Qass X^WW Book il- \ ■ J-y 'h A SYSTEM OF ETHICS .... And hence virtue would be, as it were, the health and beauty and harmony of the soul ; vice, however, disease and ugliness and weakness. Plato. .... Accordingly, the highest good of man consists in the exercise of the virtues and excellences of the soul, especially of the highest and most perfect. Aristotle. Virtue is nothing but action in accordance with one's own nature ; and there is nothing which excels it in dignity and worth. Spinoza. And therefore virtue is the good and vice the evil for every one. Shaftesbury. SYSTEM OF ETHICS BY FRIEDRICH PAULSEN PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF BERLIN IE often ano tftranslateti 1VITH THE AUTHOR'S SANCTION, FROM THE FOURTK REVISED AND ENLARGED EDITION BY FRANK THILLY FKOFE8SOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF MISSOURI CHARLES SCRIBNER'S SONS NEW YORK CHICAGO BOSTON -93 Copyright, 1899, by CHARLES SCRIBNER'S SONS Printed in the United States of America G bvM j OP ri TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE Of all the treatises on ethics that have appeared in recent years, none is, in my opinion, so admirably fitted for intro- ducing the beginner to this study as the remarkable work of Professor Paulsen which I here present to the English-speak- ing public in their native tongue. As the author expressly declares, the book was not written for philosophical experts, but for all those who are interested in the problems of prac- tical philosophy, and who are in need of some one to guide them in solving the same. It discusses the fundamental questions of ethics in a manner that cannot fail to attract the student and encourage him to reflect upon moral matters, which is, after all, the greatest service that any book can hope to render him. Many of our ethical treatises have a tendency to repel the average intelligent reader and to deaden instead of quickening his thought ; they make him feel that the subjects under discussion have absolutely no connection with life, at least, not with his life ; they often speak to him of things about which he knows nothing and cares less, in lan- guage which he cannot understand. This is a misfortune, for if any science has a message to deliver to the people of our country and age, it is certainly the science of conduct Professor Paulsen divides his work into four books. The first traces the historical development of the conceptions of life and moral philosophy from the times of the Greeks down to the present, and is one of the ablest and most fascinating surveys of the subject ever written. The second examines VI TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE the fundamental questions of ethics and answers them in a manner indicating the author's clearness of vision and soundness of judgment. The third, which is full of prac- tical wisdom, applies these principles to our daily conduct and defines the different virtues and duties. The fourth book is sociological and political in its nature, and deals with the "Forms of Social Life." The healthy common- sense pervading the entire work and its freedom from exag- gerations cannot but win the admiration of the reader. Owing to a desire on the part of the publishers not to in- crease the dimensions of this volume beyond a reasonable limit, I have translated only the first three of the books, leaving out, for the present, the " Umriss einer Staats- und Gesellschaf tslehre. " I have also omitted the seventh and eighth sections of the sixth chapter in Book III., which dis- cuss the duel, in order still further to diminish the size of the translation, and because, in my belief, the subject does not have the same interest for us Americans as for the Germans. My translation is from the fourth German edition which has been revised and increased. I have added notes and bibliographical references whenever they seemed desirable; they will be found in square brackets. In conclusion, I cannot refrain from expressing to Pro- fessor Paulsen my sincere thanks for the encouragement and help he has given me during the progress of this work. FRANK THILLY. Columbia, Mo., March, 189y, AUTHOR'S PREFACE TO THE AMERICAN EDITION In responding to the request of my friend Frank Thilly to speed this book on its journey, I feel impelled, first of all, to express to him my hearty thanks for his kindness in presenting my Ethics to his fellow-countrymen in their native tongue, a service which he has already performed for my Introduction to Philosophy. From my earliest youth I have had the feeling that a people closely akin to us dwelt beyond the ocean. This feeling was, perhaps, first aroused by the fact that not a few of the companions of my youth had found a new home on the other side ; in my native land, Schleswig-Holstein, from which the Anglo-Saxons once sailed westward over the sea, the migration to the West still continues. Since then the years have woven many new bonds of union. And so it is now a special source of pleasure to me, also, as an author, to come into closer contact with the great nation which has shown such remarkable energy in establishing itself in the new world. It is my earnest wish that this book may also contribute a little to strengthen the ties of spiritual fellowship unit- ing the two kindred peoples. We Germans well know, and gratefully confess, that no nation of the earth more deeply appreciates and more thoroughly understands the products of German thought than the United States of North America. FRIEDRICH PAULSEN. Berlin-Steglitz, September 27, 1898. PREFACE TO THE FIRST GERMAN EDITION Ich glaube nicht dass ich viel eignes neues lehre, Noch durch meiu ScherfLein Witz den Schatz der Weisheit mehre, Doch denk' ich von der Muh > mir zweierlei Gewinn ; Einmal, dass ich nun selbst an Einsicht weiter bin ; Sodann, dass doch dadurch an manchen Mann wird kommen Manches, wovon er sonst gar hatte nichts vernommen. Und auch der dritte Grund scheint wert nicht des Gelachters : Dass, wer dies Blichlein liest, derweil doch liest kein schlechters, — RUCKERT. FROM THE PREFACE TO THE SECOND GERMAN EDITION The second edition of this work, which has been so kindly received by a large circle of readers, embraces, in the main, the same contents as the first ; I have, however, so far as I was able, made improvements here and there. The second book, especially, has been worked over ; I hope that the fun- damental concepts have gained somewhat in definiteness, and that the entire treatment has been somewhat rounded out. Perhaps this will make it a little easier for some of the critics to understand the conception of life and its values on which my system is based. This new edition, however, is still open to the objection, which has been repeatedly urged against me, that the treat- ment of the fundamental questions is much less searching and thorough, while the questions of the day receive more attention than they deserve in a philosophical treatise. I have not been able to make up my mind to enter upon a more detailed discussion of the principles, because I do not believe that great prolixity in these matters will do any one much good. The philosophers, of course, have long ago worked out their own principles ; to the readers, however, who do not lay claim to this title, the significance and fitness of the funda- mental notions will be proved more easily by the ability of the latter to explain particular cases and to solve concrete prob- lems. I have been equally unwilling to ignore the questions which are moving our age ; the books that have nothing to say to their times, and therefore fill their pages with un- x FROM THE PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION timely logical quibbles, or with endless historical-critical discussions, are plentiful enough as it is, and there has, thus far, never been a lack of tiresome books in Germany. There are books that are timeless because they are written for all times; but there are also timeless books which are written for no time. This book does not belong to the first class, nor would it like to belong to the second. And now that I have begun to make confessions, let me confess further that this book was not written for philoso- phers at all ; God forbid that I should presume to think for people who are already overburdened with thoughts. I had in mind readers who have, in some way or other, been stimulated to meditate upon the problems of life, and are looking for some one to guide them, or, if that sounds too presumptuous, for some one to discuss these questions with them. Should any such take up this book and not lay it aside disappointed, the author's ambition will have been thoroughly realized. Besides, I do not believe that a new system of moral philosophy is either necessary or possible ; the great construc- tive principles have already been so thoroughly developed by Greek philosophy that they are, in the main, satisfactory even to-day. To bring the old truth into living touch with the ques- tions which preoccupy our age, is, in my opinion, the most important function of a modern ethics. Nor do I believe that I am mistaken in the assumption that this view is some- what widespread in our times. Perhaps there has never been so little disagreement concerning the problem and principles of moral philosophy since the days of Christian Wolff as exists at present. Let me here briefly outline the conception towards which the thought of the age seems to be tending; I call it the teleologicjil view. It is limited and defined by a double anti- thesis. On the one side, by hedonistic utilitarianism, which teaches that pleasure is the thing of absolute worth, to which virtue and morality are related as means. In opposition to FROM THE PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION xi this, teleological ethics contends that not the feeling of pleasure, but the objective content of life itself, which is experienced with pleasure, is the thing of worth. Pleasure is the form in which the subject becomes immediately aware of the object and its value, Intuitionalistic formalism is the other antithesis. This regards the observance of a system of a priori rules, of the moral laws, as the thing of absolute worth. In opposition to this, teleological ethics contends that the thing of absolute worth is not the observance of the moral laws, but the substance which is embraced in these formulas, the human historical life which fills the outline with an infinite wealth of manifold concrete forms ; that the moral laws exist for the sake of life, not life for the sake of the moral laws. This is the form which Aristotle, the founder of ethics as a systematic science, originally gave to it. This conception controlled the entire Greek thought, and modern ethics too adhered to it, until it was overthrown by Kant's great reaction in favor of a formalistic intuitionalism. Teleological ethics, however, at once found an eloquent and warm defender against formal moralism in Schiller, and in a certain sense Specula- tive Philosophy also returned to the old view. At present this science is again turning into the old channels under the influence of the modern biological conceptions. TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION Paob Nature and Function of Ethics 1 1. Definition (1) — 2. Position in the System of Sciences (1) — 8. Function (4) — 4. Method (6) — 5. Moral Law and Natural Law (13) — 6. Concept of Perfection (17) — 7. In what Sense Universal Validity may be Predicated of Morality (19) — 8. Practical Value of Ethics (25). BOOK I OUTLINE OF A HISTORY OF THE CONCEPTIONS OF LIFE AND MORAL PHILOSOPHY CHAPTER I The Conception op Life and Moral Philosophy among the Greeks S3 1. The Greek People's Conception of the Value of Life (35) — 2. Socrates (3 9)— 3. Plato (41) — 4. Aristotle (48)-— 5. Stoics (53) — 6. Epicureans (56) — 7. Common Characteristics of Greek Ethics (58). CHAPTER n The Christian Conception of Life 65 1. Christianity is Supernaturalistic (65) — 2. Its Contempt for Learn- ing (67) — 3. for the Natural Virtues (68) — 4. for Courage (69) — 5. for Justice (71) — 6. Its Relation to the State (72) — 7. to Enjoyment and Art (74) — 8. to Wealth (77) — 9. to Honor (78) — 10. Mercy, the Christian Virtue (81) — 11. Christianity aad xiv TABLE OF CONTENTS Page Family-Life (84) — 12. The Eternal Life (87)— 13. The Liberal- istic Conception of Christianity (89). CHAPTER III The Conversion of the Old World to Christianity ... 98 I. The Old World's Opinion of Christianity (98) — 2. Cause of the Change : Decline of Ancient Morality in the Roman Empire (100) — 3. The Moral Self-consciousness of the Imperial Period : Epic- tetus, Marcus Aurelius, Neo-Platonism (106) — 4. Craving for a Religion of Redemption (110) — 5. Superiority of Christianity (112) — 6. Analogous Development in the Hindoo World (113). CHAPTER IV The Middle Ages and their Conception of Life . . . .116 1. The Conversion of the Germanic Nations (116) — 2. Mood and Mode of Life (118) — 3. The Clergy (119) — 4. Historical Necessity on Part of the Church to Assimilate the World (121). CHAPTER V The Modern Conception of Life .... 126 1. Characteristics of the Modern Era (126) — 2. Renaissance (127) — 3. Reformation (129) — 4. The Love of Knowledge (135) — 5. Francis Bacon and his Dream of the Future (137) — 6. R. Des- cartes and his Programme of Civilization (140) — 7. The Modern Science of the State: Thomas Hobbes (143) — 8. Leibniz (144) — 9. The Self-satisfaction of the Modern Era (145) — 10. The Nineteenth Century : Pessimism, Nietzscheanism (147) — 11. Relation to Christianity (155). CHAPTER VI Mediaeval and Modern Moral Philosophy 169 1. Theological Moral Philosophy (169)— 2. Catholic Moral Theology (172) — 3. Modern Moral Philosophy; Thomas Hobbes (179) — 4. Spinoza (181) — 5. Shaftesbury (185) — 6. Hume, Bentham, Mill, Spencer (189) — 7. Leibniz, Wolff (193) — 8. Kant (194) — 9. Goethe, Schiller (201) — 10. Speculative Philosophy (203) — 11. Schleiermacher (205) — 12. Herbart (208) — 13. Scho- penhauer (209). TABLE OF CONTENTS XT BOOK II FUNDAMENTAL CONCEPTS AND QUESTIONS OF PRINCIPLE Paob Metaphysical and Psychological Introduction 219 CHAPTER I Good and Bad: Teleological and Formalistic Conceptions . 222 1. Possible Conceptions (222) — 2. The Teleological Conception (224) — 3. Subjective-formal and Objective-material Judgment (226) — 4. The End Justifies the Means (233) — 5. The Importance of the Particular Act (240) — 6. Provisional Repudiation of Egoism (243) — 7. Summary (248). CHAPTER II The Highest Good : Hedonistic and Energistic Conceptions . 251 1. Critique of Hedonism : Pleasure not the End of Action (251) — 2. A Modified Form of the Hedonistic Theory (258) — 3. Signifi- cance of Pleasure from the Biological Standpoint (264) — 4. Pleasure not the Criterion of Judgments of Value (268) — 5. Positive Definition of the Highest Good (270) — 6. Histor- ical Confirmation (273) — 7. Further Remarks (275) — 8. An Objection (283). CHAPTER III Pessimism 28? 1. Pessimism as a Mood and a Theory (287) — 2. Hedonistic Argu- ment (289) — 3. Moralistic Argument (297) — 4. The Historical- Philosophical Argument in the Hedonistic Sense (308) — 5. in the Moralistic Sense (314) — 6. Summary (318). CHAPTER IV The Evil, the Bad, and Theodicy 821 1. Theodicy (321)— 2. Physical Evil (322) — 3. Moral Evil (325) — 4. Consequences (332) — 5. Death (335). CHAPTER V Duty and Conscience 340 I. Origin of the Feeling of Duty (340) — 2. Relation between Duty and Inclination (346) — 3. Critique of the Kantian View (350) XVI TABLE OF CONTENTS Pa©« — 4. Further Errors of the A-prioristic-intuitionalistic Moral Phil- osophy (355) — 5. Conscience (363) — 6. Individualization of Conscience (368) — 7. Moral Nihilism (373) — 8. The Popular Usage of Language (377). CHAPTER VI Egoism and Altruism 379 1. No Absolute Opposition (379) — 2. The Effects of so-called Egoistic and Altruistic Acts (383) — 3. and their Motives Overlap (386) — 4. Our Judgment of Egoistic and Altruistic Acts (391) — 5. Relation to the Evolutionistic Theory (394). CHAPTER VII Virtue and Happiness 400 1. Effect of Conduct on Welfare (400) — 2. Effect of Welfare on Character (407). CHAPTER VIII Relation of Morality to Religion ... 415 1. Hiatorical Connection, its Causes and Effects (415) — 2. Neces- sary Inner Connection (421) — 3. Relation between Religion and Science (425) —4. Cause of Unbelief (433) — 5. The Belief in Immortality (439) — 6. Objections (446). CHAPTER IX The Freedom of the Will 452 1. Historical Orientation (452) — 2. Presentation of the Facts (457) — 3. Responsibility (460) — 4. The True Meaning of Human Free- dom (467). BOOK III THE DOCTRINE OF VIRTUES AND DUTIES CHAPTER I Virtues and Vices in General , . 475 CHAPTER II The Education of the Will and the Discipline of the Feelings, or Self-Control 483 1. Self-control (483) — 2. Temperance ; Asceticism (485) — 3. Mod- esty (491) — 4. Courage (495) — 5. Independence, Perseverance, Patience (498) — 6. Equanimity (500) — 7. Wisdom (503). TABLE OF CONTENTS xrii CHAPTER III Pag* Bodily Life 505 1. Its Purpose (505) — 2. Nourishment ; Drunkenness (506) — 3. Domicile, Clothing (515)— 4. Play and Work (519). CHAPTER IV Economic Life 529 1. Teleological Necessity of the Calling (529) — 2. Duty to the Com- munity (533) — 3. Avarice and Prodigality (536) — 4. Poverty and Wealth (540). CHAPTER V Spiritual Life and Culture 54S 1. Nature and Import of Knowledge (543) — 2. Culture, Super-cul- ture, Half-culture (547) — 3. Nature and Import of Art (556) — 4. Present Position of Art (559). CHAPTER VI Honor and the Love of Honor 569 1. Nature of Honor (569) — 2. Its Significance for Moral Develop- ment (571) — 3. The Love of Honor as Pride (573) — 4. The Love of Honor as Humility (576) — 5. Self-confidence and Self- knowledge (578)— -6. Modesty (581). CHAPTER VII Suicide 584 1. The Facts (584) — 2. How we Judge the Facts (586) — 3. The Causes (590). CHAPTER VIII Compassion and Benevolence 592 1. Compassion (592) — 2. Benevolence (599). CHAPTER IX Justice 599 1. Nature and Natural Foundation of Justice (599) — 2. Its Signi- ficance (602)— 3. Need of a Positive Legal Order (603) — 4. Punishment and the Right of Punishment (606) — 5. Duty to xriu TABLE OF CONTENTS Pag* Defend the Rights of Others and of Self (613) — 6. Magnanimity and Forgiveness (616) — 7. The Principle of Rights (624) — 8. Incongruity between Law and Morality; Necessary Wrongs (627) — 9. The Law Falls short of the Demands of Morality (633). CHAPTER X Love of Neighbor 688 1. Definition and Limitations of the Duty (638) — 2. Almsgiving (641) — 3. Selfishness (648) — 4. Significance of Love of Neighbor (652) — 5. Gratitude (655) — 6. Love of Home, of Country, of Humanity (656). CHAPTER XI Veracity 664 1. Negative Aspect: the Lie (664)— 2. Why Condemned (666) — 3. Calumny, Flattery, Hypocrisy, Perjury (669) — 4. Lie of Necessity (672) — 5. Why this Rigorism? (681) — 6. Positive Aspect: Veracity in Relation to the Individual (685) — 7. The Public Communication of the Truth (688) — 8. Why the New Truths are Persecuted (690) — 9. In how far this is Necessary (695) — 10. Is the Destruction of Error under all Circumstances a Duty ? (698). rNDEX . * , 8 ,.'..'• 711 INTRODUCTION — NATURE AND FUNCTION OF ETHICS 1. Ethics is, according to the Greek signification of the term, a science of customs or morals (Sitten). There are two forms of a scientific treatment of morals : the historical-anthropological and the practical. The first we find, for example, in Herodotus and in Herbert Spencer's Descriptive Sociology. It investigates and describes the cus- toms of different peoples and times ; we might call it etho- graphy. The second inquires into the worth of human customs and modes of behavior ; its object is to guide us in the proper conduct of life. The Greeks applied the term ethics to inves- tigations of the latter kind. It was Aristotle who gave to this science its name and systematic form. — The following introductory remarks will endeavor to define provisionally the nature of such a science. 2. All scientific discussions may be divided into two classes : theoretical and practical, theories and technologies, sciences proper and arts. The former aim at knowledge, the latter seek to control things by human action, they tell us how to make the world subservient to our purposes. According to the above definition, ethics belongs to the practical sciences ; its function is to show how human life as such must be fashioned to realize its purpose or end. Conse- quently, it stands at the head of the practical sciences, em- bracing them all in a certain measure, for all arts ultimately serve a common purpose : the perfection of human life. This is as true of the art of shipbuilding and commerce as of the art of education and government. Hence, the corresponding 2 INTRODUCTION arts are subordinated to ethics, the theory of the art of life, or included as its parts. All practical sciences are based on theories. They are merely the application of theoretical truths to the solution of practical problems. The theoretical science to which ethics bears this relation is the science of man, anthropology and psychology. Presupposing a knowledge of human nature and the conditions of human life, ethics undertakes to answer the question : What forms of social life and what modes of indi- vidual conduct are favorable or unfavorable to the perfection of human nature ? A comparison with another practical science will make the relation clear. The function of medi- cine is to teach men the physician's art ; and the object of this art is to aid the body in reaching its perfect development, to bring about favorable conditions, to ward off dangers, to remove disturbances ; dietetics and therapeutics together per- form this function. Physical anthropology forms the theoret- ical basis of medicine. We may, therefore, say : Ethics bears the same relation to general anthropology as medicine to physical anthropology. Based on the knowledge of corporeal nature, medicine instructs us to solve the problems of cor- poreal life, to the end that the body may perform all its func- tions in a healthy manner during its natural existence ; while ethics, basing itself on the knowledge of human nature in general, especially of its spiritual and social side, aims to solve all the problems of life so that it may reach' its fullest, most beautiful, and most perfect development. We might, therefore, call ethics universal dietetics, to which medicine and all the other technologies, like pedagogy, politics, etc., are related as special parts, or as auxiliary sciences. With this view the founder of systematic moral philosophy, Aris- totle, wholly agrees. A remark will not be out of place here. It is easy to see that the arts are not really new, independent sciences. Science deals with the nature of things. The fact that objects may NATURE AND FUNCTION OF ETHICS 3 be modified by our action does not constitute a special phage of their nature. Science might, therefore, confine itself to calling attention to this in occasional interspersed remarks ; physics might, for example, in discussing the subject of steam, add the following note : Such and such particular properties of gases enable us to utilize them as motors. The technolo- gies would thus be inserted into the theories as corollaries. If human beings were essentially theoretical beings, they might, perhaps, be satisfied with such a procedure. But such is not the case ; they are, rather, pre-eminently practical or volitional beings. The practical problems are earlier and more important than the theoretical problems. The sciences, we may say, without going far amiss, have been invented to solve problems ; knowledge is, at least in its first beginnings, a means to practical ends. Thus> anatomy and physiology are means to the art of healing ; geometry, as the name indicates, a means to the surveyor's art. Similarly, philosophy, or the universal theoretical science, owes its origin to the ques- tion concerning the meaning and object of life. Yes, we may go still farther and say : The ultimate motive impelling men to meditate upon the nature of the universe will always be the desire to reach some conclusion concerning the meaning, the source, and the goal of their own lives. The origin and end of all philosophy is consequently to be sought in ethics. The priority of the practical sciences is shown in a remark- able way by the form which scientific instruction has assumed on its highest stage. Our university sciences are absolutely governed by practical ends. The medical sciences do not really form a systematic science ; they are united by a prac- tical aim : the medical faculty is a technical training school for physicians. It draws all such theoretical sciences into the sphere of its instruction as it regards essential and useful to the technical training of its students. In this way, physiology and anatomy, which, in a classification based on purely theo- retical principles, would, of course, be grouped under the 4 INTRODUCTION natural sciences, under the title biology, came into the faculty of medicine. The same is true of jurisprudence and theology. Neither of these is a special, independent science ; the fac- ulties of law and theology are technical training schools, the former for judges and officials, the latter for preachers and spiritual advisers ; and whatever knowledge is required by the members of these professions, they draw upon and make sub- servient to their goal. A purely theoretical classification of the sciences would place all these subjects either under the head of history or philosophy. The question as to what was or is the law in any particular country belongs to history, as well as the question concerning the essence or the historical development of a particular religion. The question, however, concerning the nature of law in general and its significance for human conduct belongs to practical philosophy ; the question concerning the nature of God and the constitution of the uni- verse, to metaphysics. — We have here an illustration of the truth that knowledge exists for the sake of life, not life for the sake of knowledge. 3. Let me add a few further statements concerning the function and method of ethics. It has a double function to perform : to determine the end of life, or the highest good, and to point out the way, or the means, of realizing it. It is the business of the doctrine of goods {Guterlehre) to establish the goal, or the highest good. It will, to forestall the contents of a subsequent chapter, regard as the highest good, stating it in a general formula, a 'perfect life, that is, a life leading to the complete development of the bodily and mental powers and to their full exercise in all the spheres of human existence, in close communion with other closely related persons, and fully participating in the historical and spiritual life of society at large. The term welfare ( Wohl- fahrt) may also be employed to designate this goal, — which would suggest the subjective element involved in it, or the NATURE AND FUNCTION OF ETHICS 5 fact that such a life yields satisfaction ( Wohlgefuhl). Here, however, we must guard against the misconception that this feeling of satisfaction or pleasure is what gives life its real worth. The feeling is not the good, bat the form in which the good is known and enjoyed by the subject. The other function of ethics is to show by what inner quali- ties and modes of conduct the highest good, or the perfect life, is attained and realized. This problem is solved in the doctrine of virtues and the doctrine of duties (Tugend- und Pflichtenlehre). The doctrine of duties describes in general formulae how we must conduct ourselves in order successfully to solve the problems of life, that is, attain to perfection. The doctrine of virtues sets forth how we must fashion the character, or the will, in order to realize that goal : it makes clear to us that prudence, courage, justice, veracity, are quali- ties which enable us correctly to solve the problems of life, while their opposites, thoughtlessness, cowardice, and pleasure- seeking, inconsiderate selfishness and base mendacity, hinder the realization of the perfect life. Here, however, we must at once call attention to an im- portant fact. The means employed to realize the perfect life are not merely external, technical means, having no inde- pendent value, but they are at the same time parts of its con- tent. Just as the means of dietetics, work and exercise, rest and sleep, as functions of life, at the same time form constit- uents of bodily life, so the virtues and their exercise form the contents of the perfect life. Or, to use a different illus- tration : Each part in a good poem is a means of expressing and unfolding the whole, otherwise it would be a superfluous episode ; and, conversely, every means also necessarily forms a part of the poem itself and as such possesses its own poetic value. So, too, everything in moral life is both a means and a part of the end, something that exists for its own sake and for the sake of the whole. The virtues have absolute worth as phases of the perfect man, but they are at the same time 6 INTRODUCTION valuable as means, in so far as the perfect life is realized through them. In both cases, however, a difference may be noted. Not all the parts of a work of art have the same value when compared with the purpose underlying it, nor are the different virtues equally important as means of realizing the perfect life. Similarly, the different duties may be graded according to their importance. 4. Let us now inquire into the method of ethics. What is the source of its knowledge ? How does it prove the truth of its propositions ? It is customary to distinguish between empirical and ra- tional knowledge. The latter, of which mathematics is the prototype, deduces propositions from definitions and axioms, and demonstrates them logically ; that is, it shows that they follow as necessary consequences from the principles. Em- pirical sciences, on the other hand, like physics and chemistry, observe facts and reduce them to general formulae, which aim to express the uniformity in the behavior of things ; such formulas we call causal laws. The proof of the truth of these propositions does not consist in showing their logical connection with certain presupposed definitions, but in point- ing out that they adequately express an observed causal connection. It seems to me to be an indisputable fact that ethics resem- bles the natural sciences, rather than mathematics, in its method. It does not deduce and demonstrate propositions from concepts, but discovers the relations which exist be- tween facts, and which may be established by experience. Such and such a mode of conduct has such and such an effect ; that is the general form of its argument. Or, to state it in the converted form in which the causal connections are expressed in all practical or technical sciences : In order to produce or prevent such and such results, such and such means are necessary. Quod in contemplatione instar causae^ id in operatione instar regulae, says Bacon ; the causal law NATURE AND FUNCTION OF ETHICS 7 becomes a practical rule. But the correctness of the rule is proved by the causal connection ; and causal connections are ascertained by experience alone. Experience proves that cleanliness, exercise, fresh air, are means of preserving health. So, too, experience proves that prudent and rational conduct, a regular vocation, a well-ordered family life, are conducive to life ; and that indolence, shiftlessness, dis- honesty, and malice have the tendency to make life miser- able and to destroy it. The rationalistic view denies to ethics its empirical char- acter. It claims that propositions of morals are neither cap- able nor in need of empirical proof. It regards them as the expressions of an innate faculty, conscience, or practical reason, which judges and legislates a priori. It asserts that everybody knows what is right or wrong without any expe- rience. Experience decides what is advantageous or disad- vantageous in its effects, but everybody knows before all experience what is good or bad, and no experience of what human beings really do or what may be the actual effects of their action can place in doubt or correct this immediate knowledge of what they ought to do. Our answer is : It is indeed true that mankind did not await the coming of moral philosophy in order to distinguish between good and bad. Morality is older than moral philos- ophy, and there could be no moral philosophy without morality as its presupposition. It arises as the reflection on an exist- ing positive morality, which governs life and judgment, and which is not destroyed or made superfluous by its appearance. It is also true that something like an inner voice speaks to the individual : You ought to do this, you must not do that ! and that too without any reasons, in the form of an uncon- ditional imperative. This inner voice we call conscience. We shall recur to the anthropological explanation and teleo- logical interpretation of these things later on. Here, how- ever, I should like to show that it does not follow from this 8 INTRODUCTION that moral philosophy must be an a-prioristic or rational science. Let the science of dietetics again serve as an illus- tration to explain our meaning. What was said of the moral conduct of life may also be applied to bodily life. Just as men did not await the coming of moral philosophy before distinguishing between good and bad, they did not wait for the appearance of the science of dietetics in order to distinguish between the wholesome and the unwholesome. Long before medicine or any science existed, hungry men ate, the thirsty quenched their thirst, and the shivering covered themselves with skins. The ques- tion : Why do they do this, why is bread good for the hungry, and water for the thirsty ? would have seemed as strange to them as the question : Why is stealing wrong ? seems to our schoolboys. It is self-evident ; no other reason can be given for it. Here, as everywhere else, scientific investigation begins by regarding everything that has previously been accepted as self-evident, as a problem. After men had lived for untold ages according to the absolute imperatives of a naturalistic dietetics and an equally naturalistic therapeutics, which continue even to this day in the prescriptions or abso- lute imperatives of popular dietetics and medicine, what we call scientific medicine arose. Slowly and gradually, by means of observation and experiment, we have come to un- derstand the organization of the body and its relation to the external conditions of life, and have thus been gradually en- abled to prove the appropriateness of methods and cures which have long been practised, and to eliminate useless or harmful ones, and to employ new ones in their stead. Moral philosophy occupies a similar position. It, too, is confronted with a naturalistic, unscientific, traditional moral- ity. Just as bodily life was originally governed by instincts and blind habits, without physiology, so the entire human life, especially social life, was originally governed without science, by a kind of moral instincts, These moral instincts NATURE AND FUNCTION OF ETHICS 9 of peoples are called customs (Sitten). I employ this term to designate all those obligatory habits and forms of life, all those customs and laws, which uniformly govern the life of every member of a community. Like the dietetic rules, these customs appear in the consciousness of the individual in the form of absolute commands, which assign no reason for their validity. Thou shalt not kill, rob, or defraud a member of thy tribe,- — so conscience speaks, without grounds and conditions ; to do so is bad : that is a self-evident truth, just like the truth that fire burns, and bread satisfies hunger. Is this truth really incapable of proof, can moral philosophy do nothing but collect and arrange these absolute commands and prohibitions ? To say so is to deprive it of its character as a science, for science does not consist in taking inventories, but in the discovery and proof of truths. But such is not the case. The truths of popular morality themselves suggest a different answer ; they also appear in another form, namely in the form of proverbs : Pride goeth before a fall ; Lies are short-lived ; Honesty is the best policy ; A house divided against itself cannot stand. Here the imperative appears in the form of an assertion, one in which the reason is implied : Do not lie, for lies are short-lived ; Do not cheat, for ill-gotten gains do not prosper. And this suggests to us the real func- tion of a philosophy of morals. It must unfold in detail the reasons, which are simply implied in popular morality, for the different value of the different modes of conduct. Like the science of dietetics, it must show that certain modes of conduct which have been followed instinctively for a long time, are suited to the nature and conditions of human life, and are therefore beneficial, while others are injurious and pernicious. It will show, for example, that it lies in the very nature of falsehood to injure the deceiver, the person deceived, and the entire community which is united by the ties of language, by destroying confidence and thereby undermining the founda- tion of social life, without which real human life is not pos« 10 INTRODUCTION sible. It will show that stealing disturbs the economic life of the injured party, and almost necessarily utterly destroys that of the thief, and, finally, that it endangers the life of the entire community by making property insecure, which is the inevitable effect of theft, and thereby undermines the founda- tions of civilization and all human life. In this way, moral philosophy changes instinctive custom into conscious purpos- iveness. But it may possibly do more than this. Just as medical dietetics does not merely explain, but rectifies the rules of natural dietetics, so moral philosophy does not merely justify the injunctions of natural morality, but also supplements and corrects them. Thus it may, for example, in giving the rea- sons for a rule, at the same time define the limits within which it holds. In explaining the perniciousness of false- hood, it at the same time helps us to decide when wilful deception may be allowable and necessary. It solves the problem of the so-called lie of necessity, which so strangely confuses common-sense (as well as many moralists). By showing why it is good to forgive injuries, it at the same time determines under what conditions alone forgiveness is possible, and under what conditions retaliation is necessary. Naturalistic morality with its absolute imperatives leaves us entirely in the lurch in complicated cases ; it leaves it to the individual's own instinct or to his tact, as it is usu- ally called, to settle the point. Moral philosophy cannot make tact superfluous ; particular decisions, based upon con- crete circumstances, must always be left to tact ; but it may lay down rules for the guidance of tact which will accomplish more than these absolute imperatives. Such is the method of ethics in the doctrine of virtues and duties. It explains its propositions teleologically and caus- ally : in order to reach such and such a goal, such and such behavior is necessary. But what about the knowledge of the goal itself? From what source does ethics derive the know!- NATURE AND FUNCTION OF ETHICS 11 edge of the perfect life ; how does it prove that its definition of the highest good is correct ? Here the case is somewhat different. We may say : The nature of the highest good is in reality not determined by the intellect, but by the will. The individual has an idea of the conduct of his individual life, a life-ideal, the realization of which he feels to be his true function as well as the highest goal of his desires. It is really not the intellect from which this ideal springs, although it appears in the form of an idea ; its excellence cannot be proved to the reason ; it is nothing but the reflection of the innermost essence and the will of the individual himself in ideation. If other individuals have different ideals, I cannot prove to them the inadequacy of their ideals either by logical demonstrations or by empirical causal investigations. I may, perhaps, make them feel the value of my ideal by the mere revelation and description of it ; indeed, I may convince them that mine has greater value than theirs, and thus win them over to mine. Nevertheless, it is not the understanding, but the will which impels them to de- cide in its favor. The intellect as such knows absolutely noth- ing of values, it distinguishes between the true and the false. the real and unreal, but not between the good and the bad. Earlier ethics frequently discussed the question whether rea- son or feeling was the source of moral knowledge. We shall say that both are involved. The question : What is a good life, will in the last analysis be decided by immediate, incontro- vertible feeling, in which the innermost essence of the being manifests itself. It is as impossible to force a man by logical proofs to love and admire an ideal of life as it is to make his tongue feel the sweetness or bitterness of a particular fruit. We can arouse such feelings only by showing that an object possesses the qualities which originally produced them in him, owing to his nature. And to a certain extent, a person's taste for the goods of life may be changed by habit, as his taste for certain foods may be changed. In that case^ 12 INTRODUCTION however, the change depends on the internal modification of the nature of the being. But we may, when once the conception of the highest good is established, make clear to the intellect that such or such means are beneficial or injurious to its realization. It will not, therefore, be possible to give a scientific defini- tion of the highest good, which shall be valid for all, — one, that is, which we can force every individual by logical proofs to accept ; or, at least, it will be possible only in so far as the will itself is fundamentally the same in all individuals. And we may, considering the far-reaching similarity of the powers and the conditions of life, assume that this is, in a certain de- gree, actually the case. Just as all the members of an animal species, on the whole, desire to perform the same functions, so we shall find a certain similarity of ends or aims in the human species. It would be the business of a kind of natural- historical investigation to discover such a uniform goal. It would have to be shown, in the most general formulae, what men actually desire as the highest good, or the perfect life. The purpose of the moralist would here be identical with that of the biologist : he would be obliged not to prescribe the goal of life, but to discover it. Should he, however, succeed in discovering a universal end of life, he could not, of course, refuse to designate individuals absolutely deviating from the goal, or having differently -fashioned wills (if there should be such), as abnormal forms. As is well known, there are per- verse sexual impulses. Although it is impossible to prove to those who are so afflicted that their impulses are perverse — they say : Impulses are facts ; your impulse, tending as it does, is no more and no less a mere fact than ours — the physiologist is convinced that it is abnormal, and the person so afflicted can be clearly made to see that he is an exception, and that life would not be possible if the perversity were the rule. The same reasoning applies to an abnormal will. A man, for example, who is sensitive only to sensual impressions, NATURE AND FUNCTION OF ETHICS 13 say, to those of the palate, and has absolutely no appreciation of the other pleasures, the pleasures which spring from perception and knowledge, the exercise of powers, or is totally indifferent to the weal and woe of his human surroundings or uniformly enjoys their sufferings : such a being we should regard as an abnormal form, and we should not hesitate to call him per- verse, even though we could not convince him of the correct- ness of our condemnatory judgment. And it is quite possible that he would not even grant that his nature was abnormal, that is, a deviation from the average, nay, he might assert that could we but look beneath the outward appearances we should find that all others thought and felt as he did. 5. Let me here add a remark concerning the relation of moral laws to natural laws. Natural laws are formulas which express the constant uniformity of natural occurrences. In the narrower sense of the term, the concept is interpreted to mean an absolute uniformity, one admitting of no exceptions. Thus, physics assumes that the law of gravitation is an exact mathematical expression of the uniform reciprocal action of all masses in the universe. In this sense, the law of causality itself is conceived as a strictly universal natural law. In a wider sense, however, we also designate as natural laws such uniform occurrences in nature as are not absolutely, but rela- tively constant. The laws of biology for the most part belong to this class ; for example, the laws which express the uniformity of structure and function of an animal or plant species. In this sense, we may evidently call the propositions of medical dietetics natural laws : As a rule such and such a method of procedure reacts upon the body in such and such a way ; Cold water ablutions harden the skin and the entire organism against changes in temperature ; The exercise of the mus- cular and nervous systems leads to an increase in strength and skill, while organs which are not used decay ; Opium and alcohol have such and such direct and such and such indi- rect effects upon the organism. All these are uniformities 14 INTRODUCTION which cannot be determined with mathematical exactness, and which, owing to the complexity of vital processes, do not appear with the same constant regularity as those de- scribed by physics, but nevertheless they express universal and regular tendencies. In the same sense, we may call the propositions of ethics natural laws : they, too, express the constant connections existing between modes of conduct and their effects upon life. Falsehood has the tendency to produce distrust ; dis- trust has the tendency to disturb and destroy human social life : these are generalizations of the same kind as the asser- tion that alcohol tends to impair consciousness. The proposi- tion : Idleness weakens the powers of the understanding and the will, is nothing but a universal biological law, translated into psychological language. The objection is urged : The propositions of ethics or the moral laws declare what ought to be, and not what is, as do the natural laws. Thou shalt not lie, is a law of morality, one that is universally valid in spite of all the deviations of reality. The moral laws, it is held, are closely related to the laws on the statute books, not to the laws of nature. ■— They are certainly related to these ; nay, perhaps we may say that the statutes merely represent a section of the moral law. But that does not hinder them from being related to natural laws. The statutory laws undoubtedly express what ought to be, and there are exceptions to them in actual practice. Still these are but exceptions ; as a rule, the law is an expression of the actual behavior of the citizens ; we should surely not reckon among the laws of the state a law that is universally violated. It is a real law, not because it is printed on a piece of paper, but because it is an expression of the uniformity of action, even though this uniformity be not absolute. Moreover, although the law of the state has its origin in the will of man, it is, in the last analysis, based upon the nature of things, upon the causal connections exist- NATURE AND FUNCTION OF ETHICS 1& ing between modes of conduct and their effects upon life. Thou shalt not commit forgery, shalt not steal, shalt not com- mit arson, or, as the law declares : Whoever forges, steals, or commits arson, shall receive such and such punishment : this law owes its origin to the fact that such acts have injur- ious effects upon society. Stealing has the tendency to undermine property rights, forgery has the tendency to undermine credit, and consequently to interfere with the pro- duction and distribution of commodities. This natural law is the ultimate ground of the statutory law ; the statutory law is a rule of conduct for the members of a community whose aim is the security of the conditions of social life. The same remarks apply to the moral law. A moral law declares not only what ought to be, but what is. The historian of civilization will undoubtedly declare : It is an expression of the relatively uniform behavior of the members of the group who acknowledge its validity, and it is, at all events, a principle according to which acts are universally judged. If falsehood were as common among a people as truth-telling, if falsehood were not judged differently from veracity, there would be no moral law on the subject. And should a moralist come to such a community and say : But it is an absolute law that you should not lie, he would be told : We don't understand you, and will not be bothered by your whims ! There is, of course, no such a people, not because falsehood ought not to be, but because it cannot be a universal mode of conduct. Falsehood can occur only as an exception : that is a law of nature, not a logical, but a psychological law. Lying presupposes faith in human speech, and such trust can exist only where truth- telling is the rule. And when this uniform relation between truth and confidence, falsehood and distrust, becomes fixed in conduct and finally also in consciousness, the moral law is formulated : Thou shalt not lie. The causal law forms the basis of the practical rule, in morals as well as in jurispru- dence and medicine. If there were no uniform connections 16 INTRODUCTION between causes and effects, between acts and individual and social life, there would be no moral laws. The moral law is not the product of caprice, not the arbitrary command of a transcendent despot or of an uncontrollable " inner voice," but the expression of an immanent law of human life. Human life, that is, a life with a human mental-historical content, is possible only where all individuals act with relative uniformity, in accordance with the laws of morality, hence where the moral law has the validity of a biological law. Deviations from the moral law have the tendency to produce disturbances in indi- vidual and social life ; absolute violation of the moral law would lead, first, to the destruction of human historical life, and finally also to the destruction of its animal existence. Perhaps a comparison with the laws of grammar will eluci- date the formal character of the moral laws. It is popularly supposed that the laws of grammar declare what ought to be : grammar prescribes the way in which we ought to speak. The history of language regards grammar in a different light : grammar does not prescribe the ways in which we ought to speak, but describes the ways in which we do speak. The grammarian of Gothic or Middle High German collects and describes the forms which were actually used in the past ; the paleontologist collects and describes extinct forms of life; and the grammarian of the living language does the same. But a peculiar fact is observed here. There is a difference in the language of different persons, of different writers. True, we find great uniformity, at least in the general plan of the language, in the declensions and conjugations, but even here we find exceptions, especially in the spoken word. This compels the grammarian, whose real aim is to describe the language, to choose between different forms, in order to reach universal propositions. He will be guided in his choice, either by the frequency of their occurrence or by his estimate of the linguistic powers of the writers. Certain forms are declared to be the normal ones, and grammar, therefore, NATURE AND FUNCTION OF ETHICS 17 becomes a normative science after all : it decides what is correct and what is incorrect. This procedure, however, it must be confessed, is ultimately governed by teleological necessity : the purpose of the language is to communicate thoughts; deviations make this impossible, and they are therefore eliminated as disturbing elements. In the same way, popular thought regards it as the func- tion of moral philosophy to prescribe laws. But anthropology and history have a different conception of the problem. The primary aim is not to prescribe what men ought to do, and according to what principles they ought to judge, but to describe and understand the ways in which they really act and live. And to understand them means to understand the teleological necessity of their customs, laws, and institutions. Hence, here as before, a descriptive and explanatory science becomes a normative science : its propositions become prin- ciples of judgment and rules of conduct, in so far as they represent the conditions of human welfare. 1 6. Let me now make a few more statements concerning the function of ethics to define the highest good. In sec- tion 3 we used the term perfection. A perfect human life, that is, a life in which all the bodily and mental powers of man are fully developed and exercised, is the highest good for the individual. We shall have to discuss the material phase of this definition in detail later on. Here I shall simply enter upon a brief consideration of its formal side. It has been said that this is a purely formal, empty definition, which may be filled with any concrete content whatsoever. As compared with this conception, the definiteness of other views, for instance, that pleasure is the absolute good, has 1 Schleiermacher, whose entire ethics rests upon a parallelism between ethics and physics, the moral law and the natural law, discusses the difference between natural law and moral law in an academic treatise of the year 1825. (Complete Works, 3d Division, vol. II., p. 397.) Compare also F. J. Neumann, Natural Law and Economic Law (in tho Zeitschrift fir die gesamt. Staatsw., 1892, number 3) t and Eucken, Fundamental Concepts of the Present, 2d ed., 1893, pp. I73ff. a 18 INTRODUCTION been extolled. When we speak of pleasure, it has been claimed, we know what we are talking about. I shall have to defer the discussion of hedonism to a later time. Here, however, I should like to show that it is utterly impossible to give anything but a formal explanation of the highest good. Medical dietetics does not give us a concrete exposition of the perfect bodily life, but only a general outline, which may be filled in in many different ways. Similarly, ethics can give only a schematic outline of a mode of life, the observance of which does not necessarily make a life valuable, although it is the presupposition of the healthy development of life. The value of such a life depends upon the number of con- crete elements which it contains, and no system of ethics, not even the hedonistic, can undertake to describe them. The following illustration will make our meaning clear. We cannot speak of one perfect life. A people or a race con- sisting of totally similar copies of a perfect original pattern would strike us as an infinitely poor and empty affair. Nay, the very thought of such a thing is horrible. Imagine a mul- titude of human beings wholly alike as to their inner nature and life, differing from each other only in the numbers at- tached to them. Perfection consists, not in the similarity, but in the variety of forms. In order to give a concrete representa- tion of the perfect life, we should have to take our ideal of humanity, and show what different forms of human life are possible or necessary to realize the idea ; that is, we should have to describe a multitude of nations, tribes, families, in- dividuals, and the modes of life necessarily resulting from their natural endowments. This would be the function of an artistic or creative philosophy of history ; manifestly an im- possible task. Indeed, it is not even possible to deduce the past life of humanity, which history reveals to us, with its multitudes of peoples and its historical development, from an idea of humanity ; much less to outline the future historv and its new forms. NATURE AND FUNCTION OF ETHICS 19 No one expects cesthetics to represent beauty in the con- crete, that is, to deduce all the real and possible beautiful pictures, statues, poems, and musical compositions from an idea of the beautiful. The production of concrete beauty is the business of the genius. ^Esthetics reflects upon the products of genius, it aims to express in general formulae the conditions upon which the products depend, or at least without which they cannot arise. It cannot, that is to say, propose concrete problems to the future artist, but it can assist him in gaining an insight into his art and avoiding mistakes. The same may be said of ethics ; it does not describe every possible form of good life — this the moral genius evolves out of the fulness of his nature — but under- takes to describe and to justify the rules of conduct without which a good and beautiful life cannot be realized. And ethics, too, may indulge in the hope that it can, in a measure, guide the student in discovering his peculiar life's task, and guard him against error in his attempts to solve it. 7. It further follows from the above that there can be no universal morality in the concrete. The different expressions of the universal type of man demand each its own particular morality. The Englishman differs from the Chinaman and negro, and desires and ought to differ from them. Conse- quently, each one among them has a different morality. It is an undoubted fact that every nation has its own particular ideal of life and its own morality. The only question is whether " what is " " ought to be." It is absolutely essential, so it is claimed, that the propositions of morality be valid for all mankind or, in the words of Kant, " for all rational crea- tures." If we admit that there is a different code of morals for Englishmen and negroes, then shall we not have to con- clude that there is a different code for men and women, for artists and merchants, and, finally, also, one for each par- ticular man ? Indeed, the conclusion is a logical one. But I do not see 20 INTRODUCTION how we can avoid it if once we grant and insist upon the assertion that differences in life are not only not an evil, but essential conditions of the perfection of mankind. If we jus- tify the different forms of human life, we shall also have to justify the different rules of conduct. Just as the dietetics of the Englishman naturally differs from that of the negro, his morality, which, according to our conception, is merely a universal dietetics, must differ from his. We shall, there- fore, be compelled to say that a mode of conduct which is suitable and essential to the former need not be so to the latter. And we find not only that the Englishman actually treats the negro differently from one of his own countrymen, but that his relations to the negro are governed by an en- tirely different code of morality ; all of which does not mean, of course, that I am willing to justify the atrocities which have been and are still being committed every day against the savages in the name of civilization, by Europeans — alas, now also by the Germans. Only in a limited sense can we speak of a universal moral- ity. In so far, namely, as there are certain fundamental sim- ilarities in the nature and life-conditions of all human beings, in so far will there be certain universally valid fundamental conditions of healthy life. Thus medical dietetics may present certain fundamental rules as universal truths : A certain amount of food, consisting, say, of such and such substances, albumen, fats, carbo-hydrates, water, etc., furthermore, a cer- tain amount of work and rest is necessary to the preservation of bodily life. In the same sense, morality can advance uni- versal propositions : The preservation of human life demands that some attention be given to the care of offspring and the rearing of the young ; and in order that this end may be reached the sexes must live together in some permanent form. Or : A tribe cannot exist without some regulations tending to hinder hostilities among its members ; the infraction of such rules tends to breed ruin ; hence, murder, adultery, theft, NATURE AND FUNCTION OF ETHICS 21 and perjury are bad ; justice, benevolence, and veracity, the inner dispositions of the will which prevent such acts, are good. But in order that such universal rules may be directly applied, life must be adapted to the particular nature and the particular conditions surrounding it. The dietetic rule of nourishment mentioned above does not mean the same for the Esquimau as for the negro. Similarly, the rules of a universal human morality must be adapted to the special historical forms and conditions of life before they can be directly employed in determining and judging conduct. The commandment : Treat your neighbor justly and kindly, observe the rules of family and social life, does not mean the same for an African negro as for a European Christian. That monogamy is the best form of family life for a civil- ized nation does not prove that it is the best form for the entirely different conditions governing the negro tribe. We may say with perfect justice that monogamy is the higher form of family life. But that simply means that it is suitable to the higher stages of development and not that it is wrong for the lower stages to have a different form. Perhaps polyg- amy is a necessary stage in the development of the family, just as blood-revenge is a necessary stage in the development of law, and slavery in the development of society. This implies also that different times have different moral codes. That it is so is an indisputable fact, but it is hard to convince common-sense that it must be so, that it is not necessarily a sign of imperfection and perversion for an earlier age to have other customs, different acts and judg- ments, than the present. We are inclined to think that what- ever differs from our customs is all wrong. We blame the Middle Ages for burning heretics and witches, torturing sus- pects and killing criminals by the thousands. We are right in calling their methods brutal and barbarous. This, how- ever, does not prove that a brutal age did wrong in employ- 22 INTRODUCTION ing them. Perhaps it did ; perhaps, at least, these methods were frequently abused, but perhaps, on the other hand — proof, of course, is impossible from the very nature of the case — this method of procedure was suitable and necessary in that age. Perhaps the disciplining of human souls by the church was so necessary a precondition of civilization, that the Middle Ages stand justified before the tribunal of history, for suppressing, with all the means at their command, every attempt of the individual to emancipate himself from this discipline (which was the usual object of heresy). Per- haps the entire administration of justice of those days, with its brutal methods, was at least a temporarily necessary pre- condition of the complicated social life of the mediaeval towns. It is consoling that our courts and police are more efficient, and attain the same or better results by means of more humane methods, but this does not prove that the Mid- dle Ages could have preserved the peace in the same way. The Middle Ages might make the following answer to our charges : You owe it to us that you are now able to get along with such mild punishments ; it has taken us centuries of hard work to eradicate the elements which absolutely refused to adapt themselves to social order. To be sure, this was no agreeable task; but now that it is accomplished, it is not fair of you to censure us for having undertaken it. Besides, who knows how long your methods will prove successful ? And now we shall have to go still further and say : Even different groups of the same nation, and, finally, also, different individuals are subject to a special moral code. Different dispositions and life-conditions demand not only a different bodily, but also a different spiritual and moral diet. What is beneficial and necessary to one may be un- suitable and injurious to another. We are never in doubt about this fact when it comes to actual practice. We disap- prove and censure one man for something that we consider permissible or lovable in another. Indeed, we may say that NATURE AND FUNCTION OF ETHICS 23 it is not possible for different individuals to act exactly in the same way. If it is true that the entire nature of the agent manifests itself in every act — and we may say that it is characteristic of real human action to express not merely a particular phase of man's nature, but the whole will, the entire man — then every impulse and every act, every word and every judgment, bears the stamp of this particular indi- vidual. Conduct is only outwardly alike ; on the inner and the essential side the individuality asserts itself, and that is not a defect, but a mark of perfection. Only where true morality begins to disappear, where it approaches the domain of law, does the demand still hold that a man act, outwardly at least, according to rule. As Schiller's epigram puts it: Gern erlassen wir dir die moralische Delikatesse, Wenn du die zehen Gebote notdiirftig erfiillst. We must remember, however, that there is a reason why the moral preacher should emphasize the universality of the moral laws rather than the individuality of morality. Nature and inclination will take care that the individual receives his rights; whereas submission to a general rule is not to his taste. Indeed, the individual is very apt to demand that an exception be made in his case, on the ground of his special nature and circumstances, his temperament and his social position, and to excuse his conduct before others and before his own conscience, without, however, being justified from the standpoint of higher morality. Kant's rigorism is entirely in place against the inclinations of the natural man. The main thing is that the sensuous will be subordinated to universal law. This is the beginning, the foundation, of all finer, more individualized morality. The latter is, in the words of the Gospel, not the " destruction " of the law, but the " fulfilment "• (jrXrjptoais) of the law. Nor, as has already been said, can morality tell the individual in what the fulfilment consists. All it can do is to lay down general rules, leaving it to the 24 INTRODUCTION conscience and to the wisdom of the individual to adapt these to special conditions. When, however, he needs guidance in these matters, he will seek the help of a personal counsellor, a spiritual adviser, who is, perhaps, as necessary as is a medical adviser for the body. For, surely, the relations of moral life are no less complicated, its problems no less difficult, its needs no less serious, its disturbances no less menacing, than those of bodily life. Here as well as in the latter case we have a confusing mixture of inclination and aversion, fear and hope. All this seemed self-evident to an earlier age ; nothing seemed more necessary than to place the individual under the official care of a wise and experienced moral and spiritual adviser, leaving it to custom and individual instinct to care for the body. Is the present increase of physicians and the corresponding relative decrease of spiritual advisers a sign that we are more solicitous of the body than of the soul ? Or are we in hopes of influencing the soul by means of the body ? Or is it because the task of caring for the soul is becoming more difficult in consequence of the growing differentiation of thought and feeling, and because our faith in its accomplish- ment is waning ? The fact remains, on the other hand, that the rules of moral philosophy are not absolutely valid for all. We may, as was said, conceive of a universal human morality, or even of a morality for all rational creatures, but no one is able to realize it. The moral philosopher is a child of his people in thought and feelings, and is influenced by their morality; positively, for he has been moulded by their judgments and ideals from the days of his childhood ; negatively, for his no- tions of what ought not to be and his ideas of what ought to be are conditioned by his times. The abstract rationalism of the eighteenth century did not appreciate this truth, which Kant, too, failed to observe. The historical century, as the nine- teenth century might be called in contradistinction from the eighteenth, the sosculum philosophicum, no longer finds it NATURE AND FUNCTION OF ETHICS 25 possible to believe in the "universal man." Every moral philosophy is, therefore, valid only for the sphere of civiliza- tion from which it springs, whether it is conscious of the fact or not. It can have no other aim than to draw the general outlines of a mode of life which must be followed by the members of the particular sphere, in order to make possible a healthy, virtuous, and happy existence. 8. In conclusion, let me say a word concerning the practi- cal value of ethics. Can ethics be a practical science, not only in the sense that it deals with practice, but that it influences practice ? This was its original purpose. It is the function of ethics, says Aristotle, to act, not only to theorize. Scho- penhauer begins his ethics (in the fourth book of his main work) with the attempt to disprove this view. All philosophy, he says, is theoretical ; upon mature reflection, it ought finally to abandon the old demand that it become practical, guide action, and transform character, for here it is not dead concepts that decide, but the innermost essence of the human being, the demon that guides him. It is as impossible to teach virtue as it is to teach genius. It would be as foolish to ex- pect our moral systems to produce virtuous characters and saints as to expect the science of aesthetics to bring forth poets, sculptors, and musicians. I do not believe that ethics need be so faint-hearted. Its first object, it is true, is to understand human strivings and modes of conduct, conditions and institutions, as well as their effects upon individual and social life. But if knowledge is capable of influencing conduct — which Schopenhauer him- self would not deny — it is hard to understand why the knowledge of ethics alone should be fruitless in this respect. If a physician can by pointing out the causal relation existing between cleanliness and health, between the excessive use of alcohol or nicotine and the derangement of the nervous system, induce a mother to use water more freely, or a young man to be moderate, why should not a moralist have a right 26 INTRODUCTION to hope that the discovery of similar causal connections exist- ing between conduct and the form of life will influence con- duct ? If he can make clear that dissipation, indolence, anger, envy, falsehood, inconsiderateness, produce certain disturb- ances in life, while prudence, politeness, modesty, upright- ness, amiability, tend to produce good effects on the life of the individual and that of his surroundings, why should not such knowledge also influence the will ? Or shall we assume that everybody is perfectly well aware that the former modes of conduct are good and the latter bad, and that we need not wait for ethics to tell us these things ? And does experience really show that knowledge is unable to turn the will in the direction of the good ; is Schopenhauer right in saying, velle non discitur f — If so, I believe it is not the right kind of knowledge. A real insight, which, of course, does not consist merely in memorizing and rattling off a lot of formulas and maxims, is bound to be as fruitful here as everywhere else. To be sure, we cannot expect such an insight to determine the will absolutely. Natural capacities, education, habit, example, praise and censure, the admiration and contempt of our sur- roundings, and other things, play their part. But knowledge, too, is a factor and a very important factor with the wise — by whom we do not necessarily mean the learned. But as for Schopenhauer's dogma that the will is something abso- lutely fixed in every life, I am inclined to regard it as one of the articles of superstition of which there is no dearth in Schopenhauer's teaching. There is no such rigid, constant will, not even in the narrower sense in which Schopenhauer uses the term : that the relation between egoism and altru- ism is unalterably determined at birth in the case of every individual. Moral instruction, however, can have no practical effect unless there be some agreement concerning the nature of the final goal — not a mere verbal agreement, to be sure, but one based upon actual feeling. It would be futile for a physician NATURE AND FUNCTION OF ETHICS 27 to advise a man who does not care for health and bodily welfare to do certain things and to abstain from others. Similarly, it would be useless for a moral philosopher to recommend moderation and prudence to one whose notion of a " good life " is a few years of excitement and dissipa- tion, and then a bullet through the brain. Or perhaps it would not be all in vain. Who knows but what he might finally succeed in convincing such a person that he was mistaken about himself and his will, and his conception of the highest good ; who knows but what more careful reflection might show him that such a life cannot be good and the final goal of his own will ? We can hardly deny that conversions have actually taken place. Shall we say that moral preach- ing alone can produce these results, and that moral philosophy cannot ? Well, I do not know whether it is possible to draw a sharp line of separation between them. The preacher can scarcely hope to influence any one without appealing to his insight. And why should not the impartial presentation of the relations existing between conduct and welfare prove to be an effective sermon, even though — or rather let us say, just because — it does not assume the form of moralizing exhortation ? But should any one still hold the view that moral philoso- phy is not only fruitless, but dangerous and harmful, on the ground that the forces regulating life, custom and conscience, are weakened by speculations concerning their origin, import, and validity, we should reply : In the first place, such reflec- tions are not produced by philosophy, but, conversely, philoso- phy is produced by these inevitable reflections. Reflection on human conduct and judgment is inevitable. Whenever there is any controversy concerning a concrete case, concerning the Tightness or wrongness of an act, a judgment, or an institu- tion, we are compelled to go back to principles which will decide the case. Moral philosophy is nothing but a radical attempt to discover ultimate principles by which to determine 28 INTRODUCTION the value of things, in so far as these depend upon the human will. Secondly, it is especially necessary that our age reach some conclusion concerning these principles. The present is characterized by a strong desire to reject a priori all the old accepted truths. There are many symptoms of this desire : think of the avidity with which Friederich Nietzsche's ora- cular utterances concerning the necessary transformation of all values {Die Umwertung alter Werte) are received by the young, as well as of the violent condemnation by the social democracy of all existing political and social institutions. A passionate mania for the new and unheard-of, in thought, in morals, and in modes of life, has taken hold of our times. It is utterly useless to appeal to authority and tradition ; this mania is nothing but an outbreak of free individual thought, which has been repressed so long, and made distrustful by coercion ; it is the reaction against the school, which forced men not to think, but to memorize, against the church, which asked them not to think, but to believe. These are the symp- toms of the Aufklarung, the Aufklarung which was long since reported dead ; it has come back to life and has taken hold of the masses, of the young men especially, of course ; they want to do their own thinking and mould their lives, and not to be governed blindly by the traditional thoughts and ac- tions of others. And to this they have a perfect right ; it is the fundamental right and highest duty of man to think his own thoughts and to act his own acts : independent self- determination is the royal prerogative of the mind. Nothing will avail here but free, unbiassed thought. It will be the business of ethics to invite the doubter and the inquirer to assist in the common effort to discover fixed principles which shall help the judgment to understand the aims and problems of life. It will not tell him : This shalt thou do, but will inves- tigate with him the question : What art thou striving after, what are thy true ideals, not merely thy temporary moods and whims ? Perhaps he will then find that .much of what NATURE AND FUNCTION OF ETHICS 29 he was about to cast aside, as a mere command of caprice, is rooted in the very nature of things, and consequently also in his own will. 1 1 [On the Problem and Methods of Ethics, the Relation of Ethics to other Sciences, and other introductory matter, see Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics, chap. I.-IL, pp. 1-24; Stephen, The Science of Ethics, chap. I., pp. 1-40; Schur- man, The Ethical Import of Darwinism, chap. I., pp. 1-37 ; Muirhead, Elements of Ethics, chaps. I.-IIL, pp. 1-39 ; Mackenzie, Manual of Ethics, chaps. I.-IL, pp. 1-31, Appendix B, pp. 324-328; Hyslop, The Elements of Ethics, chap. L, pp. 1-17 ; Seth, A Study of Ethical Principles, chaps. I.-IIL, pp. 1-35 ; Ho ff ding, Ethik, I.-IV., pp. 1-54; Wundt, EthiJc, Introduction, pp. 1-17 (English transla- tion, pp. 1-20) ; Dorner, Das menschliche Handeln, Introduction, pp. 1-23 ; Sim- mel, Einleitung in die Moralwissenschaft, vol. I., Preface ; Miinsterberg, Ursprung der Sittlichkeit, Introduction, pp. 1-10; Runze, Ethik, vol. I., pp. 1-16, which con- tains many excellent bibliographical references ; Marion, Legons de morale, chap. I BOOK I OUTLINES OF A HISTORY OF THE CONCEPTIONS OF LIFE AND MORAL PHILOSOPHY Jta quadam non verborum sed rerum eloquentia contrariorium oppositione seculi pulchritudo comporiitur. Augustinus. CHAPTER I THE CONCEPTION OF LIFE AND MORAL PHILOSOPHY AMONG THE GREEKS I shall precede my exposition of ethics with an historical survey of the development of the conception of life (Lebens- anschauung) and moral philosophy. I shall confine my attention to the historical phenomena which are still directly influencing the life of the Western nations. No one will reach a clear and distinct knowledge of the mixed and often confused conceptions and aspirations of our age who does not pursue the great tributaries which form the stream of our moral civilization to their sources. The previous history of our moralitv and theory of life divides itself into three great periods. The first embraces the development of the ancient world to its conversion ; the sec- ond, the Christian development with its two halves, the Chris- tianity of the old world and mediaeval Christianity ; the third, the development of modern times, which has not yet come to an end. The ancient world's view of life is naive-naturalistic : the perfection of human nature in civilization is the absolute goal. The Christian conception is supranaturalistic ; turning away from civilization, it demands the death of the natural man and his impulses, in order that a new, spiritual man may arise. The modern theory of life is not so consistent: and self-contained ; it is influenced by both of these opposing tendencies. The naturalistic tendency predominates ; the dawn of the modern period is marked by the revival of the ancient $ 34 ORIGINS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY pagan conception of life (the so-called Renaissance). Still, the modern view of life contains many essential elements of the Christian conception of life ; and the supranaturalistic tendency forms an undercurrent in it, or runs parallel with it. Three groups of moral-philosophical systems, differing in form and contents, correspond to the different conceptions of life. Greek ethics proceeds from the fact of striving and acting. It asks : What is the final goal, and how can it be reached ? The goal is the highest good ; and hence the problem is : to determine the nature of the highest good, and to indicate the way to its attainment. Inasmuch as the highest good consist* in a form of human life, or presupposes it as the means of its realization, Greek ethics essentially assumes the form of a doctrine of virtues : it describes the perfect man in his differ- ent phases. Christian ethics makes the fact of moral judgment its starting- point. Human strivings and acts are objects of judgment; the predicates good and bad are applied to them. And they are thus judged not only by man, but, according to the Chris- tian conception, above all by God, the highest law-giver and judge. Christian ethics, therefore, inquires : What, according to God's commandment, is duty, and what is sin ? It is a doc- trine of duty and as such does not instruct us how to pro- mote individual and social welfare, but sets up a moral law, the application of which necessitates interpretation and casuistry. What was said of the modern conception of life is true of modern ethics : it is influenced by the two preceding stages of development, and does not therefore exhibit a thorough- going uniformity. It is as a whole — a few theological sys- tems apart — more closely connected with Greek ethics. Still, the Christian influence is every where recognizable . We notice it in the form of the science : modern ethics is largely a doctrine of duties. We notice it also in the matter ; thus, THE GREEK CONCEPTION 35 for example, duties towards others usually occupy the most important place among the duties, while in Greek ethics em- phasis is laid upon the virtues and duties which tend to the perfection of individual life. And when the highest good is discussed, the good of the individual is not first thought of, as was the case in Greek ethics, but the good of the commun- ity. The idea of the kingdom of God, which Christianity has made the keystone of its theory of the universe and life, even permeates the thoughts of those who know nothing of it or do not want to have anything to do with it. Even the men of 1789 cannot deny their relation to Christianity. They destroy the church, but the notion of a kingdom of God on earth — altered though it be — influences them also ; for where else do these ideas of the freedom, equality, and fraternity of all men and all nations come from ? 1. The moral philosophical reflections of the Greeks * start from the question : What is the ultimate end of all striving (to riXos), or what is the highest good ? It necessarily 1 There is no dearth of elaborate treatments of the subject. Besides Zeller's History of Greek Philosophy, we may mention : the thorough work of K. Kostlin, Die Ethik des klassischen Altertums, Part I., 1887 (to Plato) ; Lathardt, Die antike Ethik, 1887 ; Th. Ziegler, Die Ethik der Griechen und Rdmer, 1881. An excellent work on the ethical conceptions of the Greek people is L. Schmidt's Die Ethik der alten Griechen, 2 vols., 1882. A good survey of the history of ethics in general is given by H. Sidgwick, Outline of a History of Ethics , 1886; a detailed account of the most important movements, by P. Janet, Histoire de la philosophie morale et politique, 2 vols., 1885. [See also Wundt, Ethik, Part II., The Development of the Moral Conceptions of the Universe, pp. 270^*33 ; English translation, vol. II. ; J. Seth, A Study of Ethical Principles, Part I., The Moral Ideal, pp. 77-249 ; Watson, Hedonistic Theories from Aristippus to Spencer ; Hyslop, Elements of Ethics, chap. II., The Origin and Development of Ethical Problems, pp. 18-89 ; Calderwood, Handbook of Moral Philosophy, pp. 318-369 ; Eucken, Die Lebensanschauungen der grossen Denker. The first two chapters of Jodl's Geschichte der Ethik in der neuern Philosophie, vol. I., pp. 1-85, give a sur- vey of the history of ethics down to the beginning of modern times. Martineau's Types of Ethical Theory, 2 vols., discusses some of the most important systems. See also the histories of Greek and General Philosophy which are mentioned in Thilly's translation of Weber's History of Philosophy , pp. 8-16. Eor bibliographies on particular thinkers, see the standard histories of philosophy, especially Uber« weg, Erdmann, Windelband, Weber, all of which have been translated. — Tr.] 36 ORIGINS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY suggests itself to the agent when he reflects upon his con- duct. Aristotle, the founder of ethics as a systematic science, gives us the following lucid exposition of the subject, at the beginning of his Nicomachean Mhics. 1 Every art, and every scientific inquiry, and similarly every action and purpose, aims at some good. As there are various actions, arts, and sciences, it follows that the ends and goods are also various. Thus health is the end of medicine, a vessel of shipbuilding, victory of strategy, and wealth of domestic economy. But certain arts are subordinated to other arts ; the art of making bridles works for horsemanship, the latter for strategy, and so others for others. But inasmuch as the end of the lead- ing art embraces the ends of the subordinate arts, and since the latter are desired for the sake of the former, there must, if our desires are not to be idle and futile, be an ultimate goal or good which is not in turn a means, but is desired for its own sake, all other things being desired for the sake of it. What is this highest of all practical goods (tl to 7rdvTcov aKporarov twv irpaKTwv ayaOcov) ? As to its name, he continues, there is a general agreement. The masses and the cultured classes agree in calling it hap- piness ; it is happiness (evhaifiovla) or welfare (to ev £w ^ ev irpcLTTetv). But in what does happiness consist? Here the views begin to diverge. The masses define it as pleas- ure, or wealth, or honor, or something similar; different people give different definitions of it, and often the same person gives different definitions of it at different times ; for when a person has been ill, health, when he is poor, wealth is the highest good. Cultivated people, however, the phil- osophers (ol xapievTes) y define it as virtue and also as philosophy. We are perhaps justified in saying that Aristotle exag- gerates the differences of opinion with respect to the highest good ; in the last analysis the Greek people and their moral 1 See Welldon's translation of Aristotle's Ethics. THE GREEK CONCEPTION 37 philosophers had essentially the same conception of the nature of happiness. We are in the habit of translating the word evhau^ovia by the term happiness ( G-luckseligkeit). We thereby make it a matter of feeling. The Greek word does not connote a subjective state of feeling, but rather an objective form of life : evBaL/jLQ)v (with which dyaOoSal/jbcov, /caKoSaLficov, are con- trasted) is the man who is blessed with a good halficov and therefore with a good lot in life, for Salfxcov signifies the god- head who apportions to men their fates. Now, what is the Greek conception of a happy lot or fate ? I cannot describe it more briefly and more forcibly than by calling to mind the well known anecdote of the meeting of Solon and Croesus which is narrated by Herodotus. 1 It admir- ably contrasts the Hellenic conception of what is a good life with that of the barbarians. After showing Solon through his treasury, the king addresses him as follows : " stranger from Athens, we have heard much of your wisdom and travels, we have been told that you have visited many coun- tries, in the pursuit of philosophy, for the sake of study (Oecopirjs ev€/ca). Now, I should like to know whether you have ever seen a man whom you regarded as the happiest of all (oXfiLdoTaTos)" But he asked him, expecting that Solon would call him, the king, the happiest of all men. Solon, however, did not wish to flatter him, but spoke the truth : " King, the Athenian Tellos." The king was surprised, and asked : " Why do you esteem Tellos happier than all others?" Solon an- swered : " Tellos lived at a time when the city was prosper- ing ; he had beautiful and good children, and, above all, lived to see his grandchildren, and all of them were preserved to him ; he was, for our conditions, in good circumstances, and finally, he suffered a glorious death ; at Eleusis, in a battle between the Athenians and their neighbors, he succeeded in repelling the enemy after a gallant fight, and met a most 1 I., 30. 38 ORIGINS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY beautiful death. And the Athenians buried him where he fell, at public expense, and greatly honored him." But when the king received an equally unsatisfactory answer to the question whom Solon would regard as the happiest man after Tellos — Solon, as we know, mentions two unknown Argive youths, who died suddenly, after having done their mother an honorable service — Croesus could no longer re- strain himself : " And is our happiness (evhaufiovla) absolutely nothing in your eyes, that you place it after that of those pri- vate persons ? " Solon gave an evasive answer : " Envious are the gods and impatient, and many things are experienced in the long time which we do not desire ; and many sufferings. A human life may last seventy years, which makes, not counting the intercalary months, 25,200 days, but if we count these, 26,250 days. Of all these days no two are alike, there- fore I cannot call you happy until I know that your end has been a happy one." I call it an evasive answer ; the well known pragmatic use which Herodotus makes of the anecdote necessitates such a reply. The true answer to the question of the king would have been as follows : King, what we Hellenes and what you here, whom we call barbarians, call happiness is not the same. You regard as a happy lot to have much and to enjoy much, while for us it means to live nobly, to act nobly, and to die nobly. When a man has our good wishes, we say to him : Act nobly (ev irpdrreiv) ; while you would have to say : May good things happen to you (ev •waayeiv). Hence I have called Tellos a happy man. -He did not enjoy the luxury of a royal household, but he possessed what a citizen in a Hellenic town needs. He was a capable man, and governed his affairs wisely ; he had beautiful and good children, his city honored him, and his name was not un- known to its enemies. That is our idea of a happy man. This is what the story of Croesus and Solon, which cir- THE GREEK CONCEPTION 39 culated among the Hellenes, seems to me to signify ; it expresses the popular Greek conception of the difference between the Hellenic and barbarian view of life. According to the latter, the value of life consists in the possession of wealth and enjoyment; according to the former, virtuous activity or active virtue alone makes life worth living. For- tune may crown it with a beautiful death. — The same idea of the difference between the Hellenic and barbaric conception of life is brought out in the legendary epitaph, transmitted in various forms, which the Greeks dedicated to the legendary King Sardanapalus : Let us eat and drink, for te-morrow we shall die. 2. Greek moral philosophy consists essentially in the analysis and conceptual formulation of the popular Greek ideal of a perfect life. I shall attempt to show this by em- phasizing the chief phases of its history. The real scientific treatment of moral philosophy dates from Socrates. 1 Greek philosophy began with speculations upon the external world, upon the form, origin, and primal elements of the universe. Socrates refuses to consider these things, he makes the affairs of human life the objects of his reflections ; these he regards as more important and more capable of investigation. The change represented by Socratic thought connects itself with the general changes in the life of the Greek people. Greek life, which was centred at Athens in the fifth century, tended away from the old simplicity and constraint towards- a fuller and freer development. All the arts of civilization flourished on the soil of the new metropol- itan life. Rational arts, based upon theories, gradually took the place of the traditional handicraft ; geometry and astron- omy, music and architecture, gymnastics and medicine, strategy and rhetoric, became objects of scientific reflection and sys- 1 [For Socrates, see : Xenophon's Memorabilia, translation in Bonn's Library ; Plato's Protagoras, Apology, Crito, Phaedo, Symposium, etc. ; Aristotle's Metaphys- ics, I., 6. See also for Socrates and the following systems the references mentioned, p. 3o. — Tu.] 40 ORIGINS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY tematic treatment. Excellence or efficiency (aperrj) in these arts now became a matter not merely of natural skill and practice, but of theoretical knowledge : whoever desires to ac- quire the former must possess the latter. — Is not this true of all excellence, is it not true also of the excellence of the citi- zen and statesman, nay, of the excellence of man in general ? According to the traditional view, civic and human excel- lence is innate: whoever comes into the world as a good man and as the descendant of good men, and is reared among the good, possesses it as a gift of the gods (evhai^cav). The enlightened ones of the new period gradually convinced them- selves that all excellence, moral and political no less than technical, is the result of instruction and education: virtue can be taught, that is the new conception which the Sophists first advanced in systematic form. " If you associate with me," Protagoras promises the young man in the Platonic dialogue bearing his name, " on the very day you will return home a better man than you came." And upon being asked by Socrates in what he would become better, he adds : " If he comes to me, he will learn that which he comes to learn. And this is prudence in affairs private as well as public ; he will learn to order his own house in the best manner, and he will be able to speak and act for the best in the affairs of the state." By many of his contemporaries Socrates was looked upon as one of the Sophists. Not altogether unjustly ; he differed from the latter : he did not regard himself as a possessor of wisdom, and did not acquire money through public lectures ; but in his views he had much in common with them. Above all, he believed with them that excellence or virtue depends upon insight and may be taught. This proposition is em- phasized in all the accounts, in Xenophon, Plato, and Aris- totle, as characteristic of his point of view : Socrates, so Aris- totle declares, considered the virtues to be forms of reason. 1 i Nic. Eth., VI., 13. THE GREEK CONCEPTION 41 The game is true of human excellence as such : without knowledge no virtue ; and conversely : right conduct neces- sarily depends upon the proper insight, no one knowingly and willingly does wrong (ouSa? i/coop apbaprdvei). If a man knows the right goal and the right path, he will necessarily follow it ; his going astray and also his moral trangression are always the result of error, as the Greek word dfMaprdvecv indicates. This is especially true of civic virtue ; hence Socrates condemns the Athenian state. The democratic constitution rested upon the tacit assumption that political excellence was the inheritance, so to speak, of every citizen. Socrates is constantly attacking this view in arguments like the following : Do you not, when you wish to steer a ship, look around for a man who has learned and understands the art of navigation ? And when a man is sick you send for some one who understands the art of medicine ? But when it comes to governing the city or the state, you choose any one for whom the lot may decide. Hence knowledge, scientific knowledge of that which is really good, and of the means of acquiring it, is the great condition of all excellence and virtue. That is the view upon which Socrates bases himself and which places him at the head of the Greek moral philosophers. It is the funda- mental conception common to his successors. The sage alone, the man who has scientific knowledge — in this Plato and Aristotle, the Stoics and Epicureans, agree — is virtuous and happy in the full sense of the term. The wise man alone is capable of governing the state ; if we are to have a perfect state, kings must either become wise men, or wise men kings, to quote the well-known saying. 3. Socrates saw the necessity of a science of right con- duct and right government, but he did not solve the problem which he proposed ; he left it to his pupils to create the sciences of ethics and politics. Plato 1 first undertook 1 [See the Dialogues of Plato, Jowett's translation, especially, Theaetetus, Phaedo, Philebus, Gorgias, Republic. — Tb.1 42 ORIGINS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY the task. Its accomplishment seemed all the more urgent, the weaker the old foundations of morality were becoming. With the entrance of the Greek people upon the period of enlightenment, the old civic respectability and morality rapidly declined. The younger Sophists — as Plato portrays them in the persons of Callicles and Thrasymachus (in the G-orgias and the Republic) — formulated the facts into a theory: there is no objective difference between good and bad, it does not inhere in the nature of the things, but is a mere matter of convention and caprice. The sanction of cus- tom and law rests upon fear and superstition, which restrain the stronger from making use of their natural superiority ; or they are another means, in the hands of the mighty themselves, to strengthen their power. The enlightened one knows it and acts accordingly ; he obeys law and custom when they are conducive to his interests, he breaks them when they thwart his plans, and when he can do so with impunity. 1 Plato undertakes to overcome this enlightenment, not from without, but from within, by a deeper philosophy. This is, indeed, the only remedy: half-enlightenment, pseudo- enlightenment, can be destroyed only by complete enlighten- ment. To fetter thought, to oppose it with authorities, is utterly useless, nay, simply makes matters worse. Plato therefore explicitly places himself upon the standpoint of reason, which the Sophists, too, claim to occupy. With Socrates he recognizes the necessity of basing human and civic virtue upon knowledge. Virtue without knowledge, virtue resting solely upon education, habit, authority, correct opinion, is a blind groping ; it may accidentally find the right path, but there is no certainty of its doing so. Only the scientific knowledge of the good can make man's willing correct, certain, and steady. 1 Laas has given us a good description of this sceptical-nihilistic sophistical philosophy, which had a great deal to do with producing and influencing the Platonic ethics, as its antithesis, in the introduction to the second volume of his Idealismus und Positivismus. THE GREEK CONCEPTION 43 But is there such a thing as objective goodness and right ? This was denied by Callicles and his companions : that is good which happens to please, and that is right which we have the power of enforcing. The aim of Plato's entire philosophy, is to prove, in opposition to this, the proposition : The good and right is something absolutely independent of opinions, something determined by the nature of the things themselves. What is the good and right as such ? The Platonic philosophy gives an answer to this question that far transcends the horizon of the healthy common-sense which we find in Socrates. The good is nothing but the world, or reality itself. But, Plato immediately adds : reality as it is in itself that is, in idea. That which common-sense regards as the real reality, the sum total of these sensuous, particular things, is not the good ; the world of sense is full of imperfections. But it is not the true reality, it has no being in the real sense of the term ; its being is mixed with non-being; it is in a state of constant growth and decay. The true reality, on the other hand, of which being can really be predicated, is an absolutely existing, absolutely unitary, ideal, spiritual, being, and this is nothing but the good itself, or God. — God is both the absolutely good and the absolutely real, says scholastic philosophy, following in the footsteps of Plato. Now the question arises, What is good and right for a particular being? This will naturally depend upon his re- lation to the All-Good and All-Real ; or, stated in different language, the value of a particular element of reality can be determined only by its significance within the whole of reality. The world is not, like a bad poem, full of super- fluous episodes, but the unitary realization of an idea, the idea of the good, which unfolds itself in a variety of qualities or ideas, and so forms a cosmos of ideas, an intelligent organism in which every element of reality, like every scene in a good drama, occupies the position of a necessary 44 ORIGINS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY member. So, too, the idea of man must be denned by his place in the cosmos, if we are to reach a knowledge of what man is in reality, or in idea. If the philosopher, the dia- lectician, who has the gift of seeing things in their logical relations, succeeds in reaching this definition, he may say that he has objectively denned the essence of goodness and right. Thus Plato brings ethics into the most intimate con- nection with metaphysics ; he makes it a part of the one unitary science of the real, or the good. What now is found to be the idea of man in the idea of the universal reality ? In the Timceus, of which parts of the Phcedrus form the prelude, Plato has made the most elabo- rate attempt to explain man's place in the cosmos. The human soul is derived from the world-soul ; it is, like the latter, a mixture of two elements ; on the one hand, it participates in the real reality, in the world of ideas, the world of existent thoughts, or the life of God ; on the other, in the world of origin and decay, in the corporeal world. With the reason (z^oO?), it belongs to the world of ideas, with the animal impulses {hnQvy^iai) arising from its union with the body, it belongs to the corporeal world. These two dis- similar parts or phases of the soul are connected by an intermediate form : Plato calls it 6vfju6<; or to OvfioetSis ; it embraces the higher, nobler impulses, the affections of the heart, moral indignation, courage, the aspiring love of honor, moral awe ; perhaps the Platonic term may be best trans- lated by our word will. The organization of the inner man is made visible in the organization of the outer man; the head is the seat of reason, the citadel of the ruler; in the breast dwells the heart, the seat of the affections, as common- sense looks at it ; it is, so to speak, the watch-house in which courage and anger dwell, ready to break forth at the beck of the ruler ; under the diaphragm, at last, are situated the organs of animal desire, the organs of nutrition and repro- THE GREEK CONCEPTION 45 duction. — The function of man is to represent a cosmos on the small scale after the pattern of the larger cosmos : as the macrocosm is fashioned into beauty and order by the ideal element, so the microcosm must be fashioned into proportion and harmony, order and beauty, by reason, the ideal element peculiar to it. The anthropological-ethical application of this metaphysical principle of the science of the good is made in the dialogue on the State. It begins with a discussion of the notion of the " just man." How shall we define a just man, a man who realizes the idea, the natural or divine vocation of man ? He is one in whom the three elements, defined above, harmo- niously co-operate to perform their special functions. We thus arrive at the scheme of the so-called cardinal virtues : wisdom (<7O0/,a), courage (avSpeia), and self-control or healthy- mindedness (acocfrpocrvvr)), which three combined give us justice (Slkcuoctvvti). A man is wise, in whom reason realizes its purpose, the knowledge of the true reality, and as the ruling principle regulates his entire life ; he is courageous when the will does its work, assisting the reason in governing and bridling the irrational element; he is healthy-minded when the animal impulses peacefully perform their functions, without disquieting and disturbing the spirit. Such a well- regulated soul deserves to be called a just soul ; it typifies human nature, or the idea of man. In it the exercise of reason forms the real, essential content of life ; reason as such consists in knowledge ; perfect knowledge, however, is philosophy, that is, the dialectical re-creation of the absolute ideal reality in concepts. The other elements and their func- tions are subordinate to it. And hence we may say : Philo- sophy is the true function, the highest content and purpose, of human life. This would answer the question concerning objective good- ness : such a life is good in itself, good for man, not accord- ing to accidental opinion and convention, but in the nature 46 ORIGINS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY of things, in which philosophy forms the central purpose to which all the other functions and actions are subordinated as means. That such a " just " life is at the same time a happy and desirable life hardly seems to need proof. Just as the sound- ness of the body is subjectively experienced as good health, disease as poor health, so " justice," which is nothing but the health of the soul, or the state expressing its true nature, necessarily procures the greatest satisfaction. And so the opposite of justice (aSucla) will necessarily be the greatest subjective evil for a man, not because of some accidental effects, like punishment and disgrace, but on account of the ugliness which characterizes an " unjust " life (wahn- schaffen, misshapen, we might call it, employing a term peculiar to the Northern languages). With incomparable skill Plato portrays the life of such a " misshapen " soul and its inner discord in his picture of the tyrant, who satisfies all his desires and enjoys the privilege — which those illumi- nators envy him — of perpetrating all kinds of wrongs and violent deeds with impunity. Let me also briefly mention that the same fundamental traits reappear in the constitution of the just state, man on the large scale. A state is just in which the wise rule, the strong and courageous (a military nobility) disinterestedly and submissively serve the government, and finally, the producing classes peacefully and modestly perform their tasks. We see, Plato does not differ very radically in his views from the popular Greek conception of justice and happiness. It is true, he emphasizes the element of knowledge in his scheme, and the kind of knowledge which he has in mind, the speculative knowledge of the real reality, is, of course, something wholly foreign to the popular idea. We must not, however, lose sight of another fact. Our exposition of Plato's ethics has not sufficiently emphasized a THE GREEK CONCEPTION 47 phase of his conception of life which stands out quite promi- nently in many dialogues, alienation from the world ( Welt- fliichtigkeit) , a doctrine which differs so remarkably from the old Greek mode of thought, and approximates the Christian view. Plato does not always adhere to the conception, out- lined above, of the nature of man as a spiritual-sensuous being, but often manifests a strong tendency completely to spiritualize the nature of man : reason constitutes his real essence ; the animal nature, sensuality and desire, is an acci- dental appendage, which drags down the spirit, and of which the wise man strives to divest himself. God is pure thought, free from desire ; to be like him is the highest goal of human striving. The notions of pre-existence, transmigration of souls, and immortality are connected with this idea; this mundane life is conceived as a prison-house from which the spirit seeks to escape. It is evidently, first of all, his opposition to the doctrine of pleasure which provokes these thoughts. Callicles and his followers make the satisfaction of the desires the highest good, while Plato sees in pleasure something, " a trace of which," as we read in the Phosdrus, " a demon has added to all bad things." Hence he looks upon life as a struggle of reason with lust, a struggle in which the nobler impulses of the heart are on the side of reason. This teaching supplies the moral preacher with a wonderful weapon, which Plato himself handles with great force and skill, and we ought to make a more extended use of his writings ; they would appeal more powerfully to our young men than the weak-kneed Cicero ; the Republic is the very thing for young people whose thoughts are preoccupied with and confused by Nietzsche's Ubermensch. But perhaps it is also possible to connect this mode of thought with Plato's personal experiences. His relations with his contemporaries were not friendly. His native city gave the philosopher no opportunity for public activity, as he understood the term. That he did not always 48 ORIGINS OF MOKAL PHILOSOPHY bear his isolation with equanimity may be inferred from his harsh criticism of the persons who took a prominent part in public life, the statesmen, Sophists, and rhetoricians. He re garded them as the representatives of the most unworthy art, the art, namely, of catering to the whims of the great animal, called Demos, and thus acquiring advantages and fame ; whoever interferes with their schemes, and refuses to become a party to their crimes is doomed. And so the untimely philosopher, " like one who, in the storm of dust and sleet which the driving wind hurries along, retires under the shelter of a wall," withdrew from public life and sought refuge in the solitude of the Academy ; his life was enriched and blessed by the contemplation of the true reality, and he looked forward to his deliverance in peace and good-will, with bright hopes. 1 Thus Plato, like every honest philosopher, utilized his own personal experiences as the key with which to interpret human life, nay, all things in general. Yet he was too much of a Greek to reject this natural-sensuous world altogether. He was a pessimist in his judgment of men, but he remained an optimist in his judgment of man. In the passage of the Republic quoted above, he adds that the solitary philosopher will not do the greatest work unless he find a state suitable to him ; for in a state which is suitable to him he will have a larger growth, and be the savior of his country as well as of himself. 4. Aristotle, 2 in Dante's words " the master of those who know," " the eternal prince of all true thinkers " as Comte calls him in the Catechisme positiviste, was the first to stake off practical philosophy as a separate field of knowledge and to discuss it, as a systematic whole, in its three parts, ethics, politics, and economics. His works lack the wonderful charm 1 Republic, 496 D. 2 [Nicomachean Ethics, transl. by Welldon. For other translations and bibliography, see my translation of Weber, History of Philosophy, p. 104 s aote4. — Tk.] THE GREEK CONCEPTION 49 of the Platonic expositions, but we are compensated for this loss by a wealth of great thoughts. I shall give an outline of his ethics ; in the main it follows the lines marked out by the Platonic system. He begins with the question concerning the highest good, which all agree to designate as happiness (ev&ao/jLovla), and finds, by means of one of those Socratic inductions which are so common in his writings, that it must consist in the exercise of the specific excellence of the human soul : for, as with a flute-player, a statuary, or any artisan, or in fact anybody who has a definite function and action (epyov ti /ecu irpa^'), his goodness or excellence (rdyaObv koX to ev) seems to lie in his function, so it would seem to be with man, if indeed he has a definite function. What, then, is this function or action of man ? Aristotle compares man with organic beings and finds that he shares with all beings the vegetative func- tions, and with all animals sensation and desire, but that he alone possesses reason (to \6yov e^oz/). The peculiar func- tion of man, then, is an activity of soul in accordance with reason, or not independently of reason (yjrvxv^ ivepyeia /caTa Xoyov r) /*?; dvev \6yov). This being so, the good of man is an activity of soul in accordance with virtue, or, if there are more virtues than one, in accordance with the best and most complete virtue. 1 Now, that the life which is objectively the best also pro- cures the greatest subjective satisfaction necessarily follows from Aristotle's great psychological generalization : all un- impeded, successful exercise of the powers natural to a being is accompanied with feelings of satisfaction. The limbs take pleasure in the movements, the eye in sight, the flute-player in the music, the orator in the speech, and so every being in the exercise of its specific function : hence the most pleasura- ble thing for man is the exercise of reason. At the conclusion of the work he again takes up the sub- 1 Nic. Ethics, Book I., chap. 6. Welldon's translation. 50 ORIGINS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY ject: 1 Since reason, whether it be divine itself or the most divine part of our being, is the highest function of man, per- fect happiness will consist in the exercise of that which is peculiar to it, that is, theoretical activity. And this is a con- clusion which would seem to agree with our previous argu- ments as well as with the truth itself. For of all activities contemplation is the most continuous and the most inde- pendent of the necessaries of life ; the exercise of the other faculties is dependent upon opportunity, but the wise man is always and under all circumstances capable of speculation himself. It alone is self-sufficient, it alone has its end in itself ; all practical activities, even those of the statesman and general, which are regarded as the highest and most beautiful, have external ends ; contemplation alone is not ex- ercised for the sake of an external end. It is also admitted that there is no virtuous activity so pleasant as philosophic reflection ; at all events it appears that philosophy possesses pleasures of wonderful purity and certainty. " Hence such a life may seem too good for a man. He will enjoy such a life not in virtue of his humanity, but in virtue of some divine element in him. If then the reason is divine in com- parison with the rest of man's nature, the life which accords with reason will be divine in comparison with human life in general. Nor is it right to follow the advice of people who say that the thoughts of men should not be too high for humanity, or the thoughts of humanity too high for mortality ; ? or a man, as far as in him lies, should seek immortality {aOavari^eiv) and do all in his power to live in accordance with the highest part of his nature." Who does not feel in these words the emotion with which the usually so placid thinker expresses his deepest life- experiences ? To be sure, the purely theoretical life is unattainable by man ; God's life alone consists in pure thought. In man 1 B. X., chap. 7. THE GREEK CONCEPTION 51 reason is inseparably connected with the functions which lie possesses in common with the animals and plants, with sen- sation and desire, with nutrition and reproduction. From this it follows that human life is confronted with a number of problems, which may be characterized in general as the organization of the lower functions by reason and in harmony with the ends of reason. Thus arise the so-called ethical virtues or excellences, which are distinguished from the in- tellectual or theoretical virtues. There will therefore be as many ethical virtues as there are separate spheres of problems arising from the sensuous side of human nature. Among them we may mention: our attitude to the animal desires, our behavior with respect to economic commodities, honor, anger, fear, social and economic intercourse with men, etc. There is a virtue for every sphere. Virtuous conduct in reference to the satisfaction of animal desires is so-called healthy-mindedness (o-oxfipoo-vvr]) ; in ref- erence to wealth, liberality {eXevOeptorr]^) ; in reference to honor, high-mindedness and love of honor {fieyaXo^v^ia and L\oTifiLa) ; in reference to danger, courage (avBpeta), etc. Virtue, as language, too, suggests, is always a mean be- tween two extremes, between excess and deficiency. Courage, for example, is the normal state in regard to the fearful, being a mean between the state of the coward (SeiXo?), who stupidly runs away from danger, and the state of the fool- hardy man (Opacrvp6vr]cri,^ undoubtedly also plays a part in the ethical vir- tues, for it shows which is the normal state for every one in every case. And so we obtain the definition of ethical virtue which Aristotle places at the head of his discussion of the virtues : Virtue is a state of deliberate moral purpose con- sisting in a mean that is relative to ourselves, the mean being determined by reason, or as a prudent man would determine it. 1 It is evident that this definition does not yet furnish us with an objective standard. For what is the mean or normal, or what is the standpoint from which reason or the prudent man determines it ? Aristotle did not answer this question, because, so it seems, he did not believe an answer could be found. He repeatedly accentuates the difference between this field of knowledge and the theoretical sciences, which treat of things " which cannot be otherwise," while the prac- tical sciences deal with things " which can be otherwise." In the sixth book, where he discusses the question of prudence (^poV^o-t?), as opposed to theoretical knowledge (a-o/a), he even seems to incline to the view that the former never gives us universal judgments, but only particular decisions ; which would be equivalent to denying the possibility of a scientific ethics. And indeed we must admit that Aristotle's doctrine of the ethical virtues fails to meet the demands, which must be made upon a scientific treatment of the subject ; he makes no attempt whatever to explain the difference in value between virtuous conduct and vicious conduct, as was done later, say by Spinoza, who entertained the same general view. He confines himself to a description of virtuous modes of conduct, which draws mainly upon Greek popular usage, and does not care for systematic completeness. Of real value is the acute exposition of the meaning of the words which the Greek people used to express moral distinctions. 1 1106 b. 36, B. II, chap. 6. THE GREEK CONCEPTION 53 In this way Plato and Aristotle meet the Socratic demand for a science of the good. They take into account the place of man in the cosmos, and then attempt to define his idea, that is, his natural and divine purpose, and to show how he may realize this purpose. The conception of the perfect man which they advance, essentially resembles the popular Greek ideal. There is only one marked difference : in the scheme of the philosophers the purely theoretical exercise of the intellect constitutes the chief element of human perfection ; the philosophical ideal not only embodies the general features of the Greek character, but also embraces the personal feat- ures of the philosophers, which gives the concept greater precision. 5. The post-Aristotelian moral philosophy can hardly be said to have created any new conceptions ; on the whole it follows in the traces of its great predecessors. But it is lacking neither in great and fruitful thoughts nor in strong and forcible moral preaching. I must confine my efforts to a mere outline of the standpoints of the two chief schools, which for a long time formed the chief subject of interest in philosophy, the Stoics and Epicureans. The Stoics, 1 like Plato and Aristotle, regard the realiza- tion of his natural purpose as the highest good and highest happiness of man. They formulate this idea into a principle : life according to nature (o/jLoXoyov/juevcos rfj (frvaec £fjv). On the basis of the unusually comprehensive and valuable extracts from the ethical writings of the Stoics, which we find in Dio- genes Laertius, 2 we may outline their ethical philosophy about as follows. The underlying thought is the proposition : The fundamental impulse of every living being aims at self- preservation (rr)v TTpcornv opfjLTjv to %coov ta")(eiv iirl to Tnpelv kavTo), to which is added the polemical statement : and not 1 [See Diogenes Laertius, Book VII.; Stobaeus, Eclogues, II.; Cicero, Definibua* Bibliography in Weber-Thilly, p. 140, p. 146. — Tk.] 2 VII., 84-131. 54 ORIGINS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY at pleasure. The law of its nature is, therefore, to avoid the harmful and to strive for what is appropriate to it (ra oUela'). Pleasure, however, arises as an accompaniment when a being obtains what is appropriate to it {iTriykvvnpa, which calls to mind Aristotle's liny iy vonevov reXos). Even plants act in this way, although they are unconscious of the impulse, which is also the case with our own vegetative functions. Ani- mals, however, are conscious of the impulse, and hence it is the law of their nature to follow their conscious impulses (for them to Kara (fiver lv is equal to to koltcl ttjv opfirjv ^ioiKelcrOai). But man is endowed with reason (6 \6yos), besides impulse ; hence to live according to nature means for him to live according to reason (icaTa \6yov), for reason is by nature the regulator of desire (\6yos T(-yy'iTn<$ eiriyiveTai t% 0/3//%). It would be contrary to nature for man to follow irrational desire. — But in so far as the nature of each individual being is determined by the nature of the All, to live according to reason means for man : to obey the universal law, or, which is the same thing, Jupiter, the highest regula- tor and ruler. — And this is eudamionia and welfare (jevpoia tov /3tW), namely to do everything in harmony with our demon, according to the will of the universal governor and manager of all things. And the natural disposition of every being is its virtue or perfection (TeXetWt?) ; and this we ought to seek for its own sake, without being influenced by the fear or hope of any external effects : for it is in it that happiness consists. — If now we call a man who lives accord- ing to reason a wise man, we may say : The wise man, and the wise man alone, is virtuous and happy. These thoughts may all be regarded as applications and, in part, more definite expressions of Aristotelian principles. Reference is often made to the rigorism of the Stoic ethics, which holds that virtue alone is a good, but this is, in the last analysis, exactly what Plato and Aristotle teach : that happiness does not consist in pleasure, but in the exercise of THE GREEK CONCEPTION 55 virtue. Nor is there any radical difference in their concep- tions of the value of the so-called external goods, wealth, health, beauty, fame, etc. The Stoics will not concede that these things are real goods : in themselves they are neither useful nor harmful, good or bad, but either one or the other, according to the use to which they are put, while that only is good which can never be harmful, but only useful. Yet they confess that they are not absolutely indifferent, that wealth is preferable to poverty, health to sickness {jrpor^^va — aTroTTporjy/jLeva). These, too, are at bottom merely systemat- ized, technical statements of Aristotelian ideas. Aristotle had used an admirable figure in defining the value of external goods : they are for life what the xoprjyta i s f° r the tragedy, hence they certainly belong to the perfect happiness of life, just as the ^oprjyla is necessary to the perfect production of the tragedy, without, however, forming a real part of happiness. It seems, however, that the desire gradually grew stronger in the Stoics to make happiness (ev&ai,/uLovla) absolutely inde- pendent of external goods. The freedom from passions (iraOri) which are aroused in the soul by the acquisition and loss, the possession and want, of external goods, the doctrine that virtue suffices for happiness, old and legitimate concep- tions of Greek ethics, are emphasized more and more as moral philosophy becomes moral preaching. The practical moralist's most thankful and fruitful task is to throw man upon his own inner resources, and this task the Stoic philos- ophy accomplished with laudable skill : nowhere shall we find more forcible exhortations to make ourselves independent of the things which are not in our power, and to depend upon ourselves with inner freedom, than in Epictetus's little Manual} With this tendency to moral preaching is connected an- other element in the Stoic philosophy : the value of theoreti- > See Long's translation. 56 ORIGINS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY cal activity is lessened, while the exercise of the ethical virtues, the field of action, especially action dealing with human relations, the family and the state, gradually becomes more prominent. But the demand that we keep ourselves free remains the chief and the highest demand. 6. Epicurus, 1 too, and his disciples are in search of the highest good and find it in eudaemonia ; but their defini- tion of it differs from that of the philosophers mentioned above, nay, even from the popular Greek conception: for them eudgemonia is a feeling of pleasure. This view leads to a change in the position of virtue or excellence : virtue becomes a means to the end of pleasure. 2 The difference between the two standpoints is perfectly apparent. The Stoics agree with Aristotle and Plato in defin- ing happiness as an objective condition of the soul : a life that realizes the natural purpose of man, or perfectly realizes his idea, is itself the highest good. To be sure, the subjective satisfaction follows the objective constitution, as the shadow follows the body, but the satisfaction is not itself the good. The Epicureans, on the other hand, regard the feelings of pleasure which life procures as the good itself, and the con- stitution or character of which they are the effect, as the means. When we disregard this question of principle and examine the counsels which Epicurus gives to his pupils concerning their mode of life (for example in his letter to Menoikeus) 3 the difference largely disappears, yes, we might almost be tempted to view it as a purely scholastic or technical differ- ence. Epicurus by no means advises us to choose every pleasure, nay, he expressly warns us against it. " When, 1 [Diogenes Laertius, X. ; Cicero, De Jinibus ; Lucretius, De rerum natura (translated by Munro). Bibliography in Weber-Thilly, p. 194, note 1.] 2 Kostlin shows us in his excellent exposition of the Democritean ethics, Geschichte der Ethik, I., 196, how, even in his ethics, Epicurus was forestalled by the forceful thinker whom he followed in his physics, Democritus. 8 Diogenes Laertius, translation by Yonge in Bonn's library, X., 122-125. THE GREEK CONCEPTION 57 therefore, we say that pleasure is a chief good, we are not speaking of the pleasures of the debauched man, or those who lie in sensual enjoyment, as some think who are ignorant, and who do not entertain our opinions, or else interpret them per- versely ; but we mean the freedom of the body from pain, and of the soul from confusion." By happiness, he says, he means the health of the body and the freedom from disquiet- ude of the soul (rrjv rov o-cd/jlcltos vyueiav teal rrjv t>}? ^u^t}? arapa^iav reXos elvai rov fia/capicos tr\v). Hence the essence of wisdom is, in his opinion, to avoid the causes of confusion. Such are the loss and want of things which we are in the habit of possessing and enjoying, as well as the fear of losses. " To accustom oneself, therefore, to simple and inex- pensive habits is a great ingredient in the perfecting of health, and makes a man free from hesitation with respect to the necessary uses of life. And when we, on certain occa- sions, fall in with more sumptuous fare, it makes us in a better disposition towards it, and renders us fearless with respect to fortune. Hence we regard contentment (avrdpfceia) as a great good. Above all, we must rid ourselves of vain desires" Epicurus distinguishes between natural or neces- sary and vain or empty desires (i-iridvpiai vo-ifcai — icevai). The former, he finds, are easily satisfied, — nature does not make great demands, — while the latter, the desires of luxury and vanity, are infinite and never to be satisfied. Philoso- phy frees us from this trouble by teaching us what we should avoid and what we should strive after. Another source of trouble is the fear of death, and of what comes after death. From this, too, philosophy frees us by showing that death is nothing terrible, since, when we exist, death is not present to us, and when death is present, then we have no existence. And there is nothing terrible in living to a man who rightly comprehends that there is nothing ter- rible in ceasing to live. An enthusiastic disciple of Epicurus, Lucretius, emphasizes this phase ; every book of his work on 58 ORIGINS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY the Nature of Things 1 sings new praises to the man who freed mankind from the imaginary terrors with which super- stition had peopled heaven and earth. " Hence it is not continued drinkings and revels, or the enjoyment of female society, or feasts of fish and other such things as a costly table supplies, that make life pleasant, but sober contemplation which examines into the reasons for all choice and avoidance, and which puts to flight the vain opinions from which the greater part of the confusion arises which troubles the soul. Now the beginning and the greatest good of all these things is prudence ((fipovwo-ts), on which ac- count prudence is something more valuable than even phil- osophy, inasmuch as all the other virtues spring from it, teaching us that it is not possible to live pleasantly unless one also lives prudently, and honorably, and justly ; and that one cannot live prudently, and honestly, and justly without living pleasantly, for the virtues are connate with living agreeably, and living agreeably is inseparable from the virtues." And so Epicurus, too, reaches the popular Greek conception that virtue and happiness are inseparable, as the line in the poem expresses it : 'Qs dyados re kol cvbaifxcav dfia ylverai dvfjp. 7. Summarizing the main features of Greek ethics, we may say : It agrees with the popular Greek view that the highest good consists in the perfection of man as a natural being. Special stress is laid upon the development of the intellectual side. Even the popular conception recognizes the great im- portance of the intellect for human perfection, a fact to which the above mentioned work of L. Schmidt on the popular morality of the Greeks repeatedly calls attention. 2 The philosophers, the specific types of the Greek people, as the prophets are of the Israelites, go still further, and make reason the root and crown of all human excellence. For them wisdom or philosophy is both the means and the content oj * De rerum natura. 2 L, 156, 230ff. THE GREEK CONCEPTION 59 eudcemonia — the former, in so far as it acquaints us with the highest good and regulates practical life to the end of realizing it, the latter, in so far as philosophy, or the scien- tific contemplation of the universe, is the highest, freest func- tion of human nature, one that is desired solely for its own sake. It is said that Anaxagoras, being once asked for what end he had been born, answered : " For the contemplation of the sun, and moon, and heaven, and the order governing the entire universe." This is really the answer which the entire Greek philosophy, and the Greek mind in general, gives to the question. At first sight, the conception strikes us as a rather strange one. We are not in the habit of attaching so much impor- tance to the intellectual function ; we neither expect that prudence or insight will always result in right action, nor are we ready to believe that the true mission of man consists in the contemplation of things, or in philosophy. Perhaps we shall understand both points better when we remember how different was the position occupied by scientific knowl- edge among the Greeks from that which it holds in modern life. In our world not only the so-called learned professions, but even scientific research itself, which has been organized by the state in universities and academies, have become branches of industry. As is the case with the manufacture of shoes and watches, a man may, at present, make his liv- ing, and a good living at that, under favorable conditions, by turning out mathematical and philological, scientific and philosophical investigations. This was not the case in Greece, at least not when philosophy first arose. The philosophers emphatically declare that scientific contemplation and pro- fessionalism are absolutely incompatible : the Sophist who attempts to combine them, thereby loses philosophy ; he is, as Plato shows with bitter sarcasm in his Sophist, a dealer in sham wisdom. Heraclitus and Parmenides, Plato and Aris- totle, did not engage in the contemplation of reality for the 60 ORIGINS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY sake of acquiring money or professorships, but solely for its own sake : we work, says Aristotle, in order to have leisure, but the most beautiful way of filling our leisure is philosophy. — This difference in the outward position of scientific research is intimately connected with its altered inner constitution ; modern scientific research, is, as compared with Greek phil- osophy, more like labor, often like petty and arduous labor. The physical or historical investigator of our time employs an enormous apparatus of learning and technical skill, col- lections and instruments, in order to throw light upon some obscure nook of reality which is of little interest in itself, and does not even interest the investigator very much. The result of his work may at some time, in some connection or other, assist us somewhat in understanding reality ; often we cannot see the connection, and it is absolutely immaterial to many an investigator whether his work will contribute any- thing to our knowledge of the whole or not. The Greek philosophers, on the other hand, were happy in the belief that it was possible, and that each one of them would be able to unravel the ultimate mysteries of the uni- verse by pure contemplation. Even Aristotle, the great observer, declares that of all activities, scientific investigation is in least need of external aids; so convinced is he that the apparatus of research is a purely secondary affair. It is plain that a theoretical function which aims to solve all the great problems of the universe and of life with its world-encompass- ing thoughts, has greater significance for the personal life of a man than the investigation of Plautinic metres and the discovery of new methyls and phenyls. When the occupation with such things becomes a sport and is pursued as a sport, it may, like all sports, chess-playing or stamp-collecting, become a matter of immediate interest; but a man will hardly be inclined to regard such work, even though he fol- lows it permanently, as the real object of his existence. If, however, we could hope to unravel the mysteries of the world THE GREEK CONCEPTION 61 and of life by studying philosophy, who would not be inter- ested in it, who would regard it as too trivial? "Let no one," so Epicurus begins the letter quoted above, " delay to study philosophy while he is young, and when he is old let him not become weary of the study ; for no man can ever find the time unsuitable or too late to study the health of his soul. And he who asserts either that it is not yet time to philosophize, or that the hour is passed, is like a man who should say that the time is not yet come to be happy, or that it is too late." The belief in the irresistible power of knowledge, which is expressed in the Socratic statement that knowledge deter- mines conduct, for it is inconceivable that any one should do what he himself regards as wrong (a statement which reap- pears in some form or other in all the philosophers), has manifestly a great deal to do with the position which philos- ophy occupied in the intellectual life of the Greeks. We are perfectly aware that a man may know what to do and still not do it. From our earliest childhood we have been told and have known that we ought not to requite evil with evil but with good, even in the case of our enemies — but who acts accord- ingly ? But, Socrates would have asked us, what do you mean by " knowing " ? Surely not the ability to repeat a lot of words after a person ? For me only a living conviction is knowledge. — " Knowledge," as we often understand it, was something wholly foreign to the Greeks : they had no school instruction in which the memory was crammed with the " knowledge" of others, particularly no instruction in morals and religion. But whenever moral maxims and judgments were inculcated in their youth, as, for example, by the study of Homer, they embodied ethical conceptions which were thoroughly intelligible to the natural man. They did not discriminate, as we do, between a moral creed conned by rote and a morality of the heart. — When, however, his reflec- tions carried a philosopher beyond the popular conceptions 62 ORIGINS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY to new views ; when Socrates, for example, found that it was not as disgraceful to suffer injustice as to do injustice, these were not mere empty words for school children to learn by heart, but represented the personal convictions of the thinker, which could not fail to influence him in his actions. And when Epictetus tells his pupils that the wise man is independent of fate, because everything that really concerns him is in his power, while whatever is not in his power does not concern him, his words are not merely intended to be memorized and recited at confirmations or at final college examinations, but they stand for real experiences, and are therefore capable of arousing strong convictions. Hence I am inclined to believe that there was for the Greeks, and particularly for the Greek philosophers, more truth in the proposition, No one is voluntarily bad, than it seems to us to contain. Mere school and word knowledge, of course, is powerless, but real knowledge, knowledge that represents real personal convictions, cannot fail to influence life. Scientific research, therefore, or philosophy, occupied a position in the personal life of the Greek philosophers which it does not necessarily hold at present, the position, namely, of an end-in-itself. But another factor helped to make spec- ulative life valuable. For the Greek, practical life was syn- onymous with political life. He entertained a low opinion of industrial activity, it was regarded as vulgar ; even the pro- fession of the artist did not escape his contempt. 1 No one 1 This is clearly shown in a little treatise of Lucian's, The Dream, a work, by the way, which is very characteristic of the Greek mode of thought. Science and Art appear in a dream before the boy Lucian ; each tries to persuade him to devote himself to her. In response to the speech of Plastic Art, who holds that she has a claim upon him, because his ancestors were followers of hers, Science answers : " You have heard from this person here what advan- tages you could hope to obtain if you were to become a stone-mason. You would eventually be nothing more than an obscure manual laborer, who depends solely upon his hands for his success, receiving not much more pay than a day -laborer, base and narrow in your mode of thought, having no influence in the THE GREEK CONCEPTION 63 ever dreamed of doing deeds of charity, to which Christian orders devote themselves. Statesmanship, political and mili- tary leadership, was the only profession left. Now, public life in the smaller Grecian city-states had reached such a stage, since the fifth century, that it is not hard to understand why an honest man should have lost all desire to have anything to do with it. The popular assemblies and law-courts were the battle-grounds on which the party-leaders and orators waged bitter war against each other ; they strug- gled to get hold of " the latch of legislation," the decree of the people, in order that they might kill their opponents, or banish them and confiscate their property. The execution of Socrates luridly shows the horrible state of insecurity prevailing in the Greek cities ; it is as though a band of half-grown boys had obtained possession of the sword of the magistracy and were now playing havoc with it. In- deed, this is exactly the impression of Greek political life which we get from the history of Thucydides ; the cities and the parties in every city spent their time in aimless and repul- sive bickerings, they exhibited such baseness and malice, such cruelty and vindictiveness towards the vanquished, as would fill us with aversion, were it not for our deep sympathy with a nation otherwise so gloriously endowed. We can easily understand why men who scrupled against employing the means with which battles were waged and victories won in the popular assemblage, decided to have nothing whatever to do with politics ; most of the later philosophers followed the example of Plato, " who, in the storm of dust and sleet state, equally incapable of making yourself useful to your friends and dangerous to your enemies. — And suppose you should become a Phidias or a Polyclet, and had created a great number of admirable works, every one who saw them would, it is true, extol your art, but surely no one among all your admirers would, so long as he was in his right mind, desire to be what you are. For, however great you might become in your line, you would always be regarded as a miserable handicraftsman, who is compelled to make his living by the work of his hands." These remarks express Lucian's own view, which was evidently the new of all cultured Greeks. 64 ORIGINS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY which the driving wind hurries along, retiring under the shelter of a wall," withdrew from public life. Reflections upon the theme that the philosopher cannot be a politician (rbv bv fir) TroXneveaOaL) are common among the later philosophers. Hence there was but one thing left to them — philosophy. CHAPTER II THE CHRISTIAN CONCEPTION OF LIFE* 1. The conversion of the ancient world to Christianity was the greatest revolution which European humanity experienced. It meant the complete overthrow of all their theories of life, the " transformation of all values " {Die Umwertung alter Werte), to use Nietzsche's expression. In order to draw the lines as sharply as possible, I shall attempt, first of all, to con- trast the Christian doctrine of self-denial in its harsh grandeur with the Greek doctrine of self-preservation. The world always tends to compromises and conciliations ; they are not wanting in ancient Christianity, and in the Middle Ages they are very common, still more so in the development of the Christianity of modern times, as will be seen later on. Here I should like to accentuate the fundamental difference between the Greek and the Christian conception — sharply and one- sidedly if you please — as Christianity itself conceived it at its entrance into the ancient world. The Greek affirmation of the world ( Weltbej ahung) and the Christian negation of the world (Weltiiberwindung*), these are the two paths open to man. 2 1 [See, besides the works of Sidgwick, Wundt, Jodl, Janet, Eucken, mentioned on p. 35 : Gass, Gesckichte der christlichen Ethih ; Bestmann, Geschichte der christlichen Sitte ; Ziegler, Geschichte der christlichen Ethih ; Luthardt, Geschichte, der christlichen Ethih ; Lecky, History of European Morals ; Ueberweg, History of Philosophy, vol. II., §§ 4 and 5 ; Baur, Das Christenthum der drei ersten Jahr- hunderte (Engl, transl. by Allan Menzies) ; Harnack, Dogmengeschichte ; Fisher, The Beginnings of Christianity. Consnlt also the standard Lives of Christ and church histories. For further bibliographical references, see the beginning of the second volume of Ueberweg ; also Weber-Thilly, p. 9, note 2. — Tr.] 2 The exposition which follows has been criticised, on the ground that it rep- resents Christianity as a weak, meek, world-weary, down-trodden, ascetic affair. That is not the impression which I intended to create. Christianity was at firit 5 66 ORIGINS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY The Greeks regarded the perfect development of the natural powers of man as the great aim of life. Christianity, on the other hand, clearly and consciously sets up the opposite as the goal of life : the death of the natural, and the resurrection of a new, supernatural man. " Except a man be born again," so Christ teaches Nicodemus, "he cannot see the kingdom of God " ; the repentance {jxztclvqkx) which Christ demands, with John the Baptist, 1 is in truth a regeneration. The old and the new man are opposed to each other as the flesh (adplj*) and the spirit (7rvev/jLa). 2 Paul logically defines this antithe- sis : there is a twofold life, the life after the flesh and the life after the spirit; the former the life of the natural man, the latter, the effect of grace ; the former intent upon perishable things and leading to death, the latter turned toward eternity and leading to eternal life : " for he that soweth to his flesh shall of the flesh reap corruption ; but he that soweth to the spirit shall of the spirit reap life everlasting." 3 The new life is the death of the old ; through the spirit the deeds of the body are mortified. 4 This character of the new religion is expressed in its sacred acts. We enter into Christianity through baptism; it is called by Paul a likeness (o/W&)/xa) 5 of the death of Jesus ; certainly not a negative, but a very positive thing ; it was not characterized by feelings of depression and dejection, but by a feeling of cheerful certainty, the certainty of possessing a treasure beyond all other treasures. And from this conviction sprang the proud feeling of freedom, with which the Christian opposed the " world " and its regulations, society and its conventional values, the law and its pedantic formalism. — But my main purpose here was to contrast it sharply with the Greek conception of life and morality, and hence I first considered Christianity from its negative side, the side which distinguishes it as something entirely new in the world. Besides, Christianity now and then becomes conscious of its original negative relation to the " world " and the kingdom which is of this world, and so, in my opinion, regains some of its pristine essence and strength. A Christianity entirely reconciled and at peace with the world is a weak and powerless affair, and surely not the real and original Christianity. True Chris- tianity may always be recognized by the fact that it seems strange and danger- ous to the world. 1 Math., iv., 17. 2 John, iii., 6. * Rom., viii., 13. • Gal., Ti., 8. * Rom., vi., 5. THE CHRISTIAN CONCEPTION 67 a very intelligible symbol, so long as Christianity was at war with the world ; it was a serious reminder of the bloody bap- tism which might follow the water baptism. The other sacra- ment is no less suggestive of death ; by eating the body and drinking the blood of Jesus, the believers celebrate the mem- ory of his sacrificial death, themselves forming a community consecrated to a bloody sacrifice. It is likewise worthy of note that the new churches usually also served as burial- places, that the bones of the martyrs were interred in the altar itself. The natural man dreads contact with death ; it is a pollution, according to the Greek as well as the Jewish con- ception, even in the religious sense, while to the Christian, death is a familiar thought; it is the entrance into life. 2. The entire Christian life is permeated with this concep- tion. What the old or the natural man desires or values is regarded by the new man as worthless or dangerous; and conversely, the sufferings and privations which the former seeks to escape, the latter regards as salutary and beneficial. Let me point out the main differences between the two theories of life. The perfection and exercise of the intellectual capacities seemed to the Greeks a highly important, to their philosophers an absolutely necessary, function of human life. The attitude of primitive Christianity towards reason and natural knowl- edge is one of contempt and distrust. The poor in spirit are blessed by Jesus; the people who follow him are poor and uncultured ; what is hidden from the wise and prudent is revealed to children. Nay, natural reason and wisdom are really a stumbling-block to the kingdom of God, the preach- ing of the cross is foolishness to it. " Where is the wise ? " Paul asks the congregation at Corinth, 1 " where is the scribe ? where is the disputer of this world ? hath not God made foolish the wisdom of this world? For after that in the wisdom of God the world by wisdom knew not God, it pleased 1 1 Cor. I, 20. 68 ORIGINS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY God by the foolishness of preaching to save them that believe." The church did not strictly adhere to this view ; as a church she could not adhere to it. When she began to dominate the entire life of the peoples, she was compelled to press into her service the most important instrument of temporal power, knowledge. But primitive Christianity stood in no posi- tive relation to worldly, scientific knowledge. " The form of a servant, the spiritual form, disappeared in the third century when brilliant teachers of the church and even rich bishops appeared ; but in its poor form Christianity overcame the world." 2 And we may note the after-effects of this original relation in the entire history of the Christian church life : I am thinking not merely of the Christian's distrust of scientific investigation and the law of obedience, which the intellect, too, was expected to observe — a law, it is true, which often sprang from very worldly motives — but, above all, of that simplicity of heart which always succeeded in minimizing, among all true believers in Christ, those differences of culture and knowledge, which hinder the free interchange of thought in the personal intercourse of the worldly-minded. And deeply religious natures have always shown an aversion to puffed-up learning, to the spirit of criticism and negation, which springs from arrogance and begets arrogance, to the mania for systems, and to scientific pride. Hence the virtues of the intellect, freedom and boldness of thought and the power to doubt, the vital principle of scien- tific research, are, in the eyes of primitive Christianity; worthless and dangerous. Faith and obedience are becoming to the Christian. 3. Like the virtues of the intellect, so are also the ethical virtues of the Greeks, which are nothing but natural impulses educated and disciplined by the reason, worthless and dan- gerous, according to the conception of primitive Christianity ; 1 Hase, Kirchengeschichte, 1, 258. THE CHRISTIAN CONCEPTION 69 the more dangerous because they seem good : they are splen* did vices. " Though it may seem laudable that the soul govern the body, and reason the vicious impulses, yet the soul and reason itself, cannot by any means, unless it serve God, as God himself has prescribed it, govern them in the right way. For what kind of a lord of the body and of the vices can a mind be, which, being ignorant of the true God and not sub- ject to his governance, is prostituted and corrupted by the demons polluted with all the vices ? And the virtues them- selves, if they bear no relation to God, are in truth vices rather than virtues ; for although they are regarded by many as truly moral when they are desired as ends in themselves and not for the sake of something else, they are, nevertheless, inflated and arrogant (inflatce ao superbce), and therefore not to be viewed as virtues but as vices." This is St. Augustine's opinion of all purely human virtues. 1 4. In the opinion of the natural man, courage is the chief 1 De Civitate Dei, xix., 25. — In his Confessions he moralizes upon his own past life from this standpoint : everything natural and human in it was an alienation from God and therefore reprehensible. With tiresome monotony he passes from one period of his life to the other, and shows the emptiness and baseness of all those acts of his which sprang from his natural impulses. That the nursling cried for the breast, that the boy took pleasure in his sports and the youth in rhetorical exercises, that he was ambitious for distinction and fame, that he was devoted to friends and followed his natural sexual impulses, that he admired distinguished teachers and dedicated his maiden works to a revered man, that as a teacher he gathered young men about him and joyfully and zealously instructed them in knowledge and in eloquence, that he passionately searched for the truth and believed that he would find it in the philosophers : all this he now condemns from his newly acquired Christian-ecclesiastical standpoint : it was nothing but vanity, foolishness, and carnal corruption. One point alone, which the purely numan judgment would perhaps regard as the blackest spot in the previous life of the Saint, he passes over without a single word of blame; his resolution, namely, to abandon a woman who had been his mistress for years, and who had borne him a son, and, at the instigation of his mother, to marry a woman of his own rank. This resolution — which his mistress prevented him from carrying out — this intended act of faithlessness to a woman whom he loved, but could not marry for social reasons, he passes over without a complaint, without a word of self-reproach, only to condemn himself violently immediately after for his in- ability to resist his longing for her even after the separation. So completely do his feelings differ from the natural human feelings. TO ORIGINS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY virtue ; it is, as Greek and Roman popular usage implies, the virtue or excellence as such, and its absence is equivalent to absolute unworthiness. Courage is based upon the impulse of self-preservation ; it ensures the success of the ego and its claims in the struggle with those opposing it. The Christian, who obeys the law of God, " resists not evil," he does not combat it, but endures it ; patience or patient waiting {viro/jiovrj) is his courage. He does not wield the sword. The sword is the instrument by which to obtain one's share of the world ; the Christian has and desires no part in the world ; his heritage is in the future world, it cannot be won or lost by the sword. The old church is thoroughly imbued with the thought that a Christian cannot wield the sword. Even though the times soon accommodated themselves to the necessities of life, we can hardly suppose that they did so without some misgivings. Christian soldiers were, beyond doubt, regarded as an anomaly in the congregation, during the earlier centuries. Tertullian expresses the conviction of the primitive Christian, though in a more emphatic and categorical manner, when he says : " It is impossible to swear fealty to God and to man, to serve under the banner of Christ and under the standard of the devil, in the camp of light and in the camp of darkness ; one soul cannot serve two masters, God and the Emperor. When the Lord deprived Peter of the sword, he disarmed all." * It surely seemed an absolute con- tradiction for a clericus to wear the sword. Among all the sects which renew the old Christian mode of life, the dread of shedding blood at once reappears in its original strength. The same feeling asserts itself against capital punishment. How far removed the modern world is from the old Christian conception is perhaps nowhere so clearly seen as here : the fear of the sword and of bloodshed has wholly disappeared — disappeared even from the church. The great military heroes are the national saints of the modern nations, the 1 De idoJoJatria, chapter 19. THE CHRISTIAN CONCEPTION 71 anniversaries of victorious battles are celebrated as public holidays, the streets and squares of our cities are named after bloody battle-fields. In the schools our children learn the history of wars, which comprises the chief part of the history of mankind ; the victories of our nation over our neighbors are regarded as its most important and grandest achievements. In the churches prayers are offered every Sunday for the royal arms on water and on land. The modern Christian has no fault to find with all this — a sure sign that he differs from the primitive Christian, who proved his courage solely by his patient suffering and heroic martyrdom. 1 5. Related to the virtue of courage is the virtue of justice, by which we mean that strong sense of justice which every- where insists upon the right, the right of others as well as of self. Not to do wrong is one side of justice ; its comple- ment is not to permit wrong to be done, either to self or to others. This is what the Greeks and Romans understood by the duty of justice, and so Jhering has recently interpreted it in his book, TJte Battle for the Right? The law-suit, or the legal battle for the right, is the civil form of self-preser- vation and self-assertion, of which the sword is the military form. Primitive Christianity does not recognize justice in this sense as a virtue ; it is acquainted with only one side of it, with the duty not to do wrong, not with the duty not to per- mit wrong. It does not say : If a man injures you and tram- ples upon your rights, you ought or are allowed to resist him by lawful means ; but the law of Moses : An eye for an eye, a tooth for a tooth, is expressly abrogated and replaced by a new law : " But I say unto you, that ye resist not evil (t&> TTovrjpq)'), but whosoever shall smite thee on thy right cheek, turn to him the other also. And if any man will sue thee at law, and take away thy coat, let him have thy cloak 1 [See Herbert Spencer, Induction of Ethics, §§ 115, 118, 192. — T*-l * Der Kampf urns Recht. 72 ORIGINS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY also, and whosoever shall compel thee to go a mile, go with him twain." * And a few verses further back we read : 2 "Agree with thine adversary (tg5 avTihlfcw) quickly, while thou art in the way with him." Hence not only anger and hatred and private revenge, but law-suits are explicitly pro- hibited. This is also St. Paul's notion of it : he strictly for- bids the Corinthians to go to law before heathen judges, before the unjust, who are not esteemed in the church : " Is it so that there is not a wise man among you ? no, not one that shall be able to judge between his brethren ? " And then he proceeds : " Now therefore there is utterly a fault among you, because ye go to law with one another. Why do ye not rather take wrong ? Why do ye not rather suffer yourselves to be defrauded ? " 3 Even though this law was not always observed among the old Christians, it was undoubtedly recognized as binding ; they felt the same dread of the law- suit as a means of defending their individual rights as of the sword. 4 In this respect, too, the difference between modern and primitive Christianity is apparent enough. We regard it as the most natural thing in the world to go to law for our rights, or to turn over to the judge for punishment a man who has damaged our body and life, our honor and property. I am not saying that this is right or wrong ; all I mean to imply is that in doing these things we are undoubtedly acting contrary to the spirit of primitive Christianity. 6. This determined the attitude of the Christian towards 1 Matt., v., 38-41. 2 Verse 25. 8 1 Cor., vi., 7. 4 It must be confessed, however, that a passage in the Gospel {Matt., xviii., 15-17) inclines to a more positive treatment of this side of life : " Moreover, if thy brother shall trespass against thee, go and tell him his fault between thee and him alone : if he shall hear thee, thou hast gained thy brother. But if he will not hear thee, then take with thee ,one or two more, that in the mouth of two or three witnesses every word may be established. And if he shall neglect to hear them, tell it unto the church ; but if he neglect to hear the church, let him be unto thee as a heathen man and a publican/' However, not a single word is said of the law-suit and the law. THE CHRISTIAN CONCEPTION 73 fche state. The Greek and Roman regarded participation in the affairs of state as the highest and most important duty of man. The primitive Christian, who did not value the fund- amental political virtues, courage and the sense of justice, looked upon the state as something alien to himself and the inner principle of his life : in the state men wrangle over the things of this world, employing the means of this world ; war and courts of justice are its two fundamental functions. The primitive Christian's attitude to this entire institution was one of forbearance. He formed a part of it, as he formed a part of the world in general, as a stranger and a pilgrim ; he had even less interest in it than the member of another state. — As a passive citizen, however, his conduct was exemplary : he was obedient in all things which were not contrary to his divine mission ; he willingly paid taxes ; he obeyed all laws which prohibited wrong-doing, not only on account of the punishment, but for conscience' sake, and in so far as the magistracy realized justice, it was recognized as the order and instrument of God. When, however, he was asked to act in vio- lation of his conscience, then, of course, he could not obey ; he would not sacrifice to the gods or to the Emperor, nor swear in their name ; he thereby declared that there was something higher for him than the state, namely the kingdom of God, of which he considered himself a citizen, and he would allow no command of earthly rulers to turn him aside from the duties which this citizenship imposed upon him. But here, too, he rendered obedience in so far as he accepted the punishment which was inflicted upon him, without opposition and complaint. — Hence the Christians were both submissive to authority and yet inwardly free in their attitude to the state, something which the ancient citizen neither could be nor cared to be. — Can a Christian be an officer of the state ? In the earlier times there was little occasion for discussing the question : it was not the powerful and the noble after the flesh who first came to the community of Christ, but the ignoble and the despised in the 74 ORIGINS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY eyes of the world. It would undoubtedly have been regarded as a strange contradiction to serve both the crucified one and the lord of this world. In Tertullian the spirit of primitive Christianity strongly protests against the gradual seculariza- tion of the church. " By despising the power and the glory of this world," he declares, 1 " the Lord rejected it and condemned it, and reckoned it among the things which are the pride of the devil. If they were his, he would not have condemned them ; but that which is not of God can belong to no one but the devil. And this, too, may remind you that all the powers and dignitaries of this world are not only foreign to God, but hostile to him, the fact namely, that they condemn the servants of God to death, but forget the punishments which are intended for criminals." Even as late as the year 305 the synod of Elvira decreed : Whoever holds the office of duumvir must stand aloof from the church during his term of office. 2 Not until the conversion of Constantine, when Christianity became a state religion, did a complete change take place : now the officers of the state became the repre- sentatives and the defenders of " Christianity," and the clergy in a sense became state officers. And at present many are perhaps inclined to believe, reversing the words of Paul, 8 that the preservation of Christianity is the especial business of the wise and powerful, the cultured and high-born, and that it would die out if the princes and lords of this world and their servants did not take care of it. 7. The fourth cardinal virtue, after wisdom, courage, and justice, is, according to the Greek conception, o-ocxfcpocrvvri, or temperance. It is the state of the healthy-minded man, who understands the art of moderate and beautiful enjoyment, and can also do without things when necessary. Greek education endeavored to cultivate this virtue : by means of the gym- 1 De idol., chap. 18. 2 Uhlhorn, Die christliche Liebesthatigkeit in der alten Kirche, p. 356. See alsa Gass, Geschichte der christlichen Ethik (1881), i, 92 ff. « 1 Cor., i. 26. THE CHKISTIAN CONCEPTION 75 nastic and musical arts, the two phases of education, it strove to inculcate in the body and the soul of the young the power of self-control and the faculty of enjoying themselves beautifully. The gymnastic and musical contests formed the climax of national pleasure ; to participate in them, as a competitor for the wreath and as a spectator, was culture (rraiZevcris). The attitude of primitive Christianity towards enjoyment was an entirely different one, and hence could not recognize this virtue, or only recognize its negative side, as in the case of justice : the ability to resist the allurements of pleasure. The Christian fled from earthly-sensuous pleasure in every form; even though it might not be sinful in itself, it was too apt to endanger the soul, by fettering it to that which is earthly and perishable, and impeding the free flight of the spirit to eternity. With fearful earnestness Jesus commands us to pluck out and cast from us every member that offends us : for it is better to enter into glory lame and disfigured and without eyes, " than that thy whole body should be cast into hell." " Love not the world, neither the things that are in the world. If any man love the world the love of the Father is noo in him. For all that is in the world, the lust of the flesh, and the lust of the eyes, and the pride of life, is not of the Father, but is of the world." So the Apostle John ad- monishes the Christians in his first letter, debarring not merely coarse sensuous pleasure, but also aesthetical pleasure (the lust of the eyes) and everything that makes this life glorious and grand (aXa^oveia tov fiiov) in the eyes of the children of this world. So, too, the first letter of Peter 1 beseeches the brethren : as strangers and pilgrims to abstain from fleshly lusts, which war against the soul. And Paul does not weary of admonishing those who are of Christ to crucify the flesh. Nowhere, however, are we exhorted to make the body and the soul capable of enjoying the beautiful pleasures of life, or to train the physical and spiritual powers for par* 1 ii., 11. 76 ORIGINS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY ticipation in gymnastic exercises and games, or in the cheerful play of poetry and art. The education of a Christian has an entirely different object in view from the education of the Greek : it must open our eyes to the vanity and transitoriness of this life, and to its awful seriousness, inasmuch as the eternal life depends upon how we live here. Musical and gymnastic arts, however, are not suited to prepare us for eternal life ; they are sown in the flesh and are raised in cor- ruption. How can a Christian who aspires to the imperish- able crown strive after the virtues by which wreaths are won at heathen games ? Who can find pleasure in the fables of the poets, when he can hear the words of the Lord and the apostles ? How can he strive for " culture " who is struggling for " holiness " ? All this is so self-evident that it does not even have to be mentioned : in a true Christian even the desire for such things is inconceivable. Among the Christians it is not culture and eloquence that are prized, but silence. Silence is the first duty recommended by Ambrosius in his work on the duties of the clergy i 1 "It is written : By thy words thou shalt be condemned. Hence why wilt thou rush into the danger of perdition by speaking, when thou mayst be safe by keeping silence ? I have seen many fall into sin by speaking, but hardly a single one by keeping silence. Hence he is wise who can be silent." And soon after he says : 2 " There may be decent and amiable jests, but they are not compatible with the rules of the church ; how can we make use of that which does not appear in the Scriptures. We must also avoid the fables of the poets, lest they weaken the firmness of our resolutions. Woe unto you that laugh now, for ye shall mourn and weep : so says the Lord ; and shall we seek for matter to laugh at here that we may weep hereafter ? I believe we must not only avoid wanton jests, but all jests ; one thing alone is proper : a mouth full of sweetness and grace." 1 De off. ministrorum, I., 2. 2 I., 28. THE CHRISTIAN CONCEPTION 77 8. This also determines the attitude of Christianity to earthly goods. Since wealth is, first of all, a means to sen- suous good living, and secondly, to beautiful enjoyment and culture, he who does not value these things, cannot approve of the means which make them possible. Riches have no value for the Christian ; he has enough when he possesses what suffices to satisfy his daily needs. But riches are not only worthless, they are dangerous. There is, of course, nothing sinful in possession as such, in itself it is abso- lutely indifferent; but wealth is a serious menace to the owner, in so far as it constantly tempts him to use it, and thus enslaves the soul. Nothing recurs so frequently in the Gospels as the warning against the dangers of riches. It seems almost impossible to Jesus that a rich man should enter into the kingdom of God ; it is easier for a camel to go through the eye of a needle. Wealth makes us eager for this world and careless of the hereafter, as the rich man learned when he reaped a good harvest and soon began to meditate what to do and where to bestow his fruits ; wealth sates us and makes us indifferent to the wants of our neighbors, as Dives learned before whose door poor Lazarus lay ; wealth alienates God from us, for he allows no other God beside himself: ye cannot serve God and mammon. Therefore, Jesus commanded his disciples that they should take noth- ing for their journey : no scrip, no bread, no money in their purse, when he sent them out to preach ; and it surely was not an accident that Judas, who carried the purse, most likely because he was the ablest financier of the twelve, should have turned traitor. Hence the urgent entreaty to the good young man to give up his riches : " Go thy way, sell whatever thou hast, and give to the poor, and thou shalt have treasure in heaven." Interpreters of the Gospel are in the habit of protesting against the misconception that Christ actually commanded the young man to give up his riches. Clement of Alexandria 78 ORIGINS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY earlj r pointed out, in his discussion of the question, What Rich Man will be Saved ? that the command to sell everything and give to the poor, did not mean, as some hastily assume, that he should abandon his possessions, but merely his false opinions with respect to them, his love and greed for them. This ingenious discovery has been made over and over again. According to the same art of interpretation, we might reason : When a mother tells her child who has taken hold of a sharp knife, to lay the knife aside, this does not mean that he should put it down, but only that he should not cut himself with it ; that he may keep the knife. — Would the young man have gone away grieved if Jesus himself had thus interpreted his saying for him ? I believe he would at once have replied : " This have I observed from my youth." Here, again, I am not deciding whether the command of Jesus ought to be obeyed, or whether it could possibly be obeyed universally ; I am simply defending its true and un- mistakable meaning against all sorts of interpretations which attempt to bring the Gospel into harmony with the world. We hear it said that the fulfilment of this law would destroy oiir entire civilized life. It is very probable that it would. But what does that prove ? Where is it written that it should be preserved ? Tertullian answers the objection of those who refused to obey the law against the pursuit of handicrafts or trades relating to heathen worship, on the ground that they must live, by asking the question: Must you live ? What companionship have you with God, if you desire to live according to your own laws ? You will suffer want ? But the Lord calls those that suffer blessed. You cannot support yourselves ? But the Lord says : Take no thought for your life ; consider the lilies of the field. 9. Let us now compare the Greek with the Christian view of honor. According to the Greek conception, the love of honor is a virtue : the just man desires to be the first in his sphere (7rp