ee agents. Suppose that, in the external revela- tion, the Scriptures, the fact is revealed and affirmed that we are not free but necessary agents. Has not God himself affirmed in one revelation what he has denied in another ? Of what use can the internal revelation be, but to render us necessarily sceptical in respect to the external ? Has the Most High given two such revelations as this ? 2. fn the Scriptures, man is presented as the sub- ject, and, of course, as possessing those powers which render him the proper subject of command and prohibition, of obligation, of merit and demerit, and consequently of reward and punishment. Let us suppose that God has imparted to a being a cer- tain constitution, and then placed him in a condition in which, in consequence of the necessary correla- tion between his constitution and circumstances, but one series of determinations are possible to'him, 6* 62 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. and that series cannot but result. Can we conceive it proper in the Most High to prohibit that creature from pursuing the course which God himself has rendered it impossible for him not to pursue, and require him, under the heaviest sanctions, to pursue, under these identical circumstances, a different and opposite course — a course which the Creator has rendered it impossible for him to pursue 1 Is this the philoso- phy pre-supposed in the Bible ? Does the Bible im- ply a system of mental philosophy which renders the terms, obligation, merit and demerit, void of all con- ceivable meaning, and which lays no other founda- tion for moral retributions but injustice and tyranny? 3. Let us now contemplate the doings of the Great Day revealed in the Scriptures, in the light of these two opposite theories. Let us suppose that, as the righteous and the wicked stand in distinct and separate masses before the Eternal One, the Most High says to the one class, " You, 1 myself placed in circumstances in which nothing but obedience was possible, and that you could not but render ; and you, I placed in a condition in which nothing but disobe- dience was possible to you, and that you could not but perpetrate. In consequence of these distinct and opposite courses, each of which I myself ren- dered unavoidable, you deserve and shall receive my eternal smiles; and you as richly deserve and shall therefore endure my eternal frowns." What would be the response of an assembled universe to a de- LIBERTY AND NECESSITY. 63 cision based upon such a principle ? Is this the prin- ciple on which the decisions of that Day are based ? It must be so, if the doctrine of Liberty is not, and that of Necessity is, the doctrine of the Bible ? 4. We will now contemplate another class of pas- sages which have a bearing equally decisive upon our present inquiries. I refer to that class in which God expresses the deepest regret at the course which transgressors have pursued, and are still pursuing, and the most decisive unwillingness that they should pur- sue that course and perish. He takes a solemn oath, that he is not willing that they should take the course of disobedience and death, but that they should pursue a different and opposite course. God expresses no regret that they are in the circumstances in which they are, but that in those circumstances they should take the path of disobedience, and not that of obedience. Now, can we suppose, what must be true, if the doctrine of Necessity is the doctrine pre- supposed in the Bible, that God places his creatures in circumstances in which obedience is to them an impossibility, and in which they cannot but disobey, and then takes a solemn oath that he is not willing that they should disobey and perish, " but that they should turn from their evil way and live ?" What is the meaning of the exclamation, "O that thou hadst hearkened to my commandment," if God himself had so conditioned the sinner as to render obedience an impossibility to him ? Is this the philosophy of the 64 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. Will pre-supposed in the Bible ? On the other hand, how perfectly in place are all the passages under consideration, on the supposition that the doctrine of Liberty is the doctrine therein pre-supposed, and that consequently the obedience which God affirms Himself desirous that sinners should render, and his regret that they do not render, is always possible to them ! One of the seven pillars of the Gospel is this very doctrine. Take it from the Bible, and we have " another Gospel." 5. One other class of passages claims special at- tention here. In the Scriptures, the Most High ex- presses the greatest astonishment that men should sin under the influences to which he has subjected them. He calls upon heaven and earth to unite with him in astonishment at the conduct of men under those influences. " Hear, O heavens, and give ear, O earth," he exclaims, " for the Lord hath spoken ; I have nourished and brought up children, and they have rebelled against me." Now, let us sup- pose, as the doctrine of Necessity affirms, that God has placed sinners under influences under which they cannot but sin. What must we think of his con- duct in calling upon the universe to unite with him in astonishment, that under these influences they should sin — that is, take the only course possible to them, the course which they cannot but take ? With the same propriety, he might place a mass of water on an inclined plane, and then call upon heaven and LIBERTY AND NECESSITY. 65 earth to unite with him in astonishment at the downward flow of the fluid. Is this the philosophy pre-supposed in the Bible ? SEC. 3. VIEWS OF NECESSITARIANS. We are now prepared for a consideration of cer- tain miscellaneous questions which have an import- ant bearing upon our present inquiries. NECESSITY AS HELD BY NECESSITARIANS. I. The first inquiry that presents itself is this : Do Necessitarians hold the doctrine of Necessity as de- fined in this chapter % Do they really hold, in respect to every act of will, that, in the circumstances of its occurrence, that one act only is possible, and that can- not but arise ? Is this, for example, the doctrine of Edwards ? Is it the doctrine really held by those who professedly agree with him % I argue that it is : 1. Because they unanimously repudiate the doc- trine of Liberty as here defined. They must, there- fore, hold that of Necessity ; inasmuch as no third re- lation is even conceivable or possible. If they deny that the phenomena of the Will fall under either of these relations, and still call themselves Necessitarians, they must hold to an inconceivable something, which themselves even do not understand and cannot de- fine, and which has and can have no real existence. 2. Edwards has confounded the phenomena of the Will with those of the Sensibility which are necessary in the sense here defined. He must, therefore, hold 66 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. that the characteristics of the latter class belong to those of the former. 3. Edwards represents the relation between motives and acts of Will, as being the same in kind as that which exists between causes and effects among exter- nal material substances. The former relation he de- signates by the words moral necessity ; the latter, by that of natural^ or philosophical, or physical necessity. Yet he says himself, that the difference expressed by these words " does not lie so much in the nature of the connection as in the two terms connected." The qualifying terms used, then, designate merely the na- ture of the antecedents and consequents, while the nature of the connection between them is, in all in- stances, the same, that of naked necessity. 4. Edwards himself represents moral necessity as just as absolute as physical, or natural necessity. " Moral necessity may be," he says, " as absolute as natural necessity. That is, the effect may be as per- fectly connected with its moral cause as a natural necessary effect is with its natural cause." 5. Necessitarians represent the relation between motives and acts of Will as that of cause and effect; and for this reason necessary. "If," says Edwards, " every act of Will is excited by some motive, then that motive is the cause of that act of Will." " And if volitions are properly the effects of their motives, then they are necessarily connected with their mo- tives," Now, as the relation of cause and effect LIBERTY AND NECESSITY. 67 i§ necessary, in the sense of the term Necessity as above defined, Edwards must hold, and design to teach, that all acts of Will are necessary in this sense. 6. Necessitarians represent the connection between motives and acts of Will as being;, in all instances, the same in kind as that which exists between voli- tions and external actions. " As external actions," says President Day, " are directed by the Will, so the Will itself is directed by influence." Now all admit, that the connection between volitions and ex- ternal actions is necessary in this sense, that when we will such action it cannot but take place. No other act is, in the circumstances, possible. In the same sense, according to Necessitarians, is every act of Will necessarily connected with influence, or mo- tives. We do Necessitarians no wrong, therefore, when we impute to them the doctrine of Necessity as here defined. In all cases of sin, they hold, that an individual is in circumstances in which none but sinful acts of Will are possible, and these he cannot but put forth ; and that in these identical circum- stances the sinner is under obligation infinite to put forth different and opposite acts. THE TERM, CERTAINTY, AS USED BY NECESSITARIANS. II. We are prepared for another important inquiry, to wit : whether the words, certainty, moral certainty, &c, as used by Necessitarians, are identical in their meaning with that of Necessity as above defined ? 68 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. The doctrine of Necessity would never be received by the public at all, but for the language in which it is clothed, language which prevents the public seeing it as it is. At one time it is called Moral, in distinc- tion from Natural Necessity. At another, it is said to be nothing but Certainty, or moral Certainty, &c. Now the question arises, what is this Certainty 1 Is it or is it not, real Necessity, and nothing else ? That it is, I argue, 1. From the fact, as shown above, that there can possibly be no Certainty, which does not fall either under the relation of Liberty or Necessity as above defined. The Certainty of Necessitarians does not, according to their own showing, fall under the former relation : it must, therefore, fall under the latter. It must be naked Necessity, and nothing else. 2. While they have defined the term Necessity, and have not that of Certainty, they use the latter term as avowedly synonymous with the former. The latter, therefore, must be explained by the former, and not the former by the latter. 3. The Certainty which they hold is a certainty which avowedly excludes the possibility of different and opposite acts of Will under the influences, or mo- tives, under which particular acts are put forth. The Certainty under consideration, therefore, is not neces- sity of a particular kind, a necessity consistent with liberty and moral obligation. It is the Necessity above defined, in all its naked deformity. LIBERTY AND NECESSITY. 69 III. We are now prepared for a distinct statement of the doctrine of Ability, according to the Necessi- tarian scheme. Even the Necessitarians, with very few exceptions, admit, that in the absence of all power to do right or wrong, we can be under no ob- ligation to do the one or avoid the other. " A man," says Pres. Day, " is not responsible for remaining in his place if he has no power to move. He is not culpable for omitting to walk, if he has no strength to walk. He is not under obligation to do anything for which he has not what Edwards calls natural power." It is very important for us to understand the nature of this ability, which lies at the foundation of moral obligation ; to understand, I repeat, what this Ability is, according to the theory under consider- ation. This Ability, according to the doctrine of Lib- erty, has been well stated by Cousin, to wit : " The moment we take the resolution to do an action, we take it with a consciousness of being able to take a contrary resolution ;" and by Dr. Dwight, who says of a man's sin, that it is " chosen by him unnecessa- rily, while possessed of a power to choose otherwise." The nature of this Ability, according to the Necessi- tarian scheme, has been stated with equal distinct- ness in the Christian Spectator. " If we take this term [Ability or Power] in the absolute sense, as in- cluding all the antecedents to a given volition, there is plainly no such thing as power to the contrary ; for in this sense of the term, as President Day states, 7 70 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. u a man never has power to do anything but what he actually performs." " In this comprehensive, though rather unusual sense of the word," says President Day, a a man has not power to do anything which he does not do." The meaning of the above ex- tracts cannot be mistaken. Nor can any one deny that they contain a true exposition of the doctrine of Necessity, to wit : that under the influences under which men do will, and consequently act, it is absolute- ly impossible for them to will and act differently from what they do. In what sense, then, have they power to will and act differently according to this doctrine ? To this question President Day has given a correct and definite answer. " The man who wills in a par- ticular way, under the influence of particular feel- ings, might will differently under a different influ- ence." Now, what is the doctrine of Ability, according to this scheme ? A man, for example, commits an act of sin. He ought, in the stead of that act, to have put forth an act of obedience. Without the power to render this obedience, as President Day admits, there can be no obligation to do it. When the Ne- cessitarian says, that the creature, when he sins, has power to obey, he means, not that under the influence under which the act of sin is committed, the creature has power to obey ; but that under a different influ- ence he might obey. But mark, it is under the iden- tical influence under which a man does sin, and un- LIBERTY AND NECESSITY. 71 der which, according to the doctrine of Necessity, he cannot bat sin, that he is required not to sin. Now how can a man's ability, and obligation not to sin under a given influence, grow out of the fact, that, under a different influence, an influence under which he cannot but do right, he might not sin ? This is all the ability and ground of obligation as far as Ability, Natural Ability as it is called, is concerned, which the doctrine of Necessity admits. A man is, by a power absolutely irresistible, placed in circum- stances in which he cannot possibly but sin. In these circumstances, it is said, that he has natural ability not to sin, and consequently ought not to do it. Why ? Because, to his acting differently, no change in his nature or powers is required. These are " perfect and entire, wanting nothing." All that is required is, that his circumstances be changed, and then he might not sin. " In what sense," asks President Day, " is it true, that a man has power to will the contrary of what he actually wills ? He has such power that, with a sufficient inducement, he will make an opposite choice." Is not this the strangest idea of Natural Ability as constituting the foundation of obligation, of which the human mind ever tried to conceive ? In illustration, let us suppose that a man, placed in the city of New York, cannot but sin ; placed in that of Boston, he cannot but be holy, and that the fact whether he is in the one or the other city depends upon the irresistible providence of God. He is placed in 72 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. New York where he cannot but sin. He is told that he ought not to do it, and that he is highly guilty for not being perfectly holy. It is also asserted that he has all the powers of moral agency, all the ability requisite to lay the foundation for the highest con- ceivable obligation to be holy. What is the evidence ? he asks. Is it possible for me, in my present circum- stances, to avoid sin ? and in my present circum- stances, you know, I cannot but be. I acknowledge, the Necessitarian says, that under present influences, you cannot but sin, and that you cannot but be sub- ject to these influences. Still, I affirm, that you have all the powers of moral agency, all the natural abili- ty requisite to obedience, and to the highest conceiva- ble obligation to obedience. Because, in the first place, even in New York, you could obey if you chose. You have, therefore, natural, though not moral, power to obey. But stop, friend, right here. When you say that I might obey, if I chose, I would ask, if choosing, as in the command, " choose life, 5 ' is not the very thing required of me % When, therefore, you affirm that I might obey, if I chose, does it not mean, in reality, that I might choose, if I should choose 1 Is not your Natural Ability this, that I might obey if I did obey 1* I cannot * The above is a perfectly correct statement of the famous distinction between natural and moral ability made by Neces- sitarians. The sinner is under obligation to do right, they say, because he might do what is required of him, if he chose LIBERTY AND NECESSITY. 73 deny, the Necessitarian replies, that you have correctly stated this doctrine. Permit me to pro- ceed in argument, however. In the next place, all that you need in order to be holy as required, is a change, not of your powers , but of the influences which control the action of those powers. With no change in your constitution or powers, you need only to be placed in Boston instead of New York, and there you cannot but be holy. Is it not as clear as light, therefore, that you have now all the powers of moral agency, all the ability requisite to the high- est conceivable obligation to be holy instead of sinful 1 I fully understand you, the sinner replies. But remember, that it is not in Boston, where, as you acknowledge, I cannot be, that I am required not to sin ; but here, in New York, where I cannot but be, and cannot possibly but sin. It is here, and not some- where else, that I am required not to sin. How can the'fact, that if I were in Boston, where I could not but be holy, I might not sin, prove, that here, in New to do it. He has, therefore, natural but not moral power to obedience. But the choice which the sinner wants, the absence of which constitutes his moral inability, is the very thing required of him. When, therefore, the Necessi- tarian says, that the sinner is under obligation to obey, be- cause he might obey if he chose to do it, the real meaning is, that the sinner is under obligation to obedience, because if he should choose to obey he would choose to obey. In other words he is under obligation to obedience, because, if he did obey, he would obey. 7# 74 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. York, I have any ability, either natural or moral — am under any obligation whatever — not to sin 1 These are the difficulties which press upon me. How do you remove them according to your theory ? I can give no other answer, the Necessitarian re- plies, than that already given. If that does not si- lence for ever every excuse for sin in your mind, it is wholly owing to the perverseness of your heart, to its bitter hostility to the truth. I may safely appeal to the Necessitarian himself, whether I have not here given an uncaricatured expose of his theory. SINFUL INCLINATIONS. IV. When pressed with such appalling difficulties as these, the Necessitarian falls back, in self-justifica- tion, upon the reason why the sinner cannot be holy. The only reason, it is said, why the sinner does not do as he ought is, not the want of power, but the strength of his sinful inclinations. Shall he plead these in ex- cuse for sin % By no means. They constitute the very essence of the sinner's guilt. Let it be borne in mind, that, according to the doctrine of Necessity, such is the connection between the nature, or con- stitution of the sinner's mind — a nature which God has given him, and the influences under which he is placed by Divine Providence — that none but these very inclinations are possible to him, and these can- not but exist. From these inclinations, sinful acts of Will cannot but arise. How is the matter helped, as LIBERTY AND NECESSITY. 75 far as ability and obligation, on the part of the sin- ner, are concerned, by throwing the guilt back from acts of Will upon inclinations equally necessary % NECESSARIAN DOCTRINE OF LIBERTY. The real liberty of the Will, according to the Ne- cessitarian scheme, next demands our attention. All admit that Liberty is an essential condition of moral obligation. In what sense, then, is or is not, man free, according to the doctrine of Necessity 1 u The plain and obvious meaning of the words Freedom and Liberty," says President Edwards, " is power, opportunity, or advantage, that any one has to do as he pleases. Or, in other words, his being free from hinderance or impediment in the way of doing or conducting in any respect as he wills. And the contrary to Liberty, whatever name we please to call that by, is a person's being hindered, or unable to conduct as he will, or being necessitated to do otherwise." " The only idea, indeed, that we can form of free-agency, or of freedom of Will," says Abercrombie, a is, that it consists in a man's being able to do what he wills, or to abstain from doing what he will not. Necessary agency, on the other hand, would consist in a man's being compelled, by a force from without, to do what he will not, or pre- vented from doing what he wills." With these definitions all Necessitarians agree. This is all the Liberty known, or conceivable, accord- 76 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. ing to their theory. Liberty does not consist in the power to choose in one or the other of two or more different and opposite directions, under the same in- fluence. It is found wholly and exclusively in the connection between the act of Will, considered as the antecedent, and the effort, external or internal, considered as the consequent. On this definition I remark, 1. That it presents the idea of Liberty as distin- guished from Servitude^ rather than Liberty as distin- guished from Necessity. A man is free, in the first sense of the term, when no external restraints hin- der the carrying out of the choice within. This, however, has nothing to do with Liberty, as distin- guished from Necessity. 2. If this is the only sense in which a man is free, then, in the language of a very distinguished philo- sopher, " if you cut off a man's little finger, you thereby annihilate so much of his free agency ;" be- cause, in that case, you abridge so much his power to do as he chooses. Is this Liberty, the only liberty of man, a liberty which may be destroyed by chains ? bolts, and bars ? Is this Liberty as distinguished from Necessity — the liberty which lays the foundation of moral obligation 1 3. If this is the only sense in which man is free ? then dire Necessity reigns throughout the entire do- main of human agency. If all acts of Will are the necessary consequents of the influences to which the LIBERTY AND NECESSITY. 77 mind is at the time subjected, much more must a like necessity exist between all acts of Will and their consequents, external and internal. This has been already shown. The mind, then, with all its acts and states, exists in a chain of antecedents and consequents, causes and effects, linked together in every part and department by a dire necessity. This is all the Lib- erty that this doctrine knows or allows us ; a Liberty to choose as influences necessitate us to choose, and to have such acts of Will followed by certain neces- sary consequents, external and internal. In this scheme, the idea of Liberty, which all admit must have a location somewhere, or obligation, is a chime- ra ; this idea, I say, after " wandering through dry places, seeking rest and finding none," at length is driven to a location where it finds its grave, and not a living habitation. 4. It is to me a very strange thing, that Liberty, as the foundation of moral obligation, should be lo- cated here. Because that acts of Will are followed by certain corresponding necessary consequents ex- ternal and internal, therefore we are bound to put forth given acts of Will, whatever the influences acting upon us may be, and however impossible it may be to put forth those acts under those influences ! Did ever a greater absurdity dance in the brain of a philosopher or theologian ? 5. The public are entirely deceived by this defini- tion, and because they are deceived as to the theory 78 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. intended by it, do they admit it as true *? Suppose any man in the common walks of life were asked what he means, when he says, he can do as II pleases, act as he chooses, &c. Does this express your meaning ? When you will to walk, rather than sit, for example, no other volition is at the time possible, and this you must put forth, and that when you have put forth this volition, you cannot but walk. Is this your idea, when you say, you can do as you please ? No, he would say. That is not my idea at all. If that is true, man is not a free agent at all. What men in general really mean when they say, they can do as they please, and are therefore free, is, that when they put forth a given act of Will, and for this reason conduct in a given manner, they may in the same circumstances put forth diffe- rent and opposite determinations, and consequently act in a different and opposite manner from what they do. VI. The argument of Necessitarians in respect to the practical tendencies of their doctrine demands a passing notice. All acts of the Will, they say, are indeed necessary under the circumstances in which they occur ; but then we should learn the practical lesson not to place ourselves in the circumstances where we shall be liable to act wrong. To this I reply : 1. That on the hypothesis before us, our being in the circumstances which originate a given choice, is LIBERTY AND NECESSITY. 79 as necessary as the choice itself. For I am in those circumstances either by an overruling Providence over which I have no control, or by previous acts of the Will rendered necessary by such Providence. Hence the difficulty remains in all its force. 2. The solution assumes the very principle denied, that is, that our being in circumstances which origi- nate particular acts of choice is not necessary. Else ^ why tell an individual he is to blame for being in such circumstances, and not to place himself there again ? GROUND WHICH NECESSITARIANS ARE BOUND TO TAKE IN RESPECT TO THE DOCTRINE OF ABILITY. VII. We are now fully prepared to state the ground which Necessitarians of every school are bound to take in respect to the doctrine of Ability. It is to deny that doctrine wholly, to take the open and broad ground, that, according to any appropriate sig- nification of the words, it is absolutely impossible for men to will, and consequently to act, differently from what they do ; that when they do w r rong, they always do it, with the absolute impossibility of doing right ; and that when they do right, there is always an equal impossibility of their doing wrong. If men have not power to will differently from what they do, it is undeniably evident that they have no power what- ever to act differently : because there is an absolutely necessary connection between volitions and their 80 DOCTRINE OP THE WILL. consequents, external actions. The doctrine of Ne- cessity takes away wholly all ability from the crea- ture to will differently from what he does. It there- fore totally annihilates his ability to act differently. What, then, according to the theory of Necessity, becomes of the doctrine of Ability % It is annihilat- ed. It is impossible for us to find for it a " local habitation or a name." As honest men, Necessitari- ans are bound to proclaim the fact. They are bound to proclaim the doctrine, that, in requiring men to be holy, under influences under which they do sin, and cannot but sin (as it is true of all sinful acts accord- ing to their theory), God requires of them absolute impossibilities, and then dooms them to perdition for not performing such impossibilities. The subterfuge to which Necessitarians resort here, will not avail them at all, to wit : that men are to blame for not doing right, because, they might do it if they chose. To will right is the thing, and the only thing really required of them. The above maxim therefore amounts, as we have already seen, to this : Men are bound to do, that is, to will, what is right, because if they should will what is right, they would will what is right. DOCTRINE OF NECESSITY, AS REGARDED BY NECESSI- TARIANS OF DIFFERENT SCHOOLS. VIII. Two schools divide the advocates of Neces- sity. According to one class, God produces in men LIBERTY AND NECESSITY. 81 all their volitions and acts, both sinful and holy, by the direct exertion of his own omnipotence. With- out the Divine agency, men, they hold, are wholly incapable of all volitions and actions of every kind. With it, none but those which God produces can arise, and these cannot but arise. This is the scheme of Divine efficiency, as advocated by Dr. Emmons and others. According to the other school, God does not, in all instances, produce volitions and actions by his own direct agency, but by creating in creatures a certain nature or constitution, and then subjecting them to influences from which none but particular voli- tions and acts which they do put forth can result, and these must result. According to a large portion of this school, God, either by his own direct agency, or by sustaining their laws of natural generation, produ- ces in men the peculiar nature which they do pos- sess, and then imputes to them infinite guilt, not only for this nature, but for its necessary results, sinful feelings, volitions, and actions. Such are these two schemes. In the two follow- ing particulars, they perfectly harmonize. 1. All acts of Will, together with their effects, external and internal, in the circumstances of their occurrence, cannot but be what they are. 2. The ground of this necessity is the agency of God, in the one instance producing these effects directly and immediately, and in the other producing the same results, mediately, by 8 82 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL, giving existence to a constitution and influences from which such results cannot but arise. They differ only in respect to the immediate ground of this neces- sity, the power of God, according to the former, pro- ducing the effects directly, and according to the latter ? indirectly. According to both, all our actions sustain the same essential relation to the Divine Will, that of Necessity. Now while these two theories so perfectly harmo- nize, in all essential particulars, strange to tell, the advocates of one regard the other as involving the most monstrous absurdities conceivable. For God to produce, through the energies of his own omni- potence, human volitions, and then to impute infinite guilt to men for what he himself has produced in them, what a horrid sentiment that is, exclaims the advocate of constitutional depravity. For God to create in men a sinful nature, and then impute to them infinite guilt for what he has himself created, together with its unavoidable results, what horrid tyranny such a sentiment imputes to the Most High, exclaims the advocate of Divine efficiency, in his turn. The impartial, uncommitted spectator, on the other hand, perceives most distinctly the same identical ab- surdities in both these theories. He knows perfectly, that it can make no essential difference, whether God produces a result directly, or by giving existence to a constitution and influences from which it cannot but arise. If ore theory involves injustice and tyr- LIBERTY AND NECESSITY. 83 anny, the other must involve the same. Let me here add, that the reprobation with which each of the classes above named regards the sentiments of the other, is a sentence of reprobation passed (unconsci- ously to be sure) upon the doctrine of Necessity it- self which is common to both. For if this one ele- ment is taken out of either theory, there is nothing left to render it abhorrent to any mind. It is thus that Necessitarians themselves, without exception, pass sentence of condemnation upon their own the- ory, by condemning it, in every system in which they meet with it except their own. There is not a man on earth, that has not in some form or other passed sentence of reprobation upon this system. Let any man, whatever, contemplate any theory but the one he has himself adopted, any theory that in- volves this element, and he will instantly fasten upon this one feature as the characteristic which vitiates the whole theory, and renders it deserving of univer- sal reprobation. It is thus that unsophisticated Nature expresses her universal horror at a system which " Binding nature fast in fate, Enslaves the human Will." Unsophisticated Nature abhors this doctrine infinitely more than she was ever conceived to abhor a vacu- um. Can a theory which the universal Intelligence thus agrees in reprobating, as involving the most hor- rid absurdity and tyranny conceivable, be the only true one ? CHAPTER IV. EXTENT AND LIMITS OF THE LIBERTY OF THE WILL. While it is maintained, that, in the sense defined in the preceding chapter, the Will is free, it is also affirmed that, in other respects, it is not free at all. It should be borne distinctly in mind, that, in the re- spects in which the Will is subject to the law of Liberty, its liberty is absolute. It is in no sense subject to the law of Necessity. So far, also, as it is subject to the law of Necessity, it is in no sense free. What then are the extent and limits of the Liberty of the Will ? 1. In the absence of Motives, the Will cannot act at all. To suppose the opposite would involve a contradiction. It would suppose the action of the Will in the direction of some object, in the absence of ail objects towards which such action can be di- rected. 2. The Will is not free in regard to what the Mo- tives presented shall be, in view of which its deter- minations shall be formed. Motives exist wholly independent of the Will. Nor does it depend at all upon the Will, what Motives shall be presented for its election. It is free only in respect to the parti- EXTENT AND LIMITS OF LIBERTY. 85 cular determinations it shall put forth, in reference to the Motives actually presented. 3. Whenever a Motive, or object of choice, is pre- sented to the mind, the Will is necessitated, by the presentation of the object, to act in some direction. It must yield or refuse to yield to the Motive. But such refusal is itself a positive act. So far, there- fore, the Will is wholly subject to the law of Neces- sity. It is free, not in respect to whether it shall, or shall not, choose at all when a Motive is presented ; but in respect to what it shall choose. I, for exam- ple, offer a merchant a certain sum, for a piece of goods. Now while it is equally possible for him to receive or reject the offer, one or the other deter- mination he must form. In the first respect, he is wholly free. In the latter, he is not free in any sense whatever. The same holds true in respect to all objects of choice presented to the mind. Motive necessitates the Will to act in some direction ; while? in all deliberate Moral Acts at least, it leaves either of two or more different and opposite determinations equally possible to the mind. 4. Certain particular volitions may be rendered necessary by other, and what may be termed gene- ral, determinations. For example, a determination to pursue a particular course of conduct, may render necessary all particular volitions requisite to carry this general purpose into accomplishment. It ren- ders them necessary in this sense, that if the former 8* 86 DOCTRINE OP THE WILL. does exist, the latter must exist. A man, for exam- ple, determines to pass from Boston to New York with all possible expedition. This determination remaining unchanged, all the particular volitions requisite to its accomplishment cannot but exist. The general and controlling determination, however, may, at any moment, be suspended. To perpetuate or suspend it, is always in the power of the Will. 5. I will here state a conjecture, viz. : that there are in the primitive developments of mind, as well as in all primary acts of attention, certain necessary spontaneities of the Will, as well as of other powers of the mind. Is it not in consequence of such actions, that the mind becomes first conscious of the power of volition, and is it pot now necessary for us under cer- tain circumstances to give a certain degree of atten- tion to phenomena which appear within and around us ? My own convictions are, that such circum- stances often do occur. Nor is such a supposition inconsistent with the great principle maintained in this Treatise. This principle is, that Liberty and Ac- countability, in other words, Free, and Moral Agency, are co-extensive. 6. Nor does Liberty, as here defined, imply, that the mind, antecedently to all acts of Will, shall be in a state of indifference, unimpelled by feeling, or the affirmations of the Intelligence, more strongly in one direction than another. The Will exists in a tri-unity with the Intelligence and Sensibility. Its EXTENT AND LIMITS OF LIBERTY. 87 determinations may be in harmony with the Sensi- bility, in opposition to Intelligence, or with the In- telligence in opposition to the Sensibility. But while it follows either in distinction from the other, under the same identical influences, different and opposite determinations are equally possible. However the Will may be influenced, whether its determinations are in the direction of the strongest impulse, or op- posed to it, it never, in deliberate moral determina- tion, puts forth particular acts, because, that in these circumstances, no others are possible. In instances comparatively few, can we suppose that the mind, antecedently to acts of Will, is in a state of indiffe- rence, unimpelled in one direction in distinction from others, or equally impelled in the direction of diffe- rent and opposite determinations. Indifference is in no such sense an essential or material condition of Liberty. However strongly the Wilr may be im- pelled in the direction of particular determinations, it is still in the possession of the highest concei- vable freedom, if it is not thereby necessitated to act in one direction in distinction from all others. 7. I now refer to one other fixed law under the influence of which the Will is always necessitated to act. It is the law of habit. Action in any one direction always generates a tendency to subsequent action in the same direction under similar influences. This tendency may be increased, till it becomes so strong as to render action in the same direction in 88 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. all future time really, although contingently, certain. The certainty thus granted will always be of such a nature as consists fully with the relation of Liberty. It can never, while moral agency continues, come under the relation of Necessity. Still the certainty is real. Thus the mind, by a continued course of well or ill doing, may generate such fixed habits, as to render subsequent action in the same direction perfectly certain, during the entire progress of its future being. Every man, while conscious of free- dom, should be fully aware of the existence of this law, and it should surely lead him to walk thought- fully along the borders of " the undiscovered coun- try," his location in which he is determining by the habits of thought, feeling, and action, he is now generating. STRONGEST 'MOTIVE REASONING IN A CIRCLE. A singular instance of reasoning in a circle on the part of Necessitarians, in respect to what they call the strongest Motive, demands a passing notice here. One of their main arguments in support of their doc- trine is based upon the assumption, that the action of the Will is always in the direction of the strongest Motive . When , however, we ask them , which is the strongest Motive, their reply in reality is, that it is the Motive in the direction of which the Will does act. " The strength of a Motive," says President Day, " is not its prevailing, but the power by which it prevails. Yet we may very properly measure this EXTENT AND LIMITS OF LIBERTY. 89 power by the actual result." Again, " We may- measure the comparative strength of Motives of dif- ferent kinds, from the results to which they lead ; just as we learn the power of different causes, from the effects which they produce :" that is, we are not to determine, a priori, nor by an appeal to conscious- ness, which of two or more Motives presented is the strongest. We are to wait till the Will does act, and then assume that the Motive, in the direction of which it acts, is the strongest. From the action of the Will in the direction of that particular Motive , we are finally to infer the truth of the doctrine of Necessity. The strongest Motive, according to the above defini- tion, is the motive to which the Will does yield. The argument based upon the truism, that the Will always acts in the direction of this Motive, that is, the Motive towards which it does act, the argument, I say, put into a logical form, would stand thus. If the action of the Will is always in the direction of the strongest Motive, that is, if it always follows the Motive it does follow, it is governed by the law of Necessity. Its action is always in the direction of this Motive, that is, it always follows the Motive it does follow. The Will is therefore governed by the law of Necessity. How many philosophers and the- ologians have become " rooted and grounded" in the belief of this doctrine, under the influence of this sophism, a sophism which, in the first instance, as- sumes the doctrine as true, and then moves round in a vicious circle to demonstrate its truth. CHAPTER V. THE GREATEST APPARENT GOOD. SECTION I. We now come to a consideration of one of the great questions bearing upon our personal investigations — the proposition maintained by Necessitarians, as a chief pillar of their theory, that " the Will always is as the greatest apparent good." PHRASE DEFINED. The first inquiry which naturally arises here is ; What is the proper meaning of this proposition ? In reply, I answer, that it must mean one of these three things. 1. That the Will is always, in all its determina- tions, conformed to the dictates of the Intelligence, choosing those things only which the Intelligence affirms to be best. Or, 2. That the determinations of the Will are always in conformity to the impulse of the Sensibility, that is, that its action is always in the direction of the strongest feeling. Or, 3. In conformity to the dictates of the Intelligence, and the impulse of the Sensibility combined, that is that the Will never acts at all, except when impelled GREATEST APPARENT GOOD. 91 by the Intelligence and Sensibility both in the same direction. MEANING OF THIS PHRASE ACCORDING TO EDWARDS a The following passage leaves no room for doubt in respect to the meaning which Edwards attaches to the phrase, u the greatest apparent good." " I have chosen," he says, u rather to express myself thus, that the Will always is as the greatest apparent good, or as what appears most agreeable, than to say, that the Will is determined by the greatest apparent good, or by what seems most agreeable ; because an appearing most agreeable or pleasing to the mind, and the mind's preferring and choosing, seem hardly to be properly and perfectly distinct." Here unde- niably, the words, choosing, preferring, " appearing most agreeable or pleasing," and " the greatest ap- parent good," are defined as identical in their mean- ing. Hence in another place, he adds, " If strict pro- priety of speech be insisted on, it may more properly be said, that the voluntary action which is the imme- diate consequence and fruit of the mind's volition and choice, is determined by that which appears most agreeable, than by the preference or choice it- self." The reason is obvious. Appearing most agreeable or pleasing, and preference or choice, had been defined as synonymous in their meaning. To say, therefore, that preference or choice is determined by " what appears most agreeable or pleasing," 92 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL, would be equivalent to the affirmation, that choice determines choice. " The act of volition itself, he adds, " is always determined by that in or about the mind's view of an object, which causes it to appear most agreeable," or what is by definition the same thing, causes it to be chosen. The phrases, " the greatest apparent good/' and " appearing most agree- able or pleasing to the mind," and the words, choos- ing, preferring, &c, are therefore, according to Ed- wards, identical in their meaning. The proposition, " the Will is always as the greatest apparent good," really means nothing more nor less than this, that Will always chooses as it chooses. The famous ar- gument based upon this proposition in favor of the doctrine of Necessity may be thus expressed. If the Will always is as the greatest apparent good," that is, if the Will always chooses as it chooses, it is gov- erned by the law of Necessity. The Will is as the greatest apparent good, that is, it always chooses as it chooses. Therefore it is governed by this law. By this very syllogism, multitudes have supposed that the doctrine of Necessity has been established with all the distinctness and force of demonstration. The question now returns, Is " the Will always as the greatest apparent good," in either of the senses of the phrase as above defined ? GREATEST APPARENT GOOD. 93 THE WILL NOT ALWAYS AS THE DICTATES OF THE INTELLIGENCE. 1. Is the Will then as the greatest apparent good in this sense, that all its determinations are in con- formity to the dictates of the Intelligence. Does the Will never harmonize with the Sensibility in op- position to the Intelligence ? Has no intelligent being, whether sinful or holy, ever done that which his Intellect affirmed at the time, that he ought not to do, and that it was best for him not to do ? I answer, 1. Every man who has ever violated moral obliga- tion knows, that he has followed the impulse of de- sire, in opposition to the dictates of his Intelligence. What individual that has ever perpetrated such deeds has not said, and cannot say with truth, " I know the good, and approve it ; yet follow the bad ?" Take a matter of fact. A Spanish nobleman during the early progress of the Reformation, became fully con- vinced, that the faith of the Reformers was true, and his own false, and that his salvation depended upon his embracing the one and rejecting the other. Yet martyrdom would be the result of such a change. While balancing this question, in the depths of his own mind, he trembled with the greatest 'agitation. His sovereign who was present, asked the cause. The reply was, " the martyr's crown is before me, and I have not Christian fortitude enough to take it." He died a few weeks subsequent, without confessing the truth. Did he obey his Intelligence, 9 94 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. or Sensibility there ? Was not the conflict between the two, and did not the latter prevail ? In John 12 : 42, 43, we have a fact revealed, in which men were convinced of the truth, and yet, because " they loved the praise of men more than the praise of God,' 7 they did not confess, but denied the truth, a case therefore in which they followed the impulse of desire, in opposition to the dictates of the Intelligence. The Will then is not " always as the greatest apparent good," in this sense, that its action is always in the direction of the dictates of the Intelligence. 2. If this is so, sin, in all instances, is a mere blun- der, a necessary result of a necessary misjudgment of the Intelligence ? Is it so ? Can the Intelligence affirm that a state of moral impurity is better than a state of moral rectitude ? How easy it would be, in every instance, to u convert a sinner from the error of his way," if all that is requisite is to carry his Intellect in favor of truth and righteousness ? Who does not know, that the great difficulty lies in the enslavement of the Will to a depraved Sensi- bility ? 3. If the Will of all Intelligents is always in har- mony with the Intellect, then I affirm that there is not, and never has been, any such thing as sin, or ill desert, in the universe. What more can be said of God, or of any being ever so pure, than that he has always done what his Intellect affirmed to be best ? What if the devil, and all creatures called sinners, GREATEST APPARENT GOOD. 95 had always done the same thing? Where is the conceivable ground for the imputation of moral guilt to them ? 4. If all acts of Will are always in perfect har- mony with the Intelligence, and in this sense, " as the greatest apparent good," then, when the Intel- lect affirms absolutely that there can be no ground of preference between two objects, there can be no choice between them. But we are, in fact, putting forth every day just such acts of Will, selecting one object in distinction from another, when the Intellect affirms their perfect equality, or affirms absolutely that there is and can be no perceived ground of pre- ference between them. I receive a letter, I will sup- pose, from a friend, informing me that he has just taken from a bank two notes, perfectly new and of the same value, that one now lies in the east and the other in the west corner of his drawer, that I may have one and only one of them, the one that I shall name by return of mail, and that I must designate one or the other, or have neither. Here are present to my Intelligence two objects absolutely equal. Their location is a matter of indifference, equally absolute. Now if, as the proposition " the Will is always as the greatest apparent good,"! affirms, I cannot select one object in distinction from another, with- out a perceived ground for such selection, I could not possibly, in the case supposed, say which bill I would have. Yet I make the selection without the least 96 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. conceivable embarrassment. I might mention num- berless cases, of daily occurrence, of a nature pre- cisely similar. Every child that ever played at S odd or even," knows perfectly the possibility of selecting between objects which are, to the Intelli- gence, absolutely equal. I will now select a case about which there can possibly be no mistake. Space we know perfectly to be absolutely infinite. Space in itself is in all parts alike. So must it appear to the mind of God. Now w r hen God determined to create the universe, he must have resolved to locate its centre in some one point of space in distinction from all others. At that moment, there was present to the Divine Intelligence an infinite number of points, all and each absolutely equally eligible. Neither point could have been se- lected, because it was better than any other : for all were equal. So they must have appeared to God. Now if the u Will is always as the greatest apparent good," in the sense under consideration, God could not in this case make the selection, and consequently could not create the universe. He did make the selection, and did create. The Will, therefore, is not, in this sense, " always as the greatest apparent good." THE WILL NOT ALWAYS AS THE STRONGEST DESIRE. II. Is the u Will always as the greatest apparent good " in this sense, that it is always as the strongest desire, or as the strongest impulse of the Sensibility ? GREATEST APPARENT GOOD. 97 Does the Will never harmonize with the Intelligence, in opposition to the Sensibility, as well as with the Sensibility in opposition to the Intelligence ? If this is not so, then — 1. It would be difficult to define self-denial accord- ing to the ordinary acceptation of the term. What is self-denial but placing the Will with the Intelli- gence, in opposition to the Sensibility ? How often in moral reformations do we find almost nothing else but this, an inflexible purpose placed directly before an almost crushing and overwhelming tide of feeling and desire ? 2. When the Will is impelled in different direc- tions, by conflicting feelings, it could not for a mo- ment be in a state of indecision, unless we suppose these conflicting feelings to be absolutely equal in strength up to the moment of decision. Who believes that ? Who believes that his feelings are in all instances in a state of perfect equilibrium up to the moment of fixed determination between two dis- tinct and opposite courses ? This must be the case, if the action of the Will is always as the strongest feeling, and in this sense as the u greatest apparent good." How can Necessitarians meet this argu- ment ? Will they pretend that, in all instances, up to the moment of decisive action, the feelings im- pelling the Will in different directions are always ab- solutely equal in strength ? This must be, if the Will is always as the strongest feeling. 9 * 98 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. 3. When the feelings are in a state of perfect equi- librium, there can possibly, on this supposition, be no choice at all. The feelings often are, and must be, in this state, even when we are necessitated to act in some direction. The case of the bank notes above referred to, presents an example of this kind. As the objects are in the mind's eye absolutely equal, to suppose that the feelings should, in such a case, impel the Will more strongly in the direction of the one than the other, is to suppose an event with- out a cause, inasmuch as the Sensibility is governed by the law of Necessity. If A and B are to the In- telligence, in all respects, absolutely equal, how can the Sensibility impel the Will towards A instead of B ? What is an event without a cause, if this is not ? Contemplate the case in respect to the loca- tion of the universe above supposed. Each point of space was equally present to God, and was in it- self, and was perceived and affirmed to be, equally eligible with all the others. How could a stronger feeling arise in the direction of one point in distinc- tion from others, unless we suppose that God's Sen- sibility is not subject to the law of Necessity, a position which none will assume, or that here was an event without a cause ? When, therefore, God did select this one point in distinction from all the others, that determination could not have been either in the direction of what the Intelligence affirmed to be best, nor of the strongest feeling. The proposition, GREATEST APPARENT GOOD. 99 therefore, that " the Will always is as the greatest ap- parent good," is in both the senses above defined de- monstrably false. 4. Of the truth of this every one is aware when he appeals to his own Consciousness. In the ampu- tation of a limb, for example, who does not know that if an individual, at the moment when the opera- tion commences, should yield to the strongest feeling, he would refuse to endure it ? He can pass through the scene, only by placing an inflexible purpose di- rectly across the current of feeling. How often do we hear individuals affirm, " If I should follow my feelings^ I should do this ; if I should follow my judgment, I should do that." In all such instances, we have the direct testimony of consciousness, that the action of the Will is not always in the direction of the strongest feeling : because its action is some- times consciously in the direction of the Intelligence, in opposition to such feelings ; and at others, in the conscious presence of such feelings, the Will re- mains, for periods longer or shorter, undecided in respect to the particular course which shall be pur- sued. THE WILL NOT ALWAYS AS THE INTELLIGENCE AND SENSIBILITY COMBINED. III. Is not the Will always as the greatest apparent good in this sense, that its determinations are always as the affirmations of the Intelligence and the im- 100 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. pulse of the Sensibility combined ? That it is not, I argue for two reasons. 1. If this was the case, when the Intelligence and Sensibility are opposed to each other — a fact of very frequent occurrence, — there could be no acts of Will in either direction. The Will must remain in a state of absolute inaction, till these belligerent powers settle their differences, and unite in impelling the Will in some particular direction. But we know that the Will can, and often does, act in the direction of the Intelligence or Sensibility, when the affirma- tions of one and the impulses of the other are in direct opposition to each other. 2. When both the Intellect and Sensibility, as in the cases above cited, are alike indifferent, there can be, on the present hypothesis, no acts of Will whatever. Under these identical circumstances, however, the Will does act. The hypothesis, there- fore, falls to the ground. I conclude, then, that the proposition, " the Will is always as the greatest apparent good," is ei her a mere truism, having no bearing at all upon our pre- sent inquiries, or that it is false. In the discussion of the above propositions, the doctrine of Liberty has received a full and distinct il- lustration. The action of the Will is sometimes in the direction of the Intelligence, in opposition to the Sensibility, and sometimes in the direction of the Sen- sibility, in opposition to the Intelligence, and never GREATEST APPARENT GOOD. 101 in the direction of either, because it must be. Some- times it acts where the Sensibility and Intelligence both harmonize, or are alike indifferent. When also the Will acts in the direction of the Intelligence or Sensibility, it is not necessitated to follow, in all in- stances, the highest affirmation, nor the strongest desire. SEC. II — MISC ELLANEOIJS TOPICS. NECESSITARIAN ARGUMENT. I. We are now prepared to appreciate the Neces- sitarian argument, based upon the assumption, that " the Will always is as the greatest apparent good." This assumption is the great pillar on which that doctrine rests. Yet the whole argument based upon it is a perpetual reasoning in a circle. Ask the Ne- cessitarian to give the grand argument in favor of his doctrine. His answer is, because " the Will always is as the greatest apparent good." Cite now such facts as those stated above in contradiction of his assumption, and his answer is ready. There must be, in all such cases, some perceived or felt ground of preference, or there could be no act of Will in the case. There must have been, for example, some point in space more eligible than any other for the location of the universe, and this must have been the reason why God selected the one he did. Ask him why he makes this declaration ? His reply is, be- cause " the Will is always as the greatest apparent good." Thus this assumption becomes premise or 102 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. conclusion, just as the exigence of the theory based upon it demands. Nothing is so convenient and ser- viceable as such an assumption, when one has a very- difficult and false position to sustain. But who does not see, that it is a most vicious reasoning in a circle 1 To assume the proposition, " the Will always is as the greatest apparent good," in the first instance, as the basis of a universal theory, and then to assume the truth of that proposition as the basis of the ex- planation of particular facts, which contradict that theory, what is reasoning in a circle if this is not ? No one has a right to assume this proposition as true at all, until he has first shown that it is affirmed by all the phenomena of the Will. On its authority he has no right to explain a solitary phenomenon. To do it is not only to reason in a circle, but to beg the question at issue. MOTIVES CAUSE ACTS OF WILL, IN WHAT SENSE. II. We are also prepared to notice another assump- tion of President Edwards, which, if admitted in the sense in which he assumes it as true, necessitates the admission of the Necessitarian scheme, to wit : that the determination of the Will is always caused by the Motive present to the mind for putting forth . that determination. " It is that motive," he says, a which, as it stands in the view of the mind, is the strongest which determines the Will." Again, u that every act of the Will has some cause, and conse- GREATEST APPARENT GOOD. 103 quently (by what has been already proved) has a necessary connection with its cause, and so is neces- sary by a necessity of connection and consequence, is evident by this, that every act of Will, whatsoever, is excited by some motive." " But if every act of the Will is excited by some motive, then that motive is the cause of that act of the Will." " And if voli- tions are properly the effects of their motives, then they are necessarily connected with their motives." If we grant the principle here assumed, the con- clusion follows of necessity. But let us inquire in what sense motive and volition sustain to each other the relation of cause and effect. The presence and action of one power causes the action of another ', so far , and so far only, as it necessitates such action; and causes its action in a particular direction, so far only as it necessitates its action in that direction, in opposi- tion to every other. Now the action of one power may cause the action of another, in one or both these ways. 1. It may* necessitate its action, and necessitate it in one direction in opposition to any and every other. In this sense, fire causes the sensation of pain. It necessitates the action of the Sensibility, and in that one direction. Or, 2. One power may necessitate the action of ano- ther power, but not necessitate its action in one direc- tion in opposition to any or all others. We have seen, in a former chapter, that the Motive causes the 104 DOCTRTNE OF THE WILL. action of the Will in this sense only, that it necessi- tates the Will to act in some direction, but not in one direction in distinction from another. Now the error of President Edwards lies in confounding these two senses of the word cause. He assumes that when one power causes the action of another in any sense, it must in every sense. It is readily admitted, that in one sense the Motive causes the action of the Will. But when we ask for the reason or cause of any one particular choice in distinction from another, we find it, not in the motive, but in the power of willing itself. OBJECTION — PARTICULAR VOLITION, HOW ACCOUNTED FOR. III. We are also prepared to notice the great objec- tion of Necessitarians to the doctrine of Liberty as here maintained. How, it is asked, shall we account, on this theory, for particular volitions ? The power to will only accounts for acts of Will in some direction, but not for one act in distinction from another. This distinction must be accounted for, or we have an event without a cause. To this argument I reply, 1. It assumes the position in debate, to wit : that there cannot be consequents which are not necessa- rily .connected with particular antecedents, which antecedents necessitate these particular consequents in distinction from all others. 2. To account for any effect, all that can properly be required is, to assign the existence and operation of a cause adequate to the production of such effects. GREATEST APPARENT GOOD. 105 Free- agency itself is such a cause in the case now under consideration. We have here given the exist- ence and operation of a cause which must produce one of of two effects,andis equally capable,under the circum- stances, of producing either. Such a cause accounts for the existence of such an effect, just as much as the assignment of an antecedent necessarily producing certain consequents, accounts for those consequents, 3. If, as this objection affirms, an act of Will, when there is no perceived or felt reason for that act in distinction from every other, is equivalent to an event without a cause ; then it would be as impossible for us to conceive of the former as of the latter. We cannot even conceive of an event without a cause . But we can conceive of an act of Will when no rea- son, but the power of willing, exists for that particular act in distinction from others. We cannot conceive of an event without a cause. But we can conceive of the mind's selecting odd, for example, instead of even, without the Intellect or Sensibility impelling the Will to that act in distinction from others. Such act, therefore, is not equivalent to an event without a cause. The objection under consideration is con- sequently wholly baseless. FACTS LIKE THE ABOVE WRONGLY ACCOUNTED FOR. IV. The manner in which Necessitarians sometimes endeavor to account for acts of Will in which a selec- tion is made between objects perceived and felt to be 10 106 DOCTRINE OP THE WILL. perfectly equal, requires attention. Suppose that A and B are before the mind. One or the other is to be selected, or no selection at all is to be made. These objects are present to the mind as perfectly equal. The Intelligence and Sensibility are in a state of entire equilibrium between them. Now when one of these objects is selected in distinction from the other, this act of Will is to be accounted for, it is said, by referring back to the determination to make the selection instead of not making it. The Will does not choose between A and B, at all. The choice is between choosing and not choosing. But mark : To determine to select A or B is one thing. To select one in distinction from the other, is quite another. The former act does not determine the Will towards either in distinction from the other. This last act remains to be accounted for. When we attempt to account for it, we cannot do it, by refer- ring to the Intelligence or Sensibility ; for these are in a state of perfect equilibrium between the ob- jects. We can account for it only by falling back upon the power of willing itself, and admitting that the Will is free, and not subject to the law of Ne- cessity. CHOOSING BETWEEN OBJECTS KNOWN TO BE EQUAL HOW TREATED BY NECESSITARIANS. V. The manner in which Necessitarians treat facts of this kind, to wit ? choosing between things per- GREATEST APPARENT GOOD. 107 ceived and felt to be equal, also demands a passing notice. Such facts are of very little importance, one way or the other, they say, in mental science. It is the height of folly to appeal to them to determine questions of such moment as the doctrine of Liberty and Necessity. I answer : Such facts are just as important in mental science, as the fall of a piece of gold and a feather, in an exhausted receiver, is in Natural Philosophy. The latter reveals with per- fect clearness the great law of attraction in the ma- terial universe. The former reveals with equal con- spicuousness the great law of Liberty in the realm of mind. The Necessitarian affirms, that no act of Will is possible, only in the direction of the dictates of the Intelligence, or of the strongest impulse of the Sensibility. Facts are adduced in which, from the necessity of the case, both Faculties must be in a state of perfect equilibrium. Neither can impel the Will in one direction, in distinction from the other. In such circumstances, if the doctrine of Necessity is true, no acts of Will are possible. In precisely these circumstances acts of Will do arise. The doc- trine of Necessity therefore is overthrown, and the truth of that Liberty is demonstrated. So impor- tant are those facts which Necessitarians affect to despise. True philosophy, it should be remembered, never looks contemptuously upon facts of any kind, 108 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. PALPABLE MISTAKE. VI. We are prepared to notice a palpable mistake into which Necessitarians have fallen in respect to the use which the advocates of the doctrine of Lib- erty design to make of the fact, that the Will can and does select between objects perceived and felt to be equal. " The reason why some metaphysical writers," says President Day, " have laid so much stress upon this apparently insignificant point, is probably the inference which they propose to draw from the posi- tion which they assume. If it be conceded that the mind decides one way or the other indifferently, when the motives on each side are perfectly equal, they infer that this may be the fact, in all other cases, even though the motives to opposite choices may be ever so unequal. But on what ground is this conclusion warranted ? If a man is entirely indifferent which of two barley-corns to take, does it follow that he will be indifferent whether to accept of a guinea or a farthing ; w r hether to possess an estate or a trinket ?" The advocates of the doctrine of Liberty design to make, and do make, no such use of the facts under consideration, as is here attributed to them. They never argue that, because the Will can select between A and B, when they are perceived and felt to be equal, therefore, when the Will acts in one direction, in distinction from another, it is always, up to the mo- ment of such action, impelled in different directions DIVINE PRESCIENCE. 109 by feelings and judgments equally strong. What they do argue from such facts is, that the Will is sub- ject to the law of Liberty and not to that of Neces- sity. If the Will is subject to the latter, then, when impelled in different directions by Motives equally strong (as in the cases above cited), it could no more act in the direction of one in distinction from the other, than a heavy body can move east instead of west, when drawn in each direction by forces per- fectly equal. If the Will is subject to the law of Necessity, then, in all instances of selection between objects known and felt to be equal, we have an event without a cause. Even the Necessitarians, many of them at least, dare not deny that, under these very circumstances, selection does take place. They must, therefore, abandon their theory, or admit the dogma ? of events without causes. 10' CHAPTERVI. CONNECTION OF THE DOCTRINE OF LIBERTY WITH THE DIVINE PRESCIENCE. The argument on which Necessitarians chiefly rely, against the doctrine of Liberty, and in support of that of Necessity, is based upon the Divine prescience of human conduct. The argument runs thus : all acts of the Will, however remote in the distant future, are foreknown to God. This fact necessitates the conclusion, that such acts are in themselves certain, and, consequently, not free, but necessary. Either God cannot foreknow acts of Will, or they are neces- sary. The reply to this argument has already been anticipated in the Introduction. The Divine presci- ence is not the truth to which the appeal should be made, to determine the philosophy of the Will pre- supposed in the Bible. This I argue, for the obvious reason, that of the mode, nature, and degree, of the Divine prescience of human conduct we are pro- foundly ignorant. These we must know with per- fect clearness, before we can affirm, with any cer- tainty, whether this prescience is or is not consis f ent with the doctrine of Liberty. The Divine pre- science is a truth of inspiration, and therefore a fact. The doctrine of Liberty is, as we have seen, a truth DIVINE PRESCIENCE. Ill of inspiration, and therefore a fact. It is also a fact, as affirmed by the universal consciousness of man. How do we know that these two facts are not per- fectly consistent with each other? How do we know but that, if we understood the mode, to say nothing of the nature and degree of the Divine pre- science, we should not perceive with the utmost clear- ness, that this truth consists as perfectly with the doctrine of Liberty, as with that of Necessity. If God foresees events, he foreknows them as they are, and not as they are not. If they are free and not necessary, as free and not necessary he foresees them. Having ascertained by consciousness that the acts of the Will are free, and having, from reason and revelation, determined, that God foreknows such acts, the great truth stands revealed to our mind, that God does and can foreknow human conduct, and yet man in such conduct be free ; and that the mode, na- ture, and degree, of the former are such as most perfectly to consist with the latter. I know with perfect distinctness, that I am now putting forth certain acts of Will. With equal dis- tinctness I know, that such acts are not necessary, but free. My present knowledge is perfectly consist- ent with present freedom. How do I know but that God's foreknowledge of future acts is equally con- sistent with the most perfect freedom of such acts. Perhaps a better presentation of this whole subject cannot be found than in the following extract from 112 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. Jouffroy's " Introduction to Ethics. " The extract, though somewhat lengthy, will well repay a most at- tentive perusal. DANGER IN REASONING FROM THE MANNER IN WHICH WE FOREKNOW EVENTS TO THAT OF DIVJNE PRE- SCIENCE. " To begin, then, with a very simple remark : if we conceive that foreknowledge in the Divine Being acts as it does in us, we run the risk of forming a most in- correct notion of it, and consequently, of seeing a contradiction between it and liberty, that would dis- appear altogether had we a truer notion. Let us consider that we have not the same faculty for fore- seeing the future as we have of reviewing the past ; and even in cases where we do anticipate it, it is by an induction from the past. This induction may amount either to certainty, or merely to probability. It will amount to certainty when we are perfectly acquainted with necessary causes, and their law of operation. The effects of such causes in given cir- cumstances having been determined by experience, we can predict the return of similar effects under sim- ilar circumstances with entire certainty, so long at least as the present laws of nature remain in force. It is in this way that we foresee, in most cases, the physical occurrences, whose law of operation is known to us ; and such foresight would extend much further, were it not for unexpected circumstances which jcome in to modify the result. This induction can never go beyond probability," however, when we consider the acts of free causes ; and for the very reason that they are free, and that the effects which arise from such causes are not of necessary occur- DIVINE PRESCIENCE. 113 rence, and do not invariably follow the same antece- dent circumstances. Where the question is, then, as to the acts of any free cause, we are never able to foresee it with certainty, and induction is limited to conjectures of probability. " Such is the operation, and such are the limits of human foresight. Our minds foresee the future by induction from the past ; this foresight can never at- tain certainty except in the case of causes and effects connected by necessary dependence ; when the ef- fects of free causes are to be anticipated, as all such effects are contingent, our foresight must be merely conjecture. MISTAKE RESPECTING THE DIVINE PRESCIENCE. "If, now, we attempt to attribute to the Deity the same mode of foresight of which human beings are capable, 'it will follow, as a strict consequence, that, as God must know exactly and completely the laws to which all the necessary causes in nature are sub- ject — laws which change only according to his will, — he can foresee with absolute certainty all events which will take place in future. The certain fore- sight of effects, therefore, which is to us possible only in particular cases, and which, even then, is always liable to the limitation that the actual laws of nature are not modified, — this foresight, which, even when most sure, is limited and contingent, must be com- plete and absolute certainty in God, supposing his foreknowledge to be of like kind with ours. " But it is evident that, according to this hypothesis, the Deity cannot foresee with certainty the volitions of free causes any more than we can ; for, as his foresight is founded, as ours is, upon the knowledge of the laws which govern causes, and as the law of 114 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. free causes is precisely this, that their volitions are not necessary, God cannot calculate, any more than a human being can, the influence of motives, which, in any given case, may act upon such causes. Even his intelligence can lead no further than to conjec- tures, more probable, indeed, than ours, but never amounting to certainty. According to this hypothe- sis, we must, therefore, say either that God can fore- see, certainly, the future volitions of men, and that man, therefore, is not a free being, or that man is free, and that God, therefore, cannot, any more than we can, foresee his volitions with certainty ; and thus Divine prescience and human free-will are brought into direct contradiction. " But, gentlemen, why must there be this contra- diction ? Merely because we suppose that God fore- sees the future in the same way in which we foresee it ; that his foreknowledge operates like our own. Now, is this, I ask, such an idea as we ought to form of Divine prescience, or such an idea as even the partisans of this system, which I am opposing, form ? Have we any reason for thus imposing upon the Deity the limitation of our own feebleness ? I think not. " Unendowed as we are, with any faculty of foresee- ing the future, it may be difficult for us to conceive of such a faculty in God. But yet can we not from analogy form such an idea ? We have now two fa- culties of perception— of the past by memory, of the present by observation ; can we not imagine a third to exist in God — the faculty of perceiving the future, as we perceive the past ? What would be the con- sequence ? This : that God, instead of conjecturing, by induction, the acts of human beings from the laws of the causes operating upon them, would see them DIVINE PRESCIENCE. 115 simply as the results of the free determinations of the will. Such perception of future acts no more im- plies the necessity of those actions, than the percep- tion of similar acts in the past. To see that effects arise from certain causes is not to force causes to produce them ; neither is it to compel these effects to follow. It matters not whether such a perception refers to the past, present, or future ; it is merely a perception ; and, therefore , far from producing the effect perceived, it even presupposes this effect al- ready produced. ~ u I do not pretend that this vision of what is to be is an operation of which our minds easily conceive. It is difficult to form an image of what we have never experienced ; but I do assert, that the power of see- ing what no longer exists is full as remarkable as that of seeing what has as yet no being, and that the rea- son of our readily conceiving of the former is only the fact that we are endowed with such a power : to my reason, the mystery is the same. " But whatever may or may not be in reality the mode of Divine foreknowledge, or however exact may be the image which we attempt to form of it, it always, I say, — and this is the only point I am de- sirous of proving, — it always remains a matter of un- certainty, which cannot be removed, whether the Di- vine foreknowledge is of a kind like our own, or not ; and as, in the one case, there would not be the same contradiction that there is in the other, between our belief in Divine foreknowledge and human freedom, it is proved true, I think, that no one has a right to assert the existence of such a contradiction, and the necessity that human reason should choose between them." * 116 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL, LINGULAR INCONSISTENCY OF NECESSITARIANS. There is no class of men who dwell with more frequency and apparent reverence, upon the truth, that il secret things belong to God," and those and those only, u that are revealed to us ;" that " none by search- ing can -find out God ;" that u as the heavens are high above the earth, so are His ways above our ways, and His thoughts above our thoughts ;" and that it is the height of presumption in us, to pretend to understand God's mode of knowing and acting. None are more ready to talk of mysteries in religion than they. Yet, strange as it may appear, it is nevertheless true, that their whole argument, drawn from the Divine fore- knowledge, against the doctrine of Liberty, and in favor of that of Necessity, is based entirely upon the assumption that they have found out and fully understand the mode of the Divine prescience of hu- man conduct ; that they have so measured and deter- mined the " ways and thoughts" of God, that they know that he cannot foresee any but necessary events ; that among many events, all in themselves equally possible, and none of them necessary in distinction from others, he cannot foreknow which, in fact, will arise. We may properly ask the Necessitarian whence he obtained this knowledge, so vast and deep ; whence he has thus " found out the Almighty to perfection ?" To me, the pretension to such knowledge appears more like presumption than that deep self-distrust and humiliation w T hich becomes the DIVINE PRESCIENCE. 117 Finite in the presence of the Infinite. This know- ledge has not been obtained from revelation. God has never told us that He can foresee none but necessa- ry events. Whether He can or cannot foresee events free as well as necessary, is certainly one of the " secret things" which God has not revealed. If we admit ourselves ignorant of the mode of God's fore- knowledge of future events (and who will dare deny the existence of such ignorance in his own case ?), the entire argument of the Necessitarian, based upon that fore-knowledge, in favor of his doctrine, falls to the ground at once. NECESSITARIAN OBJECTION TO THE ABOVE ARGUMENT. To all that has been said above, the Necessitarian brings an objection which he deems perfectly unan- swerable. It is this: If actions are free in the sense maintained in this treatise, then in themselves they are uncertain. If they are still certainly known to God, they are both certain and uncertain, at the same time. True, I answer, but not in the same sense. As far as the powers of the agent are con- cerned, the action may be uncertain, while God at the same time may know certainly how he will exert his powers. In reference merely to the powers of the agent, the event is uncertain. In reference to the mind of God, who knows instinctively how he will exert these powers, the event is certain. n CHAPTER VIL BEARING OF THE DOCTRINE OF LIBERTY UP- ON THE PURPOSES AND AGENCY OF GOD 5 JN RESPECT TO HUMAN CONDUCT. All truth is in harmony with itself. Every particu- lar truth is, and must be, in harmony with every other truth. If the doctrine of Necessity be assumed as true, we must take one view of the relation of God's purposes and agency in respect to the conduct of moral agents. If, on the other hand, we assume as true the doctrine of Liberty, quite another and a dif- ferent view, in respect to this whole subject, must be taken. In the remarks which I have to make upon this subject, I shall assume the truth of the doctrine of Liberty, together with those of the per- fect Divine Omniscience, Wisdom, and Benevolence, The question now arises, in the light of all these great truths, What relation do the Divine purposes and agency sustain to human action ? In what sense does God purpose, preordain, and bring to pass, the voluntary conduct of moral agents ? To this ques- tion but one answer can be given, in the light of the truths before us. God purposes human action in this sense only : He determines himself to act in a given manner, because it is wisest and best for him to act DIVINE PURPOSES. 119 in that manner, and in that manner only. He deter- mines this, knowing how intelligent beings will act under the influence brought to bear upon them by the Divine conduct. He purposes and brings about, or causes human action in this sense only, that in the counsels of eternity, He, in the exercise of infinite wisdom and goodness, preordains, and at the time appointed, gives existence to the motives and influences under which moral agents do act, and in the light of which they voluntarily determine their own charac- ter and conduct. conclusions from the above. god's purposes consistent with the liberty of creatures. 1. We perceive the perfect consistency of God's purposes and agency with human liberty. If the motives and influences in view of which men do act, do not destroy their free agency, — a fact which must be true from the nature of the Will, — then God's pur- poses to give existence, and his agency in giving ex- istence, to these motives and influences, cannot in any sense destroy, or interfere with such agency. This is a self-evident truth. SENSES IN WHICH GOD PURPOSED MORAL GOOD AND EVIL. 2. We also perceive the senses in which God pur- posed the existence of moral good and evil, in the universe. He purposed the existence of the motives, 120 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. in view of which He knew that a part of His sub- jects would render themselves holy, and a part would render themselves sinful. But when we contem- plate all the holiness and consequent happiness which do exist, we then perceive the reason why God gave existence to these motives. The sin conse- quent, in the sense above explained, constitutes no part of the reason for their existence, but was always, in the Divine Mind, a reason against their existence; which reason, however, was overpowered by infinite- ly more important reasons on the other side. The good which results from creation and providence is the great and exclusive object of creation and provi- dence. The evil, God always regretted, and would have prevented, if possible, i. e. if compatible with the existence of the best possible system." DEATH OF THE INCORRIGIBLE PREORDAINED BUT NOT WILLED. 3. We also perceive the perfect consistency of those Scriptures which represent God as, on the whole, purposing the death of incorrigible transgres- sors, and yet as not willing it, but as willing the op- posite. The purpose to destroy is based upon the foreseen incorrigibleness of the transgressor, — a pur- pose demanded by perfect wisdom and benevolence^ in view of that foreseen incorrigibleness. The in- corrigibleness itself, however, and the perdition con- sequent, are evils, the existence of which God never DIVINE PURPOSES. 121 willed; but are the opposite of what he willed, are evils which a being of perfect wisdom and goodness never could, and never can will. It is with perfect consistency, therefore, that the Scriptures represent God, in view of incorrigibleness foreseen, as purpos- ing the death of the transgressor, and at the same time, in view of the fact that such incorrigibleness is the opposite of what He wills the creature to do, as affirming, that He is not " willing that any should perish, but that all should come to a knowledge of the truth." GOD NOT RESPONSIBLE FOR THE DEATH OF THE INCORRIGIBLE. 4. We see, also, how it is, that, while God does that, and eternally purposed to do that, in view of which he eternally knew that certain of his creatures would for ever destroy themselves, none but them- selves are in fault for such destruction. The reasons are these : ( 1 . ) God never did anything in view of which men ought to act thus, nor which did not lay them under obligations infinite, to act differently, and which was not best adapted to secure that end. (2.) Their destruction constituted no part of the object of God in creation and providence, the oppo- site of this beino; true. (3. ) The great object of God in creation and provi- dence was and is, to produce the greatest possible 11* 122 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. amount of holiness and consequent happiness, and to prevent, in every possible way consistent with this end, the existence of sin, and consequently of misery, — Now if creatures perish under such an influence^ they perish by their own fault. SIN A MYSTERY. 5. I have a single remark to make upon those phenomena of the Will, in which evil is chosen in- stead of good, or sin instead of holiness. That all intelligent beings possess the power to make such a choice, is a fact affirmed by universal consciousness. But that any being, under any circumstances, should make such a choice, and that he should for ever re- fuse to return to the paths of virtue, notwithstanding his experience of the consequences of sin, is an abuse of human liberty, which must for ever remain an inexplicable mystery. When a being assigns the real reason in view of which right is chosen, we are always satisfied with such reason. But we are never satisfied with the reason for the opposite course. CONCLUSION FROM THE ABOVE. One conclusion forces itself upon us, from that view of the Divine government which consists with the doctrine of Liberty. The aspect of that gov- ernment which results from this view of the subject commends itself to the reason and conscience of the intelligent universe. Mysteries we do and must find DIVINE PURPOSES. 123 in it ; but absurdities and contradictions, never. Un- der such a Government, no being is condemned for what he cannot avoid, nor rewarded for what he could but do. While 11 God sits on no precarious throne, Nor borrows leave to be," the destiny of the creature turns upon his own de- serts, his own choice of good or evil. The elucida- tion of the principles of such a government " com- mends itself to every man's conscience in the sight of God." CHAPTER VIII. OBLIGATION PREDICABLE ONLY OF THE WILL. SECTION I. The Will, as I have already said, exists in a trinity with the Intelligence and Sensibility. In respect to the operations of the different departments of our mental being, I lay down the two following proposi- tions : 1. Obligation, moral desert, &c, are directly predi- cate only of the action of the Will. 2. For the operations of the other faculties we are accountable so far forth only as the existence and character of such operations depend upon the Will. In other words, it is for voluntary acts and states only that we are accountable. This I argue because, 1. Obligation, as we have seen, consists only with Liberty. All the phenomena of the Intelligence and Sensibility, in the circumstances of their occur- rence, are not free, but necessary. Accountability, therefore, cannot be predicated of such phenomena. We may be, and are, accountable for such phenomena, so far forth as their existence and character depend upon the Will : in other words, so far forth as they are voluntary, and not involuntary, states of mind. 2. The truth of the above proposition, and of that MORAL Oh OT9. 129 only, really corresponds with the universal conviction of the race. This conviction is expressed in two ways. (1.) When blame is affirmed of the operations of the Intelligence or Sen* ^riabJy thus thoughts or sentiments. You nave no right to When such act is contemplated in this point of light, it is almost universally admitted that it can- not be of a mixed character. But then another test is applied — that of intensity. It is conceivable, at least, it is said, that the intention might possess a higher degree of intensity than it does possess. It is, therefore, pronounced defective. On the same supposition, every moral act in existence might be pronounced defective. For we can, at least, con- ceive, that it might possess a higher degree of in- tensity. It has been abundantly established in the last Chapter, however, that there is no such test of moral actions as this, a test authorized either by rea- son or revelation. Sincerity is the only standard by which to determine the character and deserts of all moral acts and states. In the light of this standard, it is intuitively evident, that no one act can combine such contradictory and opposite elements as sin and holiness, right and wrong, an intention to obey and to disobey the moral law. 2. The opinions and reasonings of distinguished philosophers and theologians on the subject may be adduced in confirmation of the doctrine under con- sideration. Let it be borne in mind, that if the same 13* 146 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. act embraces such contradictory and opposite ele- ments as sin and holiness, it must be, in reality, op- posed to itself, one element constituting the act, be- ing in harmony with the law, and in opposition to the other element which is opposed to the law. Now the remark of Edwards upon this subject demands our special attention. " It is absurd,' 5 he says, " to suppose the same individual Will to oppose itself in its present act ; or the present choice to be opposite to and resisting present choice ; as absurd as it is to talk of two contrary motions in the same moving body at the same time." Does not the com- mon sense of the race affirm the truth of this state- ment ] Sin and holiness cannot enter into the same act, unless it embraces a serious intention to obey and not to obey the moral law at the same time. Is not this, in the language of Edwards, as u absurd as it is to talk of two contrary motions in the same mov- ing body at the same time." Equally conclusive is the argument of Kant upon the same subject. Having shown that mankind are divided into two classes, the morally good and the morally evil ; that the distinguishing characteristic of the former is, that they have adopted the Moral law as their maxim, that is, that it is their serious intention to comply with all the claims of the law ; and of the latter, that they have not adopted the law as their maxim ; he adds, u The sentiment of man- kind is, therefore, never indiffexent relatively to the SIMPLICITY OF MORAL ACTION. 147 law, and he never can be neither good nor evil." Then follows the paragraph to which special atten- tion is invited. "In like # manner, mankind cannot be, in some points of character, morally good, while he is, at the same time, in others evil ; for, is he in any point good, then the moral law is his maxim (that is, it is his serious intention to obey the law in the length and breadth of its claims) ; but is he like- wise, at the same time, in some points bad, then quoad [as to] these, the Moral law is not his maxim, (that is, in these particulars, it is his intention not to obey the law). But since the law is one and uni- versal, and as it commands in one act of life, so in all, then the maxim referring to it would be, at the same time universal and particular, which is a con- tradiction ;" (that is, it would be his intention to obey the law universally, and at the same time, not to obey it in certain particulars, one of the most palpa- ble contradictions conceivable.) To my mind the above argument has all the force of demonstration. Let it be borne in mind, that no man is morally good at all, unless it is his intention to obey the Moral law universally. This being his intention, the law has no higher claims upon him. Its full demands are, and must be, met in that intention. For what can the law require more, than that the voluntary powers shall be in full harmony with its demands, which is always true, when there is a sincere inten- tion to obey the law universally. Now, with this 148 doctri;;e of the will. intention, there can be nothing in the individual mo- rally evil ; unless there is, at the same time, an in- tention not to obey the law in certain particulars ; that is, not to obey it universally. A mixed moral act, or intention, therefore, is possible, only on this condition, that it shall embrace these two contradict- ory elements — a serious determination to obey the law universally, and a determination equally deci- sive, at the same time, to disobey it in certain parti- culars ; that is, not to obey it universally. I leave it with the advocates of the doctrine of Mixed Moral Action to dispose of this difficulty as they can. 3. If we could conceive of a moral act of a mixed character, the Moral law could not recognize it as holy at all. It presents but one scale by which to determine the character of moral acts, the command requiring us to love with all the heart. It knows such acts only as conformed, or not conformed, to this command. The mixed action, if it could exist, would, in the light of the Moral law, be placed among the not-conformed, just as much as those which are exclusively sinfuL The Moral law does not present two scales, according to one of which actions are classed as conformed or not-conformed, and according to the other, as partly conformed and partly not-conformed. Such a scale as this last is unknown in the circle of revealed truth. The Moral law presents us but one scale. Those acts which are in full conformity to its demands, it puts down as SIMPLICITY OF MORAL ACTION. 149 holy. Those not thus conformed, it puts down as sinful ; as holy or sinful is the only light in which actions stand according to the law. 4. Mixed actions, if they could exist, are as posi- tively prohibited by the law, and must therefore be placed under the category of total disobedience, just as much as those which are in themselves entirely sinful. While the law requires us to love with all the heart, it positively prohibits everything short of this. The individual, therefore, who puts forth an act of a mixed character, puts forth an act as totally and positively prohibited as the man who puts forth a totally sinful one. Both alike must be placed under the category of total disobedience. A father requires his two sons to go to the distance of ten rods, and positively prohibits their stopping short of the distance required. One determines to go nine rods, and there to stop. The other determines not to move at alL One has put forth an act of total diso- bedience just as much as the other. So of all moral acts which stop short of loving with all the heart. 5. A moral act of a mixed character cannot pos- sibly proceed from that regard to moral obligation which is an essential condition of the existence of any degree of virtue at all. Virtue, in no degree, can exist, except from a sacred regard to moral obligation. The individual who thus regards moral obligation in one degree, will regard it equally in all degrees. The individual, therefore, who, from such regard, 150 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL« yields to the claims of the law at all, will and must conform to the full measure of its demands. He cannot be m voluntary opposition to any one demand of that law. A mixed moral act, then, cannot pos- sibly proceed from that regard to moral obligation which is the essential condition of holiness in any degree. This leads me to remark, 6. That a moral act of a mixed character, if it could exist, could arise from none other than the most purely selfish and wicked intention conceivable. Three positions, we will suppose, are before the mind — a state of perfect conformity to the law, a state of total disobedience, and a third state combin- ing the elements of obedience and disobedience. By a voluntary act of moral election, an individual places himself in the last state, in distinction from each of the others. What must have been his in- tention in so doing ? He cannot have acted from a regard to moral rectitude. In that case, he would have elected the state of total obedience. His in- tention must have been to secure, at the same time, the reward of holiness and the u pleasures of sin " — a most selfish and wicked state surely. The suppo- sition of a moral act, that is, intention combining the elements of holiness and sin — is as great an ab- surdity as the supposition, that a circle has become a square, without losing any of its properties as a circle. 7. I remark again that the doctrine of mixed moral SIMPLICITY OF MORAL ACTION. 151 action is contradicted by the express teachings of inspiration. " Whosoever cometh after me," says Christ, " and forsaketh not all that he hath, he can- not be my disciple." The Bible knows men only as the disciples, or not disciples, of Christ. All who really comply with the condition above named are His disciples. All others, however near their com- pliance^ are not His disciples, any more than those who have not conformed in any degree. If an indi- vidual has really conformed to this condition, he has surely done his entire duty. He has loved with all his heart. What other meaning can we attach to the phrase, " forsaketh all that he hath ?" All persons who have not complied with this principle are de- clared to be wholly without the circle of disciple- ship. What is this, but a positive assertion, that a moral action of a mixed character is an impossi- bility ? Again. u No man can serve two masters." " Ye cannot serve God and mammon." Let us suppose that we can put forth intentions of a mixed charac- ter — intentions partly sinful and partly holy. So far as they are in harmony with the law, we serve God. So far as they are not in harmony with the law, we serve Mammon. Now, if all our moral exercises can be of a mixed character, then it is true that, at every period of our lives, w r e can serve God and Mammon. The service which we can render also to each, may be in every conceivable degree. We may 152 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. render, for example, ninety-nine degrees of service to God and one to Mammon, or ninety-nine to Mam- mon and one to God. Or our service may be equal- ly divided between the two. Can we conceive of a greater absurdity than this ? What also is the meaning of such declarations as this, u no fountain can send forth both sw r eet water and bitter," if the heart of man may exercise in- tentions combining such elements as sin and holi- ness ? Declarations of a similar kind abound in the Bible. They are surely without meaning, if the doctrine of Mixed Moral Actions is true. 8. Finally. It may be questioned whether the whole range of error presents a dogma of more per- nicious tendency than the doctrine of Mixed Moral Actions. It teaches moral agents that they may be selfish in all their moral exercises, and yet have enough of moral purity mingled with them to secure acceptance with the "Judge of all the earth." A man who has adopted such a principle will almost never, whatever his course of life may be, seem to himself to be destitute of real virtue. He will al- ways seem to himself to possess enough of it, to ren- der his acceptance with God certain. The kind of virtue which can mingle itself with selfishness and sin in individual intentions or moral acts, may be possessed, in different degrees, by the worst men on earth. If this be assumed as real holiness — that ho- liness which will stand the ordeal of eternity, who SIMPLICITY OF MORAL ACTION. 153 will, who should conceive himself destitute of a title to heaven ? Here is the fatal rock on which myri- ads of minds are wrecked for ever. Let it ever be borne in mind, that the same fountain cannot, at the same time and place, " send forth both sweet water and bitter." " Y e cannot serve God and Mammon." OBJECTIONS. Two or three objections to the doctrine above es- tablished demand a passing notice here. AN ACT OF WILL MAY RESULT FROM A VARIETY OF MOTIVES. 1. It is said that the mind may act under the influ- ence of a great variety of motives at one and the same time. The same intention, therefore, may be the result of different and opposite motives, and as a consequence, combine the elements of good and evil. In reply, I remark, that when the Will is in harmony with the Moral law, it respects the good and rejects the bad, alike in all the motives presented. The op- posite is true when it is not in harmony with the law. The same regard or disregard for moral obli- gation which will induce an individual to reject the evil and choose the good, or to make an opposite choice, in respect to one motive, will induce the same in respect to all other motives present at the same time. A mixed moral act can no more result from a combination of motives, than different and op- 14 154 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. posite motions can result in the same body at the same time, from forces acting upon it from different directions. LOVING WITH GREATER INTENSITY AT ONE TIME THAN ANOTHER. 2. It is said that we are conscious of loving our friends, and serving God, with greater strength and in- tensity at one time than at another. Yet our love, in all such instances, is real. Love, therefore, may be real, and yet be greatly defective — -that is, it may be real, and embrace elements morally wrong. It is true, that love may exist in different degrees, as far as the action of the Sensibility is concerned. It is not so, however, with love in the form of intention- intention in harmony with moral obligation, the only form of love demanded by the moral law. Such in- tention, in view of the same degrees of light, and under the same identical influences, cannot possess different degrees of intensity. The Will always yields, when it really does yield at all to moral obligation, with all the intensity it is, for the time being, capable of, or the nature of the case demands. MOMENTARY REVOLUTIONS OF CHARACTER. 3. On this theory, it is said, an individual may be- come perfectly good and perfectly bad, for any inde- finite number of instances, in any definite period of time. This consequence, to say nothing of what SIMPLICITY OF MORAL ACTION. 155 is likely to take place in fact, does, as far as possibili- ty is concerned, follow from this theory. But let us contemplate it, for a moment, in the light of an ex- ample or two. An individual, from regard to moral obligation, maintains perfect integrity of character, up to a given period of time. Then, under the influ- ence of temptation, he tells a deliberate falsehood. Did his previous integrity so fuse itself into that lie, as to make it partly good and partly bad ? — as to make it anything else than a total falsehood ? Did the prior goodness of David make his acts of adul- tery and murder partly good and partly bad ? Let the advocate of mixed moral action extract the ele^ ments of moral goodness from these acts if he can. He can just as well find these elements here, as in any other acts of disobedience to the Moral law. u The righteousness of the righteous cannot save him " from total sinfulness, any more than from con- demnation " in the day of his transgression." CHAPTER XI. RELATION OF THE WILL TO THE INTELLI- GENCE AND SENSIBILITY, IN ALL ACTS OR STATES, MORALLY RIGHT OR WRONG. The Will, sustaining the relation it does to the In- telligence and Sensibility, must yield itself to the control of one or the other of these departments of our nature. In all acts and states morally right, the Will is in harmony with the Intelligence, from re- spect to moral obligation or duty ; and all the desires and propensities, all the impulses of the Sensibility, are held in strict subordination. In all acts morally wrong, the Will is controlled by the Sensibility, ir- respective of the dictates of the Intelligence. Im- pulse, and not a regard to the just, the right, the true and the good, is the law of its action. In all such cases, as the impulses which control the Will are various, the external forms through which the internal acts, or intentions, will manifest themselves, will be equally diversified. Yet the spring of action is in all instances one and the same, impulse instead of a regard to duty. Virtue does not consist in being controlled by amiable^ instead of dissocial and malign impulses, and in a consequent exterior of a corres- ponding beauty and loveliness. It consists in a volun- NATURE OF VIRTUE, 157 tary harmony of intention with the just, the right, the true and the good — from a sacred respect to moral obligation, instead of being controlled by mere impulse of any kind whatever. On the principle above illustrated, I remark : THOSE WHO ARE OR ARE NOT TRULY VIRTUOUS, HOW DISTINGUISHED. 1. That the real distinction between those who are truly virtuous, and those who are not, now be- comes apparent. It does not consist, in all instances, in the mere exterior form of action, but in the spring or intention from which all such action proceeds. In most persons, and in all, at different periods, the amiable and social propensities predominate over the dissocial and malign. Hence much of the exterior will be characterized by much that is truly beautiful and lovely. In many, also, the impulsive power of conscience— that department of the Sensibility which is correlated to the idea of right and wrong, and im- pels to obedience to the Moral law — is strongly de- veloped, and may consequently take its turn in con- trolling the WilL In all such instances, there will be the external forms of real virtue. It is one thing, however, to put on the exterior of virtue from mere impulse, and quite another, to do the same thing from an internal respect and sacred regard for duty. How many individuals, who may be now wearing the fairest forms of virtue, will find within them, as 14* 158 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. soon as present impulses are supplanted by the strong- action of others, in opposition to rectitude, no max- ims of Will, in harmony with the law of goodness, to resist and subject such impulses. Their conduct is in conformity to the requirements of virtue, not from any internal intention to be in universal har- mony with moral obligation, but simply because, for the time being, the strongest impulse happens to be in that direction. No individual, it should ever be kept in mind, makes any approach to real virtue, whatever impulses he may be controlled by, till, by a sealing act of moral election, the Will is placed in harmony with the universal law of duty, and all external action of a moral character pro- ceeds from this internal, all-controlling intention. Here we find the broad and fundamental distinction between those who are truly virtuous, and those who are not. SELFISHNESS AND BENEVOLENCE. 2. We are also prepared to explain the real dif- ference between Selfishness and Benevolence. The latter expresses and comprehends all the forms of real virtue of every kind and degree. The former comprehends and expresses the forms of vice or sin. Benevolence consists in the full harmony of the Will or intention with the just, the right, the true, and the good, from a regard to moral obligation. Self- ishness consists in voluntary subjection to impulse^ NATURE OF VIRTUE. 159 irrespective of such obligation. Whenever self- gratification is the law of action, there is pure self- ishness, whatever the character or direction of the impulse may be. Selfishness has sometimes been very incorrectly defined, as a supreme regard to our own interest or happiness. If this is a correct defi- nition, the drunkard is not selfish at all ; for he sacri- fices his present and future happiness, to gratify a beastly appetite, and destroys present peace in the act of self-gratification. If selfishness, however, consists in mere subjection to impulse, how supreme his selfishness at once appears ! A mother who does not act from moral obligation, when under the strong influence of maternal affection, appears most distin- guished in her assiduous care of her offspring. Now let this affection be crossed by some plain question of duty, so that she must violate the latter, or sub- ject the former, and how soon will selfishness mani- fest itself, in the triumph of impulse over duty ! A gift is not more effectual in blinding the eyes, than natural affection uncontrolled by a regard to moral obligation. Men are just as selfish, that is, as per- fectly subject to the law of self-gratification, when under the influence of the social and amiable pro- pensities, as when under that of the dissocial and malign, when, in both instances alike, impulse is the law of action. Moral agents were made, and are required to be, social and amiable, from higher princi- ples than mere impulse. 160 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. COMMON MISTAKE. 3. I notice a mistake of fundamental importance into which many appear to have fallen, in judging of the moral character of individuals. As we have seen, when the Will is wholly controlled by the Sen- sibility irrespective of moral obligation, the impulsive department of conscience takes its turn, among the other propensities, in controlling the action of the voluntary power. Now because, in all such instan- ces, there are the exterior forms of virtue, together with an apparently sincere internal regard for the same, the presence of real virtue is consequently in- ferred. Now before such- a conclusion can be authorized, one question needs to be determined, the spring from which such apparent virtues origi- nate. They may arise from that regard to moral obligation which constitutes real virtue. Or they may be the result purely of excited Sensibility, which, in such instances happens to be in the direction of the forms of virtue. DEFECTIVE FORMS OF VIRTUE. 4. Another very frequent mistake bearing upon moral character deserves a passing notice here. Men sometimes manifest, and doubtless with a con- sciousness of inward sincerity, a very high regard for some one or more particular principles of virtue, while they manifest an equal disregard of all other principles. Every real reform, for example, has its NATURE OF VIRTUE. 161 basis in some great principle of morality. Men often advocate, with great zeal, such reforms, together with the principle on which they rest. They talk of virtue, when called to defend that principle, of a re- gard to moral obligation, together with the necessity of self-sacrifice at the shrine of duty, as if respect for universal rectitude commanded the entire powers of their being. Yet but a slight observation will most clearly evince, that their regard for the right, the true, and the good, is wholly circumscribed by this one principle. Still, such persons are very likely to regard themselves as virtuous in a very high degree. In reality, however, they have not made the first ap- proach to real virtue. Their respect for this one principle, together with its specific applications, has its spring in some other department of their nature, than a regard for what is right in itself. Otherwise their respect for what is right, would be co-extensive with the entire range of moral obligation. SEC. II. TEST OF CONFORMITY TO MORAL PRINCIPLE. In preceding chapters, the great truth has been fully established, that the Moral law addresses its commands and prohibitions to the Will only, and that moral obligation is predicable only of the action of the voluntary power, other states being required, only as their existence and character are conditioned on the right exercise of that power. From this, it undeniably follows, that the Moral law, in all the 162 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. length and breadth of its requirements, finds its entire fulfilment within the sphere of the Will. A ques- tion of great importance here presents itself: By what test shall we determine whether the Will is, or is not, in full harmony with the law ? In the investi- gation of this question, we may perhaps be thought to be intruding somewhat into the domain of Moral Philosophy. Reasons of great importance, in the judgment of the writer, however, demand its intro- duction here. The Moral law is presented to us through two comprehensive precepts. Yet, a moment's reflec- tion will convince us that both these precepts have their basis in one common principle, and are, in reality, the enunciation of that one principle. The identical reason why we are bound to love God with all the heart, requires us to love our neighbors as ourselves. So the subject is presented by our Saviour himself. After speaking of the first and great commandment, He adds, " the second is like unto it," that is, it rests upon the same principle as the first. Now the question is, What is this great principle, obedience to which implies a full discharge of all obligation, actual and conceivable ; the principle which comprehends all other principles of the Moral law, and of which each particular precept is only the enunciation of this one common principle in its end- lessly diversified applications ? This principle has NATURE OF VIRTUE. 163 been announced in forms somewhat different, by dif- ferent philosophers. I will present two or three of these forms. The first that I notice is this. It shall be the serious intention of all moral agents to esteem and treat all persons, interests, and objects ac- cording to their perceived intrinsic and relative im- portance, and out of respect for their intrinsic worth, or in obedience to the idea of duty, or moral obligation. Every one will readily apprehend, that the above is a correct enunciation of the principle under consider- ation. It expresses the fundamental reason why obedience to each and every moral principle is bind- ing upon us. The reason and only reason why we are bound to love God with all the heart, is the in- trinsic and relative importance of the object present- ed to the mind in the contemplation of the Infinite and Perfect. The reason why we are bound to love our neighbor as ourselves, is the fact, that his rights and interests are apprehended, as of the same value and sacredness as our own. In the intention under consideration,, all obligation, actual and conceivable, is really met. God will occupy his appropriate place in the heart, and the creature his. No real right or interest will be dis-esteemed, and each will intention- ally command that attention and regard which its in- trinsic and relative importance demands. Every moral agent is under obligation infinite ever to be under the supreme control of such an intention, and no such agent can be under obligation to be or to do anything more than this. 164 DOCTRINE OF THE WILLo The same principle has been announced in a form somewhat different by Kant, to wit : " So act that thy maxim of Will (intention) might become law in a system of universal moral obligation "—that is, let your controlling intention be always such, that all In- telligents may properly be required ever to be under the supreme control of the same intention. By Cousin, the same principle is thus announced : H The moral principle being universal, the sign, the external type by which a resolution may be recog- nized as conformed to this principle, is the impossi- bility of not erecting the immediate motive (inten- tion) of the particular act or resolution, into a maxim of universal legislation " — that is, we cannot but affirm that every moral agent in existence is bound to act from the same motive or intention. It will readily be perceived, that each of these forms is really identical with that above announced and illustrated. It is only when we are conscious of the supreme control of the intention, to esteem and treat all persons and interests according to their in- trinsic and relative importance, from respect to the idea of duty, that, in conformity with the principle as announced by Kant, our maxim of Will might be- come law in a system of universal legislation. When we are conscious of the control of such an intention, it is impossible for us not to affirm, according to the principle, as announced by Cousin, that all Intelli- gents are bound always to be under the control of NATURE OF VIRTUE. 165 the same intention. Two or three suggestions will close what I have to say on this point. 4 COMMON MISTAKE. 1. We notice the fundamental mistake of many philosophers and divines in treating of moral exer- cises, or states of mind. Such exercises are very commonly represented as consisting wholly in excit- ed states of the Sensibility. Thus Dr. Brown re- presents all moral exercises and states as con- sisting in emotions of a given character. One of the most distinguished Professors of Theology in this country laid down this proposition, as the basis of a course of lectures on Moral Philosophy, that " every- thing right or wrong in a moral agent, consists ex- clusively of right or wrong feelings " — feelings as dis- tinguished from volitions as phenomena of Will. Now precisely the reverse of the above proposition is true, to wit : that nothing right or wrong, in a moral agent, consists in any states of the Sensibility irrespective of the action of the Will. Who would dare to say, when he has particular emotions, desires, or involuntary feelings, that the Moral law has no further claim upon him, that all its demands are fully met in those feelings ? Who would dare to affirm, when he has any particular emotions, that all moral agents in existence are bound to have those identical feelings ? If the demands of the Moral law are fully met in any states of the Sensibility — which would be 15 166 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. true, if everything right or wrong, in moral agents, consists of right or wrong feelings — then all moral agents, at all times, and under all circumstances, are bound to have these same feelings. For what the law demands, at one time, it demands at all times. All the foundations of moral obligation are swept away by the theory under consideration. LOVE AS REQUIRED BY THE MORAL LAW. 2. We are now prepared to state distinctly the na- ture of that love which is the "fulfilling of the law." It does not, as all admit, consist in the mere external act. Nor does it consist, for reasons equally obvi- ous and universally admitted, in any mere convictions of the Intelligence. For reasons above assigned, it does not consist in any states of the Sensibility. No man, when he is conscious of such feelings, can affirm that all Intelligents are bound, under all cir- cumstances, to have the same feelings that he now has. This would be true, if the love under consi- deration consists of such feelings. But when, from a regard to the idea of duty, the whole being is vol- untarily consecrated to the promotion, in the highest degree, of universal good ; and when, in the pursuit of this end, there is a serious intention to esteem and treat all beings and interests according to their intrin- sic and relative importance ; here is the love which is the fulfilling of the law. Here is the intention by which all intelligents, in reference to all interests and NATURE OF VIRTUE. 167 objects, are, at all times, bound to be controlled, and which must be imposed, as universal law, upon such Intelligents in every system of righteous moral legis- lation. Here is the intention, in the exercise of which all obligation is fully met. Here, consequent- ly, is that love which is the fulfilling of the law. In a subsequent Chapter, my design is to show that this is the view of the subject presented in the Scriptures of truth. I now present it merely as a necessary truth of the universal Intelligence. IDENTITY OF CHARACTER AMONG ALL BEINGS MORALLY VIRTUOUS. 3. We now perceive clearly in what consists the real identity of moral character, in all Intelligents of true moral rectitude. Their occupations, forms of external deportment, and their internal convictions and feelings, may be endlessly diversified. Yet one omnipresent, all-controlling intention, an intention which is ever one and identical, directs all their moral movements. It is the intention, in the promotion of the highest good of universal being, to esteem and treat all persons and interests according to their in- trinsic and relative importance, from regard to moral obligation. Thus moral virtue, in all Intelligents possessed of it, is perfectly one and identical. In this sense only are all moral agents capable of per- fect identity of* character. They cannot all have, at all times, or perhaps at any time, precisely the same 168 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. thoughts and feelings. But they can all have, at all times, one and the same intention. The omnipresent influence and control of the intention above illustrat- ed, constitutes a perfect identity of character in God and all beings morally pure in existence. For this reason, the supreme control of this intention implies, in all moral agents alike, a perfect fulfilment of the law, a full discharge of all obligation of every kind, CHAPTER XII. THE ELEMENT OF THE WILL IN COMPLEX PHENOMENA. SECTION I. Every perception, every judgment, every thought, which appears within the entire sphere of the Intel- ligence ; every sensation, every emotion, every de- sire, all the states of the Sensibility, present objects for the action of the Will in one direction or another. The sphere of the Will's activity, therefore, is as extensive as the vast and almost boundless range of the Intelligence and Sensibility both. Now while all the phenomena of these two last named faculties are, in themselves, wholly destitute of moral charac- ter, the action of the Will, in the direction of such phenomena, constitutes complex states of mind, which have a positive moral character. In all in- stances, the moral and voluntary elements are one and identical. As the distinction under considera- tion has been overlooked by the great mass of phi- losophers and theologians, and as very great errors have thereby arisen, not only in philosophy, but in theology and morals both, I will dwell at more length upon the subject than I otherwise should have done. My remarks will be confined to the action tff the Will in the direction of the natural propensities and religious affections. 15* 170 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. ACTION OF THE WILL IN THE DIRECTION OF THE NA- TURAL PROPENSITIES. EMOTION, DESIRE, AND WISH DEFINED. 1. In respect to the action of the Will in the di- rection of the natural propensities, such as the ap- petites, the love of esteem, of power, &c, I would remark, that the complex states thence resulting, are commonly explained as simple feelings or states of the Sensibility. In presenting this subject in a pro- per light, the following explanations are deemed ne- cessary. When any physical power operates upon any of the organs of sense, or when any thought is present in the Intelligence, the state of the Sensibili- ty immediately and necessarily resulting is called a sensation or emotion. When any feeling arises im- pelling the Will to seek or avoid the object of that sensation or emotion, this impulsive state of the Sensibility is called a desire. When the Will con- curs with the desire, a complex state of mind results, called a wish. Wish is distinguished from Desire in this, that in the former, the desire is cherished and perpetuated by the concurrence of the Will with the desire. When the Desire impels the Will towards a prohibited object, the action of the Will, in concur- rence with the desire, constitutes a wish morally wrong. When the Desire impels the Will in a re- quired direction, and the Will, from a respect to the idea of duty, concurs with the desire, a wish arises which is morally virtuous. This principle holds true COMPLEX PHENOMENA. 171 in regard to the action of all the propensities. The excitement of the propensity, as a state of the Sen- sibility, constitutes desire — a feeling in itself desti- tute of all moral qualities. The action of the Will in concurrence with, or opposition to, this feeling, consti- tutes a complex state of mind morally right or wrong. ANGER, PRIDE, AMEITION, &C. Anger, for example, as prohibited by the moral law, is not a mere feeling of displeasure awakened by some injury, real or supposed, perpetrated by another. This state, on the other hand, consists in the surrendering of the Will to the control of that feeling, and thus acting from malign impulse. Pride also is not the mere desire of esteem. It consists in voluntary subjection to that propensity, seeking es- teem and admiration as the great end of existence. Ambition, too, is not mere desire of power, but the voluntary surrendering of our being to the control of that propensity. The same, I repeat, holds true in respect to all the propensities. No mere excitement of the Sensibility, irrespective of the action of the Will, has any moral character. In the action of the Will in respect to such states — action which must arise in some direction under such circumstances — moral guilt, or praise worthiness, arises. I might here adduce other cases in illustration of the same principle ; as, for example, the fact that in- temperance in food and drink does not consist, as a moral act or state, in the mere strength of the appe- 172 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. tite — that is, in the degree in which it is excited in the presence of its appropriate objects. Nor does it consist in mere excess in the quantity partaken of — excess considered as an external act. It consists, on the other hand, in the surrendering of the voluntary power to the control of the appetite. The excess referred to is the consequent and index of such volun- tary subjection. The above examples, however, are abundantly sufficient to illustrate the principle. RELIGIOUS AFFECTIONS. 2. We will now contemplate' the element of the Will in those complex phenomena denominated reli- gions affectio?is. The position which 1 here assume is this, that whatever in such affections is morally right and praiseworthy, that which is directly refer- red to, where such affections are required of us, is the voluntary element to be found in them. The voluntary element is directly required. Other ele- ments are required only on the ground that their ex- istence is conditioned upon, and necessarily results from, that of the voluntary element. This must be admitted, or we must deny the position established in the last Chapter, to wit : that all the requirements of the Moral law are fully met in the right action of the Will. SCRIPTURE TESTIMONY. My object now is to show, that this is the light in COMPLEX PHENOMENA. 173 which the subject is really presented in the Scrip- tures. I will cite, as examples, the three cardinal virtues of Christianity, Repentance, Love, and Faith. The question is, Are these virtues or affections, pre- sented in the Bible as mere convictions of the Intelli- gence, or states of the Sensibility ? Are they not, on the other hand, presented as voluntary states of mind, or as acts of Will] Are not the commands requiring them fully met in such acts 1 REPENTANCE. In regard to Repentance, I would remark, that the term is scarcely used at all in the Old Testament. Other terms and phrases are there employed to ex- press the same thing; as for example, " Turn ye ;" " Let the wicked forsake his way ;" u Let him turn unto the Lord ;" " He that confesseth and forsake th his sins shall find mercy," &e. In all such passages repentance is most clearly presented as consisting exclusively of voluntary acts or intentions. The com- mands requiring it are, therefore, fully met in such acts. In the New Testament this virtue is distin- guished from Godly Sorrow, the state of the Sensi- bility which accompanies its exercise. As distin- guished from the action of the Sensibility, what can it be, but a voluntary state, as presented in the Old Testament % When the mind places itself in volun- tary harmony with those convictions and feelings which attend a consciousness of sin as committed 174 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. against God and man, this is the repentance recog- nized and required as such in the Bible. It does not consist in the mere conviction of sin ; for then the worst of men, and even devils, would be truly re- pentant. Nor does it consist in the states of the Sen- sibility which attend such convictions ; else Repent- ance would be Godly Sorrow, from which the Bible, as stated above, definitely distinguishes it. It must consist in a voluntary act, in which, in accordance with those convictions and feelings, the mind turns from sin to holiness, from selfishness to benevolence, from the paths of disobedience to the service of God. LOVE. A single passage will distinctly set before us the nature of Love as required in the Bible — that Jove which comprehends all other virtues, and the exer- cise of which is the " fulfilling of the law." " Hereby," says the sacred writer, " we perceive the love of God." The phrase u ofGod"i& not found in the origin- al. The passage, as it there stands, reads thus : " By this we know love ;" that is, we know the nature of the love which the Scriptures require, when they affirm, that u love is the fulfilling of the law." What is that in which, according to the express teaching of inspiration, we learn the nature of this love 1 u Because he laid down his life for us : and we ought to lay down our lives for the brethren." In the act of " laying down his life for lis," we are COMPLEX PHENOMENA. 175 here told, that the love required of us is embodied and revealed. What is the nature of this love ? I answer, 1. It is not a conviction of the Intelligence, nor any excited state of the Sensibility. No such thing is here referred to. 2. It does and must consist exclusively in a volun- tary act, or intention. " He laid down his life for us." What is this but a voluntary act % Yet this is love, the " love which is the fulfilling of the law." 3. As an act of Will, love must consist exclusive- ly in a voluntary devotion of our entire powers to one end, the highest good of universal being, from a re- gard to the idea of duty. " He laid down his life for us." " We ought to lay down our lives for the brethren." In each particular here presented, a universal prin- ciple is expressed and revealed. Christ " laid down his life for us," because he was in a state of volun- tary consecration to the good of universal being. The particular act was put forth, as a means to this end. In a voluntary consecration to the same end, and as a means to this end, it is declared, that " we ought to lay down our lives for the brethren." When, therefore, the Scriptures require love of us, they do not demand the existence of particular convictions of the Intelligence, nor certain states of the Sensibility. They require the voluntary consecration of our en- tire being and interests to the great end of universal good. In this act of consecration, and in the employ- 176 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. ment of all our powers and interests, under the con- trol of this one intention, we fulfil the Law. We fully discharge all obligations, actual and conceiva- ble, that are devolved upon us. The exercise of love, like that of repentance, is attended with parti- cular convictions and feelings. These feelings are indirectly required in the precepts demanding love, and required, because when the latter does exist, the former will of course exist. OF FAITH. But little need be said in explanation of the nature of Faith. It is everywhere presented in the Bible, as synonymous with trwt, reposing confidence, committing our interests to God as to a " faithful Creator." Now Trust is undeniably a voluntary state of mind. " I know," says Paul, u in whom I have believed," that is, exercised faith, u that he is able to keep that which I have committed to him against that day." Here the act of committing to the care of another, which can be nothing else than an act of Will, is presented as synonymous with Faith. Faith, then, does not consist in conviction, nor in any excited feelings. It is a voluntary act, en- trusting our interests to God as to a faithful Creator. The principle above established must apply to all reli- gious affections of every kind. COMPLEX PHENOMENA. 177 SEC. II. GENERAL TOPICS SUGGESTED BY THE TRUTH ILLUSTRATED IN THE PRECEDING SECTION. Few truths are of greater practical moment than that illustrated in the preceding section. My object, now, is to apply it to the elucidation of certain im- portant questions which require elucidation. CONVICTIONS, FEELINGS AND EXTERNAL ACTIONS — WHY REQUIRED, OR PROHIBITED. 1. We see why it is, that, while no mere external action, no state of the Intelligence or Sensibility, has any moral character in itself, irrespective of the ac- tion of the Will, still such acts and states are spe- cifically and formally required or prohibited in the Bible. In such precepts the effect is put for the cause. These acts and states are required, or prohibited, as the natural and necessary results of right or wrong intentions. The thing really referred to, in such commands and prohibitions, is not the acts or states specified, but the cause of such acts and states, to wit : the right or wrong action of the Will. Suppose, that a certain loathsome disease of the body would necessarily result from certain inten- tions, or acts of Will. Now God might prohibit the intention which causes that disease, in either of two ways. He might specify the intention and di- rectly prohibit that ; or he might prohibit the same thing, in such a form as this : Thou shalt not have this disease. Every one will perceive that, in both prohibitions, the same thing, precisely, would be re- 16 178 DOCTRINE OF TfiE WILL. ferred to and intended, to wit : the intention which sustains to the evil designed to be prevented, the relation of a cause. The same principle, precisely, holds true in respect to all external actions and states of the Intelligence and Sensibility, which are specifically required or prohibited. OUR RESPONSIBILITY IN RESPECT TO SUCH PHENOMENA. 2. We also distinctly perceive the ground of our responsibility for the existence of external actions, and internal convictions and feelings. Whatever ef- fects, external or internal, necessarily result, and are or may be known to result, from the right or wrong action of the Will, we may properly be held respon- sible for. Now, all external actions and internal convictions and feelings which are required of or prohibited to us, sustain precisely this relation to the right or wrong action of the Will. The intention being given, the effect follows as a consequence. For this reason we are held responsible for the effect. FEELINGS HOW CONTROLLED BY THE WILL. 3. We now notice the power of control which the Will has over the feelings. (1.) In one respect its control is unlimited. It may yield itself to the control of the feelings, or wholly withhold its concurrence. (2.) In respect to all feelings, especially those which impel to violent or unlawful action, the Will COMPLEX PHENOMENA. 179 may exert a direct influence which will either greatly modify, or totally suppress the feeling. For exam- ple, when there is an inflexible purpose of Will not to yield to angry feelings, if they should arise, and to suppress them, as soon as they appear, feelings of a violent character will not result to any great extent, whatever provocations the mind may be subject to. The same holds true of almost all feelings of every kind. Whenever they appear, if tkey are directly and strongly willed down, they will either be greatly modified, or totally disappear. (3.) Over the action and states of the Sensibility the Will may exert an indirect influence which is all-powerful. If, for example, the Will is in full harmony with the infinite, the eternal, the just, the right, the true and the good, the Intelligence will, of course, be occupied with " whatsoever things are true, honest, just, pure, lovely and of good report," and the Sensibility, continually acted upon by such objects, will mirror forth, in pure emotions and desires, the pure thoughts of the Intelligence, and the hallowed purposes of the Will. The Sensibility will be wholly isolated from all feelings gross and sensual. On the other hand, let the Will be yielded to the control of impure and sensual impulse, and how gross and impure the thoughts and feelings will become. In yielding, or refusing to yield, to the supreme control of the law of Goodness, the Will really, though indirectly, determines the action of the Intelligence and Sensibility both. 180 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. (4.) To present the whole subject in a proper light, a fixed law of the affections demands special attention. A husband, for example, has pledged to his wife, not only kind intentions, but the exclusive control of those peculiar affections which constitute the basis of the marriage union. Let him cherish a proper regard for the sacredness of that pledge, and the wife will so completely and exclusively fill and command her appropriate sphere in the affections, that, under no circumstances whatever, will there be a tendency towards any other individual. The same holds true of every department of the affections, not only in respect to those which connect us with the creature, but also with the Creator. The affections the Will may control by a fixed and changeless law. Such being the relation of the Will to the Sensi- bility, while it is true that there is nothing right or wrong in any feelings, irrespective of the action of the Will, still the presence of feelings impure and sensual, may be a certain indication of the wrong action of the voluntary power. In such a light their presence should always be regarded. EELATION OF FAITH TO OTHER EXERCISES MORALLY RIGHT. 4. In the preceding Section it has been fully shown, that love, repentance, faith, and all other religious exercises, are, in their fundamental and characteristic elements, phenomena of the Will. We will now, COMPLEX PHENOMENA. 181 for a few moments, contemplate the relations of these different exercises to one another, especially the relation of Faith to other exercises of a kindred character. While it is true, as has been demon- strated in a preceding Chapter, that the Will cannot at the same time put forth intentions of a contra- dictory character, such as sin and holiness, it is equally true, that it may simultaneously put forth acts of a homogeneous character. In view of our obligations to yield implicit obedience to God, we may purpose such obedience. In view of the fact, that, in the Gospel, grace is proffered to perfect us in our obedience, at the same time that we purpose obedience with all the heart, we may exercise im- plicit trust, or faith for " grace whereby we may serve God acceptably with reverence and godly fear." Now, such is our condition as sinners, that without a revelation of this grace, we should never purpose obedience in the first instance. Without the continued influence of that grace, this purpose would not subsequently be perfected and perpe- tuated. The purpose is first formed in reliance upon Divine grace ; and but for this grace and consequent reliance, would never have been formed. In con- sequence of the influence of this grace relied upon, and received by faith, this same purpose is afterwards perfected and perpetuated. Thus, we see, that the purpose of obedience is really conditioned for its existence and perpetuity upon the act of reliance 16* 182 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. upon Divine grace. The same holds true of the relation of Faith to all acts or intentions morally right or holy. One act of Will, in itself perfectly pure, is really conditioned upon another in itself equally pure. This is the doctrine of Moral Purification, or Sanctification by faith, a doctrine which is no less true, as a fact in philosophy, than as a revealed truth of inspiration. CHAPTER XIII. INFLUENCE OF THE WILL IN INTELLECTUAL JUDGMENTS. MEN OFTEN VOLUNTARY IN THEIR OPINIONS. It is an old maxim, that the Will governs the un- derstanding. It becomes a very important inquiry with us, To what extent, and in what sense, is this maxim true ? It is undeniable, that, in many impor- tant respects, mankind are voluntary in their opi- nions and judgments, and therefore, responsible for them. We often hear the declaration, " You ought, or ought not, to entertain such and such opinions, to form such and such judgments." " You are bound to admit, or have no right to admit, such and such things as true." Men often speak, also, of pre-judging particular cases, and thus incurring guilt. A ques- tion may very properly be asked here, what are these opinions, judgments, admissions, pre-judgments, &c. ? Are they real affirmations of the Intelligence, or are they exclusively phenomena of the Will ? ERROR NOT FROM THE INTELLIGENCE, BUT THE WILL. The proposition which I lay down is this, that the Intelligence , in its appropriate exercise, can seldom 184 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL* if ever , make wrong affirmations ; that wrong opinion^ admissions , pre-judgments, Sfc. , are in most, if not all instances, nothing else than phenomena, or assumptions of Will If the Intelligence can make wrong affir- mations, it is important to determine in what depart- ment of its action such affirmations may be found. PRIMARY FACULTIES CAJSNOT ERR. Let us first contemplate the action of the primary intellectual faculties— Sense, or the faculty of external perception ; Consciousness, the faculty of internal ob- servation ; and Reason, the faculty which gives us necessai'y and universal truths. The two former faculties give us phenomena external and internal. The latter gives us the logical antecedents of phe- nomena, thus perceived and affirmed,— to wit : the ideas of substance, cause, space, time, &c. In the action of these faculties, surely, real error is im- possible. SO OF THE SECONDARY FACULTIES. Let us now contemplate the action of the secon- dary faculties, the Understanding and Judgment* The former unites the elements given by the three primary faculties into notions of particular objects. The latter classifies these notions according to quali- ties perceived. Here, also, we find no place for wrong affirmations. The understanding can only combine the elements actually given by the primary SOURCE OF ERROR. 185 faculties. The Judgment can classify only according to qualities actually perceived. Thus I might go over the entire range of the Intelligence, and show, that seldom, if ever, in its appropriate action, it can make wrong affirmations. ERROR, WHERE FOUND. ASSUMPTION. Where then is the place for error, for wrong opinions, and pre-judgments ? Let us suppose, that a number of individuals are observing some object at a distance from them. No qualities are given but those common to a variety of objects, such as a man, horse, ox, &c. The perceptive faculty has deceived no one in this case. It has given nothing but real qualities. The Understanding can only form a notion of it, as an object possessing these par- ticular qualities. The Judgment can only affirm, that the qualities perceived are common to different classes of objects, and consequently, that no affirma- tions can be made as to what class the object per- ceived does belong. The Intelligence, therefore, makes no false affirmations. Still the inquiry goes round. " What is it ?" One answers, " It is a man." That is my opinion. Another : " It is a horse." That is my judgment. Another still says, " I differ from you all. It is an ox." That is my notion. Now, what are these opinions, judgments, and no- tions ? Are they real affirmations of the Intelligence ? By no means. The Intelligence cannot affirm at all, 186 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. under such circumstances. They are nothing in reality, but mere assumptions of the Will. A vast majority of the so called opinions, beliefs, judg- ments, and notions among men, and all where error- is found, are nothing but assumptions of the Will. Assumptions are sometimes based upon real affir- mations of the Intelligence, and sometimes not. Suppose the individuals above referred to approach the object, till qualities are given which are peculiar to the horse. The Judgment at once classifies the object accordingly. As soon as this takes place, they all exclaim, u well, it is a horse." Here are assumptions again, but assumptions based upon real affirmations of the Intelligence. In the former in- stance we had assumptions based upon no such affir- mations. False assumptions do net always imply moral gtftlt. Much of the necessary business of life has no other basis than prudent or imprudent guessing. When the farmer, for example, casts any particular seed into the ground, it is only by balance of proba- bilities that he often determines, as far as he does or can determine, what is best ; and not unfrequently is he necessitated to assume and act, when all proba- bilities are so perfectly balanced, that he can find no reasons at all for taking one course in distinction from another. Yet no moral guilt is incurred when one is necessitated to act in some direction, and when all available light has been sought and em- ployed to determine the direction w 7 hich is best. SOURCE OF ERROR. 187 As false assumptions, however, often involve very great moral guilt, it may be important to develope some of the distinguishing characteristics of assump- tions of this class. 1. All assumptions involve moral guilt, which are in opposition to the real and positive affirmations of the Intelligence. As the Will may assume in the absence of such affirmations, and in the direction of them, so it may in opposition to them. When you have carried a man's Intellect in favor of a given pro- position, it is by no means certain that you have gain- ed his assent to its truth. He may still assume, that all the evidence presented is inadequate, and conse- quently refuse to admit its truth. When the Will thus divorces itself from the Intelligence, guilt of no ordinary character is incurred. Men often express their convictions of the guilt thus incurred, by saying fo individuals, " You are bound to admit that fact or proposition as true. You are already convinced. What excuse have you for not yielding to that con- viction ?" Yet individuals will often do fatal violence to their intellectual and moral nature, by holding on to assumptions, in reality known to be false. 2 . Assumptions involve moral guilt which are form- ed without availing ourselves of all the light within our reach as the basis of our assumptions. For us to assume any proposition, or statement, to be true or false, in the absence of affirmations of the Intelligence, as the basis of such assumptions, when adequate light 188 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. is available, involves the same criminality, as assump- tions in opposition to the Intelligence. Hence we often have the expression in common life, " You had no right to form a judgment under such circumstan- ces. You were bound, before doing it, to avail your- self of all the light within your reach." 3. Positive assumptions, without intellectual affir- mations as their basis, equally positive, involve mo- ral guilt of no ordinary character. As remarked above, we are often placed in circumstances in which we are necessitated to act in some direction, and to select some particular course without any perceived reasons in favor of that one course in distinction from another. Now while action is proper in such a condi- tion, it is not proper to make a positive assumption that the course selected is the best. Suppose, that all the facts before my mind bearing upon the charac- ter of a neighbor, are equally consistent with the possession, on his part, of a character either good or bad. I do violence to my intellectual and moral na- ture, if, under such circumstances, I make the as- sumption that his character is either the one or the other, and especially, that it is the latter instead of the former. How often do flagrant transgressions of moral rectitude occur in such instances ! PRE-JUDGMENTS. A few remarks are deemed requisite on this topic. A pre-judgment is an assumption, that a proposition SOURCE OF ERROR. 189 or statement is true or false, before the facts, bearing upon the case, have been heard. Such assumptions are generally classed under the term prejudice. Thus it is said of individuals, that they are prejudiced in favor or against certain persons, sentiments, or causes. The real meaning of such statements is, that individ- uals have made assumptions in one direction or an- other, prior to a hearing of the facts of the case, and irrespective of such facts. INTELLECT NOT DECEIVED IN PRE-JUDGMENTS. It is commonly said, that such prejudices, or pre- judgments, blind the mind to facts of one class, and render it quick to discern those of the other, and thus lead to a real mis-direction of the Intelligence. This I think is not a correct statement of the case. Pre- judgments may, and often do, prevent all proper inves- tigation of a subject. In this case, the Intelligence is not deceived at all. In the absence of real data, it can make no positive affirmations whatever. So far also as pre-judgments direct attention from facts bearing upon one side of a question, and to those bearing upon the other, the Intelligence is not thereby deceived. All that it can affirm is the true bearing of the facts actually presented. In re- spect to those not presented, and consequently in re- spect to the real merits of the whole case, it makes no affirmations. If an individual forms an opinion from a partial hearing, that opinion is a mere assump- tion of Will, and nothing else, 17 190 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. THE MIND HOW INFLUENCED BY PRE-JUDGMENTS, But the manner in which pre-judgments chiefly affect the mind in the hearing of a cause, still remains to be stated. In such pre-judgments, or assump- tions, an assumption of this kind is almost invariably included, to wit : that all facts of whatever character bearing upon one side of the question, are wholly indecisive, while all other's bearing upon the other side are equally decisive. In pre-judging, individu- als do not merely pre-judge the real merits of the case, but the character of all the facts bearing upon it. They enter upon the investigation of a given subject, with an inflexible determination to treat all the facts and arguments they shall meet with, according to previous assumptions. Let the clearest light poured upon one side of the question, and the reply is, " After all, I am not convinced," while the most trivial circumstances conceivable bearing upon the other side, will be seized upon as perfectly decisive. In all this, we do not meet with the operations of a deceived Intelligence, but of a " deceived heart," that is, of a depraved Will, stubbornly bent upon verifying its own unauthorized, pre-formed assumptions. Such assumptions can withstand any degree of evidence whatever. The Intelligence did not give them exist- ence, and it cannot annihilate them. They are ex- clusively creatures of Will, and by an act of Will, they must be dissolved, or they will remain proof against all the evidence which the tide of time can roll against them. SOURCE OF ERROR. 191 INFLUENCES WHICH INDUCE FALSE ASSUMPTIONS. The influences which induce false and unauthor- ized assumptions, are found in the strong action of the Sensibility, in the direction of the appetites, nat- ural affections, and the different propensities, as the love of gain, ambition, party spirit, pride of charac- ter, of opinion, &c. When the Will has long been habituated to act in the direction of a particular pro- pensity, how difficult it is to induce the admission, or assumption, that action in that direction is wrong ! The difficulty, in such cases, does not, in most in- stances, lie in convincing the Intelligence, but in inducing the Will to admit as true what the Intelli- gence really affirms. CASES IN WHICH WE ARE APPARENTLY, THOUGH NOT REALLY, MISLED BY THE INTELLIGENCE. As there are cases of this kind, it is important to mark some of their characteristics. Among these I eite the following : 1. The qualities of a particular object, actually perceived, as in the case above cited, may be common to a variety of classes which we know, and also to others which we do not know. On the perception of such qualities, the Intelligence will suggest those classes only which we know, while the particular object perceived may belong to a class unknown. If, in such circumstances, a positive assumption, as to what class it does belong, is made, a wrong assump- 192 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. tion must of necessity be made. The Intelligence in this case is not deceived. It places the Will, however, in such a relation to the object, that if a positive assumption is made, it must necessarily be a wrong one. In this manner, multitudes of wrong assumptions arise. 2. When facts are before the mind, an explanation of them is often desired. In such circumstances, the Intelligence may suggest, in explanation, a num- ber of hypotheses, which hypotheses may be all alike false. If a positive assumption is made in such a case, it must of necessity be a false one ; because it must be in the direction of some one hypothesis be- fore the mind at the time. Here, also, the Intelli- gence necessitates a wrong assumption, if any is made. Yet it is not itself deceived ; because it gives no positive affirmations as the basis of positive as- sumptions. In such circumstances, error very fre- quently arises. 3. Experience often occasions wrong assumptions, which are attributed incorrectly to real affirmations of the Intelligence. A friend, for example, saw an object which presented the external appearance of the apple. He had never before seen those qualities, except in connection with that class of objects. He assumed, at once, that it was a real apple ; but sub- sequently found that it was an artificial, and not a real one. Was the Intelligence deceived in this instance ? By no means. That faculty had never affirmed, that those qualities which the apple presents SOURCE OF ERROR. 193 to the eye, never exist in connection with any other object, and consequently, that the apple must have been present in the instance given. Experience^ and not a positive affirmation of the Intelligence, led to the wrong assumption in this instance. The same principle holds true, in respect to a vast number of instances that might be named, 4. Finally, the Intelligence may not only make positive affirmations in the presence of qualities per- ceived, but it may affirm hypothetical ly, that is, when a given proposition is assumed as true, the In- telligence may and will present the logical antece- dents and consequents of that assumption. If the as- sumption is false, such will be the character of the antecedents and consequents following from it. An individual, in tracing out these antecedents and con- sequents, however, may mistake the hypothetical, for the real, affirmations of the Intelligence. One wrong assumption in theology or philosophy, for example, may give an entire system, all of the leading princi- ples of which are likewise false. In tracing out, and perfecting that system, how natural the assumption, that one is following the real, and not the hypotheti- cal , affirmations of the Intelligence ! From this one source an infinity of error exists among men. In an enlarged Treatise on mental science, the subject of the present chapter should receive a much more extensive elucidation than could be given to it in this connection. Few subjects would throw 17* • 194 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. more clear light over the domains of truth and error than this, if fully and distinctly elucidated. In conclusion, I would simply remark, that one of the highest attainments in virtue which we can con- ceive an intelligent being to make, consists in a con- tinued and vigorous employment of the Intelligence in search of the right, the just, the true, and the good, in all departments of human investigation ; and in a rigid discipline of the Will, to receive and treat, as true and sacred, whatever the Intelligence may present, as possessed of such characteristics, to the full subjection of all impulses in the direction of un- authorized assumptions. CHAPTER XIV. LIBERTY AND SERVITUDE. LIBERTY OF WILL AS OPPOSED TO MORAL SERVITUDE. There are, among others, two senses of the term Liberty, which ought to be carefully distinguished from each other. In the first sense, it stands oppos- ed to Necessity; in the second, to what is called Moral Servitude. It is in the last sense that I pro- pose to consider the subject in the present Chapter. What, then, is Liberty as opposed to Moral Servi- tude ? It is that state in which the action of Will is in harmony with the Moral Law, with the idea of the right, the* just, the true, and the good } while all th LIBERTY AND SERVITUDE. 195 propensities are held in perfect subordination — a state in which the mind may purpose obedience to the law of right with the rational hope of carrying that determina- tion into accomplishment. This state all mankind agree in calling a state of moral freedom. The indi- vidual who has attained to it, is not in servitude to any propensity whatever. He " rules his own spirit." He is the master of himself. He pur- poses the good, and performs it. He resolves against the evil, and avoids it. " Greater," says the maxim of ancient wisdom, " is such a man than he that taketh a city.'" Moral Servitude, on the other hand, is a state in which the Will is so ensnared by the Sensibility , so habituated to subjection to the propensities , that it has so lost the prerogative of self -control ^ that it cannot re- solve upon action in the direction of the law of right , with any rational expectation of keeping that resolu- tion. The individual in this condition " knows the good, and approves of it, yet follows the bad." " The good that he would (purposes to do), he does not, hut the evil that he would not (purposes not to do), that he does." All men agree in denominating this a state of Moral Servitude. Whenever an indi- vidual is manifestly governed by appetite, or any other propensity, by common consent, he is said to be a slave in respect to his propensities. The reason why the former state is denominated Liberty, and the latter Servitude, is obvious. Liberty 3 196 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. as opposed to Servitude, is universally regarded as a good in itself. As such, it is desired and chosen. Se»- vitude, on the other hand, may be submitted to, as the least of two evils. Yet it can never be desired and chosen, as a good in itself. Every man who is in a state of servitude, is there, in an important sense, against his Will. The state in which he is, is regard- ed as in itself the greatest of evils, excepting those which would arise from a vain attempt at a vindica- tion of personal freedom. The same principle holds true in respect to Moral Liberty and Servitude. When any individual con- templates the idea of the voluntary power rising to full dominion over impulse of every kind, and acting in sublime harmony with the pure and perfect law of rectitude, as revealed in the Intelligence, every one regards this as a state, of all others, the most to be desired and chosen as a good in itself. To enter upon this state, and to continue in it, is therefore re- garded as a realization of the idea of Liberty in the highest and best sense of the term. Subjection to impulse, in opposition to the pure dictates of the In- telligence, to the loss of the high prerogative of " ruling our own spirits," on the other hand^ is re- garded by all men as in itself a state the most abject, and least to be desired conceivable. The individual that is there, cannot but despise his own image. He, of necessity, loathes and abhors himself. Yet he submits to self-degradation rather than endure the LIBERTY AND SERVITUDE. 197 pain and effort of self-emancipation. No term but Servitude, together with others of a kindred import, expresses the true conception of this state. No man is in a state of Moral Servitude from choice — that is, from choice of the state as a good in itself. The state he regards as an evil in itself. Yet, in the ex- ercise of free choice, he is there, because he submits to self-degradation rather than vindicate his right to freedom. REMARKS. MISTAKE OF GERMAN METAPHYSICIANS. 1. We notice a prominent and important mistake common to metaphysicians, especially of the Ger- man school, in their Treatises on the Will. Liberty of Will with them is Liberty as distinguished from Moral Servitude, and not as distinguished from Ne- cessity. Hence, in all their works, very little light is thrown upon the great idea of Liberty, which lies at the foundation of moral obligation, to wit : Liberty as distinguished from Necessity. " A free Will," says Kant, " and a Will subjected to the Moral Law, are one and identical." A more capital error in philoso- phy is not often met with than this. MORAL SERVITUDE OF THE RACE. 2. In the state of Moral Servitude above describ- ed, the Bible affirms all men to be, until they are emancipated by the influence of the Remedial Sys- 198 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. tern therein revealed— a truth affirmed by what every man experiences in himself, and by the entire mass of facts which the history of the race presents. Where is the individual that, unaided by an influence out of himself, has ever attained to a dominion over his own spirit ? Where is the individual that, with- out such an influence, can resolve upon acting in har- mony with the law of pure benevolence, with any rational hope of success ? To meet this great want of human nature ; to provide an influence adequate to its redemption, from what the Scriptures, with great propriety, call the " bondage of corruption," is a fundamental design of the Remedial System. CHAPTER XV. LIBERTY AND DEPENDENCE. COMMON IMPRESSION. A very common impression exists, — an impression universal among those who hold the doctrine of Necessity, — that the doctrine of Liberty, as main- tained in this Treatise, renders man, really, in most important respects, independent of his Creator, and therefore, tends to induce in the mind, that spirit of haughty independence which is totally opposite and antagonistic to that spirit of humility and depen- dence which lies at the basis of all true piety and virtue. If this is the real tendency of this doctrine, LIBERTY AND DEPENDENCE. 199 it certainly constitutes an important objection against it. If, on the other hand, we find in the nature of this doctrine, essential elements totally destructive of the spirit of pride and self-confidence, and tending most strongly to induce the opposite* spirit, — a spirit of humility and dependence upon the grace prof- fered in the Remedial System ; if we find, also, that the doctrine of Necessity, in many fundamental particulars, lacks these benign tendencies, we have, in such a case, the strongest evidence in favor of the former doctrine, and against the latter. The object of the present Chapter, therefore, is to elucidate the tendency of the doctrine of Liberty to destroy the spirit of pride, haughtiness, and self-dependence, and to induce the spirit of humility and dependence upon Divine Grace. SPIRIT OF DEPENDENCE DEFINED. Before proceeding directly to argue this question, we need to settle definitely the meaning of the phrase spirit of dependence. The conviction of our dependence is one thing. The spirit of dependence is quite another. What is this spirit ? In its ex- ercise, the mind rests in voluntary dependence upon the grace of God. The heart is fully set upon doing the right, and avoiding the wrong, while the mind is in the voluntary exercise of trust in God for "grace whereby we may serve Him acceptably.' 5 The spirit of dependence, then, implies obedience 200 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. actually commenced. The question is, does the belief of the doctrine of Liberty tend intrinsically to induce the exercise of this spirit ? In this res- pect, has it altogether a superiority over the doctrine of Necessity ? DOCTRINE OF NECESSITY TENDS NOT TO INDUCE THE SPIRIT OF DEPENDENCE. 1. In accomplishing my object, I will first con- sider the tendency, in*this one respect, of the doctrine of Necessity. An individual, we will suppose, finds himself under influences which induce him to sin, and which consequently, if this doctrine is true, render it impossible for him, without the interposi- tion of Divine power, not to sin. A consideration of his condition tends to convince him, that is, to induce the intellectual conviction, of his entire dependence upon Divine grace. But the intellectual conviction of our dependence, as above shown, is one thing. The spirit of dependence, which, as there stated, consists in actually trusting the Most High for grace to do what he requires, and implies actual obedience already commenced, is quite another thing. Now the doctrine of Necessity has a tendency to produce this conviction, but none to induce the spirit of de- pendence : inasmuch as with this conviction, it produces another equally strong, to wit : that the creature, without a Divine interposition, will not, and cannot, exercise the spirit of dependence. In LIBERTY AND DEPENDENCE. 201 thus producing the conviction, that, under present influences, the subject does not, and cannot exercise that spirit, this doctrine tends exclusively to the annihilation of that Spirit. When an individual is in a state of actual obedi- ence, the tendency of this doctrine upon him is no better ; since it produces the conviction, that while a Divine influence, independently of ourselves, pro- duces in us a spirit of dependence, we shall and must exercise it ; and that while it does not produce that spirit, we do not and cannot exercise it. Where is the tendency to induce a spirit of dependence, in such a conviction \ According to the doctrine of Necessity, nothing but the actual interposition of Di- vine grace has any tendency to induce a spirit of dependence. The belief of this doctrine has no such tendency whatever. The grand mistake of the Ne- cessitarian here, consists in the assumption, that, be- cause his doctrine has a manifest tendency to produce the conviction of dependence, it has a tendency equal- ly manifest to induce the spirit of dependence ; when, in fact, it has no such tendency whatever. 2. We will now contemplate the intrinsic tenden- cies of the doctrine of Liberty to induce the spirit of humility and dependence. Every one will see, at once, that the consciousness of Liberty cannot itself be a ground of dependence, in respect to action, in favor of the right and in opposition to the wrong : for the possession of such Liberty, as far as the power 18 202 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. itself is concerned, leaves us, at all times, equally liable to do the one as the other. How can an equal liability to two distinct and opposite courses, be a ground of assurance, that we shall choose the one, and avoid the other ] Thus the consciousness of Liberty tends directly and intrinsically to a total an- nihilation of the spirit of self-dependence. Let us now contemplate our relation to the Most High. He knows perfectly in what direction we shall, in our self-determination, exert our powers under any influence and system of influences brought to bear upon us. It is also in His power to subject us to any system of influences he pleases. He has re- vealed to us the great truth, that if, in the exercise of the spirit of dependence, we will trust Him for grace to do the good and avoid the evil which He requires us to do and avoid, He will subject us to a Divine influence, which shall for ever secure us in the one, and against the other. The conviction, therefore, rises with full and perfect distinctness in the mind, that, in the exercise of the spirit of dependence, ac- tion in all future time, in the direction of purity and bliss, is secure ; and that, in the absence of this spirit, action, in the opposite direction, is equally cer- tain. In the belief of the doctrine of Liberty, another truth becomes an omnipresent reality to our minds, that the exercise of this spirit, thus rendering our " calling and election sure," is, at all times, practi- cable to us. What then is the exclusive tendency of LIBERTY AND DEPENDENCE. 203 this doctrine ^ To destroy the spirit of self-depend- ence, on the one hand, and to induce the exercise of the opposite spirit, on the other. The doctrine of Necessity reveals the fact of dependence, but destroys the spirit, by the production of the annihilating con- viction, that we neither shall nor can exercise that spirit, till God, in his sovereign dispensations, shall subject us to an influence which renders it impossi- ble for us not to exercise it. The doctrine of Liberty reveals, with equal distinctness, the fact of depend- ence ; and then, while it produces the hallowed con- viction of the perfect practicability of the exercise of the spirit of dependence, presents motives infinitely strong, not only to induce its exercise, but to empty the mind wholly of everything opposed to it. GOD CONTROLS ALL INFLUENCES UNDER WHICH CREA- TURES DO ACT. 3. While the existence and continuance of our powers of moral agency depend wholly upon the Divine Will, and while the Most High knows, with entire certainty, in what direction we shall exert our powers, under all influences, and systems of influ- ences, brought to bear upon us, all these influences are entirely at his disposal. What tendency have such convictions, together with the consciousness of Liberty, and ability to exercise, or not to exercise, the spirit of dependence, but to induce us, in the ex- ercise of that spirit, to throw our whole being into 204 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. the petition, "Lead us not into temptation, but de- liver us from evil 1" If God knows perfectly under what influences action in us shall be in the direction of the right, or the wrong, and holds all such influ- ences at his own control, what attitude becomes us in the presence of the " High and lofty One," but dependence and prayer 1 DEPENDENCE ON ACCOUNT OF THE MORAL SERVITUDE OF THE WILL. 4. Finally, a consciousness of a state of Moral Servitude, together with the conviction, that in the exercise of the spirit of dependence, we can rise to the u Glorious Liberty of the Sons of God ;" that in the absence of this spirit, our Moral Servitude is per- fectly certain ; all these, together with the conviction which the belief of the doctrine of Liberty induces (to wit: that the exercise of the spirit of dependence is always practicable to us), tends only to one result, to induce the exercise of that spirit, and to the total an- nihilation of the opposite spirit. While, therefore, the doctrine of Liberty sanctifies, in the mind, the feeling of obligation to do the right and avpid the wrong, a feeling which the doctrine of Necessity tends to annihilate, the former (an effect which the latter cannot produce) tends only to the annihilation of the spirit of pride and self-confidence, and to induce that spirit of filial dependence which cries " Abba, Father !" CHAPTER XVI. FORMATION OF CHARACTER. ELEMENT OF WILL IN FORMATION OF CHARACTER. CHARACTER COMMONLY HOW ACCOUNTED FOR. In accounting for the existence and formation of peculiarities of character, individual, social, and na- tional, two elements only are commonly taken into consideration, the natural propensities^ and the cir- cumstances and influences under which those pro- pensities are developed and controlled. The doctrine of Necessity permits us to take nothing else into the account. Undoubtedly, these elements have very great efficacy in determining character. In many instances, little else need to be taken into con- sideration, in accounting for peculiarities of charac- ter, as they exist around us, in individuals, commu- nities, and nations. • THE VOLUNTARY ELEMENT TO BE TAKEN INTO THE ACCOUNT. In a vast majority of cases, however, another, and altogether a different element, that of the Will, or voluntary element, must be taken into the reckon- ing, or w T e shall find ourselves wholly unable to account for peculiarities of mental and moral de- 18* 206 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. velopment, everywhere visible around us. It is an old maxim, that " every man is the arbiter of his own destiny." As character determines destiny, so the Will determines character ; and man is the arbiter of his own destiny, only as he is the arbiter of his own character. The element of Free. Will, therefore, must be taken into the reckoning, if we would adequately account for the peculiarities of character which the individual, social, and national history of the race presents. Even where mental and moral developments are as the propensities and external influences, still the voluntary element must be reckoned in, if we would account for facts as they exist. In a majority of instances, however, if the two elements under consideration, and these only, are taken into the account, we shall find our con- clusions very wide from the truth. AN EXAMPLE IN ILLUSTRATION. I will take, in illustration of the above remarks, a single example — a case with which I became so familiarly acquainted, that I feel perfectly safe in vouching for the truth of the statements which I am about to make. I knew a boy who, up to the age of ten or twelve years, was under the in- fluence of a most ungovernable temper — a temper easily and quickly excited, and which, when excit- ed, rendered him perfectly desperate. Seldom, if ever, was he known to yield in a conflict, how- FORMATION OF CHARACTER. 207 ever superior in strength his antagonist might be. Death was always deliberately preferred to submis- sion. During this period, he often reflected upon his condition, and frequently wished that it was other- wise. Still, with melancholy deliberation, he as often said to himself, I never can and never shall sub- due this temper. At the close of this period, as he was reflecting upon the subject again, he made up his mind, with perfect fixedness of purpose, that, to the control of that temper, he would never more yield. The Will rose up in the majesty of its power, and assumed the reins of self-government, in the respect under consideration. From that mo- ment, that temper almost never, even under the high- est provocations, obtained the control of the child. A total revolution of mental developments resulted. He afterwards became as distinguished for natural amiability and self-control, in respect to his temper, as before he had been for the opposite spirit. This total revolution took place from mere prudential considerations, without any respect whatever to moral obligation. Now suppose we attempt to account for these dis- tinct and opposite developments of character — de- velopments exhibited by the same individual, in these two periods — by an exclusive reference to natu- ral propensities and external influences. What a to- tally inadequate and false account should we give of the facts presented ! That individual is just as 20S DOCTRINE OF THE WILL, conscious, that it was the element of Free Will that produced this revolution, and that when he formed the determination which resulted in that revolution, he might have determined differently, as he is, or ever has been, of any mental states whatever. All the facts, also, as they lie out before us, clearly indicate, that if we leave out of the account the voluntary element, those facts must remain wholly unexplain- ed, or a totally wrong explanation of them must be given. The same principle holds true in all other instan- ces. Though natural propensities and external in- fluences greatly modify mental developments, still, the distinguishing peculiarities of character, in all instances, receive their form and coloring from the action of the voluntary power. This is true, of the peculiarities of character exhibited, not only by indi- viduals, but communities and nations. We can never account for facts as they are, until we con- template man, not only as possessed of Intelligence and Sensibility, but also of Free Will. All the pow- ers and susceptibilities must be taken into the ac- count, if men would know man as he is. DIVERSITIES OF CHARACTER. A few important definitions will close this Chapter. A decisive character exists, where the Will acts in harmony with propensities strongly developed. When a number of propensities of this kind exist^ FORMATION OF CHARACTER. 209 action, and consequently character, may be change- able, and yet decisive. Unity and decision of character result, when the Will steadily acts in harmony with some one over- shadowing propensity. Character is fluctuating and changeable^ when the Will surrenders itself to the control of different pro- pensities, each easily and highly excited in the presence of its appropriate objects, and yet the ex- citement but temporary. Thus, different propensi- ties, in rapid succession, take their turn in controlling the Will. Indecision and feebleness of character result, when the Will uniformly acts under the influence of the principle of fear and caution. To such a mind, in all important enterprises especially, there is always " a lion in the way." Such a mind, there- fore, is continually in a state of distressing indecision when energetic action is necessary to success. CHAPTER XVII, CONCLUDING REFLECTIONS. A few reflections of a general nature will conclude this Treatise. OBJECTION. THE WILL HAS ITS LAWS. 1. An objection, often adduced, to the entire view of the subject presented in this Treatise, demands a passing notice here. All things in existence, it is said, and the Will among the rest, are governed by Laws. It is readily admitted, that all things have their laws, and that the Will is not without law. It is jumping a very long distance to a conclusion, however, to infer from such a fact, that Necessity is the only law throughout the entire domain of exist- ence, physical and mental. What if, from the fact, that the Will has its law, it should be assumed that Liberty is that law ? This assumption would be just as legitimate as the one under consideration. OBJECTION. GOD DETHRONED FROM HIS SUPREMACY, IF THE DOCTRINE OF LIBERTY IS TRUE. 2. Another objection of a general nature, is the assumption, that the doctrine of Liberty destroys the Divine supremacy in the realm of mind. " If man," says Dr. Chalmers, " is not a necessary agent, God is a degraded sovereign." A sentiment more dishon- orable to God, more fraught with fatal error, more CONCLUDING REFLECTIONS. 211 revolting to a virtuous mind, when unperverted by a false theory, could scarcely be uttered. Let us, for a moment, contemplate the question, whether the doc- trine of Liberty admits a Divine government in the realm of mind. The existence and perpetuity, as stated in a former Chapter, of free and moral agency in creatures, depend wholly upon the Divine Will. With a perfect knowledge of the direction in which they will exert their powers, under every kind and degree of influence to which they may be subjected, He holds all these influences at his sovereign disposal. With such knowledge ^nd resources, can God exer- cise no government, but that of a degraded sove- reignty in the realm of mind ? Can He not exercise the very sovereignty which infinite wisdom and love desire ? Who would dare affirm the contrary ? If the doctrine of Liberty is true, God certainly does not sit upon the throne of iron destiny, swaying the sceptre of stern fate over myriads of subjects, mis- called moral agents ; subjects, all of whom are com- manded, under infinite sanctions, to do the right and avoid the wrong, while subjected to influences by the Most High himself, which render obedience in some, and disobedience in others, absolute impossi- bilities. Still, in the light of this doctrine, God has a government in the domain of mind, a government wisely adapted to the nature of moral agents — agents capable of incurring the desert of praise or blame ; a government which all approve, and under the be- nign influence of which, all who have not forfeited 212 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. its protection by crime, may find " quietness and as- surance for ever." OBJECTION. GREAT AND GOOD MEN HAVE HELD THE DOCTRINE OF NECESSITY. 3. In reply to what has been said in respect to the tendencies of the doctrine of Necessity, the fact will doubtless be adduced, that the greatest and best of men have held this doctrine, without a development of these tendencies in their experience. My an- swer is, that the goodness of such men, their sense of moral obligation, &c, did not result from their theory, but existed in spite of its intrinsic tendencies. They held this doctrine in theory, and yet, from a consciousness of Liberty, they practically adopted the opposite doctrine. Here, we have the source of the deep feeling of obligation in their minds, while the intrinsic and exclusive tendency of their Theory , even in them, was to weaken and annihilate this hallowed feeling. The difference between such men and sceptics is this : The piety of the former prevents their carrying out their theory to its legitimate re- sults ; while the impiety of the latter leads them to march boldly up to those results — a fearless denial of moral obligation in every form. LAST RESORT. 4. The final resort of certain Necessitarians, who may feel themselves wholly unable to meet the ar- guments adduced against their own and in favor of the CONCLUDING REFLECTIONS. 213 opposite theory, and are determined to remain fixed in their opinions, may be readily anticipated. It is an assumption which may be expressed in language somewhat like the following : " After all, the im- mortal work of Edwards still lives, and will live, when those of his opponents will be lost in oblivion. That work still remains unanswered." A sweeping assumption is a very easy and summary way of dis- posing of a difficulty, which we might not otherwise know what to do with. Let us for a moment con- template some of the facts which have been undeni- ably established in reference to this immortal work. (1.) At the outset, Edwards stands convicted of a fundamental error in philosophy, an error which gives form and character to his whole work — the confounding of the Will with the Sensibility, and thus confounding the characteristics of the pheno- mena of the former faculty with those of the pheno- mena of the latter. (2.) His whole work is constructed without an appeal to Consciousness, the only proper and au- thoritative tribunal of appeal in the case. Thus his reasonings have only an accidental bearing upon his subject. (3.) All his fundamental conclusions have been shown to stand in direct contradiction to the plainest and most positive testimony of universal Conscious- ness. (4.) His main arguments have been shown to 19 214 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. be nothing else but reasoning in a circle. He de- fines, for example, the phrase " Greatest apparent good," as synonymous with choosing ,and then argues, from the fact that the " Will always is as the greatest apparent good," that is, that it always chooses as it chooses, that it is subject to the law of Necessity. So in respect to the argument from the Strongest Motive, which, by definition, is fixed upon as the Motive in the direction of which the Will, in each particular instance, acts. From the fact that the action of the Will is always in the direction of this Motive, that is, in the direction of the Motive towards which it does act, the conclusion is gravely drawn, that the Will is and must be subject, in all its de- terminations, to the law of Necessity. I find my mind acted upon by two opposite Motives. I can- not tell which is the strongest, from a contempla- tion of what is intrinsic in the Motives themselves, nor from their effects upon my Intelligence or Sen- sibility. I must wait till my Will has acted. From the fact of its action in the direction of one Motive, in distinction from the other, I must then draw two important conclusions. 1. The Motive, in the di- rection of which my Will did act, is the strongest. The evidence is, the fact of its action in that direc- tion. 2. The Will must be subject to the law of Necessity. The proof is, the action of the Will in the direction of the Strongest Motive, that is, the Motive in the direction of which it did act. Sage CONCLUDING REFLECTIONS. 215 argument to be regarded by Philosophers and Theolo- gians of the 19th century, as possessing the elements of immortality ! (5.) His argument from the Divine fore-knowledge has been shown to be wholly based upon an assump- tion unauthorized by reason, or revelation either, to wit : that he understands the mode of that Fore- knowledge, — an assumption which cannot be made except through ignorance, as was true in his case, without the greatest impiety and presumption. (6.) The theory w 7 hich Edwards opposes has been shown to render sacred, in all minds that hold it, the great idea of duty, of moral obligation ; while the validity of that idea has never, in any age or nation, been denied, excepting on the avowed au- thority of his Theory. (7.) All the arguments in proof of the doctrine of Necessity, with the single exception of that from the Divine Fore-knowledge — an argument resting, as we have seen, upon an assumption equally baseless, — involve a begging of the question at issue. Take any argument we please, with this one exception, and it will be seen at once that it has no force at all, unless the truth of the doctrine designed to be established by it, be assumed as the basis of that ar- gument. Shall we pretend that a Theory, that has been fully demonstrated to involve, fundamentally, the errors, absurdities, and contradictions above named, has not been answered ? 216 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. WILLING, AND AIMING TO PERFORM IMPOSSIBILITIES. 5. We are now prepared to answer a question about which philosophers have been somewhat di- vided in opinion — the question, whether the Will can act in the direction of perceived and affirmed im- possibilities ? The true answer to this question, doubtless is, that the Mind may will the occurrence of a known impossibility, but it can never aim to produce such an occurrence. The Mind, for example, while it regards the non- existence of God as that which cannot possibly occur, may come into such a relation to the Most High, that the desire shall arise that God were not. With this desire, the Will may concur, in the wish) that there were no God. Here the Mind wills a known impossibility. In a similar manner, the Mind may will its own non-existence, while it regards its occurrence, on account of its relation to the Divine Will, as impossible. But while the Mind may thus will the occurrence of an impossibility, it never can, nor will aim, that is, intend, to produce what it regards as an impos- sibility. A creature may will the non-existence of God ; but even a fallen Spirit, regarding the occur- rence as an absolute impossibility, never did, nor will aim to annihilate the Most High. To suppose the Will to set itself to produce an occurrence regarded as impossible, involves a contradiction. CONCLUDING REFLECTIONS. 217 For the same reason, the Will will never set itself upon the accomplishment of that which it is per- fectly assured it never shall accomplish, however sincere its efforts towards the result may be. All such results are, to the Mind, joracft'caZ impossibilities. Extinguish totally in the Mind the hope of obtaining the Divine favor, and the Divine favor will never be sought. Produce in the Mind the conviction, that should it aim at the attainment of a certain end, there is an infallible certainty that it will not attain it, and the subject of that conviction will no more aim to attain that end, than he will aim to cause the same thing, at the same time, to be and not to be. In reply, it is sometimes said, that men often aim at what they regard even as an impossible attain- ment. The painter, for example, aims to produce a perfect picture, while he knows well that he cannot produce one. I answer, the painter is really aim- ing at no such thing. He is not aiming to produce a perfect picture, which he knows he cannot, and will not produce, but to produce one as nearly perfect as he can. This is what he is really aiming at. Question the individual critically, and he will confirm what is here affirmed. Remind him of the fact, that ne cannot produce a perfect pic- ture. I know that, he replies. I am determined, however, to produce one as nearly perfect as possi- ble. Here his real aim stands revealed. The same principle holds true in all other instances. 19* 218 DOCTRINE OF THE WILL. THOUGHT AT PARTING. 6. In taking leave of the reader, I would simply say, that if he has distinctly apprehended the great doctrine designed to be established in this Work, and has happily come to an agreement with the author in respect to it, the following hallowed impression has been left very distinctly upon his mind. While he finds himself in a state of profound and most pleasing dependence upon the Author of his being, in the Holy of Holies of the inner sanctuary of his mind, one idea, the great over-shadowing idea of the human Intelligence, has been fully sancti- fied — the idea of duty, of moral obligation. With the consciousness of Liberty, that idea must be to the mind an omnipresent reality. From it we can never escape ; and in all states, and in all worlds, it must and will be to us, as a guardian angel, or an avenging fiend. But one thing remains, and that is, through the grace proffered in the Remedial Sys- tem, to " live and move, and have our being," in harmony with that idea, thus securing everlasting " quietness and assurance" in the sanctuary of our minds, and ever enduring peace and protection under the over-shadowing perfections of the Author of our existence, and amid all the arrangements and move- ments of his eternal government. W Deacidified using the Bookkeeper process. Neutralizing agent: Magnesium Oxide Treatment Date: Nov. 2004 PreservationTechnologies A WORLD LEADER IN PAPER PRESERVATION 1 1 1 Thomson Park Drive Cranberry Township, PA 16066 (724)779-2111