Class D -k PRESENTED BY A PLEA FOR HEDONISM A THESIS PRESENTED BY John C. Palmer, Jr., A. M., Ph. D., it Wellsburg, W. Va. For the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy, on Examination, in Course A. Philosophy, in the Po8t-Oraduate Department of the University of Wooster, June, 1903. Reprinted from the Post-Graduate and Wooster Quarterly for July, 1903. Herald Printing Co., Wooster, Ohio. • » * * * * THE LIBRARY Or CONGRESS '* IwASHINGXON Joto C. Palmer, Jr., P,h. D., Wellsburg, W. Va. A Graduating Thesis;. Course A, Philosophy. I.. INTRODUCTORY. It is the purpose of this essay to show that the ulti- mate ethical question is the question, of the consequences of our actions. Ethics has to deal with human conduct and its consequences. The consequences of conduct determine the permissibility or advisability of the conduct. I expect further to show that it is the pleasant or painful consequences of our acts in which we are inter- ested. If we were not sentient creatures, that is, if we merely had knowledge without any feeling of pleasure or pain in that knowledge, with that knowledge there would be no problem of conduct, for there would be no conduct. In other words, our sentience lies at the base of our activ- ity. 1 To put the matter in terms of mechanics, it is because we find ourseves in unstable equilibrium, in a state of unrest or discomfort, that we act. Our actions are for the sake of establishing a new equilibrium in our sentient consciousness. *See Taylor, The Problem of Conduct, Page 338. 9 A Plea for Hedoi&Bin: •f In the following discussion, Iassupadthat a man is a per- sonality , a center of * intelligent activity. He is different from the brook ap,^ the growing tree, even though we can- not state the difference "in terms of human speech. He is different again from a meracreature of instinct and impulse. His intelligence makes him an original center of force, even though we, cannot explain the nature of voluntary activity, or conduct.. These assumptions are not intended to settle any metaphysical controversy. But unless we make such assumptions, man becomes a mere machine, an irresponsible and delusive mechanism. Ethics, from her place as the queen of science, is degraded to a subordinate place among the mechanical sciences. Such a conclusion would involve consequences too serious to be lightly accepted. If man is a machine, political science and theology are as meaningless as astrology and magic. 3 Hedonism does not require the assumption of a pur- pose in the universe, yet it welcomes such an assumption, so long as one takes all the facts of human existence into account. Neither does Hedonism assume the immor- tality of the human soul,, nor even its existence after death. But here again it welcomes any light which re- ligion or theology can throw upon the subject of man's destiny. Starting with man as a sentient, intelli- gent consciousness, Hedonism seeks to determine his re- lation to the rest of Universe, and what share he has in the evolution of his destiny. We begin neither on the side of the Optimist nor the Pessimist, neither with the Stoic nor the Epicurean. With whom we shall end depends on evidence which shall be forthcoming. As one reads treatise after treatise on the subject of ethics, he feels that [the writers are, after all, consciously or unconsciously, striving to answer the same question and that question is: How may Human Welfare be Advanced? It does not matter that the real questionis lost sight of in the midst ofmetaplrpsicaland psychological meanderings. It is ever present, like the theme in a technical musical com- 2 Cf. W. Wallace, Lectures aud Essays, pages 250 and 251. 'A Eleafor Hedonism. 8 position. Metaphysical, psychological-, and phygiological discussions interest us, because^ we* nope that they will throw some light on the ultimate .question of human welfare and human destiny. Ethics, is then, essentiaflyva science of man, his wel-. fare and his destiny. If ethics puts to itself the question, why should this thing be done, and that omitted, it is because the former tends to promote human welfare, while the latter would retard or prevent it. But the term welfare is a broad, abstract term, about whose content and meaning there maybe difference of opinion. Welfare is equivalent to doiog or faring well. But what is "well"? The ethical problem, then, is merely stated when reduced to terms of human welfare. Before we can decide finally what is "well" for a man or for the human race, we should know something of the origin and nature of the individual and the race. We ought to know the place of man the individual, and man the species in the universe. From the standpoint of Hedonism, the problem of human conduct cannot receive a final solution till we are aware of every fact which can affect the conse- quences of human activity. But at the seme' time, the Hedonist insists on our making the best of such facts as are available. Because we are not aware of all the conse- quences of our acts, we are by no means justified in neglecting such consequences as are now familiar. Uncer- tainty as to the ultimate purpose or destiny of the race should not diminish my interest in my own personal destiny and welfare. Prior to the nineteenth century, ignorance of man's nature and origin and his relation to the rest of the uni- verse greatly hindered any intelligent answer to the ques- tion as to his place and function in the universe at large. So long as each individual was looked upon as a special piece of workmanship, shaped according to a set pattern, like a statue or a piano, it was impossible to arrive at a correct idea of man's place in Nature. But when the doc- trine of evolution made it possible to study man as a growth, a mind among minds, an animal among animals and a living organism among living organisms, subject 4 A Plea for Hedonism. to definite laws and principles, his present character and future possibilities became a matter of supremest interest. When we apply the doctrine of natural selection to man, every trait of character and shade of temperament is pregnant with meaning; every institution, past or pre- sent, is worthy of study as having been a help or hindrance to human progress. But in our study of man and his en- viroment, we must not forget an important distinction, which is frequently overlooked. Nature, so far as we can learn, is the product of a single system of forces, working apparently according to a harmonious plan. (Whether nature is the product of mere chance, of preordained pupose, or of other Power, this is not the place to inquire. ) Man, on the other hand, according to our previous assumption, is a center of force within a force, a plan within a plan. His evolution is the combin- ed product of nature and his own intelligence, and the share of each of these forces, in the product-, is at this moment a warmly disputed question, as the recent works of such men as Benjamin Kidd, A. E. Taylor, and others bear evidence. I shall have more to say on the subject in a later part of this essay; at present it will suffice to say that in my opinion the part played by intelligence in the development of man and human institutions has been much larger than evolutionary philosophers are inclined to admit. Most of our ethical concepts and beliefs, it seems to me, are the result of the perception or the sup- posed perceptions of the consequences of actions. Even our ethical emotions are to a. considerable extent, altho by no means altogether, the product of individual and racial experience. By means of intelligence and its in- strument, language, the individual and the society of to- day are the heirs of a rich estate in experience. Our con- cepts and beliefs have come down to us like precious heir- looms, well tested and ready for use; not, however, thro' inherited brain and nerve tissue, but by example, train- ing, custom, institutions, and word of mouth. This view, I am well aware, is in opposition both to those of the in- tuitionists, led by such men as James Martineau and Henry 6alderwood, on the one hand, and to those of the A Plea for Hedonism. 5 evolutionists, led by Herbert Speneer, A. Sutherland, and Leslie Stephen, on the other. The intuitionists go too far in making our ethical emotions, concepts, and beliefs, purely innate or intuitive, and hence inexplicable, and not to be tampered with. On the other hand, the evolutionists go too far in trying to explain the origin of all our emotions, concepts and beliefs by means of evolution alone. While we all admit o that the civilized man of today is somewhat superior to the savage of six thousand years ago in ethical emotions, yet when we reflect, on the one hand, on the immense prog- ress in emotional and ethical development which the negro has undergone during the three hundred years of his sojourn in America, and on the other hand on the fact that the child of refined parents, thrown by chance among savages (a very common occurrence in colonial days in America) exhibits no higher ethical emotions, concepts and beliefs than his savage fellows, we are forced to the conclusion that most of the ethical emotions, concepts and beliefs are institutional in origin, that is, the results of the accumu- lated experience of the race, gathered and transmitted in maxims, proverbs, institutions and even in the very words of the language itself. Suppose, for instance, that a million infants were selected from the most refined homes in the world and transported to a deserted island unfrequented by men, and sustained by ravens until they were old enough to care for themselves; is it not almost certain that the children would in time become the most degraded savages? Indeed, unless the island were entirely free from noxious animals and poisonous plants, it is very probable that the whole colony would perish in a very few years. Be this as it may, I cannot conceive that the rapid development of ethical concepts in western Europe within the last few centuries could be the result of so slow a progress as evolution. Leslie Stephen, in his English Utilitarians, remarks "the sudden awakening of the public conscience" 3 in England on the slave trade just prior to the French Revolution. Before 3 The Eng. Util. Vol. I, page 1 13-14. 6 A Plea for Hedonism. that awakening, the most respectable people engaged in the trade without a qualm of conscience. The generation which is just passing in America can recall a like awaken- ing hereon the slave question. Even the time which has elapsed since the days of Socrates, Plato, and Ariostotle is not sufficient to account for the marked advance on Grecian ethical concepts which is so strikingly depicted in T. H. Green's Prolegomena to Ethics. Much less could the slow progress of mental evolution account for the wonderful changes in ethical concepts which A. Suther- land has so masterfully pictured in his Origin and Growth of the Moral Instinct. But when we note the strides which the sciences have made since the days of Socrates, and particularly within the last three centuries, when we recall the progress of the arts and of our knowledge of all that relates to man's physical and social well-being, we need not be surprised at the rapid changes which have taken place in men's ethical notions. And when we refleet upon the force of habit, the strength of custom, the tenacity of inher- ited beliefs, and the universal ignorance of the ultimate foundation of institutions in general, we can only be sur- prised that opinions have yielded as rapidly as they have to the wave of progress 4 . But if the evolutionists have in their zeal gone too far in ascribing the whole of man's prog- ress to the power of evolution, they have, until the last few years, failed to emphasize sufficiently the importance of the part which nature plays in developing the anti-selfish or altruistic emotions. So far as I know, Benjamin Kidd, in his social evolution, was the first to call attention to this remarkable fact. I shall discuss the subject. At present I need only say that I regard this peculiar fact, that nature develops the race in opposition to the indi- vidual's development of himself, as one of the greatest marvels in science and at the same time the solution of the apparent contradiction which runs all through human life and activity. I believe it offers the only solution of the ethical problem, the only basis for harmonizing con- flicting ethical theories. In this brief essay I can do no *See Ileasure in the economy of life and their knowledge suffi- ciently great to realize the laws of nature and their rela- 19 See Huxley, Evolution and Ethics, Note 20, p. 114. ^Stephen, op. cit., p. 103. ^Spencer, Prin. Ethics, p. 46. 22 Alexander, Moral Order, etc., p. 225. A Plea for Hedomism. 19 tion to the sentient creature. Hedonism takes man as the partially developed product of evolution and seeks to show him as an individual and as a race what possibil- ities nature has in store for him; and if there be an after life, how the present life may be best lived as a prelimi- nary to that. Hedonism is obliged to draw upon all the other sciences for its material. 23 In fact all the sciences are but the more or less systematic efforts of man to find his place in the universe. 24 Among the sciences which Hedonism will draw most from are the sciences of the human body, its health and ailments, the economic sciences, or the sciences of satisfying man's needs, and the political and legal sciences, or the sciences which govern man's actions in society, For evolutionary Hedonism recognizes that man is by nature a sociable creature; that each tribe, nation or people, in fact, is a sort of organism, subject to definite laws of growth and decay. The welfare of the individual is, therefore, largely a func- tion of the organism of which he is a part; thus while a wise man like Socrates or Confucius might be happy among miserable associates he could be much happier, if his associates were also wiser and happier. Altruism, or interest in the welfare of others, is thus to a large ex- tent an element of Hedonism. III. The Strength of Hedonism. The chief theory of conduct which is opposed to Hedonism is intuitionism, the theory of duty or con- science. This theory looks to the human sentiments for a basis for activity. We are to be guided in our actions, not by their experienced consequences on ourselves and others, but by the approving or disapproving voice of this inward monitor. Without stopping to inquire at present into the origin and nature of this inward monitor, we find on investigation that it has varied enormously in different ages, races, localities and individuals. Thus we find that slavery has met with almost universal approval in times ^%ulsen, System of Bt&fes, Introd. ^Weber, Hist Philos., p. i. 20 A Plea for Hedonism. past, being recognized in the sacred books of the Hebrews, Hindus, Chinese, Greeks and Egyptians, and being prac- ticed to a greater or less extent by all nations. At the present time it is condemned by nearly all civilized men. The subjection of women has been likewise generally approved and practiced. Only in the most recent times and among the most developed nations has woman begun to receive the same treatment as man. Even at the present day our sense of duty does not urge us to give her the same political and social rights that men possess. Custom keeps her wages lower than those of men engaged in precisely the same work. 25 Again, the sense of duty has not prevented the basest treatment and neglect of children, even among people who were the most scrupu- lous, such as the Puritans. Once more, the caste system prevails among a large proportion of mankind. The sense of duty not only does not require members of the higher caste to treat those of a lower caste as their equals, but on the contrary pos- tively forbids such treatment. Nor is the caste system by any means confined to Asia. The young woman who marries below her station in Europe or America loses caste almost as surely as does the Hindu belle. The very word friendship implies a broader form of selfishness. One is expected to do for a friend what he would not do for a stranger or an enemy. Our consciences call on us to help a friend who is in trouble; while they are not much stirred by the sufferings of Hindus and Chinese, unless their sufferings become widespread and excessive. The word patriotism likewise implies that our country is to be preferred to other countries. Even if we do not accept the maxim, "Our country, right or wrong," we are apt to be strongly biased in her favor in case of rivalry or conflict with other countries. In opposition to the above illustrations, 26 Paul Janet and others seek to demonstate a general uniformity of opinion in all ages and nations on moral questions. But ^ee Report of Com. of L^bor, V©1. XI. ^Theory of Morals, Bk. Ill, ch. 4, A Plea for Hedonism. Ml the cases cited by them seem to show simply that the universal reasoning and sentient, pleasure-pain faculties of mankind have led them gradually to learn the same facts regarding human and physical nature, and to adapt themselves to these facts. The activities necessary to maintain the individual and the race, after making the necessary allowances for differences in the environment, must be more or less similar everywhere; and if men desire to live in society, certain general and evident rules of con- duct must be established and followed. But beyond these apparent and fundamental cases, it seems impossible to harmonize the moral views of mankind. For in addition to the cases of conflicting consciences which we have already given, we have other cases of a much more radical kind. In the sexual re- lations we find differences in opinion the most remote. To say nothing of monogamy, polygamy and polyandry, such writers as Spencer, Westermark and Sutherland give instances of what we regard as looseness of sexual prac- tice, which are almost inconceivable. So in matters of honesty and veracity, we find that among many nations, honesty and veracity are not supposed to be due to a foreigner. Theft from a stranger and even from a neigh- bor was applauded not only in ancient Sparta, but in many other countries. And even in civilized countries clever dishonesty and deception are too often approved where the parties are very unequally situated: for example when one outwits and cheats an employer, a great corporation, or the public officers. There is often a feeling of approval of the clever urchin, who deceives his teacher. And I have heard old soldiers of high standing tell with evident self-satisfaction how they deceived and defrauded their officers, and their stories were approved by their audience. The most intelligent people sometimes will be found to distinguish between lying and deceit. Many a man who would suffer torture rather than lie verbally, will not hesitate to deceive by actions. 27 But a closer examination shows us that the sense of "See H. Spencer, Ethics II, li&\ also The Outlook, Vol. 73, p. 262-3. 22 A Plea ior Hedonism. duty, or conscience is exceedingly compliant and flexible. It gives way in nearly every instance to the accepted religious code. Whatever is prescribed by the accepted religion is approved by the sense of duty. This accounts for the child-murders so common among heathen tribes. The tribes of ancient Palestine laid their infants in the red-hot arms of a metallic god. The Hindu mother throws her babe to the crocodile and even Abraham was ready to sacrifice his only son at the supposed call of deity. But the sense of duty bends not only at the dic- tate of religion, but at the dictate of custom, where custom and religion d ) not conflict. Hence the most absurd costumes are worn, the most absurd rites observed, and the most absurd practices maintained, simply because custom has established them. In this case the sense of duty requires one to respect public opinion. This opinion is vastly stronger among the uncivilized than among ourselves. But even the best of us feel impelled by the sense of duty to comply with the customs in force around us. Once more, the sense of duty usually complies with the existing laws, in so far as they do not conflict with our religious beliefs. In any age and nation, therefore, we may expect to find the general conscience or sense of duty pretty clearly defined by the prevailing religious code, together with the accepted customs and political laws in force. If the relig- ion is false and maintains pernicious rites and doctrines, the sense of duty will be accordingly perverted. If the customs are absurd and injurious, the political laws illog- ical and narrow, the keener intellects will probably strive very gradually to modify them in the direction of improving the social welfare, but the sense of duty of the multitude will always lag far in the rear of the car of progress. For progress is usually the work of a select few; and the multitude are very slow to perceive the advantages of a change in well established institutions. 98 We are forced to the conclusion, therefore, that the 28 See Bryce, Studies in Hist, and Jurist.— Obedience, p. 463. A Plea wr Hedonism. 28 sense of duty, or conscience is not a safe and sufficient guide to human conduct. The sentiments play an extremely important part in human affairs; but we cannot safely rely on them as the ultimate criterion of the rectitude of an action or course of conduct. What habit does for one in matters of bodily action, the sentiments do for him in matters of volition. Habit permits us to devote the mind to other matters while the body carries out a given line of conduct. So the sentiments dispense with the necessity of going back to first principles before deciding on every act. They are moral habits, nothing more. If, then, intuitionism, with its reliance on an inward monitor, is unable to provide an ultimate basis for human activity, a philosophy of conduct, what has Hedonism to offer in its stead? Wherein lies the strength of Hedonism? We must admit at the start that Hedonism has a bad name. Any doctrine which advocates selfishness must expect to be frowned upon. And among Christian peoples, at any rate, any doctrine based on pleasure must likewise expect to meet strong opposition. Unless, there- fore, the Hedonist can make out a strong and clear case in its favor, he must not expect any mercy at the hands of his opponents and critics. More than this, I realize only too clearly that a misunderstood theory of pleasure might cause a vast deal of harm. It would perhaps be better to let men blunder along after their old guides than to have them think they need no guide at all; that they are at liberty to do as they please, and to gratify every de- sire and passion as it arises. It is incumbent on the Hed- onist to guard by eYery possible precaution against any such misconception of his doctrine. Hedonism, as I under- stand the doctrine, seeks to establish a philosophical basis for conduct, not a stronghold for the libertine. It is not intended to work any sudden revolution in the morals and manners of civilized men, and this for the simple reason that in spite of their erroneous theories of the ultimate bases of conduct and of certain details of activity, civilized peoples have unconsciously followed hedonistic principles in their development. They have 24> A Plea for Hedonism. builded better than they knew. The canon of conse- quences has been accepted and followed to some extent in all ages and nations, But other theories have often greatly retarded its application, even to the extent of destroying great nations. The nations which have sur- vived and progressed are, I believe, those which have grasped most firmly and applied most faithfully the canon of consequences. As I hive tried to point out in the first section, it was largely because the ancient Greeks were untrammelled by any religious code that they were able to make the freest use of the canon of consequences. Thus they were able to develop the most accurate and valuable moral theory which the world knew before the present age, and by its use to re;ich the highest pinnacle of civili- zation. I cannot agree with Mr. Spencer in his indictment of Greek civilization. 29 The Hindu and the Chinaman, on the contrary, tied themselves hand and foot with strin- gent religious and social codes. Hedonism, therefore, is evolutionary, rather than revolutionary. It conceives that there are vastly higher and broader stages of civilization yet in store for human- ity; but it does not hope to attain these by any sudden leap. It will have done enough if it enables the car of civilization to move steadily onward and Upward. Yet at the present time, when the ethical problem, that is, the question as to the ultimate foundation of moral conduct, is studied and discussed as it never was before, it seems well worth while to help all one can in reaching a solution of tne problem. In the first place, then, Hedonism is irreconcilably opposed to every form of asceticism, that is, to pain for the sake of pain. Nearly all the religious and ethical systems of the past have been vitiated by the taint of asceticism. This is not the place to inquire into the origin of the monstrous notion that the Deity could take delight in the sufferings of his creatures. It is sufficient for our purpose to call attention to the important place which this belief occupies in most religious systems. The ^Ethics, II, I 58. A Plea for Hedonism. 25 refrgious and ethical systems of western Asia and Europe seem to have drawn their ascetic element from Egypt, where, according to Schaff, 30 a pessimistic atmosphere seems always to have prevailed. Christianity has not escaped the taint. In spite of the humane teachings of Jesus, the Egyptian influence was strong enough to fill the symbols of the church with ascetic doctrines and all Europe with monks and monasteries. Hedonism insists that men have a right to be happy, that pain is intended to benefit and not to torture, that the religious or ethical doetrine demanding suffering or sacrifice that does not result in a greater compensating good to the sufferer or some other sentient creature, is oertainly erroneous. Asceticism is unreasonable and cannot justify itself. Yet the ascetic element in various guises is really what makes most other ethical systems different from Hedonism. Thus it is this element of asceticism which, sometimes drawing strength from the doctrine of self-discipline or stoicism, constitutes the essence of all the doctrines of despair, such as Buddhism. The ethics of despair may be hedonistic if it avoids this ascetic element. For if the powers of evil really are stronger in the universe, then doubtless we are justified in seeking Nirvana or some other escape into non-existence. But we are still at liberty to reinvestigate the facts of nature for the pur- pose of deciding whether existence is on the whole (500 painful to be endurable. There was but little of the ascetic element in the stoicism of Greece and Rome. But when the current of orientalism struck the philosophy of Greece, the ascetic element mingled with the philosophic and pain for the sake of pain became a prominent element in the ethical doctrines of the middle ages. Preserved by the religious orders against the strong reaction of German common sense which swept over western Europe with the spread of German civilization, asceticism sprang again into prominence at the reforma- tion in the Puritanism of England and Germany. During ^Church History. 26 A Plea tor Hedonism. the last three centuries men have been gradually elimi- nating the ascetic element from the religious and ethical systems of Europe. The reaction probably reached flood tide in the.days of William Paley and Jeremy Bentham. Since their day there has been a slight disposition to revert toward asceticism, owing partly to the writings of Thomas Carlyle and partly to disappointment of the hopes placed in the political and social reforms of the nineteenth century. Asceticism draws a certain amount of strength from the evident value of self-discipline. But asceticism, or pain for its own sake, and self-discipline, or pain for the sake of compensating good to self or others are radically different. Self-discipline is a hedonistic doctrine. Exper- ience teaches the value of discipline as clearly as it teaches the absurdity of asceticism. But too often the one is taken for the other. Suffering to produce good for another is confused with suffering that another is sup- posed to enjoy as suffering. It is a curious fact in nature that sentient creatures are unquestionably able to enjoy the agony of their fellow creatures. By a natural infer- ence, one's deity is supposed to possess this same abnor- mal characteristic. But of all illogical and abhorrent emotions, this one seems to be unquestionably the worst. Hedonism insists that no being, be he creator or creature, has the right to enjoy the pain of another. Whatever destiny the powers of the universe have in store for me, I have certainly the right, in so far as I have the power, to make that destiny as little painful and as fully pleasant as possible. And the same right which I insist upon for myself, I insist upon with equal emphasis for my fellowmen. In the next place, Hedonism is the natural doctrine of conduct. All sentient creatures seek pleasure and avoid pain as naturally and as certainly as water seeks its level. Indeed, the tendency to seek pleasure and avoid pain is so strong and natural that an opposite doctrine seems almost inconceivable. Hence not only many philosophers but even whole nations, as the Hindus, believe that sen- tience and activity are inseparably connected by the law of A Plea for Hedonism. 27 cause and effect. But without admitting this extreme view, we must concede a natural disposition or tendency in all conscious beings to seek pleasure and avoid pain. More- over, science seems to indicate that pleasure and pain are teleological, that is, they play an important part in the pres- ervation and evolution of both the individual and the race. No one will deny that without the faculties of pleasure and pain no living creature could maintain its existence very long. Sentience, or pleasure-pain is the faculty which enables a living creature to maintain the equilibrium with its environment which is essential to life. And pleasure, usually, if not always indicates that the equilibrium is satisfactory, while pain, usually, if not always, indicates that something is wrong. If one were disposed to argue, therefore, that man is the creation of an intelligent being, the exis- tence of these wise provisions for his persistence among the struggling forces of the universe would certainly be a strong point in his favor. But whether the gift of an intelligent Creator, or the product of chance, pleasure and pain are certainly indispensible faculties of all sentient creatures. And even if we can never demonstrate that conscious existence was intended to be as pleasant as poss- ible, or that the individual may strive to make it as pleasant as possible, we are at least certain that without the pleasure-pain apparatus, conscious creatures could not subsist at all. Pleasure being, then, such an insepar- able accompaniment of healthy, normal consciousness, and pain as clearly the index of the abnormal and defec- tive, is not the burden on the opponents of Hedonism to show that sentience should not be taken as the ultimate guide to conduct? As we have repeatedly indicated above, sentience alone would not be a sufficient guide to conduct, from the fact that man is an exceedingly com- plex being, full of conflicting desires and emotions. Reason, therefore, must stand as judge among the pleas- ure-pains and determine which are entitled to recognition as components of the sum total of pleasurable conscious- ness and which should be rejected as injurious to the sentient community. 28 A Plea tor Hedonism. To the question: Why has Hedonism a bad name? we answer: Because men see that the pleasure seeker so often comes to grief and makes himself and others miser- able. Ignorance and folly too often misguide men in the search for happiness. Hence the advocate of Hedonism cannot repeat too frequently that sentience alone cannot be relied upon as a guide to conduct. But neither must this statement be misconstrued or misquoted. For after all, reason must rely on sentience as the test. But it is the course of sentience, the sum of pleasures or whatever one may call the total make-up and summary of a complete conscious existence, considering both its quality, or breadth, its intensity or depth and its duration or length which reason must direct and govern. The reader will see the difficulty of translating sentient ideas into terms of space and quantity. Yet I doubt not that he will under- stand what I mean. Another reason for this ill-repute of Hedonism is the fact that it is often mistakenly supposed to be opposed to self-restraint and self-discipline. But philosophic Hedonism, as we have said again and again, is in the fullest accord with all legitimate self-discipline. If we always remember therefore that the aim and end of Hedonism is to secure the richest, fullest, deepest, purest, longest, pleasant consciousness for the individual, we shall not be confused or misled by instances of blind and foolish pleasure-seeking, with their calamitous and repul- sive results nor by any unfair comparisons with self-dis- ciplining ethical regimes. Every sentient creature desires pleasure, or happiness as well as escape from pain and evil. Hedonism endeavors to help him obtain these results in the fullest degree, it may be by self-restraint or it may be by self-culture or indulgence. It does not tell men: You must do thus and so; it simply says: If you wish a given result you may obtain it in a certain way. The man who breaks the law of hedonism will call himself a fool. And most men would rather be anything else than fools. Hedonism, then, is the only natural ethics, the only ethics which seeks to lead and guide men rather than drive them, the only ethics which appeals to both their A Plea, tor Hedonism. 29 emotions and their reason, their whole nature, instead of commanding and compelling them. But man is by nature a social creature*. He prefers with the ant and many higher animals to live in groups. And the greater his development and intelligence the larger become the groups in which he lives. But group- life, or social-life is only possible under certain conditions and only enjoyable to those endowed with the social or sympathetic emotions. The individual must consent to give up certain pleasures and liberties, must submit to certain rules and restraints. I care not whether you pre- fer Hobbes' theory of the Original State of War, which drove reasonable men into society as the lesser of two evils, or Kousseau's theory of the Social Contract, entered into by mutual consent for the sake of its advantages, or the theory of a divinely instituted state with the place of each member eternally fixed for him, or the theory of a state slowly evolved by natural processes. The result is the same in the end. Social life means the yielding up of certain liberties and pleasures by the individual which he might enjoy if he lived alone, and the acquisition of cer- tain joys and comforts which the anchorite must forego. Hedonism can be applied to several of these political theories. But in any given society the thoughtful indivi- dual submits to the social law, be it political, economical or etiquetical, because the advantages to himself of such submission are greater than the disadvantages. I am aware that the multitude submit to social rules largely from the force of habit, indolence, reverence, fear and affection. 31 But even the most ignorant man has a vague idea of the reasons for social laws. The most stupid man has an occasional brilliant idea, and the ferment of ideas in the multitude will in time seize upon the beneficial social principles and throw out the defective ones, much as the fermentation of cider throws extraneous matter to the top of the cask. The popular wisdom is thus not 3: See Bryce, Studies, etc., IX Obedience, and X, The Nature of Sovereignty. SO A Plea for Hedonism. entirely to be despised, especially among a progressive people. Hedonism, then, is the logical basis of all prudent conduct, whether in the pursuit of knowledge, of health and comfort, of family affairs, of friendly intercourse with our neighbors, of art and culture, or in the greater intercourse which makes up the nation and the family of nations. There can never be any conflict between Hedon- ism and the sciences and arts. All the sciences and arts are the hand-maidens of Hedonism. Whatever makes men wiser, stronger, healthier, richer, more industrious, more friendly, more practical and enduring, better trained and educated for the struggle with nature, their environ- ment and their own character will be welcomed by the hedonist. Whatever on the other hand, makes men ignorant, weak, sickly, poor, lazy, ill-natured, stupid, boorish, narrow, mean, unfriendly, harsh, reckless or in any other way retards progress and enlightenment is condemned by Hedonism. Nor is there anything incon- sistent in this position. In case of the drunkard and the opium fiend, everybody can see the folly of his course of action. But in these other cases of a narrow selfishness or willfulness, the perversity and disadvantage of the course is only not so apparent. Every man desires health and strength, vigor and skill. If men disregard the laws of health, therefore, it is either through ignorance or though a weakness of the will brought on by various causes. Even while indulging the craving for drink or for morphine the drunkard does not cease to regret the prob- ably ultimate results of his folly. It is the business of Hedonism to persuade men to discipline themselves not for the sake of discipline, nor to gratify the whim of a superior, but for their own good and greater pleasure in the end. If every man has an equal right to seek happiness in his own way, certain logical results follow which it is important to consider in this place. In the first place, it follows that in one sense might makes right. A man may do what he likes and what he can. But other men may A Plea for Hedonism. 31 do the same; and it follows that by combination the superior number may restrain the inferior. But if we were to stop here Hedonism would be the most pernicious of all doctrines. We hasten to add, therefore, with the apostle, that all things are not expedient. What one may do, and what, all things considered, he will prefer to do are very different. Thus, it is in my power to destroy my furniture, to mistreat my dog and my child, to be harsh with my wife and surly with my friends; but exper- ience teaches me that these things are not expedient. And if my nature has been properly developed, they are undesirable and repugnant to me. Kindness, affection and friendliness pay better in the long run. Hedonism urges men, therefore, to the most careful study of the whole situation. Right is not what one is able to do, but rather what one who is normally developed prefers to do and must do to attain his greatest welfare, that is, his fullest sentient consciousness. It also follows from the principle of the equal right of all to strive for their own greatest good, that each man may join in the restraint of his fellow-men where their actions interfere with his welfare. But this doctrine is also likely to be misunderstood. As stated above, it is an empty formula. The individual should still inquire into ultimate results. Such an inquiry, the Hedonist claims, will show that the welfare of the normal individual is nearly always identical with that of the group. Admit- ting that there are rare cases where social welfare and individual welfare appear not to coincide as the world and the individual are now made up, yet the hedonist insists that in the long run the good of the state and that of the individual are identical. Thus utilitarianism is a branch of Hedonism. For in striving for the greatest good of the greatest number (the formula of utilitarianism), the individual feels sure that indirectly he is promoting his own welfare. It will readily be seen from what has already been said that Hedonism is not only superior to other ethical systems in its appeal to men's natural inclinations and 32 A Plea for Hedonism, emotions, but that it has the advantage of appealing to their reason and experience as well, and is thus the only progressive ethics. A moral system which rests on men's sentiments, on custom or on some vague metaphysical prin- ciple, such as the doctrine of the everlasting and immut- able right, tends to become more and more rigid and stationary. Thus the Hindus, with their complicated Brah- minical law, are shut off from all opportunity of advance in civilization. The Chinese, likewise, with the Confucian doctrines and customary morality have been stationary in civilization for two thousand years. The ancient Jew, through a misinterpretation of the Mosaic law, or a defect in that law, w T as excluded from all progress in art and culture. So during the middle ages theological ethics hindered the progress of art, science and commerce in end- less ways. Who can say how much higher civilization would be now if women had enjoyed the same freedom since the beginning of the christian era that they enjoy in America today? These instances will show the importance of having a moral principle which encourages instead of retarding science and culture. That other moral theories have con- structed lofty ideals, the hedonist is ready enough to admit. Buddha, Confucius, Zarathustra, and Kant were all high-minded and noble men. But in so far as they based their moral systems on false principles, they were the means of retarding rather than improving the condi- tion of the people. Buddhism is rich in noble maxims of conduct. But as a whole it is probably worse that no system at all. Zarathustra and Confucius taught many wholesome doc- trines, but taken as a whole, their systems have retarded civilization. So the formalism of Kant might be safe enough in an age where each of the virtues had a well settled, practical meaning for the individual; and where the duty to parents, to children, to neighbors and to the state were well recognized. But the fact that they were settled would make change all the more difficult if any formal theory of ethics were adopted. "So act that the maxim A Plea iov Hedonism. 33 of your conduct may be adopted as a universal law" becomes dangerous among a people who are settled in their customs. For, as was pointed out above, the sentiments of the individual are almost certain to approve the existing regime. And when a more vigorous thinker appears, who sees the injurious effects in terms of welfare, of existing practices, he meets with universal opposition from all the advocates of formalism. In the next place, we notice that Hedonism is not only the natural, logical and progressive ethics. We find that it has been the actual element of value in all the great ethical systems of the past. From the very awakening of intelligence, sentient, conscious beings must have begun to study the consequences of actions, along with the laws of nature and of the human constitution. Conduct which is guided by consequences is called prudent. Most conduct of this kind has become so much a matter of course that we have long since ceased to think of it as having any ethical quality whatever. And it is very common for moralists to exclude all prudent activity from the field of ethics, or at the most to give it but a passing glance. Thus Kant insists repeatedly that all conduct which is induced by prudence or self- interest must be excluded from the field of ethics. Me would investigate the field of disinterested or altruistic conduct alone. But the hedonist maintains not only that prudent activity is a very important branch of ethics but that in the actual systems of the past, prudence has been the vital element. Thus every moral maxim which appeals to one's judgment of value must be classed as hedonistic. When Jesus said: "Come unto me, all ye that labor and are heavy laden, and I will give you rest", he was appealing to the sentient nature of mankind. So when he said, "He that believeth on me shall be saved; and he that believeth not shall be damned". So, when he said, "In my father's house are many mansions". So the whole sermon on the mount, his most complete dis- course, is entirely hedonistic. 83 For even after command- 32 See Matth, V; 3: VII; 27. 84 A Plea for Hedonism. ing the most complete systems of non-resistance and altruism which has ever been known 33 he adds in verse 45, "That ye may be the children of your Father which is in heaven". The sermon opens with the blessings which are to fall on those who accept and follow the doctrines of the sermon. And then it closes 34 with the remarkable parable of the wise man who built his house upon a rock and the foolish man who built on the sand. Wisdom and folly are the watchwords of Hedonism. Whether we hold that accepting the doctrines of Jesus makes a man happier or not in this life, there is no question that Jesus meant to to teach that his followers should have an exceeding great reward when He came in His glory. He went about doing good, not merely good in the abstract, not merely preach- ing good sermons, but practical, hedonistic good. He healed the sick, made the blind see; caused the lame to walk, cured insanity, raised the dead, and even gladdened the hearts of the wedding guests with excellent wine. All through his ministry, Jesus appealed to men's sentient na- ture. He reasoned with them; he pointed to their misery, discord and empty formalism, and urged them to turn to a reasonable course of life. And whether we accept his teaching as divine or merely human, we must admit that he points out the value of altruistic conduct for the indi- vidual as no one else has done before or since. I do not mean to say that there were no other important elements in the teaching of Jesus. That teaching was religious as well as ethical. We must also admit that an element of asceticism is to be found in the doctrines of Jesus as they come down to us. More tender than stoicism and more vigorous than epicureanism, the ethical doctrines of Jesus have done a great deal toward the spreading of Christianity through- out the world. The whole Jewish system of ethics is hedonistic. Even where its demands are given as the dictates of God, they are coupled more or less directly with the threats and prom- 3T v. 33-44- A Plea for Hedonism. 35 ises of Jahveh. It is true that the philosophic element was not prominent in the Jewish code. The rites and cere- monies are to be observed and performed because God has so commanded. The reward was to be directly bestowed by him, not as the natural consequence of obedience, but as a token of merit. But the formal code of conduct was too firmly instated by priest, levite and people to be shaken by the thundering arguments of Isaiah or the plaintive discourses of Jeremiah. But after all the Law of Moses was full of wise, hedonistic principles; with some ex- ceptions it was equitable, just and wise. The land-owner, the debtor, the widow, the orphan, the criminal, and even the stranger were wisely dealt with. The criminal law T was comparatively mild, the law of torts not too severe. The laws of marriage and divorce were among the best of ancient times and we know from history that Jewish family life was remarkably clean and high-toned. Confucius, too, adopted a hedonistic theory of ethics. His theory was more philosophical than that of the early Jews. He gave more reasons for the conduct which he prescribed; that is, he pointed out the value of the con- duct. Confucius, like Socrates, taught that morals and manners must begin with self knowledge. And while pre- scribing a minutely detailed code of action for the indi- vidual, which in the end became an incubus on Chinese civilization, yet his studies led him to see that altruism is only a wiser Hedonism; and while rejecting all religion he announced the same fundamental rule of conduct which Jesus prescribed, 500 years later, in the .Golden Rule. Had Confucius been succeeded by thinkers as broad as himself, who could have put life into his moral system, China might have made wonderful progress in civiliza- tion. Unfortunately, no ruler would accept his system of government; his disciples devoted themselves to the letter of the law, and China became ensnared in an impenetrable wilderness of formalism. Zarathustra, too, the moral and religious law-giver of the Persians, adopted hedonistic principles. Two great beings, the one li^ht or good, and the other darkness, or evil, have been engaged in a struggle for supremacy from 86 A Tha, tor Hedonism. all eternity. But the good being is on the side of the welfare, or good of the individual; the evil or dark being is constantly endeavoring to injure mankind. In the end the good will triumph and those who are on his side will receive their reward. Zoroastrianism has many wise hedonistic maxims and principles, tending to promote the welfare of the individual and society. Buddha, likewise, was a moral reformer. And like most moral reformers, he was stirred to thought and activity by the misery and wretchedness which he saw around him. After devoting many years to the study of the problem of evil, he reached the conclusion that happi- ness consists in Nirvana, or perfect peace. But the peace of Buddhism, while it frees one from suffering and is thus hedonistic, is almost the peace of non-existence. Never- theless, all the doctrines of Buddha are based on the fundamental idea of escaping from sentient evil. The prescibed course of conduct is directed entirely toward the attainment of Nirvana, or escape from suffering. The fact that Buddha and Confucius were unable to point to a larger hope in the life beyond, as did Socrates and Jesus, does not militate against our argument. Their doctrine was negatively hedonistic, while the doctrines of Jesus and Socrates are both positively and negatively hedonistic. Buddha, like Confucius and Zarathustra, studied the consequences of actions and with an endless prolixity of formal details, he mingles wise, hedonistic principles of conduct, based on the observation of human society, human greed and human frailty. Overburdened with the sense of the wretchedness which all the watchfulness ©f his guardians could not conceal from him, he left his princely home to study in peace and quiet the problem of evil. Like Moses and Confucius, he returned, fertile in plans for improving the welfare of his fellowmen. His theory of life was more spiritual than that of Confucius, but the prob- lem which he was trying to solve was precisely the same: to wit, the problem of human misery and human happi- ness. I spoke above of popular wisdpm. This wisdom is set forth among every people in the form of proverbs and A Plea for Hedonism. 87 fatto. These proverbs and fables embody the condensed and pithily expressed experience of the race. Prof. Legge says that for centuries * the Chinaman has been largely guided in the conduct of his life by the excellent maxims of Confucius. Jewish literature, too, is rich in proverbs. The same is true of the Arabic, a near relative of the Hebrew. Among savage tribes the philosophy of life is usually embodied in familiar proverbs, which are passed from mouth to mouth and from father to son. Originat- ing as they do and passing from country to country, these s-ayings are often couched in the most contradictory terms, and embody the most conflicting theories of life. But a careful study of them will show that they are drawn from a more or less rich experience, and that they are all based on hedonistic principles. Frequently they prescribe rules of conduct for the indi- vidual which are apparently injurious to him, and yet they are accepted as a part of the prudential philosophy of the tribe. For example, ' 'Honesty is the best policy," announces the result of a large experience in dishonesty by the whole race. Its truth is often hard to realize, yet many a man has been governed by this simple maxim when conscience, the sense of duty, and the fear of Grod were unable to control his actions. Men who were unable to comprehend the reasonings of Isaiah and Socrates could lay up in memory the maxims of Solomon and the fables of iEsop. And there is reason to believe that the modern Englishman, German, or American is more influ- enced by the proverbs in which our languages are so rich, than he is by the subtle, metaphysical doctrines of Kant and Martineau, Luther and Edwards. But all proverbial philosophy is professedly a pruden- tial philosophy. It tells the individual what his prede- cessors have found most profitable in life. It gives him the benefit of their experiences; condenses into a line for him the biography of a race. Proverbial philosophy is often trustworthy, too. It comes with no ax to grind, no system to maintain, no party to support. Like the pebble on the river beach, it comes from no man knows where; and, like the pebble, it has been tossed and tried 38 A Plea for Hedonism. until it is worn smooth and perfect. Hence the proverb- ial philosophy of any people is well worthy of study. These gems of thought, these heirlooms of experience which have survived the mutations of kingdoms and peoples are more priceless than the treasures of princes. And what is the burden of their tale? Is not their united voice to the effect that, "Experience is the best teacher;" that "your sin will find jou out;" that "The thief will be caught in his own trap;" that "One lie makes two more necessary;" that "If you cast your bread upon the waters it will return to you after many days;" that "He who sows the wind, will reap the whirlwind"? Chastity, honesty, veracity, mercy, bravery, modesty, industry, patience, friendliness, shu, or reciprocity, (the golden word of Confucius), are all based on sound prudential reason. The experience of the race has demonstrated and in these proverbs embodied the fact that these virtues are not empty forms, not incomprehensible principles, not the dictates of a whimsical deity, not the froth of an evanes- cent sentiment, but that they are the rational maxims of a happy life, the fundamental principles of a moral sciene base on human nature and solicitous for human welfare. But not only have the professedly ethical theories which have had the most widespread influence among mankind drawn their main strength from their hedonistic principles, teachings, threats and promises; not only have the popular principles of conduct and theories of the destiny of man, as embodied in proverbs, maxims and omens, accepted Hedonism as the ultimate desffrry of the race, but the great religious systems of the race, which have been already more or less closely associated with their ethical principles and moralmaxims, have likewise rested on a similar basis. Fear and hope are the sentiments to which religion has always appealed, fear of present or future evil or suffering, hope of future peace or bliss. Sometimes the evil to be escaped and the reward to be obtained was expected in the present life, sometimes in a more or less definite life in another world, sometimes, as among the Buddhists, the Egyptians and some of the Greeks, in a future earthly life (Karma transmigration); A Plea wr Hedomism. 89 and sometimes, as among the ancient Jews, in th§ lives of one's descendants. Ancestor worship certainly sprang from hedonistic motives. A man believed in a more or less vague way that the spirits of the departed still retained power for good and evil. It was important, therefore, to keep in their good graces by offerings, sacrifices and ceremonial attentions. Where ancestor worship prevails, a man's good fortune and evil fortune, his health and his sickness, his rich harvests and his famines, his good luck and his accidents are attributed to the good or ill will of these ancestors. Hence ancestor worship, especially among people who show no great love for their kindred while they are on earth, is purely a prudential affair, almost a matter of business. And among the idol worshipers it is very common to reproach the god for not performing his part of the contract. Sometimes he is even beaten, or mistreated in other ways to awaken him to the fact that where he has received the stipulated offerings and sacrifices, he should send the needed blessings, rain, health, good crops, game, or whatever it may be. Even among the most highly civilized Christians this feeling still lingers. The man who goes to church regularly, is kind to his family, gives to the poor, treats his neighbor squarely, is apt to think that the Lord should prosper him and to feel abused if his crops are bad, his children are sick, or especially if a .serious acci- dent or misfortune befall him. Hero worship is even more clearly hedonistic than ancestor worship. For the affection which might lead one to perform certain rites in memory of a beloved parent does not exist toward a departed king or ruler. One may be devoted to a good ruler, but it is because that ruler has proven serviceable, has lightened the bur- den of taxes, driven off the public enemy, punished inter- nal disorder, enforced law and equity among his subjects, and broadened the opportunities of the individual to lead a happy and undisturbed life. It is the belief that the wise ruler can still do something for his subjects that 40 A Plea for Hedonism. leads them to curry favor with Ms departed spirit. It is fear of the despotic ruler that leads to the effort to appease the wrath of his departed spirit. I have already spoken of Confucianism, the ethical religion of the Chinese, of Buddhism, the religion accepted by so many millions in India and China, and of the system of Zoroastrianism, the religion of Persia. All of these were seen to rest on hedoDistic doctrines and prin- ciples. Judaism, too, v. as a hedonistic religion. The Old Testament is full of threats and promises. Ajid the most frequent argument of the religious leaders was to point to the hedonistic results of obedience and disobedience. The Jew firmly believed that the conquests and other national disasters were the direct result of unfaithfulness to the Mosaic law, and that the restoration and preserva- tion of the remnant was due to their repentance and reformation. Although they believed themselves to be God's favorite and peculiar people, they did not expect him to favor them unless they faithfully obeyed his com- mands; and conversely, if they were obedient, they expected the favor of heaven. The Mohammedans are, if possible, even more hedon- istic and practical in their religious beliefs and observances than the ancient Jews. Their Gfod is a just Grod; and by a just God, they mean a Grod who stands strictly by his contract^ Worship him according to his commands and he will bless you in this world and the next. Disobey him and he will punish you in this life and damn you eternally in the next. Grod has revealed his will, his promises and his punishments in the Koran. Follow the Koran, and your welfare for time and eternity is assured. I have already spoken of the ethical system of Jesus. Christianity, which sprang from his teachings is com- monly supposed to be opposed to all hedonistic systems. It is supposed to be a religion of self-denial, of unselfish- ness, of altruistic conduct. But Christianity is the child of Judaism, and, as I showed above, Jesus based all his arguments on hedonistic principles. The selfishness which Jesus and his followers condemn is the narrow selfishness which in the end is net truly self-beneficial. A Plea for Hedonism. 41 Christianity claims to save men not only from the eternal penalties of their sins, but it as distinctly offers eternal happiness to those who accept the simple plan of salva- tion, and peace that passeth understanding throughout the earthly life. The self-denial which the Christian advo- cates can be accepted by the consistent hedonist, — at any rate when coupled with the blessings held out by Chris- tianity. If those blessings are guaranteed, the most ardent hedonist will admit that the self-denial is worth while. It is true that the more spiritual Christians profess to base their doctrines on love and not on the hope of reward. But if heaven and hell were cancelled from the doctrines of Christianity, there is reason to fear that there would be a great falling off in the number of Chris- tians. A few high spirits may find Kant's doctrine of duty and the doctrine of love sufficient sanctions of con- duct. But for the great majority of mankind duty in the abstract and love in the abstract would prove almost totally worthless as sanctions of conduct. Common men must have a sanction of a more practical kind. The con- sequences of conduct must be kept before their eyes. Even the force of habit, even the strongest religious beliefs, will not hold men to conduct which they plainly see it is to their interest to avoid. And if the promise of inconceivably rich rewards and the threats of inconceiv- ably awful punishments have not been able to constrain men to obey the rules of Christianity with even plausible strictness, how much more would these rules be neglected if these terrible sanctions were abolished? One feels safe in saying that even if the negative sanctions, the punishments, were abolished, the neglect of Christianity would increase in a marked degree. This, too, not only in spite of a future reward but in the face of the fact that Christianity is largely based on philosophical hedonistic principles. The reaction would be due to the fact that too many people accept Christianity through fear. They are afraid to disobey. They have not grasped the philosophy of conduct. They do not perceive that Christianity is pointing out the line of conduct which is best for the individual. They feel that they must be 42 A Plea tor Hedonism. "good" in order to escape bell and consequently "good- ness" is always a burden to them. Because it Is forced on them they dislike it, just as a school boy dislikes his studies. The same state of facts doubtless exists among the followers of all religions. Fear and not reason holds them to the mark. Here and there a thoughtful individ- ual catches a glimpse of the beauty of holiness, of the reasonableness of the philosophy of the prescribed con- duct, (if it happens to be reasonable or philosophical, which too often is not the .case.) But the masses obey blindly and doggedly, because they think they must. But if the ethical and religious thinkers who have had the greatest influence on the lives and conduct of their fellowmen have attained this result by an appeal to the sentience of their hearers, and by a demonstration of the personal advantage of accepting their doctrines, the political and economic thinkers have still more plainly and emphatically appealed to prudential reasons. Even those statesmen who have insisted most strongly on the divine origin of kings and other institutions, have felt compelled to bolster up their claims by sanctions of a sentient nature, that is, by a system of rewards and punishments. But the true statesman, the wise ruler, in all ages and nations has had the welfare of the people at heart and has sought to provide the political and eco- nomic institutions which would best promote the general welfare. Whatever additional prerogatives have been claimed for the state, the protection of the citizen from external enemies, the suppression of crime, the mainten- ance of good order and justice have always been recog- nized as falling within the sphere of duties or rights of the ruler. Moses and Manu, Solon and Lycurgus, Murna and Justinian, Washington and Gladstone all had the welfare of the people at heart. It is true that the glory of the state has sometimes blinded men's eyes to the needs of the people. But however this may have been, it is now universally admitted that the ruler should constantly have in mind the welfare of the people. Utility, not consistency with any abstract theory, is the modern test of political and economic science. And A Plea lor Hedonism. 43 in the political systems of the past, it was the useful institutions which preserved the systems and made them acceptable. Take the Common and Statue Law of England. It was not its theory of the divine rights of kings, its subjection of women, its descent by primogeni- ture, its aristocratic electoral system, or its state- supported church which made it so strong and so valuable. Its admirable system of justice, its Magna Charta and Habeas Corpus, its Court of Equity and House of Commons, and above all its constant appeal to sentient facts and common sense were its real strength and grandeur. The same is true of the Roman law, from which English law drew far more than its admirers like to admit. The exceeding flexibility of both these systems, where flexibility permitted improvement in the interests of the general welfare, and their stern inflexibility where there would have been danger to the public or the individual good, is the secret of their inestimable value. Unconsciously resting on the sound good sense of practi- cal men, Roman and English law are living monuments of the value of hedonism . But the case for Hedonism grows clearer and stronger as we proceed. If the political and economic systems of the world which have proved the most durable and excel- lent are more obviously hedonistic than the religious and ethical systems, the social systems of the progressive nations show still more clearly the marks of hedonism. This subject is so vast that one can do little more than call attention to its more salient features. Questions of family life, of education, of pauperism, of the helpless and disabled, of marriage and divorce, of the prevention and suppression of vice, of amusements, of health and disease, trade, commerce and science, must be determined by hedonistic rules. The first requisite of the continued existence of the individual and of the race is the observance of the rules of health. No one will claim that these rules can be deter- mined otherwise than by experience, that is, by the canon of consequences. The final purpose of man's earthly 44 A Plea tor Hedonism . sojourn is not yet positively known, unless we accept the evidence of- revealed religkm. Unless, therefore, conduct which conduces to the* pleasan test possible life is clearly forbidden by an authoritative revelation, the hedonist insists that that conduct is legitimate. More than this, a revelation which ran counter to the laws of health would have to be very clear and positive or intelligent men would refuse to accept it. Such practices as self mutilation, self torture, excessive fasting, celibacy, asceticism, and deliberate poverty have gradually become discounte- nanced by intelligent man. They belong to a philosophy of pain, which, however strong a hold it may once have held on the religious consciousness of mankind, has grad- ually fallen into disfavor. The number of men who believe that Grod takes delight in the sufferings of any of his creatures is rapidly decreasing and the sooner they have all disappeared the better it will be for the race. The religion which attempts to retard the wheels of progress will certainly and deservedly be crushed in the attempt. But progress means increase in intelligence, strength, health, skill and happiness; increase in the knowledge of the laws of nature and of the human con- stitution; and increase in skill in the application of the knowledge for the benefit of humanity. Progress means an elevation of the ideal of human destiny and an increase in the effort to attain that ideal. Progress means the discovery of the causes of human misery and wretched- ness, and the removal of those evils, in so far as it lies within human power to remove them. Progress means faithfulness to truth and honesty about facts, though all our preconceived notions and theories must be sacrificed. IV. THE DIFFICULTIES OF HEDONISM. A Plea for Hedonism which should neglect to examine the many objections which have been made t© the doctrine would be a very one sided argument. The attempt to answer all the objections which have been put forward in opposition to our theory would be to write a book as large as those of Thomas Aquinas and Kichard Cumber- land. But a glance at some of the chief objections will A Plea for Hedonism. * 45 serye to strengthen the position of Hedonism as the real guide to conduct. 1. The "Sum of Pleasures." Among the objections most frequently advanced against our theory is that which the late Professor T. H. Green dwelt most upon, to wit: that there can be no "sum of pleasures" and that therefore it is not possible to strive for "the greatest possible sum of pleasures". That pleasure cannot be gathered like black-berries and heaped up in baskets, everyone will admit. But that one may enjoy a greater amount of pleasure or happiness than another, everyone knows to be the case. In matters of food, two loaves are better than one; in matters of clothing, two blankets are better than one; in matters of senses, two eyes are better than one; two ears better than one; in matters of activity, two hands and two feet are better than one hand and one foot. In matters of education, two years of schooling are better than one, two hundred volumes more serviceable than one hundred; in matters of agriculture, two horses are better than one, two cows better than one, a two story house better than a one story house. So in matters of pure enjoyment, a two days vacation is preferable to one day, two chickens go farther at a picnic than one, two pounds of candy than one, two bottles of wine than one. If those who argue that there can be no summation of pleasures mean to say that there is no such thing as varying the. amount of one's pleasures, they are talking against facts. If they mean anything else they do not interest either;,the Hedon- ist or the practical man. 35 2. The Problem of Responsibility. It is sometimes objected to the doctrine of Hedonism that it destroys human responsibility. For if each indi- vidual is his own judge as to what will promote his great- est happiness, other men have no ground for interference, even if he is mistaken. The contented swine knows his own mind better than any one else can know it, and if 35 See Taylor, Prob of Conduct, p, 530, 46 A Plea for Hedonism. the wallow furnishes him the means of the purest enjoy- ment, creatures who do not care for the mire should not interfere. There is an element of truth in this contention. We must not try to force upon a nature interests which are wholly alien to it. By no possible contrivance can the pig be made to enjoy the parlor as much as he enjoys his wallow. And if it were necessary to take pig natures into account in the state and in society, it would be necessary to make allowance for this fact. 36 But while human tem- peraments vary greatly, they do not vary so greatly as do the temperament of a man and a pig. There are cer- tain general traits which are found in all men's natures, certain likes and dislikes, certain sympathies and antip- athies. It is on the basis of these traits that society and the state are constructed. 37 Within certain limits we encourage individuality, but certain bounds must not be passed by the individual. He must not commit murder, arson, theft, slander, assault and battery, adultery or nuisance. Every intelligent man is presumed to know the evil consequences of such acts, in terms of welfare (pleasure and pain), upon his neighbors. Their effects are so uniformly evil that the state itself attends to their punishment. There is an implied agreement among all moral citizens not to commit such deeds. Other acts, such as drunkenness, lying and rudeness the state does not attempt to punish unless accompanied by acts of interference with the rights of others. The child and the lunatic are 'excused from responsibility for the same reason that the dumb beast is excused. They lack the intelligence necessary to link cause and effect. The prob- lem at which criminologists are now working is whether the criminal has that degree of intelligence which should enable him to see the results of his act as they are seen by the normal man. 88 But even if a man is lacking in intelli- ^Hoffding, Ethik., p. 109. 37 See W. Wallace, lectures and Essays, pp. 250 and 261 et seq. 38 Whar4:on, Crim. Law, I. ch. 2; WbVs Pollock on the Iyaw of Torts, ch. 2,- p. 23. See WV Wallace, op„ cit f 310, A Plea for Hedonism. 47 gence, the sanctions of law and morals are sometimes binding upon him. If he knows that an act is forbidden under a given penalty, he should be punished, even if he is not able to reason out the full consequence of his act. 39 For only thus can society maintain its existence. Luna- tics and small children are greatly restrained by the certainty of punishment, although they are unable to appreciate the reason for the establishment of punish- ment. In fact, the philosophers themselves have not yet come to an agreement as to the basis and grounds of punishment. The limits, also, within which society shall restrain the actions of the individual are still a matter of dispute. The Socialist would have the state take charge of almost the whole human life, while the individualist would limit state control to the enforcement of the criminal law. This is not the place to follow up the discussion; suffice it to say that in our opinion the question is purely one of utility. If the majority of the citizens within a given area prefer socialism, it seems to me that they are justified in adopting such a mode of government. The individual who dislikes such a course can move away or exert his influence to reform the law. What I have said above does not amount to saying that might makes right. At least, if by right is meant the greatest welfare of the individuals of the society. For the action of the majority may really prove injurious or even destructive to the society. Such a course makes only a relative right or political right. 40 Conformity to the social law, whatever it may be, entitles one to the social approval and the escape from the sanc- tions of the social law. Rut such conformity does not ensure the actor his greatest happiness or welfare. Nor has any society more than a relative justification in adopting a law which is not for the welfare of the society. An independent people is responsible to.no other earthly 39 Sidgwick, Meth. of Eth., Bk. I, ch. 5; Maudsley, Responsibility in Xvlental Disease. 4<> Herein ljes the fallacy of F|obbes v who made the political sanction to conduct absolute. Leviathan, ch. 26, 48 A Plea for Hedonism. power for its acts, but that does not make its acts abso- lutely right. Only correspondence with the greatest wel- fare of the society can make a law absolutely right. 41 As A. E. Taylor says, "When the evolution of ethical senti- ment is complete, I am responsible to myself for obedience to a law which I impose on myself, for the discharge of duties which I expect of myself, and should continue to expect, though God and man were to agree to connive at my disregard of them 48 . In other words, when I have adopted my ethical ideal, no matter what it may be, I have become a law unto myself, the judge of my own action." 4 * 3. The Variability of Human Nature. Another objection which has been often urged against Hedonism is that human nature is so variable as to make any standard of action based thereon of little if any value. This objection is not substantially different from the last preceding. What pleases my taste may be disgusting to my neighbor. What he likes may be repulsive to me. The tastes of youth vary from the taste of old age. The young love activity, noise, strife, opposition. The old love quiet, peace, unanimity, concordance. One man loves self-assertion, boldness, courage, coolness, nerve and skill. Another prefers humility, meekness, kindness, affection and grace. One man prefers wealth and pomp, praise and prominence. Another prefers a quiet nook with his pipe and his book, or independence and rags like Huckleberry Finn. One man is self-contained and prefers his own company to that of any one else. Another lives in the conversation and opinions of other men. One man never loses sight of his own interests; his every act is a move to promote his own welfare. Another is naturally sympathetic. He seldom thinks of his own welfare, but is "Since the above was written I find that Prof. William Wallace has already expressed the same idea in much better terms. See Essays and Lectures, pp. 253-4. 42 A. B. Taylor, The Problem of Conduct, p. 153. * 3 Kant no doubt had this evolutionary product in mind when he declared for the famous "categorical imperative." A Plea tor Hedonism. 49 always studying how he can do more to make his fellow- men happier. One man spends all his substance for the good of others. Another wears himself out devising methods for getting possession of the goods of others. Differences of temperament are familiar to us all. 44 How will the hedonist reconcile all this variability? The hedonist will not reconcile it at all. He takes men as they are. When he finds that the benevolent dis- position is for the social good, he will join with nature in encouraging such men. But the greater part of the problem nature must solve. She has probably found use for courage, anger, covetousness, and pugnacity in the past, or she would have rooted them out of human nature before this. 45 "This variability of sentiment is but the concomitant of the transition from the aboriginal type of society fitted for destructive activities, to the civi- lized type fitted for peaceful activities." But so long as this variability exists, of course the line of conduct of differently constituted individuals could not be expected agree in all respects. The hedonist is not bound to lay down any hard and fast rules of conduct. He insists, on the contrary, on the greatest freedom for all in the formation and pursuit of these ideals. Certain general rules all must observe; but beyond these, there is a wide field left open for the individ- ual choice and preference. 4. The Paradox of Hedonism. One of the most frequently mentioned objections to Hedonism is the so-called "Paradox of Hedonism". In the briefly worded phrase of Prof. Sidgwick, "To get pleasure, one must forget it." Sidgwick and others urge that pleasure cannot be the end or aim of conduct from the fact that when we fix our thoughts too closely on the pleasure which our activities are to bring us, the result is generally disappointing. The pleasure seeker is by no means the happiest of mortals. Men who fix their ^ee Lotze, Micrososmus, Bk. VI., ch. 2. 4 ^See Spender, Prin. Peyc.,,11, §524. 50 A Plea for Hedonism. minds on the attainment of other objects than their own pleasures are usually the most contented and happy. Those who raise this objection neglect, it seems to me, several important psychological phenomena. The first of these is the law of attention. The human mind is so constituted that the field of clear consciousness is always narrow. And owing to the fact that human ideals must be attained by more or less elaborate means or processes, it is generally necessary to concentrate tke attention so closely on the means and details, that the ideal or ulti- mate purpose of the conduct is for the time shut out from the field of consciousness; just as the top of the hill is shut off by the windings of the road. These facts are so familiar that it appears stranger that a psychologist with the penetration which Sidgwick possessed should overlook them. But while our ideal may be forgotten while we are devoting attention to the means, it has not really passed into oblivion. Jacob, for instance, during the seven years of his service for the hand of Rachel must have found it constantly necessary to devote his whole attention to his work. But the ultimate reward was before him all the time. Had Rachel died, his course of life would have been instantly changed. Young Hanni- bal, too, as he underwent the weary exercises necessary to train him for the hardy life of a soldier, must have frequently forgot his oath to destroy Rome, yet that oath spurred him on through all trials and hardships. So the man who devotes his life to art, science or literature must frequently lose himself in the drudgery of essential preparation and discipline, yet he expects the attainment of his ideal to bring a great satisfaction and pleasure. Once more, those who insist upon the paradox of Hedonism, as well as those who hold that pleasure is not the only object of desire 46 forget the sources and nature of pleasure. For our present purposes, it is only necessary to point out that activity as such is usually agreeable. Compulsory inactivity is the severest punishment to most men. For this reason the pursuit of aa iieal is often as ^Especially Green, Prolog, to Ethics, p. 186 et seq. A Plea lor Hedonism. 51 pleasant or even pleasanter than the attainment thereof. Thus all kinds of games afford amusement, the end to be accomplished being quite subordinate. Once more, the mere contemplation or the accomplishment of success is often a sufficient motive to justify much toil and trouble, regardless of the importance of the success itself. Some men are willing to devote a lifetime of drudgery to accomplish an ideal, which other men would regard as trivial. Others again derive their enjoyment from the struggle in which they engage, from the victories and triumphs which they secure, regardless of the actual ulti- mate value to themselves or others of these achievements. Again, some men prefer the enjoyment of as much inactiv- ity as possible. Such natures would prefer an eternity of Nirvana to one of "playing on a golden harp" or other activity. Lastly, the pleasures of some men are intellectual, those of others, emotional, and those of others, sensual. The intellectual and sensual pleasures relate more closely to the self than do the emotional. MaDy of the emotional pleasures arise from altruistic activities. Some men are so constituted that activity for the benefit of others is always more enjoyable to them than self-beneficial activi- ties. For a mind so constituted, no doubt it is true that the best way to get a pleasure is to forget it. And in all the cases above mentioned, it is evident that the ideal is either a purely pleasant or agreeable one or else involves sufficient pleasure or satisfaction in its attainment to make it come under the category of Hedonism. The course of life which one prefers to follow and would willingly pursue a second time is hedonistic, whether the goal of that life or only the struggle toward that goal is the ground of that satisfaction and desirability. Un- trammeled preferability is the real hedonistic test. Hence those, such as Green, 47 who attempt to distinguish between "pleasure' ' and "self-satisfaction" are making a limitation which Hedonism refuses to recognize. Men's prefeianees lie at the base of their activities. Hedonism * 7 op. cit. p. 187, 52 A Plea for Hedonism. seeks to reach and guide through these preferences. In some cases the preferences themselves need enlightenment. That is the business of the scienes. In other cases new preferences are needed. This is never strictly the business of ethics— assisting nature. V. THE PROBLEM OF ALTRUISM. 1. Pseudo Altruism. Our purpose, then, is to outline, if possible, a philos- ophy of conduct; that is, to show what line of conduct is most desirable or preferable, under the circumstancs of a particular environment. So much of conduct, therefore, as can be shown to be desirable to the individual as an individual, whether it is also conducive to social welfare or not, that is, whether it is socially desirable or not, need not concern us in the present section. (Kant ruled self- benefitting acts out of the province of ethics. ) For, if under every possible view of the environment, present and future, the proposed line of conduct is desirable or prefer- able for the individual, we must assume that the individ- ual will follow that line of conduct if possible, as soon as he becomes aware of this fact. The trouble in the past has been that the individual took too narrow a* view of the environment and was unable to see that conduct which was socially desirable was also individually desir- able. Thus the advantage of association in the largest possible groups under similar laws did not become apparent to men for thousands of years. But the destruc- tion of tribes who failed to see the advantage of larger unions, and the gradual development of the more fortu- nate tribes and nations which combined their strength has at last developed the idea of world empires. The advantages of universal education, of faithful fulfillment of contracts, of veracity and honesty, of chastity and sobriety, of politeness, neighborliness, considerateness and respectfulness have only gradually dawned on the human mind. That a perfectly selfish and unsympa- thetic man may contribute largely to the social welfare in all these and many other ways is apparent. T^hus a wise man might so act among a savage tribe as to gain the A Plea for Hedonism. 58 credit of \ being exceedingly altruistic, and yet be act- ing all the time in his own interest. This policy is now very commonly pursued among enterprising merchants and traders, not only among savages, but in the midst of the highest .civilization. From what we have, sad, it is apparent that a vast amount of con- duct is credited as altruistic or disinterested which is not so in reality. It is further apparent that much activity is called disinterested which would not be so called if we were well enough informed to see that the actor is really working for his own benefit, that is, that in addi- tion to the altruistic results of his actions they have also self-beneficial results which amply justify them. In many eases, too, the actor looks on these self-beneficial results as a sort of reward for the altruistic consequences of his acts, and is thus further supported in his action by the consciousness of a supposed merit, a merit which would disappear could all men clearly perceive the self-beneficial consequences of the acts. For we do not ascribe merit to acts whose beneficial consequences to the actor are clearly and certainly foreseen. But these concepts of equity and justice, which lead us daily to a thousand acts without a thought o ftheir having any moral quality whatsoever are the product of age— any training of the race in social experiences. By means of the canon of consequences, we have become so thoroughly drilled in the more common matters of social intercourse, that it is only with an effort that we can perceive their moral quality. Hence the line between pseudo-altruism and prudence is gradually being pushed back, as men perceive the prudential advan- tage of a given course of action— that it is clearly to the advantage of the actor to follow it, one ceases to attrib- ute merit to the act. As we show in the next section, there is reason to believe, and it is the object of Hedonism to point out to all men, that the field of prudence will in time cover the entire field of human voluntary activities. 2. Eational Altruism. There is another important group of activities which are commonly classed as disinterested, which on closer 54 A Plea lor Hedonism. examination turn out to be only a sUlbffci&r l&em of interested activities. Take the familiar tfase of a tfaan who enters an arm y. If uninstructed, the n&tupal impulse would be to run when danger appears. But the wise general will explain to his soldiers that a bold front often frightens the enemy away, that even where this does not happen, that by standing firmly together each individual is really much safer than if he attempts to retreat. Following such instruction the soldier learns to face the danger and stand by his comrades when they are in danger. The importance of keeping watch is appreciated by all, and therefore when the turn of any individual comes to stand sentinel, he takes the chances of being shot for the sake of preserving himself and others, and also for the sake of having others stand sentinel when their turn comes. Take now a more intricate case. We Mave Indicated above that the wise man learns the value in the long run of veracity, honesty, chastity, kindness, politeness and the many other social virtues. But he also finds that these virtues can only be acquired by eonstant exercise. This constant exercise forms a habit. Now, when a case comes where a lie would possibly be advantageous, the habit of veracity has become so strong that the truth comes out, even while the speaker realizes that it may cost his fortune or his life. A thoughtful man may have reflected on the possibility of such an occurrence early in life. But it was only a possibility and the chances in favor of its not occurring, or the net gain of truth telling may have been such as to lead him consciously to take the chances, or to take the smaller evil with the greater good. Where the whole course of conduct is profitable, then the particular instance where the course proves dis- advantageous should not be classed as disinterested, especially where it was necessary to form a habit of acting in the given way in order to attain the best results. But experience teaches that all the common virtues, which on the whole are recognized by intelligent people as profit- able to the actor, but which in particular instances could be departed from with advantage by the ack>r, can attain A Plea for Hedonism. 66 their fullest usefeikkeas only by constant and unremitted practice all through life, thereby making them ataost mechanical by habitual practice. Thus the habit? of veracity may become so fixed as to make death easier than falsehood. While frequent departure from the truth makes lying so easy as to give no sting of conscience whatever. The same is true as to faithfulness to promises. To a man like Regulus, death by torment is preferable to breach of promise. A man who has not trained himself to this habitual fidelity to promises would feel amply justified in breaking a promise extorted as was the promise of Regulus. The same rule holds good as to pro- fanity, to abstinence from intoxicants and sexual indul- gence, and to honesty. 48 Self-culture, which is the aim of self- discipline, is the contradictory of social justice, which is the aim of true altruism. This self-cultivating activity I have called rational altruism. When two habitual virtues come into conflict, we have a curious altruistic puzzle, such as the problem of veracity when in conflict with the habit or impulse of kindness. Shall I lie to prevent the wrongful death or injury of a friend? This question has puzzled philosophers from the days of Aris- totle, to those of James Martineau. Rational altruism would apparently solve the problem in favor of veracity; but pure altruism, submitting to the power of the altru- istic sentiment, will probably always solve it in favor of kindness. The foregoing remarks are intended to show the reader how narrow the margin of conflict is between activity which is socially beneficial and that which is beneficial for the individual but injurious to society. The narrower this margin can be made to appear, the easier it will be to persuade men to live morally. For so long as you can point out to a man that the line of conduct which you suggest is really prefer- able for him, is in fact that which he would follow if he knew his own interest, you may expect that he will listen 48 Taylor brings the above distinction out very clearly in Chap. V. of his Problem of Ethics. 56 A Plea tor Hedonism. to you. But if you appeal to a man's conscience, to his sense of duty, to the social welfare, or the happiness of posterity, you may' feel sure that he will listen to you unwillingly. No one can calculate the amount of misery which exists because men are either following unwillingly a course of action which they feel in duty bound to follow, but would prefer not to follow, or are living for self, while feeling that t hey ought to be doing something else. An ethical theory, therefore, which can convince men, even in a small degree 1 hat what they think duty is really self- interest, and what they think self-interest is really often injurious will conf * r a great boon on mankind. There is misery and wretchedness in life at best, without any mpre of it based on unnecessary grounds. 3. Pure Altru ism. But after all has been said that it is possible to say in the way of narrow ing the margin of conflict between self- interest and altruism, we must acknowledge that there is still a margin left. The welfare of the individual, at the present day, does not quite correspond, so far as we can see, with the welfare of humanity. More than this, individuals are found who are consciously acting in ehe interest of society to the detriment of their own interests. Real self-sacrifice is a fact so familiar that we cannot shut our eyes to it. Heroism is a word to be found in most languages, and heroes are to found in all ages and among all peoples. Maternal love, social sympathy and pity are too well known to be denied. Moreover, the efforts of Bentham, James Mill and others to reduce altruism to terms of self-interest were not successful. 49 No doubt they had in mind the instances we have given above of pseudo-altruism and rational altruism. But we must admit many cases of true self-sacrifice, conscious, deliberate self-sacrifice. How shall we account for these cases? That self-sacrifice is not logically justifiable on hedonistic principles we must continue to assert. But if it is not logically justifiable, how can it be accounted for? * 9 Stephen, the Eng. Util., I. p. 313 et seq; II. 321. A Plea for Hedonism. 57 Leslie Stephen, Herbert Spencer and S. Alexander, three of the leading evolutionary becUmkts, answer the question by pointing out that our activity is determined by the ideas and emotions present at the moment of decision. Now the present idea of a future pleasure or pain may be very different from the actual pleasure or pain, when it arrives. While the idea of the suffering which another will endure, together with our own after recollections of the same, may present a very vivid motive to perform the act. Thus our own good is the motive after all. As Spencer points out, the pains of another may be as clear to us as our own future pains. Our sym- pathies are strongest where we have ourselves experienced the sufferings which we now see in another. And with sufferings which we have never experienced our sym- pathies are correspondingly weak. The actual pain or pleasure of another is not, therefore, our motive in altru- istic activity, but the ideas of those pains and pleasures which exist in our own minds. There is no doubt considerable force in this line of reasoning. Yet A. E. Taylor, in his Problem of Conduct, denies that it has any validity; taking the ground that we have no present idea of future pleasures and pains at all. But this view is certainly erroneous. I have said above that from the standpoint of Hedonism altruistic conduct is illogical. But because it is illogical, it by no means follows that it cannot be accounted for. There are other impulses of the same kind. Superstitious feelings are also illogical, but one cannot for that reason free him- self from them. The child shrieks with terror when his little brother plays bear, knowing all the while that there is no real danger. Adults will do the same at the sight of an artificial snake, or even a jaek-in-the-box. Many people do not like to start on a journey on Friday, or to sit at a table with twelve others, or to break a looking- glass, or to give or receive an edged present. They laugh at their own feelings, but cannot shake them off. Some people dare not stand near a precipice because the impulse to leap over is too strong to be resisted. Some 68 A Plea tor Hed&atem. children cannot resist the impulse to handle or crush certain objects, knowing full well that they are obswved and will be punished. A man will often ftad it Impossible to resist the impulse to swear, or to tell some one what he thinks of him, even while he knows that the penalty will be heavy. Again, the impulse to laugh often comes on us at the most inopportune moments. We would give our right hand to hold it back, but on it comes. The impulse to take revenge or to wreak spite Is likewise often irresis- tible in the face of penalties. The impulse to play tricks is another instance. Everyone will recall children and even adults who could not resist the opportunity to play a practical joke, even though regretting the consequences at the very moment of acting. Now all these are really cases of disinterested, although not altruistic, activity. It is irresistible. Nature has implanted certain impulses in us which all our reason is not strong enough to over- come. Many of our impulses can in time be brought under control. When we perceive their evil consequences, we make a constant effort to rid ourselves of them. But in the case of altruistic impulses, the advantage to society leads men to approve the acts inspired by fehem, and thus they tend rather to become confirmed, because the approval tends to make them self-interested acts. Besides, as I have indicated above, nature selects for sur- vival the individuals who are strongly gifted with altru- istic impulses. 80 Thus these impulses tend to become stronger from generation to generation. But the indi- viduals who have the most vivid imaginations and can picture the pains and pleasures of others most readily will be those who will have the strongest sympathies. So nature will continue to select those individuals who find the most pleasure in promoting the pleasures of others, and who will do the most to lessen the pains of others. The activities inspired by these impulses are not then, strictly speaking, a part of voluntary conduct at all. 50 Duhring, Der Wert des Lebens, cited by Hdffding, Hist. Mod. Philos., II., p. 560. A Plea wr Hedonism. 99 They belong to the class of activities which nature takes care of— the instincts and reflex actions. 81 As I have already indicated, Mr. Benjamin Kidd, in his Social Evolution and his Western Civilization, has emphasized more strongly than any other writer the share which nature takes in human evolution, by means of the evolution of the ethical and religious impulses. He brings a large array of facts to show that not intellectual devel- opment but moral and religious development have been the characteristics of the races which have won in the struggle for existence. The chief reason for this is that intellectual families die out. They are anxious to have their child- ren occupy as high a grade in society as they themselves occupy, and this desire retards marriage. Thus only five out of the five hundred noble families in England can trace back their ancestry in the male line to the fifteenth century. The same is true in France and probably in all other countries. The aristocracy is constantly dying out and being replaced by a new aristocracy. 52 Mere intellec- tual development, however high, is not sufficient to secure the persistence of the race. It is generally conceded, for instance, that the Greeks were the most highly, developed intellectually of any people who ever lived. Yet while they are still in existence, nominally, they were long ago outstripped in the race for existence, and there is probably very little if any of the blood of the ancient Atheneans now flowing in the veins of the Grecians. The old stock has entirely disappeared. They lack those traits of character which insure posterity or racial persis- tence. The same thing happened among the Romans. In the days of the empire the old families disappeared and were replaced by foreigners. Spain, France and England have had a similar experience. Nature, then, is constantly selecting for race preservation those individuals who have the social sentiments, love of offspring, devotion to family life, loyalty to clan, tribe, or city, pity for the weak and mit freude with the strong, most strongly developed. 51 See Calkins, Introd. to Psyc, p. 333, et seq. 52 See especially Soc. Evol. Chap. IX. 60 A Pirn for Hedonism. The variation of social sentiment may be very slight, is in fact slight; but nature never overlooks these slight varia- tions. They may also be what we call accidental. (And that may mean mere blind chance, or the work of an unseen artificer working out a great design.) But so long as they are hereditary they answer the purpose of nature. Neither is it necessary that they be intellectually justifiable. To sacrifice self for others may seem unreasonable, but if nature impels us to do it, we must submit just as we submit to the trouble of finding food and drink when we are hungry or thirsty. But it will be objected that this view fails to account for the high esteem which is universally accorded to self- sacrifice. Let us see. In the first place, it is natural for the recipient to approve the beneficial act. This approval is not based on the personality of the act, that is, on the fact that it was voluntarily and consciously performed by an intelligent being. For we approve the beneficial acts of nature. When the stone we throw brings down the fruit or the game, when the seed we plant grows, and when the experiment we try succeeds, we have this feeling of approval. In the next place, experience teaches us that the man who is capable of self-sacrifice is a desirable companion. The sacrificial act is an index to the character fit for society. It indicates the presence of of a "good" man, one who will not break promises, lie, steal nor in other ways prove himself unsocial. It indi- cates what we call a "good-natured" man. But we approve and love good-natured animals as well as good- natured men. Animals which are affectionate, tameable, not given to treachery nor to fits of anger, which are obedient and tractable, which are playful and good- humored are taken up as companions by men and loved. And who will undertake to draw a line between the altruistic activity of a brute and that of a man? The maternal instinct is as strong, if not stronger, in the former as in the latter; the gregarious or social instinct is as strong if not stronger, for man is by no means so gregarious as the herbivorous animals and certain birds. Nor is the social instinct equally developed in all men. A Plea for Hedonism. 61 Even those who live in large cities often confine their lives largely to the family. And many men prefer the seclusion of family life on a farm, far from the crowd. Seme even prefer solitary life. The instincts of pity* and generosity are perhaps more prominent in men than in brutes because men can perceive the consequences of actions more clearly. And yet the instinct of pity, or a£f< ction for the weak is certainly highly developed in many brutes. Again, we must remember that altruistic individuals oiiten cannot realize their own merits. The true hero can not understand the admiration of others. To the affec- tionate mother it seems only natural for mothers to love and care for their offspring. Her disapproval of unsym- pathetic parents arises from a feeling that they are lack- ing in "natural" traits. There is an instinctive dislike for defective or deformed people. (Hence we call an unsym- pathetic parent "unnatural.") And the sympathetic feel that the unsympathetic are defective. But to the sym- pathetic mother there is no feeling of special approval of other affectionate mothers; such conduct seems "natur- al." 68 The same is true in even a greater degree with the true hero. He does not feel that he has done anything extraordinary. 54 He has simply done what his nature called him to do. There is no sense of effort or strain, because there is in fact no unnatural strain. The hero is humble, because he is not conscious of having done any- thing to be proud of. The proud hero (and they are numerous enough) is one who perceives the advantage of heroism. He knows that people admire strength, beauty, skill, endurance, energy and success, and having one or more of these traits he admires himself and enjoys by anticipation the pleasures of admiration and praise. He knows that people admire and approve self-discipline as well as self-sacrifice, aud he is willing to pay the price for the popular admiration and approval. This admiration and approval of power, whether in form of strength, ^epken, Science of Bthie& p. 26£ %n& Ut&,» X, P- 259- M Jacob A. Riis, The Making of an American, pi 423. 62 A Plea, for Hedonism. beauty, skill, eloquence, endurance, energy, cunning, or of training and self-discipline, is partly hereditary and partly institutional. 86 The advantages of power, both for the individual and for the race, is so apparent that we should expect it to be approved and encouraged. Train- ing and self-discipline are especially valuable both for the individual and for the race. And the step from self-dis- cipline to altruistic self-sacrifice is so short that it is taken unconsciously. In our admiration for the trained man, we usually fail to distinguish between the two. And even the philosopher finds it hard to draw the line. 56 4. Abnormal Altruism. That the altruistic impulses are of natural origin is further shown by the fact that, like selfish impulses, they are liable to be abnormally and hence injuriously developed. The mother may be so affectionate as to "spoil" her child, or break down her own health. 57 The generous man may give away all his property, thereby injuring himself and, what is of more importance, those who are dependent on him for a living, especially his immediate family. The patriot usually neglects those who are immediately depend- ent on him. 58 The reformer is apt to do the same. The man who is gifted with too much pity cannot be just. Rogues and rascals constantly impose on his good-nature. This is why it is said that women would not make good judges or jury-men. They could not render a fair decision or verdict. (I do not make this assertion myself, but quote the common opinion.) The hero is not so cautious as the selfish man, and is more apt to lose his life. Bravery often becomes reckless daring, if not foolhardiness. The over-sympathetic man finds it hard to tell the truth when the truth will hurt a friend, hard to be honest when dis- 55 Comp. Ladd, Phil, of Conduct, Chap. XI, p. 231. S6 See, for instance, Bradley, Appearance and Reality, chapter on "Goodness." S7 6ee Spencer, Ethics, I, $72. •"Tel soulage le miserable, qui neglige sa famille et laisse son fils tfaflsl'indigence."— I^a Bruyere, Characteres, Ch. XII, p. 375.' (Ed. 1890.) A Plea tor Hedonism. 68 honesty will help a neighbor at the expense of a stranger. The Japanese are said to be so polite that they will com- mit almost any crime rather than hurt the feelings of other people. Thus altruism presents a problem within a problem. Traits of character which were intended to preserve the race, tend when excessive to destroy the social order, and thereby the race itself. But as all altruistic activity is illogical, how shall excessive altruism be curbed? We can nob reason with the altruistic person. He is acting according to his nature. All that is left to do is to dis- approve such conduct so strongly that in time this disap- proval will act on his feelings. Nature herself will also tend to weed out the excessively altruistic. It is this excessive altruism which Nietzsche and his followers object to. 59 Nietzsche would apparently have us select and breed men as we select and breed horses, cattle and sheep. But assuming the possibility of doing so, we must still deter- mine the ideal character for man; and the question then arises whether the emotional or sympathetic character is not the ideal, and if so, how it may best be secured? They argue that our sympathy interferes with race evo- lution, and their argument is apparently just. Too much sympathy, pity and generosity tend to make the idle and shiftless more so. But Nietzsche goes too far in his demands. Even among animals, where the struggle for existence has full play, it is not the strongest and most cunning individuals that survive, but the most sympa- thetic. Any attempt, therefore, to lend a hand in the struggle for existence by helping the strong to survive against the weak would probably result either in the destruction of the whole race, or the nation that tried the experiment. 5. Moral Education. It is well known that to a certain extent we can educate or repress either the selfish or the altruistic impulses in oausselves or others, Shall we educate the 59 The Twilight of the Godp\ ' 64 A PJea wr Hedonism. selfish and repress the altruistic emotions or the reverse? Here again it seems to me that we must resort to,the canon of consequences. We have pointed out above that the most altruistic impulses are at the same time beneficial to self. I believe that science will show in time that those pseudo-altruistic impulses are inextricably united with the altruistic impulses which are beneficial to the race but prejudicial to the individual, when considered by themselves. If this is the case, no one will want to rid himself of those socially beneficial impulses. Thus if my neighbor's vine has overgrown my fruit tree, I will not tear down the vine to preserve my fruit if by tearing it down I shall at the same time kill my tree. So in a case where the individual interests clearly conflict with those of society and the individual lacks the sympathetic impulses necessary to make him strive for the social interest rather than his own, he must still inquire whether he should not seek to cultivate the lacking impulses for the sake of other impulses which will accompany them. As we pointed out above the altruistic impulses which are beneficial to self can only be acquired by a self-discipline that will make them practically mechanical, and when they have become so habitual as to be reflex, or mechan- ical, they will act in cases which will be injurious to self as well as in cases which are beneficial to self. In other words, the character which wisdom requires in order to secure the greatest possible happiness to the individual in his environment on earth is an organic unit of an altru- istic nature. He who seeks to reach the highest possible earthly happiness by the strictly selfish road will not succeed. The so-called paradox of Hedonism is one of the deepest and most wonderful laws of human nature. One must build up an altruistic character to attain such peace on earth as is given to men to enjoy. As Maeter- link so beautifully points out, 60 "The true sage must suffer. He suffers, and suffering forms a constituent part of his wisdom. He will suffer, perhaps, more than most men, for his nature is far more complete. And being ^Wisdom and Bestiny, Sec, 39 A Plea tor Hedonism. 65 nearer to all mankind, as the wise must ever be, his suffer- ings will be the greater, for the sorrows of others are his." And yet the true sage enjoys a peace that passeth under- standing. At the end of life he can say with Paul: "I have fought a good fight." His cup of sorrow may be fuller, but he will drink it willingly. The path of wisdom is so sweet and peaceful, that no one would exchange it for all the paths of temporal pleasure. Thus the apparent conflict between self-culture and social justice is resolved into a higher unity, just as all the apparent conflicts in the universe resolve themselves into higher unities when our knowledge has widened sufficiently to perceive the broader laws. The world is full of conflicts and contradictions for the ignorant, but as knowledge widens, the conflicts disappear one by one, until at last we grasp the conception of the unity of nature. Thus pure disinterested altruism is an ineradicable accompaniment of self-interested altruism, and hence of Hedonism itself. Not only so, but experience proves that purest hedonistic results may be best attained by direct- ing the thought to the social or unselfish aspect of conduct than by the reverse process. Yet so long as one clearly realizes from the start that his own greatest happiness will follow the former course, he is a consistent hedonist. And with that knowledge constantly before him, he will not be apt to fall into the excesses of an abnormal altruism. Justice to self will regulate justice to others. The ideal of self-culture will serve as a model for social culture. VI. CONCLUSION. A few words will suffice by way of conclusion. Glan- cing back over the line of our argument it will be seen that we tried to show first that "Man's Place in Nature" has been determined by the general course of universal evolu- tion and is largely independent of his own desires and wishes. We might have gone further and shown that so far as "Man's Place in Nature" is concerned, the problem of conduct is only a temporal problem. The evidence points very clearly to the recent origin of the human race 66 A Plea for Hedonism. on earth; and it points almost as clearly to the rather early termination of man's earthly existence, speaking in terms of the infinite ages of eternity. In view of these facts, we recognized the importance for the problem of conduct of any light which either science, theology or re- velation can throw on the problem of man's nature and ultimate destiny. For the philosopher, the problem of earthly existence can never seem supremely important, unless that exist- ence is in some way related to an after life. If the earthly life be all, the ethical problem at times seems hardly worth the solving. And yet while this is true, there is no ground for despising the earthly life. Moral science is still at least as important as any of the other sciences. As a sentient creature, man may as well make the most of the earthly life which science and revelation will permit. The strength of Hedonism lies in its insistance on the worth and dignity of the earthly life, even while we are still in uncertainty as to the after-life. It would be idle here to attempt to force conclusions upon the reader. The most learned men have differed in opinion as to the nature of the evidence in favor of an after-life. Some men find in man's moral nature satisfactory proofs of immor- tality. Others find the evidence insufficient and unsatis- factory. This much is certain, however. Some myster- ious power, which for convenience we have called nature in this essay, is shaping man's nature in a marvelous way, so as to adapt him more fully for social life. The human sentiments, and particularly the altruistic and sympathe- tic sentiments have always played and will always con- tinue to play a very important part in the development of the human race. One of the objects of this essay has been to discover just what part the involuntary part of man's nature and what part his intelligence plays in the matter of conduct. Our conclusion was, that the province of intelligence tends constantly to encroach upon the domain of the emotions. But we also found that certain emotions, by their very nature were safe against the en- croachments of intelligence and that as to these emotions, to-wit: the altruistic, there is a tendency toward their A Plvn lor Hedonism. 67 coincidence with the dictates of intelligence. When this point is reached man's character will have become ideal. Whether such a character is destined by nature to fit man for the earthly life alone or for a larger, broader, higher sphere of activity is a question which the writer will leave to the reader's own further consideration. From the stand-point of Hedonism, the earthly life, even if we concede that in some cases it is not under the present regime, will in the course of time become valuable in itself to humanity. In the mean time, ethics must ever remain the queen of all sciences. In the scale of interest and im- portance, ethics must ever rank above all the other intel- lectual inquiries of the scholar. But in thus speaking of. ethics, it must be taken to include the whole problem of human destiny.