) It can idealize and apply the relations of ob- jects to extension and time. (3.) It can form and employ an ideal standard for the intensity and the direction of the activity of natural or spiritual agents, and for the material objects and acts which symbolize them. We will consider these acts in their order. § 180. The examples already cited both prove and illustrate the fact, that the imagination very largely JJ| C anra > r"in| acts in the way of reuniting and rearranging the [ J ® a ce ina \ f ion ^ e materials furnished to experience, and they also sug- gest the limitations under which this function can be employed. It is obvious, also, that the so-called parts of objects, and objects treated as parts, are as minute and numerous as any species of analysis can separate. There are sense-parts and sense-wholes, representative-parts and representative-wholes, and thought-parts and thought-wholes. A whole, as a building or tree, may be a part of the landscape with which it is connected ; while it is still a whole with respect to its doors, windows, roof, etc., and whatever else makes it quan- titatively complete. This is an example of sense-wholes and sense-parts. Again, the several properties or relations of the dwelling or the tree, its form, dimensions, color, smell, etc., are thought-parts, which can be combined into new wholes, by taking away and adding, as we have already seen. If these new wholes are individual, they are formed from representation ; if they are generalized, they are the work of thought proper, or logical wholes in the larger sense of the word. The synthesis of the creative imagination reaches as far and is applied as widely as the analysis of sense aud thought can go. The imagination may reunite into varying products all that perception and conscious- ness separate or distinguish, and under every one of the rela- tions in which they apprehend their objects. These relations are its only limits and laws. § 181. We have already referred to the fact, that Tae idealiza . the imagination, in every work of art, goes beyond, f^J^*^ 1 *" and outdoes the perfection and refinement of nature. and tim ® in 1 art, and ma- The forms which sculnture moulds, and which draw- thematicai x * science. ing outlines, are, as we have seen, more perfect than any winch nature produces ; certainly, they are more perfect than 302 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §181. any which the senses can discern, or which nature can furnish as models. These constructions cannot be explained by any pro- cess of analysis, or selection of the parts of real objects, whether this analysis is called mental, or is performed by sensible instru- ments. The lines and shapes of grace which have been copied in marble or drawn upon canvas, in respect to delicacy of tran- sition and ease of movement, far surpass those of any living- being or actually existing thing. They are suggested by, but not copied from, any such beings or things. The story that the Grecian painter assembled from every quarter the most celebrated beauties, that he might borrow some charm from each, and combine all together in a perfect work, could never have been true. While it is true that nature, in some respects, far outstrips and surpasses what art can do, it is true, on the other, that the imagination, in her province, can go far beyond the attainments of nature. As we have already said, we even measure nature by some of the achievements of art. We ap- ply the ideals of the imagination still more frequently to try and to test what spiritual achievement furnishes. Those peculiar products which are employed in mathematical science, and which are known as geometrical and numerical quantities, cannot be made by any process of separation or com- bination of the parts of material objects. In matter there are no points, lines, surfaces, solids, and spheres, such as geometry conceives and reasons of. The unequal faces of a material cube, the rough edges formed by two adjacent faces of a solid, the obtuse corners in which three adjacent faces terminate, are none of them these objects of thought, nor are they wholes from which these can be evolved or separated as elements or consti- tuting parts. The line is not part of an edge, nor is the surface a part of the material face. If they were parts which could be separated by actual sense-perception from a whole, they must exist in that whole, or be distinguished as one of its material constituents. If it be said that these are distinguished and separated in the mind, that the process of analysis or abstraction is mental, it is still true that the mind can only separate what it first discerns. These objects cannot be discerned by bodily sense, nor can they be represented by simple imagination. They must be created § 182. REPRESENTATION. — THE IMAGINATION. 303 by the mind, for the mind to behold, when the mind beholds them. It may be properly said to construct or to create them — first, in individual examples and applications, and then by rapid and easy generalizations. An individual point, line, surface, triangle, solid, sphere, is first constructed by the mind in relation to and by suggestion of a rude material occasion, and the pro- duct is then generalized by the ordinary processes and conceived as resembling every similar creation, so that whatever is true of the one, is readily affirmed of all. What is true of geometrical, is true also of numerical quantity. Numbers symbolize the relations of objects contem- plated in a series, as constituting a whole, divisible into unit parts. In order to conceive of number, the mind must first view objects in all these relations. But in nature, so far as the senses can know, there are no equal parts constituting divisible wholes. Whether the ultimate molecules or atoms of matter are or are not equal, none such are discerned by the senses. The successive mental states which consciousness observes and by which it first apprehends and measures the successive portions of time, are none of them observed in actual experience to be equally long or short. All these must be idealized in the imagination before they are separated by its analysis and combined in its creations. We proceed to § 182. The spiritual acts and states of which we 01 .3. Theforma- are conscious, differ from one another m respect to tion of an ideal , t'l-i • • i standard for the direction which they take — i. e., in respect to the psychical acts objects on which they terminate, and hence to the quality of the affections — as well as in respect to the energy or intensity with which they are performed. But none ever reach a perfection in either respect which is so complete as can be con- ceived. Whatever or however we know, feel, or choose ; we can conceive it possible to surpass what we actually do or expe- rience. A perfect standard is created by the imagination. It cannot be derived from the parts which we observe in ourselves or others, because the parts are no more perfect than are the wholes. Consequently, whenever we perceive dimly and believe that we might perceive more clearly, or whenever we would feel warmly or purely, or choose rightly, and our feel- ings or choices do not satisfy our tastes or our conscience, 304 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 182. we then create for ourselves an ideal standard of spiritual achievement. In respect, also, to the expression of these ideals in material forms, the imagination creates and applies the ideals which it always aims but always fails to reach. Whether the medium of expression be language — the language of gestures, of looks, of tones, or of articulate speech — or whether it be lines, or color, or solid form, as employed by the draughtsman, the painter, or the sculptor, it is all the same. The use which we can make of the medium is never so perfect as our ideal of what is possible. As we have noticed already, every such medium, physically re-" garded, falls short of the psychical perfection which we can conceive — i. e., create — in the mind. When this medium or material is required, not only to set forth an idea of simple out- line, form, or color, but to represent another ideal of thought, feeling, and passion, then it is found to be doubly true that the ideals which the mind can frame, rise far above the reality which the voice or hand can execute. Hence it is that the ideal excellence of the poet, the orator, the actor, the musician, and the artist, is ever higher than his achievements — that the one flees before the other like its shadow, and can never be overtaken. The ideals of science and of art, of achievement and of duty, are the products of that form of psychical activity which is properly called the creative imagination. It is imaginative, because the representative or imaging power is conspicuously prominent in its functions. It is creative, because there is no counterpart in nature from which its objects and products are literally transcribed or copied. But this is not all. The reason and the feelings are conspicuous, aud both rational and emotional relations are recognized and controlling. The creative function is rendered possible by the union of the thinking power with the imaging power ; the joint action of both resulting in those ideal products which address the intellectual and emotional nature. The ideals of the mathematical imagination are only possible when the imagination has been disciplined by thought. One chalk or pencil line is narrower than another, one of the lami- nse of mica is thinner than another. As we divide these lines and cleave off these lamina?, we seem to approximate to the ideal line and the ideal surface, simply because the senses and the § 182. REPRESENTATION. — THE IMAGINATION. 305 imagination are less distracted and occupied with sense or imaged properties. The imagination selects, therefore, the line or sur- face whose thickness is least obvious to the senses, to suggest or represent the sole relation to space with which the intellect is for the moment concerned ; or, which is even more satisfactory, it takes for a point an object whose dimensions are the smallest dis- cernible to the senses or picturable to the imagination, and con- siders it simply as moved or movable directly to another point like itself, and thus constructs in the imagination the mathemati- cal line. That is, it begins with an object or an image as far removed from sense as possible, and uses it so as to suggest the various relations which extended matter holds to space ; or, to speak more exactly, to other matter extended in space. By the imagined motion of this line, it proceeds in a similar way to construct the surface, etc., etc. The so-called approximation of the actual to the ideal line and surface, consists in the more facile suggestion of the relations in question by means of one reality rather than by another. The ideal of the artist depends on the relations of outline, form, color, etc., etc.,- to aesthetic pleasure; whatever may be its sources and kinds. He brings the line, the model, or the picture, as nearly as his materials and skill will allow, to a condition in which there shall be no drawbacks to the pleasurable effect which is sought for. As long as a single distracting or inconsistent feature or property is prominent, so long is his ideal unreached. As this will always be the case from defect of materials or defect of skill, so long will it be true that he can never make his work absolutely perfect, and that his ideal of what he imagines might be possible, will never be reached. The ideal of the inventor is some agent, or combination of agencies, that are freed from the limitations which pertain to the ordinary machines or instruments. These he illustrates to him- self by fondly and sometimes obstinately conceiving of his model only in those relations of adaptation and capacity which he knows it to possess, and overlooking or denying other limitations to which it is liable. The ideals of psychical and moral attainment suffer under limi- tations of another sort. We select the most satisfying example of the actual which we can find, and fixing our attention upon 306 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 182. those of its relations which we desire to contemplate, and with- drawing it from all defects and limitations, we make the example an ideal of the psychical power or the moral excellence which we wish exclusively to contemplate. If the ideal excellence is contemplated as an attainable end of our being, or is enforced by the authority of conscience or the will of the Supreme, then that which was a conceivable ideal is viewed in still other relations. It is accepted as possible : though an ideal of the imagination, it is enforced as reasonable and obli- gatory. The result of this analysis is but another illustration of the. interdependence of all the powers upon one another, and espe- cially of the higher functions of the imagination upon thought and reason. It enforces and explains the near affinity of the imaging with the thought-power. It also indicates the advan- tage which language and music may have over painting and sculpture in expressing and suggesting what color and form cannot convey. These truths also enable us to understand and explain how it happens that all ideas, however refined and elevated, are in some sense founded upon and related to the actual experience of each individual. A person born and nurtured upon a plain, who had never seen a hill or a mountain, can scarcely imagine the charm to the eye and the excitement to the mind which such scenery imparts. One who has never been upon the sea, can neither picture to himself nor to others the wild sublimity of an ocean tempest. The oriental, basking in the heat of a tropical sun, and always surrounded by the fruits, the foliage, and the flowers that such a sun alone can nourish, cannot form an ideal picture of an arctic winter. Nor can the Scandinavian, out of the pale sunlight of his brightest days, or the most luxuriant vegetation of his starveling summer, construct an adequate representation of the exuberant life, and the glowing intensity of a tropical landscape. The actual life of every painter and every poet, in the mate- rials which it furnishes, must largely determine the direction and characteristics of his imaginative power. From the writings of Dante, of Milton, of Scott, and of Bunyan, as well as from the pictures of Raphael and Murillo, of Gainsborough and Wilkie, § 183. REPRESENTATION. — THE IMAGINATION. 307 one can easily conclude as to the place of their birth, the kind of education which they received from the books and men and scenery with which they were conversant. § 183. It follows that the imagination is capable of steady growth, and requires constant cultivation. tioo Is^aSbfe This training and growth are not, however, occa- culture! sional, but constant ; they are not the results of sepa- rate efforts, which are consciously directed to some definite ends of creation, but are the consequents of an activity which is spon- taneous, irrepressible, and often excessive. Indeed, in all minds t^e creative imagination mingles more or less prominently with the other mental operations, always modifying and sometimes greatly disturbing the acting of these powers and their results. In sense-perception, the imagination too often selects for itself what it will see or hear, and brings a report accordingly of what it thinks it has seen and heard. After the desires are grown strong and the character is fixed, the shaping spirit of the imagi- nation enters largely as a modifying influence into the perceptions. In the observations of consciousness, and the reports which it records of what it has seemed only to observe, the same influence and the same effects may be traced of its creative energy. The observation and the record are both disturbed by the power to notice what we are anxious to find, and to leave unobserved, or to imagine that we cannot see, what we do not wish to find to be true. In the act of recalling for ourselves or communicating to others what we may have actually observed or experienced, the creative imagination often intrudes, consciously or unconsciously biassed by the desire to please ourselves or our fellow-men. The frequent and strange untrustworthiness of the memory, can be accounted for only by the selecting or idealizing activity of the imagination, when it seems to be simply recalling the actual past. Inasmuch as the thought-power, in its various acts of reaching general conceptions and conclusions, chiefly depends on the fidelity of the representative power in reproducing the actual; whenever it creates instead of recalling, all the results of think- ing must be disturbed. In this way the imagination may and does enter very largely into the acts of generalization, inference, and deduction ; disturbing and misleading all. 308 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 184. § 184. More generally we may say, this creative Is developed a & n / J J . ' from the earii- power is developed at the earliest period 01 our ex- est till the . . * x . _ latest periods istence, and is busy in all ages and conditions 01 our human life. Childhood, in some of its aspects, is the most literal, and the most observant of reality ; yet even then the shaping activity of the imagination is always busy, filling the real world with another of fancies and dreams. The most trivial and unsuitable objects are sufficient to excite its actioD. The rude and unfinished toy is more acceptable to the child than the more costly and elaborate, because it leaves more room for the constructive power. It is all the better if the greater part of the work is left for this to complete and supply. The sports and plays of childhood are little romances, prompted and acted over for the simple exercise and delight of the imagination. In later years the imagination is always busy. The interest which each man takes in the position in life which he holds or aspires after ; in his employments, his friends, and associates ; or the dislike and disgust which he conceives for each and for all; arises from the ideal lights with which the imagination invests them. The eye of the painter looks every landscape into a picture, and idealizes every face that it beholds. The lunatic, the lover, and the poet Are of imagination all compact. Midsummer- Night' 8 Dream. Act v. This constant activity of the creative power explains its rapid growth, and its development into the capacity for sudden and surprising achievements. Whenever an occasion calls for the manifestation of the power thus trained and matured, it acts as by the force and with the promptness and precision of apparent inspiration. Whether the exigency be that of the artist, the poet, or the inventor, the creative power formed by the ceaseless activity of years meets its requirements from the resources that it has been gradually providing. These resources may consist in part of the countless creations which it has shaped in connection with its perceptions and reveries, and which are again summoned back by the memory when first these images are needed ; or, the resources brought to the exigency may be the dexterity which has been § 185. REPRESENTATION. THE IMAGINATION. 309 acquired by use, and which dexterity consists in the power of so controlling the associating power that it shall yield the very materials which are wanted for the imagination to work upon. In no other way can we explain the rapidity, the precision, and the success with which the constructing and inventive power seems to act when it is tasked to its utmost energy and produces its finest results. § 185. The fact has been noticed, that the creative , . • i n i Special appH- lmagination is present by its actings with all the cations of the other powers of the soul, and determines the char- The poetic im- acter of their products. We have also seen, in our analysis of ideals, that the converse is true as well. All these powers are present in varied proportions and energies in those activities which are recognized as the acts of the imagination, and give a varied character to what are called its products, whether they appear in the form of poetry, fiction, the fine arts, philosophy, ethics, or religion. Of these, the poetic imagination is the most interesting, and invites to a special analysis. Poetry may be defined, that use of the creative power which is employed for the gratification of the emotional nature in the production of pictures more or less elevating in their associations, which are fixed and expressed by means of rhythmical language. The sources from which the poetic power derives its materials are as numerous and extensive as the universe of matter and of spirit, and yet but few of these materials subserve the proper aims of the poet. While the poet may lawfully appropriate truth of every kind, provided it serves his purpose, yet it is pre- eminently that truth which holds or may be made to assume some relation to man which is of use in poetry. This human truth, which these pictures suggest, illustrate, or enforce, must be that which is within the comprehension and reach* of all men. It is not the truth of the schools, nor of any special and limited society, not that which is capable of being conveyed in abstract or technical words or understood by a select few after a special training, but it is the truth which is open and intelligible to all men upon certain implied and easily recog- nized conditions. This is the first of the three characteristics 310 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 185. which are recognized by Milton in his brief description of poetry as " simple, sensuous, and passionate." Poetry should indeed be simple, because its products are de- signed for the use of all men ; and its images, thoughts, and words should be easily comprehended by all who have attained certain advantages of culture, and have been trained to a certain degree of thought and feeling. It should also be sensuous — that is, it deals with images, not with generalized and scholastic lan- guage. It presents pictures to the mind's eye, not refined and subtle reasonings to the thought-powers. It introduces action into every scene. It is eminently concrete and picturesque. It should also be passionate — i. e., its simple and pictured truth should come from a soul that is animated by warm and elevated emotions. The presence of feeling as a requisite of all that com- position which is called imaginative, is not always recognized so distinctly as it deserves to be. Without feeling, and, in general, without feeling of a higher kind, the mere power to create is of little worth, and its results are of little interest. Indeed, without it the power will not be so matured into a predominant energy, or be so regulated, as to become a ready instrument at the service of its possessor. But with it, the creation of the kind of pictures in which the emotions delight, becomes a pastime and an occu- pation, and poetry is to the poet its own " exceeding great re- ward." Inasmuch as only the higher emotions act with a steady and intellectual pressure in the refined occupation of poetic cul- ture and composition, the images which association presents and the imagination detains and reconstructs, are of an elevated character; they assume the lofty and ennobling character of ideals in the better sense of the word. Hence it becomes so gen- erally true that poetry is almost necessarily elevating in its na- ture and influence. Hence it has been held to have something in it that is divine. The ends of poetry are not always elevated. Poetry may serve sim- ply or chiefly to amuse. "When this happens ; when its pictures are employed for this end, and the associations under which they are present, and the emotions which they excite, are not especially enno- bling, the poetic imagination is, in the language of later critics, called the fancy. "When the aims are higher than simple gratification, and therefore involve more elevated associations and feelings, it §186. REPRESENTATION. — THE IMAGINATION. 311 is dignified as the imagination by eminence, and so designated. The adjective imaginative follows very closely this higher sense of the word. In this activity the image-making power simply plays or sports with images for their picturesque effects and the amusement which they give — or arranges them for ends of illustration or pleasure. Though it abounds in images, it lacks the loftier attributes of the higher imagination. § 186. It is peculiar to the poetic imagination in all higher and lower forms that language is its medium. It i S language m is not essential that this language should be metrical ; though a rhythmic movement, and the regular return of similar syllables in measured accent greatly heightens its effects. The poetic power is also shared by the novelist, the dramatist, and the orator. But poetry must always employ language, and for this reason it essentially differs from painting, sculpture, and even music. Painting and sculpture create images indeed, but they fix them permanently upon the canvas or embody them in marble. But poetry can only suggest them by words ; it por- trays its images only, as by words it wakens in the imagination of another, images similar to those which the poet himself con- ceives. If the imagination that receives is feeble, slow, and per- verse, it is in vain that the poet tries to excite it to follow his lead. But if it is strong, quibk, and sympathizing, it may be aroused by the words ,of the poet to finer creations than even the poet himself has known. The suggestive power of words gives to the poet a marvellous advantage in the greater breadth of his field and the variety of his effects. The painter and sculptor ap- parently present all their work to the eye. It is true that this work is better appreciated by one eye than another. In one sense it takes an artist to interpret an artist ; but even with this allowance, the range of their indications is narrow, and the possi- bility of manifold suggestions is limited. But words have a ca- pacity to suggest more than they directly convey, and hence to take" up into their import a multitude of pictures according to the variety of uses to which they are applied. The word whose literal import is prosaic, trivial, or mean, when used by genius in a new application, becomes poetic, picturesque, and elevating. The material which in common use is cold, conventional, and dry, has capacity, by dexterous combinations, to awaken delightful 312 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. .§187. imagery, and to kindle exalted associations. In this way- language itself becomes permanently enriched and elevated by the fact that it has been employed by men of poetic genius. § 187. The relation of the imagination to thought phic e imagina- has been the subject of much discussion, and has given rise to no little diversity of opinion. Many have contended that its influence is unfavorable to the operations of the intellect in the discovery of truth ; that it distracts the attention, biasses and misleads the judgment, and disqualifies for any of the reasoning processes. On the other hand, the fact is undisputed that the men who have been most distinguished in philosophy, especially as discoverers or inventors, have been re- markable for reach and glow of imagination. Striking examples of the combination of the poetic imagination with eminent phi- losophical genius are numerous. We name Plato, Kepler, Gali- leo, Bacon, Newton, Leibnitz, Davy, Owen, Faraday, and Agassiz. A moment's reflection will show how this must necessarily hap- pen. The objects of present observation must always be limited in number. They must reappear in the form of representations. The facts with which the philosopher has to do must come to him in the form of images, when he would discern their various relations and subject them to the processes of thought. It is im- portant that these should be readily represented. This can only happen when the associative power is wide in its range of rela- tions, and quick in its activity. These qualities almost invariably accompany, if they do not necessarily involve, great energy of the creative power. But whatever may be thought of the. importance of a vivid imagination, as furnishing the materials for the philosopher, to invention it is entirely essential ; indeed, without an active imagi- nation, philosophic invention and discovery arc impossible. To invent or discover, is always to recombine. The discoverer of a new solution for a problem, or a new demonstration for a theorem in mathematics, the inventor of a new application <8f a power of nature already known, or the discoverer of a power not previously dreamed of, the discoverer of a new argument to prove or deduce a truth or of a new induction from facts already accepted, the man who evolves a new principle or a new definition § 187. REPRESENTATION. THE IMAGINATION. 313 in moral or political science — must all analyze and recombine in the mind things, acts, or events, with their relations, in positions in which they have never been previously observed or thought of. This recombination is purely mental. Every discovery is, in fact, a work of the creative imagination. It is true the power of thought must attend the operation. Unless the representations and combinations are made and regu- lated with reference to the ends of thought, they will be made in vain. But the range of these pictured objects must be wide ; every one of them must be vividly conceived, that all the attri- butes, and analogies, and relations may come before the eye of the mind. The more vividly this presentation is made, provided the processes of analysis and comparison go on with equal energy, the wider is the field of discovery and the greater is the chance of success. The world of images is also far more plastic than the world of reality. Its materials come and go more quickly than real objects. More can be crowded at once into the field of view. The mental analysis and synthesis required, can be more rapidly performed upon the shadows which the mind summons to its service, than upon the things which it can slowly call up and slowly survey. But there are special reasons why the peculiar type of imagi- nation which the poet requires is closely allied to that which is essential in philosophic genius. To the higher imagination, as required by poets and orators, there is always requisite the power to interpret the indications or analogies of the beings and phe- nomena which they observe. The intensity of interest that fixes and holds the mind in the patient attention of the philosopher is closely allied to that strongly absorbed and controlling enthu- siasm which holds the poet to the images which his fancy summons or creates. Both dwell in such a world with an enthu- siasm which is not easily understood by others. That which maintains the interest of each, is the passion of each for the image-world which he recreates. That which gives to each his mastery over this world, is the familiarity which results from long-continued practice in calling up its objects and in moulding them at his will. Such a mastery, arising from such a continuity of effort, can only be attained by that passionate interest which is the secret of genius, whether genius labors for the ends of 14 314 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §188. scientific or poetic truth ; whether the end for which it labors is the truth of science that addresses the intellect, or the truth of feeling which controls the heart. In the communication of scientific truth there can be no question that a large measure of imagination is of essential service. He who would amply illustrate, powerfully defend, or effectively enforce the principles and truths of science, is greatly aided by a brilliant imagination. This, of all other gifts, is the best security against that tendency to the dry and abstract, the general and the remote, to which the expounder of science is exposed by reason of his familiarity with principles which are strange to his pupils and readers, and which need to be continually explained and illustrated by fresh and various examples. The philosophic writer or teacher who is gifted with imagination is more likely to be clear in statement, ample in illustration, pertinent in the application, and exciting in the enforcement of the truths with which his science is conversant, whatever may be its subject- matter. § 188. The practical and ethical uses of the imagina- JLd.6 prttctiCEil * and ethical tion are numerous and elevated. These are suffi- ciently obvious from the single consideration, that the standards by which we regulate our aims and estimate our achievements must always be ideal creations. They are con- tinually formed and reformed by the imagination. These ideals, so far as the particulars of the character and the life are concerned, may vary both in their import and in the vividness with which this import is conceived. If they are consistent with the conditions of human nature and human life; if they are conformed to the phy- sical and moral laws of our nature, and to the government and will of God, they are healthful and ennobling. Such ideals can scarcely be too high, or too ardently and steadfastly adhered to. But if they are false in their theory of life and happiness, if they are untrue to the conditions of our actual existence, if they in- volve the disappointment of our hopes, and discontent with real life, they are the bane of all enjoyment, and fatal to true happi- ness. It is not what we actually attain or possess that makes us happy or wretched, but what we think is essential, or possible, or just for ourselves to attain. The ideal standard by which we §188. REPRESENTATION. — THE IMAGINATION. 315 measure and judge our attainments in all these respects, is a most important element of satisfaction or discontent. It is of little consequence what a man has, if he imagines that he must have something more in order to be truly happy. If his ideal contemplates self-sacrifice, suffering, and evil, as possible condi- tions of good, he will be still more secure of a happy life. If it reaches forward to another scene of existence, and brings before him the blessedness of a character perfected by suffering and made fit for the purest and noblest society conceivable, his happi- ness on earth may even be augmented by disappointment, sorrow, and pain. If, on the other hand, these ideals are factitious or unreason- able, they become the source of constant wretchedness. If a man, to be happy, must be as rich or as fashionable, as successful or as accomplished as he dreams of, all his actual enjoyments pass for little or nothing till his ideal desires are gratified. These are the standards by which he measures his good. If he fails to realize these, he cannot be satisfied. The ideals we frame of life and happiness must involve a more or less positively ethical character. We cannot imagine what we are to be and to become in fortune and success, without pro- posing more or less distinctly what we ought to be in character and to perform in action. Hence, in a certain sense, what a man aspires to become, has already ethically decided what he is. His aims and standard are the reflex of his wishes and his will, as well as the assurance of what he can achieve in the future. The ideal standard of duty may be constantly corrected and improved. From his own experience of the effects of acts or habits, or his observation of these effects in others, a man may supply what he has omitted to observe, or correct that in which he has erred, and so advance to a higher and more perfect rule of feeling, of manners, and of life. In this way a community may rise or sink, may advance or go backward. Every man may also advance the ideal of others by his good life, by the realization in himself of what is worthy, and his more perfect manifestation of it in appropriate and beautiful acts. The contemplation of fictitious characters, elevated and ennobled by ideal beauty, has served to quicken and enforce the ethical ideal of thousands of susceptible minds. The poet, the novelist, and the dramatist, 316 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §189. may quicken the fervor, and instruct the minds, may elevate the tastes, and reform the lives of all their readers. § 189. The relation of the imagination to religious Relation of the _..,.. . _ . >„» , . n imagination to faith is interesting and important, lhe objects of our faith, by their very definition, have never been subjected to direct or intuitive knowledge. And yet the imagi- nation pictures these objects as real and most important. What are the materials out of which it creates them ? Whence the suggestions which it idealizes into more refined and spiritual essences ? By what authority does it invest these creations with verisimilitude and impose them upon the assent of the intellect, as representing the most real and important of all truths ? What analogies are there between the finite and the infinite which authorize the imagination to use the one to symbolize the other, and which justify its faith in its own symbolic creations ? Of the Divine Being as Infinite, we have no direct experi- ence. All our direct apprehensions of spiritual attributes and relations are of the limited only. It is by the limited that we reach the unlimited even in thought. Conceding that we can think the infinite, can we also image it? We cannot. The sphere of the imagination is only the finite. All the pictures which it can construct are of limited objects. It is by means of such pictures only that it can image its concepts of the infinite, if it attempts to image these at all. That it can adequately picture them, no man believes. What is pictured by the image, is some limited example of some real being which sug- gests or exemplifies the thought-relations required. These thought-relations are : existence, power, knowledge, ori- gination, foresight; — all which, we say and believe, are both finite and infinite. But when we seek to image these as infinite, we select some finite examples that illustrate these attributes ; we choose an image to give life and reality to the analogon of that which we believe to be unlimited in respect to its sphere and energy. But these utmost efforts of the imaginative power to reach the infinite and the absolute, are always attended by the belief that they fall short of the reality ; that no enumeration of finite objects, however interesting in themselves, or significant they may be, are at all adequate to illustrate the divine; that no continuation § 189. REPRESENTATION. — THE IMAGINATION. 317 of space or of time can express the divine eternity ; that no quanta of dependent beings can fitly represent the Being who is self-existent. To have the materials that shall enable a man fitly to image the infinite, one must himself be infinite. There are, indeed, analogies between the created and the creating spirit ; else the one could not know the other in any sense or to any degree. But these analogies are too few and too inadequate to enable or authorize man to penetrate into the secret things which belong to God, or to make conceivable the divine by any images which man applies so freely and so rationally to limited things. The imagination is not easily content to use the analogies which are placed at its command, and to refrain from using those which it may not lawfully employ. It would fain go further than it can or ought. To do this, has been its constant temptation. To re- fuse to go as far as it may and ought, is weak and unphilosophi- cal ; but to attempt to go further, is always irrational, and, it may be, impious. In respect, also, to the capacities and experiences of the spirit- state, — when separate from a human body or any material organization — the imagination is limited in the materials of its working and the products which it creates. We know the soul only in its connection with the body. To image any of its acts or states without a constantly present background of bodily sensa- tions, is to imagine a mode of existence that seems to us imper- fect and unnatural. We cannot imagine the soul without the body by which to know and act, and without material objects to act upon. If we attempt this, we bring to our aid some attenuated matter for the soul's habitation and instrument, and we surround it with a world of objects that wear the forms of material things. But here the question continually presents itself, How far can we image that world by this, and the. soul's experiences in that world, by its experiences in this? Can we properly imagine either? May we apply the pictures drawn from this life to illus- trate or make conceivable the scenes and events of another state ? We not only can, but we must; yet ever with the caution, that the images which we use be not allowed to suggest more than the data authorize. It should not surprise us to find that the imagination, when it rises into faith in the objects of the unseen world, invariably uses 318 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 189. pictures that are borrowed from the world of matter, and phrases all its language from materials furnished by this imagery. It cannot do otherwise. However lofty its conceptions may be, however soaring its aspirations, undoubted its beliefs, or ardent its hopes, all these must be pictured and expressed in the images taken from that world of matter which is adapted to a soul that knows and acts through a material organism. If there be a revelation that is conveyed by human language or addressed to the human soul, it must in this respect be accommodated to the capacities of the soul that is to understand and accept it. The fact that a revelation must be conveyed by such a medium, does not disprove that it is possible, or at all detract from its im- portance or authority. It cannot be argued against its divine origination or supernatural confirmation, that it conforms itself in this respect to the nature of the being to whom it is given. If, however, we regard the necessary limits of imagination and faith, we shall not expect that either will do more for us than lies in the capacities of either. "We shall not confound the images of analogy with the intuitions of direct knowledge. We shall not mistake the accessories of illustrative imagery for the realities of the concepts or truths which this imagery sets forth. We shall not revel in sense-pictures of the fancy, as though the sensuous in them were literal truth. We shall not be imposed upon by pretended seers, because, forsooth, their pictures of the unseen are so minute, so copious, and so beautiful, or so confi- dently set forth ; overlooking the circumstance that these visions may be merely the residua of a too luxuriant fancy, or the creations of an excited and perhaps an insane imagination. The recognition of the human limitations in the divine, will teach us to interpret the divine aright, while it may save us from accept- ing as divine that which is only limited and human. § 190. THOUGHT-KNOWLEDGE DEFINED AND EXPLAINED. 319 PART THIRD. THINKING AND THOUGHT-KNOWLEDGE. CHAPTER I. THOUGHT-KNOWLEDGE DEFINED AND EXPLAINED. Thinking and § 190. The third kind of knowledge of which the the thought intellect is capable, is thinking, or thought. The power denned. ■*■ . a J term thought, when used in this special or technical sense, is applied to a great variety of processes, which are familiarly known as abstraction, generalization, naming, judging, reasoning, arranging, explaining, and accounting for. These processes are often grouped together, and called the logical, or rational processes. The importance and intimate relationship of these processes is seen by their place with respect to the higher knowledge and attain- ments of man. It is by thought only that we can form those concep- tions of number and magnitude which are the postulates and the materials of mathematical science. By thinking, we both en- large and rise above the limited and transient information which is gained by single acts of consciousness and sense-perception, as we lay hold of that in both which is universal and permanent. By thought, we know effects by their causes, and causes through their effects : we believe in powers, whose actings only we can directly discern, and infer powers in objects which we have never tested nor observed : we explain what has happened by referring it to laws of necessity or reason, and we predict what will hap- pen by rightly interpreting what has occurred. By thinking, we rise to the unseen from that which is seen, to the laws of nature from the facts of nature, to the laws of spirit from the phe- nomena of spirit, and to God from the universe of matter and of spirit, whose powers reveal His energy, and whose ends and adaptations manifest His thoughts and character. These processes give us the most important part of our know- ledge, and qualify us for our noblest functions. Thought makes us capable of language, by which we communicate what we 320 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 190. know and feel for the good of others, or record it for another generation ; of science, as distinguished from and elevated above the observation and remembrance of single and isolated facts ; of forecast, as we learn wisdom by experience ; of duty, as we exalt ourselves into judges and lawgivers over our inward desires and intentions ; of law, as we discern its importance and bow to its authority ; and of religion, as we believe in and worship the Unseen, whose existence and character we interpret by His works and learn from His Word. But what it is to think, and how thinking should be defined, may be more easily understood by a concrete example. We take a familiar object, as an apple, and proceed to think it, in the various processes already named. First of all, we know it as a being or a something, as dis- tinguished from nothing ; next, we think or know this being as possessed of and distinguished by attributes or properties which we can separate in thought from the being to which they belong. We go further : we observe in other objects — apples — attributes like those which we discern in this; we see the objects to be similar in color, form, taste, etc. In this way we form the mental product called a general notion or concept of the apple, or of apples in general as we say, which we can analyze and define. To abstract and to analyze, is to think. Next, we re- store, or think back, these general concepts to the individual apples, and in so doing, we divide them into higher or lower, wider, or narrower classes. Classification is involved in thinking. As we proceed, we mark and fix what we have done by lan- guage. We give names to each of these attributes, to the con- cepts and things formed and denoted by several attributes united, and to the classes and sub-classes into which they are separated. Thinking is necessary to language. Next, the apple holds relations to space and time. It is both extended and endur- ing. The perception of the apple condition ates or involves the knowledge of both space and time. By thought and imagina- tion we are enabled to separate the object perceived from both time and space, and to construct in space the various geometri- cal figures, as well as to conceive and define them by their neces- sary attributes or properties. Moreover, all sorts of entities, whether things existing, or thought-things, whether attributes or § 190. THOUGHT-KNOWLEDGE DEFINED AND EXPLAINED. 321 beings, can, by the common relations to time in the mind that thinks them, be thought in the relations of number. Again, the object — the apple — is believed to be produced from a tree, beginning as the germ in the blossom, and gradually expanding into the ripened fruit. It is known also to be dependent upon the agencies of heat and moisture acting together with the living tree. Thought, connects these as cause and effect, and finds in the phenomena thus connected, the relations of the powers and laws of their causative agents. "We proceed to a higher act of thought knowledge. By observing the powers and conditions in any class of apples, their habit of growth, the soil, situation and temperature favorable to their successful cultivation, we infer that the same are required in all cases for this kind of fruit, and confirm the suggestion by experiment. But we do not rest with the induction of poivers and laws. We observe that the apple is useful and pleasant as food. We notice that it is the product of cool climates, and can, with proper care, be preserved through the winter. We do not merely observe and record these as facts, but we connect them by the relation of adaptation, or fitness to the wants of man. The nature and processes of thought might be illustrated by an example selected from the world of spirit. By consciousness, we know only individual states of perception or feeling. But we detain or repeat one and another ; we observe their likeness or unlikeness ; we form concepts ; we group them in classes which divide the individuals to which they belong ; we fix and record the products of our acts by a name ; we find common causes, powers, and laws for similar phenomena ; we discern the adapta- tions of spiritual objects to one another and to the world of matter, and thus bind together the world of matter and spirit, in the unity and harmony of one comprehensive plan ; the thinking of man interpreting in these ways the thoughts of God. From this particular example of thought we derive the fol- lowing definitions : To know by thinking, is to unite individual objects by means of generalization, classification, rational ex- planation, and orderly arrangement, — Thought-knowledge is that knowledge which is gained by the formation and application of general conceptions. Thinking is a species of knowledge ; but knowledge has been 14* 322 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §191. defined as the apprehension of objects in their relations. Think- ing, is the apprehension of objects as generalized and their implied relations. Some persons may question the propriety of designating these several processes by the terms thinking and thought, for the reason that these words sometimes signify to imagine, or believe on in- sufficient evidence. On the other hand, it should be remembered that thinking and thought, in the best English usage, denote, in a general sense, the higher as distinguished froni the lower operations of the intellect. There are no single words so appropriate as these, which can be set apart to the technical service and designation of the operations of the rational faculty ; no other terms for these operations are in actual use whose common signification is at once so comprehensive and so definite as are these. § 191. If it be difficult to find an appropriate term fo^thl 1 power to stan d for all these higher processes, it is almost as etc. thinking ' difficult to find or select an appellation for the power which qualifies us to perform them. The intelligence and the intellect have been thus appropriated, but they are also used for the capacity of the soul for every species of knowledge, the lower as well as the higher ; for the power to know by sense and imagination, as well as the power to know by general con- ceptions. The understanding is sometimes employed in this very general sense, and sometimes limited to a single and special func- tion, as by Coleridge and others, after Kant. The judgment is used, likewise, in a wider and a narrower sense. The reason seems better fitted than almost any other term, and yet the rea- son is used for the very highest of the rational functions, or else in a very indefinite sense for all that distinguishes man from the brutes. It remains for us to choose between the rational faculty and the power of thought, or briefly, thought. For brevity and precision we prefer thought. It is scarcely necessary to observe that, like perception and representation, and many subordinate terms, thought is used at one time for the power, at another for the act of thinking, and at another for its products. Thus we say indifferently, " Man is endowed with thought as well as with sense :" " Sits fixed in thought the mighty Stagyrite :" " A penny for your thoughts !" § 191. THOUGHT-KNOWLEDGE DEFINED AND EXPLAINED. 323 The power of thought may be considered in two aspects : as a capacity for certain processes or functions ; and for eliminating and generalizing certain fundamental conceptions or relations. In the one of these aspects it performs the several acts which we have enumerated, of generalizing, judging, reasoning, etc., the most of which are usually called logical processes, because they are more or less intimately related to deduction or reasoning. In the other, it is viewed as the discoverer of certain native concep- tions or intuitions, and the propounder of certain first truths, or first principles ; which are also called necessary and universal propositions, axioms of reason, or, metaphysical conceptions and metaphysical truths. Hamilton refers these two processes to two faculties, the elabo- rative and the regulative, the one of which elaborates or works over the materials furnished by the lower powers, according to the conceptions or rules which the other furnishes or prescribes. In this he follows Kant very closely, who calls the logical faculty, the understanding, and the power which controls its beliefs by ideas, the reason. It is more satisfactory to consider the two in conformity with the analogy which we discern in the other powers of the soul ; the one as the capacity for certain definite acts or processes of knowing, which we consciously exercise and employ; and the other as the unconscious source of these conceptions, according to which the material of knowledge must arrange itself by the very constitution of the thinking power. The thinking power, viewed as the capacity for certain pro- cesses, thinks in various methods, and matures certain products, the two being often denoted by the same word. These several products are called the forms of thought, or thought-formations. These forms are the concept, the judgment, the argument or syllogism, the induction, and the system. As the discerner or the discoverer by intuition of certain neces- sary conceptions or relations, the thinking power is said to know or assume certain forms of being, according to which it performs its operations, and constructs its products or forms of thought. These are called indifferently, forms of being and forms of knowledge, for the reason that the mind can only know what is or exists, and according to the relations in which it exists. Some of these 324 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §192. forms of being or forms of knowledge are time and space, sub- stance and attribute, cause and effect, means and end. § 192. The power of thought, as a capacity for thought to the certain psychological processes, is dependent for its lower powers. . , 3 , ., exercise and development on the lower powers of the intellect. These powers furnish the materials for it to work with and upon. We must first apprehend individual objects by means of sense and consciousness, before we can think these objects* We can classify, explain, and methodize only individual things, and these must first be known by sense and consciousness. These lower powers are not only necessary to furnish the objects for thought to work upon, but they are developed earlier than the higher powers. The infant must go through a training of the eye and the ear for months, before it begins to name and classify with effect. It is the conscious subject of a multitude of mental states, before it gathers the most obvious under a general conception. The discipline of attention must be for a long time enforced, before the developed mind can learn to apply the commonest concepts or to affix the simplest names. The conceptions of cause and effect, and of means and end, are not developed till the intellect has become still more mature. To the development of thought, the representative faculty is also largely subservient. The individual object must not only be apprehended in order to be thought of, but it must be recalled again and again. To thought, the discernment of similarity is required ; and in order to this, the past must be frequently con- fronted with the present, and the present must be compared with the past. Objects striking for their likeness or their difference, must be recalled by the memory and revived to the imagination, in order that like objects and like phenomena may be grouped and arranged in the rudest classification. If the classification is to be perfected to anything like scientific exactness, the memory and imagination are to be tasked still further in order that one's thought-products may be just to the reality of things. But while the thought-power, in its various operations, is thus shown to be developed later than the several forms of direct cognition, it should not be supposed that it springs into perfect and mature energy by a single bound, or that the. acts of in- fant perception are not affected by its rudimental activity. The § 193. THOUGHT-KNOWLEDGE DEFINED AND EXPLAINED. 325 human intellect is a unit, and the action of one power is tinged or modified by the feeble energy of all the others. The sense- perceptions of the infant may seem to be more feeble and less mature than are those of the young of the brute. The higher powers may meanwhile seem to lie torpid long before they are called into distinct activity. But before they are revealed to the conscious subject of them, or are expressed in the simplest forms of language, they give direction and character to the perceptions of sense. They impart to the human eye a cast of dawning intelligence which distinguishes it from the keener eye of the dog or the eagle. § 193. Thinking, again, may be distinguished as concrete and abstract. In concrete thinking, we know abstract think- of thought-conceptions and relations only in their application to individual or concrete objects. We should say more exactly, we know individual objects under or by means of the relations which thought furnishes. In abstract thinking we separate these conceptions and relations from any and all indi- vidual objects. We consider them apart by abstraction, and sometimes treat them as though these conceptions and relations could have an independent existence. In concrete thinking, we proceed as we have described in § 189. In abstract thinking, we separate or abstract from every indi- vidual object the generalized conceptions which we produce by thinking, as also those by means of which we- think : as the con- cept, the judgment, the argument, the inference and the system, on the one hand ; and substance and attribute, cause and effect, means and end, on the other. We even abstract and generalize our very acts or processes of thinking, and view them apart from the individual examples or cases in which they actually occur. We ask, What is it to conceive, to generalize, to judge, to reason, to infer — nay, what is it itself to think ? We discuss the nature and origin of these conceptions, and their relations to one another, to the objects to which they are applied, and indeed to all our knowledge. Concrete thinking is performed by every human being whose powers are fully developed. All men freely apply its concep- tions and relations. By means of them they know sensible and spiritual objects, so far as they know these at all. A stone or an 326 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 194. apple, a horse or a dog, a house or a church, a spirit or a person, each and all are known as beings, and are distinguished and de- fined by certain attributes or properties. One of these acts upon another, as a cause producing an effect, etc. In myriad examples, objects are familiarly known by us as substances and attributes, as causes and effects, as means and ends. In the concrete form, all these conceptions are present in the language, and familiar to the minds of the most uninstructed men. But when these conceptions are abstracted, and viewed apart from individual beings, they are not made familiar to the mind without a special discipline. It is only a few men who possess the tastes or the training which qualify them readily to deal with or rightly to understand thought-conceptions when abstracted from individual things. Skill in using, and discrimination in understanding them, can only be acquired by concentrated and patient efforts. § 194. Thinking is aided by language, and, to a Relations of . . . ~, . thought to great extent, is dependent upon it as its most efficient instrument and auxiliary. But thinking is not con- stituted by, but, on the contrary, itself originates and gives form and law to language. The connection between thought and language is so intimate, that we shall have occasion to refer to it again and again. One or two general remarks in respect to it, seem here to be in place. The reason why thought requires such an instrument and assistant as language, is, that the objects of thinking are generalized objects, and to such objects there are and there can be no realities actually existing. The results or products of our thinking are not manifested by any changes which are actually affected in material or spiritual objects. It is only by language — the sound to the ear, and its symbol for the eye — that the products of thought activity can be fixed so as to be the objects of recall and future use. Hence words spring into being as fast as definite conceptions are formed. Hence it is as natural for man to speak as it is to think, and man " speaks because he thinks." The name fixes, preserves, and exhibits the transient concept as in a crystal shrine, both hard and clear. The proposition embodies the judgment for the use of the man who first thinks it, and who utters it to stimulate the thinking of others. In applying § 195. FORMATION OF THE CONCEPT OR NOTION. 327 names, we must enter somewhat into the nature and properties of the objects for which they stand. In defining terms, we must be guided to their meaning by observing the things to which they are applied. In accepting or rejecting propositions, we must think of the relations of the objects which they concern. It follows, also, that the study of words must be a study and discipline of thought. To master a language that is rich in its vocabulary, requires that we contemplate the nicer shades of thought which are expressed by the endless variety of the con- ceptions that are embodied in its words. If it is complicated in its structure, we must discriminate the delicate relations which this syntax expresses or suggests. No language can be dead to the intelligent student. Its delicate tissue reflects the varying shades of thought, feeling, and opinion that run through every part of the fabric, like threads of silk and gold. But, on the other hand, words in no sense constitute thought, as some hastily infer. Language is simply thought expressed, though the thought is made permanent by being expressed. It is formed by the thinking power, because this requires for de- velopment and perfection a sensible expression of its inner pro- cesses, and seeks a permanent embodiment and record of their results. CHAPTER II. THE FORMATION OF THE CONCEPT OR NOTION. § 195. Thinking has been already defined as that The processes ° J involved m series of processes by which we form and apply formin s the general notions or concepts. It is obvious that the first act in this series of processes is to form or de- velop these products. We begin with the concepts of, material objects, such as a stone, an apple, a horse ; and observe that such objects must be perceived, in part, at least, before we form general notions of them. We do not insist that the process of perception should be complete before the act of generalizing begins. It is necessary, however, that a percept should go before 328 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 195. the concept in the order of time, as it is the foundation for it in the relation of logical subordination. A general notion requires individual objects to which it can be applied; and individual objects in the material world can only be known by perception. The mind begins to form concepts as soon as it notices that several perceived objects are different as individuals, and yet are in any one respect alike. Before generalization, they may be known confusedly or known vaguely. As soon, however, as they are distinguished as not the same, and yet as united by a common likeness, the process of generalization has begun. This process is possible even with single percepts. If ten patches of red color, of the same form, dimensions, and intensity, were pre- sented to the eye, the mind might gather, or conceive, or grasp them together, by their common redness, and form a general notion of them ; thus uniting them as one by the single simi- larity of color. If these ten red discs of color, by the use of the remaining senses, are afterwards known to be ten red apples, i. e. if other points of likeness are perceived, the generalization is more complex in its materials, but the process is the same. The process involves acts of analysis, of comparison, and of generalization. The mind must notice that which is common, and distinguish it from that which is diverse. This act is an act of comparison. Its appropriate object is likeness. It dis- cerns a quality as similar. It takes this similar to be the same, and, so regarding it, finds it in every one of the individual objects. This similar something, conceived as common to many objects distinguished as individuals, is a general conception, notion or concept. The mental acts which we have described, are familiarly known as follows: The act of analytic attention by which the similar element in each one of any number of objects or pheno- mena is separately observed or noticed, is usually called ab- straction, because the mind draws it away from the other parts or relations. Kant and Hamilton say that abstraction refers to that from wJiich the mind withdraws itself, while it prescinds the element to which it attends. Thus, in the example cited, the mind prescinds the redness, and abstracts its attention from all the remaining attributes. The next step is, to perceive by comparison that the several §196. FORMATION OF THE CONCEPT OR NOTION. 329 objects to which we thus separately attend, are alike. The next step is, to consider these several similars as the same, the one something which is common to all the individuals perceived. This is to generalize — to make general — more properly, mentally to think or affirm a common something of all these individuals. The similar red, or round, or siveet, or bitter, is made one, and, as one, is regarded as common to each of the different individuals. Which of these acts is first performed, is immaterial — whether the mind seems to generalize before it abstracts, or the reverse ; or whether it analyzes, compares, and generalizes all in one. It is all the same as to both process and product, whether we separate the redness from the first apple which we perceive, before we apply it to the many, or are stimulated by observing many red apples to notice and abstract that which is alike and common, or whether the points of difference excite us to generalize the one or more elements in which the objects are alike. Again, when this common something has thus been generalized from like objects, it can be applied to — i.e., affirmed or predicated of — any and every other object to which it is appropriate. Thus, spherical, after being thought of a single class, as of apples or balls, may be thought of all objects that are round — as of the vast spheres which are hung in the heavens, or of globules so minute lj to be indiscernible by the naked eye. It has been already observed, that these processes develop and presuppose the distinction of substance and attribute — i. e., of being and distinguishing relations. The individual apples of which we think the redness are beings, the redness is their common attribute. What is the nature of, and what the authority by which we make this distinction, we do not propose here to inquire. For our present purposes, it is sufficient that we call attention to the fact that it is fundamental to the process of forming the notion, and that it must be assumed as real, and be firmly believed by the mind. (Cf. § 323.) § 196. The product of the processes considered, is ° r f > The product, its called a concept or notion. We emplov these terms nature and ap- L J pellation. because they may be made precise in their import and technical in their use. Conception is sometimes used ; but conception is, in our English philosophy, used indiscriminately for any and every object of the mind's cognition, or else is 330 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 196. arbitrarily limited, as by Dugald Stewart, to the individual object of representation, and thus made equivalent to image. Abstract general conception (or even general conception) is suffi- ciently precise in its import, but is too cumbrous for common use. Concept and notion have each, in their etymology, a special signi- fication appropriate to one aspect or feature of the product to which both are applied. Concept signifies something grasped or held together, and refers us to the act by which different similar attributes are treated as one, or the same act in * which separate individual beings are united as one by their common attribute or attributes. Notion, on the other hand, indicates that which is or may be known by certain signs or marks, noto3 — i. e., constituting, defining, and distinguishing attributes. Both terms may be properly employed as technical and scientific designations. The reality of any such mental product or thought-object has been questioned, chiefly by those who have misunderstood or misconceived its nature. Its import or nature has been imper- fectly or vaguely estimated even by many who have believed in its reality. It is only by explaining its nature, both negatively and positively, that its reality can be vindicated and established. The concept is not a percept, nor is its object an object as per- ceived. This last is strictly individual ; the concept is uniformly general. In order to prove this beyond question, we have only to ask what the mind knows when it sees a man, and what it thinks of when it utters the word man, and applies it in thought to the human species. No one can doubt that the two objects of cognition are diverse. The concept is not a mental image, or the object of the mind's cognition in representation. We recall an individual percept, one or many ; or we form, by creation, some image unlike any which we have in fact perceived. Both are clearly distinguish- able from that which the mind thinks or knows, when it uses a general term. We state positively: — The concept is a purely relative object of knowledge. This is its distinctive feature, that it holds definite relations to objects of sense and consciousness. As a mental product and mental object, it is relative, being formed by the mind and understood by the mind as indifferently common to single objects ; which objects only enable the mind to understand § 196. FORMATION OF THE CONCEPT OR NOTION. 331 its import. The individual things to which it relates, give to it all its significance and utility. Without these, it is a no-thing, an unintelligible and unreal fancy. This peculiarity of the concept is implied in its various appellations. It is called a general, that is, capable of being thought of many individuals, which are thereby grouped into or conceived as a class. It is called also a predieable, by its very nature capable of being affirmed or thought of single objects. It is a univer- sal — i. e., as pertaining alike to all the individuals to which it belongs. Again : as being this common and relative thing, the concept respects only the similar attributes of individuals, or such as might be supposed to be alike. It respects those elements which analysis can separate as individually distinct, and comparison can unite as alike. Attributes, properties, and relations, are the only objects which it respects. These are first discerned, then com- pared, then united into a single thought-object. Herein lies the difference between the act of a brute and the act of a man in perceiving objects that are alike. In one sense, the brute may perceive what is similar as readily as a man ; in some cases, even more quickly, for his senses may be more keen. If he has been ill-treated by any other animal, or frightened by any object, every thing like either will be avoided at once. But the brute does not attend and analyze as does a man. Hence he cannot dis- criminate so as to abstract ; or, at best, the degree and range of such efforts must be very limited. His power to compare and discern the like and the unlike would for this reason be lame and feeble,if no other could be suggested. Should it be granted that the brute can discern similar attributes, it has no power at all to con- ceive or think the similar as the same. It cannot form and use a concept as founded on attributes and as common to individual beings. Hence, the brute is incapable of language. He may utter sounds and cries which instinct extorts and to which the instinct of the hearer responds, and thus the voice and ear of the animal tribes may serve some of the useful and social ends which language accomplishes in man ; but the brute is incapable of using words as the signs of concepts, because he is incapable of thought. He cannot form and use a concept, and therefore he can neither speak nor understand a single word. Even the parrot, 332 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 197. that miracle of talkers, is incapable of language, and never utters what deserves to be called a word. We observe still further, that all which the concept contem- plates or signifies, is the common attributes which are discerned in the individuals to which it is applied. These attributes are its proper and sole import or signification. The concept, as such, is not at all concerned with the number of individuals in which these attributes are found, or with anything else which may be true of them. It is all the same to our thinking and to the con- cept which we form by thinking, whether the tree of which we make and use the notion, is here or there ; is high or low ; is the tree which we have often seen and admired, or the tree which is ten thousand miles distant ; is the tallest of the cedars of Leba- non, or of the firs of California, or the most dwarfed that exists on the coldest mountain summit. It is even indifferc whether it actually exists or not ; it is only essential that it be formed by the mind from the actual constituents of every object that is properly called a tree. § 197. Concepts are distinguished in their applica- Concepts £IS # mi • concrete and tion, as concrete and abstract I he concrete notion simple ' and contemplates attributes, and is applied to beiugs ex- content and ex- isting. The abstract notion treats attributes as though they were themselves such beings. Man and human are concrete; humanity is an abstract notion. The concrete notions are applied directly to an actually existing being, for pur- poses of classification and language, which need not here be explained. The abstract humanity is applied to designate a being that is purely fictitious, but which, in language and in thought, is treated as though it possessed actual existence. The attribute is conceived as a being, in having attributes affirmed of it; as when we say, humanity implies liability to error. It has adjectives prefixed to it, as in the phrase, our original humanity. It is divided into classes : humanity is either refined or degraded, etc. In short, it is capable of being treated in every way, as though there were living beings called humanities. But when we analyze the real meaniug of language, and the thoughts of those who use it, we find that the only beings distinguished by the mind are the living men who are endowed with human attri- butes. § 197. FORMATION OF THE CONCEPT OR NOTION. 333 Concepts, again, are still further distinguished as simple and complex. Those notions which are made from a single attribute, are simple. Those which are made of more than one, are com- plex. Simple notions are called, by Locke, simple ideas. They cannot be analyzed or decomposed into any constituent elements. The mind directly discerns them by its various powers of know- ledge. Such words as white, whiteness, green, greenness, etc., etc., are usually given as the names of simple notions. It would be more exact to say that we treat these notions as simple, be- cause we do not ordinarily distinguish in thought, or by lan- guage, the discernible shades of white and green. Those which are properly simple, would be such shades of color as can be distinguished from every other. On the other hand, chalk, chalky, are complex notions, because they signify more than one attribute. So, man and human are complex spiritual notions, for they contain many attributes. No thing or being actually existing is represented by a simple notion. A grain of sand or a mote in the sunbeam, is complex, for it has farm, dimensions, color, weight, etc., etc. Nature gives us no simple ideas. She touches us through too many avenues of knowledge. She leads us to observe varied attributes in every existing thing. "We, in our thinking, analyze and separate her complex objects, and reconstruct and recombine the elements which, at her prompting, we have abstracted and generalized. In this way we separate and reconstruct the elements or attri- butes of material objects as nature exhibits them to us, as of plants, and animals. Thus, all the concepts which are expressed by the general terms that form the staple of every language, are constructed by the mind. They are passed from one mind to another. They are fixed in words and recorded in books and literature. The names of the objects that human art and skill has constructed for use or beauty, likewise stand for the complex of simple notions which we observe in these objects. The arti- ficial creations, such as are conceived by human invention and spring from human society, the crimes which are defined by human law, the offices and relations of government, the signs and proofs of property, the rights and duties of men, all these are complex notions, which are made and sustained by civilized men, and interest most profoundly their hopes and fears. These 334 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 197. are still further removed from the notions and terms more usually- conceived as abstracta, but, like these, they are susceptible of being so analyzed as to be carried back to living beings. But these all are complex notions, and some of them are exceedingly complex in their constituent elements. If we consult a dic- tionary, and run the eye down its lists of words, we shall be surprised to find how large a portion of them stand for these artificial creations, these complexes of abstracted properties. Still further, notions are technically distinguished by their re- lations of content and extent, or, as they are often termed, their comprehension and extension, their depth and breadth. These relations grow out of the very nature of the notion, as has been shown by our definitions. A notion cannot be a notion, unless it has these two relations. It can neither be formed nor used unless both these relations are considered. The content of the notion is the attribute, or attributes, of which it consists. It is its contained attributes considered as a unit or whole. Those notions whose content we have the most frequent occasion to consider, are complex notions. Every simple notion has a proper content in the single attribute which, when conceived as common, is made a concept. Such complex notions as chilk, snow, milk, felony, burglary, theft, man, spirit, body, soul, legislation, monarchy, republic, a state, etc., have so manifestly a sum of contained attributes, that it is with especial propriety that we speak of their content. These constitute their meaning or import. When these are fully stated, the notion is defined. They are also called the essence, or essential constituents, of the notion, because they make up or form its being as a thought-product or thought-creation. The extent of a notion originally and properly signifies the number of individuals to which it is applicable. If we could know, by actual enumeration, how many horses or men there are at any time existing, their sum would be the extent of the notion horse. We rarely, however, have occasion to consider indi- viduals ; for these are divided again and again into larger and smaller groups, to each of which there is a fixed notion and name. These divisions are effected by adding to the content of the notion which includes a greater number of individuals, an additional attribute — in the case of the horse, an attribute of § 198. FORMATION OF THE CONCEPT OR NOTION. 335 color, perhaps ; and we have a new content, white horse, black horse, etc., giving an extent of fewer individuals. In many cases, we designate the concept thus newly-formed by a separate name, as pony, for a small horse, charger, hunter, roadster, etc. So trees are divided by means of notions, whose content is given as deciduous and non-deciduous. The latter are divided into pines, firs, etc.; the firs are again divided into hemlocks, spruces, etc., each having some attribute not belonging to the content indicated by the word fir or fir-tree. In consequence of these divisions or groupings of individuals into broader and nar- rower classes, the extent of the notion in actual use always stops short with subordinate groups, and does not carry us down or back to the included individuals. These individuals are always intended, however, and the subordinate classes are said to constitute the extent, because they, in their turn, are applicable to and comprehend individuals. As the content of a notion is exhibited by definition, so the ex- tent is shown by division. This division is effected as the indirect consequence of adding to the content of the notion a new attri- bute, which immediately narrows its extent. The adding a new attribute, or new attributes, for this end, is called determination, or the act of bounding off, or limiting. It follows that, as the content of a notion is increased, its extent is diminished. Hence the maxim : the content is inversely as the extent. Both propositions are true, the greater the extent, the smaller the content ; the greater the content, the smaller the extent. § 198. In forming the notion from, and applying the notion to, individual objects, the intellect classifies its Origin id these objects ; that is, it groups them into divisions C ies e . rent spe " which are broader and narrower in their extent ; and of course higher and lower when ranked according to their place in a system. This consequence follows from the fact that nature has so constructed individual beings that they are capable of being grouped into larger and smaller divisions, by means of their resembling attributes ; and from the desire in the human soul which meets this fact of nature by connecting objects in an orderly arrangement. The first efforts at classification are necessarily rude and im- 336 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 198. perfect. Children when left to themselves group together objects in singular combinations and discern resemblances between things which older people never would think of connecting. In the poverty of their language they apply the words which they possess, to the strangest uses, on the very slightest and the most whimsical analogies. They soon learn better, as we say. That is, they take from older persons the conceptions and classifications which have been made before them. In other words, they think over again the concepts that are made ready and presented for their use, in the words of which they learn both the import and the application. In learning to talk they are constrained to fall in with those classifications which previous generations have made before them, and have recorded in the language which they have left behind. Savages do not classify under the same restraints. When novel objects are presented to them, they usually seek out some concept or word already known and familiar, and extend it to the novel object by some resemblance, however forced or violent this may be. The goats which Captain Cook carried to the Pacific Islands were called by the natives horned hogs : the horse on a like occasion was called a large dog. The dog and the hog being the only quadrupeds with which these savages were familiar, these novel animals were taken into the only concepts and names that were ready for their reception. When the Romans first saw elephants, they called the animal Bos Lucas or Lueanus, a Lu- canian ox, from the province in Italy where they were first seen. The classifications of science differ from those of common life in being founded on a more exact observation, and directed by the special rules which are furnished by scientific principles. These may be certain assumed ends or known powers or laws of nature which were discovered long after the classifications had been per- fected which are recorded in the words of common life. The classification of animals into vertebrates, articulates, mollusks, radiates, and protozoans, and the subdivision of the vertebrates into mammals, birds, reptiles, and fishes, are very different from those represented in the words horse, ox, whale, snake, hawk, quail, robin. Neither the so-called natural nor the artificial systems of botany give us what we know under the household names of the lily, the rose, the pink, and the violet. And yet § 198. THE FORMATION OF THE CONCEPT OR NOTION. 337 these common names do as really classify their objects as do scientific names. To classify is no secret of science, no process reserved for the select few who are initiated into a magic art, but it is as universal and necessary as the act of thinking. The classifications of common life may be as rational and as useful for the ends of common life as are those of science for its .special uses. They are founded on the obvious appearances of objects to the senses and the mind. They are adapted to the uses of men of ordinary culture. Indeed what wealth of thinking does -every cultivated language embody and represent! Each one of its words has gathered into its subtle essence the results of the repeated and refined observations of the men who perhaps by successive efforts at last reached the concept which each single term enshrines. In like manner the technical nomenclature of .a single science when finished and arranged, is a transcript of all the discrimina- tiDg thoughts, the careful observations, and the manifold experi- ments by which the science has been formed. It represents in brief, all the most careful definitions and the most complete and best classified divisions which the devotees to its special objects have perfected by their labors. Classification is nearly allied to systemization. The division of objects into classes which are broader and narrower, has a close affinity with their orderly arrangement in classes which are higher and lower, through a succession of divisions and subdivi- sions. Both result from the application of notions in their extent to existing objects or to objects which are conceived to exist. Classification and systemization, are the characteristics and consequences of all thought-knowledge and preeminently of scientific knowledge. They are indispensable to enable us to grasp individual facts and to retain our observations. They are an intellectual convenience and an intellectual necessity. But they do not constitute the whole of thought or the whole of science. Though scientific knowledge is of necessity classified and arranged knowledge, yet much more than this is true of it. We have entered within the threshold of our analysis and comprehension of thought-knowledge, but the light which shines from the inner sanctuary casts its radiance only upon those objects which are the nearest to our view. It remains for us to consider other acts, involving profounder relations in the consti- 15 338 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §199. tution of the universe, in the methods and forms of our thinking, and in the products which this thinking evolves. § 199. It will not be amiss, however, to ask at this we° gaki UC by stage of our inquiries, what addition do we make to conceptf? by the knowledge which we gain by perception and con- sciousness, by superinducing upon it the acts or pro- cesses of thought which we have thus far considered ? . What do we know more about an object seen or experienced, by general- izing its attributes, determining its class, or assigning to it a name ? We may answer this question by asking two or three others. What more does a man know about a single apple by calling it an apple, a fruit, a plant-product, an organized being, than he does by seeing, feeling, tasting, and smelling it ? We answer, its common relations, i. e., properties, attributes, and uses. When we think or intelligently say of a sense-object, it is an apple, we both think, and impliedly say of it, it is like a multitude of other sense-objects, in many most important respects, as of color, taste, size, etc. When we think or know it to be a fruit, we enlarge still more widely the sphere or extent of the objects to which it holds relations. So when we think it to be a plant-product. That was no inconsiderable act which was signified by the re- cord which describes the various living animals as brought to Adam that he might name them. The capacity to name them implied an insight into their nature. For this reason it must of neces- sity be true, if we suppose the original man to have been en- dowed with the requisite discernment, that " whatsoever Adam called every living creature, that was the name thereof." It seems to be a trifling thing for the child to be able to affix suita- ble names to the objects and beings which first attract its atten- tion. At first thought the act is trivial, mechanical, parrot-like, as it were, to attach an articulate sound to one or more similar objects ; but when we view it as implying the power of intelli- gently applying this name to a still larger number of objects which are in many respects unlike and yet alike, it becomes an act of the gravest import. It indicates an important development of the soul's action, and the evolution of a new product. When the child asks, What is it ? meaning thereby, What is it called ? it really asks, What is the nature, what are the relations, of the § 201. THE NATURE OF THE CONCEPT. . ■ 339 object to which the name belongs, as it learns one by one what these relations are, and notices in what they are alike, and in what they are unlike. That was no slight achievement of Aristotle, to seize upon, bring out and es- tablish the truth that the concept of an object either declares what it is, or at least in- dicates the direction which must be taken in order to find this. The concept is the permanent what-ness or what-sort-of-ness, which may be thought of the things to which it is applied. It is the to ri fy elt-ai, i. e., its real and permanent nature. To ask what a thing is, according to Aristotle, is to take the first step and per- form the first of the processes which are essential to its complete mastery. It is to propose the first of those questions, the answers to all of which carry the mind through the entire circle of scientific knowledge. Aristotle also recognises the intimate connection of the concept with the word, calling the two by the same term, o Aoyos. § 200. The what which the concept and the word both propose to communicate, is not the direct ob- knowledge by servation which presentation gives, but the higher D y7nTu?tionT. d and more comprehensive knowledge which thought aims to achieve. It is not the knowledge that a being is, but the analytic and comparative knowledge of its relations. CHAPTER III, THE NATURE OF THE CONCEPT. — SKETCH OF THEORIES. In the preceding chapter we have considered the nature of the concept in a general way, so far as was required in the analysis and explanation of the psy- chological process by which it is formed. We return to it a second time for more careful consideration. $ 201. The nature of the concept and its relation to real or ex- isting objects has been the occasion of endless speculation, of fan- The doctrines tastic theories, and of sharp and persistent controversies in every pii^and Ar- period distinguished by philosophical inquiry. Socrates was the istotle. first to insist upon the importance of forming concepts of the ob- jects of our knowledge in order that the permanent and essential might bo elimi- nated from that which is accidental and transitory in individual objects. But he taught little or nothing in respect to the nature of the concept, or of that in the object to which the concept is the counterpart or correlate. Plato took up the in- quiry where Socrates left it; insisting more abundantly than he upon the neces- sity of this higher knowledge, and showing that in attaining it we must define and divide— must go from the individual to the general, by successive inductions, and so on from one step to another, till we reach that which exists of and by 340 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 202. itself — that which is alone the permanent object of [true] knowledge. This is the idea, y <-&ea or to eiSos. But what this idea is, and what are its relations to the con- cept, he does not accurately teach ; where it exists he does not assert ; whether in the object itself, or in the mind of the Creator, or in the mind of each thinking man, he does not define. He seems to teach that ideas, or the idea, have an exist- ence and essence separate from all these, that they are eternal and incorruptible, existing before all temporary and perishable beings, and imparting to the perisha- ble and phenomenal in these beings all their dignity and interest. Ideas are re- alities, things and events are their shadows. But whether by these representa- tions, he intends only personification and poetic fiction, or exact scientific defini- tion, is not always easy to decide. As against Plato, Aristotle insists that the only real beings or substances are existing beings or things, the irp^rai ova-Lai, or primary entities, as he calls them. He is distinctly aware that there are other sorts of beings besides these. The SevrepaL ovalac or second entities are distinctly discriminated from the nptorat ova-Cat, or individual beings. He aims to show in what sense the former are so called, and how they are related to real beings, or, in modern phraseology, to show the re- lation of concepts to real existences. This he does by distinguishing between matter and form. Matter cannot exist without form. Every existing being has some determinate form. There can be no form without matter. The one requires the other. The two are correlates, seeking each other, as Aristotle figuratively speaks, by a natural appetency. The form only is conceived by the mind. What the mind conceives of a being is its essence, to ri r\v elvai.. I n modern lan- guage the concept is made up of the essential qualities that are common to several individuals, omitting those which are undiscriminated; these last being matter. Aristotle set out with the determination to avoid those personifications which so abound in Plato. But he did not entirely succeed. Should we concede that he was not himself betrayed into hypostasizing these metaphors, he did not secure his disciples from this error. So it happened that the ideas of Plato and the forms of Aristotle were both regarded as actual realities, and as such, fur- nished fruitful material for the subtleties and controversies of their earlier disci- ples and commentators, in the decadence of the Greek philosophy. § 202. It was, however, among the scholastics of the middle ages Porphyry's that such discussions became conspicuous, in the schools of the questions and . x the scholastics. Realists, the Conceptualists, and the Nominalists. The immediate occasion of these discussions and controversies was furnished by a passage from Porphyry, in the preface to his Introduction to the Categories of Aristotle. This Introduction was translated from the Greek by Boethius, and a brief passage proposed the problem for the different sects which wc have named — who received their appellations from the different solutions which they gave to it. " Mox de generibus ct specicbus, illud quidem, sive subsistent, sive in solis nudis intelloctibus posita sint, sive subsistcntia corporalia sint an incorporalia, ct utrum separata a scnsibilibus posita, circa hseo consistent ia dicero rccusabo. Altissimum enim negotium est hujus modi ct majoris cgens inquisitionis." In other words, the questions which naturally suggest themselves concerning Univcrsals are the following : 'Have Univcrsals a separate existence, or do they exist in the mind only? If they have a separate existence, are they corporeal or incorporeal '( Are they separable from sensible objects or do they subsist in these only?' § 203. THE NATURE OF THE CONCEPT. 341 The extreme Realists answered these questions in the spirit of Plato, or rather of the doctrine which Aristotle ascribed to Plato, viz. : that Universal s have an existence that is separate from, and independent of individual objects. They even contended that they exist before these, in rank and creative power, certainly in point of time. These views were formulated in the motto Universalia ante rem. The moderate Realists adopted the creed of Aristotle that Universals have a real existence, but only in individuals. Their motto consequently became Univer- salia in re. The Conceptualists and Nominalists agreed in this that individuals alone have real existence : and that Universals, both genera and species, are formed by the mind, by bringing together many similar objects and designating them by com- mon terms. They differed in that the extreme Nominalists held that the name only is general and is employed to avoid an indefinite number of proper names which would be otherwise required; while the Conceptualists interposed a concept between the name and the objects collected into a class. The motto of both Conceptualists and Nominalists was Universalia post rem. The differences of opinion that ripened into these separate philosophical sects began to be manifest in the ninth and tenth centuries. It was not, however, till the second half of the eleventh that different philosophers and theologians were commonly known by these appellations, and that the doctrines themselves became the occasion of earnest and bitter strife. These divisions reappeared at intervals and were not finally terminated before early in the fourteenth. § 203. In modern times the diversities of opinion in respect to the nature of the concept have been as great, and the controversies Mo ^ rn Philo- well nigh as active as they were among the schoolmen. The same questions have in fact been agitated, and the same difficulties encountered, with this difference — that the form which these questions have taken has been more generally psychological, rather than metaphysical. This was no more than was to be expected from the general course of modern philosophy. But in the recent German speculations, the logical and metaphysical direction of thought has preponderated over the psychological and inductive. Hobbes, a nominalist of the extremcst school, says, Human Nature (c. 5, $ 6) " The universality of one name to many things hath been the cause that men think the things themselves are universal; and so seriously contend that besides Peter and John and all the rest of the men that are, have been, or shall be in the world, there is something else that we call man, viz. : man in general, deceiving themselves, by taking the universal or general appellation for the thing it signi- fieth." * * * "It is plain, therefore, there is nothing Universal but Names." In The Leviathan (p. i., c. iv.) he says : " There being nothing universal but names, for the things named are every one of them Individual and Singular, one Uni- versal name is imposed on many things for their similitude in some quality or accident." Locke, on the other hand, who was a Conceptualist, says in his Essay (B. IV., c. vii.,§ 9), "Does it not require some pains and skill to form the general idea of a triangle, [which is yet none of the most abstract, comprehensive, and difficult,] for it must be neither oblique nor rectangle, neither equilateral, equicrural, nor scalenon; but all and none of these at once. In effect, it is something imperfect that cannot exist [t. e., in fact, or actually] ; an idea wherein some parts of several 342 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 203. different and inconsistent ideas are put together. 'Tis true the mind in this im- perfect state has need of such Ideas, and makes all the haste to them it can, for the conveniency of communication, and enlargement of knowledge." That he was not a Realist appears from the following (B. III.,c. iii.,§ 11 sqq.) : * * " It is plain by what has been said, that General and Universal, belong not to the real existence of things ; but are the inventions and creatures of the understanding, made by it for its own use, and concern only signs, whether words or ideas." "When therefore we quit particulars the generals that rest [remain] are creatures of our own making, their general nature being nothing but the capacity they are put to by the understanding, of signifying or representing many particulars." He argues at length against the Realistic doctrine of permanent essences or spe- cies. " Whereby it is plain that the essences of the sorts, or (if the Latin term please better) species of things, are nothing else but these abstract ideas." " To be a man or of the species man, and to have a right to the name man, is the same thing. Again, to be a man, or of the same species man, and have the essence of a man, is the same thing." To these doctrines of Locke, Leibnitz, in his Nouveaux Essais, G.W.Leibnitz, takes the following exceptions : He denies that the essence of the species is only an abstract idea, and asserts that the generality of such ideas consists in the mutual resemblance of individual things, and this re- semblance is arealify. {Nouv. Ess., B. III.,e. iii.,$ 11.) Berkeley, Introduction to the Principles of Human Knoicledje, thus attacks the doctrine of Locke. After describing the doctrine as commonly received, he pro- ceeds : "Whether others have this wonderful faculty of abstracting their ideas, they best can tell ; for myself I find, indeed, I have a faculty of imagining, or re- presenting to myself the ideas of those particular things I have perceived, and of variously compounding and dividing them. I can imagine a man with two heads, or the upper parts of a man joined to the body of a horse. I can consider the hand, the eye, the nose, each by itself abstracted or separated from the rest of tho body, but then whatever hand or eye I imagine must have some particular shape and color. Likewise the idea of man that I frame to myself, must be either of a white, or a black, or a tawny, a straight or a crooked, a tall, or a low, or a mid- dle-sized man But I deny that I can abstract one from ancther or con- ceive separately those qualities which it is impossible should exist so separated; or that I can frame a general notion by abstracting from particulars in the man- ner aforesaid." And yet Berkeley, in another passage concedes the power of ab- straction so far as this: "A man may consider a figure merely as triangular, with- out attending to the particular qualities of the angles or relations of the sides. So far he may abstract. But this will never prove that he can frame an abstract, general, inconsistent idea of a triangle." In respect to generalization also, ho concedes the following: "An idea, which considered in itself, is particular, be- comes general by being made to represent or stand for all other particular ideas of the same sort. To make this plain by an example: supposo a geometrician is demonstrating the method of cutting a line into two equal parts. He draws for instance, a black line, of an inch in length. This, which is itself a particular line, is nevertheless, with regard to its signification, general; since as it is there used, it represents all particular lines whatsoever ; . . . . and so the name line, which taken absolutely is particular, by being a sign is made general." Hume agrees with Berkeley, adopting nearly his language The only difference § 203. THE NATURE OF THE CONCEPT. 343 between Hume and Berkeley is, that Berkeley makes the particular idea to repre- sent the general, while Hume adds that it becomes general by being annexed to a term which is customarily conjoined with many particular ideas, and readily re- calls them. In other words, Hume introduces his doctrine of the association of ideas to explain how one idea and term can represent several objects, and become general. This last doctrine has been expanded and re-applied by later writers. Reid, in criticising both Hume and Berkeley, does not give his own views in the form of a statement precisely defined. He seems scarcely to know what his own opinion is. In respect, however, to the question under consideration as to the nature of the concept, he lays down some important distinctions which are quite in advance of the doctrines previously admitted. He observes (1) that a general idea must be the product of an individual act of the mind, and in that sense and so far, is an individual, and not a general, entity. (2.) " Universals can- not be the objects of imagination when we take that word in its strict and proper sense." " Every man will find in himself * * * that he cannot imagine a man without color, or stature, or shape." " I can distinctly conceive universals, but I cannot imagine them." (3.) "Ideas are said to have a real existence in the mind, at least while we think of them, but universals have .no real existence. "When we ascribe existence to them, it is not an existence in time or place, but ex- istence in some individual subject ; and this existence means no more, but that they are truly attributes of sach a subject. Their existence is nothing hut predi- cnhility , or the enpacity of being attributed to a subject." Essays on the Intellec- tual Powers. Essay V.,c. vi. Dr. Thomas Brown, {Lectures: 46, 47) avows himself to be a conceptual- ist, and contends that all the nominalists have either in fact admitted or un- consciously implied the truth of this doctrine. He distinguishes three steps or elements in the generalizing process (1) "the perception or concep- tion of two or more objects, (2) the relative feeling of their resemblance in certain respects, (3) the designation of these circumstances of resemblance by an appropriate name." He criticises some expressions of the conceptual- ists as incautious, particularly the usa of the word idea to express "the feeling of resemblance," because this word " seems almost in itself to imply something which can be individualized and offered to the senses." " The same remark may, in a great measure, be applied to the use of the word conception, which also seems to individualize its object." "The phrase general notion would have been far more appropriate." " Still more unfortunate is a verbal impropriety in the use of the indefinite article." " It was not the mere general notion of the nature and properties of triangles, but the general idea of a triangle of which writers * * have been accustomed to speak." This has exposed the doctrine of general no- tions to ridicule, such as Martinus Scriblerus is made to use against Locke. Sir William Hamilton, {Lectures on Metaphysics, Lee. 35) criticises Brown severely for misrepresenting the nominalists, in asserting that they overlook the fact that resemblance in individual objects is the ground of applying to them universal names. Hamilton then labors earnestly to show that discerned or pre- dicated resemblance is individual, and not general ; inasmuch as if likeness exists between a pair of objects, it must be an individual relation of likeness. In his logic, however, and in all the treatment which he gives to the concept, Hamilton proceeds upon the hypothesis of Conceptualism, in the manner in which Reid qualifies and explains it. Indeed, it would seem that his peculiar doctrine 344 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 203. of the syllogism and deductive reasoning can have no meaning on the theory of Nominalism. And yet he would almost have us believe that he is a Nominalist, and " that the opposing parties are really at one." John Stuart Mill, in his Logic, B. i., c. 2, and his Examination of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy, chap. 17, earnestly advocates Nominalism. Names are names of things, but while they denote things, they also connote the attributes of things. Thus horse (or chalk) denotes every individual horse (or piece of chalk), but at the same time it notes or marks, i. e., connotes all that is peculiar to every horse, or to the class horse. Instead of the term concept, or general abstract no- tion, Mill would use class name. The mind, whenever it uses the class name in- telligently, must have some individual object before it, either perceived or re- membered. It need not, however, direct its attention to every part of this indivi- dual object. It need think of, i. e., attend to, only those parts which the name connotes. It need not think of all of these even, but only of those which it has oc- casion to use for its immediate purposes. Of the modern German philosophers, Kant should be named first, not only in the relation of time, but on account of the influence which he has exerted upon all subsequent philosophy. Kant distinguished very sharply between individual and general objects of knowledge, and in the spirit of this distinction introduced many technical terms which are not only still retained in the Gternian systems, but have been adopted by English thinkers. Kant's terminology is not only a permanent monument of his own activity, but it has served to fix some very important dis- tinctions in the minds of speculative men. Kant says very little psychologically concerning the nature of the concept as the product and object of the mind's activ- ity, or concerning its relation to the objects of sense. Speculatively, however, he treats this topic very fully. First of all, the concept, der Begriff, is the product and object of the understanding, as the percept die Vorstellung — der Sinnliche Gegcnstand, — is the product and object of the action of sense. The image das Bild, das Schema, is the work of the fantasy, both reproductive and productive. The pcrccjDt is individual and so is the image proper. The concept is general and de- finite. The Schema is intermediate between the two, being indefinite and mova- ble, and in a certain sense general (cf. $ 149). The percept, the image, and the Schema are all directly apprehended by the mind. The concept is mediately apprehended and mediately applied, requiring, to be used, that it should bo imaged in an individual object, or applied to some individual. Knowledge by concepts is preeminently mediate knowledge. In the concept, the matter is distinguished from the form. The matter is fur- nished by the senses, the form by the understanding; before, however, the two aro brought together, the sense-matter must become a percept in the forms of space and time. E.g. The matter of the orange is furnished by all the senses. This matter becomes the percept orange by taking certain relations of space. It be- comes a concept by being viewed by the understanding as a being with attributes which aro distinguished from each other, and yet are common to many indivi- duals, involving the recognition of diversity, similarity, and production or causa- tion. These and other such forms arc given by the understanding itself; which, in acts of thought, as it were, covers over or invests the matter of the senses with any or all of them. It would seem from these doctrines, that Kant was emi- nently a conceptualist, inasmuch as he insists so much upon the concept as the medium of thought, and so often repeats the assertion that thought is knowledge § 205. NATURE OF THE CONCEPT. 345 by the medium of concepts. Bat he does not declare himself such. His discus- sions are all logical and metaphysical rather than psychological. Though a theory of the powers and processes of the soul is constantly implied by him, it is rarely presented in the ps} T chological form. / § 204. Kant emphatically gave that ideal direction to philosophy which reached its terminus in the extreme doctrine of Hegel, who G. W. ¥. Hegel, makes the concept everything and the individual nothing, who evolves the real world from the concept, to which he ascribes an infinitude of ele- ments and a power of self-development, adequate to produce the countless varieties of individual things. Should it be said that this is a misconstruction of his doc- trine; that he treats only of the relation of concepts to one another, and of indi- viduals only so far as they are conceived or turned into concepts, the result is the same, so far as our position is concerned ; which is that he does not concern him- self with the relation of the concept to the individual, nor with the nature of the concept as a product of the mind, or as a representative of concrete being, but regards it as an all-sufficing and independent entity. Hegel may therefore be called a logical realist. CHAPTER IV. THE NATURE OF THE CONCEPT, GENERAL NAMES. — LANGUAGE. The brief review which we have taken of the various theories of the concept will enable us to see more clearly and to define more exactly its real nature as a mental product, and its re- lations to the objects from which it is formed, and to which it is applied. Every false or defective theory is founded upon some important truth. The consideration of defective or exaggerated theories is most useful in enabling us to ascertain the truth in all its relations, and thus to develop it completely, as well as to distinguish it from errors of excess or defect. In the light of our historical sketch, we observe : § 205. 1. The concept, as a mental object or product, is to be distinguished from the mental act by acterfetics of which it is originally produced or recalled. Such an act is necessarily individual. The concept produced or recalled is general. 2. The concept, as a mental product and a mental object, implies that the distinction of individual beings and their attributes is accepted as real, and must therefore be admitted as possible. 15* 346 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 205. 3. The attribute must first be known or apprehended as related to a thing or being. It is always held by the mind as attributable to or predicable of some being or thing. Its import, or what is thought of by the mind, is not the being as such, but the being as related, or the being together with a something related to it. 4. The attribute thus related, is next viewed in the relation of similarity to other individual attributes, constituted and known like itself. When the individual red is compared with other individual reds, there is added to its import its likeness to each and all of these. 5. The use of the concept thus formed to classify objects enlarges its meaning still further. The capacity of the concept to be a classifier, arises from two circumstances : the fact that the attribute which is its germ, is common to more or fewer individual beings, and the fact that these attributes are dis- tributed in gradation. Whenever it happens that one attribute, as red, belongs to more beings than another attribute, as sour ; then the red may denote the larger class — i. e., the genus; and the sour, the smaller or subordinate class — i. e., the species. Sour, in such a case, may be the differentia of the species — the sour- reds. If oval were universally present with the species sour-reds, it might be a property ; if hirsute were sometimes present and sometimes absent, it would be an accident of the same species. The application of any attribute in all or any of these class- relations, obviously adds to its import. When a concept is used to classify, an additional relation is thereby taken up into its meaning, and this meaning is thereby so much enlarged. We distinguish what may be called generalization — the use of the concept as general or as common to more or fewer indi- viduals, from generification — the arrangement of these indi-" viduals into higher and lower classes. Generification simply recognizes the fact that these concepts are distributed in gradation, some belonging to more and others to fewer individuals, and that consequently these are classed according to their extent into genera and species. The process and the product in the second case, both imply and are built upon the process and product in the first. In the first, we bring the individual under the general, by the direct act of forming the general from the individual in the way described. We know the individual under this concept or § 206. NATURE OF THE CONCEPT. 347 general name. In the second, we perform the reflex act of employing the general to divide all the individuals to which it belongs into classes as wider and narrower, or higher or lower. § 206. 6. The mind, whenever it uses a general term intelligently, must understand or conceive the conceptuaiist import which belongs to it in some or all of the are bothrigit. particulars which we have enumerated. We do not intend that the mind consciously distinguishes and dwells upon each of these relations, but that, in forming and applying such terms, it must in some sense have recognized them all. The question in dispute between the different parties is, what object the mind thinks of or has before itself when it uses general terms. Our previous analysis has, we think, established that it thinks of all these thought-relations, and that they all enter into the distinctive import or meaning of the concept as such. The conceptuaiist is right, if what he contends for is that the mind must impliedly have formed a concept of one or more generalized attributes, as often as it employs a general term. If the nomi- nalist contends that the concept is only a general name — i. e., a name which the mind applies to many objects — he is manifestly in the wrong. What the mind considers, is not the name, but the meaning or import of the name. 7. The nominalist is right when he urges that the mind cannot conceive or acquire knowledge of the import of any concept, except by means of some individual example of the qualities or relations which it includes. We cannot know what single sensible attributes signify, as red, sweet, smooth, etc., without the actual experience of the sensation which each occasions, or of one that is analogous. So is it with the concepts of simple acts and states of the soul, as to perceive, to imagine, to love, to choose. The same is true of the concepts that are clearly complex, ^s house, tent, knife, tree, horse, meadow, mountain, valley, township, legislature, authority, wealth, value, rent, wages, feudalism, civiliza- tion. Of all these concepts, the elements must first have been made intelligible to the mind in some concrete example — i. e, by being observed, experienced, or thought, in some individual being or agent. We cannot know a quality or qualities, a relation or relations, 348 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §206. except as exemplified in some individual being or thing, for the reason that these can neither exist nor be known except as belong- ing to beings or things. We cannot know what red is, except by the inspection of something red ; what imagining or remembering are, except as an individual spirit imagines or remembers ; what equality, identity, height, or depth are, except as some object is known as equal to another or identical with itself, or as high or low as compared with another. The theory of the nominalist also finds ready acceptance, be- cause names are so prominent and efficient in aiding thought. Experience teaches that, without the help of names the mind makes little progress in forming or applying its concepts. The use of language, and of spoken language even, is found to be almost essential to successful thought. Without language, the discriminations of attributes are few, the generalizations are narrow and limited, the power to enter into and receive the thoughts of others is almost dormant. Many have gone so far as to conclude that, without words — i. e., names — we cannot think at all. Experience with deaf- mutes, who have acquired little even of the language of signs, disproves this extreme conclusion. These show, by their actions, that they generalize — i. e., form concepts — to a limited extent. They classify and arrange observations, they analyze and com- pare attributes, they apply principles in deduction and infer them from data. But while these facts show that it is not impossible to think without names, they also prove conclusively that without such aid, it is impossible to think with much effect. As soon as they learn to form and use names by the mastery of signs and written language, their power of thought is greatly quickened, and their stock of concepts is rapidly increased. But the lan- guage of the eye alone, which is the only language at their command, is immeasurably below the language of the ear in the fineness and variety of its material, as well as in its capacity for ready assimilation and recall. Still, the surprising acquisitions made by deaf-mutes, in spite of all the disadvantages under which they suffer, decisively prove that the mind is not re- stricted .to any one kind of material out of which to form for itself a language; that words, in whatever form, are only the signs of thought, and are not essential to thought itself. S 207. NATURE OF THE CONCEPT. 349 § 207. 8. The truth that every concept is capable , . n -. • r t • i 1 .1 • • The imaging of being referred to an individual thing or image, of concepts. and every individual or image can be thought into a concept, reconciles the strife between the conceptualist and the nominalist. The conceptualist, in insisting that the concept must ignore and neglect the individual and its characteristics, often seems to overlook the dependence of the concept upon the individual thing or image as the originator of its materials, and the ex- plainer of its import. Locke says, positively, " the general idea of a triangle " " must be neither oblique, nor rectangle, neither equilateral, equicrural, nor scalenon, but all and none of these at once." "In effect it is ... an idea in which some parts of several different and inconsistent ideas are put together." The nominalist asserts that the only ideas which we can frame or mental objects which we can think of, are individual. Bishop Berkeley insists : " The idea of man that I frame to myself must be either of a white, or a black or a tawny, a straight or a crooked, a tall, or a low or a middle-sized man ; " plainly imply- ing that we can form no other thought of man than of one possessing these and other individual characteristics. And yet he concedes that, " An idea, which, considered in itself, is particular, becomes general by being made to represent or stand for all other particular ideas of the same sort." But how the indivi- dual can represent particular ideas, he does not explain, and seems never to have considered. This remark brings the point in dispute to a distinct issue, in the questions, " How can one individual represent other indivi- • duals ? Or, How can the individual explain and illustrate the general? A concept is general, an image is individual, how can you think the one into the other ?" The sides of every indivi- dual triangle must have a definite length, and the angles a de- finite measurement and relations. Every individual man has in like manner a definite height, form, color, etc. We think these into concepts, not by overlooking the individual relations of each, but by considering their likeness to similar attributes in other objects ; the sides and angles, not in their individual re- lations, but simply as sides and angles — i. e., as bounding a figure and as being contained within two lines. We do not so 350 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 208. much leave any thing out of view, as we add the new relations of likeness which the formation of the concept involves. An object viewed without thought-relations, is an image. An image with these relations added, becomes a concept It is true that, when we think the image into a concept, we give special attention to fewer elements; but we need not overlook or oirit any in regarding these few. Least of all do we introduce into the concept elements that are inconsistent or incompatible, and conceive — i. e., image — a triangle which is neither rectangular, acute, or obtuse, as Locke asserts is necessary and as Berkeley objects is impossible. It is curious and instructive to notice here, that Different ima- . ., , . , , , ges illustrate every man images the concepts which he employs or cept. an " hears of, by examples that are peculiar to himself, and which are derived from his individual experience or observation. If his experience or education is marked by very striking peculiarities, the concrete examples suggested to him by every concept and name will be as peculiar. An Esquimaux, a Chinese, and a European, would picture very different objects to the imagination, on hearing or reading the words state, legisla- tion, wealth, money, wages, civilization, fashion ; and even the more concrete terms, house, city, ship, oar, sail, knife, feast, procession, township, and meadow. And yet their concepts denoted by these words are substantially the same, inasmuch as the more important and essential relations of objects are common, however greatly their individual characteristics may differ. This circumstance explains how there may be a community of thoughts, with a very diverse experience. The nature of things and the nature of man remains unchanged. The same powers, laws, and ends are perpetually reappearing, the same principles are continually illustrated, under forms the most un- like. § 208. 9. The realist emphasises the truth that The truth rep resen alism edbyre- every real concept should suggest or express some one or more of the essential properties and unchanging laws of individual beings. He is not content with the view of the nominalist, who makes the general term a mere class-name for the simple convenience of language, nor with the view of the conceptualist, who regards the concept as a chance-assemblage of attributes. He insists that concepts proper ought to signify and § 208. NATURE OF THE CONCEPT. 351 represent those objects and those attributes only which are per- manent and constantly occurring. This is the truth that has given currency and influence to the realistic theory, in spite of the extravagant and metaphorical language, and the insuffi- cient arguments by which it has been stated and enforced. All individual objects of nature exist under constant con- ditions, and are produced by permanent forces, according to fixed laws and ends. These constituents, conditions, causes, laws, and ends of individual objects are often called their inner truth, their essential nature, their true meaning, their real and permanent being. The individual mass of earth or ore, the single crystal, leaf, herb, tree, fish, bird, reptile, quadruped, and man, have accidental relations of position, form, size, color, or taste ; they exist here or there for a longer or shorter period of time, but these relations are of little importance for the higher ends of knowledge and of practice. It is to reach and to impart the knowledge of permanent elements, causes, laws, and designs, that concepts are formed, classes are arranged, and names are given. As we have seen already, many of the earliest classifications and concepts are rude and unsatisfactory for scientific purposes, because they are founded upon attributes that are superficial and narrow in their significance and indicate few or none of the per- manent elements and laws of being. These are gradually out- grown and displaced by others which as soon as discovered sug- gest more comprehensive agencies and laws. No better illustration can be adduced of the differ- „ .,„ . . , _ , , The classiflca- ing import of dinerent kinds 01 concepts and classes, tions of bo- than is furnished by the history of botany. Linnaeus hit upon the convenient expedient of classing the different in- dividual plants by the number of the stamina that appear in their flowers and of subdividing the classes into orders by the number of pistils. The device was convenient, because all plants have flowers, and the number of the stamens and pistils is in most cases constant, and presents a ready means for their division and subdivision into classes and sub-classes. To a cer- tain extent this division signified something — so far at least as the number of stamens and pistils was found to indicate other common characteristics of importance, and seemed to point to deeper qualities and laws. But this was by no means universally 352 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 208. the case. The classes and orders that were founded upon the number of these organs, were concepts of little interest, because they signified nothing in respect to the structure or the germina- tion, the growth or the habits, the flower or the fruit. Hence the Linnean system was abandoned for a system of classes and of nomenclature, which was founded on indications of greater prac- tical and scientific significance. The mistakes of the realists have been twofold. They have, both in language and thought, confounded the subjective concept, which is a purely psychological product, with its objective cor- relate — the related elements which it represents or indicates; and have often called both by the same name, and invested them with the same properties. They have used a highly metaphoric. terminology to express the nature of universals, and their rela- tions to individual beings. The ideas of Plato and the Pla- tonists, present from eternity in the Divine mind ; the forms of the Aristotelians, incapable of existing apart from matter, yet essential to every material thing and species ; the substantial and essential forms of the schoolmen, as well as their universals ante rem and a parte rei ; the forms and ideas of Kant ; the notion of Hegel, — self-moving from the empty yet posited nothing, and self-developed by constant growth into all the fulness of the idea f with a capacity claimed for this notion to pass into the objective, giving the world of material being, and then to return to itself so as by self-conscious affirmation and distinction to blossom into spirit and thus complete the circle of absolute knowledge ; — all these are examples of the exaggerations and personifications of realism in its endeavors to express a most important truth. This subject has, of late, assumed a very great interest and importance among naturalists, in connection with the question of the permanence of species in the natural and vegetable kingdoms. Certain naturalists contend that none of the so-called species are permanent, either in the plan of nature, or its actual divisions ; that every one of them has been developed by evolution from previously existing types, which owed their form and apparent permanence to certain conditions or laws that were but temporary in their action and transitory in their results. In this way Dar- win, (Origin of Species, etc.,) Huxley, and others, reason from certain varieties produced within species, that all species existing § 209. NATURE OF THE CONCEPT. 353 at present, have been themselves developed. Herbert Spencer, by a broader application of the same general assumption, makes every type of existence, both material and spiritual, to have been developed from lower forms, which are held in being till forms still higher and more exalted shall displace them. On the other hand, Owen, Agassiz, and Dana find that the classifications of science must assume a more permanent and firmer foundation for the species which they accept, in the action of permanent forces after the fixed types that are contemplated in the unchanging plan and the manifested thoughts of God. In this assumption they express the scientific truth of the bold metaphors of Plato, who taught that by definition and division, we find in the tem- porary and phenomenal those eternal and real ideas which exist in unsoiled and unalloyed purity in the mind of the Deity alone. (Cf. Agassiz, Essay on Classification.) § 209. 10. The reasons why language aids «ur _. . . . ' _. . J © & Value of nam- tnmking are the following. iog aud of ian- (a.) The name is both a sensuous and an individual object. It presents to our sense-perceptions a definite object, which we can readily evoke, distinctly apprehend, and easily and unmis- takably repeat. What it represents, is indeed abstract and general, but the name itself is an individual object of sense-perception. The word addresses a single sense, the ear or the eye singly, or the two combined. In either case it is ready to appear when called for. The winged word flies to our aid, and the ghostly product of thought is at once embodied before the senses. (b.) The word is the sign, not of the whole of the individual thing or being which might image or exemplify the concept, but of a portion of its attributes or relations. In consequence, words present a greater variety and refinement of objects than exist in the world of nature. The words red fruit, acid-fruit, currant, cherry-currant, may all be imaged or exemplified by the same sense-object, viz., the fruit before us. Red stands for a single one of its properties ; fruit, and hence red fruit, for several ; cur- rant, for more ; and cherry-currant, for even more. So the terms company, organized company, and legislature, may all be exemplified by the same body of individuals discerned by the senses, while each of the words represents more or fewer of its attributes or relations. 354: THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 210. To fix and represent a single attribute by a word, is also neces- sary for the service of communication which language performs. Another mind could not be brought to direct its attention to the attribute and property which we with difficulty discern, unless the attribute were represented by a name. This, however, does not weaken, but rather confirms the service of the word to thought, in rendering its acquisitions permanent and ready for use. (c.) Names enable us to add to our stock of logically depend- ent concepts. One concept is dependent upon and grows out of another. One concept, when formed, enables us to form another, and is often the essential condition of the existence of the second. (d.) Names aid most efficiently in rapid thinking, by sparing us the necessity of dwelling on the entire import of the word be- fore us. In conversation or rapid discourse, as well as in reading by the eye, only enough of this import is attended to to satisfy the present occasion — all else is omitted. Even whole sentences, when they are familiar, are received as the signs of single con- cepts or relations, viz. : those which the present occasion requires. This can only happen when the language is familiar to the eye and the ear, so that, as the eye and the ear each catch enough to identify the word or phrase, the mind also catches enough of the import to satisfy the present occasion. Were not the words addressed to the senses, and capable of rapid formation and re- ception, they could not serve in this rapid application. § 210. 11. The analysis which has been given of The relation of t h e na t U re of the concept and its relations to the in- symbohc to in- * ied tive kn ° w " dividual object or image, explains more exactly the relation of what is called symbolic, mediate, or logical knowledge, to that which is intuitive, immediate, and experimental. We have already spoken of this distinction in a general way. We return to it again, for the sake of greater exactness. Know- ledge by concepts is symbolic, mediate and logical. Knowledge by direct apprehension, whether in connection with consciousness or perception, is called intuitive. When I perceive a sense-object, as a man, a house, or tree, or am conscious of an individual state of spiritual activity, or dis- cern with the mind's eye a mathematical figure, I know intui- tively each of these objects. When I recognize either as belong- ing to a class, or give to either a name, I am said to know it by § 210. NATURE OF THE CONCEPT. 355 means of the concept or name ; and these concepts or names are said to be the media or symbols, which I employ in knowing. This distinction, as thus stated, originated with Leibnitz, and much has been made of it by later thinkers, as Kant and other Ger- man philosophers, as also by Hamilton, Mansel, and Morell r,moDg the English. The grounds for this distinction have been explained already in the positions, that every concept supposes an individual concrete, either real or imaginary, in which it is exemplified, and no person can conceive the import of the concept except as he resorts to this concrete for interpretation and explanation. When I pro- nounce such words as white, red, sweet, sour, etc., I presuppose that the person to whom I address them has known by expe- rience, i. e., by intuition, what they signify ; that he has either seen these colors and tasted these tastes, or those which are in some respects like them. If he has had no intuitive or analogous ex- perience of them, my words convey to him no meaning. The same is true of all the so-called simple ideas of Locke, which are the constituent elements of all those which are complex. It should be remembered, however, that language may be used either for philosophical thought on the one hand, or pictorial and emotional effect on the other. In the one case, the mind is occu- pied with the more abstract and general relations of objects. In the other, those which are broader and more obvious are em- ployed, often solely for the excitement and gratification of the emotions. In both cases, use must be made of the objects and images of individual experience. But in the first, the relations concerned are less dependent upon the individual images which happen to be suggested, because to convey or awaken general relations is the chief end. The individual examples by which each individual hearer or reader verifies or illustrates these con- cepts and their relations, is of less importance, provided he under- stands their import. But even here intuition is far better than symbolic knowledge ; rather should it be said, intuition with thought is far better than symbolic knowledge without intuition. The most careful defini- tion of a mountain, the ocean-surf, a cataract, a giraffe, a palm-tree, may convey impressions far less satisfactory, and far less accu- rate, than tHe inspection of a moment might furnish, provided 356 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 210. the inspection leads to thought — i. e., to the formation or verifi- cation of concepts. With the concrete before us, our concepts are more exact, because we see for ourselves. The concrete also furnishes the material for any new concepts which we ourselves may form directly from their objects. The defects of mere words and of the images which they awaken in comparison with actual intuition are still more striking when the objects are described rather than defined, and for the purposes of vivid impression and excited feeling. One is forcibly im- pressed with these defects, when he reads a description of a scene in nature with which he is personally familiar ; especially if he reads it with the scene actually before him. However graphic or complete the description may be, it is but a lifeless outline when compared with the fulness and vividness of the reality, or with the throng of images which are awakened in the memory. The impressions received from words by one who has never wit- nessed the reality, are but as thin and pallid shadows, when con- trasted with fall and glowing intuitions. The most exact descrip- tion of the falls of Niagara is a very different thing to one who has recently seen the cataract, or who reads with his eye open upon the scene, from what it can be to one who has never seen its wonders. If a person has never seen any waterfall, it is still more impotent to instruct the mind. These facts bring to light very distinctly the truth that lan- guage operates to a very great extent by suggesting the images and remembrances which have been gained by the experience and observation of each individual person. Besides the direct office of instructing the mind, it serves to awaken a multitude of kindred images and facts which are suggested by them. Words which to one are dead and meaningless are to another full of life and import. Words meant only in kindness may awaken images of sorrow and pain. The reader of poetry must have somewhat of a poet's power to receive and re-create. The stu- dent of philosophy must have something of a philosopher's reach and insight, to understand and judge what he reads. There is a large class of facts and truths, as well of scenes and events, to which language can do but scant justice. These are those to which the facts and events which we know and have experienced are only remotely analogous. Language is feeble § 210. NATURE OF THE CONCEPT. 357 to convey to the inhabitant of a plain or a prairie, the impressions of mountain scenery ; to the stranger to woods, the grandeur of an aboriginal forest ; to one who has always lived inland, the glory and the beauty of the ocean. When the means of finding analogies are still more scanty, the communication by language is still less successful. How curiously do we endeavor to anticipate what may be the scenes and objects to which another life may introduce us ! But how feeble is our power to imagine these, because our stock of analoga is so scanty ! We desire most earnestly that description in lan- guage may convey to us the desired information. But language may be to a large extent inadequate, because all the images of which language can avail itself must of necessity be taken from the scenes of the present state of being. It is sometimes asserted that the Infinite Spirit can have no common relations with the finite, — that all our conceptions of the infinite, being finite, must there- fore be inadequate and unworthy ; and that, consequently, all attempts of language to convey knowledge from the higher to the lower must be forever impossible, because the media — t. e., the images and concepts — must both be finite. This is urged against the possibility of any communication from God through the forms of finite nature, or by the media of human speech. It may be granted that, to the mind, in its studies of nature, the images that are suggested or pre- sented, and the language founded on such images, are wholly inadequate to express the divine, because they are finite ; it may be granted even that the concepts of spiritual relations must necessarily be interpreted and illustrated by images taken from finite objects, and that so far there are essential defects in all our imagi- nations concerning God : yet it may remain true that there are relations of simi- larity and analogy between the finite and the infinite spirit, which render it pos- sible that tbe one should be understood by the other, and that the language which describes the one to the other should convey actual truth. The infinitude of God may not exclude personality, which itself establishes a likeness between man and God. Personality may involve similarity of know- ledge in respect to all the higher relations of truth. A common sympathy may rest upon a similarity of emotional capacities, while similarity in the still higher endowment of a personal will, may render possible a similar moral goodness. These likenesses or analogies, may coexist with the greatest disparities in every other respect. The one being may be infinite and the Creator; the other may be finite and created ; and yet the One, by indications through his works and com- munications by his word, may make himself truly, if not perfectly, known. The imagination of the finite may be inadequate to picture the infinite, and yet the thinking of the finite may apprehend the relations by which the infinite first thinks and therefore creates, and in creating manifests himself to the created. 358 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 211, CHAPTER V. JUDGMENT, AND THE PROPOSITION. § 211. The processes already considered, and which im P ife U d d f™the are involved in forming and applying notions, are uTe^fthec^ alike in this; they are all acts of judgment. The cept ' mind cannot know, — much less can it think, without judging. To think, is to judge. Even in forming or evolving its notions — that is, in providing itself with the materials for what arc usually called acts of judgment — the mind must judge. The truth of this assertion is evident from the following con- siderations. (1.) It is evident from an analysis of the act itself. If we retrace the steps which we have taken in forming concepts, we find that we cannot know attributes, except as we affirm them of individual beings. An attribute without a being is inconceivable in thought and impossible in fact. Sup- pose we meet with a series of unknown and unnamed objects, each of which has some attribute or property, that is unfamiliar and even without a name : or suppose the attribute to be familiar and nameable, while the objects are unnamed. We think and say of each of these objects, it is yellow, red, or green. In thinking or saying thus we in fact perform a process which can only be represented by some proposition, one element of which is affirmed of another : e. g., x. is yelloiv, red, or green ; or if each is as yet unnamed, £ [individual] is y [general]. The nearest and best expression of this act which we find in any form of language is the impersonal verb, as, it shines, it lightens, it rains, in the use of which the unnamed being is present to the senses, and the at- tribute is judged or affirmed of it. (2.) It is still further implied in the truth already developed, that every notion is by its very nature and essence relative, i. e., related to individual objects or actually existing things. (3.) The same is evident from the consideration of the meaning of names, or notions in language. A name is the verbal symbol of a concept or notion. But to be a name, it must be a name of some object or objects; some object must be called by it ; it must be applied to some thing or being. But these acts imply judgment. § 212. JUDGMENT, AND THE PROPOSITION. 359 (4.) It is implied by the nature and definition of knowledge. An act of knowledge has already been shown to be necessarily and universally an act of judgment, whether it takes the form of presentation, representation, or thought. Every such act implies the apprehension of an object as existing ; and more, its existence in some relation. If it is true that knowledge by perception and memory implies judgment, much more does knowledge by thought; forasmuch as the general with which thought has to do, can by its very essence and nature, be only a relative and a predicable entity. We conclude then that wherever there is a notion, there is an implied act of judgment. Every such notion has been formed by judgment, and is capable of being expanded into a judgment. It is an organic thing, representing in its very essence the act which gave it being, and capable of being developed into similar though more complex products. It is like a seed, which is a miniature plant, having come from a plant and being ready to spring into a plant ; or it is like the cell which is the organized and organizing element of development in vegetable or animal life. We do not judge by a mechanical and superinduced act of the intellect, which, finding two names or notions, proceeds to fasten them together ; but it is of the very nature of the notion, that it can be applied or united to some object. This natural and neces- sary act of union or synthesis is an act of judgment. The true doctrine may be stated thus : every concept is a contracted judg- ment ; every judgment is an expanded concept. § 212. The judgments by which concepts are , . ° j o j sr Judgments are formed, are called primary, and psychological judg- psychological ■* J 7 * J y j n anc i logical. ments. They are distinguished by the circumstance that their subject is an existing and individual thing. Judg- ments in which concepts are affirmed or denied of one another are secondary and logical. The secondary, comparative, and logical judgments are all founded on those which are primary, natural, and psychological. To be convinced of this truth, we need only to consider the expression of judgments in language, and to trace the order of progress by which logical judgments, i. e., judgments consisting of concepts, come to be reached and un- derstood. The secondary judgment, when its subject is an individual be- ing, differs from the primary in this, that the subject is denoted 360 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 21 2. by means of a common term. Instead of saying it, we say this orange. If the subject is a universal, as all oranges, the mind gives the result of its observations or inductions, by using the concept in its largest extent. When purely mental entities are treated of, whether a fiction of the imagination, as the centaur, or a mathematical construction, as the triangle, or an abstractum, as virtue, they are treated as actually existing beings. How the sub- ^ ne ^ act ^ as a l rea( ty been established, that the ment° f £ JU el- conce pt ; by its very nature, contemplates attributes pressed in lan- on [j . an( j that concepts, like man, human, humanity, so far as their constituent attributes are concerned, stand for precisely the same content of attributes. When they are expressed in language, however, man and human differ in this, that the one word, man, denotes a being to which these at- tributes belong, and the other, human, denotes the attributes only. By what process the mind comes to be possessed of these two sorts of words, we need not here inquire. But when it does possess them, it cannot but use them. Instead of thinking or saying, it is yellow, or, it rains, the man says, orange is yellow, cloud rains. Soon he learns to say this in three ways ; this orange is yellow, some oranges are yellow, all oranges are yellow, accord- ing as he uses the general name for one, a part, or all of tho beings for which the orange stands. In order to do this, he ap- plies special terms to denote these three relations, viz., the words the, this, or one ; some [a few or many] ; and all. The fact that a concept has the two relations of extent and con- tent, fits it to be used both as the name of one or more indivi- duals, and as an attribute only. When a concept is used to de- note beings, it is used in the relation of extent. When it is used to denote attributes, it is used in the relation of content. In the secondary judgment, a concept used in its extent only is employed as the subject, taking the place of the individual intuition ; the notion as content is retained as the predicate : and the natural judgment in which only one notion is used, becomes a secondary judgment in which two notions appear. The two species of judgment are, however, essentially one and the same, inasmuch as both express what is essentially involved in the act of thinking, viz. • the act of affirming a concept of an existing being or thing. § 214. JUDGMENT, AND THE PROPOSITION. 361 § 213. The copula expresses the act of judging or The g . nifica _ affirming, whatever is the kind of judgment or the rela- li ^ z the co ~ tion affirmed. It makes no difference whether it is or is not expressed, it is still present as an element in every judg- ment. The act of judgment is the same whatever be its verbal expression, whether subject, predicate and copula are condensed in a single word, as, pluit — or expanded into two, as, it rains — or into three, as, the clouds are raining. The copula does not require or imply that there should be an actually existing material or spiritual thing or agent, of which the attribute is affirmed or thought. The being may be an imaginary being, as a centaur, or a mathematical entity, as a triangle, or an abstractum, as whiteness, or virtue, or legislation / and yet one or more attributes may be asserted or thought of each. All that the copula pro- perly signifies^ is, that the concept has this or that attribute, one or many. Whether the concept is of a real being or a thought-being is left to be deter- mined by other sources of knowledge. If a centaur is spoken of, we know it has only imaginary existence ; if a triangle, that it is a mathematical conception or construction; if virtue or legislation, we know we must go back to concrete beings, to find the realities of which these are abstracts. § 214. It has been established that every notion is classesof - ud . a contracted judgment and everv judgment is an ments - / ud s- 17 ° j j s ments of con- expanded notion, and also that every notion has two tent - relations — the relation of content and the relation of extent It follows that notions can be expanded into two kinds of judg- ments : judgments of content and judgments of extent Each of these forms of judgment require special illustration. We begin with the Judgment of Content. This is the form of all original and natural judgments. It is by a judgment of con- tent, i. e., of a common attribute or relation — that every notion is originally formed. In this form judgments most frequently occur in language. Objects are observed and their common attribute or attributes are thought, i. e., judged, of them, and the judgments when expressed in words are those propositions which abound in every language. It is only by a reflex act that the mind de- velops and employs judgments of extent. These natural judgments of content, serve the purposes of common life and of common intercourse. For the ends and uses of science we need to go further and to employ propositions of definition. In such propositions we assert not merely one or more attributes for information, but we indicate for distinction, the 16 362 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 214. attributes which make up or constitute the entire content. To satisfy the ends of science we must express what is called the whole content, since if we state only those elements which are common to this concept and many others, and omit one or more that is peculiar, we do not distinguish it from others. If we define a cir- cle as a curvilinear figure, the circle is not distinguished from an ellipse. If we define man to be a two-legged and featherless being, this is true also of a plucked chicken. Hence the rule by which we try and determine a good definition : The proposition which expresses it must be convertible. The content was called by Aristotle and the Scholastics the essence, i. e., the attributes or elements which make the notion to be what it is as a notion. Aristotle, however, also recognized in the essence that which existed really and permanently in the objects to which the concept belonged, rather than the attributes themselves which constitute the concept. He applied essence metaphysically rather than logi- cally, to the objective correlate of the concept, rather than to the concept itself as an intellectual or purely subjective product. A proposition of content properly expresses only logical truth. It very often implies, however, real existence. Propositions may concern existing beings or notions of beings to which there is no corresponding reality. The proposition as a definition only, ex- pands the content or essence of the concept, without deciding whether any corresponding reality exists in fact. When for example we define the centaur we give the attributes that make up the conception without asserting or even knowing whether such a being exists. When we define a triangle we state the essential constituents of the concept produced by the constructive imagi- nation, knowing that it has no other existence. When we define man we both define the concept and believe the concept is realized in actual fact. The definition of centaur implies only thought- essence or logical truth. The definition of man implies both logical and real truth. The copula is, in the one case signifies is defined as or consists of; in the other — is defined as and really exists. In very many cases we readily interpret the meaning of the copula and the character of the judgment and definition, by our knowledge of the subject-matter. In other cases we have no § 215. JUDGMENT, AND THE PROPOSITION. 363 such knowledge as qualifies us to determine whether the defi- nition is really true, as well as logically consistent. Suppose any one of the following concepts is to be defined : virtue, duty, in- alienable right, natural liberty, tyranny, a sovereign state. It is of essential importance to know whether the definition concerns only the concept as a mental product, existing in and for the mind only, or whether there are actual relations and activities of human nature, to which the concept corresponds. In the first instance we should need to consider only, whether the concept is correctly defined as the term is ordinarily used, or_as this or that school of philosophers or politicians have conceived it. In the second, we should inquire, whether it answers to a truth of fact, i. e., whether the concept has a corresponding reality. Scientific truth implies both logical and real truth. Logical truth is but another name for logical consistency. A dexterous logician, if suffered to frame his own concepts and construct his own propositions, may easily frame a system which shall have sufficient truth to give plausibility to all that is defective by omission, or false by positive error. Every definition should therefore be scrutinized both as to its consistency and its truth. It should always be remembered that a proposition may be logi- cally true and yet really false, while science requires that the definition should not only be logically consistent and logically complete, but also really exhaustive and actually true. § 215. The proposition of extent is the natural Stents ° f consequent of the proposition of content. The pro- position of content is first in time, because the knowledge of the individual goes before the knowledge of the general. As soon, however, as a single attribute is affirmed as common to many individuals, then this common attribute can be employed as itself dividing or separating these individuals into a class by themselves. As soon as we think, This house is white, it is pos- sible for us to refer the house to the class of white objects. But because every generalized attribute may classify the objects to which it belongs, it does not follow that the mind recognizes it in this relation, or expresses the relation in language. It is not till the adjective, white, becomes a noun, that we use it as a classifier, and think or say, whites, i. e., white men, are English, French, etc., etc., or white things are so and so. It is not till we 364 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §215. turn back upon our thinking, and recognize the fact that these attributes divide into classes the beings to which they belong, and even go further and notice that some classes of objects are wider and some narrower than others, that we have occasion to think of these notions in their extent, or to expand them into proposi- tions expressing this relation. Propositions of extent like those of content, strictly considered, only assert logical truth — i, e., the subordinate classes into which the concept is divided. But they often imply the real existence of the objects to which both the comprehending genus and the included species belong. Propositions of extent, whether used in common life or for the purposes of science, are clearly distinguishable from propositions of content. It is, however, easy to confound the one with the other ; and easy to interchange the one with the other. Indeed we are often tempted to translate the propositions which express the one into those which express the other. We cannot say that man is an animal without implying that he possesses those attri- butes which are involved in the concept and the term animal. Whenever we assert that man is a species of which animal is a genus, we must ascribe to man certain attributes. Conversely, we cannot assert certain attributes of man without placing him in a distinct class. These facts are not at all inconsistent with the truth that at some times we use propositions with sole refer- ence to their content, and at other times with exclusive respect to their extent. Indeed, the use of propositions of extent is a neces- sary condition and consequence of logical division. But if division is distinguishable from definition, then are propositions of extent clearly distinguishable from propositions of content. As definition gives complete propositions of content, so division gives exact and complete propositions of extent. Both pro- cesses are involved in the beginnings of thinking. They are only carried forward to their completed perfection when wo reach the precise and comprehensive knowledge which science attains. Both are the necessary conditions of the formation and use ''of general terms, and are the constant accompaniments of language. Both are perfect in their ideal aims whenever the definitions in any branch of knowledge become precise and true, and the divisions orderly and exhaustive. § 216. JUDGMENT, AND THE PROPOSITION. 365 § 216. It is a superficial view to regard scientific Scientific and x ' i common know- knowledge as different in kind from common know- ledge. ledge : to reason as though the man of science has developed in- tellectual powers which are peculiar to himself, or has discovered special processes or rules having no relation to those which are natural to all men. The powers employed by the true phi- losopher and the uncultured are the same. The common man thinks as really, and in his way as effectively and as sagaciously, as does the philosopher. Often it is not easy to find the dividing line which separates common from scientific knowledge. We cannot say, in the history of any branch of knowledge, Here common knowledge ceases and science begins : At this point he who knows as a man, begins to know as a philosopher. Of some sciences it is true, that at a certain period of their development, common terms are exchanged for those which are technical, and a scholastic, some- times a repulsive nomenclature takes the place of words which are familiar from use and warm with grateful associations. Even objects that in the earliest classifications had been grouped together by afimities so close that they seem to have a necessary and unbroken relationship, are strangely separated, and find them- selves suddenly in a new and unpleasant society. Plants and trees apparently the most alike are thrown into the most distant groups, and those which are apparently the most diverse and dissimilar are inexplicably brought together. In those sciences which are less technical in their definitions and classifications, the lines of transition and division are not even suspected. We cannot find the place where science in its technical form begins, and formally takes its leave of common knowledge. In Psycho- logy, Ethics, Politics, Law and Theology, common terms are in a great measure still retained ; they are only employed with a more careful definition and a more exact application. Science when viewed in the light of our analysis, is simply Jsnowledge by concepts carefully defined in.order to a complete divi- sion and a methodized arrangement of the things or objects to which these concepts are applicable. In forming scientific notions, the mind discovers relations and attributes which it had never ob- served before. In looking more patiently, it observes more closely. As it proceeds to use and apply the notions already 366 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 217. attained, in the processes of deduction and induction which are yet to be explained, it discerns still other relations of likeness and unlikeness. As it proceeds in its triumphant course it still continues to define and divide. Science began when it formed the first proposition of content. This involved a proposition of extent. It will have finished its course and completed the circle of its possible triumphs, when it shall have exhausted all that is knowable by these two processes, each involving the other — when it shall have arranged in systematic order, everything which can be known, by complete and subordinated divisions as the result of true and exhaustive definitions. CHAPTER VI. EEASONING. — DEDUCTION OR MEDIATE JUDGMENT. Nature and im- § 217. The process of thought or mode of think- portance of rea- i n g which we are naturally led to consider next in order is reasoning. That to reason is a function of the thinking power, will be questioned by none. By many it is esteemed its special and almost its sole function, a function which absorbs all the rest into itself. Many make the capacity to reason to be the exclusive and distinctive endowment of man, striving to account for all the other thought-processes by resolving them into this. Reasoning, also, like every other act or mode of know- ing, is itself an act of judgment. It is distinguished from judg- ment proper by being mediate and indirect ; whereas judgments proper are immediate and direct. The acts of judgment proper have already been explained as acts in which a general notion is thought or affirmed of an in- dividual being, or a concept, by direct inspection and comparison. When, for example, we judge of ten apples, that they are red, or oval, or round, or of equal or unequal weight, or of similar taste or odor, we perform acts of direct or immediate judgment. But when we reason concerning them, that because they are red, § 218. REASONING. — DEDUCTION OR MEDIATE JUDGMENT. 367 or similar in odor, therefore they taste alike, we judge indirectly or mediately ; we consider, not only the apples themselves, but the relation of one of their properties to another. This truth is implied in the remark that in judgment we compare two notions, and discern or pronounce that the notions agree or disagree; whereas in reasoning we compare two judgments, and declare or discern that the judgments agree or disagree. If we distinguish the process of reasoning from the product or result — as in the other acts of the intellect — we should call the first reasoning and the second an argument The latter is exclusively limited to deduction. § 218. The process called reasoning is two-fold, in- 7- 777. T'i -it Reasoning, in- ductive and deductive. It is known by the two names, ductive and de- induction and deduction. These two are sufficiently distinguished by the following definitions : In deduction the mind begins with general propositions, and reasons to those which are particular or individual ; in induction, it reasons from individual or particular to general judgments. In deduction we assume or imply that the mind is already fur- nished with judgments or beliefs that are more or less general, and proceed to derive from them, those which are particular or singular. In other words, we apply the predicate of a general proposition to a particular or individual, to which we had never applied it before. For example : ' we ought in every act to con- sult the wishes of our parents ; therefore we ought to do this in choosing our business in life.' In induction, on the contrary, we proceed from singular or particular to general propositions or truths. We observe that one or several pieces of iron-ore, with certain characteristics, are magnetic. We infer that every similar piece of iron-ore is magnetic. Both these processes are called processes of reasoning. The means employed, i. e., the grounds or foundations of each, whether they are general or particular propositions or individual facts, are called reasons, sometimes data. But to reason par emi- nence, is to perform the process of deduction; and reasons or grounds of belief are preeminently those general principles or truths from which we derive or deduce particular conclusions. Hence, when we use the words to reason and a reason, we are usually understood to have in mind the deductive process. On the 368 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 219. other hand, we say freely that we reason by induction or induc- tively ; and no phrases are more common than inductive reasoning and reasoning by induction. These two processes are usually combined together in every case in which our knowledge is enlarged by what we call reason- ing. When we use examples of reasoning for the purpose of illustrating the nature of the process, we seem to be able to sepa- rate deduction from induction. But whenever we reason with the express design of adding to our knowledge, or of increasing our confidence in that which we already possess, both processes are called into requisition. If, for example, we should reason de- ductively, to prove to a person who did not already believe it, that a particular act of obedience, or perhaps of resistance, to the government, was obligatory ; we should use the process of induc- tion to prove that such an act was distinguished by the character- istics or criteria which showed it to come under the duties of a loyal citizen. In many cases of induction, also, the process of deduction is brought into requisition. "We can scarcely suppose that Frank- lin established the identity of lightning with machine electricity, without asking himself many times over what would be the con- sequents in fact, if bis hypothesis should prove true. We know that Sir Isaac Newton drew certain inferences from the supposi- tion that the law of gravitation was real, when combined with a false datum in respect to the earth's diameter ; and because ob- served facts did not coincide with the theory, he did not accept the theory which his so-called induction had already reached. Induction and Deduction, like the analysis and synthesis of which they are special forms, accompany each other in all the higher processes of thought. The two blend together so inti- mately that it is often difficult to sever them, or to find or trace the line where the one begins and the other terminates. Thus far we have considered Deduction and Induction together. We proceed to study them apart, chiefly from a psychological point of view — beginning with Deduction. § 219. Our chief inquiry is, what is the proper deduction? 80 conception of the deductive as an intellectual process; and incidental to this, what is the nature and what are the results of the product which it evolves. To answer this § 219. REASONING DEDUCTION OR MEDIATE JUDGMENT. 369 question satisfactorily we must consider, first of all, the forms of language in which the process is expressed and its results are preserved. These forms are two, the Enthymeme and the Syllogism, or the abbreviated and the expanded syllogism. The enthymeme consists of two expressed propositions, which are connected by because or therefore. The syllogism consists of three, of which the first two are simple assertions, and the third is introduced by therefore. For i -nr • f usurper, ) , 7 r 7 (cannot exact obedience;) example, M is a. [ i awfu f ru { ery \ therefore he [ ougU to be oheijed . j -mt ( cannot exact allegiance,) 7 7 . f a usurper ; ) or > M j ought to be obeyed, ) became he IS \alamful ruler ;\ are examples of the two forms of the enthymeme. j Every lawfuTruSr require allegiance > "! "vf • f a usurper, ) , ■• «? "IM" J cannot require ought to be obeyed; J Jyi 1S ( a lawful ruler, J tneretore 1Vi ( ought to be obeyed? 06 ' } are examples of the expanded syllogism. In the enthymeme, the first proposition may be either the con- clusion, or it may be the reason. In the syllogism, the first proposition is called the major premise ; the second, the minor premise ; and the third, the conclusion. The two premises of every syllogism must have one term common to both, which is called the middle term. In the ex- amples given — lawful ruler and usurper are the middle terms respectively of the two syllogisms. Unless there is this middle term, there is no force or convincing power in the argument: if we introduce two middle terms, there is no conclusion. The middle term must also have the relation affirmed to the other two. If we substitute worthy or unworthy person for lawful ruler or usurper, the conclusion will be false. Every enthymeme can be expanded into a syllogism. The syllogism when expanded expresses in separate propositions the truths which the enthymeme implies. There is in every enthy- meme the suppressed premise of a syllogism. When we reason in the examples given, M is a lawful ruler, therefore he ought to be obeyed, or M ought to be obeyed because he is the lawful ruler, we believe and imply in the argument — though we do not assert — that every lawful ruler ought to be obeyed. This is the major premise of the syllogism into which the enthymeme is by this addition expanded. The difference between the enthymeme and the syllogism is onlv a difference between a contracted and 16* 370 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §220. an expanded form of expression ; or between an elliptical and a fully explicated sentence. It is a difference of language only, and not in the least a difference of thought or of the relations of thought or knowledge ; what is expressed in the one, being implied in the other. n T ot e a u"°S?r § 22 °* The syllogism is the only form which fully tiorT ° f dedu ° expresses in language all the processes in the act of deduction. Some have contended that it is one of the forms of deduction, but not the sole form appropriate to it. Thus, Princi- pal Campbell in his Philosophy of Rhetoric contends that the syl- logistic is only one of the possible methods of reasoning, while there are others which are in many cases greatly to be pre- ferred to this ; and J. S. Mill, in his Logic, urges that it is not a form of reasoning at all, but a convenient expedient for recording and referring to the results of our experience in particular or individual cases. It is obvious, for the reasons already given, that it is a form into which all deductive reasoning may be phrased, and it is the one and the only form in which all the materials considered and the relations involved are fully stated in language. When for example we supply the premise that had been suppressed in the enthymeme, we do not add that which is superfluous to the process through which we have gone, or to the argument w'lich the process implied. We simply express in language what we had thought or were ready to think in fact — that which if we had not believed when we drew our conclusion, we should not have reached it at all. Thus, if we did not believe that all lawful rulers ought to be obeyed, we could not reach the inference that M ought to be obeyed because he is the lawful ruler. Again ; In the syllogism the process of reasoning is fully ex- panded and complete. Any additional propositions, whether connected with either of the premises or with the conclusion, are seen at once to be a premise or a conclusion of another syllo- gism. If for example we enlarge the premise, "all lawful rulers ought to be obeyed," by the reason " because it is the will of God, or an obvious duty," we introduce an additional process of reasoning, the object of which is to prove that the first premise is correct. If we add a reason for holding that M is a lawful ruler, as " because he has been properly commissioned or §221. REASONING. DEDUCTION OR MEDIATE JUDGMENT. 371 fairly elected," we do the same for the second premise. If we annex to the conclusion an additional remark, as " therefore M ought to be obeyed, and to disobey him is a serious crime," we simply introduce a second conclusion, which requires another ar- gument to support it. Every argument, whether positive or negative, whether the propositions are universal or particular, can be expressed in the form which has already been stated, by changes in the phrase- ology or the position of the terms, without affecting the sense or the force of the argument. This is demonstrated at length in every treatise on formal logic. A few examples will suffice for our purpose. If we make the first premise negative by substituting " no lawful ruler should be disobeyed," the real nature of the argument is not changed. The same is true if in the second premise we substi- tute "M rules lawfully" for "M is a lawful ruler" — a proposition of content for one of extent. If we change the form of the first premise by inverting the order of the terms, that is, by conversion, which we can do with the negative premise and retain its full meaning, we bring the middle term into the predicate of each of the premises ; but the argument and its power to prove a conclusion are the same. If we convert the second, or minor premise, we bring the mid- dle term into the subject of each premise, but this does not alter the strength of the argument. If we transpose the order of the premises, the relation of each part to the conclusion is the same, whatever may be the order in which the two are uttered. All these changes can be made in the arrangement of the parts of the syllogism, without affecting the nature or force of the argument. § 221. The rules for testing the validity of the , The dicta or ° o J formulas of the syllogism may all be founded on the maxim, usually syllogism. called the dictum de omni et nidlo. It is as follows : whatever is predicated of a class either affirmatively or negatively, may be affirmed of whatever is contained in or under the clasp. For this dictum, later logicians have substituted the maxim, Nota notes est etiam nota rei, rejougnans notee repugned etiam rei. This is adopted by J. S. Mill in his Logic, I., c. ii, § 3. It is the same in principle with the dictum of Aristotle. The same is 372 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §221. true of the special construction of the syllogism proposed by Hamilton, by which the propositions are stated in relations of quantity, and the dictum de omni et nullo is displaced by whatever is a part of a part is a part of the containing whole. In another form this dictum would be founded on the fact that the middle term, as it is a concept, stands to other notions in the two relations of extent and content, and would read thus, " A notion that is, or is not, in any extent, may, or may not, take to itself the notion which is of its content." The last formula has the advantage of stating concisely both the likeness and the differ- ence between an act of judgment and an act of reasoning. For in an act of judgment, as we have seen, a concept may be expanded either in the direction of its extent or of its content. So far as the single act of judgment is concerned, the notion is viewed in only one relation, that of its extent or of its content, as the case may be. But in an act of reasoning, a notion, i. e., the middle term, is viewed in both these relations at once, and the result is that a relation is developed and observed between notions, which had not been discerned before. But neither the relations of a genus to a species nor those of a part to a whole, nor those of extent and content combined, give to the premises of the syllogism the power of demonstration. They suggest and they test the validity of a syllogism, but they do not explain that in the deductive process which gives it convin- cing power over the mind. No syllogism is valid to which the dictum de omni et nullo cannot be applied, but it does not follow that the maxim expresses the real ground of our faith in the psy- chological process which we call deduction. The relations of both major and minor terms to the extent and the content of the middle, may be the only relations that need to be expressed in language, and yet may not develop or exhibit the real relation which leads to our assent to the conclusion. In point of fact, every attempt to explain the deductive pro- cess, as such, by these relations, has failed, and the failure of these attempts has perpetually exposed the doctrine of the syllo- gism to suspicion and contempt. Cf. Locke, Essay, B. IV., Chap. 17, §§ 4-8; G. Campbell, Phil, of Rhetoric, B. I, Chap. 6; D. Stewart, Elements, P. II., Chaps. 2, 3 & 4 ; J. S. Mill, System of Logic, B. II., Chap. 3; S. Bailey, Theory of Reasoning. § 222. REASONING. — DEDUCTION OR MEDIATE JUDGMENT. 373 The real error or defect consists in making the essence or im- port of both induction and deduction to consist in classification and the apprehension of class relations. If induction consists only or chiefly in establishing general facts by extended observa- tion, then deduction must by consequence signify the recognition of what must already have been known in the formation of the class. If induction is a synthesis of individuals into a compre- hensive whole, then deduction must be an analysis of this whole into its parts. If the synthesis has been carefully made, then the analysis is unnecessary because it is superfluous. According to this view of the two processes, deduction is only subsidiary to in- duction, and when we seem to perform the process of demonstra- tion or proof, it is the inductive and not the deductive element which gives it any value or force. § 222. The relation which is characteristic of the deductive process is that of a reason to its consequent, Jn^reSon or of a ground to its inference. It is by means of ^n™^^ t0 this relation that we know objects by means of this process of knowledge. This relation is suggested to the mind in the syllogism by the relation of a whole to a part, but it is not therefore resolvable into this relation, nor should it be confounded with it. When we say, all magnets attract iron ; this is a magnet ■ therefore it attracts iron ; the word all suggests or indicates that there is some reason founded on the nature or properties of the magnet, which forces us to believe that this particular magnet will do the same. This relation finds expression in language by because in the enthymeme, and by therefore in the syllogism. Because signifies by cause of. Therefore means for, i. e., on account of that, viz., that which had been . previously stated in the pre- mises ; there being equivalent to the foregoing. Both words signify by reason of. In other words, in order to explain the process of deductive reasoning, we must assume that every thing that exists and occurs, whether in the material or spirit world, exists and occurs under the real relation of causation, or constituent elements and laws. Every phenomenon and every thought-creation in the universe exists by the workings of powers with which finite agents are en- dowed, in obedience to fixed conditions and laws, in order to accomplish rational ends or results. Every such existence is an 374 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §222. effect ; material things, spiritual agents, nay, even mathematical and logical concepts. The nature and the constitution of these effects are all explained by the causes, conditions, and ends, by, under, and for which, they are conceived to exist and to act. Any one of these elements, when applied to explain their existence, or to confirm our knowledge when we seek explanation or proof, is called a reason. When such a reason is discovered to explain or account for a fact or phenomenon, the process is called induction. When it is applied to impart or confirm knowledge concerning a fact or truth in respect to which the mind seeks to be informed or convinced, the process is called deduction. To know by either or both of these processes is to know by a reason, — it is to reason, ratiocinari ; it is reasoning, ratiocinatio. For proof of this we appeal to the process of reasoning itself. In doing so, we should not employ any of those trivial examples which occur in most books of logic, but rather select some exam- ple of the process of deduction when it is of actual service, i. e., when it is employed to relieve the mind from doubt, or to answer its questionings as to what is true. In every such case we shall find that the mind has no direct access to the object before it, and can gain no immediate or intuitive knowledge. It is the cause, the effect or the law, the end or the means, — one side or term, — to which the mind has any means of access. But it knows or may know that under the law of causation this is necessarily connected with the other term. The use of this relation for the relief of doubt or the acquisition of knowledge, is reasoning. When the relation of causation is applied to this use it passes into the rela- tion of reason and its cob sequent. The necessary connection in- volved in causation when thus applied gives to deduction con- vincing force. This discerned necessary connection between a cause and its effect, means and end, etc., etc., is what we call the force of demonstration or deduction. That tho deductive process and the syllogism aro founded on the relation of causality was distinctly taught by Aristotle. Ho remarks, Anal. Post., II., 2 : to nei> yap alnov to pdaov, which means in this connection, tho middle term, is causal in its significance. To the liko effect is the passage, Anal. Post., II., 12, to yap fxeo-ov alnov. Aristotle distinguishes between tJte catise of being and the cause of knowing, — ratio essendi and ratio cognoscendi, i. e., between tlie cause and the reason, but ho does not show how tho ono is related to tho other. Tho later Greek logicians being more occupied with tho forms of the syllogism § 223. REASONING. DEDUCTION OR MEDIATE JUDGMENT. 375 and its application to the detection of fallacies than with its psychological import, left very much out of view this important hint of their great master. The scholas- tics committed the double error of believing that the syllogism was the sole instru- ment of acquiring new knowledge, or of discovery properly so-called, to the neglect of induction ; and of supposing that the formal relations of the syllogism constituted and measured all the relations of things. Hence the axioms were so generally received in the Continental schools, that the principles of identity, of con- tradiction, and excluded middle — the so-called laws of thought — are the only criteria of real truth and actual knowledge, and that the process of deduction itself can be explained by these axioms. Leibnitz is a distinguished and notable exception to this nearly uniform course of speculation. He asserts that, for the purpose of philosophy, besides the principle of contradiction another is required, viz., the principle of the sufficient reason. But the principle of the sufficient reason of Leibnitz is explained and applied by himself indifferently, alike to the causes of actually existing phe- nomena and the reasons of demonstrated truth. That is, the ratio essendi is not distinguished from the ratio cognoscendi, and of course there is no attempt to show the relation of the one to the other. It is not surprising that a principle so imperfectly enounced did not take a permanent place in the schools of philo- sophy. Even Wolf himself, Leibnitz's professed disciple and expounder (OntoL, g 70 sqq. ; Met., $ 30 sqq.), attempts to resolve the law of causation and the suffi- cient reason into the law of contradiction. The tendency of modern philosophy has been to consider the law of the sufficient reason as extra-logical (Hamilton, D?'s.,p. 603), or to derive it in both forms, of real and logical cause, from the relations of concepts to concepts, instead of founding the ratio cognoscendi on tho ratio essendi, i. e., on the relations of things ; thereby inverting the processes of nature and destroying confidence in the grounds of knowledge and of faith. § 223. The conception of the logical reason is • i • •, -t v ,• ,i ,i , n ,i The relation of wider in its range and application than that 01 the logical reasons i i • i •, • p t i mi i • to causes and real cause on which it is rounded, ihe real cause is i awB . usually prior to the effect which it produces. The mind in apprehending or observing its actual workings, assumes or supposes the cause, in order to anticipate or explain the actual effect. But in applying this relation for the purposes of reason- ing, the mind may begin with the effect and conclude to a cause, as properly as when it begins with the cause and reasons to an effect. Either involves the other in a connection of thought ; either can be made to imply the other in the order of deduction or reasoning. The reason and the cause coincide, when from an actual cause, (the conditions and laws being included or supposed,) we reason to the certainty or reality of the effect. Thus the fire did or will fall into a vessel of gunpowder, therefore an explosion did or will occur. They diverge, when we reason from the effect to the 376 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §224. cause, i. e., when the effect is made the reason for our belief in or knowledge of the cause : as the vessel of gunpowder exploded, therefore heat in some form was present. The known effect is in this case the reason for the believed or proved conclusion. In a similar way we reason both forwards and backwards from the means to the end and from the end to the means, making either the end or the means the reason, and the means or the end the conclusion. So in moral action we reason from the motives forward to the act or purpose, and backward from the act or purpose to the impelling motives, making either the reason for believing the other, with such reservations as the nature of their mutual activity requires. The distinction should also be noticed between causes, i: e. powers, and laws. Laws designate those permanent circumstances or relations which, though not separate agents themselves, modify the production of the effect, so that with or without these, the effect does or does not actually occur, or the energy of the effect varies as these circumstances vary. The best example of a law as distinguished from, a cause or agent, is the law of gravitation — according to which the force varies inversely as the square of the distance. For the purposes of reasoning, however, the law may be viewed as giving efficiency to the cause ; i. e., the power in question, e. g., gravitation, is known or manifested as a cause which we can apply in deduction, so far as or when it obeys certain laws. § 224. When we employ reasons to prove geomet- r-asons ietrical r ^ ca ^ truth, the grounds of the process and the conviction which it imparts are found in the nature of the materials conceived as necessitating certain products or effects in a way similar to that in which an existing agent, whether matter or spirit, brings to pass its results. The triangle, square, cube and sphere are regarded as possessed of certain properties, which, when subjected to certain changes, or brought into certain combinations, make the existence of certain other properties necessary. The ratio essendi, or the conceived proper- ties of the geometrical figures'' in space as constructed by the mind becomes the ratio cognoscendi. The geometrical figure is regarded as having causal efficiency, the effects or consequences of which cannot be set aside. § 224. REASONING. — DEDUCTION OR MEDIATE JUDGMENT. 377 Thus: two triangles are similar, i. e., their sides and cor- responding angles are equal, because they are the halves made by the diagonal of a parallelogram. The reason is found in the properties of the parallelogram. But these properties are deter- mined by the constructive acts of the mind, space being assumed as allowing the mind to conceive or construct certain figures. These figures when constructed are divided, i. e., new figures are constructed — they are compared with each other — they are su- perimposed upon one another — in short, there is a series of con- secutive acts passing into effects, the acts determining the effects, and the effects being determined or defined by the mind's acts and the material, viz., space, with which it works. We reason from these acts, i. e., from that conceived as the cause to the effect, or from the effect back to the cause, precisely as when the cause and effect are material. The same is true, when we reason from the essential consti- tuents of a logical concept ; or construct what some logicians call immediate syllogisms, e. g., conclusions of logical conversion, etc. These last scarcely deserve to be called proper, as the process is merely formal. But if they are so regarded, then the parts and the whole, from one to the other of which in such cases we reason, have been previously fixed by the thinking power, or the power to generalize at all. These logical products, as wholes and parts, positives and negatives, etc., are regarded as causal of certain results to any objects brought into certain relations with them. They are reasoned of as though they were actually exist- ing beings with causal properties obeying unchanging laws. By the same rule : We say, some islands are surrounded by water, because all islands are surrounded by water. Any special act of duty can only be performed by a moral being, because duty in every case is the act of such a being. S78 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §226. CHAPTER VII. REASONING. — VARIETIES OF DEDUCTION. § 225. The sameness of the process of deduction are e ^tiree; enables us to understand the diversity in the several vided. u " varieties of deductive reasoning. These are deter- mined by the differences in the subject-matter upon or about which the process of deduction is employed, so far as this subject-matter occasions a difference in the character of the reasons upon which the reasoning depends. Material forces and reasons differ from the psychological and moral. Both these are •unlike the mathematical. Those which are purely logical differ from all the others. These differences in the subject matter also require a special preparation in each case, in order to make it ready for the application of the deductive process proper. The varieties of deductive reasoning usually recognized are the Probable, the Mathematical, and the Formal. Probable reasoning is again subdivided into three, the physi- cal, the psychological, and the historical, according as the subject- matter is physical beings and phenomena, spiritual agents and their manifestations, or those combinations of the two which make up human history. It is often called applied reasoning, because its materials are facts known by observation and induc- tion, and its processes are applied to the materials thus acquired or furnished. Mathematical reasoning is threefold, according as it is con- cerned with continued or discrete quantity, or as it combiues the methods appropriate to each. It is geometrical, arithmetical and analytical. Formal reasoning concerns itself with pure concepts abstracted from all beings and phenomena, and with the relations which such concepts involve. It is sometimes technically styled simply logical deduction, and its arguments are called immediate, or purely logical, syllogisms. § 226. In probable or applied deduction, we may eoning. s iea " for the present assume that the premises are fur- nished by induction and observation. In applied § 226. REASONING. — VARIETIES OF DEDUCTION. 379 reasoning as defined, induction is always necessary to furnish major premises, because there can be no reasons, if there are no general or universal powers or laws. For minor premises in these cases, observation often suffices, because it often furnishes individual facts or events. When these minor premises affirm any thing of a class of generalized objects, induction may be re- quired as well as observation. This description of reasoning is called probable, sometimes problematical and moral, simply because the subject-matter depends on causes which are con- tingent and is not necessarily true. Its reality cannot be proved by demonstrative evidence. As such it is contrasted with the mathematical and formal, the subject-matter of which is in no sense a real being or event, and is dependent on no contingency for its existence or occurrence, but on the properties or relations of mathematical and logical concepts. The terms probable, etc., do not, however, imply that the processes involved are less valid or convincing, or that the premises or conclusions are less trustworthy. But whether the reasoning process, as such, relates to facts of matter, to facts of spirit, or to facts of history, it rests upon reasons in the way already explained. The facts are reasoned out whenever the power or law with its conditions is employed to prove that they must have occurred inasmuch as the causes exist which require them ; or whenever facts or events known to exist are explained by being referred to such agencies or laws. Thus, the suspended weight let loose, it is reasoned, must fall, because the force of gravitation is always in action ; or the reason why it fell, or why it ought to be believed that it fell, is that this power was acting at the time, under certain of its laws. In the sphere of spirit, I reason that at the thought of Han- nibal I shall always think of Fabius, because the two, by asso- ciation, have become permanently fixed in my thoughts. By a reference to the operation of this power under its laws, I explain the fact, that I thought of Fabius a moment previous. The student and interpreter of history reasons concerning the events of the past when he seeks to explain them by their appro- priate causes and laws, or to forecast the future by means of the great forces or agencies, — the so-called principles — through which the course of events and the results of important move- ments in society can be interpreted. 380 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §227. Deduction is more satisfactory and convincing when applied to material than when applied to spiritual phenomena, because the agencies known in the one sphere are more numerous than in the other, and because the laws according to which these agencies produce their results are capable of being expressed in mathematical formulae. Hence, in many of the physical sciences we apply the rigor, the certainty and the variety of geometrical deduction, as in Mechanics, Optics, Navigation, Theoretical As- tronomy and Chemical Analysis. § 227. This introduces into the sphere of pure de- Mathematical . . reasoning, ma- duction a second element, viz., the mathematical, which in many of the physical sciences, is combined with that which is contingent or problematical, but which in the pure or abstract mathematics, gives character to what is called by eminence mathematical reasoning. The objects or entities with which mathematical reasoning is concerned, are constructed by the mind itself on the suggestion of, and of course with reference to, certain material things and occurring acts, which are related to one another in space and time. Hence these entities themselves have certain definite re- lations to space and time, which are called their properties. We find ourselves, at a certain stage of intellectual develop- ment, possessed of the concepts which are employed in geometry, arithmetic, and algebra — as the Point, the Line, the Superficies, the Triangle, the Square, the Circle, the Cube, the Sphere, the Cone, etc., as also the Unit, the Sum, the Difference, the Multiple, the Divisor and the Ratio. These are properly called concepts or general notions. The individual objects of which these concepts are affirmable are, as it would seem at first, individual objects of sense or spirit; as when we affirm a line, or point, or superficies to belong to a block of ivory. On second thought, we are sure that the mathe- matical point, line, or surface, cannot belong to any material object as such, for the reason that there are no perfectly even or sharp edges or even planes in any material object. Nor are there in nature any perfect units, exactly the counterparts of one an- other. These individual entities are then generalized, and become concepts ; having a content and extent, and being capable of § 228. REASONING. VARIETIES OF DEDUCTION. 381 definition, division, and classification. The individual and the general are however scarcely distinguished by the mind itself. Indeed, in the mathematical processes the mind passes so quickly from the individual to the general and returns so readily to the individual as not always to notice for the moment with which it has to do, whether with the lines and triangles as individuals, or with them as the representatives of all conceivable lines and tri- angles. It is another marked and distinctive peculiarity of these rela- tions, that they are clearly and entirely distinguishable from all other generalized properties. The length, breadth, etc., of any material object cannot be confounded with its sensible qualities, nor can the relations of number be mistaken for those proper- ties of matter or spirit of which sense or consciousness takes cog- nizance. Not only are they clearly separated as classes, but each member of the class is sharply separable from every other. The line can not possibly be confounded with the surface, nor the sum with the difference. § 228. These concepts, like all others, can, as has been explained, be expanded into propositions of content and Definitions and extent. Mathematical propositions of content are the definitions which state the attributes that constitute the essence of each of the complex concepts which we form by mathematical construction, as the square, the triangle, the cube, etc., etc. The best and most satisfactory definitions are those which bring directly before the mind the act or process by which the concepts are supposed to be constructed. Such definitions we sometimes phrase in the language of com- mand, as, draw me a line, move a plane, etc. For this reason they are called postulates, posiulata, i. e., concepts which may be constructed and assumed without dissent. The definitions of the concepts of number scarcely need to be given. We assume at once that all men know what they signify. When an explana- tion of them is required, we refer directly to the process of num- bering, i. e., we count by a series produced by the constant addi- tion of units. Mathematical definitions also state the entire im- port or essence of their concepts. We are certain that the defini- tions of a triangle and square are exhaustive. Such concepts are in their very nature transparent : we can see through them as 382 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §228. through crystal water to the bottom of a mountain lake. We know that the properties enumerated perfectly distinguish each concept from every other. The definition does not indeed ex- press all that is true of its concept as related to every other in every conceivable combination, (else reasoning or analysis could not add to our knowledge,) but it gives all that is essential to enable the mind to distinguish it from every other, and adequately to define what its content is. Mathematical propositions of extent are such as these : Trian- gles are plane or spherical ; and each of these is acute, obtuse, or right-angled. For the same reason that mathematical defi- nitions are exhaustive, mathematical divisions are known to be complete. As the first are exhaustive, on account of the limited number of the elements involved, it follows, that all the subdivi- sions which depend upon such elements, can be easily compassed, and confidently enumerated by the mind. Hamilton pertinently observes : " Mathematical, like all other reasoning, is syllogistic ; but here, the perspicuous necessity of the matter necessitates the correctness of the form ; we cannot reason wrong." Axioms are prominently employed in mathematical reasoning. Axioms differ from definitions in this, that they state the neces- sary relations that are involved in the nature or application of all the concepts of quantity as such, whereas the definiton expands the content or extent of some special concept. Axioms are of two species, the analytic and the synthetic. Examples of analytic axioms are such propositions as the fol- lowing, ' the whole is greater than its part,' and ' things that are equal to the same thing are equal to one another.'' They are called analytic propositions as contrasted with synthe- tic, because, as it is contended, they evolve or explicate in the predicate what is impliedly known or assumed in the subject. There is another class of axioms, such as these : Two straight lines cannot inclose a space : Two or more parallel lines, if pro- duced ever so far in either direction, can never meet. These examples apply to geometrical quantity only. These are clearly synthetical propositions. Whatever may be true of those of the other class, in axioms of this sort the predicate contains matter which the subject does not imply. And yet these propositions § 229. REASONING. — VARIETIES OF DEDUCTION. 383 are self-evident and intuitively true. They cannot and need not be demonstrated. The question has been earnestly agitated whether the axioms or the definitions are the foundations of geometrical reasoning. It has been very generally held that the axioms are the real prin- cipia upon which such reasoning depends : that is, that they are the unproved but assumed major premises of which, with certain minor premises furnished by the definitions, all those syllogisms are constructed that make up the demonstrations of geometry. It is obvious that the only kind of axioms to which this ques- tion can apply, is the first of the two classes above cited, the so- called analytic axioms. Those of the second class, all would concede, are as truly principles as are the definitions ; i. e., they are as well fitted to serve as major premises for syllogisms. The method after which the demonstrations are conducted by Euclid, has lent a decided support to this view. In all these demonstrations, these axioms are constantly cited as major premises for the truth of the conclusions which are derived from them. The arguments are in substance as follows : All things that are equal to the same thing, are equal to one another. The case of the equality of the two lines or angles A, and B, to a third C, is a case of the kind. Therefore, this is a case of their being equal to one another. — A is equal to B. Against this doctrine cf. Locke, Essay, B. iv. c. vii. § 10. Beid, Essays on the Intel. Powers, Essay vi. chaps, v. and vii. Princi- pal Campbell, Philosophy of Rhetoric, B. i. c. v. § 1. Dugald Stewart, Elements, Part ii. subd. i. c. i. sec. i. (1) and (2). For our present purpose, it is of little consequence to deter- mine whether the axioms or the definitions are or are not the foundations of geometrical deduction. In the one case we begin our series of deductions with certain general truths that are more extensive than, and are prior to the subject-matter of geometry. In the other we find our first propositions in the de- finitions, or the additional truths which the definitions introduce and make possible. § 229. It is more important to observe that what ,-, , i ■, . . re Tbe construc- is called geometrical demonstration is wry jar jrom tion of geome- being a process of pure deduction. As preliminary to Auxiiiarylines,' this and coincident with almost every one of its steps, 384 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 229. a process is carried forward of preparing the materials concerning which we reason, so that they can be brought into comparison. This is ordinarily termed the construction of the diagram or the drawing of auxiliary lines. In some cases these constructions are very easy and simple, in others they are difficult and com- plex. In all cases they task the power of ready invention, and fertile suggestion. The preparation of the diagram for the de- monstration of the 47th prop. 1st book, of Euclid's Geometry, is no inconsiderable achievement of inventive skill and sagacity. It ought to be observed, that in order to be certain of the possibility of drawing some of these lines, and of the character of the figures which will result from them, we can neither depend upon the axioms or definitions, nor upon the results of previous reasoning processes, but must rely solely upon our direct intuition of the properties and relations of the figures which our postulates enable us to draw, and which our defini- tions describe. We know, for example, by intuition only, that we can connect the opposite extremities of a square or rectangle, and that the diagonal thus drawn will divide the rectangle into two triaugles with a common base. In constructing a rectangle, we must presuppose the space which we circumscribe, and some of the consequent relations to it and to one other of its bound- ing lines. So soon as we divide this space, we add to this know- ledge also, by direct inspection or intuition. The same is true whenever we add to or divide any construction, whether one that is original or superinduced. It should be noticed, that in all cases of complicated geometri- cal construction, the completion of the diagram is the result, to a large degree, of a tentative process. We draw a line, and then observe whether the new relations brought into existence by this construction may serve as connecting links between the proposed conclusion and its proof. The new constructions which we form for each new theorem, furnish fresh material for yet other processes of deduction, and thus enlarge the material by successive syn- theses, to which our deductions can be applied. The new truths which these new constructions enable us to discover are intuitively- assented to, both in their conditions and their evidence. They are axiomatic, and similar to the axioms of the second class which w T e have already considered. The number of such axiomatic, i. e. y § 230. REASOXIXG. — VARIETIES OF DEDUCTION. 385 obvious truths made possible by the endless variety of geometrical constructions, is well nigh unlimited. "With every new construction, some new relation is evoked, and its truth is intuitively assented to. Moreover, in geometrical reasoning the several quantities must be measured by or with one another. The diagrams are con- structed, and the needful auxiliary lines are drawn solely in order that the parts may be so prepared that one may be compared with another. As the triangle is the simplest figure that can be constructed, the original measurement to which, in the last analysis, all others are reduced, and by which they are tested, is that of two triangles. In Playfair's Geometry the first act of demonstration and that to which all the remaining attach them- selves and are referred, is that of the fourth Prop, by which two triangles are superimposed on one another. The possibility of comparing two triangles being established, we have the means of comparing all those plane figures which can be resolved into equal triangles. This may be considered another auxiliary step in geometrical demonstration. It is obvious that thi3 or any act of measurement is not deduction proper. § 230. After the material has been prepared we proceed to apply to it the processes of geometrical demonstration. How we do this Geometrical can be understood most satisfactorily by an example. piaiued by an In the fifth proposition of Playfair's Geometry, B. I., it is proposed example, to prove that the angles at the base of an isosceles triangle are equal. The first step is to prepare the diagram by producing the two sides, A B, and A C, indefinitely towards D and E. In the lines thus drawn, the two points F and G are taken at equal distances from A, and B G and C F are joined. It is manifest, 'to the eye' as we say, that we have two pairs of triangles, A B G, A C F, B C G and C B F. The first two have the two corresponding sides equal — the one by con- struction, the other by the addition of equals to equals — as also the included angle common. By deduction from the conclusion of the* fourth proposition, the bases C F and B&r and the ceveral angles are proved to be equal. These two conclusions give, in the two smaller triangles, one side of T - each equal ; by subtraction of the equals A B and A C from the equals A F and A G, the sides B F and C G are equal ; that the included angles included between the equal sides of each are equal was proved from the fourth proposition. It fol'ows by the same syllogism upon the same premises, that the angles B C F and G B C are equal. These equals are, then taken from the equals A C F and A B G, and the remainders are equal. These are the angles at the base of the isosceles triangle. 17 386 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §231. It will be seen that the syllogisms employed are either five or two, according as we consider the axioms to be or not to be the foundations of geometrical deduc- tion. There are three cases in which the axioms, if equals be added to or taken from equals, are employed in what, in form, appear to be syllogisms. In the other two the conclusion of the fourth proposition is made the major premise, and the conclusion is regularly deduced. In all, we have a general proposition for a major premise, a particular case for the minor, and the conclusion made up of the major and minor term. That is. there are in all these cases, formal syllogisms; but there is this difference ; in the one case the axiom adds no force to the belief of the conclusion, because this would be equally clear to the mind without it; in the other, we are referred to the nature of the concept or construction — as of two triangles equal in two sides and the included angle — as necessarily involving equality in the remaining side of each. The reason for the conclusion is the pro- perties of such triangles as constructed by the mind, by means of the known pro- perties of space. It would be a trivial fiction to say that the relation of equality requires that two things equal to the same thing should be equal to one another; but this must be said, if the axiom is a reason for the special applications of itself. But again : we demonstrate "or deduce in this way by these two concatenated syl- logisms, that the angles at the base of this individual isosceles triangle are equal to one another. But we see at once that it must follow that whatever is true of this or any isosceles triangle must be true of every one. Hence we generalize this conclusion directly, and make it ready to be used as the major premise of another syllogism. This is the last step in the process of a geometrical demon- stration. It is not by induction proper, however, that we pass from the indi- vidual to the general, for the reason that the properties and relations of space which are used in an individual construction in space, do not like those of matter indicate one another with more or less probability, but each requires the other by an unavoidable necessity discerned by intuition. The processes of arithmetic and algebra are scarcely considered processes of deduction at all, not because deduction is not present and actually performed, but because it plays so inconsiderable a part in reaching the results. The chief con- cern of the mind in performing problems of this sort, is to invent such combina- tions and to apply such methods of dealing with them, as will bring to pass the result — which is usually to establish a new equation between elements that can be evolved from the data. The mind seeks to change the expression of the quantities given, so that they can be advantageously compared. The mind de- duces only when it applies some rule or principle, or uses a formula previously determined to be true of all members or all objects similarly situated with the individual case. Both these processes are similar in principle to the expedient of devising auxiliary lines in geometry. The result is readily generalized. § 231. The third species of deduction is the formal syiioglml iate or purely logical, such as is employed in immediate syllogisms. Here the reason for the conclusion is found in some one of the necessary relations of the concept, whenever such a relation can be applied or viewed as a cause necessitating a new relation expressed in the conclusion. Inasmuch as there § 231. REASONING. — VARIETIES OF DEDUCTION. 387 are several such essential relations, a variety of such deouctions is possible. Syllogisms of this sort are called by Kant syllogisms of the understanding, because the understanding is defined by Kant to be the logical faculty. These conclusions are sometimes styled immediate, in contrast with those which are mediate, because they are built upon a single proposition, or more exactly because no middle term is present or provided in the ordinary ac- ceptation of the word. The major premise is derived from an expansion in language of those relations which necessarily be- long to the concept, and may be expressed in purely formal pro- positions. These arguments are usually treated in books of logic under the title of the Conversion and Opposition of Propositions, and often are not treated as syllogisms at all. The following is an example, usually cited as of subaltern opposition: All islands were originally attached to a continent; therefore, some islands, or this island, e. g., Ireland, was originally attached to a continent. The argument in this form is an enthy- meme. In order that it may be expanded into a syllogism the major premise is required : it becomes — whatever is true of all islands is true of some islands ; it is true of all islands that they were attached to a continent ; therefore it is true of some islands that they belonged to a continent. We assert, No man is perfect ; therefore, some men, or this man is not perfect : the major premise being whatever is denied of all men is denied of some men, or this man. In conversion we conclude from All men are mortal, that some mortals are men. From No man is perfect, that no perfect being is a man, and so on throughout the cases that are possible, the major premise in each instance being a periphrastic proposition, as the predicate affirmed of all men may be the subjeet when limited by some, etc. It might seem at first that the proper major premise in such cases, should be the more general axiom, as in the first example; whatever is true of any whole is true of it* parts. But on a second thought we correct ourselves by observing, that in such a case no middle term can possibly be devised to connect the major with the minor. The same is true, only more eminently, of what are called the laws of thought — as the laws of identity, of contradiction, and of the excluded middle ; no matter is furni s hed in such propositions, by which we can proceed to a conclusion. They arc not laws of thought in the sense of being major premises for deduction. They are rather generalizations of the particular processes which 388 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 232. the mind performs, and of the relations which they involve. They are simply rules for logical consistency (cf. g 270). The force of the argument in all these cases is found in the essential nature of the concept, as involving certain relations, e. g., of the whole to its part, of the subject to its predicate, and of the positive to its negative. But the nature of the concept is but another name for the properties or relations which the mind ne- cessarily conceives every concept as possessing, which the mind must necessarily think it as being, or as able, in other relations, to effect or evolve. The purely logical properties or relations are viewed as causes of what is expressed in the conclusion, like phy- sical causes and mathematical relations, and so far forth are used by the mind as the reasons of the conclusions which it accepts. § 232. The foregoing analysis of the varieties of in most acts of deduction requires us to distinguish that part of the process which is preparative or auxiliary, from that which is simply and strictly deductive. That which is characteristic of each one of these varieties is derived from the elements and ma- terials which these subsidiary processes furnish for deduction. But in actual reasoning, the two operations are so intimately blended together, that it is not easy to distinguish the one from the other. For example, in probable reasoning, the force and conclusiveness of the argument may seem to turn chiefly upon the facts of obser- vation and testimony which establish the minor premise, or the inductions which support the major, and very little upon the act of bringing the two together in the relations of an argument. As soon as the auxiliary and preliminary steps are taken, the conjunction of the parts as major and minor, naturally occurs to the mind, and, with it, the inevitable conclusion. In geometrical reasoning, as we have seen, the establishment of the conclusion sought for, depends almost entirely on the skilful suggestion of the appropriate auxiliary lines, and the orderly concatenation of the several arguments, so that the result may spring forth of it- self. In common life, the issue of the reasoning depends upon the establishment of certain facts, in connection with certain principles. Upon the proof of the facts and the enforcement and illustration of the principles, the reasoner expends the re- sources of memory and invention, of wit and eloquence. The § 233. REASONING. — VARIETIES OF DEDUCTION. 389 facts being established and the principles received, the argument enforces itself. Skill in the invention of middle terms, or media of proof, is an art in respect to which men differ more widely than in re- spect to merely logical consistency, or the capacity to derive con- clusions from their premises. Upon skill and aptness in this, is founded very largely the estimate in which the ability of a rea- soner is held. But this affluence of invention and skill in selec- tion must also be attended with a ready tact in forecasting all the results of a multitude of deductive processes, when applied to all the cases which invention suggests. There must also be present the capacity to hold the attention evenly and steadily in long and closely-connected series of deductions, all which capacities come only from the special development, and usually from the patient and practiced training of the philosophical powers. When these habits are matured by such training, the soul learns to act with the precision and rapidity of intuition. It must so act in order to reason with success when pressed by a powerful antagonist, in the haste and excitement of debate, or under the unexpected and ingenious assaults or defences which are elicited in an active controversy. The establishment of the principles or the reasons which are involved and required in an argument, is often the point of chief importance. Inasmuch as the deductive power is prominently employed here, the logical faculty, or power of analytic and con- sistent thinking is especially tasked, and superiority in this is ne- cessarily manifest. The power readily and surely to fall back upon principles, and to apply them to special cases with apt- ness and force, is the power which distinguishes the reasoner from the man of extensive knowledge, the man of fertile invention, the man of ready wit, or the man eloquent in description and appeal. To this power must be superadded, as it is always sup- posed, the capacity to proceed with logical clearness and rigor from the reason to the conclusion. The last marks the logician pro- per, as he is contrasted with and distinguished from the reasoner. § 233. This analysis also enables us to answer the question which has been frequently agitated, whether Sf^ur'know- 3 deduction adds to our knowledge. Many have con- senfe \ In what tended that it does not and cannot. They urge, that 390 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 233. if we know the major premise, we already know the conclusion ; that when we assent to the major, All men are mortal, we have already decided the question, whether Peter is mortal, and that whatever advantage there may be in employing an argument, the argument does not add to our stock of knowledge. We do not, it is urged, gain by it any new truth. To this argument, in the form in which it is urged, we might reply, in the first place, that if we substitute for "we know already," the phrase " we might know if we would think or reflect," there would be less reason to object to it. The design of reasoning is often to lead a person to reflect or think concerning the applica- tion of the facts or principles to which he assents. When a man institutes a process of deduction, or follows one presented by another, one of three things may be true. First, he may never have accepted, through ignorance or want of thought, the major premise, or, at least, not so distinctly as to be ready to apply it in every particular case. But he may be induced to accept it for the first time by the excitement of the occasion — i. e., by the. use or application which is now to be made of it. Second, he may never before have accepted the minor so as to be able to connect it with the general truth, even though it had already been familiar to his knowledge and assent. Third, he may have ac- cepted both major and minor, but may never have thought of the two together so as to perceive that relation between the two which involves the conclusion. In the second place, an argument is usually addressed to a person who has not accepted a conclusion, by a person who has accepted it. The one who uses the. argument, knows this conclu- sion to be true. The person to whom it is addressed has not as- sented to it. The argument is used to make him give this assent. In some sense of the phrase, it adds to the knowledge of the person whom it convinces. It ordinarily does this by leading him so to reflect, that he enlarges his knowledge or his belief. First, it may be, he is led to accept the major ; next, he assents to the minor ; and last of all, he is induced so to connect the two, that he himself is convinced, and of himself accepts the conclusion. Reasoning is, in fact, constantly employed to enlarge the knowledge of men. It would be idle, as it might seem, to con- § 234. INDUCTIVE REASONING OR INDUCTION. 391 tend that the student of a system of geometry does not increase his stock of knowledge, or that all the knowledge which he gains is acquired by induction or intuition. Deduction is constantly employed as a means of instruction in all departments of science, and it would seem with the greatest advantage to those whose knowledge it augments. But knowledge is as truly concerned with the apprehension of relations, as with the cognition of facts. New or additional knowledge is as properly the knowledge under new relations of facts already known or very familiar, as the acquisition of new facts by observation, testimony, or induction. Deduction applies reasons to facts or events, in order to establish their truth, or ex- plain their existence or occurrence. It is often required, as we know, to convince ourselves or others that a fact or event must have been true or must have occurred. The man that is con- vinced by such a process of the reality of any fact, must thereby have gained new knowledge of its relations. Or, again, the process is applied to explain why it occurred ; the fact or event being admitted, the reason for its occurrence is asked for. When such reason is given by the application of the deductive process, the fact is known in a new relation. The knowledge of the fact as explained by its reason is certainly new knowledge. Deduction applies general causes, elements or pro- perties, as reasons to confirm or explain events and facts. It not only adds to our knowledge, but it adds knowledge of a kind which is eminent for its worth and dignity — thought-knowledge of the most exalted character — knowledge in the light of the prin- ciples and laws which govern and explain all individual facts and events. CHAPTER VIII. INDUCTIVE REASONING OR INDUCTION. § 234. We have seen that, in order to perform those processes of deduction which relate to facts and prop^riy^and events— the processes called probable reasoning— the cXd. perIy s °" mind must be furnished with major premises or gen- eral propositions. 392 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 234. The process by which we gain the truths thus applied, is called induction or inductive reasoning. We proceed to inquire : What is the nature of this process ? What are the conditions and grounds of its exercise? What the assumptions on which it rests? What are its applications to human knowledge, aud what the rules for its successful use? Induction is usually denned as the deriving generals from parti- culars ; and in this is contrasted with deduction, in which we are said to proceed from generals to particulars. This definition is correct so far as it goes, but it is by no means precise or exhaust- ive. There are many processes conceivable, in which we derive generals from particulars which are not processes of induction. For example : We observe ten oranges, and, noticing them one by one, perceive a common likeness of qualities. We gather the results of our observations into the general judgment or proposi- tion : all these oranges are slightly oval, or light yellow, or yellow mottled with green. It is obvious that such a judgment, though general and derived from particulars, has not been gained by induction. This is further obvious from the fact, that such propo- sitions cannot be applied in deduction. To seek thus to apply them, would be an idle form, attended by no advantage, and leading to no conviction. If all that we know or had learned was simply : all swans hitherto observed were white, or all men observed or reported have died, we should already have included in the major premise the truth of the conclusion, and it would be idle to expand the knowledge already gained into a form of deduction. With such general propositions as premises, deductive reasoning would be either superfluous or impertinent. " If induction," says Galileo, " must go through every indi- vidual instance, it would be either useless or impossible ; impossi- ble if the number of cases were infinite ; useless, because then the universal proposition would add nothing new to our knowledge." And yet inductions like these — so-called — have been named by some the only perfect or truly logical inductions. (Cf. Sir Wm. Hamilton, Logic, Lee. xvii. §62; Lee. xxxiii. § 108; Appendix vii.) It is sufficient to observe that, if such inductions are ex- posed to no error, they contribute no truth. They are safe but useless, for they admit of no application, except as a convenience for the memory. § 234. INDUCTIVE REASONING OR INDUCTION. 393 That which is properly called induction is a process of another character. Examples of it are such as these. I observe a certain number of oranges, and, noticing their characteristics, infer or believe that all oranges have certain peculiarities of form, internal constitution, habits of growth, etc., etc. In like manner, I infer all swans are and must be white ; not merely all the swans that have existed, or those which have been observed or described, but the whole species in the past, the present, and the future. In such cases we take, the examples which we have observed, to stand for or represent the entire class. It follows that judgments of induction differ from simple judg- ments, in certain important particulars. To return to our first example ; we see ten oranges with certain well-defined character- istics. We bring them under their appropriate concepts, and judge or affirm these concepts of the individual objects. In in- duction we proceed further : we add to these simple judgments yet another, viz., that what we have found to be true of these, may be received as true of all others like them. The ground of the first judgment is facts observed and compared. The ground of the second is what is called the analogy of nature. A judg- ment of induction is then a judgment of comparing observation, enlarged by a judgment of analogy. The judgment of observation is founded on observed similarity. The judgment of analogy is founded on an interpreted indication. What is usually called experience, includes acts of induction. Simple observation and judgment do not constitute what we usually call experience ; for this imports not only that we have made and preserved observations, but also that we are capable of applying their results in parallel cases. This implies the power to discriminate between cases that are, and those that are not similar. Without this power or discipline, observation or bare experience would be possible but useless. For it would enable us simply to attain and retain our knowledge of the past, but never to apply it to the future. In view of these considerations, the questions return upon us with augmented interest and importance : What is the ground, what the nature, and what are the rules for a sound induction ? They are questions which have often been asked, and not always very satisfactorily or thoroughly answered. As preliminary to 17 * 394 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 235. the development of the correct answers, and to a satisfactory- theory of induction, we may profitably consider a few examples in w T hich the process has been successfully applied. § 235. The inductions of common life have already of coSmoniife been noticed. They differ from the inductions of of science/ 0118 science, in that their results are incapable of being reduced to universal statements to which there are no exceptions. Nor do they result in the discovery of ultimate properties, agencies, and laws. Their results are seen in the common sense and common prudence which are essential to the performance of the common acts and duties of common life. Uncommon skill and readiness in interpreting such indications is termed acuteness, discernment, sagacity, and tact. Less than the usual capacity to make such inductions' quickly and correctly, is denominated slowness and stupidity. The average capacity is called common sense, in one of the significations of this term. The second class of examples of the process of induction is furnished by the discoveries of science. The inductions of common life are in one sense discoveries, but the indications are so readily interpreted and the inferences are derived with so great unanimity and universality, that the intellectual process (or processes) by which they are made, attracts little attention, and is, therefore, not readily analyzed. But when some new and wonderful agent in nature is brought to light, or some new law of its acting is established, and especially when the power or law is applied to some brilliant or useful result, we inquire with the greatest interest, How came the discoverer to think of that ? How did he satisfy himself that what he thought was true ? In such cases we are more likely to find answers to our questions, inasmuch as the steps of the process have often been slowly made, and the considerations which have led to them can be distinctly reproduced. We select, first of all, the brilliant discovery by Franklin of the identity of lightning with electricity. With the electrical agent, or, as it was called in his time, the electric fluid, Franklin was entirely familiar. He was so far master of the methods of developing it in sufficient quantity or intensity, as to be able to produce its ordinary and obvious phenomena, as well as to ex- hibit phenomena that had previously been unknown. He had § 235. INDUCTIVE REASONING OR INDUCTION. 395 the electrical machine and the Ley den jar, and could produce at pleasure the electrical light, and the report following the con- nection of bodies in opposite electrical conditions. With these, then somewhat novel phenomena, he had become entirely- familiar in observation and thought ; as familiar as men in common life are with the aspect or form of a fruit, or with the expression of a gentle or vicious animal. He had also closely observed the phenomena of lightning, and had noticed simi- larities which had never been thought of before. The wave-like sheet and the zig-zag line and the loud report were seen to re- semble the less impressive phenomena of the machine and the Leyden jar ; and it occurred to his thoughts that the similarity of the phenomena indicated a common agent or power as their cause. This suggestion was strengthened by the thought, that clouds might be to clouds, or clouds to the earth, as the opposite surfaces of the Leyden jar. The mere observation of simi- larities like these might have satisfied the mind of Franklin, that the power or fluid in the heavens must be the same with that which could be accumulated by the machine from the earth. When at last he succeeded in bringing the power in question to affect a small quantity of matter, when he made it to run along an insulated kite-string, to emit a spark, to charge a Leyden jar — in short, to exhibit not only similar but the same indications with machine electricity, the induction could no longer be doubted. The decisive experiment proved the correct- ness of his thought. Dr. Black was led to the discovery of carbonic acid gas, by observing that caustic lime increased in weight when changed into common lime, and by inferring that this weight must be derived from some agent in the atmosphere. This suggested the thought that the other alkalies, being like caustic lime in other properties, were like it also in this. The experiment was tried, and the suggestion was found to be correct. This put him upon the inquiry what the agent was which entered into combination with all these substances. The inquiry resulted in the separation of carbonic acid gas as a newly-discovered agent, and the determination of its properties and laws. Dalton is said to have discovered the law that chemical com- binations are effected by the union of their constituent elements 396 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §235, in fixed proportions; and that, when a larger portion of an agent, as oxygen, enters into such a combination, it is invariably a multiple of a smaller. He was led to this by the knowledge that, in some cases, a combination in such proportions had in fact been observed. Being a teacher of mathematics and accustomed to mathematical relations, he generalized the result of a few chance observations into a universal law ; it " being irresistibly recommended by the clearness and simplicity which the notion One of the most instructive instances of modern discovery, is that achieved by Sir Humphrey Davy, of the metallic bases of the alkaline earths. The similarity in appearance and in many chemical properties between such alkalies as potash, soda, and lime, and the clearly identified oxyds of metals, had led to the suggestion, that they were similar in chemical constitution — i. e., that they all were oxyds of metals. But the metals believed in do not exist in nature in a separate state, nor had they ever been exhibited in separate form by any agent of decomposition hith- erto employed. The suggestion that there were such metals, and that they might be evolved, was confirmed by all the indications required as evidence, except their actual production. The ap- plication of the galvanic battery to chemical decomposition, and the triumphant success which had attended its use, led Davy to try it upon the hitherto intractable and irreducible potash. Under the solvent power of this wondrous agent, the knot which had never before been unloosed was in an instant untied. At the magic touch of this new instrument, the little globe of the newly-discovered metal leaped into view, and the happy sugges- tion was confirmed and accepted as an undoubted fact. It scarcely needed an experiment to convince the sagacious inter- preter, that similar metals were encrusted within common lime and soda. The discoverer was almost as certain before as after the battery was applied, that calcium and sodium would in fact be evolved. In the last series of discoveries we notice the following order and progress of thought and experiment. First, the oxyds of metals were observed to be like the alkalies in certain important properties. But the metallic oxyds were known to be produced \>y chemical changes ; copper, iron, etc., constantly undergoing § 235. INDUCTIVE REASONING OR INDUCTION. 397 this process before our eyes. The two substances being alike in certain particulars, it was conjectured that they were alike in others. If pure potassium could have been found in a sepa- rate state, the readiest way to determine the point would have been to oxydize the metal and see whether the result would be potash. The next thing was to cfe-oxydize it. This was ac- complished by the agency of galvanism. The fact that galvanic agency could decompose chemical compounds so intractable, suggested that possibly there were none which it could not over- come. If this were so, it would follow, that the force which held them in union, must be electric. This was established by its ap- propriate evidence, and is called by Whewell, " the highest gen- eralization at which chemical philosophers have yet arrived.' , Hist Inductive Sciences, B. xiv. c. 10. The mental process is precisely that which is common to every case of Induction. Cer- tain objects are seen to be alike in certain properties or laws. It is believed or judged that similarity in these particulars indi- cates likeness in others. Potash is like iron-rust in certain re- spects ; therefore it is like iron-rust in being the oxyd of a metal. All chemical compounds are strikingly alike in certain parti- culars. Certain of these are separable by the electric force ; therefore all are separable by this agency. But if separable by it, they are held in union by the same force. From discoveries of this kind we pass to those in astronomical physics — to the discoveries of Copernicus, Galileo, Kepler, and Newton. Copernicus began by discovering, as it is said, the heliocentric theory of the solar, system. The way in which he was led to adopt and defend it, is described by himself. He had found in ancient authors, accounts of Philolaus and others who had asserted the motion of the earth. "Then I began to meditate concerning the motion of the earth ; and though it appeared an absurd opinion, yet, since I knew that in previous times others had been allowed the privilege of feigning what circles they chose in order to explain the phenomena, I conceived that I also might take the liberty of trying whether, on the suppo?ition of the earth's motion, it was possible to find better explanations than the ancient ones of the revolution of the celestial orbs." " Having then assumed the motions of the celestial orbs which 398 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §235. are hereafter explained, by laborious and long observation I at length found that, if the motions of the other planets be com- pared with the revolution of the earth, not only their phenomena follow from the supposition, but also that the several orbs and the whole system are so connected in order and magnitude, that no one part can be transposed without disturbing the rest, and introducing confusion into the universe." In 1609 Galileo constructed his telescope, and very soon dis- covered the satellites of Jupiter. This at once confirmed the Copernican theory, by opening before the eyes of men another system subordinate to the solar, of heavenly bodies revolving about their primaries, thus giving an analogon of the greater. The subsequent discovery by the same instrument of the phases of Venus, at once confirmed the new theory of the revolution of the planets about the sun, and answered an objection against it by explaining why Venus did not appear larger when nearer the beholder. Copernicus furnished the suggestion, by reflecting on the known fact, that the apparent places of objects may be accounted for by the motion of one or both, and that the simplest solution or theory was to be preferred. Galileo, by his telescope, prepared the way for the experiment, by enabling observers, in a certain sense, to observe for themselves whether it was the sun or the earth which moved. Kepler prepared the way for the discoveries of Newton, by his determination of the orbits of some of the planets, and the law of their motions. Newton had been himself familiar with the law by which, in obedience to terrestrial gravity, bodies fall to the earth's surface. The first thought which led to the extension of this agent to the celestial bodies occurred to him in 1666. "As he sat alone in a garden, he fell into a speculation on the power of gravity : that, as this power is not found sensibly diminished at the remotest distance from the centre of the earth to which we can rise, neither at the tops of the loftiest buildings, nor even on the summits of the highest mountains, it appeared to him reason- able to conclude that this power must extend much further than was usually thought. ' Why not as high as the moon ?' said he to himself; 'and, if so, her motion must be influenced by it; perhaps she is retained in her orbit thereby.' " Upon this sug- gestion, he proceeded to the calculation of the deflection of the § 235. INDUCTIVE REASONING OS INDUCTION. 399 moon from a tangent to its orbit in a single second ; it being assumed that the moon was at the distance from the earth which was thon received. The result disappointed him ; for he found that this deflection would be thirteen feet, which did not cor- respond with that required by the supposition that gravity deflected it. He laid his calculation aside. The subsequent discovery that the course described by a falling body is an ellipse, and that the distance of the moon from the earth could be correctly ascertained, enabled him to accept his theory on the grouud that it coincided with actual fact. The distance of the moon had previously been computed on an assumed but mistaken diameter of the earth. A more accurate measurement of a degree upon the earth's surface led to a correction of the distance of the moon, and Newton's theory was henceforward accepted as a demonstrated truth. He first conjectured that the extension of a known force from the earth to the heavens, is possible and rational. He asks, "if so" "what then?" following out his in- duction by a mathematical deduction. He then, by other mathe- matical calculations decisively tested this deduction, and the conjectured agent was established as a vera causa, and its laws were carefully computed ; the true theory of the heavenly bodies was forever settled. The examples cited are sufficient to illustrate the nature of the inductive process. They have been taken from the physical sciences, not because these differ essentially from those which concern moral and political subjects, but because they illustrate more strikingly the steps of induction. The objects with which they are concerned are more interesting to the majority of men. The effects of discoveries in them are more obvious. The experi- ments and observations which have led to them are more brilliant and startling. Many of their results are permanently fixed in the arts of life, both useful and ornamental. Some of them are continually brought to our thoughts by engines and instruments which materially contribute to the convenience and comfort of man. The telescope, the prism, the quadrant, the hydraulic press, the steam engine, the galvanic battery, are all permanent memorials of what these processes have wrought, and they prompt to eager inquiries after the operations by which they were first constructed in thought. 400 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §236. The attentive consideration of these examples proves that induction in science is substantially the same process with in- duction in common life — that in both cases it is a process of in- terpreting indications. § 236. This assertion prompts the inquiries, Why then dica'tkms ofsd- are the processes of common induction so easy and those ence more dim- Q ^ gc i ence so i»9> { ' e -> to have no content > sought by what he called its becoming, i. e., the independent and necessary movement of the concept, to evolve all the categories from one another, not only of thought but of material and spiritual existence, in a self-completing and perpetually repeated circle. This self-evolved and self-completing circle of necessary concepts was conceived by him as the Idea, and all these together con- stituted the Absolute, i. c, the sum total of mutually-related,possible, and conceiv- able thoughts and things. § 250. THEORIES OF INTUITIVE KNOWLEDGE. 433 Hegel's mistake was twofold. He attempted to derive things from thoughts, or real from logical relations, instead of finding all logical, i. e., all generalized relations in those which are real. He attempted to derive one category from an- other, instead of explaining the apparent dependence of one upon another by the order in which they are developed to, and the extent in which they are applied by, the mind through its psychological limitations. § 250. The categories or intuitions may be divided into the formal, the mathematical, and the real. The ^J 1 ^^* formal are those which are involved in any act of logical knowledge, whatever be its object-matter — whether it be real, imagined, or generalized — whether it be an actually exist- ing or a purely mental creation. They are essential to the most abstract form of knowledge, and appear in all its objects or products. The mathematical are those which grow out of the existence of space and time and suppose these to be realities. The relations included under this definition are not exclusively used in the sciences of number and quantity, but inasmuch as they are fundamental to these sciences, we distinguish them by the epithet mathematical ; using it to designate all the time and space relations and those directly dependent upon them. The real are those which are ordinarily recognized as generic to and fundamental of the so-called qualities and properties of existing things, both material and spiritual., We do not, however, by using the term real, imply or concede that the formal and the mathematical are any the less real — but that they are not limited so exclusively to objects really existing. CHAPTER II. THEORIES OF INTUITIVE KNOWLEDGE. A complete sketch of the various theories which have been held in respect to the nature, origin, and authority of primitive notions and intuitive judgments, would include the most important portion of a complete history of Metaphysics or Speculative Philosophy. Such a sketch would be entirely out of place in the present work, and will not be attempted. We shall only endeavor to group and critically examine, under a few comprehensive titles, those theories which have any present interest for modern thought, or which are still maintained in modern schools of philosophy. 19 434 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §253. £ 251. 1. It has been extensively taught that these original ideas a dh-ectm^ t°l an< i first truths are discerned by direct insight or intuition inde- vision of first pendently of any relations to phenomena. The power to behold them is conceived as a special sense for the true, the original, and the infinite ; as a divine Reason which is permitted to gaze directly upon that which is eternally true. Such are the representations of Plato, Plotinus, etc., among the ancients. Thus the Platonizing and Cartesian divines of the seven- teenth century, as Henry More, John Smith of Cambridge, Ralph Cudworth, and multitudes of others, freely express themselves. Malebranche, Schelling, Coleridge, Cousin, and others, have given sanction to such views more or less clearly con- ceived and expressed. Those who combine with philosophic acuteness, the power of vivid imagination and eloquent exposition, not infrequently meet the diffi- culties which attend the analysis and explanation of the foundations of knowledge by these half-poetic and half-philosophic representations. It is manifest that the representations which they give are not true when liter- ally interpreted. No direct inspection of primitive ideas and principles is con- ceivable. It is not by withdrawing the attention from, but by fixing it upon, the facts and phenomena of the actual world, that the truths and relations of the world which is ideal and rational can be discerned at all. g 252. 2. Many of the earlier philosophers and theologians of The theory that modern times, following the Scholastics of the middle ages, were they are dis- accus tomed to say that these ideas and truths are discerned by the cerned by the J J light of nature, light of reason and the light of nature, that they shine forth or are evidenced by their own light. The use of this language is in part to be traced to the often-repeated maxim of Aristotle that some truths cannot be demonstrated, but must be accepted without proof j in part by a Platonic interpre- tation of the passage in the gospel of John (i. 9), in which the Word is said to enlighten every man who cometh into the world. It is obvious that the phrase is figurative and expresses only the fact which re- mains to be explained and accounted for, that these truths are neither generalized from experience nor deduced by logical ratiocination ; that they are no sooner thought of than they are assented to, and that upon them as original assumptions rests the validity of all generalization and deduction. $ 253. 3. The doctrine has been earnestly held and taught that That they are these ideas and beliefs are innate in or connate with the soul. This nate . " is well known as the doctrine which Descartes is supposed to have taught, and to the refutation of which Locke devoted the first book of his Essay. It is that the intellect finds itself at birth or as soon as it wakes to conscious activity, to be possessed of ideas to which it has only to attach the appropriate names, or of judgments which it needs only to express in fit proposi- tions. Whether this doctrine as thus stated and defined, was ever held by any one may perhaps be questioned. Even Descartes himself seems, when pressed, wholly to abandon the doctrine in the form in which he had propounded it and made it the foundation of the most important conclusions. On the other hand, it would be conceded by many, and can be defended as true, that the capacity to evolve these ideas and these truths is born with man and forms an essential feature of his constitution as man. Not only is man endowed with these capacities, but he is furnished with tendencies which impel to their exercise, and after which these conceptions aud judgments arc surely and ncces- § 254. THEORIES OF INTUITIVE KNOWLEDGE. 433 sarily developed so soon as the mind applies the necessary attention or awakes to the requisite conditions. Even before these conceptions are generalized they are assented to in the individual and concrete, in the most important kinds of know- ledge. \ 254. 4. From the doctrine of innate ideas and the school of Descartes, the transition is natural and direct to the views held by The views of Locke and the several divisions of his school. These are naturally scuoo i # grouped together, though the interpretations of the meaning of Locke are very diverse, and the several schools that are named after Locke, hold opposite and incompatible opinions. It will be found, however, that they can all be traced to Locke, either as they are sanctioned by his direct authority or were derived from some of his principles by logical deduction or natural growth, or as they were devised to supplement some of his supposed oversights or defects. Locke, as is well known, rejected the doctrine of innate ideas and protested most vigorously against it, in the first book of his Essay. This protest was of the greatest service to philosophy in delivering it from the vague and fantastical assertions upon this subject which had been allowed before his time. It has been questioned and may be doubted, whether any sober and considerate thinker ever received the doctrine in the form and sense in which Locke rejected it. But it is certain that many philosophical writers have expressed themselves in language which warranted the interpretations which Locke thought it necessary to refute. But Locke did not guard* himself against serious oversights in this polemic. He did not distinguish between those positive ideas of objects and acts in both matter and spirit which make up the materials or facts of knowledge — and the relations between these materials, which, u possible, are more important than the facts which they connest. Nor did he conceive at all the difference between an idea as acquired by experience and as occasioned by experience. He did not dis- cern that a relation which is developed by experience to conscious apprehension, must be implied or assumed to make experience possible. Ha did not distinguish between innate ideas and innate dispositions or capacities to develop and assent to truths which involve original ideas. To correct these oversights, Leibnitz subjoined his well-known reply to the adage, " nihil in intelleciH quod non prius in sensn" — "nisi ijpse intellectus." Locke asserts positively that all our ideas are obtained through two sources, Sen^pition and Reflection : Sensation gives the knowledge of sensible objects and their qualities; Reflection gives the knowledge of spirit and its operations. He was careful to add that except through these two sources we have no ideas what- ever. What Locke intended by ideas admits hore of a question similar to that which was noticed in connection with innate ideas. Did he mean positively to exclude from idea3 thosa necessary relations by which the mind connects all the objects of matter and spirit which it observes or experiences? It is probable that this distinction was not in his mind, and that for this reason he did not provide against uncertainty or ambiguity of interpretation. It was not unnatural that different constructions should be put upon doctrines thus announced, and that ac- cording to these diverse interpretations, there should spring up among his fol- lowers different schools of philosophy. One class of those who called themselves his disciples, by greatly limiting or almost setting aside his definition of reflection, interpreted him as teaching that 436 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 254. all our positive ideas are of material objects, and perverted his principles so as to make him teach a materialistic philosophy. Condillac thus applied his doctrine, and derived from it the conclusion that all our ideas, whether those of sense or spirit, are simply transformed sensations. " LocLe distingue deux sources de nos idees : les sens et la reflexion. II serait plus exact de n'en reconnaitre qu'une source, parce que la reflexion n'est dans son principe que la sensation elle merue, soit parce qu'elle est moins la source des idees que le canal par lequel elles decou- lent des sens." — Traite des Sensations. This doctrine in the form in which it was taught by Condillac and by others of the French school, was long since aban- doned, but tendencies to the same doctrine, if not to the same opinions in respect to the nature and origin of mental activities and their products, retain their hold most tenaciously among many modern psychologists, such as J. S. Mill and Alexander Bain with others. Hume (Treatise on Human Nature, Part III.,§ £ 2, 3, 4, 14, 15 j Inquiry con- cerning the Human Understanding, § 7,) applied Locke's dictum in respect to the sources of knowledge, to the analysis of the relation of causation, or as he called it, of the ideas of Cause and Effect, and of Necessary Connection. He first demonstrates, as it is easy to do, that these ideas are not to be gained from Sen- sation. He then inquires whether they can be gained by Reflection, or the con- scious experience which we have of the exercise of power in the production of effects by volition. To this he answers in the negative, experience giving us only the invariable succession or the constant conjunction of these internal ideas. How then, he asks, does it happen that we connect objects as causes and effects, and what is the meaning of the combination ? We certainly do thus connect them, and we give to them as thus connected the names respectively of causes and effects. To his own question, he replies : Objects which are observed to be always conjoined, we invariably associate in our minds : When we observe the one we cannot avoid thinking of the other: The principle of association is that which explains, and it is the only mental law that explains, the combination of objects and events as causes and effects. The solution applied by Hume to the single relation of cause and effect, has since his time been applied to the explanation of other of the so-called necessary truths or primitive cognitions. Dugald Stewart used it to account for the belief that every visible or colored object involves a belief in, and an apprehension of extension. Dr. Thomas Brown carried it still farther, applying it to a great num- ber of relations. James Mill, in his Analysis of the Human Mind, was the first to find in the doctrine of inseparable or indissoluble associations a solvent for all necessary beliefs and original conceptions. John Stuart Mill, his son, in his Logic and Examination of the Philosophy of Sir William Hamilton, has applied this principle in detail to all the so-called original and necessary truths with the conceptions which they involve ; persisting in attempting to show by this single for- mula that mathematical conceptions and axioms are generalized from experience, that the universal and necessary belief in.causation is itself the product of induction, which again results from associations that cannot be overcome or separated. Herbert Spencer, whilo on the one hand he earnestly contends that inconceivability of the opposite is the decisive test of original truths, holds that these very axioms arc our earliest inductions from experience. Moreover, he holds that the capacity of induction itself is not only the result of processes of association, but § 255. THEORIES OF INTUITIVE KNOWLEDGE. 437 these descend from one generation to another with an augmented tendency, till they acquire that irresistible force which excludes the conceivability of other re- lations. All these writers may be said to belong to the school of Locke, but they receive only one or two of his leading doctrines and interpret them in a narrow spirit, and apply them to explain conceptions and beliefs to which Locke never thought of applying them. \ 255. 5. Dr. Thomaa Reid, with Hutcheson, Oswald, and Beat- tie, was aroused by the skeptical conclusions derived by Hume and Dr. Reid and Berkeley from the doctrines of Locke, to combat his principle as g cu . 00 i. it had till then been interpreted — that all ideas are obtained from sensation or reflection— and to assert for the mind itself an independent power or source of knowledge. This power was called by him Common Sense, and to it was referred our belief in the original and fundamental elements of all knowledge. Reid was especially earnest in asserting the necessity of first principles as the foundations of knowledge in general and of every special science in particular. Of these principles there is a great variety — logical, grammatical, mathematical, moral, sesthetical, metaphysical, as well as those facts given in the experiences of sense and consciousness. All these are discerned hy that power which he called common sense, and occasionally judgment. The nature and the conditions of this faculty he did not exactly define, nor its relations to other powers, nor the laws of its acting, nor the character and place of its products. He was content to assert that there must be a source of this kind of knowledge independently of experience, and that these first truths are to be received upon its authority. Dugald Stewart followed Reid in insisting upon "fundamental laws of human belief," and " ori- ginal elements of human knowledge." He, however, subjected to analysis some of those truths which were asserted by Reid to be original, and allowed to the law of association an influence which Reid had not recognized. Brown deviated materially from Reid and Stewart in attaching greater importance, in his analysis of our conceptions, to the laws of association. He resolved the relation of cause and effect into that of invariable antecedence and succession. He occasionally refers to some original belief or tendency to belief as necessary to explain our actual experience. He also distinctly recognized a faculty or power called rela- tive suggestion, which of itself originates or discerns certain original relations; making it, like Reid's/KC^men^ to be the originator of and voucher for these original relations or categories. His system is not always congruous or consist- ent with itself, inasmuch as he attributes greater authority at one time to the assoeiational, and at another to the intuitional element. In France, Royer Collard and Jouffroy followed in general the method and the doctrines of Reid, with a more analytic scrutiny and a more systematic arrangement of the original data of knowledge. Each of these writers made some important improvements upon the doctrines of their teachers. Maine de Sir an followed out the doctrine of Locke in respect to Reflection, and attempted to find in Reflection the source of some important first truths. He went further than Locke in this direction and borrowed from Leibnitz some im- portant modifications of Locke's teachings in respect to the nature of power and the essential activity of the mind as a discoverer of original and independent truth. Cousin sought to unite Reid, Collard and Kant. These writers might perhaps be more properly grouped together as belonging to a separate school— the Scottish, or the Scottish and French School. But a more 438 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §256. careful study of the doctrines of Locke reveals the fact that in the latter part of the Essay, when he came to analyze and account for the ideas of relation, parti- cularly of such primitive relations as substance, cause, and adaptation, he departs from the doctrines which he was supposed to have laid down in the preceding chapters. He certainly did not place that construction upon them which many of his disciples imposed after his time. In accounting for these original ideas, he seems to ascribe them directly to the intellect itself, and to an original power to discern, and an original necessity to receive them as true. In short, without asserting, in form, any new source of ideas, and without in the least abandoning his previous teachings — while in reply to the objections which were brought against him for inconsistency, he earnestly defends his own consistency with himself — he does in fact take the same ground with Reid and the Scottish School. Cf. (T. E. Webb. Intellectualism of Locke.) If this is a correct interpretation of Locke's real opinions, then Reid and his disciples are pi-operly connected with the school of Locke, notwithstanding their earnest polemic against some of the doctrines which they supposed him to teach. g 256. 6. From Hume and Reid, who were antagonist disciples Kant and his j n ^ e school f Locke, we pass to the speculations of Kant, and consider his views of first principles and the categories. Kant, like Reid, was aroused by the skepticism of Hume to investigate the foundations of knowledge. He saw that if the solution given by Hume of the relation of causa- tion were accepted and applied to others which are as original and fuadament.il, then scientific knowledge would be impossible, and religious faith would be un- supported by any rational foundations. He therefore set himself to th3 work of examining, by critical analysis, the intellectual powers, to ascertain, if possible, whether knowledge a priori is possible, and if so, what must be its original ele- ments and authority. The results of his critical inquiries were as follows : The human intellect may be considered as Sense, Understanding, and R ason, and to each of these powers or modes of action, there are elements a priori. To the Sense, space and time must be assumed as a priori conditions. If these are not thus assumed, neither perception nor consciousness could possibly gain the know- ledge appropriate to each. Moreover, unless the knowledge of both space and time is a priori, the mathematical sciences would be impossible. The Understanding is the power of generalizing and of logical reasoning. To this, certain forms of conception are also necessary as its a pnori conditions, such as substance and attribute, and cause and effect. Without these forms a priori, the processes of the Understanding would be impossible and their products would be untrustworthy. The Reason is the power by which we give unity to our knowledge of both material and spiritual phenomena, as well in the several portions of each, as when these portions are mutually connected and related with one another. To this unifying process, there must be assumed, as necessary presuppositions, certain ideas a priori, viz.: the soul, the external world, and God. The a priori elements of our knowledge, according to Kant, are the receptivi- ties of space and time for the Sense; the forms or categories for the Understand- ing ; and the ideas for the Reason. That these elements are assumed and applied in all our higher knowledge, was shown by Kant to follow necessarily from the analysis of that knowledge which is gained by the intellect, and indirectly from § 256. THEORIES OF INTUITIVE KNOWLEDGE. 439 the direct analysis of the operations of its several powers. These were the positive results of his psychological analysis. But Kant raised another inquiry. Are these a priori and necessary assump- tions themselves worthy of confidence ? Are they true, and do they hold good of the nature of things, or do they simply arise from the constitution of the human intellect — a change in which might involve a change in these necessary relations and in the knowledge which is built upon them ? To these questions of his own asking, Kant makes the following reply : These assumptions have for man a regulative farce, but perhaps only a relative truth and validity. That is, while man must act in his intellectual processes under the belief that these principles are primary and universal, and thus admit them as giving law to his own intel- lect, and as grounding and explaining all his knowledge, he is not authorized thereby to assume that they hold good as the laws of those minds which may be supposed to be constituted differently from the human, or that they hold true of the knowledge which such minds acquire. On the one hand, we cannot deny that, they do hold true for other beings and their knowledge; and on the other, we cannot deny that they do not. For aught that we know, it may be true, that other beings might be so constituted as not to assume these principles, or to know by means of the relations which they involve. We cannot affirm that there are such beings. We cannot deny that there may be. We cannot conceive how there should be. We cannot imagine intellectual processes that do not run back into these relations and principles, nor can we conceive of any knowledge which is not held together by these relations, but we have no* rational ground for denying t -at both are possible. This is the last result of the critical examination to which Kant subjected the intellectual faculty. These views have had extensive currency among the phil- osophers of Germany and England, and the assertion of them has wrought like leaven, to stimulate inquiry and to excite to counter assertions. Many who would not accept them have found it difficult to show their groundlessness or their un- truth, in part or in whole. Many philosophers who have followed Kant in his analysis of the foundations of our knowledge, have felt themselves constrained to enter a special protest against these views, or to seek to vindicate a different theory. The only part of Kant's theory with which we are here concerned is the sug- gestion which he makes, that the relations and principles which we find to be original and assume to be true for our own thinking and knowledge, are not ne- cessarily true and valid for all thinking and all knowledge. Concerning this we observe : (1.) It is a question of Speculative Philosophy or Metaphysics, and not at all a question of Psychology. Psychologically considered, the views of Kant do not differ materially from those of other philosophers so far as the proposition is concerned, that certain truths must be received as universal and necessary, and that these are given to the mind a priori. It is one chief object of his Critique to show that such principles are not obtained by experience, but must be assumed in order to make experience possible, as without them we could have neither experience nor science. That which he subjoins to this ascertained result of psychological analysis, is the suggestion that this may be true in human psychology only, and not in the psychology of other knowing beings. Whatever may be the probability or rca- 440 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 256. sonableness of this suggestion, it is in no sense a psychological fact. It is purely a philosophical thesis, to be urged and defended on speculative grounds. (2.) This metaphysical suggestion or thesis is unsupported by any grounds of analogy or probability. The facts which suggested the thesis are the known changes in the objects of sense-perception, which are connected with known changes in the organism of the percipient or in the medium by which this perci- pient apprehends. These changes are most conspicuous in vision. An object seen through a colored lens, be it red or green or blue, is seen to be red or green or blue. In like manner, the color of objects is, to a limited extent, affected by changes in the physical condition of the eye. Some men, through disease, see objects colored as they are not in reality. Others are incapable of seeing any differences of color, or at best, only a few varieties. Upon analogies derived from these facts, Kant justifies himself in asserting that there may or might exist created or finite minds which know other relations than those of time, space, substance, causality. To this it is enough to reply that the facts from which these suggestions are derived are phenomena of the cor- poreal organism — while the acts and objects to which they are applied by way of analogy pertain to the pure intellect. We know moreover of the phenomena of the organism, that the corporeal organism is a factor which, with material condi- tions, not only presents the object for the mind to perceive, but makes it to be what it is to a certain extent, so that the object changes with its changing factors and conditions. But to these thoughts* or intellectual relations no such conditions are required. Certainly the ebjects are not known to change with any conditions. So far as these relations are applied to material objects it makes no difference what the objects are. Many are equally applicable to spiritual beings, and their phenomena, products, and trustworthiness cannot be weakened or set aside by analogies derived from material beings and phenomena. All positive grounds for applying any analogies of the kind are found to be wanting. (3.) The suggestion of Kant is inconsistent with, and overthrown by, the reach and necessary use of some of these very relations which are brought into dis- trust. It is open to the charge of being an intellectual felo de se. For example, all the positive ground for the suggestion, founded upon an analogy which we have seen to be invalid because irrelevant, rests upon one of these first truths them- selves, one of these very original relations, which Kant subjects to metaphysical doubt as to whether it may not be merely contingent upon the human constitu- tion. It is perfectly clear that the question which he raises, is whether know- ledge by these relations as a subjective process, and the relations themselves as objective facts, may not be and probably are, effects of which the human con- stitution is a cause. We notice also that the reason by which he supports his suggestion is, that we are justified in so interpreting — which wc have shown is misinterpreting — certain signs or indications furnished by analogous phenomena. In this argument it will be obvious to all our readers who accept the analysis which we have given of induction, that the assumptions which he contends aro only regulative, are used and applied by him as though they were real. Ho cer- tainly applies with entire confidence, the relations of cause and effect as neces- sarily and really applicable to the constitution of man as viewed by all beings whatever, and wholly omits to notice that he has suggested that these relations necessarily employed in human thinking, are merely contingent upon the acci- § 258. THEORIES OF INTUITIVE KNOWLEDGE. 441 dents of that thinking, and may not belong to the constitution of the soul as viewed or known by any other being, whether creature or Creator. Tbi3 is not all. Not only are they used as though they were real, but they are used as real in order to prove that tbey are only regulative. He reasons thus : Upon tbe principles to which I must conform as the laws of my human thinking, do I conclude that it is more than probable that these principles themselves are true of human thinking only. How convincing and consistent such reason- ing is, it is easy to see. $ 257. 7. From Kant to Hamilton the transition is natural, be- cause the connection between their views is most intimate. Ham- Positive and ilton holds that our native cognitions are both Universal and Ne- Negative Ne- cessity. cessary. The Necessity of a cognition may, however, be of two species. It may be either Positive or Negative. It may either result from the power of the thinking principle, or from the powerlessness of the same to think otherwise. Of Positive Cognitions he says: " To this class belong the notion of existence and its modifications, the principles of identity, contradiction, and ex- cluded middle, and the intuitions of space and time." All these are discerned by the mind by a necessity which positively pertains to the objects discerned and in the reality of which the mind absolutely confides. To the other class belong the relations of Substance and Phenomena, and of Cause and Effect. These are necessary through the imbecility of the mind to conceive of existence in any other way than under these relations. This neces- sity is only a special case of the application of the more general law of the con- ditioned ; which in its turn is described as the necessity which constrains the mind to think of every object as a medium between two extremes, each of which is respectively contradictory of the other and so both cannot be true, while yet the mind must think the object under one of the two. The exposition and discussion of this Law of the Conditioned may be deferred till we consider its application to the special conceptions and relations of Cause and Effect. (Cf. § 297.) It is enough to say here, that it seems to be in its principle the same with the doctrine of Kant, that certain cognitions are necessary to the mind because of its peculiar constitution, which would no longer be so in case this constitution were changed or other than it is. They are therefore Regulative only, that is, they control the actions of the human mind and their products, because we cannot avoid employing them, knowing all the while that we are obliged to do this be- cause we are finite. They are true relatively, i. e. f true only in relation to our limited capacities. "We urge against this substantially the same objections to which the doctrine of Kant is liable, viz. : that we must use these very conceptions which are said to be merely Regulative and Relative, in the very judgments which we form of the mind and these very relations ,• and again, its tendency is skeptical, like that of Kant. It ought to be regarded with distrust if for no other reason than that it introduces contradictions between the decisions and dicta of the separate aetivb- ties of the intellect. §258. 8. To meet, or rather ; to shut off, the difficulties pro- pounded by Kant, and in part assented to by Hamilton, Faith has F a jth 'as con- been proposed as the source of certain original conceptions and pasted with 1 x r ' * knowlouge. primary beliefs. Sometimes Feeling, or some act more akin to the 19* 442 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §258. emotive than to the intellectual powers, has been urged as the originator and voucher of the primary beliefs, and indirectly of the knowledge which is built upon them. This faith or feeling has most usually had for its object or objects, the Absolute, the Infinite, or the Unconditioned, rather than the ultimate concep- tions under which finite existences are thought by the mind and the primary re- lations by means of which these existences are classified and connected. God, the Soul, Time, Space, Immortality — have been usually the objects which it is asserted are received by this original assent of Faith or Feeling. Sometimes the moral relations have been conceived as the direct object of the soul's apprehension, together with God and the soul. The tendency to cut the knot which an intellec- tual analysis has failed to untie, is most conspicuous as perpetually reappearing in the entire history of modern philosophy. The need of an ultimate and deci- sive authority for our confidence in the actings of the soul, has often prompted to a coup de main, by which some usurping power, under the fairest names, has seated itself in the place of rule, and the usurpation has been acquiesced in, by reason of the temporary peace and order which has followed in the intellectual convictions and the received systems of science, morality and theology. Descartes, having vainly sought for some criterion of truth which should assure him that his senses did not deceive him, and that his judgment in regard to his spiritual operations might be trusted, found repose in the veracity and benevo- lence of the Great Creator, of whose existence he was assured by the innate idea which attests both his existence and his perfections. This being given, the cognitions and inferences of the intellectual faculty may be trusted, when they are properly tested by the criteria or norms which the Creator himself has pro- vided. Kant, after despairing to find in the speculative Reason any warrant for trusting those necessary cognitions which are universal to all men, and assumed a priori as the conditions of all experience and all science, finds in the categorical imperative of the Practical Reason a voucher for the law of Duty. Unconditional faith in Duty was the corner-stone of his system, the only sure foundation which he could find among the ruins into which he had disintegrated the structures of the merely speculative Intellect, and upon which he could rebuild the same and make them compact and safe. Faith in Duty requires faith in God to defend and reward Duty. Hence the same Practical Reason which commands us categorically (i. e., unconditionally, and without asking or finding reasons or grounds) to believe in Duty, commands us to believe there is a true and perfect God. But such a God will not deceive his creatures. If we trust in Him we may confide in the specula- tive testimony of the Reason which he has constructed and created, concerning those conceptions which it originates and requires ; and may assign them the place which they take and hold in our knowledge, not as being merely a priori assumptions under which we are obliged to think, but as being fundamental truths which we must accept as real. By the Practical Reason we allow these forms of thought by which we must regulate our thinking, to become the representatives of those forms of being which control the world of reality. Jacobi felt the difficulties in which Kant involved himself and the minds of his generation, but was not content with the solution which he furnished. He adopted another, similar in principle, indeed, but slightly varied in its applications. To the power of apprehending that which is primary and unconditionally true, he gave the names, at first of Faith, afterwards of F*eUng and the Revelation of the § 258. THEORIES OF INTUITIVE KNOWLEDGE. 443 Divine, and last of all, of Reason Proper. The objects which this power appre- hends are not moral and religious objects and relations exclusively; but the objects of sense and consciousness with the relations which they involve, as truly as God, the Soul, and Immortality. These are all received by the direct faith of the soul, and this faith and the truth of what it receives is the precondition of all analysis, inference and deduction : In all these processes we simply analyze and explicate what is given to faith impliedly and as a whole. Jacobi simply asserted these principles to be the foundation truths of all knowledge. He did not show how they could be true or why we believe them. Indeed, he despaired of any such analysis. He did not feel adequate to illustrate them in the detail ; he simply rested in their truth. Schleiermacher recognized feeling — the feeling of dependence — as the ground and medium of all the knowledge of the Absolute that we can attain. But we can neither conceive of God nor define our concepts of him. All efforts in this di- rection, as well as their results, are entirely inadequate and misleading. So far he is at one with Jacobi. With him he makes feeling or faith the ground of our appre- hensions of the Infinite and Divine. In respect to our knowledge of and faith in the conceptions that are fundamental to finite knowledge — he would be foremost to assert that these are a priori conditions and assumptions of the intellect, and that nature herself is constructed in correspondence with these forms of human thought : we have therefore the amplest ground for trusting the processes that are essential to our higher knowledge and the results to which they conduct us. The relations of finite existence, including those of space and time, of substance and attribute, of cause and effect, were considered by Schleiermacher forms of exis- tence, or real forms in contradistinction to the subjective forms of Kant and Fiehte and the notion forms of Hegel. These are apprehended by the intellect directly, or, in the phraseology of his system, by the intellectual function, to the opera- tions of which, in connection with the organic function, all the forms of finite knowledge are to be referred. Some of the more recent German philosophers, as Chalglsen*, Eeiff, and pre- eminently Lotze, rest their confidence in the fundamental assumptions of the human intellect, upon ethical grounds. The questions propounded by Kant, viz. : " Suppose after all that the constitution of our nature should itself not be trust- worthy when it causes and impels us to think according to these original forms and fundamental assumptions ? Suppose that the relations or forms of things, which seem to correspond to the relations or forms by which we think should prove to be unreal ?" they answer thus : " We must believe that nature is benev- olent in her indications and. therefore true. We assume that goodness and vera- city regulate both the objective relations of the universe Avhich we study and the subjective constitution of the intellect which interprets it. For these reasons we rely upon the categories of both thought and being, and learn to think in accor- dance with them, trusting the results which we gain. As Hamilton (as we have seen): in his views of the extent and limits of our knowledge, followed Kant and Schleiermacher, so he borrowed from both the required solution. While he asserts that we cannot think the infinite and uncondi- tioned, because to think is to limit and to condition, he concedes that we know the same. When he is asked how ? he replies, by faith: we must believe in the Infinite. The extremes of our knowledge, between which we form our concepts — and out of the relations of which we form our concepts — wc must believe exist and are related 44£ THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 260. to one another. The fact of their necessary existence we receive by a direct insight, which he calls both faith and knowledge. He borrows from Kant conceptions that are appropriate to the Practical Reason — so far at least as ethical distinc- tions, moral liberty and a personal God are concerned. From Jacobi he adopts the term faith. With the doctrine of Schleiermacher the details of his theory of the Unconditioned are closely allied. Cf. Hamilton {Met., Lee. 38; also Appendix, Letter to Calderwood). That which gives plausibility to the doctrine that Faith or Feeling is the ulti- mate ground of this kind of knowledge is that it is not received by any act of conscious assent to propositions, of which the elementary concepts are first dis- tinctly apprehended apart and then united, but the mind first believes or knows before it reflectively discriminates its knowledges into their elements. Hence the act is called faith in opposition to and in distinction from judgment, the last being supposed to involve analysis as well as combination. Ethical and religious ob- jects are those which most frequently bring it into exercise, and these invariably excite more or less feeling. Hence the special source of these convictions is con- ceived as something not intellectual, and is simply called feeling at one time, and faith at another. The oversight lies in making these terms to imply that the act is not intellectual. It must be preeminently an intellectual act and power, for it conditions all the special acts and cognitions of which the intellect is capable. §259. 9. The immediate successor of Kant was J. G. Fichte, J. G. Fichte. whose system was proposed as a modification and improvement of that which was taught in the Critique of the Pure Reason. Fichte derived all knowledge, — the materials as well as the forms, the a posteriori and the a priori, — from the activity of the Ego. Every thing which the mind knows, being as well as relations, so far as it is known, is the work of the Ego, and is evolved from its own creative activity. So far as the categories of thought are concerned, Fichte endeavors to show that each one of them is necessarily involved in the several concrete creative acts by which the Ego constructs for itself the known universe. Its first act is to affirm its own being. But in this it must apply and evolve the law or relation of iden- tity, A=A. Its second act is to affirm the non-Ego. But this in like manner in- volves the law of contradiction, (A) is not (non-A). The third is to recognize the indivisible Ego as opposed to a divisible non-Ego. This involves the reciprocal activity of each on the other, and this implies the relation of Causative efficiency. The other relations are all evolved in a similar way by the productive activity of the Ego, together with the non-Ego which this activity calls forth. Time and space, substance and attribute, reality, possibility and necessity, etc., etc., are all ac- counted for by the creative activity of the Ego, as it proceeds from the simpler to the more complex processes and products of human knowledge. $ 260. 10. Schelling followed Fichte — by the effort to mediate Schilling's between him and Kant — so far as to provide for a common origi- eeories eca " nation and relationship for the subjective and objective. His in- tellectual intuition recognizes at first the indifference of both, from which it develops as correspondent to one another the forms of thought and the forms of being. Tho authority for the categories in this double application must be in that intuition which affirms them to bo common to the two. In his later philosophy, which was modified to avoid and displace the logical idealism of Hegel, Schelling assumes tho reality of concrete and actual being, and teaches the § 262. THEORIES OF INTUITIVE KNOWLEDGE. 445 mind's competence to originate and affirm necessary and original relations only in their application to, and by occasion of supposed concrete knowledge. For this reason he asserted for these a priori relations and for philosophy itself, what he called only a negative value. | 261. 11. Heijel substituted thought for Schelling's intellectual intuition, i. e., that mental activity which produces and is con- Hegel's theory cerned with the concept or logical notion ; but he made a fatal mis- thought, take in conceiving that thought, viz., abstract thinking, could be ex- plained independently of concrete knowledge and actual being, and that the for- mer could explain the latter by the relations of pure or abstract thought. He Avas therefore compelled, by logical consistency, to. endeavor to evolve and explain every form of actual being by the development or evolution of the notion from within itself. The categories or the original and necessary relations of knowledge, according to Kegel, are all the relations which are necessarily evolved in the process by which simple, i. e., abstract being is developed into the several forms of thought and ex- istence, and through them all, till the absolute is attained, i. e., till the process is complete and with it the cycle of the original relations or categories which are re- quired for its evolution. $ 262. 12. According to Herbart, some of the categories are the products of the action and reaction of ideas. They are not the ory- necessary laws or forms of the mind's knowledge, but are the growth and result of its psychological functions as determined by the laws which ^govern the formation and mutual action of the results of the impressions made upon the soul by matter, and the soul's reaction against them. These results are perceptions or representations. Concepts, or general notions, arise only when a number of similar objects have been perceived. These different elements in their struggle for reappearance crowd one another out of view, and only those are ap- parent which, being alike, reinforce one another, and so survive the struggle. The conceptions of Space and Time are series of reproduced objects, the parts of which are more or less indistinct, as they stand related to the here and the now. A thing or being and its attributes, is either an original whole analyzed into its con- stituent parts, giving the attribute of quality, or a whole with its attendant series of time and space accompaniments giving the attribute of quantity. The suc- cessful connection of these attendant parts or accessory series is affirmation — the unsuccessful is negation : both these involve the two corresponding forms of judgment or the apprehension of relations. The relations of substance to attributes and of cause and effect are inconsistent with the logical laws of identity and contradiction, which are assumed by Herbart to be original and independent laws of thought. To remove these inconsistencies is the object of his metaphysical system. This he essays to do by " the method of relations." It would seem that the logical laws are the only categories, properly considered, which Herbart accepts, for the reason that these logical criteria are applied by him as the fixed rules and original measures by which every other re- lation is tried and tested. 446 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §263. CHAPTER III FORMAL RELATIONS OR CATEGORIES. § 263. Following the classification of categories of being! es ° ry o r intuitions which we have adopted and explained (§ 250), we begin with those which we have defined as formal. These are also called Logical, for the reason that Logic has to do with the concept as such, i. e., the pure concept and its necessary relations. The concept as such consists of those elements, and those only, that must be conceived as present in every object when thought of. That is, it must embrace those elements only which are common to every such object, whether it is a real or an imagined being. These elements, while they belong to things as well as to concepts, are yet essential to the concept and the other entities of pure logic, and hence are referred pre- eminently to the power of thought. We begin with being. This will be readily acknowledged to be the most extensively applied of all the concepts, and there- fore fundamental. Everything which we know, we know to exist. To know is impossible and inconceivable, if it does not involve the certainty that that which is known, exists or is. Being is the correlate of knowledge. Hence, this concept is apparently fundamental to fmiSmeutaJ. 86 au others. It belongs to every object with which the mind has to do in knowledge, and it belongs to each with equal propriety — to Him whom we call, in the poverty of our language, the Being of beings, and to the most transient and trivial creation of the humblest of His creatures ; to the universe in the most comprehensive meaning of the term, and to the ma- thematical point, which is the product of the thought of a moment. We sometimes dignify the being which is independent and per- manent with the assertion that this only or truly has benig, or only and truly is ; but this is by a metaphor only, and does not in the least affect the proper import of the term or of the con- cept for which it stands. The positive existence of the object, but neither its dignity nor its duration, is expressed by the word. § 265. FORMAL RELATIONS OK CATEGORIES. 447 § 264. Being is the most abstract of all possible . ,. t . f . , The most r„b- concepts. After every property or relation which we Btractofaiithe know of an object is set aside from any existing thought or thing, there remains the affirmation ; this is. This re- sulting concept cannot be thought away. For this reason it is called logically the first or the most elementary of all concepts. As it is the last which we reach by analysis, it is the first with which our synthesis begins. Psychologically, the knowledge of being in the concrete, pre- cedes that of being in the abstract. We know individual beings before we know being as a concept. Logically, or, more properly, metaphysically, the concept of being is the first and most fundamental of all the concepts, because it is the most extensively applied, and is the highest of our gen- eralizations (§ 249). But it cannot be understood as a concept, except by means of individual objects. To begin with the con- cept in the abstract, excluding that knowledge which interprets and makes it clear, is literally to begin with nothing. To at- tempt to develop from it actual being, is to give an example by failure, of the truth, ex nihilo nihil fit I Hegel begins the de- velopment and explanation of our real knowledge with the con- cept of being in the abstract, and seeks to construct and develop from this the conception and knowledge of real existence, and the relations which it involves. In doing this, he is obliged to interpret his meaning by a tacit assumption of that which he formally ignores and denies — i. e., to draw upon direct and pre- sented knowledge for the interpretation of the conceptions and relations which he professes to develop and account for. The at- tempt is vain ; the method is false ; the solution is impossible. The knowledge of being is expressed by judgments or proposi- tions, the subjects of which are known individually. We tacitly assert or think of every such object; ^,or this, is or exists. From these we generalize the concept — being. Being or existence is not, however, an attribute or a relation, though it is conceived or treated as such when it is thus generalized. It is obvious that being must be assumed in order that an attribute or relation may be known. § 265. Being cannot be defined — i. e., resolved into ** i ? d f finaW . e & ' and mdetermi- any more elementary constituents. It can be de- nate - 448 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 265. scribed, however, by the conditions or circumstances under which it is present to the mind : When we ask, What is being ? we cannot answer in the way of definition. But inasmuch as whenever we know we apprehend being, by referring to the act of knowing we understand, though we cannot define, the import of the concept; i. e., we explain the concept, being, by the act which involves and supposes it. It was said (§ 196) that all concepts are founded on attributes or relations generalized, aud that the. only difference between nouns and adjectives arises from their use and not^their meaning; the same content being present in every case — a content of attributes only. How, then, it might be urged, is it possible that there should be any concept of being at all, if being is not only not an attribute, but is the direct contrast of an attribute and must be supposed to make an attribute conceivable or pos- sible ? This inquiry has in part been answered. In order to be turned into a concept, being is treated as an attribute ; it is predicated of the individuals to which it belongs and thus is made to suggest itself as essential to any relation. It is worthy of notice also that some fixed permanent attribute as of standing, etc., is usually selected to image or represent beingness. Simple being is a concept wholly indeterminate. It stands for itself and for nothing besides. It is supposed in every other. It must be assumed to determine every other. We must begin with being, before we can add a single characteristic to make it defi- nite. This is what Hegel had in mind in his assertion : Being or entity is equal to nothing, i. e., it is equivalent to a notion without content. As an abstract conception, it has no relations to any other concept, and consequently no attributes ; it is wholly un- defined. "Being, the undetermined, immediate object of know- ledge, is in fact nothing, no more nor less. Nothing is [has] the same determination, or rather, absence of determination with, and, for that reason, is equivalent to, simple entity. Hegel, {Logic, vol. i, p. 22; Encyc, p. 406.) But though being, as a concept, and in its relation to other concepts, is indeterminate, it is not without signification. The concept is taken from and affirmed of and interpreted by, indivi- dual beings which we actually know by direct knowledge. § 266. FORMAL RELATIONS OR CATEGORIES. 449 § 266. From being we pass to relation ; both ex- -, , i • i ■ • t i • r* Relationship. istence aud relationship being involved m the act of Diversity aud knowing. By relations, individual objects, as well as concepts, are distinguished and connected. But relationship in- volves diversity in the concept produced, and negation as the judgment by which diversity is affirmed. Two entities — i. e., objects apprehended — are essential to the apprehension of a connecting relation. But if the two are known they must be distinguished — i. e. } known as different from each other, in order that they may be again connected. It follows that the relation which is the most extensive of all others, is the relation of diversity or difference. In every act and object of knowledge two relations are sup- posed, those of diversity and of similarity. If there is more than one concrete Being, one is diverse from the other. If both are alike Beings, i. e., are comprehended under the concept Being, they must be alike at least in that they are both knowable. In brief, diversity and similarity — i. e., logical or formal sameness — are everywhere present. This truth is asserted in the proposi- tion, that every act of knowledge is at once an act of analysis and of synthesis. In every single act of knowledge we separate — i. e. } distinguish — in order that we may combine. We can only unite so far as we separate, and we unite by similarity. The relation of difference or diversity is expressed by the proposition, this being is not that. A is not B, or B is not A ; the color is not the taste, the taste is not the color ; the pictured moon is not the mind, the mind is not the moon which it pictures. I am not the object seen or tasted, etc., etc. It will be remembered that these propositions are all individual propositions, and that none of them are or can be general. The individual goes before the general in these propositions of relations, as in all others. From the recognition and affirmation of relations in general are evolved what are called relative concepts or notions. From the Relative no- 1 , . tions. Negative negative proposition which expresses the relation of diversity are notions. produced what are termed negative concepts. No sooner is A distinguished from B, than we can apply to it the negative notion of not-B. In the same way reciprocally, the notion not- A can be affirmed of B. These two notions are purely relative. The whole content or import which they express, is limited to the single relation in which they stand to the other object, which other object, A or B, as the case may be, is supposed to be positively known. 450 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 267. In like manner, other relative notions may be formed, as if we take a substance and it puts us to sleep, we conceive the unknown something which produces this sleep-making; that is, we need know it no further than by its relation to this effect. The only notion which we have of it may be purely relative to the known effect. The negative relation, as indeed any relative notion, is at first apprehended as individual, and then generalized. No sooner is A pronounced to be not B, than we proceed to apply this to C, D, E, F, etc., as well as to A — indeed, to all objects except B itself. We need know nothing more of them than that they are, to be justified in classing them alias not-Bs, or in affirming of them the negative concept thus generalized. This is the ground of the division of all real and conceivable things by dichotomy, as it is called. It will be observed, however, that negation expresses a relation between two actual beings, or two beings treated or conceived as real. It supposes two positives known or conceived, each of which is thought as related negatively to the other. The concept nothing — nonentity — is a purely relative concept. All being or entities, whether real or imaginary, are grouped under the most general of all concepts. To this is attached the relation of negation. What is expressed, is the proposition that the concept is exhaustive, and that it is impossible to con- ceive or believe in any thing beside. By a fiction of speech and of thought this proposition is contracted into the concept nothing — nonentity — as though there were a really existing object negatively related to being. To form it we group all known or knowable objects under the general concept of being and attaching to this the negative particle, make nof-being=no th.mg=nothing. When Hegel asserts that the concept being or en ity equals nothing in its import, he has in mind that it is a concept which cannot be analyzed into any constituent concept or thought element : it is therefore unrelated to any other ; it is undeter- mined : it has no notional or formal content. So far from being true that this concept has no import, no concept has an import so extensive. Its import is reached in the various forms of direct knowledge, which furnish the material and meaning to every concept, and a reference to which is supposed every time the concept being is used. Hegel reasons that, because the concept being is the siimmum genus among con- cepts, it is the originator of all other concepts : not only so, but by the law of self-evolution, it is the originator of things or actual beings. The failure of the attempt, and the absurdity of the theory on which it rests is manifest when the effort is made to cross over from the notion world to the real world ; when the effort is essayed to evolve time and space, matter and spirit from concepts only. The effort seems to be successful only because the real world with its relations is ever ready at hand behind the concept world which symbolizes it, to furnish tho signification which is required. Real being, and real relations are very easily confounded with the generalized concepts of the same. The two are easily inter- changed, and it is by a kind of intellectual juggling or slight-of-hand that any success appears to be attained, or any conviction is produced. substance and § 26 ?. Diversity or negation is applied to a being maiiy" te con- as distinguished from its relations, to one relation as ce 1V ed. distinguished from another relation, and also^ to one § 267. FORMAL RELATIONS OR CATEGORIES. 451 being as distinguished from another by means of its relations. We distinguish or separate objects from one another whether material or spiritual : first, in real knowledge,by intuition or direct inspection; next, in thought knowledge, by employing relations for this purpose, and especially those similar relations by which beings are grouped under concepts. This introduces us to the category of substance and attribute, so far as it is merely formal. Whenever a being is thought of, i. e., is distinguished from another being by the number and the extent of its relations, then we have the relation of substance and attribute in its pure or abstract form. A substance formally con- ceived is a being distinguished by certain relations. An attribute is one of the relations which thus distinguishes a being. Every concept whenever it is complex, as having a de- finite content, implies the relation of a whole constituted of and separable into parts. This implies the relation of more or less. The extent of a concept, as applicable to more or fewer objects, and therefore as higher or lower, implies the same relation. The relations of wholes and parts and of greater or less are properly formal relations, as involved in the very nature of the concept. They are relations of formal or logical quantity, which is dis- tinguished from mathematical quantity by characteristics subse- quently explained. The relation of diversity with its several applications suggests the relation of identity. In affirming that A is not B, or is diverse from B, we imply that A is identical with itself. That the mind comes to the distinct recognition of this relation at an early period of its development, and makes frequent appli- cation of it afterwards, is too obvious to need confirmation. That the relation is original, and is intuitively discerned, is equally clear. If a concept is known as identical, it is of course implied that the individual beings to which it belongs have similar relations in common. These individuals cannot be distinguished, except by means of the relations of time and space, which are conceivable as possible of either, but not of both together. One concept is distinguished from another by the relations which make the con- tent and determine the extent of the one and the other. Many hold, that the first object to which identity is applied 452 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 268. is the soul itself, as distinguished from the diverse states of which it is conscious. As the Ego distinguishes itself from its changing states, it knows that the states are varying, but the Ego is the same. In doing so, it must compare itself at one time with itself at another, or itself in one state with itself in another. Identity again may be affirmed of a material object, as of a house, a ship, a tree, or a horse. In such cases the objects are perceived at different times at least, and are often changed in form, appearance and properties. The test or standard of identity may be real and natural, or it may be conventional and factitious. But the relation itself is not thereby altered. Identity may also be applied to a purely mental product. Often it is interchanged with similarity, when it is applied to a concept, e. g., I have a similar image of the same object which I previously imagined or perceived. It is not necessary that the concept should be formed by all men from the same individuals, but it is meant that the similarity between the individual objects is so perfect that one individual may be substituted for another in forming it, and that it may be applied to one as freely and as properly as to another. When it is thus applied it concerns the relations of content and extent, and signifies that the same defini- tions and divisions are applicable in every case. § 268. To guard against using concepts in different oms of identity, senses in any of the processes of thought, the law of identity, the law of contradiction and the law of excluded middle are set forth as the three fundamental laws of thought, i. e., of formal thought. These respect the identity and diversity of con- cepts only. They are the axioms of logical thinking, but not neces- sarily the rules for every form and mode of knowledge. They are such practical rules as have been found necessary from the dangers to which men are exposed from the various forms of expression in which concepts and their relations are phrased. The law of identity is designed to avoid the twofold danger of supposing, on the one hand, because the diction is altered, that the concepts, propositions, and reasonings are changed, or on the other, that, because the phraseology is similar, the meaning is the same. Complex concepts only can be tried and tested by this law; and these can be tested both in their content and extent. The § 268. FORMAL RELATIONS OR CATEGORIES. 453 law applied to the content asserts that a concept is, for purposes of logic, the same with the sum of its constituting elements : A= (a, b, c, d, and e) ; i. e., all these being taken together, the one is convertible with the other. When applied to the relation of extent, it asserts that the concept as genus is identical with the total of its contained species or subordinate parts. To make the logical law of identity the mere meaningless truism, — A is A, i. e., that a concept in the same form of diction is identical with itself, — is inept and absurd. The logical axiom or law of contradiction : A is not not- A, is only a generalized application of the intuition of difference to any concept whatever, taken in both extent and content. A thing or a concept is not another, it is not any one of the things or con- cepts from which it differs, nor all of them united. This truth, expressed as a rule, requires that the concept "should never be confounded with or substituted for either." The law of excluded middle is, every B is either A or not- A. This is another application of the intuitions of difference and identity when generalized. When A has been distinguished from not- A, it is at once discerned that these two concepts divide the extent of all conceivable existences into two classes. This truth is then stated as a principle ; which is ready to be used as a law whenever it is required to guard or correct our thinking. Much evil has resulted from the error of taking these three logical laws as the original and the only laws of our knowledge. It was entirely natural for philosophers who were practiced in the schools of formal logic to suppose that everything which man be- lieves to be true could be demonstrated by the methods and after the principles of the syllogism. The tenacity with which this persuasion has been adhered to is most remarkable in the history of all systems and schools of thought. For a long period after the revival of philosophy it seemed that man would never cease to attempt to give a logical demonstration for the very axioms and principles on which all demonstration must rest. Logical proof was required for all knowledge, for the belief in a material world, for our confidence in memory, for the distinction between the facts of experience and the illusions of the imagination ; in short, for everything known or believed by man, — and to logical proof these three laws of thought were assumed as the axioms. Hence, 454 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 2G9. the attempt was persistently made to found upon these laws the whole structure of human knowledge, and to deduce or demonstrate from them, the validity of this knowledge in all its forms and applk cations. CHAPTEE IV. MATHEMATICAL RELATIONS : TIME AND SPACE. We proceed to consider the mathematical categories ; or those relations which involve the belief in time and space. These re- lations are of the most extensive application. They all must in a sense be recognized in every act of consciousness and perception. By means of these, material and spiritual objects are parted and united, are individualized and generalized. They suggest the space and time which are infinite and absolute — the correlates of limited time and limited space. In order to relieve the treatment of the subject as much as possible, we will consider them first under their more familiar aspects and relations, and afterwards in those which are more recondite and difficult. We begin with I. Extension as given in Sense-Perception ; or the relations of matter which introduce and require the knowledge of Space. § 269. All matter is known as extended. The Development beings or objects of which we become cognizant in rliations^el- the use of the muscular and sensorial apparatus are tension. extended. The percepts and things which are* pre- sented to the sensorium as eye and ear and hand, are perceived as extended. It is not meant that this extension in one or all of its dimen- sions is known at first as separable from the matter to which it pertains and of which it is affirmed ; but as belonging to matter and affirmable of it. All extended objects are known as ex- tended, at least in two dimensions. We cannot conceive the eye and the hand to rest upon or to move along any so-called object without the apprehension of an extended surface. A ball or cube when followed by the eye or grasped by the hand is known to return upon itself, and both are sooner or later known as ex- § 270. MATHEMATICAL RELATIONS : TIME AND SPACE. 455 tended in three dimensions or directions, i. e., as high, broad, and deep. This extension is first known as outer, i. e., as enclosing matter. But when the child peeps into a box, or surveys from within, the walls, floor and ceiling of the apartment with which it is familiar, it distinguishes the surfaces which are inner or enclosed by matter, from those which are outer and enclose matter. After the process of perception is complete by a synthesis of percepts and their relations, the mind proceeds to analyze these elements, and to think of them separately from any single sub- stance. But after disposing of all the qualities apprehended by sense-perception, it still finds a residuum in the relations belong- ing to the inner and outer surfaces of matter as already described. The hand experiments upon these surfaces, and finds them rough or smooth, etc. The eye discerns them as variously colored, as light or dark, etc. But no one of the senses finds what we call their extension. There is no sense-perception to which this is appropriate, and over against which this may be set as a quality. Moreover, this very property involves the recognition of a void, to which it is also conceived to have constant relation. What is this void which we call space ? What is that property in matter which requires the recognition of space ? We may find further aid in answering these questions, if we consider first the attributes and relations which involve the kindred questions in respect to time. II. Of Time as apprehended in consciousness ; or, the relations of events which introduce and involve the knowledge of Time. §270. Every psychical act or state, whether appre- hended more or less distinctly as a part of the whole reSed^the series; and the entire series viewed as an unbroken actsofthesoul - whole, are known as continuing or enduring. How soon, or whether it is by the gradual discipline or the in- stant application of the powers that psychical phenomena are separated into distinct events, we need not inquire. Whenever they are distinguished, the whole and the parts are known as continuous or enduring. An act that is literally instantaneous, a psychical state beginning and occupying no time at all, is abso- lutely inconceivable. What we call instants are not timeless, but the least knowable or appreciable portions of time. As every ob- ject of sense-perception — whether many as one, or one of many 456 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 270. — must be known as extended, so it is with the phenomena of consciousness. Continuance, or duration,belongs to each and to all. But there are two distinct classes of psychical objects given to consciousness ; first, the energy of the ego by which it manifests its continued, unbroken, and identical life ; and second, the special activities which change every instant. As the subject of chang- ing activities — the soul knows itself to be living and acting contin- uously. It also knows itself as acting and suffering in states that change as continuously. Some of these states may seem also to coincide with others, as one continuous or successively repeated act of knowledge may run side by side with two or more diverse states of feeling. Upon this continually existing and proceeding life of the soul, all its special activities and states are projected, as it were ; as one portion of extended matter is perceived over against the back- ground of other matter more extended than itself. These activi- ties thus connected are known to exist in a series involving the relations between one another of now, before, and after. These relations are applied first of all to the individual activities of the soul. But just as we speak of portions of matter as here, there ; before, behind ; within, and without ; so we apply these time rela- tions to the states of the soul. As we find one portion of matter included by or including other portions, so we can cut off a single portion of the continuous life of the soul by voluntary or invol- untary effort, and contemplate those states which are included within, or are excluded from it. Time may be conceived as void of psychical phenomena; as space is void of material beings and acts. Not that time can be absolutely void, but portions of the soul's existence can be considered as such, in the sense explained. But it is not at all essential to the knowledge of events in the relations of time, that time should be distinctly conceived as void. We can know events as past, present, and future, by considering each of them as successive phenomena of the continued life of the soul. We have to do thus far only with time-relations in the con- crete, and as given in consciousness. By consciousness as here used it is obvious we do not intend merely the power or the act by which the soul knows its own states as present and imme- diate. In this sense we cannot be conscious of duration. We §271. MATHEMATICAL RELATIONS : TIME AND SPACE. 457 must include some use of the representative power in respect to past and future events, as well as the belief that what is rep- resented, was or will be actual. Consciousness must be enlarged to this extent of meaning, before it can connect objects in the re- lations of time. III. Of the mutual relations of Extended and Enduring objects. § 271. Material objects, as we have seen, are ap- prehended by sense-perception as extended. Spiritual C ern 8 e extended acts and states are known in consciousness as endur- objects to^the? ing. But sense-perception and consciousness occur in fact, as two elements in the same psychical energy or state. As a consequence, the relations of extension and duration are intimate and interchangeable, and the conceptions and language originally derived from and appropriate to the one, are appro- priated to the other. First : The relations of time are transferred from the activi- ties and phenomena of spirit, to the activities and phenomena of matter. Duration or continuance is, as .we have seen, originally dis- cerned of the activities and phenomena of the spirit. To these the relations of time are directly and properly applied. When these relations are affirmed of more than one object, whether of matter or spirit, the intervention of the memory of the observer is required. We cannot say of the trotting of a horse, of the flight of a bullet, or of any other motion, that it continued so many seconds or minutes, without supposing the observer who is all the while looking on, to translate the objects really taking place into objects as perceived by himself, i. e., into results of acts of his own, each enduring so much time. Material acts or phenom- ena must be connected by the soul's subjective activity that they may be recalled. Moreover, whatever may take place in the series of objective or material acts; that which is unobserved is totally omitted in the estimate of time : to the mind as enduring it is, as though it had not been at all. The relation of time can neither be applied, nor thought of as applied to any material acts or events, except through the medium of the duration of some person who has first applied to them his own spiritual ex- periences either in fact or imagination. Every such applica- tion, when fully translated or explicated, is made as follows. 20 458 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 271. While I was thinking or observing for so long a time the, horse trotted or the bullet sped for the same space of time. Second : But though duration, as a spiritual experience, is the ultimate standard or measure ; the actual measures of the dura- tion even of spiritual phenomena, — are taken from the objective or material world. The reason is obvious. Any standard furnished from individual and spiritual experience must be so indeterminate to one's self as to be useless, and, moreover, must be wholly inaccessible to every one besides. Though, in our ulti- mate analysis, we say to ourselves, " While I was thinking and feeling so and so, the pendulum vibrated, the horse ran, the bullet sped so or so long," yet it is practically impossible for us to fix and render familiar any individual or often repeated series of thoughts and feelings, so as to use it as a standard even for our- selves. Even if we could do this for ourselves, we could not bring it within the reach and use of others. But two individuals, and a great number of individuals, can observe the same vibrating pendulum, the same advancing and retreating shadow on the dial, «r the same rising and setting sun, and can use these as standards to measure all phenomena whether internal or external. Third : the language of duration is taken from material and extended objects, for a similar reason. In fact and from neces- sity, all the relations of time are expressed in terms originally appropriate to material objects, and the relations of extension which they involve. Long, short, before, after, etc., were first applied to material objects, and from them transferred to the re- lations of time. As will be seen hereafter, this is but a single example of the necessity by which the language and terms of every kind that are applied to spirit and its relations must be de- rived from space-objects and space-relations. Material objects are not only known to be extended, but as measuring one another, i. e., as susceptible of quantity. Quan- tity supposes the inquiry, How much? How many For, How great? It has for its answer, So much, So many, So large — referring at once to some object which as a unit or standard measures a whole. The extended material universe, as at first vaguely and confusedly conceived, is unbroken, having only superficial exten- sion. By the process of sense-perception it is soon broken into § 272. MATHEMATICAL RELATIONS : TIME AND SPACE. 459 separate objects, each of which may be compared with the whole, in respect to breadth and the other relations. As extended objects divide and measure one another, so one or more separate acts or states of the soul which follow one another in a series, may be contemplated as dividing, and yet making up this whole, the whole of time being constituted by the continued activity of the soul during these its different acts. Measure in the general sense, as applied to spirit objects and material objects, im- plies the relation of whole and j)aris. This relation, as we have seen, is involved in the analysis and synthesis of sense-perception, consciousness, representation, and thought, etc., and is essential to the very process and product of knowledge in every form, and hence belongs among the formal relations. Measure, in the more exact sense, we need not say, supposes number. IV. Of extended and enduring objects as Imaged or repre- sented: or, space and, time objects as enlarged and measured by the Imagination. § 272. Only a small portion of the material uni- , ,,,,,, . ., Limitations of verse is apprehended through the senses by any single sense-percep- act of the mind. The hand can cognize an object of only equal extent with itself. The eye has a far wider, but still a very limited range. All beyond either, is apprehended and measured by the representative power. Even within the limits to which the eye reaches, and upon those very objects which the eye seems to command, the representative power is largely em- ployed in estimating extent in the dimensions of distance and size. That which i? before the eye is the utmost which the eye can in any sense be said to perceive, and much even of this extent is estimated by the eye of the mind. The objects within the reach of the hand and the direct inspection of the eye, we measure by select- ing some one as a unit, in the manner explained. Those beyond these bounds, we measure in a similar way, with this difference only, that the material measured, and the standard by which it is measured, are furnished by the imagination only, working upon the suggestions or occasions which perceived objects furnish. We seem to perceive the real height of the lofty tree that shoots up from the horizon against the sky, while it is but a mote to the eye; we think we perceive the width of the stream that threads 460 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 273. the distant meadow with a silvery line, but these estimates arc possible only by the aid of the picture-making power, that brings its objects by the side of the tree under which we stand, or upon the margin of the stream where we sit. We have already learned, in considering the acquired perceptions, that it is only by the aid of the imagination that we supply the defects of the senses, and interpret their indications. , , § 273. We are dependent upon the imagination Beyond these ° . . we use the im- alone for our estimates of distance and size beyond agination. # > ** the limits of actual perception. These estimates vary with the actual knowledge which we have gained of such objects by inspection and can recall by the memory, and with the practice which results from the frequent application of defi- nite standards by the representative power. The adult surpasses the child immeasurably in this power. The man of various observation and of disciplined powers excels the man of limited knowledge and of untrained habits ; the modern, instructed and taught as he is, presents a very striking contrast to the wisest of the ancients. A child between three and four years old, of no inferior intelli- gence, and of good opportunities for instruction and thought, was once asked how far distant the sun sets, and answered promptly, In the next field. This child had walked and driven for miles in every direction from its home, and would have remem- bered, if prompted by leading questions, that all the roadways along which it had gone were bordered by adjacent houses, fields, and gardens, like those within sight, but it had never learned to combine these objects by imagination or to measure such a whole by the unit of a familiar standard so as to estimate their relative dimensions. The conceptions and estimates of the uncultivated man are very like those of the immature child, especially if such a man is con- fined by his habits of life to a single narrow valley or a limited range of travel. Every thing beyond these limits is confused and unmeasured. The horizon of his actual perceptions, or the slightly enlarged horizon of his expeditions for hunting and war, includes all that he knows or soberly imagines. He may at times fill the blank vacuity beyond, with objects that are monstrous, horrid, and gro- tesque — objects that are terrific to his unintelligent fears, or are § 274. MATHEMATICAL RELATIONS : TIME AND SPACE. 461 bewildering to his insane expectations ; but be fixes on few or none which hold definite or rational relations to others as measures or bounds. The spatial world formed by both child and savage, is well represented by the rude maps of the early geographers, in which the countries actually traversed are drawn with a certain degree of definiteness, though the near is out of all proportion to the remote ; but the regions beyond are a blank bounded by an un- certain line, along which uncouth monsters are placed, or the un- known and measureless water or desert shuts in the picture. The child and savage neither think nor care how large are the sun and the stars, or how many are the steps, the miles, or leagues, which would be required to reach them. In this way, and in this only, can we explain the very inadequate conceptions on these subjects which the early astronomers accepted. § 274. Our estimates of time-objects, like those of space-objects, are largely the work of the representa- time- objects tive faculty. The passing and present acts and states of our own spirits, and the coincident operations and phe- nomena of the material world, are the only time-objects of which we have direct cognizance. Past objects are gone. Future objects do not yet exist. Present objects alone directly confront the mind. The past must be recalled by memory, the future must be anticipated in the imagination, i. e., both must be re-pre- sented to the mind, so as with the present to complete the series of time objects. To measure past events, we must be able to recall , . , . , , , , Different ca- tnem in then* order, so as to have before us the ma- parties in dif- • i i • • -r» -i-m 1'erent men. terial which we are to estimate. But men diner greatly in their capacity to revive past objects in their fulness and order. If the capacity to recall with success be possessed, time and effort must be added that any past series may be restored, so as to be estimated and measured. Some self-discipline and prac- tice are required that a measure may be prepared from our inner experience which shall be ready for use, and also that the same standard shall be uniformly applied. Differences in both these particulars in different x , Differences in persons, and in the same persons at different times, the estimates n -..™ -, • i of time - account for the singular differences which are so no- torious in our estimates of time. No fact is more generally ac- 462 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 274. cepted, than that two series of events may occupy the same length of time as measured by the clock, and may seem to vary very greatly from one another as measured by the mind. If we are waiting impatiently for the arrival of a friend or a railway train ; or if we are listening to a tiresome conversation or a tedious lecture, the time seems very long. On the other hand, if the conversa- tion is interesting, or the pastime is absorbing, the time flies swiftly along. The child cannot believe that the hour has come which calls him from his play, to school or to bed. A trip by a steamer seems much longer than a trip by railway, when the time is the same. Each are sensibly shortened if the tedium is beguiled by spirited conversation. A week spent in the daily routine of regular employment, goes quickly by ; while a week of constant traveling, filled up by a rapid succession of exciting objects, often seems surprisingly long. The years of childhood glide slowly away. Every day and every month stretches to an interminable length, because our. present enjoyment brings no disappointment, and because it stands between us and some future happiness which the mind is impatient to grasp. The years of our busy middle life slip hastily by, though we would fain delay their flight, because we are too busy to measure the passing years. The constructions and measurements of space and time which we have thus far considered, do not involve definite relations of number and magnitude. They are made for practical use and convenience, and require only general impressions of their time or space relations, or a ready reference to some familiar object or series as a standard of measurement. The mind judges the time spent in one occupation to be abou|; as long as the time spent in another. ' It took me about as long, or twice or half as long, as to do this or that familiar act. The distance from A to B is equal to the distance from C to D ; or it may be greater or less/ But when we say London is 3 or 4,000 miles from New York, or, the moon is 238,650 miles distant from the earth ; or, Washing- ton and Napoleon were born and died so many years after the birth of our Lord, we apply measurements of a different char- acter, by means of definite standards of both space and time. It is interesting to notice in this connection, the history of the progress made by the human race in the standards of both time § 275. MATHEMATICAL RELATIONS: TIME AND SPACE. 463 and space. The savage measures time by the budding of the oak, or the return and departure of birds or other game. By and by he marks the coming and going of the moon. Then rude de- vices like the clepsydra or the sand-dial are introduced. Last of all, the scientific observer employs the chronometer and the astronomical clock. So, in standards of length, the mind has passed from the use of parts of the body, to measurements by the aid of the pendu- lum, or a portion of a circle of the earth, in order to find an accurate and trustworthy standard. Standards of both space and time are derived from whence stan- ,•11., i • • i -vr • i dards for both material objects, real or imagined. JNo images can be space and time formed of space or time as such, or of what are some- times called pure or empty space and time, but only of those ob- jects or events which hold a relation to either or to both. When these are pictured or imaged, they carry with them those rela- tions which the originals necessarily involve, and from which they cannot be severed in reality or in thought (§ 206). Thus, for a standard of space, the words yard, or rod, or mile, may call up some visible or tangible object most indefinitely pictured, or with the words, a minute, an hour, a day, or year, some series of events that have required a remembered period, or a part of such a period. Both these are pictured, not for their own sake, but for the sake of the time or space which they suggest. But these standards are concepts as well as images, and they cannot be com- pletely understood, even as images, till they are considered also as concepts. This leads us to consider V. Space and time objects as Generalized; or, the Concepts of the relations of objects to time and space. § 275. Different individual objects and events hold . 1.11 How tne rela - similar space and tune relations, whether they are tions of space , and time ob« presented to sense and consciousness, or are represented jecta are gen- to the imagination. Space-objects- may be alike in relative position, distance, form, size, etc., etc. Time objects may be alike in coexistence, in antecedence or subsequence, in their relative place in the order of occurrence, and in the intervals by which they are separated from one another or from any other event. The mutual relations which exist between time and space objects may also be common to any number of both classes. 464 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 275. These relations are as readily generalized as are the attributes of material or spiritual things. It is as easy to generalize the forms and sizes of objects as their color or their taste ; the beforeness and afterness of a spiritual act, as any one of its qualities of knowledge or feeling. It is true there is this difference : these relations are in their nature incapable of being directly picturable to the imagination, like the properties of matter and spirit. In order to represent them at all, we must first picture the objects which hold them and so recall or suggest the relations themselves. But as concepts these generalized products are as easily formed and comprehended as any others. The words by which these relations are named and known, are as truly generic as the terms usually called common. All of them, it is true, have a more or less direct relation to an indivi- dual place and time, and seem therefore to be less general than the other appellatives ; but they are all capable of being equally attributed to many individual objects, and hence are as truly generic as they. We cannot say here, there, now, before and after, without implying that an individual observer occupying an indi- vidual place at an individual portion of time apprehends the object in this very relation, but it is possible that many objects at different times may be here or there, and v. v. now or then, before or after, i. e., at the same time, in different places. Hence the hereness and thereness, the nowness and thenness, the beforeness and afterness may be common to many individuals, and like sensible or spiritual qualities, may be affirmed or predicated of all. These objects may be grouped under, or classified by means of these general relations. The terms which denote these, take their place side by side with other common terms. Very many adjectives of time, as prior, later, present, past, and future, and of space, as long, short, high, deep, and broad, and of form, as circular, trian- gular, square, spherical, and conical, and of motion, as swift, slow, etc., will occur as belonging to these classes of words. All these classes of terras, like all other notion w T ords, require some image to explain and illustrate them to the mind. But they are pecu- liar in this, that every object in nature and in spirit has some re- lation to time and space, and hence it is indifferent what one is cited to exemplify these universal relations. § 276. MATHEMATICAL RELATIONS : TIME AND SPACE. 465 VI. Of Mathematical Quantity ; the process by which its concepts are evolved, and their relations to time and space. § 276. These concepts naturally divide themselves into two classes, the concepts of magnitude and the con- mathematical cepts of number, or the concepts which are respect- geometrical, ively related to space and time. We begin with those which imply the existence of space, as being the most easily ex- plained and understood ; i. e., with geometrical concepts or con- cepts of pure magnitude. Of these the most familiar are, the point, the line, the surface, the triangle, the square, the rectangle, the rhomboid, the solid, the cube, the sphere, etc. These terms stand for both images and concepts, in other words, for the products of the imagination and of thought. As images they are individual, as concepts they are general. The creative imagination idealizes not only the sensible and spiritual properties of these objects and phenomena, but it ideal- izes their space and time relations, § 181. It transforms the perceived edge with its actual breadth and ragged outline into the ideal line which has neither breadth nor undulation. It smooths the undulating surface into an evenly lying geometrical superficies. In the same way it refines the blunted corner of a die or cubical block into the mathematical point which is ideal- ized as having place but no extent in any direction. These rela- tions cannot themselves be thus imaged, but an object itself can be imaged with these relations thus idealized. Every such object is at first individual. But when the relation is generalized, we have a concept in place of an image, holding the same relation to the concrete and individual which belongs to any other concept. These concepts, like all other concepts, need to be imaged and il- lustrated by concrete objects. Only in this way can their import be understood, and their validity established. All geometrical conceptions are dependent upon the assumption of the space-rela- tions of objects. Without these space-relations they have no meaning. They presuppose the belief in these space-relations, as actually belonging to every material existence. They rest upon the belief in that absolute and infinite space which limited space presupposes and involves. Space, with the space-relations of ob- jects, is the ever-assumed background upon which all geometrical 20* 466 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §277. constructions are projected, and over against which all its pro- cesses are interpreted. The reality and the validity of these conceptions Geometrical ° rest entirely upon the mind's own power to construct Quantity. an( j comp^e^ them. The mind knows that it can construct these concepts, and knows what they are when con- structed. Geometry postulates that every student may make these concepts for himself. Its language is confident, " draw a line" " conceive or construct a plane," " think of a point" It lays the foundations for its reasonings in these postulates. It defines the meaning of these constructions by analyzing their relations to one another and to the space to which they all have a commcn rela- tion. It illustrates, or, as we usually say, demonstrates any rela- tions unknown before by referring to new constructions as exem- plified in some material substance, for example, in a cube or sphere, a cone, a dot, a chalk line, a rough surface on a blackboard or pa- per bounded by marks — which are no mathematical entities but serve to represent them and hold the attention to the constructions they represent. In the so-called demonstrations of Geometry one figure is supposed to be drawn in connection with another. Addi- tional figures are placed by the side of those with which we begin, or those already drawn are so divided as to enable the mind to bring into comparison figures that had been inaccessible and in- commensurable. As it is with the original and simpler definitions, or postulates, so is it with these complex constructions : space is supposed as the necessary attendant of each and of all, makiDg possible the original constructions and the evolution of the new relations, which the mind discerns ultimately so soon as the requi- site figures and connecting lines have been prepared and com- bined. As has already been shown, § 229, the nerve and force of the geometrical demonstration rests more upon these successive intuitions than upon that element which is properly deductive. The concepts of § 277. The concepts of number are conditioned upon number. those relations of objects to time which are involved in the mind's continued activity in uniting them as parts into wholes. To number, some object must be selected which shall serve as the unit, i. e., which can be conveniently repeated as a recurring part of a whole of extended objects, or of a continued series of men- tal states. § 277. MATHEMATICAL RELATIONS 7 TIME AND SPACE. 467 These constituent parts are numbered when the mind connects each with the next by relations to its own activity in time. That with which it begins is called first. The next, when connected with the one taken first in time, is second. When ano- ther is thus connected, we have the third, and so on. Thus we count, or number. The act seems so simple as scarcely to admit or require explanation. It is obvious, however, that this act is only possible as we connect and contemplate objects in relation to a consecutive series of mental acts — that is, a series of mental acts following each other in time. We find, then, that the relation of number requires that ob- jects should first be connected as wholes and parts, and then contemplated in an arrangement which depends entirely upon the time-relations of the mind that views them. In other words, number depends upon those relations of time which we as- sume and know to be inseparable from the soul's own subjective activity. When a series of mental states is itself measured and num- bered, it must be remembered that in reflective consciousness this series itself is made objective to the mind. It is treated or viewed as though it were a series or whole of material objects. It is contemplated by a series of acts wholly subjective, involving as spiritual acts, the attribute of duration to themselves, and as successive, the relation of number in the objects which they unite and measure as wholes and parts. Whatever objects are numbered must be arranged in a continued series. This is possible only by the recognized relation of such objects to the mind's continued action in contemplating them. They must also be viewed reciprocally as wholes and parts, as the mind gathers the objects, when thus arranged, into a group, which it breaks into parts, reuniting these parts with each other at its will, and making m its units larger or smaller as choice or chance directs. To both these relations time is the necessary condition, — to the continued subjective act of the mind in connecting objects into a series, and to the arranging of them as wholes and parts. In other words : To the act of counting, time must be assumed as both the subjective and objective condition ; but the relations by which objects are viewed or connected in the act of counting 468 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 278. when abstracted, generalized, imaged and symbolized, are the relations of number. These relations can be applied to any objects whatever — to material objects, to spiritual objects, to acts or states of the mind itself, to the very acts of the mind in numbering ; in short, to any objects whatever, whether of direct or reflex cognition. Any series of objects can be used as the symbols or images of number. Thus a row of marbles, of kernels of grain, or a series of marks is usually selected. Such objects can be readily inter- changed, and they are chosen because they suggest little more than their numerical relations. For convenience of recording and re- calling the results of the processes of counting, arbitrary symbols have been selected. Thus, for two objects made one by a single addition, we employ the symbol of two marks, as in the Roman system, IT, — later, the Arabic character 2 ; then III Rom., 3 Ar.; then instead of five marks we use V and 5 ; instead of four and six, V diminished by I going before and increased by I fol- lowing, or the Arabic characters 4 and 6, etc., etc. The principal concepts of number are the unit, the sum, the dif- ference, the multiple, the divisor and the ratio. These concepts cannot be defined so readily as they can be imaged and exemplified. To explain and illustrate their import we must go back to the several acts which represent them. Their meaning is originally taught and successively enforced by directions to select certain objects and proceed with them thus and thus, i. e., they rest upon postulates as truly as do the concepts of geometry. They assume that the mind can perform certain thought-processes which result in certain thought-products. The psychological condition of these processes is the arrangement of ob- jects in a series, whether material or spiritual. Their logical condi- tion is the reality of time-relations, and of time itself as making these relations possible. That number depends upon and implies time, is obvious still further from the language which we continually use in our definitions and analyses. We say, add this so many times ; ten taken twice, i. e., two times ten, is twenty ; ten divided one time- by two, or diminished once by three, is respectively five and seven. § 278. The application of number to magnitude, or The applica. * , «' ,. , „ . tion of number ot the concepts oi discrete to those of continuous to magnitude. #1 1 1 • . quantity, depends on the mutual relations ot time and § 279. MATHEMATICAL RELATIONS : TIME AND SPACE. 469 space objects which have already been explained, § 273. "We take any portion of space as a whole, we divide it into parts, we number these parts, we discern ratios between them. "We ex- press the powers of curves by their equivalent formulae of lines as symbolized by numbers, etc., etc., creating all those conceptions and performing those processes which modern analysis has disco- vered and applied. VII. Of the application of mathematical conceptions to Material phenomena. § 279. Pure Geometry deals only with ideal con- mathematicar structions in ideal Space, and pure Arithmetic and applicable & to Algebra with ideal concepts conditioned on ideal material ob- Time> T k e p QSS ibility of applying these ideal crea- tions to material things and phenomena is explained by the fact that the concepts of number and magnitude are all generalized from the relations of concrete objects and events to both space and time. In the order of time and acquisition we know applied number and applied magnitude before we know pure number and pure magnitude. The latter are always ex- plained by the former. On the other hand, when we apply the concepts of pure mathematics to material substances, we find that those properties which were left out of view in forming them must be brought into view to modify our ideal inferences. In esti- mating the velocity of bodies we think of them only as capable of constant force and of accelerated motion. "When we com- pare the results of our mathematical processes we find that they do not hold good of real phenomena, because they assumed what rarely if ever actually occurs, i. e., a force that is entirely constant and equable. Or perhaps, they omitted to recognize the increase of resistance consequent upon the increase of velocity. Thus in Mechanics, bodies are viewed as attracted by gravitation, as held together by cohesion, as impelled by a natural or artificial agency, as capable of both force and motion, as acquiring and losing velocity. For the purposes of this science gravitation is idealized as a constant force manifested in motion, the rapidity of which is inversely as the square of the distance. The nature of gravity itself as a material agent, is not considered, nor that of inertia; nor is the resistance of intervening media, but only the simple fact of motion, or a tendency to motion, with certain constant 470 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 280. relations to space and time. In like manner cohesion is defined by the relations involved in the phenomena of motion. So the laws and properties of bodies in motion or in pressure are expressed by space and time relations. Whether bodies do in fact move or tend to move with regularity in these relations so that their motions can be measured or computed, are facts that can be ascertained by observation and induction only. For example : Newton's great laws in respect to the causes and continuance of force and motion are all generalized observations of facts of sense enforced on grounds of high probability. In other words, they are grounded upon induction. These laws or facts being assumed, we reason and compute with respect to the direction and rate of bodies in motion, with respect to the pressure and weight of bodies tending to move, and with respect to the results of bodies conspiring together in motion, just as we can reason or compute with respect to a sizeless or weightless point that is supposed to move in a breadthless line. That is, we apply to these material objects the concepts, relations and rules of the pure mathematics. But when we compare the results of our computations and demonstrations with bodies actually existing and phenomena actually occurring, we find that the two do not coincide. When we inquire why the prophecy given by our demonstration or computation is not fulfilled by the facts of the velocity, weight or pressure of the material bodies with which we come in contact, we account for the discrepancy by those elements or properties which we were obliged wholly or partially to disregard, such as inertia, resistance, friction, and the like. In many cases these are so unimportant that we subject them to no estimate, but take the result as exact enough for our purposes. In other cases, as in gunnery, astronomy, and the working of machinery, we seek to express the value and effect of these very elements in special mathematical formulae, and subject them to mathematical computations similar to those which we had applied to the prime forces. VIII. Of the relation of space and time concepts to Motion. § 280. It is obvious that the space and time rela- Time and space ,. « ■, . , , .-, i* i i • / relations, can tions oi objects when thus generalized become muversals generalized. er of a very wide extension. The inquiry naturally sug- gests itself whether these relations can be generalized §280. MATHEMATICAL RELATIONS : TIME AND SPACE. 471 still further, and so be included under relations of a still wider extension, as well as subordinated under one another. We find the medium of such generalization in the capacity of material objects for motion. Every material thing can be moved. The eye and the hand learn to separate the objects of perception from the great universe with which they are at first united, by the circumstance that they are moved and movable. The limit- ing surfaces, edges and corners of such objects are determined and traced out by the moving of the hand or the eye along or up to their several limits. Every act of motion brings with it the possible suggestion of some one of the relations of space. We find, moreover, that there is not a single relation of space which cannot at once be brought before the mind, and, as it were, suggested by motion. Each one of these can, in a certain sense, be expressed and defined in terms and concepts of motion. Even the relations of position can be expressed by means of motion. The' meaning of here and there, above and below, behind and before, are all definable by acts of motion— to and from, this way and that way,'— joined with counter or resisting mo- tions, which stop their progress. When the question is asked of a child, What do you mean by any one of these terms ? he inva- riably replies by explanations by motion. He says, in effect, Move an object in this or that direction, and then arrest it, and it will be here or there, before or behind, above or below. The relations of time can also be generalized by means of the motions of material objects. A moving body suggests duration as truly as it does extension, when all its import is received ; the act of starting suggests then as truly as it does there ; the act of stopping suggests now as well as here. It may have come to do so by a secondary and transferred meaning ; but it does so in fact and by a universal and inevitable connection. Even when time is thought or affirmed of mental acts and events, it is still represented by motion in space. Hence by a natural consequence, when time is affirmed of processes (or states) that are purely spiritual, its relations are represented in language and thought by motions that are corporeal. It follows that motion furnishes all the materials for a common generaliza- tion of both space and time objects, and for the comprehension and arrangement of time and space relations in the same logical system. 472 THE HUMAN INTELLECT.' §281. This explains why mathematical entities or quanta are so natu- rally denned by means of motion; a fact confirmed and illustrated by many such definitions. These definitions always rest upon, and can be expressed by postulates, and these postulates always suppose an act or acts of motion. In geometry we say, draw a line ; terminate or bisect a line, giving a point ; move a line and it gives a surface. In arithmetic and algebra we say count, that is, unite as wholes, or add, subtract, multiply, and divide ; all of which terms suggest or supposes some images taken from spatial motion. § 281. The extended and enduring objects which euJuring Tb- we have thus far considered, are limited objects, and jects are hmi- fa Q relations to space and time which they involve are also limited. Whether they are presented by sense-perception or consciousness, whether they are represented to the imagination or generalized in thought, they are necessarily limited. The so-called dimensions of extension — length, breadth, and thickness, — and the various relations of duration, can only be affirmed of finite beings and activities. If affirmed of the In- finite, it is of its relations to the finite. Even mathematical re- lations can be conceived of only as limited or definite quantities. These, as we have seen, presuppose some objects imagined to exist in space, or series of such objects connected by acts continuous in time, of which certain attributes and relations are affirmed, i. e., they invariably presuppose limited objects. The infinite and indefinite have therefore no place in mathe- matics. What is called the mathematical infinite is either a quantity as yet not measured or numbered, i.e., a quantity in re- spect to which these processes have been begun but are not yet completed ; or a quantity so nearly commensurable with another that it may be substituted for it. The so-called infinite quanti- ties of the mathematics are quantities not yet actually or proxi- mately defined, i. e., mensurable but not yet measured or defined. They should be carefully distinguished from what, in distinction from them, may be called the actual infinite or unconditioned. The conception of the mathematical infinite or indefinite may be rendered possible by the real infinitude of time and space, but in import the two are wholly diverse, if indeed we can be said to have any concept at all of the latter. § 282. MATHEMATICAL RELATIONS : TIME AND SPACE. 473 IX. Of Space and Time as infinite and unconditioned. § 282. The several attributes of limited extension . i • i • i • Extension and and duration, involve relationship to and questions duration distin- guished from, concerning space and time. but related to These attributes and properties, when considered collectively are called collectively, extension and duration. The appropriate names of the entities to which these properties in- volve relations, are space and time. Thus distinguished, exten- sion and duration, i. e., extension and duration in the concrete, or the extension and duration of individual objects, are known by experience; while space and time, as soon as they are appre- hended at all, are known a priori, i. e., to be the necessary and fundamental conditions of all actual existences and events as ex- tended and enduring. It is not asserted that in applying these attributes to objects of experience the mind necessarily adverts to the relations to time and space which they imply, but only that when the mind gives attention to them, it cannot fail to discover that these relations are implied, and with them the existence of time and space. To make this discovery the mind may need to make the experience of many objects of sense and consciousness. It- may need the discipline of many acts of attention to separate and analyze what is at first known confusedly and without discrimination. In order fully to appreciate the time and space relations of ob- jects and events to one another as well as to time and space themselves, the imagination may need to be called into exercise. One material object may need to be annexed to another and still others to these, before space can be fully understood in all the relations which it involves to the extended objects thus believed or supposed to exist, or to other extended objects besides. In like manner, many events must be experienced, in order that the com- mon relations of all these and of all conceivable enduring objects to time, may be distinctly apprehended, and clearly distinguished from the time which is common to them all. The psychological conditions of knowledge are clearly distinguishable from the es- sence and the evidence of the objects that are known. The one describes the subjective conditions that render it possible for an in- dividual to employ and apply his mind in such a manner as to discern a fact or truth. The other describes objectively, what in 474 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 283. its nature is know able by all individuals under these subjective con- ditions, and the evidence, if there be any, by which it is known. § 283. Extension and duration are also the limits joctJ and ° " or the grounds of the limits of objects and events. These pertain not to space and time, but to objects and events as related to Space and Time, and therefore and by this means, to one another. When, for example, I perceive a box either inclosing or in- closed by what we call a void, and affirm that what is without is not that which is within, or conversely ; both that which is within and without are conceived as matter with surfaces mutu- ally coinciding, but yet dividing or limiting the one from the other. If I conceive of the outmost limit of the universe of mat- ter and ask what is beyond, immediately as I ask the question I attach the limiting surface to other matter which is conceived to be beyond, and the outlines of which I begin to trace by the con- structive motion of which the imagination is capable. Of this outline, one portion, viz., the limiting surface already described, is fixed. The others are not yet drawn ; the mind has no occa- sion even to conceive them drawn, and it rests in the knowledge or belief that "it might complete them in any way in which it chooses. But as soon as they should be completed they must ne- cessarily be conceived as inclosed by or with matter, for the simple reason that an extended surface of that which has no actual being cannot be conceived or thought of. In a similar way the instant which terminates or limits an event, is the beginning of another as yet inchoate or incomplete. So the beginning of an event already past, is the end of the event that was transacted before it. What we call Space and Time are those entities which can be occupied, as we say, by beings and events, i. e., which render their actual existence possible, and which in rendering them possible, also make it possible that they should be limited from one an- other, i. e., distinguished from one another by their common relations to space and time. It follows that : Relations of place do not belong to space, but they belong to bodies perceived or imagined to exist in space. Relations of time do not belong to duration, but to events occurring in, i. e., presupposing time. § 285. MATHEMATICAL RELATIONS : TIME AND SPACE. 475 § 284. Space and time are unlimited, simply be- In what sens9 cause the conception of limitation is inapplicable to them, |^ c e e *"J because by its very nature it is only applicable to and unlimited - affirmable of extended matter and occurring events, — when we attempt to apply it to Space and Time we can only do it by moans of objects and events. This attribute is therefore simply negative. It denies that the relation of limitation which pertains to bodies and acts can pertain to Space and Time. It is important to notice this distinction in order that we may preserve ourselves from many of the alleged incompatibilities which are conceived to be involved in the attempt to know or conceive of Space and Time. Thus Hamilton (Met. 38) urges that we are under the necessity of conceiving space and time either as an absolute maximum or an absolute minimum, and that it is impossible to do either, because the mind, as soon as it has fixed the limits to the ultimately great or the ultimately small, will immediately overstep or go be- yond the limits which it had just established, and will find itself continually baffled in its impotent efforts to grasp or conceive either. In the same strain, Kant had urged that the mind, in its attempts to conceive of space and time, must continually set up two incompatible propositions — which he calls Antinomies — both of which cannot be true, and yet one of which would seem to be necessary. Both overlook that the maximum and minimum which we attempt to conceive are not space and time, but bodies and events as limited in space and time. The maximum and minimum in the case are not space and time, nor are they concepts of either, but they are concepts of bodies and events as re- lated to and limited by space and time. They are limited concepts, and in their very nature logically inapplicable to objects which cannot be limited. To attempt to think of time and space under any such concepts, however great or small, is to make an effort which will involve certain and constant contradiction and inconsis- tency. To attempt to picture time and space to the imagination is impossible, for we can only picture objects and events with definite properties and charac- teristics. Even when we lay aside all properties except what we call their time and space relations, what we picture or imagine are still limited objects in space and time — objects with some defined limits of extension and duration, but not space and time themselves. It is true that every time we picture or image such objects we must think of their relations to their correlates, time and space; but time and space, in themselves, can neither be imaged nor pictured. § 285. Again, Space and Time cannot be genera- gpace and lized or apprehended by or under concepts. Concepts Generalized suppose definite attributes of objects limited by and u ^ c e e r ts Li s her individualized in Time and Space. But Time and Space are withdrawn from these conditions of generalization, for they are necessarily supposed as the conditions and correlates of 476 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 286. all individual existences and their attributes. Even the relations of extension and duration, by which individual objects are pos- sible, cannot be intelligible except by means of these very entities which are the necessary correlates to these universal properties of all individual existences. These related properties are gen- eralizable, but the entities themselves to which they are related cannot be generalized. Space and Time cannot in the ordinary sense of the term be defined. If we cannot form concepts of these entities by means of generalized attributes or relations, it is manifest that we can- not define these concepts, because to define is simply to state the attributes into which a concept thus formed can be resolved, § 214. They are not simple concepts, for simple concepts pertain to single indecomposible attributes or relations, § 197, and no one will for an instant believe or contend that the import of either space or time is exhausted by any single property or relation. What, is demonstrated to be necessary from the nature of the case, is confirmed by fact and experiment whenever we make the trial. Whenever we endeavor to define these entities we find ourselves employing concents which presuppose that they are already known. Every concept that we use is an attribute or relation of some object or event which exists in space or time, and which implies some relation of the same to one or both. We fall, therefore, continually into the circle of using in our defini- tions terms that presuppose that to be known which we attempt to define or describe. § 286, Space and time are known by intuition as They are — r . J - known as the the necessary conditions of the existence and the con- conditions of „ ,_ . „ , . their limited ception oi all o meets and events. J^very object and correlates. r _ . ... . , , i . i i event, as has been already explained, has properties or attributes which imply the existence of these entities. In knowing that these objects exist, we know that time and space exist as their actual conditions. In conceiving of these objects or events as real or possible, we must conceive of them as related to space and time, and, of course, must recognize time and space as their logical conditions. While, then, it is true that we can neither generalize nor define time and space, because the very attributes which we must employ imply both, it is true, on the other hand, that we cannot § 287. MATHEMATICAL RELATIONS : TIME AND SPACE. 477 generalize or define any object whatever without recognizing both, and, therefore, time and space must enter as the material into all our concepts. Again : Though time and space cannot be defined or conceived by the relations of objects and events which imply time and space, yet, on the other hand, as the correlates of all such objects, they can be explained to the mind by means of the limited relations which imply their real existence. So far is it from being true that, be- cause space and time are known by intuition, they are known out of relation to limited objects and events; that rather it is only possible to know them by means of such relations. On the other hand, they are only known as implied in the relations which are called collectively the extension and duration of such concrete realities ; on the other, they cannot be generalized nor defined by means of any such relations, because all imply their existence. It has already, § 247 (5), been asserted that the distinct recog- nition of these correlates, is, as it were, the fifth or last stage of the mind's attainment in cognition ; which is reached only by the few who are trained to habits of speculative analysis and discrimina- tion. If this is so, then it is obvious that the number of thinkers is very small who have any occasion to ask the question, whether space and time can be defined, or whether they are known out of relation to or by means of their relations to the concrete. But the persons who have occasion to ask these questions can certainly comprehend that the very relations which cannot pos- sibly be used to define time and space, because they imply them, may, for this very reason, be the only medium of bringing them before the mind for the uses of thought. § 287. What then, are space and time f Are they 7 7 . . . „ Whatare space substances, qualities, or relations? Or, are they the and time ?eon- forms or subjective conditions of knowledge by sense or consciousness? Or is it impossible to ascertain what they are? These questions will force themselves upon the attention of a few ; and they require an answer. Are they substances? That they are material things with sensible qualities will scarcely be imagined or contended by any one. No one would honestly believe or seriously urge that they can be heard, or smelled, or seen, or tasted, or touched. Space 478 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §287. and time are not perceived in such ways or by such means, and hence cannot be classed with material substances. Nor are they spiritual beings. They have none of the properties of spirits. They cannot think, or feel, or will. Nor can they be apprehended by consciousness in the special sense of the term. Neither time nor space is a spiritual substance. They are not qualities or properties of spirit or matter. Dr. Samuel Clark maintained that space and time are attributes or modes, and that inasmuch as both are infinite, there must be an Infinite Being to which they belong. James Mill, in his Analysis of the Human Mind, chap. xiv. asserts that they are simply abstract terms which stand for collective conceptions of those attributes of extension and duration, which belong to individual beings and acts. But it needs no further discussion to prove that they are and can be neither. Nor are they simply relations, as Leibnitz maintained. This philosopher defined space as an order of co-existence/ and time as 'an order of succession/ {Third letter to Dr. S. Clarh, § 4, ed. Erd.,p. 752.) Using exten- sion as its equivalent, he defines space as the order of possible co-existences ; and time as the order of inconstant possibilities. {Reply to Bayle, ed. Erd.,p. 189.) Calderwood defines time as " a certain correlation of existences," and distinguishes his own view from that of Hamilton, who calls it " the image or concept of a certain correlation of existences." {The Phil, of the Infinite, 2d ed., c. v.) It is evident from what has been said already, that space and time are neither relations nor correlations, but correlates to beings and events. Extension and duration are the relations or correla- tions in question ; but these involve space and time as realities. Again : Space and time are not forms of intuition [?'. c, presentation] in the sense suggested by Kant, that is, not subjective forms only. This philosopher taught that if we distinguish the matter apprehended by perception and consciousness from the forms of this matter, then space is the form of sense-perception or ex- ternal intuition, and time is the form of consciousness. There is a sense in which this doctrine is true. Extension is the form of material objects in the sense that all such objects are perceived as extended, and none can be apprehended except under the form or condition of being an extended object. When all the matter which is given in the various sensible qualities is thought away, the rela- tions of extension remain. The same is true of the matter furnished in conscious- ness as distinguished from its relations of duration. But the doctrine as further expounded by Kant is open to two exceptions. First : § 288. MATHEMATICAL RELATIONS : TIME AND SPACE. 479 He fails to distinguish between extension and duration as relations, and the correlates space and time which they involve. He does not notice that these very relations, after or under which all objects and their concepts are and must be formed, do in their very nature involve the intuitive knowledge of space and time as realities, and that to suppose that they are only forms is to exclude and eliminate that which is given and affirmed by their very nature. Second: The suggestion or the assumption that they depend on the subjective constitution of the human intellect is unwarranted by positive evidence and is contradicted by the testimony of the intellect itself. The supposition that intellects of another order might possibly exist, which could know objects without the relation of space and time, is without proof and against proof (2 259.) In other words, that which makes it possible and necessary for extension and duration to be the forms of perception and consciousness is the fact that the objects of these two modes of knowledge are in reality related to the entities space and time. § 288. St. Augustine is reported to have said — " What Conclusion , is time? If not asked, I know, but attempting to explain, I know not." This, in one view, is correct. We know by intuition that time and space exist, but to explain or define what they are, is not so easy. It may relieve our embar- rassment in part to explain why we cannot answer the question in one sense, and why we can in another. If, in answering the question ivhat, it is expected or required that we should class them with objects limited by space or time, or objects having material or spiritual properties, or objects holding relations to space and time, in other words, that we should class them with beings, qualities, or relations, in the ordinary acceptation of these terms, then it is obvious that we cannot answer this question at all. We cannot say what they are. But we know that they exist, i. e., there exist realities which answer to the terms. Their existence is implied in the existence of every limited object and property, because every such object and property is related to them. We cannot believe or know that the one exists without knowing that the other exists also. But can we in any sense of the word, what, explain the nature of that which we know exists? We can, so far as to say that they are entities to which all these limited objects are related, and which are, therefore, correlates to them. If they are correlates to all limited objects, they are known and described by their relations to them. By their very nature they are entities to which these objects bear these rela- tions, and by their relations to these objects they are known and thought of They cannot be said to be defined in the sense in i- 480 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §289. which limited objects are defined, but they can be suggested or described to the mind as the necessary correlates of limited ex- istences, by means of their relations to them. These relations to both space and time are represented in thought and language by means of motion, as has already been explained, and hence it follows that space and time are set forth in thought and language by the same medium. We conclude that in whatever sense space and time are uncon- ditioned, infinite, and absolute, they are not so in any such sense as to exclude the possibility of being related to the finite. By means of these relations they can be both conceived and known. (§342.) CHAPTER V. CAUSATION AND THE RELATION OF CAUSALITY. § 289. From the formal and mathematical intui- Causation as a . . law, and as a tions we come to those which are real, i. e., which are principle. . . . required to explain the attributes which are respect- ively distinctive of material and spiritual beings. Into these real relations all the actually existing properties and powers of matter and spirit are resolved. Under the laws which regulate their operation, the effects and purposes that describe the universe are accomplished. We shall consider first, the relation of causality or causation. The relation of causality is sometimes called the Law, at other times the Principle of causality, causation, or cause and effect. Causation- as a law is viewed as a relation actually prevailing in or ruling over the finite universe of physical and spiritual being. Causation as a principle is placed first or highest with reference to the other concepts or truths which depend upon or are derived from it — either relatively or absolutely, according as the truth is received as original or derived. The first of these appellations is objective and real, and indicates its universal preva- lence among objects actually existing. The other is subjective and logical, and designates the place which the relation or the proposi- § 290. CAUSATION AND THE RELATION OF CAUSALITY. 481 tion in which it is expressed holds in the systematic arrangement of our knowledge, (cf. § 246). Causation as a law may be stated thus : Every finite event is a caused event, or, more briefly, is an effect. Causation, as a principle, may be thus expressed : Every finite event may be ac- counted for by referring it to a cause as the ground or reason of its existence. It is scarcely necessary to observe, that the proposition, every effect must have a cause, is purely and simply identical. It is mere tautology, expanding in the predicate what had been im- plied in the subject. The term effect, in its import, implies a cause by a logical necessity. To say an effect must be caused, is as reasonable as to say, a caused event is caused, or, xy = x X y. § 290. Causation, both as law and principle, is „ 3 ' Mr r r Event defined. affirmed of events. But what is an event f An event is something which is known to be, which was not ; or which begins to be or to occur. Events are, therefore, finite, i. e., limited by relations of space or time. Their existence or occur- rence implies change. Something is here and now which was not. Of these changes it is affirmed that they were caused. In the material world, events are changes of place or relative position, motions in space, changes of form, changes of properties in respect to existence or intensity. They are often called pheno- mena, i. e., manifestations to the senses or the consciousness of some power or agency. Events or phenomena are more numerous and conspicuous in the vegetable and animal sphere. There is growth, change of form and of structure, the manifestation of new colors, odors, and above all, there is constant motion. In the mental or spiritual sphere, new thoughts, new feelings, new purposes, pass before the observant eye of consciousness faster than they can be accounted for. But besides phenomena of these classes in the world of life, which appear in acts, states, or qualities, more or less lasting, there are still others in the existence and production of new and separate beings, material and spiritual. Besides these, there are conditions or states more or less per- manent which require to be accounted for, such as the equilibria of forces, or pressure, as illustrated in the action of gravitation or electricity, the tendencies of fluids at rest or in motion. All 21 482 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 291. these, so far as tne law of causation is concerned, come under the class of events or phenomena. Many of these so-called events and phenomena are a combina- tion of several, and made up of many units. But whether simple or complex, each one of them is caused. If the question be raised, What is a single event, or the simplest phenomenon ? we have only to reply, that any change, the least extensive in space, or the briefest possible in time, which can be discerned by human ob- servation, is a single event. § 291. Again : we distinguish between the causes Cause distin- _° & _ . °. . '. __ guished from of an event and the conditions 01 its actually pro- ducing the effect. The stroke of a hammer is the cause of the fracture of a stone, of the flattening of a leaden bullet, of the heating of a bit of iron. The conditions of the effect would, in such a case, be said to be the properties of the stone, the bullet, or the iron. In any such case the effect is frequently said to be the resultant of the joint action of the striking hammer and the resisting stone, lead, or iron. This doctrine is thus generalized by Mill : " The real cause is the whole of these antecedents (or conditions), and we have, philosophically speaking, no right to give the name of cause to one of them exclusively of the others." (Log.,B. iii., c. v., § 3). To the same effect, says Hamilton : " Every effect is only produced by the concurrence of at least two causes (and by cause, be it observed, I mean every thing without which the effect could not be realized)." {Met, Lee. 3.) In common life a distinction is made between the efficient and patient cause, the last being used for the object, i. e., that on which the causal agency shows a result, or upon which it is exerted. It is obvious that that whose activity is most obvious or demonstrative, is called the efficient. The patient or recipient often exhibits no force or energy, as, the cohesion of the stone, lead, or iron in the cases supposed. Sometimes the objects in their matter and chief elements are said to be the same, but the force or causal agency is applied under diverse conditions of quantity, time, or distance: as a chemical agency is doubled ; the gravitating force operates with a varying energy ; a wave of light acts with twice a given ra- pidity. These conditions are called in scientific language, the laws of the acting of the forces or powers — the causal agents — of nature. § 292. CAUSATION AND THE RELATION OF CAUSALITY. 483 § 292. Of causation both as a law and a principle we assert that the relation is original and independent. canDot'be ? " Those who regard it as secondary and derived usually Sm^eiation* resolve it into some relation of time. The history of speculation abounds in such attempts. This is not surprising. The relations of time pertain to all objects whatever. If objects are connected by the relation of causality, the same objects must also be united to observation either as co-existent or as succes- sive. The most conspicuous advocates of this disposition of the causal relation are David Hume, Dr. Thomas Brown, and John Stuart Mill. Hume defines a cause as a constantly precedent, and an effect as a constantly subsequent event. The necessity by which conjoined objects are connected as cause and effect, arises from their being united in the mind's own experience, and the consequent fact that the thought or observation of the one determines the mind to a lively idea of the other. They are discovered to be thus re- lated by the constant conjunction of the two. Dr. T. Brown agrees with Hume that the relation of cause and effect is nothing more than the constant and invariable connec- tion of two objects in time, — the one as antecedent and the other as consequent. Brown differs from Hume in holding that two objects need only be conjoined in a single instance in order to be known as cause and effect respectively, while the theory of Hume requires that they must be frequently conjoined in order to be causally connected. Indeed the interest and meaning of Hume's causal connection depends upon the tendency of the mind to think of those objects together which have been observed to be conjoined in fact. Brown contends that the only use of re- peated observations is to enable the mind to analyze or separate complex objects into their ultimate elements; a single conjunc- tion of any two clearly distinguished objects, in his view, gives their causal connection. " A cause, therefore, in the fullest definition which it philosophically admits, may be said to be, that which immediately precedes any change, and which, ex- isting at any time in similar circumstances, has been always, and will be always, immediately followed by a similar change. Priority in the sequence observed, and invariableness of antecedence in the past and future sequences supposed, are the elements, and the only elements, combined in the notion of cause. By a con- version of terms, we obtain a definition of the correlative effect; and power, as I 484 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 292. have before observed, is only another word for expressing abstractly and briefly the antecedence itself and the invariableness of the relation." — T. Brown, Inquiry, etc., Part L,Sec. 1. Cf. Lectures, Lee. vii. The Theory of Hume and Brown has, in its essential features, been reproduced and defended by John Stuart Mill. It is fully and fairly stated in his own language in the following extracts from his System of Logic. " The law of causation, the recognition of which is the main pillar of inductive philosophy, is but the familiar truth, that invariability of succession is found by observation to obtain between every fact in nature and some other fact which has preceded it." * * " To certain facts, certain facts always do and as we believe always will succeed. The invariable antecedent is termed the cause ; the invari- able consequent, the effect ; and the universality of the law of causation consists in this, that every consequent is connected in this manner with some particular antecedent, or set of antecedents. Let the fact be what it may, if it has begun to exist, it was preceded by some fact or facts, with which it is invariably con- nected."— B. IIL,c. v., g 2. "I have no objection to define a cause, the assemblage of phenomena, which occurring, some other phenomenon invariably commences or has its origin. Whether the effect coincides in point of time with, or immediately follows, the hindmost of its conditions, is immaterial. At all events it does not precede it; and when we are in doubt between two coexistent phenomena, which is cause and which effect, we rightly deem the question solved if we can ascertain which of them preceded the other." — B. III.,c. v.,§ 6. In other words, causation does not imply production, depen- dence, efficiency or force, but simply uniform succession or con- stant conjunction. All events or begun existences are or may be presumed to be invariably preceded by certain events, more or fewer, in a set or assemblage, each one of which is as truly a cause as any other. Against these views of Mill and others, we contend that the re- lation of causation cannot be resolved into any relations of Time. Our reasons are these. It is conceded by Mill, that in some cases, no interval of antecedence or succession can be discerned between the cause and the effect. To set aside the force of this un- deniable fact, he contends that though this is true, yet all those cases in which we have occasion to resort to the law of causa- tion, are cases of begun existence, in which the cause is obviously before the effect. He insists therefore that "practically" his view of the nature of causation cannot be controverted. This we grant, so far as to allow that in most instances in which we have occasion to discover a cause or predict an effect, the event is a § 293. CAUSATION AND THE RELATION OF CAUSALITY. 485 begun existence. In other words, practically every caused exis- tence is a begun existence, and every cause precedes its effect, and every effect follows its cause : or, which is the same thing, the re- lations before and after usually attend the relation of causality. This is simply the truism that all events, i. e., all begun exis- tences, or phenomena, occur in time; or, stated in another manner, that all finite phenomena are subject to time-relations. But it is one thing to assert, which is all that Mill does in this passage, that we can determine causes and effects by meams of their constantly attending relations of time, and quite another to show that the two relations are identical. That they are not identical is proved by the fact that, without the assumption of the relation of causation as distinct and real, logical deduction would be impossible. This has been shown in the analysis of deduction already given. Induction also would be unmeaning. It is idle to contend that the force of the reasons and laws by which we explain and predict events is exhausted by resolving them into uniform antecedences and successions in time. This has been already shown under Induction. It will be more conclusively proved when we consider in its place the explanation of Induction given by Mill in his own theory of the nature of the causal relation, § 294. This explanation not only fails to satisfy the mind in respect to induction, but it reacts against his under- lying and assumed construction of the causal relation. But aside from these considerations, we contend that the very statement of the proposition is its own sufficient refutation. The human mind clearly distinguishes the relations of time from the relations of causality] and production. The intelligent and universal use of the whole vocabulary of terms appropriate to each of these classes of relations is but the constant attestation that this dis- tinction is made universally and necessarily by the mind; in other words, that causation cannot be resolved into any relation of time. § 293. The relation of causality being established, we assert that the mind intuitively believes that every f cauKty ?n- event is caused, i. e., is produced by the action dent™ y of some agent or agents, which, with respect to the effect, are called its cause or its causes. The reasons for this view are the following : — 486 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 293. (a) We explain the occurrence of events in common life, on the assumption of this truth. To explain phenomena is to refer to the beings or agencies which have occasioned them. When these producing agents are discovered, and the modes and laws of their action are referred to or unfolded, the process of ex- planation is complete. (b) When an event has occurred which is not yet accounted for, and the mind is aroused to the effort to solve or explain its occurrence, it believes just as firmly that it can be accounted for in the way described, as if the explanation had been in fact attained. It is as confident before as after the cause has been determined, that its occurrence depends upon some cause or causes. Upon this confidence rest all the inquiries and experi- ments which it sets on foot. (c) The mind not only explains the past, but it relies upon the future, on the ground of its faith in causation. It provides for or secures future results by availing itself of the causes which it knows will produce them. It employs these agents in all its plans and experiments with entire certainty of the results which they will effect. It predicts these results with confidence so soon as it is certain of all the causes which are or may be put into action. (d) In these explanations and experiments the mind is impelled by a special emotion, always present and powerful. Curiosity is more than an interest and desire to know an event as a fact : it impels to the knowledge of its causes and laws, of its origin and growth. The existence of a strong and apparently original emotional capacity of this sort confirms the view that the relation itself is original as a law of existence, and that the belief in it is a fundamental principle of the mind's knowledge. What the mind unconsciously assumes to be true in practical life, it distinctly and consciously applies in all the methods and processes of thought and of science. We have seen that deduc- tive reasoning has no meaning unless the relation of causality is assumed, and that induction in its researches after the forces and laws of matter and of spirit, makes the same assumption. Science, in all its processes, investigates the properties, the powers, the forces, the attributes, and the laws, of all existing § 294. CAUSATION AND THE RELATION OF CAUSALITY. 487 objects. But properties, powers, forces, and attributes are all of them terms which directly assert or indirectly imply that there is a causal energy or activity in these objects. The laws of matter and of spirit have no import, and can admit no applica- tion, except as causal agencies are affirmed which these laws measure or formulate. Except as the causal relation is believed and assumed, scientific knowledge can have no import, and sci- entific inquiries would be meaningless and impossible. Moreover : the belief in the relation of causality is wrought into and expressed by the structure of language. There are words which express causal activity, words which express the re- ception of such activity, and words which express the changes which are wrought in objects by means of causal activity. The grammar of every language furnishes proof of this, both in its etymology and its syntax. These considerations prove decisively that our belief in causation is an intuitive principle which meets all the criteria of universal- ity, necessity, and originality. § 294. This opinion is disputed by many. Vari- Counter theo- ous counter theories have been devised to account for lief ' not the universal or, as the case may be, for the very gene- induction or ral application of causation. The first of these aS8 ° counter theories which we notice is, that the belief in the univer- sality of causation is, like other general beliefs, acquired by induction. This is the doctrine of J. S. Mill. "With respect to the general law of causation it does appear that there must have been a time when the universal prevalence of that law throughout nature could not have been affirmed in the same confident and unqualified manner as at present. There was a time when many of the phenomena of nature must have appeared altogether capricious and irregular, not governed by any laws, nor steadily consequent upon any causes." * * " The truth is, as M. Comte has well pointed out, that (although the generalizing propensity must have prompted mankind from almost the beginning of their experience to ascribe all events to some cause more or less mysterious) the conviction that phenomena have invari- able laws, and follow with regularity certain antecedent phenomena, was only acquired gradually ; and extended itself as knowledge advanced, from one order of phenomena to another, beginning with those whose laws are most accessible to observation." — B. III.,c. xxi.,j? 3. " I apprehend that the considerations which give, at the present day, to the proof of the law of the uniformity of succession, as true of all phenomena with- out exception, this character of completeness and conclusiveness, are the follow- ing : First, that we now know it directly to be true of far the greater number of 488 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 294 phenomena ; that there are none of which we know it not to he true, the utmost that can be said being that of some we cannot positively, from direct evidence, affirm its truth," etc., etc. " Besides this first class of considerations there is a second, which still further corroborates the conclusion, and from the recognition of which the complete establishment of the universal law may reasonably be dated." u When every phenomenon that we know sufficiently well to be able to answer the question, had a cause on which it was invariably consequent, it was more ra- tional to suppose that our inability to assign the causes of other phenomena arose from our ignorance, than that there were phenomena which were uncaused, and which happened accidentally to be exactly those which we had hitherto had no suffi- cient opportunity of studying. It must, at the same time, be remarked, that the reasons for this reliance do not hold in circumstances unknown to us, and beyond the possible range of our experience. In distant parts of the stellar regions, where the phenomena may be entirely unlike those with which we are acquainted, it would be folly to affirm confidently that this general law prevails, any more than those special ones which we have found to hold universally on our own planet. The uniformity in the succession of events, otherwise called the law of causation, must be received not as a law of the universe, but of that portion of it only which is within the range of our means of sure observation, with a reasonable degree of extension to adjacent cases. To extend it further is to make a supposition without evidence, and to which, in the absence of any good ground from experience for esti- mating its degree of probability, it would be ridiculous to affect to assign it." — B. III.,o. xxi.,§§4, 5. Closely allied to this is the doctrine of Hume : that the belief is the result of association. Indeed, Mill blends the two in one, inas- much as he makes induction to be the result of repeated or insepara- ble associations. This doctrine expressed by Hume is as follows : " The first time a man saw the communication of motion by impulse, as by the shock of two billiard-balls, he could not pronounce that the one event was con- nected, but only that it was conjoined with the other. After he has observed several instances of this nature, he then pronounces them to be connected. What alteration has happened to give rise to this new idea of connection f Nothing but that he now feels these events to be connected in his imagination, and can readily fore- tell the existence of one from the appearance of the other. — Inquiry, etc.,Lec. vii.,p. 2. " Necessity is something that exists in the mind, not in objects ; nor is it possi- ble for us ever to form the most distant idea of it considered as a quality in bodies. Either we have no idea of necessity, or necessity is nothing but that de- termination of the thought to pass from causes to effects, and from effects to causes, according to their experienced union. ' A cause is an object precedent and contiguous to another, and so united with it that the idea of the one deter- mines the mind to form the idea of the other, and the impression of the one to form a more lively idea of the other.'" — Human Nature, B. I., Lee. xiv. (1.) The advocates of each of these theories overlook the real question at issue. The belief to be explained or accounted for, is, that every event has a cause. The belief which the advocates of this theory seek to account for, is the belief that to each particu- § 294. CAUSATION AND THE RELATION OF CAUSALITY. 489 lar event or class of events, some definite cause has been or may be actually assigned. That this last can only be the product of experience is obvious. That this is the belief in support of which they adduce illustrations and arguments is evident from the pas- sages which we have quoted from Hume and Mill. That this is not the belief which is in question, needs no illustration or argu- ment. (2.) No simple experience of actual events can establish the application of its results any further than the range of actual events of which we have had this experience. But in both General- ization and Induction, we go far beyond our actual experience. When, from the observation of a few objects or a few events, we generalize a concept or a law which we apply to objects or events more or less like them, we use the belief that what we have observed will prove true of what we have not observed. Whether what we have observed are called simple uniformities of antecedence and succession, or uniformities of causation, makes no difference with the nature of the act by which we pass from the known to the unknown. Mill himself most pertinently observes : "We believe that fire will burn to-morrow because it burned to-day and yesterday ; but we believe on precisely the same grounds that it burned before we were born, and that it burns this very day in Cochin-China. It is not from the past to the future [only or as such] as past or future, that we infer, but from the known to the unknown ; from facts observed to facts unobserved ; from what we have per- ceived, or been directly conscious of, to what has not come within our experience." He also admits, in the passages already quoted, that we do not limit ourselves to experience. In asking why, when we cannot assign a definite cause for an event, we yet believe it to be caused, he says it is " more rational to suppose that our inability to assign the causes of other phenomena arose from our ignorance than that there were phenomena which were uncaused." While then he insists that we have no warrant from experience in applying the results of experience " to circumstances unknown to us and beyond the possible range of our experience," and contends that " the law of causation must be received not as a law of the uni- verse, but of that portion of it only which is within the range of 21* 490 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 294. cur means of observation," he is careful to subjoin " with a rea- sonable degree of extension to adjacent cases." It would be difficult to give a meaning to the phrases " it is more rational to suppose" and "with a reasonable extension to adjacent cases" without finding in them a real, though reluctant homage to the intuition, " Every event must be caused" (3.) Induction assumes this belief as already present to or ready to be applied by the mind. Mill concedes that Induction itself has axioms. He says, " whatever be the best way of ex- pressing it, the proposition that the course of nature is uniform, is the fundamental principle, or general axiom of Induction." The proposition that "the course of nature is uniform"must mean that the unknown uniformities of succession or causation correspond to those which are known. If this is a general axiom or funda- mental principle of Induction, it would seem that it cannot be gained or derived by means of Induction. And yet Mill contends that the axiom which is necessarily assumed to give meaning and reality to the process of Induction is acquired by means of the pro- cess to which it is a necessary pre-condition. (4.) The resolution of this belief into tenacious or inseparable associations, or as Hume more bluntly expresses it, into " custom or habit" is more palpably untenable than the other theory or form of this theory. The resolution of the objective reality of this connection into a mere subjective association of the two terms fails to satisfy the mind, because it does not account for what is believed. How the mind comes to think of the one when the other is observed or thought of, is a very different question from this, ' how or by what relation does the mind believe that the objects thus thought of together, are con- nected in fact V It is a mere truism to say that objects observed or thought of together will be conjoined by association. The fact that the mind is constantly determined to one thought by the presence of another, is very different from the fact that the two things thought of, are necessarily determined the one by the other. If the two are viewed simply as psychological experi- ences, even the subjective law by which the objects concerned are presented to the mind in constant conjunction, is clearly dif- ferent from the subjective belief that the objects so presented are united causally. The philosopher who directly, like Hume, or indirectly, like § 295. CAUSATION AND THE EELATION OF CAUSALITY. 491 Mill, resolves the principle of causality into the law of association, complicates rather than simplifies the problem. For he imposes upon himself the obligation to show that the objective world of fact corresponds to the subjective world of ideas. This he must show by deduction, induction or intuition: but deduction and induction both rest upon intuition ; consequently even the theory which attempts to dispense with intuition must in the final analy- sis rest upon it, in one form or another, as the ultimate arbiter. § 295. The two next theories resolve the principle of causality into the observations of experience, ascrib- into outward ing it to our sense-perceptions of the phenomena of Seizor both. • • n .-I i Locke and De matter, or to our conscious experience ot the pne- Birau. nomena of the soul, or, again, to both of these con- jointly. Locke seems to advocate, in different passages of his Essay, every one of these theories. The following passages may be fairly taken to represent each of the three : — " In the notice that our senses take of the constant vicissitude of things, we cannot but observe that several particulars, both qualities and substances, begin to exist ,• and that they receive this their existence from the due application and operation of some other being. From this observation we get our ideas of cause and effect. That which produces any simple or complex idea, we denote by the general name, cause, and that which is produced, effect. Thus finding in that substance which we call wax, fluidity, which is a simple idea that was not in it before, is constantly produced by the application of a certain degree of heat, we call the simple idea of heat in relation to fluidity in wax, the cause of it, and fluidity, the effect." — Essay, B. II., c xxvi.,§ 1. "A body at rest affords us no idea of any active power to move; before it is set in motion itself, that motion is rather a passion than an action in it. For when the ball obeys the stroke of a billiard-stick, it is not any action of the ball, but bare passion." " The idea of the beginning of motion, we have only from reflection on what passes in ourselves, where we find by experience, that barely by willing it, barely a thought of the mind, we can move the parts of our bodies which were before at rest. So that it seems to me, we have from the observation of the operation of bodies by our senses, but a very imperfect, obscure idea of active power, since they afford not any idea in themselves of the power to begin any action, either motion or thought. But if from the impulse bodies are observed to make one upon another, any one thinks he has a clear idea of power, it serves as well to my purpose, Sensation being one of those ways whereby the mind comes by its ideas ; only I thought it worth while to consider here by the way, whether the mind doth not receive its idea of active power clearer from reflection on its own operations, than it does from any external sensation." B. II., c. xxi.,$ 4. 492 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §295. Locke's view has been understood to be, that by simple obser- vation and experience of material or spiritual events, we know that they are connected as causes and effects, and that on the ground of the experience thus given in sense and consciousness, we believe, conclude, or infer, that all events are so connected. To the theory as thus interpreted the reply is decisive : First, that simple experience of the known can of itself furnish no warrant for a belief concerning the unknown, unless we apply or assume some a priori principle or original intuition ; Second, sense-perception and consciousness are usually so denned as to include the discernment of the relations of space and time. But the relations of space and time are a priori, and are discerned by intuition. It cannot then be urged that sense and conscious- ness as forms or acts of simple experience, are the source or sources of our belief of causation. Experience is a posteriori, and excludes any a priori element. Eoyer Collard and Maine de Biran, two distinguished philoso- phers of the modern French school, have each introduced im- portant modifications of the theory of Locke. Eoyer Collard, Fragmens de Lecons ( (Fames de T. Beid, T. iv.,p. 296), contends that our experience of psychical phenomena alone gives us direct knowledge of the causal relation, inasmuch as mental states are, by their very nature, known to be caused by the ego. We know by consciousness that we are causes, and these are the only causes which we do know. But we know that every event is caused, as a self-evident and intuitive truth. Maine de Biran, {(Euvres, T. iv.,) expands this general state- ment into a refined theory which he explains with great subtlety, and defends with equal boldness as follows : — The soul, in all its higher states and elements of states, is not receptive but active. As active, it is the originator or producer of effects. These effects are of two sorts : those which are purely psychical, and those which are external as they affect the body and originate motion. In those states which are purely psychi- cal, and in the other states so far as they are such, consciousness distinguishes between the ego, the ego in action, and the result of the acting of the ego. (a.) The ego, discerned or apperceived, is not the soul as a sub- stance, but only the individual ego. (b.) The ego thus apper- § 295. CAUSATION AND THE RELATION OP CAUSALITY. 493 ceived is known neither as out of action, nor as prepared for action but as acting — these acts in all cases being individual, (c.) This activity is also causal or productive action. In its very nature and essence it is known as passing into effects. In other words,De Biran holds that the relation of causation is gained by the soul through conscious observation of the ego in action. In answer to the more important question, How does it know that every event has a cause ? De Biran would reply : On occasion of the individual apperception described, we extend the causative relations to objects other than ourselves, by a principle of natural induction or analogy. His theory, stated in a single proposition, is that we believe all events external to our own experience to be caused, because we explain all such events by natural induction, after the like- ness or analogy of that spiritual causation of which we are directly cognizant in ourselves. The theory of De Biran may be admitted, that we gain our first knowledge of the causal relation from the experience of per- sonal and individual causality, without involving his second posi- tion, viz: that, by natural induction, we make a universal application of our individual experience to every possible event. The so-called natural induction of De Biran must rest upon or involve an intuition, equivalent to the a priori principle, every event must have a cause. Otherwise it is impossible to see what warrant we have to transfer what is true of our individual experience to the whole spiritual and material universe. The fact th&typsychologically, we have the earliest and most complete exemplification of the causal relation in our spiritual experience, does not in the least explain, philosophi- cally, why it is that we believe this relation to be of universal application. From the fact assumed or believed that the soul derives its first notion of cause from its conscious activity, the inference has been derived that causation is pre- dicate of spirit only ; that a material cause is contradictory in conception and impossible in fact. This inference has been held in two forms. (1.) It has been inferred, first, that the conception of a material cause is self- contradictory; because, forsootb, our knowledge of the causal relation is derived from our own psychical activity. Spirit alone, it is contended, is essentially ac- tive and causal, and in spirit, will is that only which is active. Matter is incapa- ble of force; it presents the appearances of antecedent and successive phenomena, but behind these appearances there is no force except what spirit imparts. 494 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §296. Against this view the following objections are decisive : (a.) The soul finds in its own positive psychical experience, evidence that "force and power are" not "applicable only to will;" for it finds spiritual energies that are neither intelli- gent nor voluntary. When it seeks and strives to fix its attention, to recall for- gotten objects, and to control its rebellious desires, it contends against actual forces which are not uniformly regulated by intelligence or controlled by the will. There are ' secondary causes ' within the soul at least, if there are not in matter. (&.) It does not follow, because we derive the notion of causation or force from the conscious activities of an intelligent will, that the relation itself involves either intelligence or will. Let it be conceded that at first the soul, by a not unnatural illusion, refers every event which it does not produce by its own activity to some spiritual agent other than itself. It soon learns to correct such judgments. It learns that a spirit does not directly blow upon the trees or agitate the sea, for it finds the agitation of the air interposed ; it then discovers that this agitation is occasioned by heat ; then that heat is dependent upon the sun, or some other agent. (c.) According to this theory, the universe of matter and of spirit, except so far as it is capable of intelligence, is unreal and impossible. Matter without qualities or powers, is inconceivable; but qualities and powers involve force, i. e., causal energy. The exercise of power is also inconceivable, except by beings capable of voluntary energy. For these reasons we reject the theory. We distinguish intelligent and volun- tary activity from simple causal energy. We distinguish causal from creative force, i, e., origination under conditions furnished by another being from origina- tion without such conditions. We distinguish primary from secondary causes. (2.) The second inference derived from the position that the activity of spirit furnishes the notion of causation, is, that there is but one agent in the universe, and He is the Creator; that causation is conceivable of neither created matter nor created spirit, and the apparent activities of both are held to be varied mani- festations of His single force, in phenomena successive to one another. If this doctrine were true, it could not be legitimately derived in the way prescribed by this theory, which makes the notion of causality to be furnished from a created or finite agent, and yet infers it to be inapplicable to any other than a being which is infinite and uncreated. Malebranche (Rech. de la Ver., p. 2, c. 3,) advocates the theory in question, but not on these grounds, but as an inference from his general theological and philosophical position, that God is the only agent, and that in him we perceive as well as produce every object in the universe. §296. A class of theories of historical importance com- which resolves prehends all those which resolve this relation between causality into a . , . , relation of con- things into some a prion relation between concepts — in other words, into some logical axiom, principle, o&* relation. The fallacy common to all these consists in inverting the order of nature and of reason. A correct estimate of logical relations and principles would show that they are all dependent upon some assumed reality of things. Among such realities, the relation of § 297. CAUSATION AND THE RELATION OP CAUSALITY. 495 causality is prominent and fundamental. It cannot be derived from the laws of identity and contradiction, which as we have shown concern concepts only and are designed to hold the mind to consistency in their use. It has not been uncommon with the philosophers of the later German Schools to seek to resolve the principle of causality into the principle of the sufficient reason viewed as a logical axiom. This follows from not clearly determining and carefully keeping in mind the relation of the ratio essendi to the ratio cognoscendi in the principle of the sufficient reason itself. Because the logical reason is more general or extensive in its application than the real cause, they have resolved cause into reason, instead of explaining reason by means of the relation of cause. We have already shown, under Deduction, that the syllogistic process, and indeed all logical reasoning supposes the ratio essendi, i. e., real causal action, or that which may be conceived as such, and that without this all deduction is meaningless and inconclusive, (§§ 221, 2.) This inversion of the real order of the dependence of these con- ceptions may be traced to Wolff and Kant. Kant sanctioned it by the suggestion that is fundamental to his system, that the forms of thought are not necessarily representative of the forms of be- ing. Kant makes the relation of causality to be a metaphysical relation of that explicability of one concept by another which is required by the logical faculty, instead of a real relation of things. It has been carried to its furthest extreme by Hegel in the fun- damental position of his philosophy which he boldly attempted to make universal, viz., that all the so-called relations of being may be developed from and are resolved into relations of thought, so that the actual world is but the necessary evolution of the relations that belong to the logical concept. The relation of the reason to its consequent, and by consequence, of cause to effect, is only a special application of that law of identity; misin- terpreted by his logic, which is properly applied only in the sphere of abstract thought. § 297. Another theory called a priori is the theory advanced by Sir William Hamilton, (Met., Lee. 39, theory of £au- 40.) This theory derives our conceptions of, and our belief in, this relation, not from a power, but an impotence of 496 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 297. mind ; in a word, it resolves it into the more general "principle of the conditioned!' The law of the conditioned is, that the " con- ceivable has always two opposite extremes, and that the extremes are equally inconceivable. That the conditioned is to be viewed not as a power, but as a powerlessness of mind is evinced by this — that the two extremes are contradictories, though neither alter- native can be conceived or thought as possible, one or other must be admitted to be necessary." This general powerlessness gives the special relation of causal- ity, when applied to the two positive forms under which every object is and must be conceived, viz., existence and time. By the necessity of the first, the mind cannot but think of every object as existing. It cannot, if it tries, think of anything as not ex- isting. By the second the thing existing is not now what it was a moment before. We cannot think of any object as non-existing in the present. No more can we think of the same as non-exist- ent in the past. We cannot think of its absolute commencement in the past, nor can we think of its absolute termination in the future. We can neither think of its absolute non-commencement nor of its infinite non-termination. " This gives us the category of the conditioned as applied to tne category of existence under the category of time." By this application of the principle of the conditioned, the principle of causality is gained. For the law of causality is simply this, that when an object appears to commence in time, we cannot but suppose that the complement of existence which it contains has previously existed ; " in other words, that all we at present come to know as an effect, must previously have existed in its causes." According to this theory, the cause or causes of an object are the sum of the constituent elements of its being, existing at a pre- vious time in a different form ; the effects are the same as existing in another form at a subsequent time. This applies to every form of causation, even to the creation of the universe. For creation is not a springing of nothing into something ; " it is conceived, and is by us conceivable merely as an evolution of a new form of existence by the fiat of the Deity." The objections to this explanation of the relation of causation, as taught by Hamilton, are the following : § 297. CAUSATION AND THE EELATION OF CAUSALITY. 497 (1.) It is not true that it is an original and necessary belief, that the complement of existence is not changed with the changes of phenomena. For example, when a pile of fuel is consumed by fire, and only an inconsiderable residuum of ashes remains, men do not necessarily and instinctively assert that the total of the original constituents of the fuel is undiminished. So far is this from being true, that, on the other hand, they are slow to ac- cept the evidence furnished by the more careful experiments of science, that the products, when analyzed and gathered after com- bustion, equal the elements of the substance before it was burned. (2.) The asserted impossibility to think an object as non-existent is a logical, not a real impossibility. We cannot think any thing not to be in thought, because, while we think of it, it must exist for us as thought. Even when we think of it as not existing, whether in the present or in the past, we must first think of it as existing in thought, and to this object as existing in thought we deny existence in fact. If we think of a centaur or a hip- pogriff, we must think of it as being. If, because we cannot think of an object actually existing to be non-existent, we may infer that the complement of its existence does not change, we may also infer that, because we think of a centaur and a hippogriff as existing, they both in fact exist. (3.) The theory is utterly inadequate to explain psychical causality. The operations of the soul are, as we have seen, eminently causal. From our conscious experience of this class of actions the first notion of causality is derived. Whether the effects in question are produced by the action of the soul within itself, and are purely psychical, or whether they are wrought in the nervous organism by the soul ; whether they are wrought upon matter by the soul, or upon the soul by matter ; in each of these cases the theory fails to satisfy. There is no comple- ment of existence appearing in different forms at different times. Whether the effect is psychical, physiological, or material, is not conceived as the sa'me constituents under a new form. It is what the terms denote it to be — a product, an effect, a result of activity, a consequent of the powers and activities which are re- quired for and appropriate to the result. (4.) It is still more incongruous with any right notion of crea- 498 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 297. tive causality. The creation of matter or of mind implies the production or origination into existence of that which did not previously exist in any of its constituents. It is called by Ham- ilton, " the evolution of a new form of existence by the fiat of the Deity." But evolution ought, in consistency with his theory, to signify the changing of the materials already existing under one form, into some new form of the existence already in being. This would require either that we believe in the co-eternity of matter with God, and that we restrict the agency of the Deity to the exercise of a merely plastic or formative energy, or it would involve the pantheistic view, that in the spiritual nature or constitution of God there was also present a material substance, from which by a new evolution of divine activity, the created universe emerged, as a new form of the matter which had from eternity existed in God. From spirit as such, from a pure spiritual essence, it cannot be conceived that matter should be evolved, in any consistency with the theory of Hamil- ton as defined by himself. The various attempts to resolve the relation of Conclusion. , Our position causality into some other relation either a posteriori reaffirmed. . . . . or a priori having failed to be satisfactory, we return with greater confidence to the original position which we have already explained and defended, that it is original and intuitive. The various applications of the relation and principle of causality in the processes of the intellect, as well as its significance as an assumption fundamental to our higher knowledge, illustrate and enforce its importance. CHAPTER VI. DESIGN OR FINAL CAUSE. From the principle or relation of causation we pass by a natural transition to the principle of design or adaptation, or, as it is usually termed, of final cause. This in an eminent sense, is a synthetic relation, and is contrasted with the relation of causality as analytic. The movement of the latter is from the individual to the general, from the less to the more comprehen- § 299. DESIGN OR FINAL CAUSE. 499 sive. The movement of adaptation and final cause is from the general to the particular and the individual. It unites con- stituent elements into constituted wholes. 2 298. The term final cause is thus explained : Aristotle and Terms ex- the schoolmen divided all possible or conceivable causes into four; plained. For- the material, formal, efficient, and final. The material causes are m j}\ material ,J ' •" ' J efficient, and those material elements or principles of which any existence is final causes. composed, whether the matter is bodily or spiritual. The formal cause is the property or aggregation of properties which constitute its essence or logical content (in Aristotelian phraseology, its form). In these two senses, the word cause is equivalent to element or constitutive principle, each differing ac- cording as that which is constituted is matter or form. The efficient cause corresponds with the cause of modern philosophy, except that it was formerly appropriated to the most conspicuous or prominent of the agents or conditions that produce a result; whereas, in modern usage, the term is extended to all those agents which, in combination, originate an effect. The final cause was the design or end which was conceived as impelling and directing the action of a number or succession of agencies, till it was actually brought to pass. The significance of this appellation can be understood by an example. If I form a purpose, the event or result when made actual, will be the end of a series of events or actions. Hence the end, by a secondary signification, is made to signify a purposed result or a design, and the adjective final receives the same import. This purpose is called a cause, because it is conceived when formed as causing those events or acts which are necessary to its realization. Hence the appellation, final cause, — i. e., a cause, which, beginning as a thought, works itself at last into a fact as an end or final result. Aristotle called the formal cause rr\v ovo-iav *ai to ti tj v elvai, the material cause Trjv v\r)v (cat to viroKeifi.evov, the efficient cause o#e»> rj apxv xr}? Kiviycrecos, and the final cause to o5 eVe/ca koL rayaOov. Met. 1. I. 83 a 27, a 29, a 30, a 31. § 299. The relation of design supposes that agen- Deg? cies exist or may exist, which might cause a result adaptation, to be. The result is called the end or final cause. The capacity of these efficient causes when combined to pro- duce the effect is called their adaptation or fitness for it. This adaptation may be considered subjectively or objectively. If it is viewed as arranged or known by the designer, it is considered sub- jectively, i. e., it is a design. But whether it is known or not, the capacity for or the possibility of it exists and remains to be disco- vered. It pertains to actually existing forces and laws of nature, and is a relation which may be affirmed of such causes. A series or combination of causes, viewed as fitted for an end are called the means — literally the intermediate agencies — between the end as thought and the end as produced. 500 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 301. § 300. The position which we assert and defend aswime^as'ni is that this relation is believed a priori to pervade cessary and a a ^ existence, and must be assumed as the ground of the scientific explanation of the facts and phenomena of the universe. We do not inquire whether this relation is ex- emplified in our experience as a psychological fact, but whether it lies at the ground of all our knowledge as a necessary relation of things, and a first principle or axiom of thought — whether, in other words, the principle of adaptation ranks with the principle of efficient causation as a necessary and a priori truth. We assert that the relations and laws ascertained by asking the questions why and how, are not the only relations conceivable, but that others hold the same place in our knowledge, viz., those which the question what for requires as its an- swer. Among his four causes, Aristotle gave the highest pre- eminence to the oo hexa or the what for. Was Aristotle right in assuming that the end is as important to be known as the defini- tion, the constituents and the origination of a being or a phe- nomenon ? § 301. Our reasons for the truth of this position Reasons. The mind impelled are the following : jects by this (1.) The mind is impelled to seek, and is satisfied - when it finds that any objects or events are related as means and ends. Whatever these objects may be which are con- nected under this relation — whether they are individuals that fill only single points in space and endure but for a moment of time, or classes of beings that pervade the universe by their agency, and endure with energy unwasted from generation to generation — the mind inquires, for what do these exist and act ? and if it can find an answer, it accepts it with rational satisfac- tion. It asks the question and accepts the answer in a way precisely analogous to that in which it inquires and learns, By what agency and under what law does any thing exist and act ? It asks as pressingly and as persistently, concerning what it may find in this relation, as concerning what it can know under the relation of causation. When it receives a probable answer, it welcomes it with a more complete and a higher satisfaction than a similar explanation by efficient causes and their laws. This § 303. DESIGN OR FINAL CAUSE. 501 ground of analogy would lead us to believe that the two relations are both original and intuitively assumed. § 302. (2.) The relations under which this axiom requires that' objects should be connected, is higher higher a 'thau than any of those which arise under the category of causa°uo e n? cient efficient or blind causative force. The relation of means to ends supposes that of cause and effect. We must first suppose causes or agents to exist, before we can suppose them to be applied or employed as means. But when forces and their laws are ascertained, and by them unity and order and dependence are established among the otherwise dis- connected beings and events of the universe, the mind takes a step higher in its aspirations, seeking to rearrange under more elevated relations the objects united under the lower. The one class being presumed, and in part at least successfully established, the mind believes that a higher is possible, and proceeds to dis- cover it. Subjectively viewed, this relation gives a higher satis- faction. Objectively regarded, it stands higher in rational value than that of efficient causation, which is only a stepping-stone and preparation for it. § 303. (3.) The principle has been of essential ser- vice in scientific discovery. Should it be conceded that The p rinc ; ple the appropriate sphere of science proper is to develop ^ntiLT'iefvke and establish the so-called powers and laws of nature, ^ scov s e c r ientific and that the discovery of adaptations lies without its sphere, it would still be true that the belief that the universe is full of such adaptations, is of essential service in suggesting powers and laws previously undeveloped and undetermined. JThe history of scientific discovery abounds in confirmations of this truth. When Harvey observed at the outlet of the veins and the rise of the arteries, certain curiously constructed valves, — those in the one, opening inward towards the heart, and in the other, open- ing outward away from the same, he was persuaded that the arrangement indicated an end which supposed activities and laws which he proceeded to ascertain and determine. Further illustrations of the value of this principle in scientific discovery will be given when we treat of its application to the several sciences. Cf. § § 316 seq. 502 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 305. The Founda- § 304. (4.) The entire superstructure of ike inductive ductwVpLios- Philosophy rests upon the principle in question. ophy - It has already been shown that the Inductive method rests on several assumptions. They are such as these : nature is uniform in her operations and laws ; the indications or signs of less obvious powers and laws may be confided in ; the analogies of nature are important means of suggesting facts and laws, and of inciting to experiment and discovery ; the simplest relationships, the fewest agencies, and the most economical uses of forces are always presumed. These and other like axioms of the student of nature are but varied applications of the principle in question, viz., that in the universe objectively considered, there is an intelligent and wise adaptation of powers and laws to rational ends, and that the same is true of the relation of the universe to the knowing mind. It is not sufficient for the philosopher to say that without these assumptions, the science of nature itself would be impossible, in- asmuch as the conception of science requires that powers should be fixed, and laws should be uniform, and indications and analo- gies should be trustworthy — that were science not to assume the truths of these maxims she would commit suicide. To this it is pertinent to reply, What if science itself should be impossible ? What is the imperative necessity for science ? Every reply to these questions implies that the adaptations of nature to the methods and impulses of the knowing mind are such as indi- cate at least that class of designs in the structure of the universe which the possibility of science requires. § 305. (5.) It is also needed to explain those pheno- Required to ... . i • i i . explain the mena of organic existence, which the relations of phenomena . . -, of organic efficient causes are entirely incompetent to resolve or existences. . , . even to define. An organic being, or an organism, can only be defined as a beiDg of which each organ acts for the integrity and well-being of every other organ, and all act together for the life of the whole. More abstractly, and in the terms of the relation in question, an organism is a being in which each of the parts and the whole are respectively means and ends for one another. We find it, in fact, to be true, that in any living being, whether plant or animal, the elements or organs act together so as to promote the action of each other, §305. DESIGN OR FINAL CAUSE. 503 and of the whole. If the appropriate function of each organ is performed, the function of every other is also fulfilled, and when all together are exerted they are the conditions of the growth, the development and the remaining functions of the plant or animal. In the animal, the action of the lungs is necessary to that of the heart, and the action of the heart to that of the lungs, the action of both to the action of the stomach, and the action of the stomach to that of both these, and the mutual action of these and the remaining organs, to the health and life of the whole body. The elements or agents of which these organs are composed, have their well ascertained mechanical and chemical properties, and when these are combined in inorganic substances, their results follow the laws which control them. But when they are combined in living beings or their organs, these powers and laws do not explain in the least degree these compounds or their functions. The materials or agents which form the heart, the lungs or the brain, do not at all explain the peculiar substance, form, or functions of these organs ; much less do they account for the singular capacity which they possess of producing a whole, on which they depend for their own existence as a living heart, lungs and brain, — which in its turn as a living whole is de- pendent on each of these. All that we can do, is — within the sphere of the mechanical and chemical relations of the constituent elements — to observe the resultant products into which they are transmuted ; but the laws by which these results are produced, are mostly hidden from view. The Inductive philosophy, with its efficient causations, is here wholly at a loss : It cannot explain how the agents which form the vegetable or the animal cell should impart to that least microcosm the wonderful power of developing a new cell from within itself, or of adding cell after cell to its substance. . Much less can it explain why or how it is that one cell is the rudiment of a plant and another that of an animal — that one expands into this plant, and another into that ; one into this animal and another into that. All this is totally unknown. The principle of life and the conditions of life are only names for causes that cannot h» explained by such methods. The effects cannot even be described, much less explained by the relations of efficient causation. 504 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 307. Under these circumstances we resort to the relation of adap- tation and the assumption of design in order to define and ex- plain the phenomena. After no other relation than this can we explain the fact that dead matter is transmuted into living par- ticles, and that aggregates of these particles are developed into living organs, which act together so long as the being lives of which they are parts. By no other law than that of design can we explain how each class of living beings works for itself, having a form, habits, tastes, and instincts peculiar to itself, and how each individual of each class is an end to itself, having an individual form, size, and other peculiarities more or less marked, according to its rank and place in the scale of being. § 306. Two facts are here sug nested touching the Relation of ° . . fe& ° final to efficient relation of final to efficient causes. The first is that causes in the . ,. . * higher orders the higher we rise in the scale of being, the less we know of the relations of efficient causes; while those of final cause are more and more various and conspicuous. In un- organized matter we have occasion chiefly to apply efficient causes and their unvarying laws. As we ascend into the regions of life, we are more and more baffled in our attempts to detect the elementary forces and to determine their unvarying laws, but are more and more gratified at seeing the relations of adaptation be- come more and more conspicuous. The second is, That one of these relations does not displace the other , and the discoveries in respect to the one neither compel nor allow us to dispense with the search after the other. On the contrary, the more complete is our analysis of efficient forces and our determination of their laws, the greater is the opportunity to notice how the structure whose constituents are resolved by analysis, is controlled by manifest fitness and adaptation. Each newly discovered element and determined law opens an opportunity for some adaptation as yet unobserved. § 307. To the doctrine that the belief in design is Objections- (1.) ... . , , . . Men mistake in intuitive, the following are urged as objections: ments about S- (1.) Men mistake in discovering or assigning ends, and the mistakes into which they fall are irrational and foolish ; whatever man in his selfishness and limitation may think important to himself, he thinks must have been designed in the economy of nature, and thus is exposed to the danger of § 309. DESIGN OR FINAL CAUSE. 505 setting up his narrow and interested judgments as the real adap- tations and intents of the Creator. It is sufficient to reply that, if men mistake in assigning the ends of phenomena, they do the same in interpreting their effi- cient causes. We do not raise the question whether men can dis- cover -particular ends with infallible certainty, but whether they intuitively believe there are ends to which all beings and agents are adapted, and for which they are designed. § 308. (2.) It may be objected that we have no means of testing and confirming our inductions in prorations can , , ., n , , neither be respect to ends, while m respect 01 causes and laws tested nor con- we are provided with tests, rules, and methods which are universally acknowledged to be amply sufficient. " In ordinary cases the methods of agreement, of difference, and of concomitant variations are acknowledged to be ample: In special exigencies artificial experiments may be instituted to supplement the defi- ciencies of simple observation : But in ascertaining ends we have no such methods, tests, or experiments." We reply: It will be found on closer inspection, that the methods appropriate to the two are more nearly alike than -would be at first imagined. It has been already shown, that the end or purpose, in its relations to the means of its realization, may be conceived of as an efficient force carried back from the end to the beginning of the series of causes and effects, which drives them to their issue by a constant energy. If this be so, the question, What is the particular end of a combination or series? may be answered by the methods appropriate to efficient causes. It may in some cases be less easy to conjecture the probable end than it is to conjecture the probable cause, inasmuch as many such ends might in a given case, be supposed to be equally compatible with the effects. But, on the other hand, in other departments of nature, as the organic and historical, the ends and adaptations flash upon the mind without the need of inquiry or tests of any kind, while in these very departments the efficient forces usually elude the most subtle analysis, and refuse to yield to the most exact and rigorous methods. § 309. (3.) It may be still further objected that the adaptation of means to ends is an actual relation, of t ion L derived i • i /• • i • •# from conscious which we are aware jrom our own conscious activity, experience 22 506 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 310. and it is simply by a fiction that we transfer it to other, i. e., to material objects. To this objection we reply, that the activity of our own souls and the relations which are instanced or exemplified in our con- scious mental and moral functions, hold precisely the same rela- tion to efficient as to final causes. The most complete knowledge, we may say the only complete knowledge, which we have of power or efficiency, is gained through or by means of the active energy of our own spirits. By this, we in a certain sense image, cf. § 206, this abstract relation whenever we have occasion to affirm it of impersonal or material agents. In doing so, we use examples, associations, and language taken from our personal activity. It is not true, however, that we affirm this relation of all the objects in the universe, because we have happened to experience its agency in our own spirits. It is by an intuition that we affirm it to be necessary to a rational construction of the universe. But this very objection itself suggests an argument in defence of the propriety of making a similar application of final cause. The power of adapting means to ends is one with which we ourselves are very familiar in our own conscious ex- perience. We propose ends. "We devise and arrange, i. e., adapt means to bring them to pass. We interpret the actions of others by supposing that they are directed by such intentions and adap- tations. We interpret the results of their actions when they are fixed and made permanent in structures controlled by the same relation. It is a fair argumentum ad hominem to use urn ue~tioned n * n re Pty' wnen & is objected that we interpret the uni- in some appii- verse by a relation derived from our uniform and per- cations. J x sonal experience, that in this experience we have an agency directed in part, at least, by design. The agency is spiritual, which first proposes ends and then adapts forces for their achieve- ment. It is certainly possible or supposable that the results of a similar agency should pervade the universe, and make themselves manifest in discoverable adaptations. To assume or employ it in the explanation of phenomena is not necessarily unphilosophical. § 310. (4.) It may be objected still further, that dpieS W °iSro" if we recognize final cause as a principle, we introduce fdsophy which into the universe, for the explication of its phc- co»flicr ssibIy nomena, two 'principles, of which the one may at § 311. DESIGN OR FINAL CAUSE. 507 times conflict with the other. In so doing we weaken confidence in the processes and axioms of pure science, and in the stability of the laws and the order of nature. Science, it is contended, must assume not only the stability but the supremacy of its own laws, and it can neither recognize nor respect any other. It may be urged in reply that the principle of final cause, is so far from weakening our rational confidence in the stability of the laws of nature or disturbing our faith in the axioms of science, that it confirms both. What science blindly assumes, this rationally accounts for and makes necessary. It gives a reason for the order of nature and the principles of knowledge ; and the only reason which can be suggested, viz., the adaptation of such order to the uses and ends pf the human intellect, and of human science. As we have shown already, it furnishes the only solid foundation for the assumptions of induction. But it will still be objected ; if efficient causes and physical laws are to acknowledge themselves thus indebted to final causes, they must also confess their subjection to the same, and be ready to stand aside and be suspended whenever the principle of final cause shall require. In other words, the order of nature may be broken whenever the requirements of final cause shall so direct, whenever the claims of the so-called reason of things, or of al- leged moral and religious interests may demand an inroad upon this regularity, either in special acts of creation or exertions of miraculous agency. This we assent to, but, we find no reason on this account to reject the principle or its asserted supremacy, but an additional reason for accepting both. If the principle of final cause will not only render the service of sustaining our confi- dence in the stability of the laws of nature in all ordinary cir- cumstances, but will also account for such extraordinary devia- tions from this order as may be required in the history of man, then for this double service it deserves to be esteemed of greater value and authority. [Cf. Locke, JSsmy, B. iv. c. xvi. § 13.] § 311. (5.) It is objected still further, that the search after final causes has seriously hindered the after final 7 ..-II causes has hin- aavaneement of science, by turning aside the atten- dered discov- tion and interest of observers from their appropriate duty, which is the investigation and determination of efficient causes and their laws. 508 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 311. Lord Bacon, it is said, was so alive to its evil influence as to utter his memorable and oft-repeated caution in the words: " Causarum finalium inquisitio sterilis est et tanquam virgo Deo consecrata nihil parit." — De Aug. Sclent, III. 4. Descartes was still more strenuous in the same opinion, as appears from these assertions : " Totum illud causarum genus quod a fine peti solet in rebus physicis nullum usum habere existimo ; non enim absque temeritate me puto posse investigare fines Dei." — Med. iv. 20. " Ita denique nullas unquam rationes circa res naturales a fine quam Deus aut natura in iis faciendis sibi proposuit discernimus, quia non tantum debemus nobis arrogare ut ejus consilioruin nos esse participes putemus." — Princ. Phil., p. I. 28. To this objection we reply : That what Bacon intended was that the attention of the inquirer should not be diverted from the investigation of efficient causes by the suggestion of ends or adaptations, for the appropriate sphere of the interpreter of nature is to develop agents and laws that are unknown, or newly to confirm and exemplify those already established. In this he was right. But, that Bacon himself believed that nature is penetrated and illumined by the higher relations of design is evident from this among similar intimations : " I had rather be- lieve all the fables in the Legend and the Talmud and the Alco- ran, than that this universal frame is without a mind." * * " For while the mind of man looketh upon second causes scattered, it may sometimes rest in them and go no further; but when it beholdeth the chain of them, confederate and linked together, it must needs fly to Providence and the Deity." — Essays, xvi. When Bacon says that the inquiry after final causes is without fruit, he must mean ' practical fruit,' or the production of direct advantage to the interests of man. It is, in fact, so far from being barren, that as we have already seen, § 303, the considera- tion of ends has been fruitful in the suggestion of undiscovered agencies as their means, and has thus proved itself a most impor- tant agent in such discoveries. It has been more efficient in leading to the prudens qucestio, the sagacious guess, or the ingenious hypothe- sis, which has so often opened the way for decisive experiments. If our doctrine is correct, that the methods and rules of induction themselves rest upon the belief in design, then final cause is so § 312. DESIGN OR FINAL CAUSE. 509 far from being barren that she deserves to be honored as the Alma Hater of the Inductive Philosophy itself. § 312. (6.) It is objected again, that what (6 . )Theadapta . are called the adaptations of nature, are only ^ s Jj£j nat "JJ| the necessary conditions of existence and its pheno- conditions of u u *■ existence. mena. When, for example, the eye is said to be adapted to the light, and both to the production of vision, this says the objector, is only another phrase for saying that the eye as we find it, acting with the light as we find it, produces its pictures upon the retina, and these acting with the intellect and sentient organism, produce the sense-perceptions which we call vision. What are called the ends of nature, to which her forces are said to be adapted, are simply the effects of which these forces are the necessary and actual conditions. The fish, we say, is adapted in its structure and its instincts to the water, and the water exists with relation to the fish, but the truth is that there could be no fish without water, for without water, the existence and conception of the fish are impossible. We know what appears, i. e., what is made mani- fest, and we know it under the single relation of the forces which cause it to be. This is the only relation under which we can regard it. As to whether other effects might or might not have been pro- duced from these causes in different conjunctions and intensities, we have no means of deciding. Whether other effects may not be produced in future we cannot say. All that we know is what has been, and now is, and by what means. These have been, and are, and occur under the operation of these very causes and laws. We inquire concerning the actual conditions of things, not con- cerning possible designs. In reply to this class of objections, we need only say that they apply, not to the position that the belief in final cause is a first principle, but to the doctrine that this belief is derived from ob- servation and required by experience. If the principle is intui- tive and a priori (in the sense explained, § 246), we bring it with us to the explanation of the facts. We do not derive it from ex- perience by an a posteriori method, but we apply it to experience by one that is purely a priori. It is true, if facts and phenomena were inconsistent with the principle, we should be embarrassed by the discrepancy of the two. But no incompatibility is urged, 510 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 314. only that final causes are not proved by experience. It is conceded that the explanation by efficient causes is not incon- sistent with that by final causes, inasmuch as it is through effects actually produced that we infer these effects were intended and provided for. But we take issue with the position that we find nothing more than the conditions of existence. "We find not simply the condi- tions of mere existence in the causes of effects produced, but the conditions of well-being, or adaptations to a highly artificial, ele- vated, and refined existence and enjoyment ; and these in # forms so manifold as to be entirely consistent with the a priori princi- ple which we bring to the explanation of the facts. The illus- trations of this assertion can only be gathered from the study of individual examples. § 313. (7.) It may be objected again: that adapta- (7.) Adapt^ ^ on can ori [y ^q traced in fact in a limited class of tion is limited J isten5 aaic ex_ phenomena, viz., those of organized existence, whereas were it necessarily presumed it might be dis- cerned in all kinds of being, the inorganic as truly as the organic. It is sufficient to reply that examples can be found in every kind of object-matter as will be shown in another place. They are more striking within the region and sphere £>f life, indeed, but are not less real beyond that sphere. Besides, this axiom is the foundation on which rests the structure of the inductive method, which is as often applied to inorganic as to organic being. This makes it necessary to apply it to every kind and style of existence. (8 we are not § ^^. (8.) It might also be urged that we cannot W ffirSin- d it of trace or interpret adaptations on a scale sufficiently an kinds of ex- extensive to warrant our affirming that they exist istence. ° # jj throughout the whole universe of being. ""We may, indeed, guess at them within a limited range of observation. But it is presumptuous to assume that we can trace the adapta- tions and discover the ends of the entire universe." If this were admitted to be true, it would not hold against the principle that ends exist, and that adaptations to them regulate all the things that are. It is for the principle that we contend, not for infallibility in the application of it to individual cases. The same law holds good of final causes as of efficient §315. DESIGN OR FINAL CAUSE. 511 causes. That both exist, and both control the universe is known to the human mind by the necessity of its nature. The discovery of instances and examples of each is accomplished by experi- ence and induction. Both can be traced by observation in but few classes of objects, and within that portion of the universe only which comas under our eye or ear, or the report of our fel- low-men. But the one can be traced as far as the other. What is connected with its fellow as adapted to an end under this relation, is an ef- ficient agent or force. If we can trace gravitation as far as the utmost verge of material being, we can also affirm that it was designed to hold the masses in their relative positions and their paths of motion. The principle of final cause moreover is abso- lutely required to warrant the extension of the relations of effi- cient causes observed within a limited sphere, throughout those regions of which observation and testimony can give only an uncertain and incomplete report. § 315. (9.) Last of all it may be said, that the recognition of this as a first principle would require Lmnfit be a£ • -?•,/• 11.1- . firmed of anim- US to ascribe intention and adaptation to an un- limited Bein S . limited Being, whereas it supposes certain forces or powers already given or existing, and the problem arises how to dispose of these so as to attain or produce the designed result. Such a problem can never, it is contended, be presented to an unlimited Being, who, by the very supposition, is not confined to forces or agencies which already exist, but can produce effects by a fiat of creative will. Moreover, the supposition would introduce into such a mind and order the reverse of the rational. It would make the production of agencies go before the disposition of them to an end. It would make blind force precede wise fore- cast. None of these inferences are warranted. Because in the order of design thought must recognize the possible adaptations of forces, it does not follow that the forces must exist in order to be thought of as existing, or in order that certain adaptations should be determined on. Both, indeed, may be objects of design, the ex- istence of the forces and their adaptations ; or, rather, the existence of the forces because of their adaptations to accomplish some end or ends of thought. Even the human mind, impotent as 512 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 316. it is to create, sometimes imagines to itself, i. e., creates iu thought some new agent in the world of matter or of spirit, and revels in contriving the variety of uses to which it might make it subser- vient. How much more readily may that Being whose thoughts can in any instant become powers, laws, and facts ! § 316. But the most instructive view which we can The principle take of this principle is to contemplate the variety of is illustrated _ . . and confirmed, its applications. It has already been observed that by its applica- _. T , tions (i.) to First or Intuitional Truths, are never apprehended metaphysics. . . • ' mi in actual application as general propositions. They can only be discerned in the concrete, as they actually connect indi- vidual things or phenomena. Thus we cannot discern causation or adaptation as universal and a priori ; we only discern an event or being as causative or caused, as a means or an end. When we appeal to the use which is made of these relations in the sciences as proof that they are fundamental and intuitive, we expect to find that these sciences constantly assume these relations to be valid, by explaining phenomena by means of them. The con- stant repetition of this relation and the important uses to which it is applied add incidental strength to the positive arguments for regarding it as an intuition of the intellect. 1. The first application which we notice is that which is made by metaphysical science itself. We have already insisted on its importance in sustaining the metaphysical axioms of Induction. Upon this we need not dwell. Its application in the formation and arrangement of those gen- eral conceptions which are a.t once the materials and the conditions of all science, is of equal consequence, though perhaps not equally obvious. (a.) The principle of final cause regulates the formation of concepts. "We have already seen that so far as the form of the concept is concerned, it is by abstraction or analysis that we separate the qualities or attributes of existing beings, and by synthesis unite them into new and generalized products. These processes regulate the form but not the import of the concept. We are not at liberty to select any attributes which analy- sis gives us and to unite them into any complex notion which they might form. Some are adapted by logical compatibility to be conjoined, while others are not so fitted. §316. DESIGN OR FINAL CAUSE. 513 But again : not all the attributes which are logically compati- ble are, in fact, united into concepts by any earnest thinker. The eentaur, the mermaid, the hippogriif, are logically possible, but not actual. Why ? Because the properties or attributes which constitute them are not adapted to exist together in the same be- ing, and, of course, except for the service of the fancy, are never combined. There is something in these properties, or in what they represent, which fits them to co-exist, or they could not with any reason be combined in a concept which connects the rational and real ; which represents things as actual or possible, or con- templates them as designed to be under existing powers or laws. (6.) The same principle must be assumed in the arrangement of a system of concepts as genera and species. It is evident, that as we might make as many concepts as the va- ried aggregations of single attributes would allow, so these might be arranged into as many genera and species as the fertile law of permutation and combination would permit. Any one attri- bute might be taken as generic without regard to its actual extent in nature ; with this any other might be combined as a differentia without regard to the compatibility of the two as pro- vided by the adaptations of nature's laws. It is contended by some, that in the classifications which we actually make, we are guided by mere convenience, that we can make any attribute ge- neric which we please, provided it be more extensive than its differentia in its actual prevalence, but that there are no such things as real genera and species ; these terms having no meaning in such an application. If we assume that there are no affinities or adaptations in properties and laws, and no ends to which the powers of nature are adapted, and which are designed to be permanent, this view is correct. But the moment we assume that such adaptations exist, and that they can be discovered by ob- servation and induction, then the belief in permanent classes is justified and explained. (c.) This relation is essential to an intelligible conception and definition of an individual. (d.) The principle is of the greatest value as a criterion of truth and a rule of certitude. When skepticism suggests that every principle may be questioned, and every observation of fact may be mistaken ; that the objective creation may be a shifting 22* ' 514 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 317. phantasmagoria, and the subjective mind but a lying glass of opinion; then the thought of the inconceivable non-adaptation of such a universe to any rational end even of knowledge, re- stores our confidence in the testimony of the senses, the experi- • ences of consciousness, and the inductions of thought. We try all these indeed by one another, after the tests which experience and science have discovered, but we trust them only when they conspire to ends that are worthy of rational order in a universe adapted to be known by a being who is manifestly designed to know, and to confide in his knowledge when it is properly tested and proved. § 317. 2. In the Mathematics even, the presence me?r?cai m con -~ of this relation is recognized. struction and T . .. 1 t i n deduction. In pure geometry it may be applied more fre- quently than would be anticipated. The circle is adapted to prove a great variety of theorems, and to solve many problems, as is exemplified in any treatise on geometry. If we are required to construct two triangles on the same base, the angles of which at the apex of each shall be right angles, it can readily be done by describing a half-circle on this line as a diameter, and any number of triangles can at once be drawn so as to fulfill the required conditions. We discern in a portion of space bounded -by a half-circle, this capacity or adaptation, that waited long to be discerned. The relations of pure number open as wide a field of inherent fitnesses to serve the ends of the student. It is upon the faith that additional adaptations remain to be discerned that the mathema- tician prosecutes his work of inventive discovery. The adaptations of the mathematics to the service of physics are if possible still more striking. No projectile was ever thrown -in an exact parabola ; yet the theory of this curve is adapted to explain the direction and motion of every body that is launched into the atmosphere. The theory of the lines in which bodies tend to move, and the rates in which bodies move in fact when impelled, is adapted to regulate the mechanics of bodies as they fall to the earth, and the motions of the orbs which revolve in the heavens. It also explains the phenomena of the pressure of fluids. The relations of number solve the mystery of chemi- cal combinations : they explain the symmetry of agreeable forms § 318. DESIGN OR FINAL CAUSE. 515 and the harmony of musical sounds. They enable us to discern a common law in the arrangement of the leaves upon the stem of every tree, and in the placing of the planets along the lines which stretch out from the sun. On the first thought, it would seem that in extension and number it would be impossible to find so great a variety of possi- ble adaptations. But on reflection, we find that their capacity of multiform application is the only key to the perfection of the sciences of matter and the reduction of its forces to unvarying laws. We have urged that the belief in final cause must be intuitive, because we could not otherwise confide in the axioms of induc- tion. But we see in the provision for the possibility of mathe- matical science, and of its universal application to material phenomena as the indispensable condition of their laws, another example of design where we had least expected its manifestations, viz., in those time and space relations which render the mathe- matics possible. § 318. 3. Geology and Paleontology both assume the truth and applicability of the principle of final g^etc; mge °* cause. Geology was at first content to explain the formation of the crust of the globe by analyzing its parts into their constituent elements, and recording the order in which the rocks had been compacted and broken down, and the strata had been formed and deposited. In these investigations it proceeded as a science of observation, watching and recording the operations of the forces of nature according to laws already ascertained. But, aided by paleontology, geology has proposed to itself a higher problem, and contemplated facts under more elevated re- lations. It has traced a plan and order of development resting on the assumption of a series of ends subordinated to one another, and terminating in a habitation equally adapted to man's higher and lower nature. It has ventured to recall the successive phases of organic life by reproducing extinct species of plants and animals amid the lakes, marshes and jungles in which they sported and from which they subsisted, and to arrange these phases in the order of time and of a more and more perfect de- velopment. The assumption which has directed these bold essays and enabled the geologist successfully to apply the hints fur- 516 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §319. nished by facts observed, is, that an order of fitness and progress has been followed from the first, and every epoch has pre- pared the way for the next succeeding ; the adaptations of each being complete in animals, plants, and scenery. Following the same clue, this science has found in each previous epoch, not merely the materials of the one which succeeded, but the ex- istence of a less perfectly developed form of life. This series terminates with man, who not only represents the highest type of life, but shows that he is the end for which all others are designed, by the fact that he alone can comprehend the import of the plan and recognize the relations of the parts to the whole, and of the whole to himself. Geology, by the very aims which it proposes, and the splendid results which it has achieved, gives its tacit yet fervent assent to the original authority of the intuition of final cause. Applied in g e- § 319, 4 - Philosophical Geography gives a similar hfstor 1 "^ and testimony. This science, as conceived and perfected by Eitter, takes the earth where geology leaves it, and shows how each continent and country was fitted for the part which it has played in the world's history, by its structure, surface, soil, and climate, by its mountain barriers to repel, and its coasts and harbors to invite ; by its river-systems to bind re- moter portions, and its insular situation to facilitate defence. It shows that every part of the earth was not only adapted from the first to receive and develop the race which was allotted to it, and to become the scene of events which have made it memora- ble, but to transmit the results of these achievements to neigh- boring countries and other races, and even to transfer them to remote parts of the earth and a later and better civilization. By referring intellectual and moral influences to favoring physical conditions, it enables us to find an adaptation to important moral results, even in the physical arrangements of the earth. The Philosophy of History also must assume that the events of human history, have occurred in obedience to definite laws regu- lating constant forces. Whatever these forces may be called — or whatever may be the law of their action, the historian cannot seek to interpret or explain them without believing that there are definite aims toward which these forces tend, and after which they are regulated, § 321. DESIGN OR FINAL CAUSE. 517 § 320. 5. Comparative Anatomy rests upon the same intuition. It could have no meaning, as it pa ratlve n ana- would have no truth without it. It is a science of sio?o g y nd phy " similar adaptations, not only of organs to functions, but of analogies of form and feature and inner structure to the completeness of a progressive plan, and even to the achievement of an aesthetic effect and the expression of an aesthetic import. Give this science a bone, and it will draw or model the animal, tell you how large he was, how formed, on what he lived, what were his habits and disposition, what the length of his life, — -just so far as it reads the adaptations that gather and cluster around this fragment of a skeleton, which except as thus inter- preted were only a broken and abraded fossil. 6. In Physiology, special and general, similar relations are more numerous and manifest. The departments of animal and vegetable life abound, or rather overflow with examples of fitness and adj ustment. The nicer the analysis of elements and of organs, and the more subtle the detection of .offices and func- tions, so much the more exquisite are the discerned relations of adaptation of each to each. Not only is there seen a fitness of one organ to another, — as of the lungs to the heart, — and to the common end of all, but there is a fitness of every organ to the element in and by which it acts, — as of the lungs to the air and of the eye to the light. The more we learn of the structure of the one and of the properties of the other, the nicer are the adaptations which we discern between the two. The adaptations of the body of man to the functions and uses of the rational soul, are still more striking ; but we here approach, if we do not cross, the line which divides physiology from An- thropology. § 321. 7. In Anthropology we trace these higher adaptations. The human hand does not differ more topology ; an " strikingly from the hand of the monkey than the mind of the monkey from the mind of man. The mind of man has endeavored to discover and combine the powers of nature, and to devise the appliances of art. Whatever the mind has prompted the hand to construct, the hand has been able to frame, either through the seemingly exhaustless versatility of its flexible organism, or by the tools and machinery with which it 518 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 321. has contrived to supplement its powers. So wonderful has been this service, that it has been questioned, whether the human in- tellect or the human hand has been the most conspicuous in shaping human destiny and in developing human history. The hand has also by the economy of nature been fitted to be the medium of conveying varied intellectual and emotional expres- sion to the intellect and heart, which have been as mysteriously fitted to receive and interpret its indications. The hand invites and repels, commands and forbids, soothes and enrages. It ap- peases with its gentle waving, and smites with its ferocious energy. It adores with the uplifted arm, it blesses with the outspread palm ; it blasphemes with aimless and impotent motions, and curses with its downward stroke. But there is no adaptation of the mind and body sions^o^and that gives to both united, an interest which at once oflangmTge* 168 so fascinates and baffles our prying scrutiny, as that exhibited in the agency of both in the production, use, and development of language. There are two conditions of language, the bodily and the mental. The bodily are also two, the mouth and the ear, to which the hand and the eye are acces- sary. But for expression the mind must also furnish the material through its required capacities and development. Language is impossible until the mind observes and generalizes and affirms. The mind must first think the material and spiritual universe with which it comes in contact, into the thought-world which its powers and laws fit it to create, before it can give to it expression by language. This adaptation of the vocal and the spiritual to each other, and of the possible elaboration of the one to the possible refinement of the other, go far beyond any observed fitness of the eye to the light, or of the ear to the agent of sound. Not only are these two parts of the complex body and soul fitted to expand side by side with one another, but the expression of thought in language reacts with wondrous energy on the development and refinement of thought itself, so that it is not only true that the developed thought finds itself able to em- ploy language in its service, but it is also true that the thought in order to be developed, must express itself in language. Man not only speaks because he thinks, but he speaks in order that he may think, i. e., think with clearness, precision and progress. The §322. DESIGN OR FINAL CAUSE. 519 two are not merely so adapted that the one can expand side by side with the other, but it is difficult to say which is the most dependent on the other. The celebrated Galen says, in his treatise concerning the human body, that by the variety and accordant action of its ad- justments, it seems to utter an anthem of praise to its Maker. But the philosopher who reflects on the mystery of human lan- guage, in the subtlety of the elements involved, the variety of the conjunctions, the delicacy of the structure, and the capacities for growth and development, might find, as he watches in the lispings of infancy the feeble beginnings of such splendid results, a new meaning in the familiar words " Out of the mouths of babes and sucklings thou hast perfected praise." § 322. 8. In Psychology the manifestations of final cause are more frequent and obvious than in psychology! r ° either physiology or anthropology. It is now and then difficult for consciousness to analyze its operations under the relations of efficient causation, or to trace each product back to the separate force from which it springs into being. But the adaptations of these operations and products to one another, and to the manifest ends of the soul's culture and well-being are often so obvious and remarkable, that they partially settle questions that would otherwise remain unsolved. For example, in considering the acquired perceptions, we find that animals possess from the beginning, a capacity of judging of distance and size which man is forced to acquire by slow and painful effort. We question whether our observations can be trusted, whether there is not some error or oversight in the analysis of the phenomena. The consideration of the end to be accomplished by this arrangement relieves the difficulty. Man, we observe, needs the discipline required by the slow process of acquiring what the animal knows at the beginning. The con- sideration of adaptation removes the similar difficulties suggested by the question, "why the range of instinct is so much wider and more unerring in the lower animals than it is in man, the highest of all?" When we consider the diversity of the destiny and ends of the two we accept with less hesitation the evidence which observation furnishes. Above all, psychology acquaints us with the rational faculty 520 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §323. as that pre-eminent power which proposes ends and devises means for their accomplishment. It acknowledges that this is the highest of the intellectual powers, that it is lawfully supreme, that in the service of this power we investigate causes and determine their laws. In the subjection and adaptation of the lower powers to this highest of all it finds confirmation of the propriety of assuming the relation of adaptation in all our interpretations of nature. If " on the earth there is nothing great but man, and in man, there is nothing great but mind," it is emphatically true that in the mind there is nothing great but the reason which proposes and discovers ends, and is itself an end to the lower actings of the intellect. § 323. (9.) Ethics, the science of duty, which is Applied and ° V / . ' . , J „ assumed in so closely allied to, if it is not a department of psy- ethics. .. . „ , , ., , . ... cnology, is founded entirely upon the intuition m question. Its subject-matter is derived from the ends of human existence and human activity. The comprehensive and funda- mental question which it asks, is, for what kind of activities is the human soul adapted by its constitution, and what must man be and do to fulfil these ends of his being ? In these inquiries, it rests on the single assumption that man is fitted for one kind of activity rather than for another, and that the action for which he is fitted is right, while the action for which he is not fitted is wrong. It asks, how shall these adapta- tions be discovered? By what faculty or capacity, one or more, are they discerned and responded to ? What are the tests or criteria by which they are distinguished?. What external actions or duties must we perform in order most effectually to fulfil these several ends of our being ? Corresponding to the power of apprehending duty, is the faculty of will or choice qualifying man to fulfil the ends for which he exists. The existence of this power, its importance to human development and responsibility, and the necessity that it should be defended in its integrity, explain the necessity of moral trial, and the possibility of moral evil — under the one relation of the ends which the possession of this power and the exposures which it involves are adapted to fulfil. The adaptations with which ethics has to do, are chiefly psy- chical, and suppose a spiritual organism in the soul — a system of § 324 DESIGN OR FINAL CAUSE. 521 internal adaptations in the several powers with which it is endowed, which indicate our duties and our obligations. These all look toward moral perfection. To this the soul is adapted and to it it tends and is impelled. Without this intuition and faith in its truth, ethics can have no meaning and duty no authority. If reason as proposing ends is the highest ruling power in man, then the reason, when it discovers and proposes the highest moral ends, exercises its loftiest functions, and reigns sovereign over the inner and outer world by a self-justified authority. § 324. 10. In Theology, or the science of God, whether natural or revealed, this principle is of theology. 1011 *° supreme importance. The most of the so-called demonstrations of the being of God, find their material or grounds of proof in the indications of design that are furnished in the material universe. These arguments are usually stated somewhat _ , . , , . rr , The common thus : Design proves or implies a designer ; The argument for , , . , . r mi „ f the Divine ex- uni verse abounds m design ; Inereiore the universe istence. implies or proves a designer : or, order and adapta- tion imply a designer ; The universe abounds in order and adaptation ; Therefore a designer exists. The major premise in this argument is obviously assumed or received as a priori. The minor is a statement of fact grounded on observation or induction. Those who employ this argument would not accept the view, that the belief that adaptation prevails throughout the universe is a first truth or axiom of thought. They rest their belief upon observation, and they search through the universe to discover instances of the presence of this rela- tion. Having observed a sufficient number, they generalize them by induction, and then apply, as the minor premise of their syllogism, the proposition which they have established by this cumulative evidence. We have sought to prove that the proposition affirming final causes is a first principle or intuitive truth ; that it is not in any sense dependent on observation, but is an original and necessary belief or category ; that so far from being derived from induc- tion, it is the necessary ground on which induction itself must rest for its validity and application. Those who accept the relation of final cause as necessary and a 522 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 324. priori may be grouped under tw.o leading classes or divisions, ac- cording as the adherents of each reject or accept the belief of a personal God. The one class believe in an immanent force, which involves no relation to any thing beyond the universe as a whole. They fully accept the truth that design rules throughout nature. They find examples of the relation of final cause everywhere pre- sent. But they insist that these do not necessarily carry the thoughts out of nature: Final cause or design is a force in nature itself, immanent in each separate object, and in all existing objects taken as an organism of parts mutually related and connected. Those who hold this doctrine, concede that adaptation prevails in nature, and must be assumed to explain its powers and opera- tions ; also, that it works in every case as though a personal mind had contrived these ends and the relations which they in- volve, and continues to direct them. But they urge that we are not compelled to ascribe this adaptation to a personal being, but may refer it to an impersonal, unconscious, unthinking force, as blind and unintelligent as the efficient forces that act by me- chanical laws. The second class contend that the necessary correlate to adaptation is a designing mind : They conceive of adap- tation as the objective relation to which thought is an essential supplement. Adaptation does not prove or in- dicate design, but it rationally implies it ; if, therefore, the adaptation is real, so is the designing mind. In assuming the one truth by an a priori necessity, you must accept the other. The belief in adapted things both logically and really carries with itself the belief in adapting thought and an adaptive thinker. The mind need not necessarily think of the two at the same in- stant, or in the same connection. The attention may be so con- centrated upon the adaptation objectively considered, its inge- nuity, the variety of the means employed, the intricacy and order of the combinations required, that it does not consciously refer to the correlate, but this fact does not prove that it is not necessarily involved. For example : in a machine of human devising, an ingenious mind can discern very many adaptations, without ad- verting to the mind which produced them, or distinctly recog- nizing the fact that it proceeded from any thought ; but as soon § 324. DESIGN OR FINAL CAUSE. 523 as it raises the question and reflects on the relation, it cannot but assent to the additional truth. The application of this principle in the service of Natural Theology raises still another question ; viz., What relation has efficient to final causation in the universe ? Does each require its separate principle or agent, or do both united direct us to one ? Does the adapting agent simply take the efficient forces and laws of the universe as it finds them, and arranging them as best it may, bring out of them the wisest results to which its sagacity may adapt them, or does it also originate the forces which it ar- ranges and combines? The one view gives the eternity of matter, with its hindrances and limitations and possibilities of evil, making the Deity a Demiurgos or Plastic energy. The other makes the originator and the arranger to be the same power and the same mind. The one view is the cruder theism of Ancient Philosophy, the other the purer theism of the Jewish and Christian Scriptures. It would carry us too far from our appropriate theme to argue here the question between the two. The discussion of it belongs to a treatise on Natural Theology. Psychology suggests that the analogy of the human soul, which combines in itself — under limits — a creating force and an adapting or designing force, furnishes a decisive argument in favor of the conclusion, that -the creator and thinker is One Being. 524 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 325. CHAPTER VII. SUBSTANCE AND ATTRIBUTE: MIND AND MATTER. § 325. We return again to the relation of Sub- Etymoiogyof stance and Attribute, and to the important application the Terms. . . . of it in the determination of the definitions of Mind and Matter and of Real and Phenomenal Being. The relation is so fundamental and so much discussed in Psychology and Philoso- phy, as to require a careful consideration. The substance or substratum with which we have to do, is the Real substance or substratum. As such it should be carefully dis- tinguished from the logical substance or subject. A logical sub- ject is any thing which is conceived in thought as a substance with attributes, whether it does or does not exist in fact. Thus any abstractum can be treated in thought and described in lan- guage as though it had real being, and were endowed with real attributes. The concepts power, goodness, responsibility, represen- tation, republic, wages, wealth, or any other abstract notion, may be conceived in thought and treated in language as having prop- erties or qualities which are affirmed of each as though it were a real being. Real substance ought also to be distinguished from the grammatical subject. The grammatical subject is any word which is used in language as though it denoted a logical subject. The concepts, substance and attribute, cannot be resolved by the etymology of the terms which designate them. The words sub- ject, substance, ^substratum, have a common derivation which literally imports something standing or lying under, and implies that there is something placed above or upon it which may be re- moved. This suggests the impression that the attributes are su- perinduced upon the substance, as folds or wrappings are thrown over or around a nucleus or core within. This prompts to the effort to lay off the covering, to separate the wrappings from the nucleus which they invest, to scale off the laminae or folds, and find the substance or substratum within or beneath, bare of all qualities and relations. But the attempt to lay aside qualities in order to find their subject is soon discovered to be vain. It is as though § 326. SUBSTANCE AND ATTRIBUTE I MIND AND MATTER. 525 one should cut down tlie trees in order to find the forest. It is found to be impossible to discover an actually existing subject without attributes. The simplest and barest object in the uni- verse — that which in its nature is the most uninteresting and the most undistinguished — as the mote in a sunbeam, the minutest perceptible grain of sanely the atom or molecule which the physi- cist cannot perceive, the monad of which the metaphysician con- fidently speculates — must always be conceived as having place and form, and as involving the relations of extension and force. The etymology and use of the terms attribute, quality, property, and accident do not give us any greater satisfaction as to the nature of the distinction. The term attribute simply directs the attention to the fact that we attribute to, or affirm of, a being, something which we distinguish from itself; but it does not in the least explain what we distinguish or that from which it is distinguished. Quality is a term of classification merely, i. e., it signifies that the being is of a certain class, without explaining why it belongs to the class in question. Property indicates, that what we thus attribute or affirm belongs peculiarly or properly to the being or substance, and accident that it belongs to it occa- sionally. These different words are only different names for the same conception, as differently used. But their etymology or application throw no light upon the conception itself, or how it originates, or why it is distinguished from its correlate substance. We learn, moreover, that we can no more find an attribute without substance, than we can find a substance without attri- butes. We cannot separate length from something which is long, nor color from something colored, nor thought from a thinking being, nor joy from a rejoicing being. The two conceptions are never parted in the world of real existence. They are not merely correlated by a logical necessity, but they are always inseparably conjoined in actual existence. § 326. But though substance and attribute do not Snbatance and exist apart, they can be conceived of and defined as ^abstract" abstracted from one another. Abstractly considered, the concept, substance, is less general than that of simple being. Being has already been explained as every object that is, or that is conceived to be,knowable or known. But every thing that is known is not only known to be, but is also known as related. 526 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 327. Hence, with every act of knowledge, the concept of being as re- lated, at once arises and becomes universally applicable to every object that is known. Certain of these relations may be used to distinguish, define, and explain these knowable objects. Any being with relations so discerned and applied as to distinguish it from other beings, is conceived as a substance, i. e. : a substance is a being distinguishable and definable by a complex of relations. The conception of attribute arises in a similar way. As soon as an object is discerned in a definite relation to another object, this relation can be affirmed of or attributed to this object. When one relation or more is applied to define or distinguish any one^ of these beings, it becomes an attribute, as used in this generic and technical sense. Every relation by which a being is known or distinguished is an attribute. It deserves to be noticed here that there are also as many different substances as there are beings distinguishable in kind by combinations of relations. An individual substance is known only by the individual relations which it shares with no other. The substance is not, however, made up or constituted, by its rela- tions. It is not the same thing as a collection of attributes. It is distinguished and defined duly by these relations. From this it is manifest that the category of substance and attribute is not simple and original like the other relations or categories which we have considered, but is complex and derived. Any one of these relations, when employed for the ends of recog- nition or description, for definition or classification, for reasoning or explanation, in short, for knowledge of any sort, whether com- mon or scientific, becomes an attribute. Any existing thing, when it is sufficiently permanent or oft-recurring to require to be known by attributes, is called a substance. There are two classes of objects-matter to which this category is most frequently applied, spiritual substances and corporeal sub- stances. Abstract ideas, or abstracta, follow the analogy of real beings, and so do grammatical subjects. Mathematical entities do the same so far as this relation is concerned. We shall con- sider the two classes which are here named, and begin with spiritual or mental substance. Spiritual or § 327. Here we encounter, at the outset, the ob- sunce! 6Ub " jection or difficulty that a mental or spiritual being § 327. SUBSTANCE AND ATTRIBUTE : MIND AND MATTER. 527 cannot be a substance at all. This difficulty is merely verbal, and is of purely casual association, arising simply from the fact that substance more frequently implies material existence. Dismissing this objection as merely verbal and superficial, we proceed to inquire in what sense spirit is a substance and what are its distinguishing attributes, especially in the form which it assumes as the human soul. Our previous inquiries have taught us that the prominent attri- butes of the substance which we call the human soul are its capacities to know, to feel, and to will. But to know, to feel, to will, are operations or modes of activity and suffering. These capacities are energies, simply causative of certain effects, or which involve energies that are causative. These three attri- butes obviously fall under the category or relation of causation. The power of the soul to be conscious of its acts and states is also a capacity for causal efficiency, which like the others is known by its exercise and its results. But we know more of the substance of the soul than that it is the cause or recipient of those effects which we call its states. The truth is established by consciousness that the soul knows these acts and states to be its own, i. e., to be caused or suffered by the individual ego, or self. These states and products of the soul's causal activity, are transient and changing, while the ego is permanent and enduring. As the cause or recipient of these changes the soul is identical with itself. They are diverse, the soul is one. The psychical attributes therefore require the categories of identity, diversity and time, as well as that of causation. Besides the attributes of the soul which are revealed in con- sciousness, it is capable of acts or processes of which it is conscious only of the results in its psychical experience. The capacities for these results, whether the results are dependent on psychical or material conditions, are also causative, and are therefore properly classed among causative attributes. Besides the relations of causation there are relations of design which pertain to the soul. These are conspicuous both in the relations of one power and act of the soul to another, and also in the relations of the soul to the external world and to the body which connects it with that world. All of these relations are 528 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 328. attributes of the soul ; some of these, however, are so necessary to an adequate conception of its nature as to deserve to be con- sidered as essential and distinguishing. We find then, that those relations of the individual ego by which it is usually defined, are its capacities to do and to suffer, to know and attain its end or destiny, and these attributes are all found in the Categories of Causation and Design. When to these we add its relations of Identity and Time we complete the cycle of its attributes. From this analysis we derive the fol- lowing definition : That Substance which we call the Human Soul, is an identical enduring self, capable of spiritual acts and states in the succession of time, which are adapted to certain ends with respect to the universe of being. The relation of substance and attribute, when thus applied, is that of a being and of certain distinguishing or essential relations, as of time, identity, causation and design, which appertain to the being. § 328. A material substance, again, is, like spiritual Btance er defined! substance, a being discerned or discernible by intui- tive or direct knowledge and also definable by a suffi- cient variety and number of relations to distinguish it from other beings. These relations are discerned by sense-perception and consciousness, and are generalized by thought. A Material Sub- stance may be defined: a being occupying definite limits in space, and productive of specific sensations in the sentient soul,on occasion of which it is perceived or known to exist. First of all, it is related to space in trinal extension. It might be urged that, in one sense, the spectrum cast by the camera on a screen, or the rainbow flung athwart a cloud are material sub- stances, with only superficial or binal extension; but material substance, in the ordinary sense, has threefold extension, or, as we say, extension in three dimensions. Corporeal substance has a second relation to space, viz., that of space-occupying or space-filling. This is often called the solidity or impenetrability of matter, but should be carefully dis- tinguished from that power of matter to awaken the sensation of hardness, which is also called solidity. The first is a relation to space which is tested and expressed by the application of motion. The second is the capacity of the body to excite a specific sensation on occasion of touch. § 328. SUBSTANCE AND ATTRIBUTE: MIND AND MATTER. 529 The third class of relations which belong to corporeal substance are its powers variously to affect, through the senses, the body as animated and ensouled, and also the soul itself as a sentient agent. Every material substance has power to produce certain so-called impressions on the so-called organs of sensation, i. e., upon the body as organized to receive these impressions. Of these effects, the vibration of the tympanum, and the formation of the image on the retina, are examples. These may occur without sensation, as is manifest in cases of disease, of mental excitement, and the use of anaesthetic agents. But the condition of any of these effects, is a living body. Consequent upon these are those effects upon the sensitive or sentient soul which are called sensations, or sensations proper. The condition of the last is a body living and ensouled. In sensation, or the sense-element of the complex act called sense-perception, the soul is purely receptive, or passive, and the material substance is active. Its various powers to produce these sensations are all compre- hended under the category or relation of causation. On the condition of the experience of these sensations the be- ing which causes them is known to exist as a Non-ego. But the pos- sibility of being perceived is in itself no attribute of matter in the sense of being a causative power. To perceive is an act of the mind. The causative energy and the capacity which fits for this act, both pertain to the mind alone. Matter, so far as it is perceived, acts neither upon the body nor the soul. Matter is, i. e., exists, and is known by the mind to be. It is not correct to say, that it is known only as the cause of the sensations which the soul suffers or receives ; making it to be known only as the unknown cause of a felt effect. Rather, it is known to be and also as causing these sensations. As existing, it is known to have other relations than its power to cause sensations. Space is a reality, and so are the spatial relations of matter as known. To define matter with J. S. Mill (Logic, I., c. 3, § 7,) as " the ex- ternal cause to which we ascribe our sensations," is to overlook entirely these relations of matter to space, and misinterpret the act of knowledge itself. To say that "matter may be defined as a permanent possibility of sensation" (Exam, of Ham., c. xi.),is to fall into a more serious error. Besides the relations of material substances to space and to the 23 530 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 329. animated and ensouled body, there is a class of relations which it holds to other bodies. These are its powers to produce effects in or upon them. They comprehend all the properties of matter, whether mechanical, chemical, or organic, which have as yet been discovered, or which science may in future unfold. That all these attributes are comprehended under the causal relation is too obvious to need illustration or proof. The relations of matter thus far considered are those of space and causation. We define material substance by means of these as a being having a definite form or outline (involving relations to space or other bodies existing in space), occupying exclusively some portion of space (involving space-relations), and productive of specific sensations in the sentient soul on occasion of which it is known to be (involving relations of causation and objective reality). We repeat the remark, that this complex or collection of re- lations do not constitute a material substance. They simply in- dicate that it is a material substance. They are relations which define and distinguish it as such. They constitute its logical es- sence only. The same is true of the element being which is im- plied in such definition. Being, like every other simple notion, cannot be defined ; but it does not follow, as we have already seen, that it cannot be known and understood. § 329. A material substance has been defined as Space occnpa- *, • -i • • T • tion and iden- exclusively occupying a portion of space. It is not tity of matter. . , ; , . . r „ F , , , „ required that this portion ol space should be 01 any definite size or dimensions. A grain of sand is a material sub- stance; so is a large mass of sand-stone : so is a portion of water or the indefinitely expanded atmosphere. All that is required is, that the mass, be it greater or smaller, should be so fixed and held together in its parts as to occupy continuously their defined lim- its. The continuity of parts is of more importance than the continuity of definite outline. This continuity or coherence of parts is maintained in different substances by different agencies. The constituent parts may be held together by simple mechanical aggregation under the force of cohesive attraction. They may be held more closely by the polar force of crystalline arrange- ment. They may be united still more intimately under the laws of chemical affinity. They may be combined and assimilated into the forms and products of organic existence ; or the sub- § 330. SUBSTANCE AND ATTRIBUTE : MIND AND MATTER. 531 stance may be conceived as an ultimate molecule, or a simple cell. Every being that is one and continuous, of whatever size, in whatever form, or held together by whatever bond of union, is a material substance. A certain continuity in time, or permanence,is either required as a defining characteristic of substance, or is implied in its defi- nition. This integrity of the whole is presumed as having continued and as likely to continue for some considerable period, or the being indicated would scarcely be called a substance. It certainly would not be worth noticing by defining attributes if it did not so remain. The relative permanence of material substance explains the conception of its identity. Identity in such a substance may pertain to the constituent elements only, or to the form only, or to the uniting force, or it may be applied to the connection of one part with another in a series of changes which involve a total alteration of both constituents and form. Thus if the same particles remain united in the same form by mechanical aggrega- tion, the substance is eminently the same ; the only diversity in such a case being that of relation to other substances — a diversity of time or place or both. Should the constituents re- main the same and the form be changed, it might be called the same, provided the constituents were viewed as more important than the form. If the external form is changed by growth or development, as in plants or animals, the continuously acting force is regarded as making them a substance. If the parts of a knife or a ship are displaced and replaced by successive re- movals and substitutions while the form and functions are re- tained, the substance is still called the same by a loose analogy taken from living agents and their gradual accretion and growth. § 330. We have seen that a change in form and .... . . n The prodac- structure or in both, involves the production 01 a new thm of new substance, because it involves the production of rela- tions which clearly distinguish such a substance. A living being, as an animal, consists in part of certain material particles or elements. If a succession of changes or decompositions and recom positions could go on before our eyes, so that we could trace the same particles back through every form in which they can possibly exist, through plant, mineral, earth, air, water, etc., 532 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. §331. in every possible form of chemical and crystalline combination, till we had reached the ultimate molecules or elements of all and of each, we should evolve a series of substances, one after another, in a consecutive order of gradation. But the simplest elements, the ultimate particles, would still be substances with attributes which they must continue to re- tain and from which they could never in fact be parted. Those who seek an interior substance, divested of attributes — the nu- cleus of the outer — are misled by a secondary use of the word. The "underlying substance" of the schools, the The real Es- "thing in itself" of Kant, are mere names, which sig- *Thing initseif. nify either being in the abstract or being in the con- crete. If it is being in the abstract, then it must be synonymous with matter as knowable, i. e., it is a concept only, which can be separated from its relations in thought but never in fact. If it is being in the concrete, then this must be known with its relations and never apart from them. In either case the substance or thing in itself, cannot be known by itself. § 331. A material substance is not necessarily in- Bubstance 6 not dependent or self-subsistent. This was insisted on by dependent m * Spinoza, who defines substance to be " that which exists and is conceived by itself." " Per substantiam intelligo id quod in se est et per se concipitur ; hoc est id cujus con- ceptus non indiget conceptu alterius rei a quo formari debeat" Ethica, p. i.,def. 3. From this definition the inference was direct and irresistible, that no finite substance is possible, because every so-called finite material substance is produced or sustained by other material beings, and is dependent on them ; or, on the other hand, there is but one such substance, and that is the total of all which exists — the universe ; this totality being conceived as abso- lute and independent. Locke falls into a similar manner of speaking when he de- scribes the constitution " which every thing has within itself without any relation to any thing without." Similar to this is the doctrine of Whewell, that substance is indestructible. " The supposition of the existence of substance is so far from beiDg uncertain, that it carries with it irresistible conviction, and sub- stance is necessarily conceived as something which cannot be produced or destroyed." Hist, of Scient. Ideas, vol. ii.,p. 32. § 331. SUBSTANCE AND ATTRIBUTE I MIND AND MATTER. 533 Our analysis has shown that a material substance is so far from being independent of other , beings and forces, that, pro- perly speaking, no material substance is in any sense inde- pendent, or can be conceived to be so. Every material sub- stance is what it is by the productive or sustaining force of all other beings and forces in the universe. It is also conceived and defined to be what it is by its relations to these forces, the ex- pressed and the implied. It cannot exist and cannot be defined except by these relations to other beings and agencies. If ma- terial substance is dependent, it is not necessarily indestructible. Should the forces which sustain it be withdrawn, or their action be changed, it would cease to be, or cease to be the same sub- stance that it was. And yet we constantly assume that material substances are permanent, — not the ultimate particles alone, but even the continu- ous forms in which they exist and perpetually reappear. If we did not assume this, we should not define the constituents of either, — we should neither form them into concepts, nor apply these concepts for the ends of knowledge. What is the nature and what are the grounds of this assumption ? They are none other than that the agencies and laws which sustain and produce these substances will remain, in order to accomplish certain ends for which they exist. In other words, it is only by re- lations of orderly design that we can explain or vindicate that belief in the permanence of the material structure as to its forms of being and their constituents which is received as an axiom in all physical or inductive philosophy. That this permanence or indestructibility is not essential or necessary, that it cannot be viewed as an axiomatic truth, appears from the broader and deeper axioms on which it rests. These axioms involve the rela- tion of design and belief in a designer. There are philosophers who deny that there are any permanent forms or elements of material substance, seem to deny Such believe that nothing is fixed, either in sub- stance or attributes ; that every thing in the universe is in a per- petual flux, that the law of development controls all existence, so that one form and species of being is evolved from another — the more complex from the more simple — in endless progression. One relation of permanence in nature must, however, be as- 534 THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 332. sumed by all these philosophers, and that is, the permanence of this law or principle of development ^itself. If it may be assumed from the limited facts and observations adduced, that the law of de- velopment has prevailed in all the ages, and has evolved one form of being after another, by a steady progress and in regular order, then the permanence of the law of development itself must be referred to a fixed purpose and design of nature. The law of development cannot, therefore, drive the fact of design out of the universe, nor dispense with the assumption of design as one of the axioms of science. § 332. Our analysis of matter and spirit has shown The reciprocal « i " -i relations of that many of the attributes of both can only be ex- material and _ .. ' * spiritual sub- plained and understood by means of one another. The one can be defined and known only by the other. To understand and describe the one we must make use of the other. But the two are in some important respects very unlike. In order to show this with success, we must first con- sider the difference between the direct and reflex knowledge of both. _i ' . The mind knows both matter and mind bv direct Mind and mat- ter directly an( j re flex knowledge. By direct knowledge in and indirectly . known. sense-perception, it knows matter as a being. By direct knowledge in consciousness, it knows itself as the agent which knows matter and is also the subject of certain sensations. It knows both these objects in certain relations. It knows mat- ter not only to exist, but to be diverse from itself the knower, and to be extended, i. e., to have space relations ; it knows itself to exist, and enduringly to feel and act, i. e., to have time rela- tions. By indirect or reflex knowledge the soul is considered as sen- tient as well as percipient As sentient it receives or suffers certain effects, viz. : the sensations of which matter is the cause. As perci- pient it knows by consciousness its own subjective states as thus caused, and by sense-perception the being that causes them ; also that this being is not itself, and is extended in space. The being having these capacities to cause these effects in itself as a sen- tient it defines as matter. In other words, in sense-perception, the intellect knows some- thing more than subjective or spiritual effects, viz., specific sensa- § 333. SUBSTANCE AND ATTRIBUTE: MIND AND MATTER. 535 tions, as of touch, sight, etc., for which it assumes an unknown cause. It cot only knows itself directly and those acts and objects that are purely spiritual, but it knows material objects also, and by its prerogative as an agent competent to know. If it did not know them directly as beings, it could not know them as extended or as diverse from itself, or even as causal agents. We say, then, without reserve, that the mind in sense-percep- tion, knows matter or material being as truly and as directly as in consciousness it knows the ego, or mental being. § 333. The qualities of matter have been divided into the primary and the secondary. The primary oi matter 1 * 1 !* include its relations to space, as extension and space- secondary. and occupancy, or impenetrability. The secondary include its causative relations to the sentient soul, as hardness, color, smell, taste, etc. [Dugald Stewart divides these relations into Mathematical affections and Primary and Secondary qualities. Ham- ilton recognizes three classes, the Primary, the Secondary, and the Secundo-primary : the primary including the relations of exten- sion; the secundo-primary, resistance, gravity, repulsion, and iner- tia ; and the secondary, the capacities to cause sensations.] The principle of this two-fold division is obviously just and the application of it is easy. The analysis already made has shown that these two classes of attributes are clearly distinguished in fact. The relations of matter to space do not in their logical con- tent, as distinguished by the mind, involve the recognition of any sensation. On the other hand, the powers of matter to produce certain sensations of touch, sight, smell, taste, and sound, can only be known by considering the sensations themselves as caused by these powers. Of the first class we have direct and positive knowledge. Of the second our knowledge is indirect and rela- tive, it being explained by the effects produced. There is still another element in matter which does not fall within either class, and this is matter as existing in distinction from its relations to other matter, to the sentient spirit, or to space or time. This is known by direct mental apprehension, in connection with felt sensations and on condition of the excited or impelled sensorium. Matter is known as being and also as causing these sensations: not as though its being were only known 53G THE HUMAN INTELLECT. § 335. by relation to these sensations ; but it is directly known as being and also as related to these sensations which it causes. Every thing which is known as related, is known to be ; consequently, the matter which is known as related to the sensations must also be known to exist. Two questions remain to be considered in respect to these two classes of qualities, (a.) Are the primary qualities distin- guished from the secondary in being alone essential to the con- ception of matter, as Locke and others assert ? (b.) Do the pri- mary qualities alone give us a knowledge of matter as it really is and as distinguished from a relative knowledge ? § 334. (a) Are the primary qualities alone essential to matter ? The primary qualities are essential to the conception of matter, so far as they are required and sufficient to define and distinguish this kind of being from every other. It is of course implied that such relations are always true of this kind of existence — that they are always present and never absent in a single individual. This being assumed, we have only to ask for a sufficient number of relations to serve the purposes of definition. It is obvious that for this purpose no other relations of matter are necessary than its relations to space. These are always present, and for the purposes of defining tha concept, matter, these only are required. It is contended that they are essential, and therefore primary, in another sense, viz., in being adequate as they exist in different forms and varieties to account for all the secondary qualities, so that color, taste, heat, electricity can all be resolved into the num- ber, position, and motion of homogeneous molecules. It is obvious however that this is not a logical, or psychological, or even a metaphysical problem, but one that is purely physical — a problem which can be solved by extensive observations of every species of matter and a more penetrating insight into its powers and laws than has yet been reached. Its solution must be left with the physicists, to whom it properly belongs. § 335. The second question, (b) involves the more nomenai d ^r comprehensive inquiry, 7s our knowledge of either fedge. ve kn ° w " matter or spirit real, or only phenomenal ? The real, in the language of recent philosophy, is opposed both to the phenomenal and the relative. It is used §335. SUBSTANCE AND ATTRIBUTE : MIND AND MATTER. 537 in the first connection by Kant, and in the second by Hamil- ton. We have seen that the knowledge of the primary qualities of matter is more direct than that of the secondary qualities, because to the apprehension of the latter the reflexive con- sideration of the soul as sentient and percipient is required. But the knowledge of the relations of matter, — as indeed of the mind, — in one se