•Me"""!"'1'"" NiMtoiu'sffi'rn EVANSTON, ILL. /ubchi . . 73 x CONTENTS. CHAPTER VI.—GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY ... 82-245 Division I.—Philosophy befoee the Time of Sooeates ...82-114 Section 1. Greek Wisdom in the Legendary Ages ... 82 2. The beginning of Philosophy ... ... ... 87 Thales ... ... ... 89 3. The Fir9t School ... ... ... 93 Anaximander ... ... ... ... 94 Anaxamines ... ... ... 95 Heraclitus ... ... 95 Democritua ... ... 98 Empedoeles ... ... ... 99 Anaxagoras ... ... ... 100 4. Pythagoras ... ... ... . ... 102 5. Zcnophanes, Parmenides, Zeno... ... ... 109 Division II. — Greek Philosophy from Soceates to Aris¬ totle ... ... ... ... 114-176 Section 1. Athens in the Time of Socrates—The Sophists 114 2. Socrates ... ... ... 122 3. The Socratics ... 135 The Cyrenaic School ... ... 135 Aristippus . . ... 135 Theodorus ... ... ... 135 Hcgesias ... ... ... ... 135 Anniceris . 135 The Cynic School ... ... 137 Antisthenes ... .. . ... 137 Diogenes ... ... .. 137 The Megarian School .. . . ... 137 Euclides ... ... ... 137 Eubulides ... .... 137 Diodoru9 . . 137 ttilpo ... 137 4. Plato ... ... .. 13S CONTENTS. XI Division III.—Aristotle ... ... ... 17G-231 Section 1. Aristotle the beginner of a New Epoch ... . . 176 2. Relation of Aristotle to Plato ... 179 3. The Logical Treatises of Aristotle . . 186 4. The Physics of Aristotle ... ... 192 5. The Metaphysics of Aristotle .. 197 6. Aristotelian Pyschology ... 218 7. The Aristotelian Ethics . . 221 8. Politics of Aristotle ... ... 230 Division IT.—The Later Sects .. ... ... 231-245 Section 1. Greece after the Time of Alexander ... ... 231 2. Epicurus ... .. ... .. . . 235 3. Stoicism ... .. ... 238 4. The Academic ... ,. 213 CHAPTER Yn.—ROMAN PHILOSOPHY 245-254 Section 1. Roman History and Mythology . . ... . . 245 2. Origin of Latin Philosophy ... . .. . . 246 3. The Roman Epicurean .. . . ... ... 248 4. The Roman Stoic ... ... .. ... 250 5. The Proper Roman Philosophy ... ... ... 251 CHAPTER Yin.—THE ALEXANDRIAN PHILOSOPHY . 254 Section 1. Alexandria 2. The Jewish Philosophy 254 256 INTRODUCTION. i. Philosophy means literally the love of "Wisdom. It is the philosophy love of a hidden treasure. Therefore it comes to mean a search after Wisdom. II. That this hidden treasure is not something which can be pnysu.ii seen or handled, weighed or measured, all have confessed. Yet it may be sought among the things that are seen and handled, weighed and measured, or, to use a more general expression still, among the things that are produced and grow—among Physical things. III. The philosopher asks whether Wisdom is in these things ■ Mctupby whether it is of the same kind with them ; or whether it is of Philosophy a different kind, -whether it is fixed, constant, unproduced ? He who seeks for an object which is not of the same kind with the things around him is called a Metaphysical philosopher. 15 INTRODUCTION. IV. Uh'iToaophy. But how has lie learned to dream of an object different in kind from these things? Is he different from them? How comes he to desire this Wisdom, this hidden treasure? Must it not have more to do with him than with them? If he knew himself, the ways, habits, manners, which belong to his race, might he not be nearer to the object which he seeks? These ways, habits, maimers, occupy the Moral philosopher. V. ivsipn <>r It is the purpose of the present sketch to indicate how treatise. men have been led into these inquiries, how in different countries and ages they have been pursued, what have been the issues of them. VI. scsjfrth— Moral inquiries are suggested by our daily acts, our ordi- ur< t«-d m it. nary speech, our necessary relations. Metaphysical inquiries are suggested by the discovery of powers in ourselves which we do not find in other creatures. The former therefore concern us most, and in a history will present themselves first to our notice. But we shall find that they cannot be separated. Of physical inquiries, so far as they have been entered upon merely for the sake of ascertaining the order and constitution of the world around us, nothing 17111 be reported. So far as they have been suggested by the desire to find Wisdom, they are too much involved in moral inquiries, they arc too evidently presumed in the word no tuphyxiral t > be passed over. The philosopher seeks for Wisdom cv(rywhere that he may know wlieic it is not. INTRODUCTION. 3 VII. All nations have been engaged in this search for "Wisdom, Limitation . ,, >f the sul - those most activelyhich have left most records of themselves „«■«. in the History of the World. Buildings, poems, pictures, mechanical arts,above all polities, have indicated the direction which different periods, countries, individuals have taken in the pursuit. But the name " Philosopher" has been generally and rightly confined to one who has engaged deliberately in the search, and has traced out a method in it. Such a man interprets the less conscious striving of his contemporaries. VIII. It would, however, be a fatal mistake to make even the Not a history 11 most rapid and superficial sketch of philosophical investiga- tions merely a record of the conclusions at which different Schools have arrived. These conclusions are in general premature efforts to terminate the search for Wisdom, to confine the results of it within a few meagre propositions. To trace the thoughts which were working in the minds of those who founded Schools, to discover how they were affected by their characters, teachers, disciples, opponents, personal and political conflicts, to watch the processes by which they were expanded, completed, narrowed, is a far more interesting work, and one which falls far more property witliiu the pro¬ vince of the historian of philosophy. Those w ho busy tliem- selves with the speculations and contradictions of Schools are likely to begin with extravagant expectations and to end in despondency. Earnest sympathising meditations upon the actual efforts of men to discover the secret of their lite, and iju< i ids r which Jiry Uv< , ei .A; in < ipial encourage- m *nts to humility and to hope. i INTRODUCTION. IX. Divjbion ot This sketch will consist of two parts. It will treat of the till, subject Philosophy before and after the coining of Christ. The sub¬ jects considered in the first part will be—1st. The Hebrew Philosophy; 2nd. The Hindoo; 3rd. The Chinese; 4th. The Persian ; 5th. The Greek ; 6th. The Roman; 7th. The Grseco-Hebraic or Alexandrian. In the second part the subjects will be — 1. The Philosophy of the first six cen¬ turies ; 2. The Philosophy of the Middle Ages; 3. The Philosophy of the centuries from the thirteenth to our own time. CHAPTER I. THE HEBREWS. SECTION I. geotjnds of hebeew philosophy. 1. The Hebrew Scriptures are commonly passed over by the Whether the historian of philosophy. Yet the book of Job describes philo- gce^ptures sophy in particularly exact language. " Where is wisdom found, recognise and where is the place of understanding ?" tliis is said to be the philosophy, inquiry in which man is more interested than in finding the veins of silver or in bringing the gold out of the earth. The book of Proverbs sets forth the search for wisdom as its subject and purpose. Man is to dig for it as for hid treasure. Such language is scarcely consistent with an opinion which has been eagerly maintained by persons holding the most opposite views respecting these books ; that they assume all knowledge to be communicated from above, and therefore not to be an object for the search or investigation of man. This opinion, however, could nut have been entertained so generally if there had been no facts or reasons to justify it. The writers of the book of Job and of the book of Proverbs presume the existence of a revela¬ tion, nay, ground their feeling of the possibility and the duty of a search for wisdom upon it. Evidently, then, this revelatjon must have a different meaning in their minds from that which it bears in the minds of many modems. To know what sense it does bear, we must refer to those books which profess to record how God made himself known to man. In these we shall find not Hebrew philosophy itself, but the grounds and elements of it. 2. The book of Genesis opens with the creation of the World, Genesis, or Order, in which we are dwelling. Modern geological disco- principles, veries and speculations have done much to remove a veil which had been thrown over the meaning of this record, and to bring forth the all-important principle, that the sacred historian is 6 THE HEBREWS. speaking of the world in its relation to Max. The whole after history is incoherent and unintelligible if this principle is for¬ gotten ; if the words " (rod made Man in his own likeness," are nivhoh'llC> uu* ^ken aM ^ll> ^ ; ^ie <*ours. jypan< |)u^. -the law and condition of man's being. That He after whose image the creature is made should not Inne given liini the capacity for beholding his own archetype, that He should refine him the power of being what he was made to he, this would he the contradiction. Accordingly it is taken throughout these Scriptures as a contradiction. God is c\ try where said to he speaking to man ; man is intended to hear. God places the first man in a garden, calls forth in him the power by wbieh he names the creatures, provides him with a helpmate, creates the marriage bond. He submits to a lower creature, denies the authority of the invisible Lord, wishes to hide himself from His presence. He is awakened to own that presence, and to feel that he has transgressed. He is driven from the garden : he is to eat his bread bv the sweat of his brow; but this labour is to teach him that he is not dependent upon the earth which he is to till and subdue ; that he is dependent upon an invisible Ruler. The first murder is committed in the world: God asks Cain for his brother. His great punishment is that he goes out from the presence of God. His descendants are described as building cities and inventing mechanical arts. Another race, of which Seth is the head, is said to he called by the name of the Lord. The first is an irregular, disorderly coudition. The second con¬ fesses itself to he under the Invine government. Though nothing is recorded of it but the succession of its families, it is treated as being in the state intended for man at this stage of his growth, (feneral violence and confusion afterwards over¬ spread the earth. A flood is sent to punish the wickedness of those who dwell upon it: the race is preserved in one of the iSeth family. A covenant of God with man is the foundation of the restored world. The sons of Noah are meant to people the earth according to their tongues, in their nations, in their families. A portion of them seeks to set at naught this pur¬ pose, and to build a tower on the plain of Shinar, that thevmay not he scattered abroad on the face of the earth. God, we are told, confounded the rebellious scheme. They left off to build that tower. But a mighty hunter established the kingdoms of Babel and of Nineveh. The Babel kingdom is throughout Scripture treated as the form of godless society. THE HEBREW HISTORICAL BOOKS. 7 4. A Divine education, then, is assumed as the regular basis Theerounfi of human life and human fellowship. God teaches man what kno\w"ai"e he is. Man knows what ho is; he fulfils his appointed task antl life- just so far as he receives this instruction. The instruction pro¬ ceeds from an invisible Being, and is addressed to something else in man than that which connects him with the visible world. He is always ready to forget God, to bow down before visible things, bo far as he does this, he becomes a slave and an animal. So far as he does this, the soeiety in which he lives becomes corrupt and untenable. 5. Abram is called out by God from his father's house to go Theedura- into a strange land. This calling is the foundation of his life. Abraham The Lord of all is speaking to him; he heeds the voice and obeys it. That Lord makes him know that He is one in whom he may trust. He believes in Him as a righteous Being. His faith is counted to him for righteousness; he acknowledges the Being in whose likeness he is made ; he becomes like Him. His outward life is of the most commonplace kind. He is simply a shepherd, with many flocks and herds, dwelling in tents, sur¬ rounded by people who dwell in cities with whom he does not mix but with whom he has frequent dealings. Once he goes forth at the head of his servants to rescue a kinsman who had taken up his abode in the city of bodom. As he returns, he finds a priest of the most high God in Salem, to whom he gives a tenth of his spoil. H e goes into Egypt: it is already an organized nation ; a Pharaoh is reigning there. He loses his faith in God, and tells a lie to save himself: it almost costs him his wife. All his discipline is of the same practical kind. He finds that God overthrows cities which have become hateful and given up to beastly crimes : he is taught to intercede for the righteous in these cities. He is sure that the Judge of all the earth will not slay them with the wicked. He must do right. Abraham is living under the promise that in him and his seed all the families of the earth are to be blessed: but he has no seed. A child is born to him by a bondwoman living in his house. Thus he hopes the promise will be fulfilled: but he is told that the child of his own wife must be his heir. She is barren : yet he believes. He waits long When the child has been born, and is growing up, he is called to sacrifice it. He gives himself to God; is ready to do what is commanded. Another ottering is provided, and Abraham is blessed for his trust. Thus the whole history, so far as he individually is concerned, is the history of a man taught to know himself by knowing in whom he has to believe. He has nothing whatever to distinguish him from his kind: he learns that which he ha-i in common with all human beings : he learns the relations in which human beings stand to the world about them and to their Creator. 8 THE HEBEEWS. tion uf tkc" suc^ a history cannot be merely an individual one. cii isen That he may know what he is, Abraham is taught what it is to be fnmiiy. a master? a husband, a father. The discipline which has most to do with himself has to do with him in these characters. It is in his position as the head of a family, the founder of a race, that God speaks to him. Thus he is educated to feel his con¬ nection with the past and the future. Hebrew history isgrounded upon the belief that God made a covenant with the patriarchs and with their seed after them. They are circumcised: they are taught that they are separated and set apart by the Lord of all. The sign shows that what they are separated from is some¬ thing in themselves. Their own flesh is cut oif. The Hebrew has the same tendency to forget God as other men. Other men, again, are treated as subjects of Divine teaching as well as the chosen race. God speaks to Abimelech and to Pharaoh. The sign of the covenant itself is shared with the descendants of Ishmael. The patriarchs are shown to have all the evils of their neighbours, to have some which belong peculiarly to them from their sense of having peculiar privileges. Jacob is more deceitful and treacherous than Esau ; he who prizes his birth¬ right than he who despises it. The one tries to get the rights of an heir of the covenant by trick ; the other thinks nothing of that inheritance, but much of the loss of corn and wine which he believes are entailed upon it. Both are disappointed : the deceiver becomes a wanderer ; but in his wandering learns that God is with him, though he knew it not, and that there is a ladder between earth and heaven. He has put himself under a Divine education ; it does not leave him till it has punished him for his falsehood. The more frank and open-hearted hunter has his reward: he does not lose what he feared to lose; he misses only that which he never cared for. Joseph and 7. The rest of the book of Geuesis is in harmony with these ins brethren p0rti0ng 0f it. The heads of the Jewish nation, the circumcised sons of Jacob, commit the crimes which might be looked for in a set of wild shepherds and settlers. Their sins are especially family sins. The one who feels what it is to be in covenant with a righteous being is taught to understand his privilege by being an exile and a prisoner. He learns that God is with him, keeping him from evil, giving him wisdom. He believes that He cares for Pharaoh and Egypt, and is their Ruler and Teacher as well as his. He becomes an instructor to a king. But it is still with his family relations that the historian is chiefly occu¬ pied ; he cares more to tell how he behaved to his brethren, and was made known to them, than how he bought up the lands of the people of Egypt. The consciences and hearts of human beings have testified that he is right; that such records do concern us more, and are really more wonderful than the the hebeew histoeicax eooes. other: they belong to humanity, to morality : they set forth the family relations of human beings as the first stage of their.spi¬ ritual history; that out of which all the other stages must gra- dually develope themselves. 8. The book of Exodus exhibits the Jewish people still as aThefamiiy collection of families: they have multiplied in Egypt, are re- ^t?on!nff a garded as a dangerous body of aliens, are reduced into slavery. The book gives the history of their deliverance from this con¬ dition. God sees the affliction of the people, and hears their cry ; He remembers his covenant, and calls a man out of one of their tribes to be their deliverer. Egypt is presented to us as a nation abounding in wise men: they practise magic and sooth¬ saying : they are the advisers of the king. Moses is brought up in the court of the king, and is learned in this wisdom. "While he is still young, he feels for his countrymen, tries to deliver them, and smites an Egyptian. He becomes an exile in the land of Midian. There, as he is keeping his father-in-law's flock at the back of the desert, the Lord God speaks to him, and tells him that He is the God of Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob. But He makes known to Moses another name—" Say to the Israelites that the I Am hath sent thee to them." In this name he speaks to his countyymen; in this name he commands Pharaoh to let the people go. " The Lord God of the Hebrews" had sent him with that message. Pharaoh asks " Who is the Lord God ?" and increases the people's burdens. The river is smitten ; flies, lice, locusts attack the Egyptians; the magicians mimic the plagues. At last they and the people confess that a real hand is stretched out upon them. The first-born are destroyed. The slaves go out with a high hand. A memorial feast is appointed them, which they are to keep from generation to generation; a witness that the Lord was the protector of their households, and that He brought them out of the house of bondage. 9. In this stage of the history, the principles are evidently The new the same as in the first. The invisible Lord is still the great whatV00' speaker and actor in it. Men are recognised as in their right signified, state when they hear His voice and confess His acting. It is stiH the rule and not the exception that he should reveal himself. But the new revelation is evidently of a deeper kind than the former. The Egyptian priests and magicians had all kinds of thoughts and speculations about God; they had all plans of representing Him and propitiating Him. Hence superstitions, tricks, exaltation of men for their skill in these tricks, worship of the visible things in which they had discovered tokens of power, instruments of utility, causes of fear. The Lord of all comes forth declaring Himself as the true Being ; Himself the 10 TIIE HEBREWS. teacher of wisdom to man, the ruler of the things to which he is doing homage. He makes the power felt which lie is conti¬ nually exercising. The plagues were signal startling specimens of judgments which He had exhibited before, and would exhibit again in that laud. They are remarkable chiefly for this, that the reason of them is explained. Natural agents are shown to obey a moral law: a righteous Being sends them; they are to punish the oppressor, and deliver the oppressed. Hebrrw l(). On this foundation the polity of the Israelites stands, polity. name ()f (ioc[ js the ground of it: He is the deliverer of the people; He calls out the leader who guides them through the wilderness; He gives them bread each morning, and causes the water to flow from the rook for them. He goes before them by night and by day; He easts the horse and the rider into the deep. He is the judge between man and man, the Teacher of their judges, lie gives the law, He appoints the priest and the sacri¬ fice ; Ho orders the host, and goes with it to battle. He is the head of the tribes ; He appoints the bounds of their habitation. The commonest arrangements have their sanction from His name. He inspires the artificer with his power of doing cunning works; He himself dwells in the tabernacle, and meets the worshipper at the mercy-seat. , tnvniMied covenant of (rod is at the root of the national as it from the was of the family society. There was for the most part no Egyptian, novelty in the mere Jewish institutions. A law, a priesthood, sacrifices, temples, existed in Egypt. The Jew did not bring these social forms with him, he found them established in the land to which he and his countrymen went as a hand of shep¬ herds. They might have been cast aside as mere portions of an idolatrous system. In that ease, the Israelites would have re¬ tained a set of family or pastoral institutions after they had grown into the dimensions of a people; in other words, they would have become an Arab horde. Had Moses stolen the tpnet of the unity of Hod from the Egyptian sages, and pub¬ lished it to his countrymen as a witness that they were no longer a degraded caste, and that they might worship the one God of nature instead of the multitudinous gods of their oppressors, this would have been their fate. If, after taking this course, he had, in accommodation to their prejudices, pretended that he had a mission from an actual, living Being, who had authorized him to establish a system in all its essentials like the Egyptian, with a hard, lazy tenet of the Divine unity appended to it, he would have framed the most incongruous scheme of falsehood ever palmed upon the world ; his name ought to be held accursed as that of the wickedest of all liars and blasphemers. Before we pronounce that sentence upon him, we should hear his own ac- the hebrew historical books. li count of the matter. He does not boast that he proclaimed any tenet about the unity of (Sod at all. He says that the I Am, the living Hod, sent him to be the guide and deliverer of his coun¬ trymen. The Egyptians believed in a hidden god. He said that hidden Hod had come forth to declare himself. The Egyptians thought that he had delegated to a set of priests the power to interpret His mind. He said Hod was ever living and acting. The priest was the witness of his presence, and of His relation to men. The Egyptian held that sacrifices were the means of converting the Dh ine will to man's will. He said they were confessions of man's revolt from Hod's will, and could never be bribes to the Divine Being, who had himself appointed their kind and their amount. The Egyptian spoke of laws which were either irreversible or to be changed at the will of the monarch. He spoke of laws as the utterance of an unseen and eternal King, which no man could set aside, which were ever proceeding from the mouth of Hod himself, enforced by thunders and light¬ nings, declaring to each Israelite that he was in the presence of Hod, warning him of tendencies which were hateful in Hod's eyes, aud would destroy him. The Egyptian had statutes pro¬ vided for the particular emergencies of the land, which must be enforced by some religious machinery. The law of Moses assumes that the Lord of all, who does not think it beneath Him to care for the growth of trees and the fall of sparrows, directed the arrangements which were suitable to an agricultural people dwelling on the shores of the Mediterranean. The Egyptians had temples where they worshipped beings whom they con¬ ceived of from the different phenomena of Kafure in the places where these temples stood. Moses affirmed that Hod does not float in the air, or dwell in the hills, or in the clouds; but that there, where it pleased him to dwell, might His glory he felt, there might the worshipper converse with him. Whether this description of the polity be true or not, it is at least consistent. It does not set aside Egyptian institutions or Egyptian faith ; it justifies them by inverting them. They were grounded upon man's conceptions of Hod ; the Israelite's upon Hod's declaration of Himself to man. The one assumes the nation to be a society which must be upheld, which cau only be upheld, by Divine sanction,—which must, therefore, forge these sanctions; the other assumes the nation to be established by the living and true Hod himself, to he the witness of His truth and permanence, to be bound to a perpetual protest and war against every attempt to confound Him with visible objects. 12. This, according to the Hebrew economy, is the one great The office of characteristic function of the nation. It grows out of the the nation- family; it is grounded on the family covenant; it must preserve 12 TEE HEBREWS. the family distinctions; its lands must be apportioned to the different tribes ; its memorial feasts must be connected with the life of the household; in buttle every man must encamp by the standard of the bouse of his fathers. But the nation is not a mere collection of families. It is a witness of a perpetual battle that is point; on between order and disorder, right and wrong, the invisible God who is the Lord of man, and the visible things which are claiming lordship over him. The Israelite, the cove¬ nant servant of God, is to take part in this tight; he is to go forth as God's instrument in putting down corruption and op¬ pression. When he has a commission to destroy, he is to aestroy. He is to hold the sacrifice of individual life a cheap thing for the sake of asserting the right and the truth, which men have violated. Idolatry he looks upon as the cause of all strife and degradation. He is to hate it with a perfect hatred, natloaamfef 11 ew stage the life of the Israelites is the com- Son mencement of Song and of Written Law. The first is the ex¬ pression of thanksgiving for deliverance from the visible op¬ pressor. It proclaims the Lord as a deliverer and a man of war. It is poured forth by an individual man who feels that he is the member of a nation, and v ho becomes its spokesman. Though he speaks the praises of God, he feels that he is inspired by God. The flame of the song, like that of the sacrifice, has been first kindled by Him to whom it ascends. The Code. The Code is precisely the opposite of the Song. It comes from the lips of the Lord; it is simply His utterance. It carries with it no inspiration. It takes each man apart, and makes him feel that he alone is spoken to, though a crowd sur¬ rounds him. Yet it too comes forth from a Deliverer; it is the sign of a new and greatly-advanced stage of education. The discipline of experience has not passed away, but distinct formal precepts have been added to it. The memorial stones or pillars have given place to the written letter. The finger of God has permanently set down the decrees which his people are to keep, its They are decrees. The whole force of the code, as a code, authority, consists in its coming forth from Him who has a right to com¬ mand, who has given the sea its bounds, and has determined what man is to be. The right of the Lawgiver to say—So it shall be—is the foundation of every precept. But then it must be remembered that He who claims this right first revealed Himself to the Israelite as his Deliverer and Friend, as the enemy of oppression and wrong, as One who does not act from self-will. A law wanting in either of these conditions the Hebrew Scriptures teach us to consider a contradiction. If law is the creature of self-will, its meaning and its sanction perish in the very attempt to enforce it. For law to proceed from THE HEBREW HISTORICAL BOOKS. 13 those to whom it is addressed, is equally at variance with the idea of these books. They assume that there is a righteous Will in the universe, and that that Will can utter itself, and has uttered itself. But the code is addressed to the covenant people. It is The Code strictly national. How, then, have the Ten Commandments 11211003 ■ been felt to be the moral institute of the tribes of modern Europe, differing as they do in all external respects from the Jewish ? It is not too much anticipating a future part of this sketch, to say that this has only happened in so far as the in¬ habitants of modern Europe have felt themselves to belong to distinct nations, and have recognised the essential grounds of the Jewish polity, the covenant, calling, actual government of an unseen Lord, as applying to themselves in their national character. Not as members of a more extensive society, but precisely as united in particular local societies, have they felt the obligations and the virtue of this code. Anything which has weakened their national feeling, or absorbed it, has weakened the authority of the Ten Commandments. Hence the distinc¬ tion between these Commandments and the mere statutes of the Jewish people has strongly commended itself to the con¬ science of these nations, not because they have denied the latter to have a Divine origin, but because they have felt that the same Wisdom which adapted a certain class of commands to the peculiarities of one locality and age, must intend a different one for another. The Ten Commandments they have recognised as possessing nothing of this limitation. The distinction of positive and essentially moral commands, Distinction which some have sought to introduce into this subject, does not positive pre- therefore seem to concern us here. We may have many oeca- cepts. sions for noticing it hereafter, but into the question of a code it cannot enter. Every part of a Law must, ex vi termini, be positive ; that is, it must be laid down. But what is laid down may concern the inhabitants of a particular district as such, or may concern them as human beings. This is a distinction to the perception of which the subjects of the Jewish economy were especially awakened. To the Commandments which were spoken on Sinai there were added no more. All the subsequent legislation, though referred to the same Authority, is separated from these. All the subsequent history was a witness to the Jew that in the setting up of any god besides the Unseen Deli¬ verer, in the fancy that there could be any likeness of Him in heaven above, or in the earth beneath, or in the waters under the earth ; in the loss of awe for His Name; in the loss of the distinction between Work and Best as the ground of man's life, and as having its archetype in the Divine Being, and as 14 THE HEBEEW8. worked by Him into the tissue of the existence of His own people; in the loss of reverence for parents, for life, for marriage, for property, for character, and in the covetous feeling which is at the root of these evils—lay the sources of political disunion and crime, the loss of all personal dignity and manliness. Property. Property, it will he seen, was carefully guarded by this code. One of its provisions refers to this subject. It cannot be pre¬ tended that this law exists for the sake of protecting individual possession, though it may truly be affirmed that the reverence for property was a sign of this second stage of Jewish educa¬ tion. AVith the earlier tent life of the patriarchs it had com¬ paratively little to do. We see the commencement of it in the disputes between the herdsmen of Lot and Abraham in the arrangements about wells, in the purchase of burying-grounds. It comes out clearly in the assignment of portions to the sons of Jacob. But as yet there are within the limits of the chosen people no distinct rules to protect it. It is connected with the distinct protesting character of the nation itself, with the dis¬ tinct sense of individuality which was awakened in its members. T),e But mixed with the family and national institutions, was the universal hint of something more large than either family or nation. The the nation. Levite tribe was exempt from the ordinary regulations of pro¬ perty. It represented the whole people, and represented each family; while it bore witness that the relation in which the Israelites stood to the I Am, could not be satisfactorily expressed without breaking through the forms and limitations of a local commonwealth. In fact, all these institutions, while they taught Israelites to prize boundaries and land-marks, — while they strengthened their attachment to place and their reverence for it, were perpetually reminding every one who devoutly sub¬ mitted to them, and meditated on them, that he had that in him which did not belong to space or to time, to which only a Being above all such restraints could speak, which only the knowledge of such a Being could satisfy. The Jewish 14. AV hatever other characteristics this history may have, or u.Ku"n",i-d may want> no oue whl deny that it is a moral and metaphysical «\t] history, history, according to the definition which has already been given of those terms. ( It is moral, in that, from the first to last, it refers directly to man, to the habits, ways, constitution of the human race, as distinct from every other race, "fit is metaphy¬ sical, inasmuch as it asserts that man himself is distinct frum physical things; that though he has that in him which is under the law of growth and decay, he has that also which connects him with vvlit.it is ti\ h e.»r stant, pernrnvvt, with t> living per¬ sonal Being, vvno is above the laws of nature, and who Himself imposed them. THE TIEBREW HISTORICAL BOOKS. 15 15. But though a moral and metaphysical history, we have Ntf the admitted already that it is uo history of a philosophy, of thoughts philosophy about wisdom, or of a search after it. Another remark must be or"'.R made here. If this is no history of a Philosophy, it is also no history of a Religion, in the sense which we commonly give to that word. It is not the history of men's thoughts about God, or desires after God, or affections towards Him. Ifprofesses to be a~history of God's umeiling of Himself to man. If it is v ' not that it is nothing, it is false from beginning to end. To make it the history of the speculations of a certain tribe about God, we must deny the very root of any speculations which that tribe ever had, for this root is the belief that they could not think of Him, unless He had first thought of them; that they could not speak of Him, unless He were speaking to them. A class of modern teachers assume that God is made in the image of man, is formed after his conceptions; and then in¬ sist that a nation must have had this conviction, which acted and lived upon the opposite one. Let every people be allowed to speak its own word, to tell us what it means. We who think the Hebrews spoke a true word—meant the true tiling, only claim for them what we would claim for all,—the right of interpreting themselves. 16. "We have denied that the history of the Hebrews is the The reii- history of a religion or a philosophy. But we fully admit that of°thebu°k's there are Hebrew books which, in the ordinary sense of the Hebrews, word, are to be called religious, just as we contend that there are some which, in the ordinary sense of the word, are to be called philosophical. "When the Jewish Rabbinical schools assigned the name of " holy writings" to one part of these books, and of " histories" to another, they expressed their feel¬ ing that there are some of them which especially embody the aspirations of the human spirit after a Divine person, just as there are those w Inch set forth the acts of that Divine person towards men. The book of Psalms is the chief of the holy writings. The tendency in later times has been to give it this character too strictly and exclusively,—to overlook the historical The Psalms, and political features of the Psalms, which are so conspicuous to all plain readers, and to regard them simply as utterances of individual sorrow, or trust, or thankfulness, or rapture. By doing so, we destroy the meaning of the writer; we do not separate his religious feelings from their surrounding elements, but give them a new character altogether. The Psalmist is not a recluse brooding over his own feelings and experiences. He is *i n an 1< ..ruing, nu ler the heavy pr"-suiv el'litr. in tli 1 battle¬ field, on the judgment-seat, through the crueiiy of persccnti l1-, the fellow ship of outlaws, the rebellion of sons, his personal 16 THE HEBEEWS. transgressions, to know his own feebleness, the necessity of Divine succour, the mysterious relations in which he stands to the Lord and to his fellow-men. As a king, the Lord of all had revealed himself to the Israelites,—a king reigning from genera¬ tion to generation, in whose government lay the only freedom, safety, hope of his subjects. Great changes had taken place in the outward condition of the Israelite; he was no more merely under the invisible Lord who had spoken IIis laws upon Sinai. The unseen A king went forth in the sight of the Host as its leader; was ^sibicklng1; confessed to be the chief of the people's strength. The difficulty was to connect these two truths together ; to prevent the visible king from interfering with the homage which was due to the Invisible, to make him the witness of God, instead of a rival and a rebel. Saul had been made king, because the people dis¬ believed that God was an actual king. The whole of David's strange history, as a shepherd-boy, a hero, an exile, a king rul¬ ing, and a king deposed, reigning righteously, and fading into acts of rebellion and injustice, testified that the temporal sove¬ reign was nothing but the representative, an imperfect type of One whose throne was for ever and ever. The twofold convic¬ tion that the unseen kingdom is the ground of every other, that it is the true substantial kingdom, and that man is intended to be the image of God in his royalty, is implied in ad the utter¬ ances of the book of Psalms, gives them their strength, their unity, their variety, makes them as human as they are national. The inward Trust in God is the life-spring of every prayer and song, trust ba«U;UtWard ^ Kim as the Lord God of Israel, who will do what He has promised, who wid show the Jewish cading not to be a vain cading, who wid fully manifest Himself to men as their Ruler, and will prove the falsehood of all the attempts of men to make Him in their likeness, and the truth of His assertion, that He has made men in His likeness. It is a long fight between the true God and the false gods, the true image, and the false image ; the struggle is desperate in that land, in every land, in each man's heart. At times, ad hopes of a successful issue seem over; " the faithful fad from among the clnldren of men," false gods and false men have their own way. God seems to have left the world to lies, to misery, to atheism. But out of the depth of despair comes hope. The Lord shad arise, and man shad not always have the upper hand; He wid defend the cause of the poor and the fatherless, and see that those in necessity have right. Let the heathen rage, and the people imagine a vain thing as they wid, He wid set His king upon His holy hid of Zion, a king who shad reign as long as the sun and moon endureth, and who shad set peace and righteousness on the earth. Throughout these Psalms, ad those elements of Hebrew life TI1E HEBREW HISTORICAL BOOKS. 17 and revelation to wliicb we have referred, the feast, the law, the tribe, the tabernacle, the priests, the sacrifices, above all, the battle-field against idolatry, present themselves to lis in connec¬ tion with all the inmost thoughts and longings of the writers. But the ingenuity of modern criticism has discovered that some of these Psalms must he the work of men who had attained a higher degree of cultivation than was compatible with the reve¬ rence for the Mosaic institutions, or with the religious system which surrounded them. One who could introduce the Lord, The p-uims saying, " Thinkest thou that I will cat bull's flesh, or drink the blood of goats or when lamenting his crime, could say, " Thou desirest no sacrifice, else would I give it Thee, but thou de- lightest not in burnt offering," must, wc are told, have been impressed with convictions which the old and orthodox Hebrew would have regarded with horror. The conclusion of the 51st Psalm, " Build Thou the walls of Jerusalem, thenshalt Thou be pleased with burnt offering, and whole burnt ottering, then shall they offer young bullocks upon Thy altar," is consoquently set down as a priestly interpolation wholly inconsistent with the tenor of the prayer. If our previous remarks are true, there is no greater proof of the earnestness with which the Psalmist had meditated on the Mosaic institution of sacrifice, and on the dif¬ ference between his own country and all others, than these pas¬ sages. The very lesson which one who devoutly obeyed the Mosaic directions about sicrifice would have learnt from them, was precisely this, that they were expressions of the surrender of the heart to Him, from whom it had gone astray ; not "gifts by which the heart might hope to bring the Divine Lord to tolerate its wrung doings. It was a lesson which every humble and contrite man would have learnt, that sacrifices would be precious in God's eyes as witnesses of a reconciled spirit, of a restored nation. But we readily admit that there is a truth indicated in these rude attempts to destroy the unity of compo¬ sitions in which the consciences and hearts of all ages have recognized a correspondence with their own deepest feelings and intuitions. If the Mosaic economy were really part of a Divine education, it should be able to show how it has done its .vnrk it should be able to say, "the men who have been under this training arc not wbal they would have been w ithout it, those who have had the longest experience of it see the furthest, the children who keep this Law are wiser than their forefathers." The hook of Psalms, we readily admit, has that in it which dots not belong to the patriarchal or legal period of Jewish history. By claiming the privileges of the children of Abraham, by medi¬ tating on the Law night and day, by the divine discipline of tnil, and strife, and sorrow, which the records of their father- 18 THE HEBBEWS. explained to them, an insight and apprehension were cultivated in them, which could not have belonged to the earlier time. TVy- \in the Divine covenant and the Divine law. Without it we could not interpret the calling of Abraham and his family; still less the national faith and the national protest against idolatry. Even some of the most apparently external arrangements of the Mosaic institutions, such as the permission of certain meats and the denunciation of certain others, the seemingly arbitrary division of clean and unclean beasts, bad been cultivating in the mind of the Israelite the feeling that there was an upward and a downward path, to one of which he had a natural inclination, into the other of which a Divine hand was leading him. The author of the book of Proverbs does but draw out the sense and purpose of these ordinances, does but recognize an essential and eternal law as lying beneath them. The whole life of man he represents as being nothing else but an expression and exhi¬ bition of this conflict. Every act he commits is done in obedi¬ ence to one or other of the influences which is every moment acting upon him. Every act confirms him in obedience to one or the other. 7. But these words—influences, principles, powers, are they The sedncei adequate for our purpose ? We have spoken of the " harlot person Sense." Solomon, with far more practical truth as well as poetical power, speaks of her as " the strange woman." He can tolerate no abstraction. It is an actual enchantress which speaks to each unhappy youth. That which is the best indivi¬ dual language is also the best general language; there is no way of describing the temptations of the race but by describing the temptations of the particular heart. He does not arrive at a notion of what is human by heaping together a number of experiences ; in each one he finds that which belongs to all. 8. If that which seduces a man away from his proper state wisdom must be described personally, how is it with Wisdom't Is that porsona • merely an abstraction ? Is that not something to be embraced, possessed, loved ? Is that not a reality, not a person ? If not, how can its attractions be measured against those of the other ? Can we follow a dream, a shadow, as we do that which we feel and know to be substantial ? H' Sense comes before us as a woman, Wisdom, so Solomon takes for granted, can be nothing less fair, less attractive. To use the feminine pronoun in one case, and not in the other, would make the meaning false in both. Wisdom must have an intense loveliness, an intense cap- 22 THE HEBREWS. tivating power, to those who have once come within the circle of its influence ; and, of course, it would be contradicting the whole doctrine of the book to fancy that this loveliness was in any sense the creature of him who beholds it, and is enamoured of it. It offers itself to him, overcomes his reluctance, draws him after it. Instead of exalting his understanding into a creator, he is bidden above all things not to lean on it, not to trust to it. If he does, Wisdom disowns him ; he is a fool, wisdom 9. But what is this Wisdom ? The question has become a divine. more aucl more awful one at each step. Solomon had declared at the outset that he who does not begin with the fear of the Lord has no hope of attaining it. That fear must have been strongly in the mind of the writer, mixed with a strange bold¬ ness, when he proceeds gradually to see Wisdom, the counsellor of man as the counsellor of God, " by whom," here on earth, " kings reign and princes decree justice, but who was set up from everlasting, from the beginning, or ever the earth was." " When there were no depths," thus Wisdom speaks, " I was brought forth, when there no fountains, abounding with water, before the mountains were settled, before the hills was I brought forth ; when as yet He had not made the earth, nor the fields, nor the d highest part of the dust of the world. When He prepared the heavens I was there, when He set a compass upon the face of the deep, when He established the clouds above, when He strengthened the fountains of the deep, when He gave to the sea his decree that the waters should not pass His commandment, when he appointed the foundations of the earth, then was I by Him as one brought up with him, and I was daily his delight, rejoicing always before Him, rejoicing in the habitable parts of His earth, an. Ecclesiastes are in the truest sense human books, that they are essentially practical, and concern the life of every one. The intense suffering of Job makes it no doubt his first concern to find out whether there is a gracious and loving Being ruling THE PROVERBS, ECCLESTASTES, JOB. over the world or no, whether his misery is to be traced to such a source, or must come from somewhere else. In his agony he (^pours out words like the east wind; he seems at times to denjr the goodness of his Maker, he continually contradicts himself. His pious, well-instructed friends, have a set of authorized, beautiful, eloquent phrases to confute him with ; they can appeal to the judgment of their elders, to whom they are mere children; they are shocked at his irreverent expressions; they wonder that he is not afraid of affronting the Being who has laid him low and might raise him again. Job tells them that he lias heard a thousand such things, he has them all by heart. But God is actually smiting him. At such a time fine speeches arc of no avail. He must know what his anguish means. It is everything to him to believe in a righteous God, he has nothing to hope in, if that hope be taken from him ; therefore he cannot be content till he sees how He is righteous, how He can be so while he is afflicting him,—a man who feels and knows inwardly that he has tried to be right and to do right, and has clung and clings still to Him whose rod is laid so heavily upon him. So far this wonderful history would seem more fit to be its classed with the Psalms than with the Proverbs. But when Pbllos°Phy- God answers Job out of the whirlwind, it is especially with a view of His wisdom that He lays him prostrate. He had as¬ serted in his inmost heart, and generally "with his lips, the righteousness of God, he had justified Him as his three friends had not done, however they seemed to do it; but he had taken no measure of the wisdom of Him who had made Orion and the Pleiades in the heavens, and the horse to paw the valley, and the ostrich to lay her eggs and forget her young ones, and the leviathan to take his pastime in the great waters. He had thought he could judge of the means by which the All-wise would accomplish His righteous ends, why he appointed suffering for man, how He maintains the conflict with evil, how He will bring it to an issue. A revelation not of the power or sove- ^kof the reigntv, but of the infinite wisdom of God, was his humiliation; this was his cure. In dust and ashes he sees the Being of whom he has heard by the hearing of the ear, actually exercising His gracious and mysterious dominion. He abhors himself; then he is raised to a new and nobler life. At this point surely the book of Job asserts its right to a place with the books of Proverbs and Ecclesiastes, among these which set forth the search after wisdom; the methods by which it pleases God to guide a man in that search, and the reward of it. ( 26 ) SECTION III. the prophets. 1. The book of Job has sometimes been considered a history of the Jewish nation rather than of an individual. One cannot wonder that such an hypothesis should have been entertained by intelligent readers; or that it should have encountered a vehement resistance. The prosperity, misery, restoration of a nation, are surely to be read in that book. Tet one who has suffered will never be persuaded that he is not reading of his own struggles,—of struggles which have passed in the heart of an actual person. The Jewish prophets teach us to reconcile the two opinions. They feel in their own hearts the miseries of their nation, and of every nation. They enable us to feel that the experiences of the particular man and of the body politic are not different, but essentially the same. The Jew has to tight the battles of his country in his soul; his study of its present condition, its past history, its coming fortunes, is not something distinct from the experiences of his own life. He understands what he sees without, by what is passing within. He does not know himself except as he is an Israelite. The prophet 2. The writings of the prophets cannot be reckoned strictly philosopher, among the philosophical writings of the Hebrews. The prophet is not primarily and characteristically a seeker, but a preacher. He comes to denounce existing evils, and foretell evils which are approaching, as one who has received light and can impart it. Nevertheless,]'any view of Hebrew philosophy must be im¬ perfect which does not include him. Mixed with his announce¬ ments and denunciations, there are continual exhibitions of the speaker's own difficulties and confusions. If he has been brought into the sunshine, he has had a long preparation of darkness and twilight. His public teaching cau never be sepa¬ rated from the school in which he has been brought up, or from the Temple in which he has seen his most glorious visions. The 3. Every Hebrew teacher was a prophet. Moses, the guide orderCtiCa* anc^ lawgiver, claims that character. A Jew would scarcely have been justified in refusing it to Abraham. For it was far from necessary that the prophet should leave written records of his thoughts. He might even bear his testimony as the father of the nation did, by acts rather than words. Still there was The nation and the individual. the prophets. 27 evidently a time when the prophet became a more distinct, sub¬ stantial element of Hebrew society,—when the name began to be the designation of a class or Order. This time is fixed in the Sacred Kecord at the point of transition between the age of the Judges and the age of the Kings. It is connected with a general shaking in the most sacred of the Mosaic institutions. It is never hinted in the Scripture Books that the priest, because he had " holiness to the Lord" inscribed on his forehead, was less prone to evil than other men. The very first High-priest, the brother of Moses, was the leader and tool of the people in setting up an Egyptian idol. But now certain members of the priestly family became utter reprobates, and the High-priest did not restrain them. The people abhorred the offerings of the Lord. Then a boy, who was dedicated to the service of the Temple, as he slept in a chamber near it, heard a voice calling him. He thought it was the priest's voice; he found it was the Lord's. He was appointed to tell the priest of his sins, and of the approaching fall of his house. The Word of God had spoken to Samuel; he let none of his words fall. It was known that there was a prophet in Israel. The elders of the people believed that there was a charm in Samnei: his the tabernacle to save them from their enemies ; they took it office" with them to battle ; it fell into the hands of the Philistines. Samuel became a judge and a deliverer. He restored law and order to the people, defined boundaries, executed justice between man and man. His sons did not walk in his ways. The people craved a leader of their hosts : Samuel told them of the Invisible King who was in the midst of them. He anointed the visible king ; he testified to him of his self-will, and foretold his ruin. He anointed the man after God's own heart. ■4. Here we have clearly pointed out to us the essential quali- The ties of the prophetical office. Hence we may understand what gchooi!tlCal a school of the prophets was. The ground of their mission lay where Samuel's lay ; they were taught that the Word of God was speaking to them ; to heed this voice, to follow it in what¬ ever it enjoined. In the school they were trained to study the law of God, to meditate upon it, to consider the past history of their people, how God had dealt with their fathers, what the meaning of their calling as Israelites was. But this was just that they might know how He was dealing with them then. They were not less under His government and guidance than their fathers. They were not reading of the acts of One who had been, but of One who was then and would be evermore. The Living God was the only name by which they could speak of Him or think of Him. Their countrymen forgot Him ; they thought that He lived only in the past, not in the present. The 28 THE HEBREWS. whole economy of priesthood, sacrifices, tabernacle, had become a dead machinery, instead of the assurance of His permanent and continual presence. The prophet was to be trained in the belief of that presence, to act upon it, to live upon it, to tell priests and kings and people that their acts were lies, their whole lives lies, except while they recognised this as the ground of them. Jews 5. This was the true Jewish education. AVe have no reason partakers of t° suppose that prophets only were trained in these schools; this divine they might train their countrymen in them. And they could teaching. on^, ^rajn them in the same lore. They could but tell them, as they do tell them in all their written discourses, that though they may have no special call to be teachers or prophets, yet that the Word of God was speaking to them, was earning them against their evil tendencies, was guiding them to be right and true, and that they could only lead safe and honest lives by following this guidance. The false Oftentimes those who claimed the special office of prophet e ' were those who heeded this teaching least. And for this very reason : they did not look upon it as the teaching of a righteous, wise Being, to the whole nation. They valued themselves upon their special gifts ; they thought it was a wonderful thing to be able to speak words in God's name. They did not submit to be schooled before they poured forth their utterances; they never learnt to distinguish between the whispers and suggestions of the harlot Sense—of the vain, self-exalting spirit—and the lesson of Him who came to humble, and sift, and purify. Therefore these men became a set of traders in prophecy. They spoke a lie out of their own hearts, and said " The Lord hath saidnow making the heart of the righteous sad, now speaking peace when there was no peace; the base, selfish flatterers of kings, inventors of tricks, patrons of idolatry; the cunning or impudent deceivers of a people which loved to bo deceived. These men converted prophecy into divination: they made guesses as to coming events from what they saw, or caught up at second-hand the utterances of departed seers. It was nothing terrible with them to speak of the judgments of God, because they really did not believe in them or in Him. They were words which might be sported with to frighten their enemies or please their disciples,—words which came out of hollow, hypocritical, atheistical hearts, and which tended more than all others to make the people hollow, hypocritical, and atheistical. The true 7. Against these false brethren of their own order, more than prophet. even against the heartless priest, the godless king, did the true prophet testify by his words and his acts. It was no part of THE PROPHETS. 29 his vocation to pass himself off for something else than he was, —to hide from himself, or even from others, the conflicts which he had with the evil in him, the iliflieulty which he had to sepa¬ rate the precious from the vile, the reluctance with which he often obeyed the Divine voice. It was not in pride of spirit that he claimed Divine inspiration. His temptation was to deny it; to boast that he had something of his own; to pretend that he could be anything, or do anything, except as he was submitting to the government of One higher than himself. He is not a person v ho seeks credit for himself by declaring what is to come. It is with the present he is mainly busy. It is God as a present God that he is bringing in all ways—by signs, by discourses, by songs—before the consciences of the presump¬ tuous or cowardly king or prophet. It is God as a present God of whom he witnesses to the heart of the crushed and oppressed Israelite. The future is all contained in the past and the pre¬ sent. God is, and therefore He will manifest Himself. He reigns; and the unrighteous rulers, Jews or heathens, shall know that he reigns. Their want of faith shall not hinder the accomplishment of His purposes. Tyranny and disorder shall not always prevent men from knowing what His gracious domi¬ nion is. Kings who were set up to testify of His rule may utterly misunderstand their vocation, priests may forget Him and become idolaters, prophets may utter lies in His name, the whole people may misunderstand why it has been called out; but a perfect King shall reign in righteousness, the true Priest and Prophet of the World shall appear. There shall be myste¬ rious sufferings mixed with mysterious exaltation. At last God will confound all the false images of Him, and manifest His true image to man. Israel may go into captivity—may become the lowest of the nations, heathens may be God's ministers for punishing it; but the promise will still prove itself true,—in Abraham and in his seed shall all the families of the earth be blessed. 8. It would be the duty of an historian of Hebrew philosophy Relation of to notice these remarkable records, if it were only to show how entirely the popular teaching of the Hebrew corresponds with of Proverbs that which appears in the specially philosophical books; how [Jj VVor entirely esotericul that teaching is in the highest and best sense Prophets, of the word, when by esoterical we mean that which concerns the inner man,—his highest, moat mysterious relations; how entirely exotrrical, if by exoterical we mean that which is pro¬ claimed to all men,—that which concerns states and govern¬ ments, and the most outward circumstances of man's life. But it is especially necessary to point out how this popular teaching, connected as it was with the deepest personal meditation and 30 THE HEBEEWS. experience, fills up a gap in the merely philosophical teaching, and removes a difficulty which might otherwise cause us great confusion. We have seen that Wisdom, in the book of Proverbs, is spoken of as a person, but as a female. Everybody must feel that the passages which were quoted from that book would have been artistically less beautiful, less perfect, if this form of lan¬ guage had not been adopted. But artistical beauty in all cases rests upon some substantial ground of truth. We could not feel the propriety of such expressions if they did not correspond to something in our hearts which required them, and would suffer if others were substituted for them. Wisdom, when regarded primarily as an object of our search and love, even though it is intimated to us that we have been first sought for and loved, does come before us in this feminine shape. But the prophet who speaks in God's name says at once "The Word of God came to me, saying." We feel sure that he is under the same teaching with Solomon; that he means the same antagonist to^the harlot Sense, the same Divine Counsellor, the same per¬ son who was with the Lord as one brought up with Him before the earth was formed, or the heavens brought forth, and whose delights were with the sons of men. Yet we are sure that this is no female voice; it is He who speaks, who commands men and judges men, the Ruler and King of their inmost hearts and spirits. Of such an One the prophets are testifying in every speech of theirs. They could not believe in a human king, or priest, or, prophet; they could not believe that man was made in the image of God, if they did not acknowledge such an One. Because they do believe in Him they are confident that God will be completely declared to men, that His image will be seen in a man. That prospect carries us beyond the region of the Hebrew philosophy as we find it in the Proverbs; but it fur¬ nishes the complement to that philosophy. By reflecting upon it we shall perhaps understand better what that philosophy is, and what all philosophy is; wherein consists its deep, essential truth, and its necessary limitation. Transition 9. From the last remark our readers may gather that it is not Hebrew^to on^ ^or sake of Hebrew philosophy that we have noticed Gentile these prophets, especially this leading characteristic of them, philosophy, jq. -g imp0ssil)}e to read them simply and not to feel that they looked upon that Being who was speaking to them in their hearts as the real Lord of all men. In their comments upon the state of the world at the time in which they were living, they go far beyond the limits of Palestine. In proportion as they discover all heathen evils in their own countrymen, they discover, and rejoice in the discovery, that there is" a bond of spiritual connection between them and all people. It was im- THE PROPHETS. 31 possible for them to believe that there could be any government, or order, or desire of light or wisdom, in any human creatures, which did not proceed from the Source of order, and govern¬ ment, and light, and wisdom. Resistance to the Divine teach¬ ing they looked upon as the sin of their own land, and of all lands. Their hopes of future blessings to their own people, and to all people, rested upon the assurance that He who was then speaking secretly would be proclaimed openly. 10. In entering upon the philosophy of the other nations of Different the earth, we have the choice of four methods. It is more considering honest to state at the outset which we shall adopt, that our l!sical science borrowed from the Hebrews. 1. Three countries are especially connected with Jewish history—-Egypt, Phoenicia, Chaldfea. Each of these countries has left memorials of itself: those of the first are becoming even more interesting to this time than to any former time ; the last is only beginning to discover its treasures to European enter¬ prise. None of the three can be said in strictness to have pro¬ duced any philosophers ; but they have indirectly influenced the philosophy of other nations, in a manner too important to be overlooked. A few words on this subject seem a necessary sequel to the chapter on the Hebrews. 2. The wise men, magicians, or soothsayers, of whom we read in the book of Exodus, were no doubt students of nature. They had observed something of its powers and mysteries, some of the influences which it exercises over man, some of the means which he possesses of directing its influences to advantage or to mischief. There can be no doubt that they believed such know¬ ledge to have been communicated by some Divine power. We are not disposed to question their opinion. If they referred any observations which they might make respecting the course of the year, or the cultivation of the earth, to a celestial Teacher, they spoke, it seems to us, far more humbly, more truly, more in accordance with the spirit of the Hebrew books, than the Romanised Jew Josephus, who, in his foolish patriotism, or his desire to make his countrymen respectable in the eyes of their masters, pretends that Abraham, or Joseph, or Moses, instructed the Egyptians in astronomy. It is almost needless to say that no hint is given by the Hebrew legislator that his ancestors imparted any such wisdom, or possessed it; what he had himself must, if we believe the New Testament commentator upon his words, hu\e been received first from the Egyptians, though his Divine Teacher, purging his mind from the idolatries and confusions with which their physical doctrines were sur¬ rounded, enabled him to give man his true place in creation. The Hebrew history does assert that Joseph, iustrueted hv the Invisible King, communicated skill and foresight to Pharaoh. Acquaintance with the mechanical arts, and with all the powers of nature which are neecs&ary to the invention of them, it never claims for Jews—it implicitly concedes to their tyrants. EGYPTIANS, PHOENICIANS, ASSYBIANS. 33 3. Here we discover the main characteristic difference between Great the development of the two people. Modern science may be allowed to claim for Egypt a long series of dynasties, clear indi- wisdom; cations of an organised hierarchy, of a civil order, with very sj.n»jlrt'8Ults great and probably very early achievements in stone and masonry. But the moral philosopher must ask, why all these great powers bore so little fruit for the world ? How was their growth stunted and deformed ? Why is it that unbounded skill and research have to be expended after all these generations, only to prove that the oldest nation in the world had a substantive existence in it ? ■i. The answer to this question seems to ustobethis—if it be the cause of the wrong one, our inquiries respecting other nations will contradict deference it:—The Egyptian knowledge of the phenomena of the uni¬ verse, and of its powers, was not balanced and sustained by any knowledge of the powers and destinies of man. Those who became acquainted with the things about them, could not but feel that they, the observers, were in some way superior to that which they observed. It is clear that they had that conviction, that they were even oppressed by it. But the objects which they saw, the facts which were revealed to them, soon became all in all. They nearly lost themselves in the things; their higher culture only helped to make the people the helpless ser- Effect of vants of them. What he could tell of his discoveries, made his premature countrymen idolaters ; what he reserved, made him feel his dif- ance with ference from them, and led him to affect new airs of superiority, to devise new arts for the purpose of keeping up the difference man, and the sense of it. Thus the sagacious man from being a true observer, passed into a diviner ; thus he became the enslaver of those whom he should have emancipated, each new invention being, as it were, the creation of a new god. Such magicians are the great corrupters of kings, teaching them to rule by craft and not by righteousness, giving them animals for subjects, not human beings. The healthy, patriarchal faith of the Hebrew boy infused a new life into the mind of a Pharoah, taught him the difference between true judgment of the future, and cunning andon his conjectures respecting it, introduced another element into countrymtu Egyptian society, or rather made the elements that were already in it sound and coherent. But the government and the faith of the people ran again into their old rut; the soothsayers and magicians turned their physical knowledge to the service of false hood and tyranny; the Pharoahs built their treasure-cities to their own glory, by the help of Jews. Then came the vindica¬ tion of moral order, and the assertion of man as cared for by God, from the lips and the rod of Moses. 5. These indications respecting the Egyptian mind, from what- VOL. I. D 34 egyptians, pekeniclans, assyrians. The contra- ever period of its history we suppose them to have been taken, Egyptian* are a c^ue interpret the later as well as the earlier stages of I'fc- it. Why its forms of idolatry should have been so various, so dependent upon local position ; why its priests should seem to have possessed such stores of secret information, and why its people should have been so degraded; why Greeks should have listened to the teachers at Memphis with so much wonder, and yet should have felt so little sympathy with them ; why the forms of their sculpture should be so gross and animal, and yet should imply so much reflection, and should suggest bo many thoughts —may not be difficult to understand, if we patiently consider what must have been the effect of men being crushed and over¬ whelmed by natural images and impressions before they had for emanci- any bmer life with which to sustain them. And hence we may pation from understand what form the moral and metaphysical philosophy ' o atry. j)gyp^jan must ]iave taken, when he was stirred up to ask questions concerning himself, as well as concerning the things around him. To grope for a meaning in these things; to discover what relation there is between animal forms and study of man, what there is in their acts which shows forth and typifies symbols. kig acts; this was the slow, painful, upward process by which the Egyptian must have sought to disengage himself from the degrading objects to which he had submitted, and to emerge into clearness and freedom. In all such efforts, if we could have any clear record of tbem, we should be bound to take the greatest influence of interest, and to recognize the guidance of a Divine hand. Facts Ejfypt upon which are notorious give us a full right to believe that the Jevvs^and intellect of the Egyptian was especially exercised in discovering Christians, the symbols of JNature, in detecting the higher and human meanings which lay beneath them. In this way the atmosphere exercised an influence over both Jews and Greeks, which we shall have to consider hereafter; still more strikingly over some of the teachers of the Christian church. But these moral in¬ quiries had no power to leaven the polity of Egypt or to reach the heart of its people. They can only bave been the struggles of a set of sages to escape from the webs which sages had first spun for themselves and their land. The history of Hindoo philosophy will furnish us with more clearly-ascertained evi¬ dences of this kind of conflict. However certain we may be that it must have taken place in Egypt, we should have to resort to mere idle conjecture if we endeavoured to trace the course of it there. Phoenicia. 6. We are so much in the habit of connecting the idea of noMn'aself commerce with human progress, that it may seem strange we favourable have so little to report of the nation which had Tyre for its sopiiy!°* capital. The Phoenicians must no doubt have gathered many EGYPTIANS, PHG2NICIANS, ASSYRIANS. 35 observations together in the course of their long voyages ; but they were observations for others to reflect upon rather than themselves. Their own genius seems to have been exclusively active. However important an element in human life the love of variety, the eagerness for new objects, may be, there must something of silence and repose mingle with it before men can steadily ask themselves " What is wisdom ?" or can care for an answer. A Phoenician colony in Africa could produce a Hannibal; a contemplative sage could hardly be looked for either in the mother or daughter city. The temper of the Phoenician, however, joined with other more stable qualities to form the mind of the Greek. He was to prove that the sea, which is the symbol and witness to man of his freedom, does not merely tempt him to seek for the outward and visible trea¬ sures which so commonly enslave it. But before Phoenicia had added anything to the traditions or the studies of the West, it had been brought into contact with the Hebrew kingdom. It was not a Joseph—a fugitive shepherd-boy—who represented the Jewish life to Hiram and his successors. Solomon showed them that the divine polity which he administered, though it had its beginning in the tent life of the patriarchs, and seemed in its legal stage devised for tillers of the ground, could expand to meet and sustain the conditions and temptations ot a mer¬ cantile people ; because a deeper wisdom than that which earth or ocean supplies had laid the foundation of it, and was still upholding it. 7. In Chaldaea, as the Hebrew Scriptures present it to us, we Difference meet again with wise men such as we heard of in Egypt; but Smof" here they are especially spoken of as astrologers. The study Egypt and of the heavenly bodies prevailed no doubt among the priests of a aa' Thebes and Memphis: the first systematicobservationsrespecting the course of the year may be rightly ascribed to them. On this knowledge their claims to superior intellect respecting human events will in part have rested. Because they knew more of nature than others, they will have been able to divine what would probably happen to the fields or the crops. It is another step indicating a different order of thought and feeling to con¬ nect the stars directly with human life, and to believe that the course of the one is influenced or regulated by that of the other. 8. Wide plains, still and beautiful nights, are favourable to Astrology, the development of such a faith: perhaps only in such circum¬ stances has it ever taken deep root. For in such circumstances we meet with a hunting rather than an agricultural people, with ^e4ut a The priest who ascribes the method of the invocation, the "p-"erty"tal nature of the sacrifice, who presents the one or the other, is the leading man of the community. The orders and ranks of priests will evidently be defined first. By the offices which they perform all others will be measured. It is evident also that at this stage of Hindoo life, the objects of worship must have been various, determined by the influences which different powers in nature exert over man, the influences of these powers being defined and arranged by the priest. 4. But there is a feeling of communion between the wor- Charac- sbipper and the beings whom he is addressing, which distin- H^dou*0t guishes this Hindoo adoration from the mere physical idolatry worship. o6 HINDOO PHILOSOPHY. of the Egyptians. The Hindoo from the first seems to seek «u'h tife"1' friendship'with his divinities, nut merely help from them. And koiIs. presently we discover that the help which he seeks is not only in feeding his cattle, or subduing his enemies ; that the friend¬ ship of the wine-cup will not satisfy his notions of intercourse Search for with the Divinity. He invokes a Purifier, he desires purification purification. for himself. His ceremonies and sacrifices, though they may have other subordinate ends, seem gradually to point more and more to this end. The purifier. 5. As they do so, one Being gradually seems to dawn upon him, through the different objects which have been distracting his attention. The name Agni comes out more and more con¬ spicuously amidst the forms which the Yedas seek to propitiate. You feel that he is becoming the special object of Brahminical service, that very soon he may supplant all the other objects, and may be confessed as that Being which all the rest were bringing into light. Such a unity we believe is latent in these early books, strictly polytheistic as they are ; a unity, it will be perceived, which seems to be the result of the worshipper's experiments and discoveries; at all events, which reveals itself to him in the course of his thoughts and devotion, in strange contrast to all that variety which yet he is obliged to acknow¬ ledge as real, and which he had taught others as well as himself to look upon as divine. Jbotencai E-ere begins that distinction between the sacerdotal and belief. the popular faith of the Hindoos, which has often been attri- Grounds of buted to wilful imposture, which has no doubt been upheld by imposture, but which may have had a less culpable origin. The wish for purification implies the sense of something in ourselves which does not belong to this earth, which may be separated from it. As the man asks himself what this is, he discovers with wonder that the very effort of putting the question sug- Th»* wonder gests the answer. He thinks; thinks of all the things that are ot thinking. a^out him. Surely his thought makes him superior to them. If he can become a purely thinking being he is not any longer one of them. He has gained that which he wants. But who can make him such a thinking being ? The God whom he calls upon must be himself a being of this kind. He must be the thinker. He must be close to the thinking man, his patron, his friend, his fellow-worker. Where can the union with him stop ? Not till they become identical; not till the man actually sinks into the God, and is lost. , Braiim the 7. Accordingly, in the next stage of Hindooism, Agni has thinker. become Brahni. A priest-god has come out clearly before us. It is impossible to give him any other name. He is emphati¬ cally the God of the priest, as distinguished from other men. He is the priest himself, raised and transfigured. It THE PHILOSOPHY LATENT IN THE EELIGION. 39 is the great effort and privilege of the priest to be absorbed in him. 8. But has not the priest himself become changed during the The priest a process ? Is he any longer the director of invocations and Phll080PlH:r. orderer of sacrifices ? Has he not become the thinker, the intellectual man, whose business it is to use all those powers which the vulgar man has not, or has never cultivated ? The priest is the philosopher, the seeker after wisdom which is hidden irom other men. More than ever he must keep himself aloof from them, must distinguish himself from those who pursue the ordinary crafts and occupations of the world. He who merely acts, if he be the greatest of heroes or warriors, must be far beneath the thinker. The thinker must preserve sacred the privileges with which he has been endued; he must transmit them to an order of successors. 9. In such a scheme, what place is there for his old occupa- How he tion? What is to be the end of sacrifices and offerings, if justifies his thinking is to be the all in all ? There may be several answers office!'y to the question besides the vulgarest and wickedest of all (to which the Brahmin had a continual tendency), that such a religion is needful for the fool, but not for the wise man. 1st. By concentrating divinity in Brahm, the universe was not deprived of its sacredness. Every part of nature was a thought of Brahm's. The cow, the elephant, the flower, were all some ah things portions of him. There was no wrong then in paying homage i|JJ5 or to these ; it might be considered a part of the service of Brahm. Srahm. 2nd. There is something inexpressibly awful to a mind at all devout in that nearness in which it felt itself to Brahm, in the confusion between the worshipper and the object of his worship. Solemn invocations, habitual pronouncing of the name Om or Attempt to Light, services of purification, might surely not be undesirable distinguish to keep the priest-student in mind that he was calling upon worshipper some being, and was not merely adoring himself, or an image the thrown from himself. 3rd. If the storms and convulsions of nature showed that there were dark thoughts in Brahm, there might be need of sacrifice or propitiation to remove these, even Propitiation though the direct worship of dark beings might not yet have become a part of the mythology, or might be denounced by those who adhered to the purer conception of it. Still there were contradictions latent in the attempt to reconcile the philo¬ sophical and the sacerdotal position of the Brahmin, which were certain to make themselves evident in his subsequent history, and which were quite as likely to produce conflicts of opinion in his own schools as any popular resistance. 40 HINDOO PHILOSOPHY. TIIE PHILOSOPHY DEVELOPED—THE BHAGAVAD GITA. tijp 1. Another great problem, or series of problems, also of the nxstpai"]03' interest, occupied the Brahmin. Contemplation was the other the business of his tribe. Still something was to be done. He castes. ^.as jjjm3eif obliged to act; the other castes existed for the sake of action. How were action and contemplation related to each Contcmpia other ? In what way was the relation between the Brahmin and actum" the other tribes to be kept up if they had a different worship from him, if they were aiming at a wholly distinct object ? What circumstances forced this question upon the mind of the Hindoo, we have no means of ascertaining. That it did, at The some time or other, become a very substantive and practical Gita^avad Pai"f of his reflections, and gave a colour and shape to all his philosophy, we know from that remarkable poem (its unity and completeness entitle it to the name, though it is, in fact, only the episode of a much longer poem), the Bhagavad Gita. The its probable date of this production is still a subject of debate among scho- date' lars. The late accomplished Latin translator of it, A. W. Schlegel, unfortunately never completed his promised essay on the subject; but he has very clearly intimated his opinion, which seems to have been formed after much reflection on its poetical structure and spirit, as well as upon its language, that it has a right to take precedence of all the efforts of Greek speculation. A much earlier origin than this remark would imply has been claimed for it by Hindoos. We cannot deny that a much later one, which would make it subsequent to the Christian era, and within a moderate distance of the numerous commentaries which were written upon it in the twelfth or thirteenth centuries after Christ, has been imagined by some authorities. However strong our inclination, on general and abstract ground, in favour of Schlegel's opinion, it must, of course, yield at once to any strong external evidence. But even essence of*16 ^ question should be ultimately settled in that way which Brahmin- would exclude the Bhagavad Gita from the records of the old lsm' world, we should still feel that a document which is admitted to contain the very essence of Brahminical philosophy, and which sets forth, in a most lively manner, questions which must have agitated the Hindoo mind at all periods, cannot be an unfit subject for this sketch. We shall endeavour, therefore, to give an abstract of it, believing that it will lead our readers into the heart of the subject, and may save them from many pages of wearisome and unprofitable discourse. THE BUAGATAD GITA. 41 2. The scene opens on a field of battle. The Kooroos and Aijoon and the Pandoos, kindred tribes, are about to engage in a Kreeshna- deadly war. Aijoon is one of the heroes of the Pandoos ; he is standing in a chariot drawn by white horses. Near him is the divine Kreeshna, of whom at present we must only say that he is the mysterious counsellor of the prince. What his offices and nature are, he himself will tell us by and by. Arjoon is looking on with dismay and horror upon a battle, Aijoon in which there were uncles, tutors, cousins, sons, brothers, and PerPlexed- bosom friends on both sides. He thinks there can be no happiness for him hereafter if he should be the murderer of people of his own race. Such a crime is likely to destroy the virtue of the whole family or tribe ; hell is threatened by the Sankar both to those who fall and those who survive. The chief sits down in the chariot between the two armies, and casts away his bow and arrows. 3. This divine adviser reproves him for his weakness. It is Krishna's his duty to fight. "Tell me what I shall do," cries the young the soul? man. " I am confounded between two duties. I am overcome with the dread of sin. I see nothing to appease my grief, though I were to rule the earth or the hosts of heaven." Then Kreeshna instructs him in the nature of the soul. Arjoon may go to the fight, for the soul neither killeth nor is killed. Tou cannot say of it, it hath been, it is about to be, or is to be here- its eternity, after. It is a thing without birth ; it is ancient, constant, and eternal. As a man throweth away old garments and putteth on new, so the soul, having quitted its old mortal frames, entereth into others which are new. The weapon divideth it its migra- not, the fire burnetb it not, the water corrupteth it not, thetl0ns' wind drieth it not away. It is indivisible, inconsumable, incor¬ ruptible ; it is universal, permanent, immoveable. The former state of being is unknown; the middle state is evident; the future state is not to be discovered. The duty of thy tribe is to fight; a soldier of the Kshatree tribe has no higher. 4. The belief of the soul's immortality is thus connected with Reward and the practice of life. But is not that dread which Argoon had of punishment, the future consequences pf his action a reasonable one ? Kreeshna intimates to him that it is not. The people who held out that kind of notion of reward and punishment looked for transient enjoyment in heaven, not for eternal absorption. The Veds, which seem to encourage it, are adapted to men in a threefold condition. Turn to spiritual things, be firm in the indifference higher path, and you will be free from care and trouble about the future as well as the present. Consider the deed, and not the event: let not the motive for action be the hope of reward. Yet let not thy life be spent in inaction. Perform thy duty, 42 HINDOO PHILOSOPHY. abandon all thought of the consequence; seek an asylum in wisdom alone. Men who are endued with true wisdom are unmindful of good or evil in this world. They who have aban¬ doned all thought of the fruit which is produced from their actions are freed from the chains of birth, and go to the regions of eternal happiness. The wise 5. Aijoon wishes to know something more of the Moonee, or ma"- thoroughly wise man. Kreeshna answers, " The wisdom of that man is established, who, like the tortoise, can draw in all his members, and restrain them from their wonted purposes. The His tumultuous senses hurry away by force the heart even of him character. restrain them. The inspired man, trusting in Hj8 me, may quell them and be happy. Such a one walketh in the blessedness. night when all things go to rest; he sleepeth in the day, the time when all tilings wake. A man trusting in the Supreme, goeth not astray; at the hour of death he shall mix with the incorporeal nature of Brahm." How man is 6. The subject of the relation of action to thought still dis- led into evil, turbs Arjoon's mind, and gives occasion for another lecture from Kreeshna. In the course of it, Aijoon asks how man is led to commit offences ; it seems as if, contrary to his wishes, inclination. was compelled by some secret force. " It is the enemy, lust or passion," replies the teacher, " insatiable and full of sin, by which this world is covered as the flame by the smoke, as the sword by rust, or as the foetus by its membrane. This inveterate foe, in the shape of desire, raging like fire, and hard to be appeased, obscures the understanding of the wise man. This destroyer of Resolution, wisdom and knowledge must be subdued. It is possible; for though the organs are great, the mind is greater ; the Kesoluticn is greater than the mind, and there is One greater than that. When thou hast resolved what is superior to the resolution, and fixed thyself by thyself, then determine to abandon inclination or desire, thy great enemy." who is 7. There is a deep mystery in the last sentence. Who is resolution1'8 ^bat suPerior tbe resolution in man ? All the disci¬ pline seems to depend on this question. Kreeshna says that he taught it to one and another,in former days, that it was handed down to the Kajarshees, and lost. But how is this, asks Aijoon, when thou, Kreeshna, hast come later into life than some of those to whom thou hast imparted this secret ? " Both I and thou," answers Kreeshna, "have passed many births; mine are known to me, but thou knowest not of thine. Al¬ though I am not in my nature subject to birth or decay, yet as His past I have command over my own nature, I am made evident by my existence6.111 P°wer- When there is a decline of virtue in the world, I make myself manifest; I appear from age to age for the preservation THE BHAGAVAJ) GITA. 43 of the just, the destruction of the Tricked, and the re-establish- raent of virtue." Two kinds of worship are pointed out: those who acknowledge Kreeshna, do not when they quit their mortal frames enter into another, but enter into him. On the other hand, there are those who seek success for their works in this His life; they worship the Devatas (demons or angels). The true worahiiipen. Kreeshna worshipper sees rest in action, and action in rest; he performs all duties, yet he, as it were, does nothing; he seeks no reward—he is pleased with whatever he may by chance obtain ; he is freed from the bonds of action,—the same in pros¬ perity and adversity. God is attained by him who maketh God only the object of his works. There are various modes of worship, all purifying; but the worship of spiritual wisdom is far better than the worshipping with offerings of things. In Methods of wisdom is to be found every work. Seek this wisdom with Purificat,on- prostrations, with questions, and with attention ; then thou wilt not again fall into folly, thou wilt behold all nature in me. Although thou wert the greatest of offenders, thou shalt be able to cross the gulf of sin with the bark of wisdom. There is not The service anything to be compared in this world with wisdom and purity. ofwisdom- He who is perfected by practice, in due time findeth it in his own soul. He who has faith finds wisdom. The ignorant, and the man whose spirit is full of doubt, is lost. Those, continues Faith, the teacher, whose understandings are in the Deity, whose souls are in him, whose asylum is in him, are by wisdom purified from their offences, and go whence they shall never return. The learned behold him alike in the reverent Brahmin perfected in -n,,, Deit/ knowledge, in the ox, in the elephant, in the dog, and in him in visible who eateth of the flesh of dogs. Those whose minds are fixed th,n,r8' on this equality, gain eternity even in this world. 8. The next lecture on the subject of the exercises of the soul The Yosri or works out the same idea in a number of forms. To the Yogi, Perfectmun- or devout man, it is said gold, iron, and stones are the same; he is the same with those who love and those who hate, in the company of saints or sinners. He delighteth in his own soul; he is in God, and free from sin ; he believes in unity, and wor¬ ships me present in all things, and dwelleth in me altogether, even on this earth. In the course of this conversation, Aijoon asks, " Whither, O Kreeshna, doth the man go after death, who, What although he be endued with faith, hath not obtained perfection cb of in his devotion : because his unsubdued mind wandered from feet mac' the discipline, does he come to nothing ?" Kreeshna answers, "No man who hath done good goeth unto an evil place: a man whose devotions have been broken off by death, having enjoyed for many years the reward of his virtues in the region above, is at length born again in some holy family; he is endued with the 44 fHINDOO PHILOSOPHY. same degree of application that he held in his former body, and he begins again to labour for perfection." Kreeshna 9. But after all, who is Kreeshna ? The question has already essence ofd been awakened in Arjoon's mind : he has arrived at the stage of and theSS' when it may be answered. I, says the teacher, am principle of the creation and the dissolution of the whole universe. There destruction *s no^ any^hing greater than I; all things hang on me, even as ' precious gems upon a string; I am moisture in the water, light in the sun and moon, invocation in the Yeds, sound in the fir¬ mament, sweet-smelling savour in the earth, glory in the source of light. I am life in all things, and zeal in the zealous. I am the eternal seed of nature; I am the understanding of the wise, the glory of the proud, the strength of the strong; free from lust and anger. There is a supernatural influence which be¬ wilders the wicked, the foolish, and the low-minded, and hinders them from coming to me. I am not in these, though they pro¬ ceed from me. Many seek me, but the wise man is constantly engaged in my service; I esteem the wise man as myself, for his spirit dependeth upon me alone. Those who worship the Devatas go to them; those who worship me alone, go to me. The Divine The ignorant who are unacquainted with my supreme nature, umty' which is superior to all things, believe me, who am invisible, to exist in the visible forms in which they see me. I know all the beings that have been, that are, that shall be ; but there is not one amongst them that knoweth me. Those who trust in me know Brahm, the supreme and incorruptible; they know the emanations from which natural things are generated ; they know the destroying nature. In this body I am the teacher of wor¬ ship. He who thinks constantly of me will find me. He who finds me returns not again to mortal birth. The universe exists, dissolves, is reproduced; there is an incorruptible abode which is ray mansion. The supreme Being is obtained by him who worshippeth no other gods ; in him is included all nature. By him all things are spread abroad. I, continues Kreeshna. am Krecshnajn the sacrifice ; I am the worship, I am the spices, I am the fire, human I am the victim, I am the father and mother of this world ; I beings. am roa(t 0f the good, the comforter, the creator, the witness, the asylum, and the friend. They who serve other gods with a firm belief, in doing so involuntarily worship me. I am the same to all mankind. They who serve me in adoration are in me. If one whose ways are ever so evil serve me alone, he becometh of a virtuous spirit, and obtaineth eternal happiness. Even women, and the tribes of Yisya and Soodra, shall go the supreme journey if they take sanctuary with me; how much more my holy servants the Brahmins and the Rajarshees! Consider this world as a finite and joyless place, and serve me. T1IE BHAGAYAD GITA. 45 10. Arjoon begins to regard bis teacher with wonder and Ardour of adoration. He is taught that reason, knowledge, clear judg- tke ^"Pie. ment, patience, truth, humility, meekness, birth, death, fear, courage, zeal, renown, and infamy, all come from him. He is the soul which standeth in the bodies of all beings ; he is the £^eosu** chief of all warriors, floods, animals; the Himmalaya among Kreeshna. mountains, the Ganges among rivers; the science in science, the spring among seasons, gaming amongst frauds, the rod and policy among rulers. " Amongst the secret I am silence, amongst the wise I am wisdom." 11. All these are the forms of Kreeshna. Arjoon aspires to Kreeshna's ".ds of itself. He who has the Baja-goon forsakes the work because it c is painful; he who has the Tama-goon neglects action through folly and distraction of mind. So of Wisdom: the wisdom of the Satwa-goon sees one infinite principle in nature; the wisdom of the Baja-goon sees manifold principles prevailing in nature; the wisdom of the Tama-goon sees only self-interest in all things. So of Pleasure: the pleasure which a man enjoys from his labour, and wherein he finds the ends of his pains, that which in the beginning is as poison, and in the end is as the water of life, is of the Satwa-goon: this arises from the consent of the understanding. The pleasure which arises from the mere meet¬ ing of the organs with their objects, which in the beginning is as sweet as the water of life, and in the end is a poison, is of the Baja-goon. The pleasure, which in the beginning and end, tends to stupify the soul, is of the Tama-goon. There is not anything, Kreeshna declares, in heaven or earth which is free from the influence ot these three qualities. HINDOO PHILOSOPHY. Tbe tribes. 18. Upon these qualities depend the respective duties of the four tribes of Brahmin, Kshatree, Yisya, and Soodra. The natural duties of the Brahmin are peace, self-restraint, zeal, Their purity, patience, rectitude, learning, theology. The natural vocations. nuties °t the Kshatree are bravery, glory, rectitude, not to fly from the field, generosity, princely conduct. The natural duty of the Yisya is to cultivate the lands, tend the cattle, and buy and sell. The natural duty of the Soodra is servitude. A man Fif w°' contented ha3 own particular lot and duty obtaineth them. perfection; for ho offers his own works to that Being from whom the principles of all beings proceed. The duty of a man's own calling is far preferable to the duty of another, let it be ever so well pursued. A man's own calling, with all its faults, ought not to be forsaken. With thy heart place all thy works in me; by so doing thou shalt surmount every difficulty. But if through pride, thou wilt not listen to my words, thou wilt undoubtedly be lost. From a confidence in thyself, thou rnayest think thou wilt not fight. ' This is a fallacious determination, for the principles of thy nature will impel thee; thou wilt do that through necessity, which thou seekest through ignorance to avoid. 19. This conclusion, though perfectly in accordance with the commencement of the story, and giving it a unity, may seem inconsistent with what has been said of the special glory of the ufdweUerhe Brahniin. Kreeshna adds, "JEeswar resideth in the bosom ln w of every mortal being, revolving with his supernatural power the universal wheel of time. Take sanctuary with him upon all occasions, oh! offspring of Bahrat; by his divine pleasure thou shalt obtain supreme happiness, and an eternal abode." The leading 20. It would have been easy to select sentences from this theUeem°f Poem> an(^ fr°m a number of other Hindoo books, and out of epoem. construct a scheme of Hindoo philosophy. But such a scheme would not at all have represented the actual thoughts md conflicts in the minds of those to whom it would be attributed. We might form a high or a low notion of this remarkable people, or of their teachers; but we should know nothing of one or the other. The occasion of the poem, its scenery, the method in which the thoughts work themselves out, are at least as important for this purpose as the results to which Aijoon or Kreeshna, or the narrator of the story, arrives. The final moral, in which the Kshatree tribe is shown to have its own work and dignity, which are not incompatible with the superior glory of the Brahmin, evidently goes through the poem. To it all the dramatic interest, and all the speculations are linked. The darkness in Arjoon's mind arises from his TIIE BIT AG AVAD GITA. 49 fancying that the work which belongs to the priest also belongs to the warrior; or that there is no escape from this conclusion but in supposing that there is a different standard for each to recognise, a different object for each to pursue, a different God for each to adore. Such an opinion had, no doubt, been taught in the Brahminical schools, and seemed a natural inference from the idea of Brahminism. The author of the poem evidently felt how opposed it was to that which he regarded as pure Brahmin¬ ism ; how it must force the Brahmin himself to acknowledge a number of different objects, while his business was to search for uuity; how it must lead to a hopeless division of the castes, which should be bound together in obedience to that which was most refined and spiritual. Evidently, then, the book is the work of a reformer who wished to make the Brahminical tribe conscious of its own vocation, as the guide, and not the tyrant, of the rpst. In the effort for this object, he brings out the highest form of Hindooism,—a form of it which never had been nor could be realised, but by which we may understand its lower and vulgarer manifestations far better than by contemplating them alone. 21. The difference of this form from that which we find in the Veds, has led many to conclude that the poem is throughout implied in a protest, though a hidden one, against the scheme of beliefthe Poem- which is embodied in them. But there seems no sufficient rea¬ son to doubt that the author is sincere in the respect which he professes for them, and that he believed that he was drawing out the sense which was latent in them. Nor, perhaps, was he wholly wrong in that opinion. Though the writers of the Veds would have been absolutely unable to follow him in a single step of his philosophical speculations ; though there is no reason to doubt that they did mean to ask Indra, and the other gods whom they invoked, to come and drink with them,—yet their cries for communion and friendship with the gods, and for puri¬ fication, grounded as they are upon religious aspirations of the creature, not upon a revelation of the Creator, do contain im¬ plicitly those ideas which are developed in the Bhagavad Gita. In one respect the writer of the poem seems to return from the more exclusive Brahminism to the earlier teaching of the Vedas. Kreeshna, not Brahm, is his hero. Now it is true that Kreesbna ^Xilrabn is Brahm, and claims the name for himself: but he presents J' himself first to us in a human shape; he comes forth as the warrior, not merely as the thinker. This difference is involved in the whole conception of the poem. The sudden manifesta¬ tion of his spiritual and divine glory which overwhelms Arjoon, does not swallow up his human form, or hinder him from ap¬ pearing in it again. However great the difficulty, the Hindoo VOL. I. E 50 HINDOO PHILOSOPHY. philosopher perceives that, in Borae way or other, this union must be realised,—that there can be no sufficient teacher of man's spirit in whom both these conditions do not meet, ultfmatcthC ^eeP an(^ Bincere the acknowledgment of such a object of this teacher is, the soul of man is still the ultimate object in this piniosophy. poem, as much as in the more narrow, merely meditative reli¬ gion. In one and the other it is equally true that the soul or spiritual part of man is always unawares becoming the God, even while there is the strongest effort to escape from this iden¬ tification,—a really earnest struggle of the man to sink in awe, to confess One mightier than himself, to become nothing in his presence. What is his presence ? Where is it ? Here the Conse- Hindoo becomes lost; he sees images of himself everywhere— quenres. gure ^at there is something which is not the image of him¬ self. To discover what it is, is worth the toil and sorrow of a life; to know it must be the great reward hereafter. But while that difficult problem is solving itself,—while he is devising the means which are best for attaining the complete fruition,— Earth is going on with her processes of growth, decay, and destruction ; the man himself is born, has to live, fight, and die. There is nothing to connect himself or Nature with God, unless he worships himself or Nature, and makes the God comprehend both. This, consequently, is the result—the downward result— to which everything in Hindoo life and society always has been tending. Tiic Hebrew 23. The Hebrew was prohibited from connecting God with Hindoo. anything in heaven above, or in the earth beneath, or in the waters under the earth. He was taught to look up to the Lord as his God, the God of his fathers, the King of his land, the Creator of things, the Lawgiver of himself. He was taught to wage war with all the tendencies to worship natural gods, which he found in himself, which he saw in others. He was taught to acknowledge the Lord as the ever-present guide, and ruler, and teacher of his whole nation ; every Jew being in the covenant; priests, lawgivers, prophets, being God's ministers to them, between^°n "^s is what is called their narrow, exclusive faith. But out of them. it, as we have seen, there grew a philosophy, the recognition of a Divine teacher of man, of a wisdom which is to be the object of his search and love. The Hindoo starts from the discovery to which the Hebrew had been led by such a long and painful The contrast discipline. He is conscious of a mysterious Teacher near him, Un'im *" of one working upon his spirit, of one who is at the same time ruler over nature. But his search begins from himself, and, in spite of his conviction that it ought not to be so, it ends in him¬ self. The purification of his individual soul becomes practically the highest end be can pursue or conceive of; he must make it THE BHAGAVAD GITA. 51 his aim; he must separate from society, to which nevertheless he feels bound, that he may pursue it. The more he learns about himself, the more he discovers that he must get rid of himself; yet he is always pursued by that demon. To sink and be lost is his only hope,—to sink in Brahm. But is Brahm anything save a projection from himself ? To sink in him, does it mean the same as to be nothing ? 24. Reflections such as these, upon which the whole condition worth and of Hindoo society for thousands of years is the commentary, th^Hindoo might suggest some doubts to those who think that the acknow- philosophy ledgment of wisdom received is unfavourable to the search after j® "bgeliever it; that the soul of man is most likely to be free when it is Hebrew working out its freedom for itself, or under the guidance of a set of wise men. But we who do acknowledge the Hebrew principle, who have that vantage-ground for contemplating the history of the universe, are not obliged to rest in this merely negative conclusion. We are bound to look upon the whole course of human thought as directed by a wisdom above man's —by One who, as the Apostle speaks, " orders the times before appointed and the bounds of men's habitations, that they may seek Him, if haply they may feel after Him and find Him." To one holding this faith, the seekings of the Bhagavad Grita, and of the whole Hindoo world, must be of profoundest interest. He must perceive, indeed, that they were baffled continually ; Spirit in but he makes the discovery with sympathy, not exultation,— shouni'b® with the certainty that they were struggling with questions studied, which belong to him and to the whole universe ; to which he too has to seek an answer, and cannot rest till he finds one. And far from seeing only contradictions either in the method of the search or the result of it, he will have continually to be humbled by perceiving how much has been made known to these in¬ quirers ; what glimpses of light they have caught, what visions of good have cheered their dreary path, what strength has been given them for thought, for suffering, even at times for manly action. If he feels even a wish to deny or to explam away this fact, he will suspect himself of a secret atheism—of having studied the Hebrew books to no profit. 25. These remarks belong especially, but not exclusively, to its relation the subject we are now considering. Por modern inquiries have hjStoryaf,er made it clear that the Sanscrit is the source of most of the Euro¬ pean languages. We have, therefore, a right to expect that the habit of thought and feeling in the Sanscrit books may be traced, under different modifications, in the nations of which we shall have hereafter to speak. We may find, in fact, that these Hindoo books are the commencement of a course of inquiry which we shall have to trace in many windings through Greek 52 HINDOO PHILOSOPHY. and through modern philosophy. The spirit of man, which in the Hebrew books has been presented to us under a Divine discipline and education, will henceforth be seen asking a multi¬ tude of questions respecting itself, its destiny, its relations to the visible and invisible world, feeling after some object near it which might be its guide or helper in the search, losing that ob¬ ject again and again, questioning earth and h« aven to tell whither it is gone, how it may be recovered. Whether this Indo-Ger- manic course of inquiries ever meets at any point that Semitic teaching of which we have been hearing; whether the unity which is revealed to the Hebrew is to explain or contradict the unity which is sought for by the Brahmin, our future history may show. But in the meantime we may remark, that the problems which we shall meet with among Ionian, Eleatic, Pla¬ tonic philosophers, will be far less perplexing to us if we have lis¬ tened attentively to the dialogue between Arjoon and Kreeshna. SECTION III. THE PHILOSOPHEB SEPAEA.TING HIMSELF FBOM THE PBIEST. I. Any allusion to the formal schools of Hindoo philosophy will belong more properly to the second part of this sketch. But there is one great Eastern revolution, assigned by most authorities to the fifth or sixth century B.C., which stands in the closest connection with the history of philosophy. Indeed, the few glimpses which we possess concerning the external facts of a conflict that has led to the most surprising results, would be absolutely unintelligible to us if we were not helped by some previous knowledge of Hindoo speculations. Hi 2. The Buddhist is constantly spoken of in Hindoo books as htuo'o 'St ^ were the member of a philosophical sect. We know him as the professor of a religion which is received by nearly a third of the inhabitants of the globe. To reconcile two such opposite descriptions, we must recollect the remarks which have been made upon the apparently unsociable characters which are united in the Brahmin, and upon the nature of Brahm himself. The priest is the man who uses his soul or intellect, in distinc¬ tion from the mass of men, who use only their senses. Brahm is the Intellect or Buddha. That there should be a sect of Brahmins who dwelt upon the idea of an intelligence in man, till they began to suspect that their own pretension to an exclu¬ sive monopoly of it was, in fact, a denial of Brahm's presence, might easily have been conjectured: that these same persons should exalt the meditative part of religion above the sacrificial would be most likely from the specimen of the same feeling we have discovered in the Bhagavad (xita. But there was a period THE PtTEE PHILOSOPHY. 53 very memorable and critical, it would seem, in the history of The mankind generally, connected with the appearance of reformers fetation, and legislators in various countries, perhaps marking the com¬ mencement of European society and civilization, when Brahmin- ism was .shaken to its centre in Hindostan, and when the wor¬ ship of the One Intelligence was proclaimed aloud as incom¬ patible with the pretensions of an hereditary caste. 3. Not the original Hindoo doctrine, as some have affirmed, in plain contradiction both to the letter and spirit of the Veds, but certainly the idea which lay hid in that doctrine, and ever and anon had threatened to break loose from it, did now become the inspiring idea of whole countries. The philosophy, disen¬ tangling itself from the old faith, became itself a faith. Budd- The inw»rrt hism is the most surprising effort of the human intellect to Buddhismf assert its own supremacy of which there ever has been, or per¬ haps ever will be, any record. European sages in the last cen¬ tury, and in the present, have cried out, " When will philosophy break loose from the fetters which priests have imposed upon it ?" Philosophy in Asia performed that task two thousand years ago. It threw off a yoke which was become quite in¬ tolerable ; it affirmed that man's soul is capable of unlimited expansion; it claimed for that soul the homage due to a divi¬ nity : it made no mere idle boast of power; it actually won the allegiance of multitudes. 4. Is the result one on which the lover of wisdom, or of his Its different kind, can delight to dwell ? All possible forms in which the in- telleet can express its belief in itself and in its own powers have been discovered and tried. The Buddhist worships sometimes the pure, absolute unity; sometimes he sees a soul above his own soul, himself transfigured; sometimes he adores men who have done great works on earth, the one Buddha distributed in numerous Buddhas. Now he denies all symbols, now every its outward thing is symbolical. He is the purest of theists, he is the most c,othins- complete of atheists. He can conceive nothing too vast for human wisdom, he sees it all gathered up in an infant. He is always flying from himself, he can find nothing but images of himself. The philosophy which began by emancipating itself its final from religion has created for itself a religion,—one especially results- narrow, artificial, material. Those who would not be priests or have priests practise all priestly impostures, are slavishly priest- ridden. The adored intellect makes uo progress, the seeker after wisdom finds no resource but in identifying the search with the object, and confessing that he finds nothing. Can this be the process destined for the emancipation of mankind ? ( 54 ) CHAPTER IV. CHINESE PHILOSOPHY. sympathy of 1. Though we have said that the Buddhist revolution was an pcauptufo- effQrt philosophers to free themselves from the shackles of an sophers hereditary faith, we are quite aware that it is not to an experi- eiVhteenth nient of this kind that the teachers of the last century would Khout? fou1 ^ave *urne(l as an encouragement and an example to themselves. tseu"Dg °U" Mysticism, which belonged as much to the revolters from the Brahminical system as to that system itself, inspired them with nothing but contempt. But the Eastern world supplied them with another object, on which they could bestow the most fer¬ vent and unbounded admiration. They found in Khoung-fou- tseu all that they missed in these sages of India, with an entire absence of that which was offensive in them. They heard of a Reasons man who, six centuries B.C., considered the outward economy of justified it. an emP're a worthier object of study than all hidden and ab¬ stracted lore, who prized maxims of life and conduct more than all doctrines respecting the Divinity, who had actually anticipated some of the most modern propositions respecting the governor and the governed. This man they found was not a mere name for a set of opinions: he had a distinct, marked personality; and his words and acts had not been limited to a narrow circle, or to one or two centuries. He had left an impression of him¬ self upon the most populous empire in the world. After two thousand years his authority is still sacred among the people, the mandarins, the emperors of China; his influence is felt in every portion of that vast and complicated society. Chinese 2. Such a fact as this is worthy of all attention. Great as is anri^Aenf the contrast between China and Hindostan—though that con- expounded trast can hardly be expressed more accurately than by saying by him. that tn India all history is a philosophy, and that in China all philosophy is a history—yet it is equally true of each people that its search after wisdom is the only satisfactory key to the events which have befallen it. The difficulty of understanding the long line of dynasties which preceded the birth of Khoung- fou-tseu, though his words and acts compel us to believe in them, is a sufficient proof of this fact. "We confess the antiquity of the empire, because it is needful as an explanation of the reform which he worked in it. The old 3. This being the ease, we are excused from dwelling as much Suhmust uP°n the old faith of China as we were forced to do on that of be learnt iu India. This faith we are obliged to examine in a great measure sureTo™1* with the eyes of Khoung-fou-tseu: he collected and remodelled him. KHOUNG-FOTJ-TSEU. 55 the books which contain it. He may have omitted much which seemed to him immaterial for the education of his country, and yet which, to a modern critic, might be of great use. At the same time we are not disposed to question the general accuracy of the conception which this teacher formed of the old institu¬ tions and the old creed of his country. There are abundant roofs of the fidelity with which he studied them, of the earnest esire which he had to preserve them. No one aspired less to His dislike the reputation of an innovator; his main object was to remove tfon""0™' innovations: yet this desire was balanced by a profound re¬ verence for that which was established. Nothing was to be brought back for the mere purpose of bringing it back. Order was not to be sacrificed even for the hope of redressing an evil. 4. Khoung-fou-tseu could not have produced the effect which The Chinese he has produced upon the empire of China,—could not be ^mystical, recognised in the character in which he has been recognised for so many ages,—if his mind had not been the very highest type of the Chinese mind; that in which we may read what it was aiming at both before and after he appeared to enlighten it. We may therefore acquiesce without difficulty in the opinion, The ancient that the Chinese religion was from the first of a much less high (he and mysterious quality than that of almost any people upon the eternal, earth ; that the belief of the eternal as distinct from, and opposed to, the temporal, which we have found so characteristic of the Hindoo, existed very dimly and imperfectly in it, and was sup¬ plied only by a reverence for the past; that the sense of connexion or communion with any invisible powers, though not absent, must have been weak and slightly developed; that the emperor The emperor must have been regarded always as the highest utterer of the divine mind; that the priest must have been chiefly valued as a minister of the ceremonial of the court; that rites and ceremonies must have had a substantive value in this land independent of all significance, which they have scarcely ever possessed elsewhere; that there was united with this tendency one which to some may seem incompatible with it—an attachment to whatever is useful and practical; that the Chinese must have entertained a profound respect for family relationships; that the relationship The father of father and son, however, will have so overshadowed all the rest, that they will have been regarded merely as different forms Obedience of it, or as to be sacrificed for the sake of it; that implicit virtues'0 obedience to authority will have been the virtue which every institution existed to enforce, which was to be their only pre¬ server. If we suppose the reverence for the shades of ancestors, for the person of the emperor, for the dignity of the father, to have been joined with something of a Sabfean worship, with some The worship astrology and speculation about the future, we shall perhaps 56 CHINESE PHILOSOPHY- arrive at a tolerably near conception of China as it may have existed under the old emperors, to whom the sage continually refers with admiration and regret, v society 5. These were habits of mind which may have been represented customs."1 more or less perfectly in the characters of particular sovereigns, and which had embodied themselves in the forms of Chinese society. A tyrant might, of course, derange the whole economy of such a world. A state of things which rested merely on custom, and was upheld by observances, might quickly pass into utter confusion. " The dynasty of Yu," says the Book of Verses, " might be compared to the Most High while it retained the affection of th6 people : we learn by its decline how hard it is to preserve the command of heaven." These words must be illustrated hereafter: we quote them now merely to show where teeuUuef°U' starting-point of the Confucian philosophy. The wisdom reformer, at which it aims is that which shall be effectual for the removal of a decayed condition of society, and the restoration of the His wise principles that are implied in it. We hear almost as much of UaiVpoK- the studious or meditative man in the Chinese books as in the ticai. Brahminical. Quite as earnestly as the Brahmins, and perhaps much more honestly than they, Khoung-fou-tseu speaks of the superiority of thought and study to all animal pleasures, to the pursuit of wealth, to the possession of offices. Tet no one is less of a Moonee. He began as a man of affairs—a Chinese official. The affairs of the empire were his study all his life through: he trained his disciples to take part in them. Educa¬ tion lie looked upon as the one necessary means to good government; but all education was to be for the sake of govern¬ ment. To ascertain the ends of government, and the means of accomplishing those ends, was the one function of the sage. TheLim-yu: Before we come to the doctrines of Khoung-fou-tseu on Kimung-fou- this subject, and show how morals and metaphysics were eom- tseu. bined in his political science, we must try to give our readers some conception of the man himself. The third of the Chinese classical books, called the Lun-yu, or Philosophical Dialogues, is that which will be most helpful for this purpose. We have there the recorded sayings of the man, which bear far more internal evidence of genuineness than those which are commonly attributed to the founders of the Greek schools. We have also the testimonies of affectionate disciples respecting him, which, if they are not wholly to be trusted, at least give us different impressions of his character, out of which we may form one for ourselves. Fancied 7. M. Pauthier, the recent French translator of the classical between3"" books of China, to whom we are under the greatest obligations for bringing the treasures of the past within the reach of our KHOUNG-FOU-TSEU. 57 ignorance, and whose enthusiasm for his subject is a warrant, in Kt.oung-fou- addition to his general European reputation, that he has really socraies. vanquished the difficulties of it, has somewhat rashly suggested a comparison between the dialogues in the Lun-yu and those in which Socrates is the hero. He is candid enough to add, that the resemblance is chiefly to the sayings which Xenophon has attributed to his master, and that it is not easy to detect the artistical beauty and form of the Platonic dialogues in their Chinese counterpart. He even admits that there is a certain monotony in the utterances of Khoung-fou-tseu, though he adds, The^contrast " even this monotony has something of the serenity and the them"0 majesty of a moral instruction, which is bringing successively *xhi0bj't®'be under our eyes the different sides of human nature contemplated 0f tiie east from a higher ground." Though, for ourselves, we might beandwest- glad to exchange a little of this serenity and majesty for the hearty and humorous sympathy of the Greek with all that is passing around him, we are quite willing to accept it as a cha¬ racteristic of another order of genius belonging to the east rather than the west, and entitled to its own meed of respect. And it is scarcely just to Khoung-fou-tseu to speak of him simply as Modesty of looking down upon his fellow-men : there are indications in his deeds and words of fellow-feeling and real humbleness of mind. The dogma which attributes such qualities in all cases to men who have exercised a great influence over their kind, whether true or not, is certainly not contradicted in this instance. 8. That our readers may not be unacquainted with the form, such as it is, of this Chinese book, through our desire to cull choice sentences that fell from the lips of Khoung-fou-tseu, we will give the substance of one or two of the chapters which seem best to explain his character and manner of thinking:— " The philosopher said, I illustrate and comment upon the Love for the old books, but I do not compose new ones. I have faith in the pu8t' Ancients, I love them; I have the highest honour for our Lao- pang" [a sage of the Chang dynasty]. " The philosopher said, To meditate in silence and to recall to ideal of a one's memory the objects of one's meditations; to devote oneself grcat man' to study, and not to be discouraged; to instruct men, and not to suffer oneself to be cast down : how shall I attain to the pos¬ session of these virtues ?" " The philosopher said, Virtue is not cultivated; study is not Lamenta- pursned manfully ; if the principles of justice and equity are ^e"agevitr professed they are not followed; the wicked and the perverse will not be corrected: that is the cause of my sorrow." " The philosopher said, If a man does not make any effort to ^ec0{ develope his own mind, I shall not develope it for him ; il a man tiou. does not choose to make use of his faculty of speech (for the 58 CHINESE PHILOSOPHY. purpose of making himself intelligible), I shall not penetrate the sense of his expressions; if, after having enabled him to know one angle of a square, he does not discover the measure of the other three, I do not volunteer the demonstration" 44 The philosopher, interrupting Yeu-youan, said to him, If we are employed in public functions, then we fulfil our duty; if we are dismissed, we have the repose of a private life. You and I are the only persons who act thus." " Tseu-leu said, 4 If you were leading three bodies of troops of 12,500 men each, which of us would you take for a lieutenant ?' The philosopher answered, 4 The man who with his own hands would engage us in a combat with a tiger,—who, without any motive, would wish to ford a river,—who would throw away his life without reason and without remorse,—I certainly would not take for my lieutenant. I should want a man who would main¬ tain a steady vigilance in the direction of affairs, who is capable of forming plans and of executing them.' " " The philosopher said, To get riches in a fair way, I would mererespec- certainly engage in a low occupation if it was necessary ; if the tabihty. means were not fair, I wonld rather apply myself to that which I delight in." Love of " The philosopher being in the kingdom of Tshi, heard the music. music which is called Tehao: he was so affected by it, that, for three months, he did not know the taste of his food. He said, 4 I do not fancy that, since the composition of that music, that point of perfection has been once attained.' " How his " Yeo-yeou said, 4 Will our master help the Prince of Wei ?' founcUmt Tseu-koung said, 41 will question him upon that point.' He the mind of went into the apartment of the master, and said, 4 What think t eirmaster. yQu pe_» an^ Qjj0U.^gj j» q^e philosopher said, 4 These men were true sages of the old world.' He added, 4 Did not they experience any regrets ?' 4 No ; they sought to acquire the virtue of humanity, and they obtained that virtue ; why should they have had any regret ?' Tseu-koung went back and said, 4 Our master will not assist the Prince of Wei.' " The wise 44 The philosopher said, To feed upon a little rice, to drink independent water, to have nothing but one's bent arm to lean upon, is a ofextemaiB. state which has its own satisfaction. To get riches and honour by unfair means seems to me like a cloud driven along by the wind." 44 The philosopher said, If it was granted to me to add a number of years to my life, I would ask fifty to study the Y- king, that I might render myself free from great faults." Ye-hong questioned Tseu-leu about Khoung-fou-tseu. Tseu-leu did not answer him. 44 The philosopher said, Why have not you answered him ? Khoung is a man who in his eagerness to The philosopher an official when it is possible. Mere courage no virtue. Khoung'a account of himself. KHOUNG-FOtNTSETT. 59 acquire knowledge often forgets to take nourishment; who in the joy which he feels at having acquired it, forgets the pains which it has cost him; and who does not disturb himself at the approach of old age. Now you know about him." " The philosopher said, X was not born endowed with know¬ ledge ; I am a man who loved the ancients, and made all exertions to acquire their information." " The philosopher never spoke in his conversation either of he extraordinary things, or of civil troubles, or about spirits." avoided. 6 " The philosopher said, If three of us were travelling together, The two I should necessarily find two instructors; I should choose the teacbers- good man for imitation, and the bad man for correction." " The philosopher said, Heaven has planted virtue in me, what then can lloan-teu do to me ?" " Do you fancy, my disciples, that I have any doctrines that I No esoteri- conceal from you ? I have none. I have done nothing that I ral doctnne- have not communicated to you, O my disciples !" " The philosopher said, I cannot hope to see a holy man; all I can do is to see a wise one." [The exact difference of the two will be explained hereafter.] " The philosopher said, I cannot hope to see a man truly vir¬ tuous ; all I can do is to hope to see a man constant and settled in his views." " To want everything, and to act as if one had abundance of possessions; to be empty, and to show oneself full; to be little, and to show oneself great—is a part very difficult to support steadily." " The philosopher said, How is it that there are men who act Action must without knowing what they do ? I should not wish to behave of reflection, myself so." "We must hear the advice of many people, choose what is good in their counsels, and follow it: see much, and reflect ma¬ turely on what one has seen; that is the second step in know¬ ledge." "The inhabitants of Heou-hing were hard to teach; one of^*usivesof their young men had come to visit the disciples of the philosopher, his school They doubted whether they should receive him among them, reproved. The philosopher said, I have admitted him to come among us, I have not admitted him to go away. Whence comes this oppo¬ sition on your parts ? This man has purified himself, has renewed himself in order to enter my school. Praise him for having gone so far; I am not responsible for his past or future actions." " The philosopher said, Is humanity so far off from us ? I wish Humanity to possess humanity, and humanity comes to me." near t0 u8- " The judge of the kingdom of Tchin asked, if Tchou-king Observation understood the rites. ELhoung-fou-tseuanswered,He does under- Khoung'f: ignorance. 60 CHINESE PHILOSOPHY. stand the rites. Khoung-fou-tseu having withdrawn, the judge said to On-raaki, I have been told that a great man never yielded asaent to the faults of others; however, a great man has done it now. The prince has married with a woman of the family On, of the same name as his own, and he has called her Ou-meng- tsew. A prince ought to know rites and customs. He, why does not he know them? On-maki told the philosopher; who cried, "What a happy man Khoung-fou-tseu is 1 if he commits a fault, men are sure to know it." what a sage " The philosopher said, In literature I am not equal to other may oast men jf £ fchnjk of a man who unites holiness to the virtue of humanity, how could I dare to compare myself to bim ? All that I know is, that I force myself to practise these virtues, and to teach them to others, without being disheartened." Khounj?- " The philosopher being very sick, Tseu-leu besought him to devot on* Perm^ disciples to address prayers for him to the spirits aud on' the genii. The philosopher said, Is that the proper thing to do? Tseu-leu answered respectfully, It is the proper thing. It is said in the book called Leni, Address your prayers to the spirits and the genii above and below. The philosopher said, The prayer of Khoung-fou-tseu is constant." Disobedi- " The philosopher said, If a man is given to luxury he is not 6reatest of su^mi8S've* H he is too parsimonious, he is vile and abject, crimes. However, baseness is better than disobedience." The highest " The philosopher said, Tai-pe might be called sovereignly virtue.'6 °f virtuous. I know not how anything could be added to his virtue; thrice he refused the empire, and the people saw nothing admirable in his conduct." Howvirtues « The philosopher said, If deference and respect towards others chievous. are not regulated by rules or by education, they are mere grati¬ fications of our own fancy. If circumspection or vigilance are not regulated by education, they are only other names for extravagant cowardice. If manly courage is not regulated by education, it means only insubordination. If rectitude is not regulated by education, it brings the greatest confusion after it." What a ruler " The philosopher said, We may force the people to follow the canuot do precepts of justice and reason; we cannot force it to comprehend them." How a man " He said, He who has an unshaken faith in truth, and who iiAit1 course! loves study passionately, preserves the principles of virtue, which are the consequences of this faith and love, to his death." The Rood " If a state is governed by the principles of reason, poverty atate!VI' an^ misery are a cause of shame. If a state is not governed by the principles of reason, riches and honour are the subjects of shame." KnorxG-rou-TSEU. G1 " The philosopher said, I see no defect in Yu ; he was sober inequalities in eating and drinking, and devoutly pious towards the spirits £[aanfrcat and the genii. His ordinary clothing was poor and mean; but how beautiful and glorious his robes were at the ceremonies! He inhabited a humble dwelling; but he directed all his energies to the making of trenches and cutting canals for the conveyance of waters." 9. Some of these sentences, which follow each other nearly in the order we have given them, require illustration from other passages. In the last sentence Yu is commended for his devotion to the Apparent spirits and genii, yet Khoung-fou-tseu seems on his sick-bed tion in ' " scarcely to have acknowledged their existence, or at least to ggj have shown no faith in their power ot helping him. This faith apparent contradiction is perfectly intelligible, if we consider exi,lained- the third chapter of this book. " Some one having asked, what His feeling was the sense of the grand royal sacrifice, the philosopher said, I do not know. He who did know this sense would find every-1 n * thing under Heaven clear and manifest for him. He would find no more difficulty in knowing everything than in putting his finger in the palm of his hand." Again, " when the philo¬ sopher entered into the great temple, he informed himself minutely about everything there. One who observed him cried out, "Who will say now that the son of the man of Tsien knows His the rites and ceremonies ? see how carefully he has looked at the"" each thing. The philosopher hearing these words, answered, I prescribed do so in conformity with the rites." Again, " Tseu-kang order" wished to abolish the sacrifice of the sheep which was offered on the first day of the twelfth moon. The philosopher said, Tse, you are only engaged about the sacrifice of the sheep, I am only concerned about the ceremony." By reflecting on these passages, we may arrive at some judg¬ ment of the religious feelings of Khoung-fou-tseu generally. There appeared to him a mystery in the sacrifice which he could not penetrate; he was far from wishing to deny it, he would not for the world abolish the expression of it; but what it meant, he did not know, or probably seek to know. He valued General the sacrifice not for its own sake, not fur any benefit which he c01iclu6l0n- expected from it, but as part of an august and. awful ceremonial. He worshipped the spirits and the genii because it was the ancient law, the established custom: therein consisted their sacredness in his eyes; but be did not speak of them, he had nothing to tell respecting them. It must not be concluded from this statement that he pretended to a laitli, for the sake of the vulgar, which be see ret lj disowned, or that he looked upon 62 cnnrasE philosophy. the worship as a mere invention to maintain the government. His sincerity There are evidences of sincerity in his own conduct which negative the first supposition ; his demand for sincerity in ministers and emperors disproves the second. The following passage might seem even to set at naught all that we have said respecting the ritualism of Khoung-fou-tseu, and to prove that he did recognize a hidden ground for those ancient customs which he so diligently preserved. " Tseu-bia asked him the Not a mere meaning of these words in the Book of Verses: ' What an ayree- rituaiist. a^e smi(e there is upon his fine and delicate mouth ! how sweet and ravishing his look ! The ground of the picture must be pre¬ pared if you would paint? The philosopher answered, ' You cannot lay on the colours till you have made preparation for them.' ' You hint,' said Tseu-hia, ' that mere ritual laws are secondary things.' 1 You have caught my meaning,' answered the phdosopher; 1 you are beginning to understand my discourses on poetry.' " So, again, he speaks in terms of a hidden sense in the rites and ceremonies of the dynasty of Hai, which laws and the opinions of wise men did not suffice to make known. Forms the language leads us at once to the main principle of this most perfect eminent teacher. Ceremonies, formalities, etiquette, in one expression >vor(j so(qai customs, embody the principle of reason,—the very principle of secret of order among men. This principle of reason is the reason. divinest thing he knows of; traditional habits and forms are the most accurate expression of it. These are the great restraints upon mere self-will; adherence to them is the sign of the ruler who desires to be in sympathy with his people. The perception of what they signify is the great privilege and endowment of the wise man ; that which he is to communicate, so far as he can at least without any intentional reserve, to his disciples; that which it is the great business of education to impress upon End of the minds both of rulers and subjects. But, after all, this education. wjS(jom cannot be expressed very much better than in the forms themselves: it must be attained by observation, practice, habitual discipline; it must come out in conduct, in gestures, in looks, as much as in words; it must be uttered, so far as it is capable of utterance, in short maxims and somewhat enigmatical poetry; which will interpret themselves slowly to the person who com¬ bines an honest purpose, diligence, and political experience. In the same manner we must understand a phrase of very frtquent occurrence in the discourses of Ivhoung-fou-tseu, and yet which we are told, somewhat strangely,hv one of his disciples, that he did not often care to introduce. It is the word which our French guide renders, and we have every reason to suppose renders accurately, humanity. There are one or two passages in the Dialogues which show that this word had a sort of profound, KHOTJtfG-FOU-TSKU. 63 almost cabalistical significance in Khoung-fou-tseu's mind, which Humanity may account for the remark that he spoke rarely of it, though, in their reports, his disciples could not avoid frequently attri- Khoune- buting it to him. " Ming-wow-pe asked, ' if Tseu-lou was ^scourseV humane ?' The philosopher said, 4 I do not know.' Wlien the same question was repeated, the philosopher answered, ' If it was a question about commanding the military forces of a great kingdom, Tseu-lou would be capable of it; but I do not know what is his humanity.' ' And Kieou, what think you of him ?' 'Well, he might be the governor of a city with a thousand houses, or of a family with a hundred chariots: I do not know what is his humanity.' ' And Tchi, what of him r" The sage said, ' Tchi, in an official sash, and occupying a post at the court, a sacred might be capable, with his good elocution, of introducing and wor(1, handing out the guests: I do not know what is his humanity.'" We have already quoted passages from Khoung-fou-tseu which indicate his great love for music. The importance which he attached to it as an instrument of education and government is, perhaps, the one point in which it is possible to discover a resem¬ blance between him and Plato. New music he evidently con¬ nected very closely with the sublime virtue, or complex of vir¬ tues, which he calls humanity. Humanity imports therefore, Music: the we conceive, that order and harmony of relations in the body byjt*s#i he felt the necessity of connecting it with some duty. superior order, even if was but a natural order: he did not like to say what the emperor obeyed, yet he must feel, and even declare, that he, like till other men, nay because he was the lirst of men, lived by obedience. Here is the point in which the personal convictions of the teacher became identical with his political philosophy, of which it behoves us now to render a more exact account. Extracts 10. " Ngrai-Koung questioned Khoung-fou-tseu on the con- Tchoung stitutive principles of a good government. The philosopher said, Young. TJie ]aws 0f the kings Wen and AVou were consigned to bamboo tablets; if their ministers were living now their laws would be in vigour: their ministers have ceased to be, and their principles a of g< mi of good government are no longer followed. The combined vir- gnveminent. tuetJ anj qualities of the ministers ol a prince make the adinims- KHOTJNG-FOU-TSEU. 65 tration of a state good, as the virtue of the earth, uniting the Depends moist and the dry, gives forth and causes to grow the plants which cover its surface. This good administration resembles tion. the reeds which are on the borders of rivers: it springs up naturally on a soil that is suitable to it A prince who who can wishes to imitate the old administration of the kings must £^®f«™no<1 .... .. , . . i i min'sters. choose his ministers according to his own sentiments, which must be always inspired by the public good. That his senti¬ ments may always have the public good for their moving prin¬ ciple, he must conform himself to the great law of duty, and this great law of duty must be searched for in humanity, which is the principle of love for all men. This humanity is man him¬ self: regard for relations is the first duty of it. " The prince can never cease to correct himself and bring What IS himself to perfection. Having the purpose of correcting and nectary in perfecting himself, he cannot dispense with the rendering to his a pnnce' relations that which is due to them. Having the purpose of rendering to his relations that which is due to them, he cannot dispense with the acquaintance of wise men, that he may honour them, and that they may instruct him in his duties. Having the purpose of obtaining the acquaintance of wise men, he can¬ not dispense with the knowledge of heaven, nor with the law which directs in the practice of prescribed duties. " The most universal duties for the human race are five, and The five the man possesses three natural faculties for practising them. {{u™easn The five duties are: the relations which subsist between the prince and his ministers, the father and his children, the husband and his wife, the elder and younger brother, and those of friends among themselves. Conscience, which is the light of intelligence to distinguish good and evil; humanity, which is the equity of the heart; moral courage, which is the force of the soul,— these are the three grand and universal moral faculties of the man. " Whether nature is sufficient for the knowledge of these uni- Results versal duties, whether study is necessary to apprehend them, j^°pr®rta t whether the knowledge is arrived at with great difficulty or not than the" —when one has got the knowledge, the result is the same, ^"''in*' at Whether we practise these duties naturally and without effort, them. " whether we practise them for the sake of getting profit and per¬ sonal advantage from them—when we have succeeded in accom¬ plishing useful works, the result is the same. " He who loves study, or the application of his intelligence to practice the search of the law of duty, is very near to acquire moral r science. He who devotes all his efforts to practise his moral >V * ffe* duties is near that devotion to the happiness of man which is called humanity. He who knows how to blush for his weakness VOL. I. F 66 CHINESE PHILOSOPHY. in the practice of his duties is very near to acquire the force of mind necessary to their accomplishment. How to " So soon as the prince shall have well regulated and improved condltmn of himself, straightway the universal duties will be accomplished bieSaiid ^owar^8 h'ra- soon as he shall have learnt to revere wise enviable.' men, straightway he will have no longer any doubt about the principles of truth and falsehood, of good and evil; so soon as his parents shall be the objects of the affection which is due 1o them, straightway there will be no more discussions between his uncles, his elder brothers and his younger brothers ; so soon as he shall treat, as it becomes him, secondary functionaries and magistrates, the doctors and literary men will zealously acquit themselves of their duties in the seminaries; so soon as he shall love and treat the people as his son, the people will be drawn to imitate its superior ; so soon as he shall have drawn about him all the savans and the artists, his wealth w ill be advantageously spent; so soon as he shall entertain agreeably the men who come from a distance, straightway will men from the four ends of the empire flock in crowds into his state, to receive part in his benefits; so soon as he shall treat with kindness his great vassals, straightway he will be respected throughout the whole empire." AYe must not separate these political axioms from the follow¬ ing, which are more purely moral -.— Hi-.solution "All virtuous actions, all duties which have been resolved eminent of* beforehand, are thereby accomplished; if they are not resolved action. upon, they are thereby in a state of infraction. If we have de¬ termined beforehand the words which we must speak, we shall not hesitate. If we have determined beforehand our affairs and occupations in the world, they will thereby be easily accom¬ plished. Perfection. " The perfect, the true, disengaged from all mixture, is the law of heaven. The process of perfection, which consists in using all one's efforts to discover the celestial law, the true prin¬ ciple of the mandate of heaven,—this is the law of man. The The saint perfect man attains this law without help from without; he has and the sage. no need 0f meditation, or long reflection to obtain it; he arrives at it with calmness and tranquillity. This is the holv man. He who is continually tending towards perfection, who attaches himself strongly to the good, and fears to lose it, is the sage." riie leading 11. These extracts are taken from the second of the classical of'tiiis*16 books which bear the general title of " The Invariable in the philosophy. Mean." In the opinion of the Chinese, it contains the very essence of all philosophy—that which belongs to the great school, for which the first sehool—what may be called the school of custom or etiquette—is the vestibule. As we shall so often KHOUNG-FOU-TSEU. 67 have to deal with the doctrine of the mean or middle in the schools of the West, it is as well that we should ascertain, as nearly as we can, what anticipation there is of it in the passages we have quoted from the Tehoung-Young. Our readers wall not have failed to have been struck with the Fonu of ,ts. form in which the Confucian maxims evolve themselves. The prop<"rf,0,ls- sorites, says M. Pauthier, is clearly a Chinese invention. To The sorites, be a good emperor, you must be a good friend; to be a good friend, you must be a good son; to be a good son, you must know the law of right, &c. This is the mode in which the sage seems naturally and habitually to deliver himself. Each duty involves another. What is the first duty from The straight which all derive their sanction—the performance of which makes ,me- the performance of the others possible ? It is difficult to find : often we seem to be moving in a circle. But evidently all duties involve a rule. To be right is to be regular. Irregularity must be the common expression for the violation of all relations. But irregularity is clearly the effect of some bias determining us to one side or another. The law of rectitude, then, must be the law of the mean. All study and discipline must be for the The mean, preservation of this. " Before joy, satisfaction, anger, sorrow, have been produced in the soul [says our book], the state in which we are found is called the mean. When once they have been produced in the soul, and they have not transgressed cer¬ tain limits, the state in which we are is called harmonic. This 31 can is the grand foundation of the world. Harmony is tho The universal and permanent law of it. When the Mean and the suite!""'1 harmony have been carried to the point of perfection, heaven and earth are in a state of perfect tranquillity, and all beings receive their full development. Khoung-fou-tseu said, the man of superior virtue perseveres invariably in the mean ; the vulgar or unprincipled man is constautly in opposition to this invariable mean. Eew men are there, he cried at another time, who know Theie-saiui how to keep long in the right way. I know the reason: culti-the mon'" vated men pass beyond it,—ignorant men do not attain it; men of strong virtue go too far,—men of feeble virtue stop short." Here we have the very marrow of Chinese life, Chinese morals, The rim v-p Chinese politics. Hence we may explain that passion for belongs"!?.1 minute ceremony which seems to Western people so ridiculous ;ts nn.st and intolerable. Hence it arises that the most affectionate dis- philosophy, ciples of a man really so honest and simple as Khoung-fou-tseu was, should spend whole pages in informing us that if he had to Reports <>f salute persons who presented themselves to him either on the right or the left, his robe, behind and before, always fell straight Kiiounj.- and well-arranged ; that bis step was quickened when he intru- bliiavlour duced guests, and that he held his arms extended like the wings 68 CHINESE PHILOSOPHY. of a bird ; that when he entered under the gate of the palace he bent his body as if the gate had not been sufficiently high to let him pass; that in passing before the throne his countenance changed all at once, his step being grave and measured, as if he had fetters on, and his words being as embarrassed as his feet; that, taking his robe with his two hands, he ascended into the hall of the palace, his body bent, and holding his breath as if he had not dared to breathe; that his nightdress was always half as long again as his body; that he never ate meat which was not cut in straight lines; that if a meat had not the sauce which belonged to it, he never touched it;—with a thousand other particulars, of which these are fair specimens, and which we willingly omit lest we should diminish our readers' respect for a really remarkable man, when our intention is only to throw light upon the national character, and to show how entirely the philosophy of Khoung-fou-tseu grew out of it, and was deter¬ mined by it. That philosophy is not a mere collection of dry Worth of formalities ; it is based upon a large experience ; brings out the nhaosophy. idea of duty as it was never brought out in the West, till Greek idea of duty, philosophy was remoulded by the Latin mind. It suggests very deep thoughts respecting the connection of social and individual individual life ; it may help us as much by that which it fails to recognize, life. SOC'al as by that which it actually proclaims. But the blanks which are so significant to us have been filled up in China, as they could only be filled up, by new maxims, a more rigid ceremonial, an intense self-conceit and self-satisfaction. There have, indeed, Attempts to been other experiments to supply Khoung-fou-tseu's deficiencies, deficiencies ^ mystical rationalism and the Buddhist divinity have been both called in to help out the cold atheism of the authorized creed. But the true Confucian feels, and feels rightly, that these plants are not indigenous to the Chinese soil, and have no rightful affinity with it. He still clings to his classical books, learns them by heart, dwells on the rules of equity, the contempt of money, the reverence for antiquity which they enforce; shows by the contradictions of his acts and life what truth there is in its zreat these maxims, and what powerlessness ; how faithfully they I'ffecta. foretell the decline of a country in which they are not obeyed; how utterly unable they are to produce obedience. The philo¬ sophers of the last century had a right to point to the existence of China through so many centuries, with all its mechanical appliances, its early maturity, its political experience, and to say its variable- " See what can be effected by mere intelligence, content to dwell uesb. upon the earth, aspiring to no acquaintance with things divine." We accept their words and their example. Such intelligence could do this; so God has willed. Alas for human beings, if there is nothing which can do more ! MENQ-TSETT. 69 12. "We should do great injustice to China if we said nothing The fourth of the fourth of the classical books, which bears another name book!**' than that of the great teacher and reformer; of a man, however, who was a teacher and reformer, who considered Khoung-fou- tseu the great legislator of the world, and laboured in a society which had become again degenerated to restore his precepts and his practice. Meng-tseu belongs to the fourth century B.C. He Meng-tseu. is immeasurably more interesting to us than his predecessor, and therefore we should suppose must seem far inferior to him in Chinese eyes. Inferior he probably was, inferior in quietness and self-control, and in perfect adaptation to the habits of the people with whom he conversed. We can quite imagine that he never would have been a great legislator, or have left any great impression upon the mind of his country, if Khoung-fou-tseu had not led the way. But in place of the solemnity and general Not 6° dryness of his master, there appears to have been in Meng-tseu Chinese^ real humour, a very earnest dislike of oppression, a courage in telling disagreeable truths to the highest personages, and a power of perceiving the practical application of sound maxims to But much the details of government, which cannot be contemplated without ™?erestin* admiration and profit after a lapse of 2,000 years. We have to us. tempted our readers to imitate the worst habits of the Chinese, if we have led them to think scornfully of eastern wisdom, or to suppose that it has no lessons for England in the nineteenth century. Let us repair our error, by asking them to listen to a conversation of Meng-tseu with Siouan-Wang the king of Tshi. The king interrogated Meng-tseu in these terms: " I have been When the told that the park of the king Wen-Wang was seven leagues in complain of circumference ; was that the case ?" Meng-tseu answered re- r°y»' Par^ speetfully, " History tells us so." The king said, " If so, was not smaiL1"" its extent excessive ?" Meng-tseu answered, " The people con¬ sidered it too small." The king said, " My insignificance has a park only four leagues in circumference, and the people consider for it too large ; whence this difference ?" Meng-tseu answered, being too "The park of Wen-Wang contained all these leagues, butlarge' thither resorted all persons who wanted to cut grass or wood. Thither went all who wanted to take pheasants and hares. As the king had his park in common with the people, the people thought it small, though it was seven leagues round. Was that wonderful P I, your servant, when I was about to cross the frontier, took care to inform myself of what was especially for¬ bidden in your kingdom, before I dared to venture further. Your servant learnt that there was within your line of customs a park four leagues round, and that the man who killed a stag there, was punished with death, as if he had killed a man. So that there is an actual pit of death of four leagues in circum- 70 CniNESE PHILOSOPHY. ference, opened in the heart of your kingdom. The people think that park too great. Is it wonderful?" From a very long conversation with the same prince, all of which well deserves to be extracted, we take a passage which is not so illustrative of the talent of Meng-tseu as many others; but it will at least prove that his philosophy is not obsolete. " To want things necessary for life, and yet to preserve an equal and virtuous mind, is only possible for men whose intelligence raises them above the multitude. The mass of the people, when it wants the necessaries of life, wants also an equal and virtuous mind. Then follow violation of law, licence, and debauchery; there is nothing which it is not capable of doing. Then you bring them before judgment-seats, then you punish them. So you catch the people in a net. If there was a man truly endowed with the virtue of humanity occupying the throne, could he com¬ mit this criminal action of catching the people in such a snare ? Condition of " At present, the constitution of the private property of the davsot"the People i-"5 such, that the children have not wherewith to minister Menu-tieu. to their fathers and mothers ; the fathers have not wherewith to support their wives i nd their children. In years of abundance, the people suffer to the end of life pain and misery; in years of calamity they are not preserved from famine and death. In such extremities, the people think only of escaping from death. What time can they have to occupy themselves with the moral doctrines which may teach them how to conduct themselves according to the laws of justice and equity ?" Meng-tseu proceeds to sug¬ gest remedies: improved cultivation of the land, plantation of trees, rearing of animals, the manufacture of silk—above all, education. sympathy of One of his great maxims is, that the monarch should always aud people 8^are pleasures with his people. " If a prince rejoices in the joy of his people, the people rejoice also in his joy. If a prince sorrows in the sorrows of his people, the people also sorrow in his sorrow. Let a prince rejoice with everybody, let him sorrow with everybody; in so doing it is impossible he can iind any difficulty in reigning." The same monarch, in another conversation with Meng-tseu, expressed great admiration for two lines in the Book of Verses: " We may be rich and powerful, but we should have compassion on the widows and orphans." Meng-tseu answered, rather abruptly, " Oh, king ! if you find them so good, why do you not practise them ?" The king answered, " My insignificance has a defect; my insignificance loves riches." Meng-tseu answered respectfully, " Kong-lieou loved riches also, so he shared them with his people that he might gratify his love. If you love them, try the same plan." The king said, " My insignificance Crimes of the pour: lion connected nith their poverty. How to gratify a taste tor riches MENG-TSEU. 71 has another weakness; my insignificance loves pleasure." and for Meng-tseu answered, with respect, " Tai-wang loved pleasure ; P,ttt-ure- he loved his wife dearly, so he contrived that in all his kingdom there should be no celibats." The following is still more pointed : it is a conversation with What an. the same patient prince. " Suppose a servant of the king trusts toXwh" a friend with his wife and children, just as he is about to set out hifi for a journey: if, on his return, he finds that his wife and chil- provinces, dren have suffered cold and hunger, what must he do ?" The king: " He must break with his friend." Meng-tseu went on : " If the chief judge cannot govern the magistrates who are under him, what must be done with him ?" The king: " He must be deposed." Meng-tseu : " If the provinces situated at the ex¬ treme limits of the kingdom are not well governed, what must be done ?" The king looked to the right and left, and turned the conversation. Meng-tseu said, " The great man has three The satisfactions : to have his father and mother still living, without "he^'ise" °f any cause of dissatisfaction or dissension between the elder and ina11* the younger brother, is the first; to have nothing to blush for in the face of heaven or of man, is the second; to meet wise and virtuous men among those of his generation, is the third. These are the three causes of satisfaction to a wise man. To rule an empire is not included among them." " When the prince of Lou desired that Lo-tcbing-tseu, a dis- Hearty )o\f ciple of Meng-tseu, should undertake the whole administration of a""*1 a of the kingdom, Meng-tseu said, ' Since I have heard that news, tkm'for^ic I cannot sleep for joy.' Some one asked, ' What, has he a great deal of energy ?' Meng-tseu said ' Not at all.' ' Has he prudence, and a mind that is apt to form great designs ?' 'Not at all.' ' Has he studied much, and has be very extensive know¬ ledge ?' ' Not at all.' If so, why do you lie awake for joy at his promotion ?' ' Because he is a man who loves what is good.' * Is that enough ?' ' Yes ; to love what is good is more than enough to govern the empire: how much more to govern the kingdom of Lou! If one who is proposed for the administration of a state loves what is good, the good men who inhabit within the four seas will think nothing of travelling one hundred leagues to come and give hiin good counsel. But if he loves not what is good, these men will say within themselves, He is a self- satisfied man, who always answers, " I knew that a long while ago." That tone and air will drive good counsellors one hun¬ dred leagues from him. If they go, then the slanderers, the flatterers, the people whose countenances say " Yes" to every word he speaks, will arrive in crowds. t Li such company, if he wishes to govern well, how can he ?' " 72 CHINESE PHILOSOPHY. SnffVrinjr The following is in a yet higher strain. " Chun came to the which^rea" empire from the midst of the fields ; Fou-youe was raised to the tramed'b ran^ minister from a mason; Kiao-he was raised from a seller Heaven. 7 of fish and of salt; Kouan-i-ou became a minister from a gaoler. Thus it is when heaven wishes to confer a great office upon its chosen men, it begins always by proving their souls and their intellects by days of sorrow ; their nerves and their bones are worn out by hard toil, their flesh is tormented with hunger. The results of their actions are always contrary to those which they hope to obtain. Thus their souls are stimulated, their natures hardened, their force augmented by an energy, without which they would have been unable to accomplish their high destiny. Men begin by committing faults, before they can cor¬ rect themselves. They experience anguish of heart, are hin¬ dered in their projects, till at last they come forth. It is uni¬ versally true that life comes through pains and trials, death through pleasures and repose." The We cannot help thinking that Khoung-feu-tseu himself comes pwpie'of a in a somewhat braver and fine spirit in the reports and village: commentaries of Meng-tseu. For instance, he quotes him as saying " that the most honest men of a neighbourhood are the pests of virtue." " Who are these men ?" asked Wen-tchang. what they "Those," said Mengtseu, " who take pains never to speak or »re- act otherwise than all around them. If you wish to find them in a fault, you never know where to take them. Whatever side you attack them, you never get at them. That which dwells in their heart has a certain resemblance to rectitude and sincerity ; what they practise seem like acts of temperance and of integrity. As all their neighbourhood boasts of them incessantly, they fancy themselves perfect people. Therefore Khoung-fou-tseu why calls them the pests of virtue. ' I detest,' says Khuung-fou- tou-tseu tseu, ' that which has appearance without reality; I detest hated them, clever men, for fear that they shall confound justice ; I detest an eloquent mouth, fearing lest it should confuse truth ; I detest the sounds of the music Tching, because they corrupt music ; I detest the colour of violet because it mimics the colour of purple; I detest the most respectable people of a neighbour¬ hood because they mimic virtue.' " Meng-tseu's 13. Meng-tseu, it will be perceived, in spite of this last tendeiiciesf1 extract, has a much more democratic tendency than his master. He is even reported to have said, "The people is the most noble thing in the world. The spirits of the earth and the fruits of the earth are second to them. The prince is of the least importance of all." Such a sentiment as this, found in a book which all Chinese men of education learn by heart, found MENG-TSEU. 73 side by side with precepts which seem to represent the emperor as the source of all light and wisdom to his people, must needs give rise to great perplexities in the more thoughtful members of the Celestial Empire, especially in those who are necessarily brought into contact with the notions and history of barbarians. The effects of such teaching may be much greater than we can foresee. Certainly one cannot expect that they will be favourable to the real freedom and moral culture of this singular people. The deepest wisdom both of Khoung-fou-tseu and Meng-tseu seems to have consisted in awaking monarchs to a consciousness of their position and their duties; their greatest failures to have arisen from their inability to show what higher and more righteous power sustains them in that position, and can give them energy for the discharge of these duties. Whatever teaching can supply that defect may be the instrument of making China what God intends it to be. A subversion of its political order must be also the subversion of its ancient wisdom, without giving it any capacity for the acquisition of fresh light. CHAPTER Y. PERSIAN PHILOSOPHY. 1. The biography of Khoung-fou-tseu is as clear, accurate, and formal as that of a man who lived a century ago. The bio¬ graphy of Zerduscht, who occupies the corresponding place in zerduscht, the annals of Persian philosophy, is altogether confused and £i8 mythical. It is hardly possible to compose any orderly history out of the wild legends of his birth, his adventures, and his reformation. The most intelligent modern critics have given up the task. They doubt whether such a man ever existed ; they think that he represents an epoch, or a great struggle of opposing principles,—that different persons who illustrated that epoch, or engaged in that struggle, may have been blended under one name, and that the traditionary history may have as much or as little to do with one as with another of them. 2. If we were forced to acquiesce in this conclusion, to what His age. period will this imaginary hero belong ? It is difficult not to connect him with that general movement of the Asiatic mind to which we have already alluded in this sketch. The Buddhist convulsion in Hindostan, the great Chinese reformation, and the movement in Iran or Persia, of which we are now to speak, if not strictly contemporaneous events, may not have been sepa- 74 PEHSIAN PHILOSOPHY. What was rated by the distance of more than a century. That there was th'"different something common in them all will easily be admitted. The oriental Indian, the Chinese, the Persian reformers, alike believed lions"10* that they were bringing back some old order or principle, which had been forgotten or violated, or for which some modern prac¬ tices and notions had been substituted. Neither the Buddhist nor the disciple of Zerduscht would have allowed, any more than Khoung-fou-tseu, that they were introducing innovations into the worship or polity of their country : all professed to sweep Their great innovations away. But their differences are only made the i erenccs. lnore remiirkable by this coincidence, and by the power which all were able to put forth. They did leave an impress upon vast regions of the earth,—they proved that there were certain great ideas of which these nations were, aud perhaps had always been, the appointed depositaries. We have tried to discover in the practical records of Chinese thought and legis¬ lation what their characteristic is ; is it possible to penetrate through the vagueness of the Zendavesta, and to detect what was latent in the minds of those who composed it, or believed in it ? he 3. To give any account of this strange collection of litanies Zendavesta. seems impossible. How it came together is a question still unsolved. The debates about the language in which it is com¬ posed are receiving so much illustration from recent inquiries, that it would be unwise to enter upon them, even if our subject required it. If we gave specimens of the style of the book, as it comes to us through the French compiler, M. Anquetil, we should perhaps rather confuse our readers respecting its object than help them to arrive at it. We shall, therefore, content ourselves with some general hints respecting the meaning and purpose of the change which has been for so many centuries connected with the name of Zoroaster,—hints not in the least novel, in accordance for the most part with the conclusions at which all students of the subject have arrived, but which may throw some light upon the question, what place Persia occupies in the history of philosophical inquiries, aud how it is connected in the way, either of resemblance or opposition, with Egypt, with India, with China, with Greece. The Persian 4. The difficulty of attributing a personal existence to Zoro- rea" person as^erver7 much that which meets us again in the cases of Lycurgus, Odin, and many more ; a difficulty, we may be per¬ mitted to remark, belonging chiefly to our own time, connected with a true feeling of the wonderful manner in which institu¬ tions, beliefs, habits, have diffused themselves through parti¬ cular races, and characterised them from the very first; con¬ nected also with a vague and false feeling,, that acts can some- ZERDTTSCHT. 75 how accomplish themselves without living agents,—that great conflicts may be transacted in the clouds and the air, without human combatants or personal leaders. In each instance we have named, it is probable that we shall ultimately return to the belief of our forefathers in an actual legislator or champion, however we may confess our inability to arrive at that very de¬ finite notion of his position and acts, which they attained by supplying the chasms of fact out of the stores of their imagina¬ tion, or by the opposite process of stripping legends of their poetry,—of all that gives them their worth and significance,— and so reducing them into facts. Of Zerduscht we must speak as an actual person; he may have had some other name,—he may have done acts of which we know nothing, and have not done any of those his biographers record ; but that there was some one who maintained the conflict which produced results so striking and so lasting we may at once assume, and speak upon the assumption. 5. The conflict of Zerduscht was with the Magians. This Hisenemies. we take to be the facts of his history, whatever fictions may ^®ians surround it. He found a set of men doing homage, as he be¬ lieved, to powers, or a power of evil. Probably they made no secret of this homage. They taught that such a power was to be worshipped; they could teach the method of the worship. They knew the secrets of the evil being; they could explain how his wrath was to be averted. Upon the belief that they pos¬ sessed this knowledge their influence stood. 6. This was practically the case whatever worship they might Ahriman the also pay to a beneficent Divinity. There is no reason to sup- pose that the reverence for Ormuzd had ceased among them, worship. Most likely there were services which they rendered habitually and punctually to him, and called upon the people to render. But what is the worship of a good Being, when the Evil dwells pro¬ fessedly side by side with him ? The latter becomes inevitably the God. The character of the whole service is leavened and moulded by his character. Let the theories respecting the relation of the two beings towards each other be what they may, Ormuzd becomes really the servant of Ahriman. The Magians were in truth his priests, even when they were nominally bowing to his rival. 7. The effects of sucb a religion manifest themselves in all °sfhi directions. Zerduscht felt them in one direction especially, on'tiiiage. The earth in Iran was overgrown with weeds; nothing was done to till it or make it fruitful. How much is gathered up in these words! What a history of the effects of a priesthood, which looks upon its chief Divinity as the author of curses instead of blessings! Slavish dependence upon seasons, without any study 76 PERSIAN PHILOSOPHY. of the laws which govern them,—a fear of meddling with the thorns and thistles as if they grew by Divine ordinance, and had a sacred right which could not be disturbed,—the arms growing feeble every day from want of manly exercise in their appointed work,—the heart growing feeble through the decay of Practice and hope: here was a state of things to which a Magian might actiir' and triumphantly point and say, " See the proof of our doctrine! rencting on Does not the evil prevail; is it not becoming mightier ? "What each other. caQ we (jQ bribe it to be less severe and all-exacting ? Where shall we direct our prayers and sacrifices if not to this terrible conqueror ?" It was an opinion which was always establishing itself by new evidence,—always producing the facts which demonstrated it. TheOrmuzd 8. What line must a reformer take to encounter them ? He worshipper. couj^ a(jm^ no compromise. He must declare at once " Your whole scheme of worship is a lie ; the ground on which it is based is a lie. The earth is meant to bring forth and bud; the thistles are meant to be destroyed. Man is meant to put the seeds into it, and call the strength out of it. These evil spirits are not his masters; he owes them no service. They create nothing, produce nothing, keep nothing alive. The powers of creation, production, nourishment, are all good. Whatever begets, brings forth, makes life more plentiful,—this is to be sought for as a counteraction to the powers of death. Let them be as Btrong as they wdll, there must be that which is stronger." Polytheism 9. To these Powers of life and production, then, Zerduscht ofZerduscht raises his prayer. It is idle to pretend that he invokes only one Power. The litanies of the Zendavesta are addressed to a multitude of Powers. And yet the opinion is not so wrong as it may seem. Zerduscht would have affirmed himself that he worshipped only Ormuzd. He felt assuredly that as all which is Mono- destructive and evil tends to division, so everything which is element good tends to unity. This was not a theory in his mind, as it latent in it. would have been in a Hindoo's ; it was a strong practical con¬ viction which he did not so much utter in words as exhibit in his acts. He worshipped goodness. Whatever seemed to be doing good, to be acting beneficially for man whether in nature or out of nature, this seemed to him to have proceeded from Ormuzd, and to have a tendency to return to him. Ormnzd 19. The Magians were of course astrologers. Their tendency light. was to contemplate the stars as evil agencies,—prophets of mischief to man. Zerduscht does not depart from the line of thought which he finds in his country. Light is the object of his reverence. Light is evidently the great source of fruit- fulness to the earth. Light is man's benefactor. It becomes ZERDUSCHT. 77 identical in Zerduscht's mind with Ormuzd. It ia Good, or such a witness and symbol of Good as he cannot distinguish from it. Hymns and invocations to Light are surely means of resisting the dark being and his agents,—means of bringing good to the land, and to those who cultivate it. 11. Zerduscht was, therefore, as practical a man as Khoung- Prayer the fou-tseu, as much aiming at the increase of the wealth of his ^ap0n of country in the simplest sense of the word. But he was directly the Persian opposed to the Chinese, in that devotion'Vas his great instru- eviTpowars. ment. The word "instrument" is hardly adequate to express this difference. Zerduscht did not look upon prayer in any sense as a mere means to a result; it was in his mind an actual looking up to a Power who was capable of helping men against their enemies. The petitioner is driven to it by the might and the multitude of the evil powers which are striving against him. His litanies, if they seek for material blessings and deliverance from material evils, yet are undoubtedly addressed to some invi¬ sible Power, some Power of Light, against a tyrant partly visible, partly invisible, who would make all his acts and his thoughts contused and dark. It is not easy to say how much Prayer of visible idolatry he would himself have tolerated; but the ™viMbie° testimony of Herodotus as to the character of Persian worship powers, is certainly entitled to very great weight, and is not, we con¬ ceive, overborne by any clear evidence on the other side. He felt the absence of' visible symbols to be the characteristic dif¬ ference between the Persian service and his own. Though he did not see the empire in the time of its strength, when we may suppose the Zerduscht reform to have been most strongly felt, yet we may be sure that its influence had not passed away; and we may fairly conclude that it was not only a protest against the worship of Ahriman, but against the homage to visible things, which his servants the Magi will doubtless have encouraged. All the petitions of the Zendavesta seem to point, primarily at least, to powers and influences,—powers and influ¬ ences, as we have said already, which dwelt in natural things, but still which were not congnizable by the senses. This dis- Tbe later tinction we may believe would come out more and more promi- gi've^pthe nently in the two opposing worships, till at last some eclectical visible world philosophy, seeking to establish a kind of reconciliation betweent0 A rimau- them, and to make a fair distribution of their respective pro¬ vinces, will have assigned the whole outward framework of things to Ahriman as his proper and original territory, main¬ taining the invisible as the creation of Ormuzd, and that through which he was carrying on repeated assaults and iucursions upon the possessions of his rival. 78 PERSIAN PHILOSOPHY. Opposition between ZerduRCht anil the Brahmins. The Persian morality. Xenoplion. Time without bounds. How this idea entered into the faith of Zerduscht. 12. But there was so such eclecticism as this in Zerduscht himself, or in auy of his true followers. His faith was in a per¬ petual uncompromising war between the powers of good and evil. The earth was no permitted or tolerated habitation of Ahriman or his subjects ; on the contrary, it was for the sake of the earth and for its restoration that all prayers and sacrifices were to be addressed to Ormuzd. And herein certainly is the interest of the Zerduscht doctrine and reformation for the moral philosopher. It was a search after light, an inquiry after the Being who gives light and order to the universe. Only this source of light and order did not present itself mainly to the Persian as an intelligence, but mainly as one who is right and true. Good and evil, right and wrong, became in his mind much more primitive, fundamental distinctions, than they ever did in the mind of any heathen people of the east or of the west. The Persians were much more distinctly a moral people than the Hindoos, or than any tribe of the Greeks. Xenophou's romance is a distinct acknowledgment of this fact by a Greek. Though he must have had plentiful experience of the gross dishonesty into which they fell when they were engaged in transactions with his countrymen, yet he still recognised and admired this as the typical form of that character which he had seen in some measure in the younger Cyrus, aud which he fancied, or tried to fancy, had been exhibited almost perfectly in the founder of the nation. 13. In one way it has been supposed that Zerduscht did recognise a kind of reconciliation between the divinity whom he abjured and the divinity whom he worshipped. A Time without bounds, it has been thought, lay in the mind of the .Reformer, beneath all his conceptions either of a good or evil being; both alike must have proceeded from it. That there are litanies in the Zendavesta which suggest such a notion, and which may be as early as the time of Zerduscht, it is impossible to deny ; that the doctrine which is deduced from them very greatly influenced the later Persian pliilosophy we shall see when we come, in the second part of this sketch, to consider how it ati'eeted, and was affected by, the faith of the Christian church. But that this abstraction really interfered in any practical sense with the homage—theexclusive homage—which Zerduscht paid to Ormuzd, and to the different benignant powers which he supposed to pro¬ ceed from him, there is, we conceive, not the slightest proof. The use of prayers to a Time without bounds did, it seems to us, express the teacher's consciousness that there must be a deeper Unity, a more absolute Being, than he had apprehended. He was not satisfied—how could he be ?■—with a Being whom he ZERDT7SCHT. 79 must contemplate as one and almighty, and yet who was identical with every gracious influence, every productive power. For the sake and honour of Ormuzd himself he needed some other more distinct mode of declaring him, of invoking him. This was the mode—awkward and incoherent, leading to the very consequence which he sought to avoid, pregnant with future abstractions and confusions, but one which a man so thoroughly practical as Zerduseht could resort to without any care about its speculative difficulties, as an escape for his spirit from a real and oppressive contradiction, as a way of bringing his worship into closer sym¬ pathy with his human and political faith. 14. The Cyropa?dia, and the testimonies of Herodotus respect- The Persian ing the feelings of the Persians towards their king, and his in- kinK- separable connection with their worship, fully confirm another most important inference which we should deduce from the legends respecting Zerduseht. The Magian, officially, was his antagonist; some monarch was always the ally in his reforms. To exalt the royal above the sacerdotal function, to prevent the kings from being the servants of the priests, was unquestionably a great part of his work. Herein he was probably acting out a An antngo- faith which was far older in Persia than himself. It is difficult not to trace—most modern historians have traced—an opposition between the Persian and Median tribes (an opposition not pre¬ venting bnt necessitating an attempt at union between them), which points to more than the strife of mere personal feelings and interests. The Median predominance seems always to in-Medians and dicate the triumph of a priestly order and of priestly habits; i>CT8ia,ls- the Persian prevalence shows that a king is ruling who knows that he is a king, and is determined to maintain his authority against all opposers, by whatever visible or invisible instruments they may work. The nobler kings, such as were Cyrus and Darius Hystaspes, do not merely proclaim their own tyranny. The) assert that Ormuzd is King; they are as entirely religious as those who are leagued against them ; their faith is the ground of all their acts; in the strength of it they decree justice, organize satrapies, improve the tillage of the land, constitute one of those mighty monarchies in which we recognised the charac¬ teristic strength and spirit of Asia. In those monarchies every¬ thing depends upon the central power, or rather upon the earnestness with which the central power confesses its subjection to a gracious and beneficent Power in whose name it rules and fights. The inscriptions which Major Eawlinson has recently interpreted show how remarkably this was the case with Darius Darius Hystaspes: they embody the very spirit of the Zerduseht refor- H>stasPes- mation, and might almost tempt us to the notion, a favourite with some German critics, (not, however, it seems to us, com- 80 PEttSIAJN" PHILOSOPHY. patible with any of the popular traditions,) that he was iden¬ tical with the Prophet. He no doubt realised the conception of the teacher much more than any mere teacher could have realised it. His order was that attempt to imitate the order of Thekinp the the heavenly bodies, the calmness and regularity of Nature, light" °f whmh one wh0 looked upon light as the centre of the outward universe, and the king as the centre of the human society, would especially have admired and rejoiced in. weakness of 15. But in the heart of this order, wonderful as it was, lay order and seeds of weakness and decay. The king confessed a King m,ad- mightier than himself; a King in whom dwelt supreme right and justice. But he was the one utterer of the will of this higher Sovereign; his own absolute dominion represented the divine absoluteness. The light which comes forth from the heavenly bodies may symbolize a goodness and wisdom that penetrates into the remotest corners, that quickens and enlivens the least thing as well as the greatest, calling forth its own distinct nature and properties. But this light may be looked upon as gathered into one luminous orb, an object of distant reverence, altogether unlike the materials on which it shines. Such was more and more the tendency of the Persian mind; the Zerduscht reform did not resist it for more than a short time, nay, in one sense promoted it. There was probably in him more of tribe feeling, more of patriotism in the western sense of the word, than we commonly meet with among Asiatics. But the strength which his faith gave to the monarchy soon made it, like the great monarchies that had preceded it, impatient of boundaries, eager to swallow up all tribes within itself, careless of their dis¬ tinctions. Zerduscht's zeal in breaking the chains of priestly domination, which had preventedthe free activity of the sovereign, might give a large scope to beneficent government, and be the instrument of putting down a multitude of abuses and abomina¬ tions that were fostered by the Ahrimanic devotion. On the other hand, he weakened the witness which was latent in the priestly character, which could not be wholly lost even after the priest had become a servant of evil powers, that there is a refuge tor the oppressed subject when the visible ruler becomes a mere self-willed despot, when all feeling of relationship to his subjects has forsaken him, when he pays habitual homage to Ahriman. The later history of Persia, while it interprets the meaning and illustrates the power of Zerduscht's principle, shows also how small a protection it afforded against this danger ; what an open¬ ing, nay, what a necessity there was for Magian conspiracies and counter-revolutions to check the regal tyranny, even to restore it when it had fallen through its own crimes and weakness; what a still greater need there was that some witness, which Asia ZERDUSCHT. 81 could not afford, to prove that life and movement are necessary for man, as well as a fixed eternal law. 16. Those who find an especial delight in proving eminent zerdnscht's teachers of former generations to be impostors, charlatans, or ambition knaves, dwell much upon some of the legends of Zerduscht's Cism.ana life, which convict him, they think, of many violent and ambitious acts. When it is settled how much of these legends are entitled to credence, we may accept them as evidence against the Eeformer. But to reject all the records which show the high estimate that his countrymen formed of him, as mere fictions— to assume those as veracious, though not less miraculous, which offend our consciences—is a monstrous violation of critical fair¬ ness. The total inference which they leave upon our mind is certainly this, that Zerduscht was possessed with a sense of his vocation to put down, by all possible means, the Abrimanic worship, to assert the worship of Ormuzd. Whether this should be done or not was a question of life and death ; the material, as much as the spiritual, well-being of Persia depended upon it. We have no doubt that, in the accomplishment of this purpose, he stirred up wars, persecuted, urged his own claims to inspira¬ tion, till he may sometimes have forgotten the work in its champion. But we are equally convinced, from the results of his labours, that he did, in the main, sacrifice himself to the cause, and not the cause to himself. 17. By doing so he has, we think, earned for himself a right Zerdusc|lt to no unimportant place in a history of Philosophy. The name in what does not belong to Persia, or to the Persian character as it was p^fosopber. formed by Zerduscht. The light which the Persian worshipped told him what it behoved him to follow, what to shun. Their rule of right was given once and for ever ; whoso trangressed it was doomed. There was no room for speculation. They abhorred it as leading to confusion and darkness—refined sym¬ bolism implied in their minds falsehood, and traffic with evil spirits. Intellectual subtlety of all kinds in the days of their strength they crushed with law and the sword, as leading to dishonesty and trickery; in the days of their weakness, they shrunk from it as an unknown mysterious power which they could not cope with. The fanaticism of Cambyses in Egypt, the struggles which are attributed to Zerduscht with the intellec- tuaHsm and priestcraft of the Brahmin, exhibit some aspects of this character towards foreigners. We have now to contemplate another ; we have to see in what sense the Persians were philo¬ sophers, by viewing them in contrast with the nation to which that title strictly and originally belongs; the nation which, in every stage of its existence, merits the apostle's description, " They seek after wisdom." VOL. I. G ( 82 ) CHAPTER VI. GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. DIVISION I.—PERIOD BEFORE SOCRATES. section i. greek wisdom in the legendary ages. Cut ere and 1. The opposition betvceen Greece and Asia presents itself to onitrast6 the schoolboy who is reading the Homeric poems. It meets between the again in the first pages of Herodotus ; he traces it through. "s ' the whole of his varied narrative ; it connects the episodes with the main story ; it gives a unity to books which strike him at first as confused and miscellaneous. In them, Persia gradually becomes the representative of Asia; the glorious conflict of the historian's own age interprets all the ages that had preceded it. Wherever the young reader turns he is reminded of this contrast, and the connection between the two people. He finds it in the retreat of the Ten Thousand; it is forced upon him by the efforts of the leader of that retreat to bring Persian manners and Per¬ sian virtues before the minds of his countrymen. He cannot dwell upon the conflicts of the republics among themselves without some event to recall to him the monarchy which had sought to crush them, and which they had defied. The mind of Demosthenes is inspired by the thought of that republican triumph, when he determines that a pretended Greek shall not obtain the dominion which the ruler of the whole barbarian world could not win. It inspires no less the heart of the son of the hated Macedonian, when he goes forth to prove that the signal-fires which proclaimed that Troy had fallen were faithful rophecies that the furthest regions of the East should bow efore the descendants of Odysseus and Neoptolemus. Ground of 2. A few very notorious facts will show that the opposition tinscontrast. wyiic]1 thus presents itself on the surface of the history existed in the heart of these nations. The student perceives at once urmuzd and that Ormuzd was not the god of the Greeks. Goodness is not Zpus' the primary characteristic of any one of their divinities. What their essential and common quality is, it is not, we think, hard to discover. The continually recurring epithet fitirtera, as applied to Zeus, immediately suggests it. The title Cloud- compeller may express his acts: this is clearly meant to be sig¬ nificant of his very nature. For it is not a solitary expression ; the more we consider the different transactions which Homer attributes to the father of gods and men, the more do we find " counsel" to be the main quality which is indicated by them. THE LEGENDARY AGES. 83 The mind of the god may be swayed by various impulses and passions, but he always acts with a purpose and devises a train of means for the accomplishment of it. 3. The other gods are like Zeus. Apollo is the deviser and Counsel tiie suggester of counsels; Athene still more conspicuously. If file Lrw-k' this character is wanting in Ares and Aphrodite, they become, for that reason, objects of ridicule to mortals, let the sword of the first and the girdle of the other be ever so mighty. 4. This quality seems to involve at once the idea of secresy and of society. The counsels are carried on deep within the heart of the divinity, but they must be shared. Zeus must communicate his intentions, or part of his intentions, to the Olympian assembly; they must be submitted to discussion, deliberation, opposition: there must be ministers to execute them; often opposing agents to thwart them. Instead of various beneficent powers, all proceeding from Ormuzd, all invoked by his name, all united against the realm of darkness, the Greek does homage to a number of beings who are bringing about a result by their conspiracies and contradictions, who are in themselves neither good nor evil, who have the same inclinations to good and evil with human beings, who often seem physically not more power¬ ful, but who have a depth and subtlety of wisdom to which men cannot attain. 5. In Persia the king presents an image of god, but he is not personally related to him. Ormuzd is continually contemplated kinsi,\,.iu ^ as the unapproachable light; his goodness, though it is shown from Zvus in acts of mercy to man, is not to be confounded with human goodness. But the counsellors in Olympus are always related to sages below; they meet with mortal nymphs, become the fathers of earthly heroes, impart to them their sceptres and their wisdom. The kings reign as sons of Jove. In early times the feeling of belonging to the divine race is the warrant of their sharing the divine attributes. There is never the least doubt what is the special and necessary constituent of royalty ; it is royal riia- not physical strength—it is not mercy, kindness, justice—it is ractens,K not courage ; it is the being a man of many devices. Courage, justice, mercy, may or may not be added to this.gift or be involved in it; but it is the fundamental one, all others are accessory. Strength is thrown into the shade in those heroes in whom we would expect it most; lightness and grace are preferred to it: Achilles is the " swift-of-foot." The ambush and stratagem, as has been so often observed, are quite as much the test of the hero as the open fight. Diomed shows his heroic talent not more in wounding Ares than in persuading Glaucon to change the golden armour for the iron, that worth a hundred oxen's hides for that worth nine, when they are meeting 84 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. as friends on the field of battle and telling the story of their kins- manship. These are indications of a deep and pervading spirit, exhibiting itself, be it remembered, in a stage of society which we are wont to speak of, and in one sense rightly, as one of great simplicity, and in those fights where strength and personal TiicHomeric prowess might seem to be all in all. Clearly tbey are not all in aniirouncil- ; council-chamber is as much a part of the Homeric pic- < hamber. ture as the field of battle: on that field, if we see distinct heroes in a death-struggle, we see also the troops moving collected, in ranks, in silence (an excellence which, except on a field of battle, would not have been specially characteristic of Greeks). tiitytypeof No one who considers the story of Odysseus, and feels, as ihe Greek all have felt, that he represented actually and prophetically all nation. 0f hj8 country's mind and tendencies, will doubt that TroXvfxrtriq is the epithet for the Greek hero as much as for the god. But no one who feels the exceeding beauty, delicacy, pathos of that story, will admit for a moment that "cunning" or "crafty" is an adequate — even the most distant approximation to an adequate—version of that title. All possibilities of craft and cunning lie in it; such qualities can scarcely have been morally offensive to the man or the nation that claimed it as the Trirknot most honourable of all badges. Within it also lay the possibi- e-sfiitiai to a wisdom which might rise superior to tricks and false- riiaracter. hood, which might discover them to be essentially foolish. The " man of many counsels" had a large sympathy, a wonderful power of communicating with men, of receiving impressions from them, of making an impression on them. He had the its noble clearest, sharpest faculty of observation; all the forms of nature iiuaimes. presented themselves to him in their distinctest outline, with all their varying shadows. Animal nature did homage to the higher instinct which dwelt in him. He felt that material things were given him to shape and mould, and quicken. Though fond of seeing the ways and the cities of men, he had still the sense of a home; the rocks of Ithaca were dearer to him than all the world besides—dear to him for the sake of those who dwelt there. He might cast away many ties which he found established at his birth ; he might leave his father's house to Sacredness become a wanderer and seeker of new lands : but the voluntary t:olunmy bonds into which he had entered, the marriage-tie, the oath to marriage, the kinsman, or fellow-citizen, or even the stranger, confirmed by the divine sacrifice, were unspeakably precious; no perils or wars were too long or distant to punish the breach of them. Of all men he most understands the meaning and worth of association, yet he is of all men the most tempted to choose a wa) of his own : of all men he is most disposed to recognise law THE LEGENDARY AGES. 85 and government as especially belonging to man, and distinguish¬ ing them from the inferior creatures ; the most inclined to break loose from law and government, in his eagerness to assert the skill of men to create them for themselves. 7. In process of time some of these great contrasts, especially Contrast of the last, were exhibited in the rivalship of the Dorian and Ionian j^'^1 and tribes. Though we may be continually tempted to fix upon the last as the proper specimens of the Greek character, though there is great excuse for such a notion, yet it is only in contem¬ plating them as both equally Greeks that we can attain to a full appreciation of that which distinguished this people from every other on the face of the earth. If there were points of sym- The pathy between the Lacedemonian and the Persian character, ^hoppoKed there was also the strongest repulsion between them. The to the Spartan Pausanias, affecting the airs of an Asiatic satrap, is a Pcr8,ai^ far more ludicrous object than Themistocles would have been in the same position. The Spartan kings when compared with the king exhibit the difference between the East and West even more strikingly than the Athenian democracy. The legislation of Lvcurgus is as little like that of the Medes and Persians as Solon's. If we inquire the reason of the difference, we shall Both find that counsel or wisdom, not goodness, is the object of faith Greek.'"1'* and reverence as much with one tribe as the other. It was the very fact of their having this common ground to start from— the sense of a community of feeling and of language—which made the differences of their conceptions respecting the conditions of wisdom and the modes of attaining it so remarkable, and their actual contests so terrible. Indeed, the existence of such opposing tribes, and the vast influence which they were both able to exert, suggest the greatest and most memorable contrast between European and Asiatic life. The vastness of the oriental despotism, with all the different races blended together, sub¬ mitting to one central lord—what a picture is this to contemplate side by side with the struggles of two small cities, each possessed with the idea of one government or principle being better than another, ready to destroy or be sacrificed for the sake of its own maxim—imparting the conviction of it, and the enthusiasm for it, to twenty other cities in different parts of the world, and in a measure to every man who dwelt in every one of them ! And it must never be forgotten that, amidst all these conflicts, there was still the common Hellenic name—there was still the feeling in all Greeks that they were separated from barbarians by that name, and by the gifts which it indicated—there was still the god of Delphi who gave counsel to the Ionians and Dorians alike, and from whom the rulers of Asia believed that oracles proceeded by which they also might be guided. 86 GRECIAN PniEOSOPnT. Delphi. 8. The acknowledgment of this teacher of civil wisdom, who at the same time could not easily be separated from the source of light to the world, is one of those facts in Greek history which every Apollo noil thoughtful student has seen to be full of significance. Apollo the light. ant[ Artemis, as our own great poet has said, " held the sun and moon in feethey, beautiful beingB, with human forms and human sympathies, possessed and governed these natural orbs; the material light which proceeded from them was only an emblem of the light which was imparted to the mind of him who sought help from the divine priestess. This inspiration was not merely produced by the exhalations of the cave, nor was it con¬ fined to her—the votary shared it in a much more practical sense. Inspiration, In later times, belief in an inspiring god, prompting the highest song as well as the wildest revelry, became embodied in the legends and the festivals of Dionysus. The Greek felt an impulse near him which was degrading him into a beast and a slave, and one which could raise him into a man and free¬ man. His actual history proved the truth of both his con¬ victions. i'r?imnd ^eu9 the G"reeks is very different from Ormuzd, 'lu' " he is almost as unlike to Brahm. The object of Hindoo worship we have seen is Intelligence, but it is intelligence as contrasted with action. Every Greek legend exhibits gods or heroes as the teachers of some art, as deliverers from some plague or nuisance, as making some one region habitable, or introducing communication between different regions, as establishers of law and order, as builders or defenders of cities. The main tendency of the Greek mind is certainly to contemplate intelligence only as bearing upon action, leading to direct practical results, governing material things and bodies of men. 10. Hence the skill, or counsel, or wisdom of the Greek was especially valued for its creative or productive powers. The (,mk more this power exerted itself, the more various the directions sc I'll -ism. -which it took; the more the suspicion began to arise in the miuds of the people, that they were themselves the authors of that to which they looked up,— that the king, the priest, the god, wore their own handiwork. Hence there lay in the very heart of the faith of the Greek a seed of unbelief, which was con¬ tinually fructifying. Hence this unbelief was likely to be most active in those whose faculties were the liveliest and the most energetic. Hence, also, there was something akin to it in the popular feeling and sympathy, even then when it clung most fondly to its old legends and ceremonies. These were loved with a parental more than a childlike fondness; the Greek clave to them as his own, as something which he was to hold against others, not which he depended upon and revered himself. THE BEGINNING OF PHILOSOPHY. 87 11. If Zeus and Apollo hold the highest place as objects of Hermes. Greek devotion, Hermes had his own special honour. The The p(wer teacher of words, the author of eloquence, had conferred a gift of words, upon mortals which the Greeks felt to be greater and more wonderful than the gifts of corn and wine. Their latest his¬ torian poiuts out with especial carefulness and earnestness, how in the very infancy of the nation the power of words was recognised ; how significant was the picture on the shield of Achilles, of the trial in the Agora, ana the pleaders who sup¬ ported each side; how public speaking was felt to be " the standing engine of government and the proximate cause of obedience,"1 long before the heroical had given place to the his¬ torical period. The most careless reader of the Iliad must have been struck by the poet's sense of the wonder which lies in " winged words," by the emphasis with which he recognises them as the especial characteristic of human beings, by his feeling that through them men held communication with the gods as well as with each other. The power of wisdom and the power of words became indissolubly connected in the Greek mind. By these, men exerted the highest influence of which they were capable; they flew forth from the lips of the speaker messengers of health or of destruction ; they were in the most remarkable sense his. Yet there was that in them which he did not make ; an order to which he was obliged to conform. 12. The mysteries expressed something which words could The not express. So far as these were connected with Demeter and "^l^hey her worship, they bore reference of course to the secret and imported productive powers of vegetables or animals ; they might be in¬ vested with a more material significance, they might be associated with all gross and sensual images. But the importance which was attached to them by statesmen showed that they were acknowledgments of a wisdom dwelling somewhere, which could not be measured or reduced into human forms, by which the operations of nature, of the mind, and even of political society, were ultimately regulated. SECTION II. THE BEGINNING OF PHILOSOPHY. 1. The seven wise men bear the same relation to the after The wise history of Greece which the seven champions of Christendom bear to the history of the Middle Ages. No doubt Bias, Pittacus, Periander, Solon, belong to the region of fact; St. George and St. Denys chiefly to that of fable. But their mys- 1 Grote, vol. ii. c. xx. p. 106. GEECIA.TT PHILOSOPHY. tical number shows that they were felt to represent different aspects of the same character. Amongst them are included tyrants, legislators, students of nature. There were the most various reports respecting them. One said that they all occupied themselves with poetry.1 Another that they were merely a set of clever men concerned about law-making.2 They were reported to be favourites of Croesus, with the exception of Thales. Others spoke of their meeting together at the Panionium, or at Delphi. Hie various 1 hese reports may all be correct. They were, no doubt, mainly hem recon- of sagacity, aovtrdi, held to possess the divine, heroic, •iiabie. Odyssean gift in a greater degree than their neighbours. That they should have been fond of putting their thoughts in verse was natural. It was a language different from that which men spoke in the market—more than met the ear was expressed by it; common men felt the power of it; a notion of prophecy was still connected with it. That these sages should have cultivated the acquaintance of a great Asiatic dynast, some for a directly personal object, some for the sake of their city, some for the pleasure of exhibiting the power of the Greek in contrast with that which seemed so much greater and was so inferior, is pro¬ bable. That they should still have been thoroughly Greeks, should have interested themselves in all Greek events for council and government, might also have been concluded. Por this reason they will no doubt have held much intercourse with Delphi. rlie different 2. But, supposing these to have been common characteristics, which their there was room for the widest divergency in their pursuits, wisdom took One might glorify himself upon his knowledge of all the weak¬ nesses of his fellows ; might apply to his own use the recognised Greek maxim, that the wise man was to have dominion over fools; by fair means or foul, by courtesy or violence, by benefi¬ cent acts or destructive ones, he might make himself a tyrant. The tyrant. His claim to that title, his power of holding it, would still be, not that he was member of some illustrious family, or that he supported some particular theory, or that he was a military chief; but that he was a wise man. Another might count it a The much nobler work to lay down rules for the preservation and legislator. Well-being of the city in which he dwelt—rules that would endure after he ceased to belong to it; he might part with ease, wealth, temporary power, for the sake of compassing this end. Such a man would be a legislator in the higher sense of the word ; but his legislation would still be a form of his " wisdom." He would be listened to and obeyed only so far as he had acquired the repu¬ tation of being a wise man, and could retain it. Lastly, if a 1 Diog. Laert. lib. i. c. i. b. 14. 2 coverobs vivas ical vo/ioflfTiKovs. THE BEGINNING OF PHILOSOPHY. 89 man had acquired any of the properly oriental lore, if he had The student studied astrology, and could calculate eclipses of the sun, there of p^81"- would be some perplexity in the Greek mind respecting him. If he turned his studies in nature to account, either for his own benefit or for the good of his country, he would be regarded as essentially a politician; if he was seen to retire from society for the sake of contemplation, he would be stigmatised as a star- gazer. But still the phrase " wise man" would describe him in both characters. It would denote the shrewdness which he dis¬ played in the common affairs of life ; it would intimate that he knew or pretended to know things which people in general were ignorant of. 3. In this last description our reader will recognise Thales, who £ "r*LES' commonly holds the first place among the aoipoi. Herodotus qj 35 3 says that " he was a citizen of Miletus, and a Phoenician by or 35' 1' descentDiogenes Laertius,1 that " be was believed by some B c 039 to have come from Phoenicia, and to have been made a citizen of or 030' Miletus, but that the greater number of people believed him to ciinton, have been a native, and of an illustrious family." The authority ¥-H- of Herodotus must assuredly outweigh the judgment of this origin.B'at,C " greater number of people," who, of course, were not willing to share the glory of such a name with Asiatics. After all, the Greeks have immeasurably the largest portion in him. If he brought his astrology from Phoenicia, he was a thorough Milesian in the application of it. To the lonians, says Herodotus,2 he predicted the eclipse which happened when the Lydians and Medes were fighting, and which led to a peace between them. It was he, the Greeks generally believed—Herodotus had a dif¬ ferent opinion—who enabled Croesus to pass the Halys, by turning the course of the river, when he was making his fatal attack upon Persia.3 It was said, however, by others that he was no friend of Croesus, that he prevented Miletus from allying itself with his fortunes, and so saved it from the wrath of the conqueror. Bias of Priene gave good advice to the Ionian cities after their overthrow by Harpagus, but Thales, says Herodotus,4 had urged them before their fall to establish a common assembly, and to fix it at Teos. 4. There were very opposite reports current respecting Thales. The Some said that he bought up the oil-presses just before the olive {h^ereeks°f season, that he might show how easily a wise man could make respecting himself rich ; others told of his falling into a pit while he was looking at the stars, and of his being mocked by an old woman for knowing that which was over his head so much better than 1 Diog. Laert. lib. i. c. i. s. 1. 2 KXei», c. lxsiv. 3 KXeiu, c. lxxv. 4 KXeio), c. clxx. 90 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. The philosophy of Thales. that which lay at his feet.1 These stories are both probably the produce of Greek invention, but they indicate the uncertainty of his countrymen whether they should assign him a place among meu of business or theorists, and their notion that in some way or other he blended the two characters. Neither of them, how¬ ever, accounts for the special distinction which he has acquired, that of being separated from the rest of the ov an(l the political or human world another. It is very important, we conceive, to recollect that this was not the case at all; that they were by vocation wisdom-hunters; that they started their game in another ground, and were led bv various accidents and impulses to follow it hither. The track of the first pursuer was that in which the next ran, till some fresh Relation of scent turned him out of it. Anaximander can hardly have been manrterto enough t° hear Thales, yet he belonged to the same city, and Thaies. was greatly influenced at least by the reports and traditions of his predecessor. But Thales discoursed; he wrote—a difference of the greatest practical importance. Thales, seeking for that order in things which he could not find among men, lighted upon a fact. Anaximander having to set down in written characters the object of the student's, inquiries calls it the beginning or Thi1oIso1^'hers e^emen^ (^PX'l or OTOLX£loy)-1 The name which seems so con- wercseeking venient for pointing out the direction of the philosophy, to a torunawcj. certain extent changes it. The pursuit of an apx>) threatens to take the place of the pursuit of wisdom. Still more dangerous was Anaximander's other phrase, " the Infinite." A formula so comprehensive seemed to exhaust all possibilities. Philosophy, just beginning, had already reached its goal. "What could it nn mere"*16 beyond the unbounded! Let us, however, do Phrase- 1 I)iog. Laert. lib. ii. cap. i. 9.1. THE FIRST SCHOOL. 95 Anaximander the justice to believe that " the Infinite" was Dot Anaxi- merely a formula iu his mind; that the name expressed thoughts maDder- too deep for utterance; that he really bowed before that which he could not measure and comprehend, while he seemed ambitious of summing it up in a few syllables. 3. In Anaximenes we perceive the effect of the step which anaxi- Anaximander had taken, and at the same time evident indications of a return to the line which he abandoned. The word up^r) is B c 543 . equivocal. It suggests the idea of " rule" as well as that of Q] 53 . " beginning." Anaximenes seems to have perceived that the lived to philosopher should seek for a power which rules, not merely for 01. 74. an element or starting-point. Plutarch, who can never be taken The d0ut,ie as a fair judge of the old philosophers, seeing that he con- force of the templated all the subjects of their inquiry from entirely aword apx*>' different point of view, may be received as evidence respecting them when he attributes language to them which he is not likely to have invented, and which has all the marks of an earlier stage of thought. Anaximenes, he says, held that " the air rules The air and over all things, as the soul, being air, rules in man."1 Such a thesoul- phrase at once explains the assertion of Aristotle, that Anaxi¬ menes made air his apx9> and connects him with the seekers for wisdom. This ruling power in man—this invisible, intangible power, which nevertheless accomplishes such wonders, compels huge bodies to obey it—what is it, where is it ? "We are looking into the natural universe to see if it is there. Is not this air— invisible, impalpable, all-penetrating, all-commanding,—the very thing ? Jove was said of old to rule in the air; to be the cloud- The air and compeller. May he not be this air ? It was a perilous question. Jove- When it was answered in the affirmative by the untrembling lips of later teachers, the result was fatal to all sense of a per¬ sonal moral ruler. We conceive the suggestion of it by Anaxi¬ menes may have been in quite a different spirit. The air may rather have been humanised and glorified by its association with Jove, than Jove naturalised and materialised by his identification with the air. The coarseness of the old mythology may have been diminished in the mind of the student; it may not have been stripped of all its real associations. 4. There was, however, another danger lurking in such lan- Hbra- guage, though not caused by it. The Greek was more liable, flourished in practice, to confound the " great Counsellor" with the soul, b.C. 503 ; the ruling element which dwelt in himself, than with the air. 01. 69,2 Of that tendency in his countryman, Heraclitus the Ephesian 1 Plutarch, De Placitis Philosonhorum, lib. i. (wegl ruv of"" V p'jj0n' V i'lQ otrra auyKgarei 96 GEE CI AN PHILOSOPHY. Hcraciitus. seems to have been especially aware; his dread of it seems to be connected with all his political theories, his physical specula- Politics of tions, bis individual sorrows. In his mind.it is quite evident Heraclitus. . ■ , , , , J that these were never separated. Love of law. 5. He believed that we should fight to death for the law. But he would not be a magistrate of Ephesus ; he would rather play at dice with the children before the temple of Artemis.1 W hat good could come of making laws for evil men ? He would live upon herbs upon the mountains rather than among those Dislike of who banished their best citizens, and would not of their own democracy choice have a good one left among them. Heraclitus, therefore, was considered a stern aristocrat and despiser of the people. Tet he is said to have received the civilities of the great king with even more indifference than those of his countrymen. His feelings towards them were, we should judge, much more those of a disappointed lover than of a scorner. " Pride or insolence," he said, " should be stifled more diligently than a fire." The vaunting of the Greeks, their sense of superiority to the rest of the world, seems to have inspired him with pity and mourning. " Tour knowledge of many things," he said, " does not give you reason or wisdom." An obvious saying, in which, nevertheless, much of his philosophy is latent. Is the individual soul, as How his Anaximenes thought, the ruling power in man? Is it not in philosophy itself a very poor, weak, insignificant thing, most contemptible grew out of when it is most presuming ? Separate a man from his fellows, feeling™°Dal an(l what is he worth ? Abolish laws, government, and what Ail things, becomes of the atoms which compose your society ? What is considered each good for ? You Greeks are always making the experiment, unreal. See what comes of it in this city of mine ! See what infinite disorder, what infinite cause for sorrow. Would not nature have told you the secret if you had studied her ? We do not find a set of individual energies and powers at work there. All things TJje central are efficient and energetical only in their harmony ; only in their 1 * subjection to some central principle of life. Take that away, and the things we behold are only phantoms ; the phenomena of the universe exhibit only an endless flux. The coal without reflux!1"1 the fire, is a man trying to exist in himself; the coal ignited, receiving communication from another nature, there is a man's soul enkindled by communication with a higher diviner reason. t?ire- 6. This statement and this comparison may explain why Heraclitus has been supposed to attach so much sacredness and significance to the element of fire. It seemed to him (old fables, diligently considered and connected with facts of experience, might teach him the lesson,) the vital quickening power of the 1 Dipg. Laert. lib. ix. cap. i. THE FIRST SCHOOL. 97 universe; that which was or which expressed—sometimes it Heraciitus. might present itself to him as the symbol, sometimes as the Symbol of thing symbolised—the universal life, by participation in which J^"ntral all particular things have their being; apart from which they power, are unsubstantial, unreal. But this physical fire was never divorced from the law which holds societies together, from the higher and universal mind with which the individual mind is meant to be in communion. When, therefore, we are The name of told that Heraciitus said the object of man's life is to know JuPlter- the name of Jupiter, we may be sure that Jupiter did not mean to him either air or fire; that it did mean a reality which he could not comprehend, which he desired should com¬ prehend him. 7. Such was Heraciitus, a man with a marked individual cha¬ racter, full of deep and pregnant intuitions. The vulgar notion Tbe crying of him as the crj-ing philosopher must not be discarded as if it Phllos°Pher- meant nothing, or had no connection with the history of his speculations. His thoughts are like fragments torn from his own personal being, and not torn from it without such effort and violence as must needs have drawn many a sigh from the sufferer. Neither is that other notion of him, as " the obscure or dark" man, an unfounded one. The fire that was in his heart and brain, and of which all the world around had presented to him the image, no doubt emitted much smoke which confused and stifled, not, perhaps, to his displeasure, the careless gazers and passers by. But there was something within him which neither his tears nor his smoke at all adequately represent. Tbe sense of a harmony existing beneath a perpetual conflict of powers, and making that very conflict the m^ans of their pre¬ servation. pervaded his being, gave the tone to all his thoughts, and realised itself to him in all the inner forms and outward images of nature. 8. These four men, Thales, Anaximander, Anaximenes, and The ionians Heraciitus, have been usually regarded as constituting the Pr°Per- Ionic school. There is a reason and an advantage in the classi- naturalists, fication. They belonged to the same region, they were exposed to similar external influences ; they succeeded each other at no very considerable intervals; there was, we think, a certain transmission of apprehensions and discoveries from the first to the last. Still it is a needful preparation for the study of those writers who were technically and practically the moral and meta¬ physical philosophers of Greece, that we should speak briefly of two or three others, who, in different circumstances, were led to occupy themselves chiefly with the phenomena and powers of Nature. TOL. I. 98 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. J>EMO- CRITUS. ji.o. 460. 01. 80. Clinton. The traditional contrast between him and Heraclitus not unim¬ portant. Effects of a irood temper and easy cir¬ cumstances. View of inimaiiity. 9. "We depart a little from chronological order,1 for the sake of bringing Demorritua of Abdera into immediate juxtaposition with Heraclitus of Ephesus. The old story, which opposes the smiles of the one to the tears of the other, is not without its significance, either as to the characters of the men or of their philosophies. He who recognises the existence of a central power adequate to keep all things at one, who believes in an order, must at times be overwhelmed by the distractions which the actual world presents to him. In proportion to the intensity of his belief will he be oppressed by the contradictious of expe¬ rience. Heraclitus worshipped law, and saw a multitude of incoherent elements resolving to disregard it. He found a refuge (but how imperfect a refuge!) in nature. There he could detect an uniting organising energy. But how, with his mind harassed and tormented by human confusions, could he help also seeing their counterpart here; a whirl of atoms, which, if the invisible compulsion that bound them together was for a moment forgotten, must make the brain sick, and the heart sadder than it was before. 10. But suppose a man should arise, whose position did not lead him to meditate much on the perplexities of human society, or to seek for the removal of them ; a man provided with exter¬ nal comforts, blessed with a good digestion, indifferent to fame,2 with a Greek habit of observation, with opportunities of seeing various cities and men, for no one of which he has any passionate preference ; and we need be at no loss to conjecture the results at which he would arrive both in practice and theory. Every one will see in such a man the elements of a benignant, agreeable, sociable companiqp; of one who would regard the disorders of humanity as mere eccentricities, to be noticed with so much the more kindliness if the suspicion should intrude itself that some of their results may be serious, even painful, to iliose who exhibit them. He would gradually come to think even the word " eccentricities" too strong to express variations which after all might not be deviations from any standard. Eor is there a standard,is there a centre? Can we find one in human beings, can we find one in the physical world ? Our senses tell us of no such. Perhaps we cannot depend on our senses. But have we anything better to depend upon ? Can we see more than those atoms, the sight of which so disturbed Heraclitus ? Is it not worth while to get at them ; to examine and dissect the world; to see what it is actually made of; to leave our own 1 reyove 8J roTs xp6"0is (&>s uvris (pjjffij/ iv r<2 p.iKptp Aiau6aporn education to the Ionic school. But it was at Athens that he died taught; to the iufiuences which surrounded him at Athens the b c 428. direction of his mind and the peculiarity of his doctrines may, Clinton. we thiuk, clearly be traced. Anaxagoras would have been most Teariies in reluctant to confess this obligation; he was, it would seem, even Athens. more utterly without patriotism, in the ordinary sense, than e\en Democritua. " You care nothing for your country," some The stars his one sa^ " Yery much indeed," was the answer; " my country. country is there," pointing to the stars. There appears to have been no affectation in such language. He was, to a degree in which no Greek before him ever had been, absorbed iu mere physical contemplation. Natural philosophy iu his mind was separated from political wisdom, even opposed to it. THE FIRST SCHOOL. 101 16. But this violent reaction against the habits and tendencies Anaxa^oras. of his countrymen must have been produced by seeing them in Effect of their fullest activity. The bustle of Athens drove him to the ^ stars. And into that country of his choice and adoption one him. finds him unawares introducing the maxims of the one which he despised. As he listened, wearily and with forced interest, to the accounts of party affinities, club fellowships, alliances among leaders formed and broken, which were brought him by some favourite and admiring disciple, one can conceive how he was led to reflect on the way in which a whole is made up of certain portions that seem perfectly distinct, and which have a mysterious attraction for each other; how the loss of that attraction is what we mean by dissolution or destruction, how by it all things are preserved in life. Out of such reflections, Homceo- quickly transferred from the region for which he had an utter menie- distaste to the one in which he delighted to dwell, the theory of Homceumeriee, in which modern students have perceived the germs of important discoveries respecting the laws of cohesion, Political and may easily have developed itself. Pericles, we may be sure, natural- would at once perceive the human analogy of which his master had lost the sense, and though he might feel pleasure at being transported for a while into a world so different from that in which his ordinary work lay, and may have found his thoughts elevated by the clearer and rarer atmosphere which he breathed there, we cannot doubt how he applied the doctrine; where he Application looked for the similar particles which he was to combine. For ^ctrfneby that there must be a combiner, Anaxagoras also taught. The Pericles, mere cohesion of particles was not sufficient. As Aristotle observes, the particles could not be the cause of the change which took place in their position and relation to each other. 17. Nous (Intelligence) was called in to produce and maintain Nons. their fellowship—called in, the critic remarks, merely as 'scheme resource when the other expedient for solving the difficulty had of the been tried and failed. Be that as it may, the philosopher clearly univer8e- told the Athenians that " all things at first were in a heap; that Nous came in and set them in order" (turned a chaos into a universe) ; a doctrine which had been always latent in the Greek mind, of which the ^njrtera Zevg in Homer had been the indication which was implied in the Ionic search for wisdom amidst natural elements. 18. But if Anaxagoras had brought to light the principle connection which his countrymen half-unconsriously recognised, he had °™°idS>wth stripped that principle not only of certain confused sensual divinities, additions which they had made to it, but of all which had rendered it practically and vitally precious to them. This Nous, which had set the stars in order, what was it to them ? It was 102 GEE CLAN PHILOSOPHY. Anaxagoras. not Zeus ; not the acting, living ruler, taking part in human Athenian affairs and interests, whom Homer had brought before them, suspicions. ye£ ^ seeme(j £0 asgurDe all functions ; to do all the work which they had ascribed to him. Was this what they had meant; was there nothing else in their traditions and their hearts besides this ? The conscience of the Athenians answered that there was something besides this. But the answer was a confused muttering one, mixed with a painful suspicion that they did not habitually believe more than Anaxagoras told them ; Grounds for not generally quite as much as he told them. Out of that mixed impression, with the true indignation, the malignant hypocritical bitterness which the different portions of it engendered, an accusation of impiety against him naturally proceeded. Mixed Accusation with it was another, which Anaxagoras must have listened to of profoun(i astonishment. He was accused of Medism—a disposition to betray Athens into the hands of Persia. Probably the fact that there was such an empire as the Persian existing had escaped him, or only remained with him as connected with some geographical observation. But his devotion to the stars may have furnished those who wished to wound Pericles through the side of his teacher with a very plausible plea for representing Excuse forit. him as having Magian tastes and propensities. The charge of malignancy during the English Civil Wars, and of the Popish Plot—of incivmne during the French Bevolution—was esta¬ blished by evidence which can leave us and our neighbours little excuse for condemning the Athenian democracy, if they yielded to such proofs. Anaxagoras, whether condemned for political or religious offences, retired to Lampsacus, we are told, with a Bmile of regret that his countrymen had exiled themselves from him. He suffered less than almost any man would have suffered from the loss of home ties and affections ; the stars were to be His seen at Lampsacus as at Athens. It is difficult to feel all the ams men . gy^^y we wjsh for a victim to the injustice of men in whose welfare he took no interest, whose evils he had never sought to reform. section rv. PYTHAGORAS. bobn b.c. g08 ob 605 (beetle!) ; b.c. 570 (rodweix and clinton). Transition 1. We pass from the least political to the most political of all kinYof* Greek philosophers. The records concerning Pythagoras inquiry. which we possess, imperfect as they are, are important, not only as an introduction to the next division of our subject,—to the life of Socrates, and to the doctrines of Plato ; they also throw PYTHAGORAS. 103 light upon the Ionic school, out of which this eminent teacher arose—some members of which, Empedocles especially, confessed the greatest obligations to him. 2. The same traditions which speak of Thales as the first phi- The name losopher of Greece, affirm that Pythagoras first used the name, p^'"80" He dared not, we are told, arrogate to himself wisdom. That he held to be a divine possession; men could only love it and seek for it. Such modesty, in the judgment of some, is very inconsistent with the character of Pythagoras ; if he exhibited it, they say it must have been feigned. For he habitually claimed Belief in his a divine inspiration, he took to himself the credit of most un- insPiratlon* usual gifts. Could he have renounced a name which had been freely bestowed upon quite ordinary mortals ? 3. The answer to this question lies in his history. At pre- word "Phi- sent we shall only remark that the difficulty is not diminished, losopher" if, following other authorities, we suppose Socrates to have in- gttribXdto vented, as he pertinaciously adopted, the word Philosopher, in Socrates, the sense we have given it. Socrates also claimed to be under divine teaching, and, what is more remarkable, made that claim the very reason for renouncing the title of " wise man." The nature of the inspiration which Pythagoras believed was vouch¬ safed to him, we may consider presently; we only ask our readers not to judge of it or of him by the reports of fanatical admirers in the post-Cliristian period, or by the satires of Lucian of Samosata. 4. Pythagoras was born at Samos, in what precise year may His raaster be doubtful. Under what master he studied has been a subject aniihiseariy of great controversy; if we might venture to choose one guess studies- out of many, which may all be false or all true, we should take that which assigns his early training to Anaximander. That philosopher, as we have seen, carried his mathematical studies further than any of his predecessors ; his geometry in a great degree determined the nature of his theory. A youthful pupil of earnest character and high imagination, coming into contact with such a thinker, would be likely to experience a great con¬ flict of feelings. The science, new not only to himself, but in some measure to all around him, would seem to him strange, wonderful, sublime ; the doctrine appended to it would repel him as cold, vague, and unsatisfactory. He would begin, we may fancy, to meditate on his teacher's favourite phrases, " the In¬ finite"—ro aweipov—this forsooth is the sum of all things in the universe. A conclusion how unlike that which geometry would have suggested ! that leads us to the idea of limitation, distinct¬ ness, in each thing and in all things. And is not such limita¬ tion, such distinctness, that which constitutes their perfection ? Surely it is this, the iripag—the ultimate limit, and not the limitless, which the wise man is to seek after. Again, Auaxi- Arithmetic. 104 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. mander talked of an dp\>). Here, indeed, he has profited by his science. Mathematics did not teach him the necessity of this. He found every line starting from a point, every series beginning from a fixed number. " But why forsake the teacher ? Why go abroad to look for your beginning when you have it in the very instrument which you carry with you ? You Ionian philosophers are groping after unity in the world about you. But where did you get that idea? Was it not from these numbers, from this geometry ? Surely it is there that we find not the mere shadow of unity, but unity itself." Therbvipas. 5. Such thoughts we may fancy began to work in the mind of Pythagoras while he was yet among Ionians ; to excite in him a discontent with previous methods of inquiry, and a hope that he might discover a better. With these feelings we may sup¬ pose him to set out on his travels, his impulse to leave bus country being, it is said, the tyranny of Polycrates. He carried away another (perhaps a greater) benefit from his Asiatic edu¬ cation. The rhapsodists, who used to sing the legends of earlier days to the Greeks of that region in which Troy stood, and in which Homer or a number of Homers lived, these were perhaps silent. But not only their words were preserved, and by this time at least committed to enduring characters, but the melodies in which they had spoken still lived in the hearts of the people. Music. The impression of the Dorian and Lydian measures on a young Greek must have been very deep ; it might be effaced afterwards in some by the passion for abstract speculation, in others it would give speculation itself a richer and more poetical charac¬ ter. All the thoughts of Pythagoras respecting the mystery of number seemed to have combined themselves from the first with musical feelings and associations. Was not music itself an illustration, the highest illustration, of this mystery ? Whence came that strange disposition of thoughts and words into verse ? whence the fascination of melody and tune ? whence, if number be not the secret law, the moving soul of the universe ? Pythagoras 6. All these apprehensions and. imaginations might have dwelt a traveller. Jq mjnd and produced little fruit, or no better fruit than a crude philosophical system. But Pythagoras, as we said, became a traveller. The reports of the regions through which he journeyed are all uncertain. This at least we may conjecture with tolerable confidence, that he was brought into contact with human beings in a variety of different positions and circum¬ stances, and that he began to think more deeply of their nature and destiny. And then what with new interest, in what a new light, wouid the number-mystery present itself to him ! This surely was the very problem which all legislators had been seek¬ ing to solve,—in what way a number of apparently separate units might be able to feel themselves really a unity. All society, PTTHAGOEAS. 105 all government, was but the working out of this problem. Away- then once and for ever with all Iouian experiments after a physical unity ! here was the true field for examination and dis¬ covery. But what is it in man which has the capacity for asso¬ ciation and organization? It is not resemblance in feature which produces it; it is not contiguity in space which produces it. It is that wonderful thing which inhabits this animal frame —which can transport itself beyond all limits of space and time. I, Pythagoras, can carry myself back to the age of Achilles and Agamemnon ; doubtless in some condition or other I actually lived in their time. I can project myself forwards into ages that shall come ; doubtless under some condition or other I shall live in those ages. But in what condition ? This soul,' which can Metempsy- thus look before and after, can shrink and shrivel itself into an ch0S18, incapacity of contemplating aught but the present moment: of what depths of degeneracy it is capable ! what a beast it may become ! And if something lower than itself, why not some¬ thing higher ? And if something higher or lower, why may there not be a law accurately determining its elevations and descents ? Each soul has its particular evil tastes, bringing it to the likeness of different creatures beneath itself; why may it not be under a necessity of abiding in the condition of that thing to which it has adapted and reduced itself ? 7. Such thoughts Pythagoras may, or may not, have borrowed where he from Egyptian priests. Doubtless to a man in his posture oflearnt mind every old tradition, every relic of national faith, will have been precious; still there was nothing in the doctrine of a metempsychosis which might not easily and naturally have grown out of his reflections upon that which makes men human, and enables them as human beings to associate with each other. To another and deeper discovery he was no doubt led by study¬ ing the governments of different countries, especially those which had received the Dorian impress. He found everywhere in these communities that the bond of connection was the recognition of Law. a power superior to man, a righteous law-giving power. No human legislature ever dared to dispense with this recognition, no society could cohere without it. Deep and awful idea! The union of men presumes a still deeper ground. Is not this ground the 7r£pac, the ultimate unity, after which we are seeking ? 8. Thus gradually we suppose the idea of limitation, which Results of Pythagoras had acquired from geometry, and which had been 18 m<,uirJr* brought out in his mind in opposition to the notion of an all- comprehending Infinite or Indefinite ; and the idea of beginning and succession which he had acquired from arithmetic, and which had come out in his mind in opposition to the notion of a mere external ground of things, fused and softened as they both were 106 GEECIAN PHILOSOPHY. Wisdom above tbe soul. to the Pythago¬ rean philo¬ sophy. The society in South Italy. Its cha¬ racter and perils. by a sense of music dwelling deep in the heart of the world, may have become associated with practical thoughts respecting the nature of the human soul, and the bonds by which souls are related to each other. 9. The more this feeling of the sacredness and mysteriousness of human fellowship unfolded itself in the mind of Pythagoras, the more peril and evil he will have seen in the pretensions of men to wisdom. The destruction of order lay in such individual pretensions. Wisdom must be contemplated as altogether above the soul; as something which it cannot appropriate, to which it must do homage; which it must seek in silence, yet not in solitude; which each man must reverence for himself, but yet which he must feel is not his more than his fellows' ; which can only be truly pursued by those who are willing to abandon out¬ ward enjoyments for the sake of it. The philosophy of Pythagoras therefore could not be carried out except in a community of living men. 10. In the bonds by which they were held together in their dealings with each other and with men without—in the silence and fear with which they acknowledged an invisible ruler—was his inmost meaning to be expressed. Thus would the proportions and relations of the universe be manifested on their highest ground ; thus would the mystical harmony be felt and acknow¬ ledged; thus would the dignity of the human soul, its capacity for growth and perfeetionment, be proved; thus would the nature of distributive justice, the geometry and arithmetic of politics, be practically realised ; thus would the idea of God be felt as the foundation of social life. Such we apprehend was the feeling that led to the formation of the Pythagorean society, which grew up in the South of Italy ; which after all deductions for the ex¬ travagance of later reporters, must have exercised a great in¬ fluence on various cities of Magna Gnecia; which wrought legislative and moral reforms, engaged in political intrigues, and was finally put down as a dangerous religious confederacy, in¬ compatible with the existence of regular government. 11. In calling this society " an order," Bishop Thirlwall and Mr. Grote have done much to explain the secret of its strength and influence, as well as of its errors and its decay. The earnest seeker of wisdom found hearts yearning for it like his own. It was an inheritance intended for them and him: in proportion as they could make it the common object of their lives, they might hope to share it together. The lessons which they re¬ ceived from their master were not communicable except to those who formed the circle around him ; to others they would have been different lessons: apart from the practical discipline which accompanied them, they were not true; they served no purpose PYTHAGORAS. 107 of purification, they were not a method of seeking wisdom. The allegiance which men so associated pay to him who has given the first impulse to their minds, and who is directing all their energies, is affectionate, devout, dangerous. They are united by sympathies and reverence. A man is the object of their reverence and sympathy. If that man has felt deeply that Sense of a their union does not stand in any power or wisdom of his, he ^"teacher will tell them so continually; he will strive, by all the forms and arrangements of their polity, to preserve them in the recol¬ lection. But if he believes that what he teaches is not bis own, he must believe, and strive to make them believe, that it has been imparted to him ; he must regard his work as a vocation. The more he uses the language which expresses this conviction, the more it will be perverted by passionate idolatrous followers ; the more will his earnest desire to disclaim wisdom be made an excuse for maintaining that he possesses it under conditions al¬ together new and peculiar. How can that idolatry fail to react upon the object of it ? How can it fail to awaken in him a idolatry of vanity, a self-consciousness, a self-glorification, which have to d>sciPll;B- maintain a fearful struggle with the earnest truth-seeking, truth-loving temper which led him to say, " I did not choose this course for myself; I did not make this discovery. A mightier wisdom has guided me on my way, and showed me what I could never have found." The histories of such struggles are not written, or written very imperfectly, even in the auto¬ biographies and secret confessions of great teachers: another day may reveal them to us, with all the strange contradictions which have pnnoked our harsh judgments, and should have called forth our pity and sorrow. The outward results of the secret battles are better known, and are often very tragical. In the case of the Pythagoreans, we have only indistinct glimpses of them, but enough, with the experience we have since acquired, to show how zealous the society must have been to bring others within the circle of their light; yet how proud in their boast of enjoying that light by some exclusive tenure! how resolute they must have been not to separate their essential and moral prac¬ tices from their outward doctrines, yet how apt, in the vehe¬ mence of propagandism, to part with all inconvenient austerity, to tolerate and use the corruptions which they undertook to remove ; how their first object will have been to use their society as a means of making all society deeper in its foundations, truer in its acts; how at last they may have come to think that it had no deeper foundation than the Pythagorean rule, and that false and dishonest means might be legitimate for the establish¬ ment of that rule. Some traditions would represent the founder as forwarding the ambitious views of his order, as sharing in its 108 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. downfall. We have no means of testing their accuracy. If they are true, they need not make us doubt the sincerity of his purpose, nor the real worth of the principle for which he testi¬ fied. The failure of a noble scheme may make good the internal conviction of him who planned it better than its success. If Pythagoras believed that human society had a mysterious and divine ground, and that every true philosopher and reformer lives to convince it of that fact, it was fitting that he and his order should perish when he or they began to fancy that they could build up society by their devices, upon their wisdom. His name remained a sacred and venerable name for Greece. None might be able to tell in terms what it had done for them. Those who spoke of Pythagorean doctrines in earlier times meant the doctrine of Philolaus, Lysis, Eurytus, Arehytas,— men who knew nothing of the Italian master, who had never shared his discipline, who had been brought up amidst the ordi¬ nary influences of Greek society. Those who spoke of Pytha¬ goras himself in neo-Platonic times meant a Thaumaturgist whom they had created by mixing Christian and Pagan records together, to convince the world that the Christian church was a plagiarism. But Plato and Aristotle retained a reverence for the name of the original master, which they never transferred to the school where his opinions were dried for use and expor¬ tation. Iambliehus and Porphyry were bearing unconscious testimony to the fact that the best and wisest teachers of ancient Greece had been led by all their studies of nature and of man, and, as they rightly deemed, by some guide who was higher than either, to seek for a brotherhood which did not rest on human wisdom; that they tried to create one, and that they failed. section v. XENOPHAXES—PARMENIDES—ZENO. p°etry a"d 1. It has been observed before, that most of the Greek sages p • obop y. were p0e(;Si Verse seemed the natural language for thoughts which were to be a kind of oracles meant for the experienced ear, perplexing to the vulgar. When the wise man became the philosopher, he more rarely used this medium of communication. The mind of Empedocles was evidently rich and poetic : Anaxa- goras, Anaximander, Anaximenes, probably never departed from ordinary discourse. But in each, whether they used this vehicle or not, the suspicion began to arise, that the poet, so far as he answered to his name, so far as he was a Maker, was the anta¬ gonist of the philosopher. Homer had a hold upon the sympa¬ thies of the Greek, which the most profound student did not Destruction of the order desirable. The feeling about Pytha¬ goras m after times. XENOPHANES. 109 possess. "Whence did it arise ? Was it a wholesome influence ? Were not his creations hindrances in the way of the investigator ? Had he not assumed the result of an inquiry which thev were pursuing ? 2. The sense of this opposition reached its highest point in xeno- Xenophancs. He was, like Pythagoras, an Ionian by birth : he fl"uAr^g'd became, like him, an Italian colonist. He felt bitterly the B c luxury of his own city, Colophon. The manners, and especially 540-500. the love of amusement in the Greeks of Asia and of the islands, 01.60-70. disgusted him. He must have gone to Italy a discontented Education man,—discontented, probably, with the investigations of lonians, pj^ee"°" as well as with their political life. The example of Pythagoras, or his own reflections, will have taught him that what he wanted was not an element or apx>/- Hut he does not seem to have been much interested in geometry or arithmetic, or to have re¬ ceived any of the same deep impressions which Pythagoras received from music. The thoughts of Pythagoras respecting the soul of man and its migrations took no hold of him. In one of his fragments he ridicules a sage for not suffering a dog to be beaten because he recognised in his growl the voice of an old friend. 3. Neither does he seem to have had a desire to be the founder or the member of any political association. He may have heard of the dispersion of the Pythagorean society, and may have turned with dislike from similar experiments. His genius, how¬ ever, did not impel him in that direction. Social unity was not the problem which he sought to resolve. The problem which did present itself to him concerned unity, but in quite a diffe¬ rent sense. What are the gods in the Homeric poems ? Is Hisquestion there any reality corresponding to them ? Are they not formed thePgods!g by the poet's brain, and clothed by him in sensible forms and images ? Is it to sensible forms and images that our minds do homage ? Pythagoras had approached the last question, but from a different side and in a different spirit. He had recog¬ nised a Being near to man, to be adored in silence and awe. Such a Being had not much in common with the gods whom his countrymen worshipped; but he never denied that homage was due to them. Nor can his secret instructions to his disciples have been that this homage was only to be paid in deference to the opinions of the vulgar. They must have been efforts to make it more sincere and significant than it was with the majo¬ rity. Pjthagoras felt that he had no substitute to offer for the personal objects he had been taught to revere. He felt that some living being, not an abstraction, not a creation of his own mind, must sustain his and every human polity. 4. In Xenophanes all these checks to freedom of inquiry 110 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. The nature respecting the faith of his country were wanting. The naked answer question, " What does my soul affirm respecting God ; what conceptions can it or can it not form respecting Him ?" came before him. His verses—for he wrote in verse of various styles and measures—were answers to it. The philosopher tries as a poet to criticise the poets; to show that they have been making the beings to whom they bow down. All the Homeric gods have the shapes and forms of men ; why, but because men have formed them after their own likeness ? If an ox were to form a god, would he not give him horns and hoofs ? How is it possible to form any conceptions of God ? What mean your finite and your infinite? Are they not both alike terms of your own mind ? How can you make Him out of them ? sceptic may sound like scepticism ; but it was not scepticism in the mind of Xenophanes. He did not say that because the senses cannot tell us of God—because we cannot measure Him by our conceptions, therefore He is not. He said just the reverse: he said, " My senses do not tell me that which is; they only tell me of appearances. My conceptions do not mea¬ sure that which is; it lies deeper " Instead, therefore, of deny¬ ing that to be, of which he said the Homeric pictures presented no likeness, his disapprobation of them arose from his desire to assert a real ground of things, independent of man's conclusions or conceptions ; which he affirms to be, but which he does not make. A very wonderful process of thought indeed, pregnant with results which our future history must unfold. Xenophanes was But tbe no atheist, but a very earnest theist. He asserted a Being. If worshipped be had been asked " what Being ?" he would have owned that negation cou^ n0^ rc'IJly- He could only say what he was not. He approached the border of negation, but he approached it man¬ fully and reverently ; therefore he did not pass it. He pointed out a void which he could not fill. That alone would have been a reason for feeling gratitude to him. But he also saw the way to a deep and radical truth. 6. A healthier thinker than Xenophanes, yet one in whom it is not perhaps possible to feel the same interest, took up his nh^um" course of inquiry : this was Parmenides. The question respect- about ing the nature of God, w hich had so occupied the philosopher n.e. 536. of whom we have just been speaking, does not seem at all in 01. 61. the same degree to have agitated him. His mind rested on the principle of Xenophanes, that what the senses present to us are appearances ; that only that which the mind affirms without the aid of the senses actually it. "What is this, then, that the mind affirms? Xi-iinphanes had said " God."' Parmenides said The one. "Unity," or "The One." My senses tell me thousands of PAKMENIDES—ZE^O. Ill things, and yet has not every man who thinks and feels ever been groping after some one root and ground of all these things ? This, verily, is what man wants, and this is affirmed to be by that within him which tights against apparitions and phantoms. Plurality is merely one of these apparitions—deceitful, transi- Plurality an tory; nothing abides but unity : this is permanent, eternal. "PP*™110"* Such a belief could not dawn upon the mind of a Greek philo¬ sopher without imparting to him a feeling of deep wonder. He had seen a succession of Ionians questioning all nature to tell them of this unity. He had seen Pythagoras evoking it out of the relations of number, and actually constructing a human society to illustrate it. And now this unity declared itself to be a condition of the human mind itself—it had been seeking for that in all other things which really dwelt only with itself. The confused look of a child gazing upon a new world, is but a faint emblem of the surprise with which such a thought must have possessed the mind of an earnest seeker on whom it has just burst. Yet he cannot doubt that it is a true thought. It makes so much of all that had before been perplexed in his mind intelligible, it accounts so well for the thoughts which have revealed themselves to other men. But what consequences follow ? Paith in the things about us becomes impossible; we live in a shadow world; we do not, in fact, behold anything. For these distinctions of things, this apparent multitude of objects, exists not; it speaks to our fancy only. The unity which the mind beholds and demands, this only has substance. 7. Every one must see how this doctrine of Parmenides laid zkso, him open to the jests of witty men, such as grow upon the sur- face of all lands, and of which Greece and her colonies were cer- q'j ' tainly not less productive than others. These wits believed 110 His answer doubt that they were opposing self-evident facts to mere dreams. to the wits But Parmenides had a friend and disciple who was not willing experience' to leave them in undisturbed possession of this opinion. Zeno of Elea was convinced that there was not only positive falsehood, but direct absurdity in that doctrine which experience seemed so irresistibly to establish, and he boldly undertook to make this absurdity palpable to the popular mind. In a series of argu¬ ments, some of which are still preserved to us, he endeavoured to show that space cannot exist, that we cannot suppose a plurality of objects without attributing self-destructive qualities to them ; that if there be a number of real existences this num¬ ber must be both finite and infinite; lastly, that the notion of movement involves a contradiction. Our readers would not, perhaps, be much interested in these early specimens of Greek subtlety ; nay, they would be inclined to denounce them as the exploits of a mere word-conjurer. But assuredly Zeno deserves 112 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. no such name. He was both in action and speculation a brave man, and we owe to him a great practical discovery. In fact, he occupies a peculiarly important position as a thinker, which it is for the advantage of our future studies in Greek philosophy that we should understand. The Eicatic 8. Every philosophy must have an instrument or organ to or"un' work with if it would make itself intelligible. Some external object served this purpose for the Ionic philosopher ; lines and numbers for the Pythagorean. But what was the instrument of the Eleatic philosopher ? He seems to have ascended into a region of such pure metaphysic, and so entirely to have rejected all common and sensible analogies, that one does not at first see how he can ever impart his doctrine to others, or at least suggest any successful method of pursuing investigations in his own direction. This difficulty seems to have been felt by Xenophanes, and to a certain extent by Purmenides. Precious and pregnant as are the hints which each of them presents us with, it seems likely that they will be obliged to stop at the point which they have already obtained, and to leave no race of successors. But Zeno has found the solution of the puzzle; he has found that words bear to this philosophy the relation which sensible objects and numbers bear respectively to the other two. The language in which we discourse with each other must needs embody the law and principle of our own mental workings, and it was exactly this principle which the Eleatics were dealing with, zeno honest 9. Zeno had only an imperfect consciousness of this truth, words.1"* °f but he acted upon it, and it bore useful fruits for him and for us. There was no falseness in his use of words. He felt that they did affirm and embody truths, and he employed them for the purpose of elucidating truths. And herein he was surely as honest as those wits who set themselves to confute Parmenides and philosophers of his class by an appeal to experience. For they too profit by our belief in words. They awaken our con¬ sciousness to the fact, that the words which we speak bear on them an impress and image of the external world; and it is this consciousness which they rest upon as their real defence against the philosophers who set at nought the evidence of the external world. Zeno awakens our consciousness to the fact, that the words which we utter express something to which there is no counterpart in the external world, and he rests upon this con¬ sciousness to oppose the conclusions of those who set at nought the witness of their own minds. Both appeals are in themselves fair, and carry conviction with them. But the one merely con¬ vinces us of a fact which we took for granted previously; the other obliges us to perceive truths lying very near our inmost being, which were yet almost entirely hidden from us. ZENO. 113 10. But it is the practical discovery which was the direct Logic result of this search after an organ or instrument for the Par- lnenidean philosophy that obliges us to regard Zeno with most admiration and gratitude. Mathematical science we owe, ac¬ cording to the best historical evidence, to the East. And it entirely accords with the calm, contemplative, and yet sensual character of the Orientals, that this should have been their con- tribu ion to human knowledge. Bub the science of Logic, the science "w kieh declares, not what are the conditions to which external things are subject, but the conditions under which we ourselves speak and judge—this was of purely Greek invention. Xo other people had ever the subtlety to conceive the possibility of such a science, far less to ascertain its distinct province and its appointed work. Though logic, in a formal and narrow sense, is considered as the antagonist of poetry, yet only a most a Greek imaginative and poetical nation could have discovered the mean- dlscovery- ing and necessity of logic, and have given it the statue-like per¬ fection which it has attained in Greek hands. Now Zeno is believed, on the best grounds, to be the inventor of logic. He first was led clearly to perceive that the mind has a distinct law regulating its own allirmations, and he consequently was first stimulated to inquire what this law may be. How much we owe to him for this achievement we shall understand better as we advance. Our principal object here has been to point out the connection between it and the Eleatic philosophy, of which Zeno was the accomplished and able defender; to indicate the kind of influence which that philosophy exercised upon the mind of Greece; to show how important a place it fills in the history of human inquiry; and to excite our readers' interest in the future development of the doctrine which they have beheld in its first germ. In so very rapid a sketch as ours it is clearly impossible to do more than notice what seems to us the living ana central peculiarity of each thinker as he arises up before us. But the real germinant principle is often hard to discover amidst the multitude of mere notions and opinions with which it has environed itself. An historian "vnill distrust his own sagacity in detecting it, and will rejoice greatly if he can find it anywhere in its rude and primitive shape. Little value as it may seem to Value of have, nay, as it may actually have, while it remains in this con- schools/ dition, yet he deems it not wise to wait till the animalcule has become a perfect insect, or till the insect has died, before he commences his examination of it. We offer this apology for noticing the ante-Socratic schools, briefly indeed, but yet at a length which many may think disproportionate to the time that we shall be able to bestow upon their successors. We are con¬ vinced that our readers, whom we wish not to furnish with a VOL. I. I 114r GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. history, but to put in a right method of procuring one for them¬ selves, will have a clear or confused understanding of the palmy period of Greek philosophy between the age of Socrates and of Aristotle, as well as of the age of senility which followed, exactly in proportion as they study or pass over the years of its infancy. Let them not hope to understand Plato or Aristotle, or even Epicurus, Zeno of Cittium, and Carneades, if they have begun with despising Heraclitus, Pythagoras, and Parmeuides. Nay, we might go further, and say that we should greatly doubt the pretensions of any one professing to have a real acquaintance with Hobbes, Locke, Leibnitz, or Kant, who could discover nothing but confusion and barrenness in these early inquiries. DIVISION II.—GREEK PHILOSOPHY FROM SOCRATES TO ARISTOTLE. SECTION I. ATHENS IN THE TIME OF SOCRATES.—THE SOPHISTS. Tiie city of 1. If Greece was the country of wisdom and wise men, no Wisdom. Que jias eyer (Joubfced that Athens was in this sense the capital of Greece; that there Wisdom was worshipped with all her rites; that there wise men had an honour which was bestowed upon them in no other part of the world. The name of the city affected all the acts of the citizens; the meanest of them had some sense that the Goddess of Wisdom was his protectress, and that he had received some endowments from her. 2. As there is no dispute about this fact, so there is none that the age of Pericles was that in which Athens attained the glory she was always aiming at, that it was then all the powers of her sons reached their manho )d. The great statesman thoroughly understood the character of the people whom he ruled. The funeral oration which Thucydides puts into his mouth, mar not have been delivered by him iu the very form in which we receive it, but it expresses exactly that accurate perception of the Athenian mind which the historian knew that he possessed. Pericks; With the same dramatical propriety, if the speech be not a AtV<*mauf rePur^» he exhibits it as the settled purpose of Pericles, not to life. restrain the tendencies of this character, but to give them their full play and development. He would suffer no Spartan morose- ness to interfere with Athenian freedom. The corrections which it needed, so he believed, must be supplied from itself. Any attempt to introduce the maxims and habits of another (tribe would destroy the Athenian energy without really (imparting to it the Dorian self-restraint. ATHENS IN THE TIME OF SOCRATES. 115 3. AVhether this calculation were a right or a wrong one, the effects of it are memorable in the history of the world. Those to which we most naturally recur are the creations of the sculptors aud poets. The perception of the beauty and symmetry The scuip- of the human form which was awakened at that time, the images p,>etB: i,ow of the gods to which it gave birth, though they may have won the admiration and influenced the character of future generations, their con- must be considered in connexion with the processions and the te,nporaneB* temples of the people for whose use they were immediately designed. So again the works of the great tragedians, however much they may deserve the attention of solitary students, ought to be thought of as represented at the festivals, as rivals for a popular prize, as acted before delighted or critical crowds. Those which have lasted through all the changes of much more than 2,000 years, show with what deep thoughts concerning the destiny of man the minds of some Athenians were exercised. But they were mixed with multitudes of other works which were probably at the time not felt to be inferior to them ; they themselves were judged by their fitness to confer present amusement, by their adaptation to the varying demands of exceedingly clever, but also probably very impatient, spectators. The quickness and versatility of an author in creating that which should excite their sorrow or their mirth, would be the measure of his popularity, even though on the whole he who had thought and felt most would call forth the deepest echoes in their minds, and would ultimately obtain the greatest reverence. ^Eschylus and Sophocles towered above their contemporaries probably even in the judgment of the many, but the qualities which we admire in them must have been to a great degree for¬ gotten in the contemplation of the immediate effects which they produced. It was for after-times to discover how much there as in them which could not be exhausted iu any shows, and which did not belong to one age or to one nation, but to mankind. 4. Why, it may be asked, are such reflections more appropriate to the age of Pericles than to the age of James I. ? Were not Ben Jonson and Fletcher regarded chiefly as men who produced masques for the entertainment of the court—Shakspeare as an actor in the Globe Theatre ? Such a remark is true in itself; but there is a special need for a student of philosophy, most of all for a student of the life of Socrates, to recollect in what light all the great men in Athens, whose main instruments were words, appeared to their fellow-citizens at this time. They were all exercising some kind of wisdom; that wisdom was addressed in They pro- the theatre, or the agora, to a class of judges who were them- '(^/arYind selves wise and conscious of wisdom; able to appreciate it, of wisdom, able to bestow the rewards of it. The great tragedians, fixing their nfinds on the heroic agi% were able to preserve them- 116 GEECIAN MTLOSOrilY. Bel\Tes from making their own wisdom the creature of the mob wisdom. It required very high genius in a comic writer, whose business was with the present, to resist that in¬ fluence ; such a man would try to do it in a measure by choosing the most broad and conspicuous conceits and affectations of his age as objects of his ridicule. But the strongest temptation could not after all beset those who were using their \\ isdom for purposes of entertainment. Those who employed it for the direct object of persuasion, those who uttered words for the sake of leading their fellow-citizens to deeds, would he in a far more dangerous position for their own honesty, might be instruments of greater and more wide-spreading mischief. By degrees the kind of power which they exercised would become the measure of all others, The rhetorician would be regarded as the man who had ascertained the effectual use of words. Poets, statesmen, thinkers of all classes, even the commonest handicraftsmen, would gradually become rhetoricians ; it would be looked upon as the craft of the wise city. TheSoptiBts 5. It has been commonly supposed that there was a certain class of men, formed in the different cities of Greece, but always esteeming Athens as their head-quarters, who helped to keep alive this tendency in the minds of young Athenians, and to give it a very dangerous prominence. These men have been called Sophists ; from them especially the notion of the name as an evil name has been derived; it has been supposed that the main work of Socrates was to counteract and undermine their Mr. Grote's influence. Learned men have shared this impression with the arguments. vujgar. most modern and critical writers with mere nar¬ rators. [Recently these notions have been impugned with great skill, and apparently with a great weight of e\idence. The existence of a sophistical system has been distinctly denied. Those who are designated by the common name were unlike each other, it is said, in all their doctrines, pursuits, habits of life. They were not men to whom any corrupt purpose or an immoral character can be imputed; proofs of their respectability may be obtained from the books of their greatest opponents. They did not cause Athenian society to degenerate from the standard of past ages, for no such degeneracy is visible in the history. The opprobrious epithet Sophist was not such at all in Greek appre¬ hension ; it was only a synonym for the wise man ; it was con¬ ferred by impartial writers upon poets, upon philosophers, upon the supposed antagonist of sophistry himself. Plato and Aristotle have chosen to use it in a bad sense ; they had a right to their own definition; but they cannot give us a right to pronounce an ex post facto sentence upon their contemporaries. Finally, we may hold the object of the life of Socrates to be a decidedly good object, without blaming the different Sophists ATHENS IX TRE TIME OF SOCRATES. 117 whom h<* or his disciple blames. He aimed at a universal stan¬ dard of wisdom and truth; they professed only to teach Athenians how to think, speak, and act. These conclusions, if they are true, must affect the whole course of our after history. It becomes us therefore to consider how far they are borne out by the able arguments and undoubted facts which Sir. Grote has produced.1 G. We at once accept Mr. Grote's definition of the Sophist as The Sophist the Platonical and the true one. He was " the professor of of^wraT wisdom; he taught young men to speak, think, and act." We wisdom, wish for no other and no worse account of him. If modem artists have thrown any darker shades into their picture, we believe they have done him a benefit instead of an injury. Their clumsy exaggeration hides the essential ugliness which Mr. Grote's flattering sketch brings out in full relief. 7. They have, we conceive, been especially wrong in their The age of attempts to blacken the age of Pericles, as if it was, essentially |jjeJ££th,sts: and inherently, worse than any previous age. In many respects respects it was assuredly much better. Not only were all the intellectual f^erages energies of the people more developed, but their great writers displayed a moral insight and purpose which are not to be found in the older times or in their immediate predecessors. Who can deny that the tone of Thucvdides is much higher than that of Herodotus ? that there is a much deeper recognition of prin¬ ciple in the (Edipus Tyrannus than in the Odyssey—that even Aristophanes (though we may quite agree with Mr. Grote in refusing him the dignity of a moral teacher) yet tacitly acknow¬ ledges a standard in his satires upon bad citizens, which would not have been as readily perceived by poets or recognised by their audiences in the times of Solon and Pisistratus ? There had been a progress unquestionably in the minds of the better men in moral perceptions and apprehensions, a progress which could not have been found in them unless their contemporaries had been capable of the same. The political training and dis¬ cipline of the Athenians must have greatly contributed to this result; their experience of society and government led them to practical distinctions which, without it, would have been hidden from them. 8. Whatever we may think of the Athenian democracy, we cannot doubt that it rendered this signal service to the eminent men who lived under it, and through them to the world. Its corrupt maxims and practices are made known to us by the emphatic protests against them which have come to us in his¬ torical reflections and prophecies—in lessons from the past, in 1 Grote, vol. viii. cap. lxvii. 118 GEECIATT PHILOSOPHY. ridicule of the present. But the protests show us what the peculiar temptation of the Athenians was ; why they were more in whnt prone to it in this than in any former time ; what kind of influences were most certain to foster it. We have seen that a majority of the Greek wise men were tyrants (or despots, as Mr. Grote prefers to call them). The natural use of their wisdom was to obtain power—to make them fit for governing fools. Every Greek was inclined to hold this opinion. It grew in him with the growth of his faculties. Democracy afforded him an obvious opportunity of exercising them in this particular direc¬ tion. The Peloponnesian war suggested thoughts (which had been latent in the Persian) of rivalry between Greeks, of Athenian ascendancy, of the difference between forms of govern¬ ment. The passionate impulses of patriotism, which had their own characteristic dangers, had yielded to deliberate schemes and calculations respecting the method of obtaining rule and wielding it. There might not be more of evil-doing in the one time than in the other. There must have been more conscious¬ ness of evil-doing; more internal wickedness ; a greater readiness in bringing crimes under a theory, and in defending them upon that theory. This is the inference which the Melian controversy inevitably suggests. Make what allowance you please for the aristocratieal tendencies of the writer: it cannot be denied that an experienced and wise man imputes to his fellow-citizens such a distinct understanding of an evil purpose and principles as we do not meet with elsewhere, and yet such an understanding as we should, without his authority, have attributed to a people possessing the Athenian wit and subtlety, professors ^ ^at waa ^"antin£ f° give this wit and subtlety their an of full play, was, that a set of men should appear, starting from the schools.1 sarae maxim as the wise men in general had started from, but furnished with a set of instruments which had not belonged to them, and ready to teach the skill which they had used in a nar¬ rower sphere for their own advantage. The professors of whom we are speaking exactly answer to this description. They pos¬ sessed all the respectability which Mr. Grote claims for them ; were many of them aged and grave; were men of uncommon sagacity and penetration. They had studied in different schools. Some had learnt under Empedocles, some under Zeno. Some devoted themselves to physical studies, some to moral, some directly to political. Each possessed some sort of wisdom. Each undertook to teach that wisdom. Each held out the acquisition of political power as the prize to be obtained. There was their common point of agreement; possibly there was no other. The young Athenians wanted to learn how to think, act, ATHENS IN THE TIME OF SOCRATES. 119 and speak upon all subjects, that they might guide the people according to their pleasure. For this purpose they sought the aid of a Sophist or Professor. 10. It was very needful that the Athenians should learn to How they think. What was to be their teaching for this end F They must think,' l° be told about natural subjects, about moral subjects, about and political subjects, by men who had been at the pains to learn what Thales said about them, what Pythagoras said about them, what Parmenides said about them. They must be told about the views of ancient cosmogonists respecting the world and the gods ; about the views of modern thinkers and allegorists upon the same subject. They must hear about the Heraclitan flux, and the Parmenidean One: they must hear about the way in which cities were said to be built by the lyre of Apollo in former days, about the way-in which they had been held together by the skill or legislation of recent despots. All these different views they were taught to compare together—to see the greater strength of the one and feebleness of the other, or to combine and reconcile them. Thus the Sophist taught his pupils to think. But all thinking is for the sake of action. Our pro¬ fessors are thoroughly practical men. They do not come to withdraw us from the business or work of the world at all. What should we care for them in Athens if they did ? We want to know about men, not about the stars. We want to defeat Brasidas, or to support our party at home against Nicias, or to make ourselves rivals to Cleon, much more than to know anything about Heraclitus, or Parmenides, or Zeno. Well! But the one learning is the way to the other ; for remember what comes between thiuking and acting; remember what Homer says of " winged words remember that these have been with Greeks always " the great engines of government, the proximate cause of obedience." If we teach you to speak, we teach you in the most efficient manner to act. These different physical, and meta¬ physical, and moral theories, will furnish you with topics for speaking ; they will be the tools of your trade ; they will give you a wonderful power of embarrassing, confuting, overawing an uninstructed opponent. All may serve this end. Theories about the order and formation of the world in the skilful hands of Hippias may make as good a rhetorician as direct moral teaching from Prodicus, or speculations upon government, human or divine, from Protagoras. All will supply topics; all will be instruments of persuasion. And then see what power Zeno has put into our hands! AVords you see may mean the most opposite, the most contradictory, things. If you could be taught the secret of this contradiction, and how to turn it to account, would not this be invaluable lore ? 120 grecian philosophy. speech the 11. In the last paragraph we have just hinted at the modern chief thing. meaning of the word Sophist, which Mr. Grrote bo indignantly repudiates. Unquestionably it is not the meaning. The one which our historian has substituted for it is far more comprehen¬ sive and satisfactory. But by the necessity of his calling, he who taught to think, to act, to speak, would come to regard the last part of his profession as that which included both the others. He would become a rhetorician and a teacher of rhetoric. For that purpose he must deal with the subtle meanings of words ; whether honestly, as Zeno did, or treacherously, would depend upon the object which he proposed to himself. If that object was to influence the mind of a mob, he was at least in consi¬ derable danger of leading his pupils to give the word sophistry that force with which we are most familiar.1 12. We cannot think, then, that accomplished scholars and honest men, like Bitter and Brandis, are fairly charged with imposing upon their less-instructed readers when they use such a phrase as " Die Sophistik" to express their feeling that there was an art which was practised by all the ditferent professors of wisdom in the age of Pericles. Such an opinion does not in the 1 As we have admitted the respectability of the Sophists generally, it is not necessary to consider the arguments which Mr. G-rote has brought to prove that respectability in each particular case. But one of his statements, upon which he places much reliance, requires a short notice. Prodieus, he thinks, can be shown by more tlian negative evidence to be not an immoral, but a highly moral, teacher. The story of the Choice of Hercules, in the form in which we commonly read it, claims him for its author. What more decided proof ran be given that he urged upon the Athenian youth a severe, even an ascetiral, self-restraint ? We have no wish to dispute the beauty or the worth of that fable. It must have been full of instruction for that age, since it has been found full of instruction for all ages. But we submit that the effect of the lesson which it inculcates is good or evil according to the object which the reader of it proposes to himself. If he wishes to acquire the power of draining marshes and killing noisome beasts, all must ble-s him for not yielding to the voice of the Goddess of Pleasure. If he merely seeks to be the strongest of men, by resisting the enchantress, it might have been better for the world and for himself that he should have yielded to her blandishments. Mr. Grote is not likely to have forgotten the celebrated paradox of Gibbon respecting the clergy, " Their virtues are more dangerous to society than their vices." On the hypothesis which Gibbon no doubt adopted, that this order is divided into those who deny themselves for the sake of obtaining dominion over their fellow-creatures, and those who yield to animal indulgences, his dictum may be easily admitted. The monk who restrains his appetites that he may be more followed and idolised as a con¬ fessor, does more barm to others, is probably more evil in himself, than the sleek abbot who is given up to his hawks and hounds. The principle is of •universal application. We must know whether Prodieus departed from the general rule of the professorial class, by not holding out political power as his prize, before we can pronounce liim a useful teacher, because be told his pupils how they might obtain the bone and nerve of Hercules. ATHENS IN THE TIME OF SOCEATES. 121 least interfere with the fact that the word Sophist may have been applied to a poet, to any person who exercised an influence through words rather than swords,—to Thales, to Pythagoras, to Socrates. Astrology has an undoubted meaning,—most per¬ sons think a bad meaning ; yet, is an astrologer more than one who studies the stars ? Why should not the man who studied them with the most ample intention of ascertaining the laws by which their courses are regulated have been called an astrologer as well as any one of the innumerable doctors who determined from the stars the events which were to occur in the political world ? These traders in natural knowledge did not form one school or guild, any more than the Athenian professors; they had their different maxims; they were rivals ; they were ene¬ mies : yet it has been usual to think that they had a common work, which may be denoted by a common name. And every man who claimed to be an astronomer, and not an astrologer, was bound to make good his claim by the labours of a life, to show wherein he differed from him who cast nativities. By doing so, he must put a stigma upon a name which was not necessarily evil before; he must acquire a name for himself which was in some sense new. He will have the ultimate compensa¬ tion of vindicating the fame of many a worthy predecessor who had not been distinctly conscious of his own end, but who had honestly sought for light when others were boasting that they possessed it and could turn it to account. Till he has accom¬ plished his task he must be content to bear the same reproach with those whom he is most opposing ; from whom he is seeking to deliver his fellows. 13. There were many at this time who scorned and ridiculed Thede- the young men of Athens because they frequented the teaching Sop™sts of one or another Sophist, and because they exhibited the effects — Amto- of the teaching in their self-conceited words and acts. Aristo- PhaueB»&c- phanes, above all, could teach these young men to laugh at themselves—at their own thoughts, speculations, imaginations— as well as at those of their teachers. In doing so, he expected perhaps to restore the habits of an older, and, as it seemed to him, a simpler method. Neither reason nor evidence wan-ant us in believing that his success was proportioned to his zeal or to his genius. He may have abated some of the nuisances which were infesting Athens; he may have diminished the race of sycophants, have made the vulgar kinds of mob-persuasion less effectual, have even done something to abate the litigious spirit of his fellow-citizens; but he can have helped very little to root out that which was the real cancer of the nation's being,—that which fed upon the hearts, not of the worst, but of the best, and noblest, and most 122 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. promising of the Athenian youth. No one could apply any sound remedy to this evil who despised the age into which ho was born,—who merely saw the effects of the sophistical poison, without understanding its nature and the constitutions on which Reformer ^ was working- only could hope to reform the young men of Athens who could heartily and affectionately sympathise with them, who did not express his contempt or indignation for their favourite teachers, but was ready to follow them through all their windings and subtleties,—who, without for a moment forgetting the purpose of finding his way back to realities, could yet grapple fearlessly with the most shadowy and impalpable abstractions. A man of this kind would have sore difficulties to encounter, through which nothing but the clear perception of his object could possibly lead him unhurt. His inward con¬ flicts, before he could be fitted for his task, must be severe ; of his outward, the greatest, perhaps, would be this: that his pur¬ pose would be infallibly misconstrued by those who were aim¬ ing, with very different instruments indeed, to resist the same evils. It would be inevitable that he would pass with them for one, perhaps the subtlest and most mischievous, of the sophis¬ tical class. Because he sought to make men feel that there was no resting-place in any of their theories or opinions, he would be suspected of universal scepticism; because he led them to feel that they were not without a ground to stand upon, if they would seek for it, he would be accused of undermining the ground on which their forefathers stood; because he endeavoured to look through the clouds which had been drawn up from the earth, into the serene heaven that lay behind them, it would be fancied that he invoked their protection and did them homage. Such a man was Socrates, and this was his fate. He was hated by Sophists, and ridiculed as the worst of them. He treated the diseases of his country according to a method exactly the opposite of that which Aristophanes adopted, and therefore he was denounced by Aristophanes as the great promoter of them.—We have now to consider what his method was, how it affected his own age, and what traces it has left of itself for subsequent generations. SECTION II. SOCRATES. BORN OL. 77, 4; B.C. 468. Socrates. p. There is little doubt that Socrates was the son of a statuary and a midwife. He was born in a little burgh of Attica. When he came to Athens we know not with any exactness; probably about the commencement of the Peloponnesian war, when SOCRATES. 123 Pericles was still living and Anaxagoras teaching. He frequented the school of the latter. Nor is it at all unlikely that he must His first have entered with considerable ardour into the studies of his teacher- master, and may have carried away from him many valuable hints. 2. Anaxagoras, as we have seen, was at the furthest remove he did from the trading Sophists of his day. Political life was with a student of them everything; with him it was nothing. He sought to dwell Na,ure- apart from the world of human beings, to find a home in the world of nature. It was surely a noble experiment. If young Pericles felt it to be so, though the desire of his life was political ascendancy, young Socrates, who never evinced that desire in any period of his life, would, one might have thought, have been carried away by it. But he could not find a country where Anaxagoras sought for one. As he listened to the sublime physical speculations of his master, he seems to have asked him¬ self, " What are all these to me ? Let atoms be connected by what law of affinity they will; let them whirl at random througn space, or be guided by an intelligence ; still the question remains, What am I ? They do not help to answer this question. But in some way or other it must be answered. Any carpenter or shoe¬ maker who can put me in the way of solving this problem would be my benefactor. The profoundest teacher whose thoughts are turned in another direction is not the man I want." The school of Anaxagoras therefore was forsaken. There was something very inviting in its quietness; but if that quietness was to be obtained by the sacrifice of human feelings and interests, the gossip of the Agora, the bustle of the Pirams, was better. 3. Socrates then was, like the Sophists, a man of business and ^^etfome action. His wisdom, if he had any, must, like theirs, be directed a professor to that which was passing around him, not to that which was ofwis,lwm- going on in some other sphere. But had he wisdom which was available for this purpose? Could he communicate knowledge about things on earth, or things in the skies ? The more he considered, the more he found that he was not a possessor of wisdom ; that it was the very thing which he needed. He could not put it into the hands of a set of disciples to use it and traffic with it. He must go in search of it. The distinction between the Sophist, or wise man, and the philosopher, had dawned upon Pythagoras, perhaps upon Thales; it became the cardinal dis¬ tinction in the mind of Socrates. To possess wisdom, to profess it, would be for him at least the most utter falsehood. He did not find that he could lay down theories or maxims about the commonest things. What he needed was to understand them ; and this, that he might understand himself, that he might find out what ground he had to stand upon; whether he had any, or was only floating in the air. 124 GBECIAX PHILOSOPHY. The Dmrinn 4. "Who can assist him in this inquiry? It was one which of Socratta. concerned his own very self; that which no eye could see, chat which lay beneath all utterance, all thought. There was near him (as Socrates believed) one who did take cognizance of the most secret movements of his mind and will, who reproved him, restrained him, warned him. A divine teacher was with him at all times. Though he did not possess wisdom, this teieher could put him in the road to seek for it, could preserve him from the delusions which might turn him out of that road, could keep his mind fixed upon the end for which he was to act and live. Xenophon asks with plain, soldier-like honesty, whether his accusers could believe that he told a lie about this matter, and hints that it would shake his faith in all reality, to suppose that the mind of a man so clear-sighted aud free from superstition could be the victim of an utterly false impression, or that it could produce the wholesome effects which he himself had witnessed. We believe that Socrates told no lie about his Daemon; that it was precisely this faith which kept him from lying; which was the cause of his clearness of sight and his freedom from super¬ stition. The eod at ^is guide or teacher Socrates connected with the mythology Delphi. of his countrymen. He seems to have interpreted the one by the other. He was sure that there was such a teacher of him¬ self; he could acknowledge, therefore, a teacher of wisdom to Greeks and men. Much that was said about the god of Delphi might seem to him profane; he turned from it with disgust. But on the whole he believed much more, not less, than his countrymen believed, and he shrunk from the scepticism and irreverence which they and their poets ventured to indulge in. He had no notion of substituting a Xous or Intelligence for Jupiter or Apollo. It would have been altogether strange if he had done so, since he was not accounting for the existence of the universe, but craving for a light to show him his own path through it. He was not, therefore, a Mnuotheist in the sense in which some ha\e represented him as being so; he did not affirm that there were not various objects of worship. In many acts of his life he confessed them. But as he felt that there was one teacher, one source of light and wisdom, who was leading him out of the contusions and bewilderments of sense, he was Eracti cully more of a Monotheist than he could have been if he ad tried to reduce the traditions of Greece into physical specu¬ lations, or had treated them as mere follies. His calling. 6. Socrates spoke of his D;emon as reproving and restraining himself; but since he connectjd this Diemon with the gods of his country, he felt of course that other men bad also a director whom they were to obey, and who could lead them to the object SOCEATES. 125 which he sought. Instead of being a solitary thinker, he had the most interna sense of a vocation to help and instruct others. Though he could not give them wisdom, he might put them into the same way of seeking it, in which he was striving to walk himself. 7. What charms he used to draw a circle about him may seem Hischa- at first inexplicable. Most of the Sophists were men advanced in age and reputation when he first appeared in Athens. They promised to fit men for being politicians, orators, generals, and offered very plausible evidence to prove that they could do what they promised. He promised nothing. He was come, he said, to exercise his mother's profession on behalf of those who had thoughts of which they wished to be delivered. You could not understand what line he took; whether he was a philologer, like Prodicus, or a professor of statesmanship, like Protagoras ; he seemed to be all things by turns, and nothing definitively or constantly. Personal gracefulness and beauty were great recom¬ mendations among the Athenians: he had large projecting eyes, like those of a bull, a flattened and upturned nose, a protuberant stomach; he wore a tattered cloak, and was seldom seen with sandals. Nevertheless, the youth of Athens began to flock about him ; they thought that he had something to teach them; per¬ haps that by some means or other he would be able to impart to them the art of governing better than the more regular doctors. It is impossible to say that some of the causes which we have mentioned as likely to alienate his countrymen may not them¬ selves have contributed to this result. The Athenians liked a humorist, and a humorist Socrates, by his outward negligences, as well as by the whole tone of his discourse, showed himself to be. Moreover, he had a most hearty, genial way of interesting himself in whatever interested those with whom he was mixing; as little of solemn quackery as was ever found in the composition of any man. Add to this that he was a thorough, genuine Greek ; Greek in all the habits of his mind, Greek in his taste for society, Greek in wit and argument, Greek in a brave un¬ flinching love for his own land, Greek in making freedom (to a much greater degree than is usually observed or acknowledged) the passion and end of his life. But all these circumstances together could not have availed to counteract the many disad¬ vantages under which he laboured, if he had not possessed the real magnet which must draw the hearts of young men after it, be they never so reluctant—a knowledge of the thing which they are really wanting, and which they have been toiling in vain to find. 8. Political power was, as we have seen, the one prize which H'9 the Sophists proposed to themselves and held out to their pupils ia ogues' 126 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. as the reward of all the trouble which they bestowed upon abstract speculations. Now, though there were different roads to this end, and though each teacher believed himself, and in¬ duced his disciples to believe, that his was the shortest, yet one method was common to them all; all sought to acquire power by meaus of words. The mastery over words was the great art which the Athenian youth was to cultivate; his own feelings, and an observation of what was passing every day in his city, told him that there was a charm and fascination in these which the physical force of an Oriental tyrant might vainly try to com- Hnw pete with. It seems to have been the first observation of usetTthem ^ocrafes when he began earnestly to meditate on the condition of his countrymen, that in this case, as in most others, the tyrants were slaves; that those who wished to rule the world by the help of words were themselves in the most ignominious bondage to words. The wish to break this spell seems to have taken strong possession of his mind. But the wish would have been ineffectual, and would only have interfered with the main feeling of his life, if he had not been able to connect the study of words with that deep question respecting his own being of which we spoke just now. As he reflected, he began more and more clearly to perceive that words, besides being the instru¬ ments by which we govern others, are means by which we may become acquainted with ourselves. In trying really to under¬ stand a word, to ascertain what was the bond fide meaning which he himself gave it, he found that he gained more insight into his own ignorance, and at the same time that he acquired more real knowledge, than by all other studies together. In this work he knew that he was really honest; he was feeling for a ground; he was breaking through a thousand trickeries and self-deceptions. If, thtu, he was to deliver his countrymen from that miserable shallowness into which they had been betrayed by the ambition of wisdom and depth,—if he was to lead them out of the multitude of systems above morality into any firm feeling that there was a morality,—above all, if he uas to rescue them from the worship of power,—this must be his means. He must not stop to canvass the wisdom of this proposition or that. He must not deuounce with great moral indignation some that struck him as very mischievous or outrageous. He must not candidly and generously concede the truth and wisdom of those which seemed to him plausible or reasonable. But in every case he must lead his disciples to inquire what they actually meant by the words of the propositions which they were using, and must consider no time wasted which they honestly spent in this labour; no perplexities or contradictions dangerous which started out of their own minds in the course of it. SOCRATES, 127 9. No doubt this would be a most irritating, vexatious course His of proceeding. No doubt an opponent who had adopted a cer- eleucl,us- tain proposition, and was provided with abundance of arguments in defence of it, would be tortured beyond measure by finding himself not fairly encountered upon those arguments, but led back into a question which he had assumed, forced to give an account of a word which he fancied every one was agreed upon, and not permitted, after all, to bring any of his own resources into play. It was most perplexing for a disciple who had come expecting that a certain doctrine would be either established or refuted, and, perhaps, that the ingenious arguments on both sides of the question might serve his purpose in a popular assembly, to find that he got no decision either way, and, more¬ over, that he himself had been talking all his life in a language which he did not understand, and using words as if they were algebraic characters. Yet in some way or other the Sophist was taught that he was in the presence of one stronger than himself. He might chafe and fret, and complain that he had been treated with great unfairness. He could not say that his opponent had not got the better of him in his own word-fighting ; he could not say that all the scepticism which he had brought into play against the common thoughts and feelings of his countrymen and of mankind had not been made to tell with tenfold force upon himself; he could not help owning and feeling that there was one in conflict with him who had some other end than the mere exercise or display of power, and yet who did possess a power before which his own quailed. On the other hand, the disciple, amidst all his bewilderment, will have gone away with a feeling that he (perhaps for the first time in his life) had actually learned something, and with a conviction that if there be not something better than the attainment of dominion over other men's minds, there is at least a most important and indis¬ pensable preliminary to it, unless we would have our own the sport of every deceiver. 10. The infinite humour and vivacity of Socrates must of His irony, course have been of the greatest service in such dialogues as these. But oftentimes his opponents will have fancied that he was merely indulging his humour when he was, in fact, follow¬ ing out his principle. The practice of confessing his uncertainty or his ignorance upon any subject that was presented to him, v, hich formed in their eyes the chief element of his " irony," was not always or generally affected. We make no doubt that he often entered upon a discussion without knowing whither it would lead; actually, as he professed, hoping to be a learner by the result of it. He was certain, not of a particular conclusion, but that his method was a sound one, and that it would conduct 128 GRECIAN PHILOSOrnY. each person who followed it to clearness and truth. It is pro¬ bable that his discoveries respecting himself and his fellow- creatures were the practical fruits of this method. For instance, Recollection it was by repeated experiments that he convinced himself of the immense importance of the habit of recollection ; how the mind that wants it is at the mercy of all accidents; how the mind that possesses it is continually realising its own possessions, receiving them as if they were then for the first time bestowed. Upon this principle the greatest part of his moral discipline depended. The necessity of removing the impediments to recollection, of leading the mind away from mere sensible images and impres¬ sions into an examination of its own treasures, was the purpose and ground of it. But this principle was redeemed from any Brahminical tendency by his habitual use of words and sensible images as the means whereby a man feels his way into the principles and grounds of his being. It is in trying to under¬ stand all common things—what the carpenter does with his wood, the shoemaker Avith his leather, the mason with his stones, —it is by really getting to know what we intend when we talk of all these things, that a man learns to understand himself. It was not therefore to an escape from common life, from daily business, that the withdrawment or recollection of Socrates pointed. It formed the habit of seeking out in everything that which it really is, and not merely its shapes, and appearances, and accidents, which the man is to cultivate, and which is ulti¬ mately to fit him for perceiving that which is deepest and truest. Flow, it is the faith attained by repeated proofs and trials, that man has that in him which does desire to find out the truth of things; and again, that he has an inclination to be constantly conversing with the mere images of things, and that just so far as the first of these tendencies is kept uppermost, and subordi¬ nates the other to it, he is in his honest sound position ; and that just so far as the lower tendency is uppermost, he becomes a mere shadow-pursuer and shadow-fighter, which is the soul of foundation ®0cra^es s doctrine. It was not adopted as a scheme to sup¬ plant another scheme ; he stumbled upon it as a fact which he could no more gainsay than any one for which he had the evidence of his senses—a fact which was, let it be explained as it would, and must be recognised in all our dealings with our¬ selves or with other men. Aicibiades H- There was one young man in Athens whom Socrates theAtheidan reSarded w^h an intense affection. In him the qualities of the character. Greek were exhibited in their highest perfection. Creati\re power, skill in the management of words, personal beauty, fascination of manner, were all united in him. The love which Socrates bore him shows how thoroughly he sympathised with SOCRA.TES. 129 the feelings which he regarded with most fear, and in which he saw all possibilities of evil. If Alcibiades could have learnt to see that there was a right and a wrong—that to walk in a line, not to devise one—to perceive, not to create—is man's business, the a\ hole history of Athens might have been different. No doubt there must have been critical moments in the life of this youth, when he confessed to himself that there was something that was more worth seeking than dominion. No doubt there were moments when the feeling that he too had a guide and monitor within him whom he might obey, was stronger than the sense of power and the inclination to wrong-doing which accompanied it. But Ahriman prevailed over Ormuzd : Alcibiades yielded to the darker power within, which was tempting him continually to glorify his own intellect—to use the mighty gifts which had been entrusted to him, for the destruction of his country and of himself. Then all the skill which he had seen his master exercising in word-fighting became his curse. It was an instrument of mighty mischief in his hands. Having once parted with the moral purpose at which Socrates was aiming, that which he received from him became indeed sophistry of the wor-d kind. It taught him to act more effectually upon the maxim, that all order and society had been invented some time or other by the strongest or the cunningest, and that what they invented the} could pull down. 12. This, says our recent historian of Greece, was not the The mere sophistical teaching. The Sophists merely intended to fit soC"ates Athenian young men for the purposes of civil life. Their aim was miarht pr»t • not so high a one as that of Socrates, but it was far from a bad mischievin ' aim. "We believe that Socrates would have answered, "Either it is this aim that I am setting before myself, or it must be a bad aim. All my own teaching, my own influence, if it has not this aim, is bad teaching, bad influence. My elenchus is nothing better in itself than the logic or rhetoric of any other professor. If it is merely taken up as a more skilful or ingenious art, it will be worse; for its purpose is to lead men into the apprehension of that which is—to silt and separate that which is from its shapes and counterfeits, from that which is not. The Sophists are destroying the heart and soul of my countrymen, because they are continually leading them to think that what they want is an art which shall enable them to do or to make, when what they actually want is a science, a means of seeing that which they did not make, that which lies beneath all our doiugs, which is at the root of our ownselves." 13. From this statement it will be seen in what sense know- Knowledge ledge seemed to Socrates the basis of morality. Those who ienwtUie suppose that he meant to exalt the human faculties and to make basis of 1 virtue. 130 GEECIAN PHILOSOPHY. them the grounds of virtue and of truth, do not merely mistake, but invert his meaning. To destroy the worship of power, and especially of intellectual power, may be said to have been the purpose of his life. And in nothing did he show this more than in his doctrine respecting the relation of knowledge to morality. As the outward eye sees certain objects, and is good for nothing except as it sees them, so the inward eye perceives certain objects, and is good for nothing except as it sees them. The objects are there. It is the whole blessing of the man to behold them ; as he beholds them he is like them, but they are, not the variable functions of his mind, but the eternal, unchangeable principles and grounds of it. A notice of Socrates is only an occasion for indicating this faith ; in speaking of his great dis¬ ciple, we must strive to expound it. Socrates the 14. Socrates then was, we conceive, as he said himself, a philo- aPph!io-ea °f s°pher> a philosopher and nothing else—a philosopher in the up her. most strict sense of the word—a philosopher who helps us better than any one else to know what philosophy is. He never imagines that his philosophy contains or provides its own object. He is the wisest of men, as the oracle said, because he knows nothing; that is to say, because he brings nothing with him, but acknowledges or recognises that which presents itself to him. When he speaks of the dignity of the philosopher, he means us to understand the dignity of a man who does not exalt himself, who does not put himself in the way of the thing which he is examining, who has the simplest, most open eye for receiving light, whencesoe ver it shall come. That there is a source of light from whence it does come, and that this light is connected with man, is a principle assumed, if it is ever so imperfectly developed, in all his words and acts. •rhe con- 15. How can such a man, it has often been asked, have been 'If Socrates compelled to drink hemlock ? Must not the restored democracy natural. of Athens have been worse, and more intolerant, than any power which ever existed on the earth P Mr. Grote answers, we think, most reasonably, that the wonder is how such a man should have been suffered to go on teaching for so long. No state, he adds, ever showed so much tolerance for differences of opinion as Athens. We would make an addition to this statement. If it had been possible to regard Socrates merely as an utterer of peculiar opinions, as one of the Greek Sophists or professors, he might still have taught with impunity. Anytus and Meletus might have had their own special causes of dislike to him; his connexionwithCritiasorAlcibiadesmighthaveawakenedsuspicion in different minds; the ridicule of comedians might have kept up an habitual prejudice against him ; but the tolerance of the Athenian people would have triumphed. He would have been S0CEAXE3. 131 acquitted on the count of corrupting the minds of the youth, as well as on that of introducing new daemons. But there always has been, and always will be, a limit to the indulgence of those who regard all opinions as equally possible. If a man positively denies that he is proclaiming an opinion, if he speaks of the pos¬ sibility of knowing, of the duty of distinguishing, of a truth which men do not create, and which does not change with the changes of our intellect—he comes under quite a different category from the promulger of opinions ; he is not entitled to the same mercy. Tolerant people, on the very ground of their tolerance, The feel bound to silence or to crush him. "What business has he to Athemans insult the opinions of other men; to tell them that there is aiVopinions, something which it is dangerous for them not to see; that there °^k°fraof are falsehoods clinging to their lives which they ought to cast truth, off ? It is long indeed before a thoroughly good-natured man can persuade himself that any one has reached this height of criminality. All pity will be shown to his fanaticism as long as it is> possible. He will be treated in spite of himself as a sectarian teacher propounding a particular opinion. But if he continues with incurable pertinacity, as Socrates did, to assert that he is not a Sophist, not the putter forth of a certain theory, it is evident that tolerant men must—experience shows that they will—resort, though reluctantly, to the same racks, dungeons, and poison-cups, which bigots are wont to employ. For it comes to this: if the teacher is right in what he says, he must be regarded as a public benefactor; the city must honour him above all its citizens. When the judges had condemned Socrates to death, they asked hiin, according to Athenian custom, what milder sentence he would propose for himself. He answered, " A public support in the Prytanmum." Though they might be offended at his audacity, their consciences told them that this was the real alternative. Not being prepared to take it, they allowed the sentence to be executed; so assuredly choosing a course immeasurably more honourable to Socrates, and more in¬ structive to after ages. 1G. We must be careful of separating the discourse of Socrates nie after his condemnation from the course of his life whicli pre- ceded it. His faith in a future state is often put forward as a immortality characteristic which distinguished him from the rest of his coun¬ trymen and of the pagan world. Now, no one refers more frequently than Socrates himself to the old stories which express this faith ; to JEaeus and Rhadamanthus, the functions that were attributed to them, the souls upon which they passed judgment. Evidently he believed that the essence of these stories was true; that they did set forth the fact of a enrr< spondetiee bit ween tl e condition of men hereafter and their condition here. As iu nthc* 132 OnEClAX PHILOSOPHY. cases, lie received the teaching of those who had cone before him; but he asked himself what that teaching meant, and how it concerned him. His countrymen believed that, somehow or other, they should he judged hereafter by what they had done here; that some particle of themselves would suffer a vague punishment or enjoy a iague happim..*. He was fixed in the conviction that a man's blessedness consists in knowing that which is, in having his soul engaged i 1 the pursuit of thi-. know¬ ledge ; that his misery consists in being without it, in ht ing given up to dreams and unrealities. He hoped that what he had desired to know here he should know ; he sought for arguments to convince himself that, however the accidents which surrounded him might change, he himself should continue, and being more disengaged and purified from the corruptions and restraints of which he had been conscious here, should he able to comerse with the perfect Wisdom and (loudness. Socrates did not tell his disciples that his future life was to be separate frotn his life here; it was the continuation and unfolding of that life which he looked for. He felt that his eyes had been partially opened, that they would he opened more perfectly, that he should sti 1, and always, be a seeker after wisdom ; but that wisdom would meet him and embrace him, and ever reveal to him new treasures, which would awaken in him ever fresh longings, and would con¬ tinually satisfy them. The seeker of wisdom, who passed here for a pursuer of shadows, would grasp substance; the seeker of wealth and power, who passed here for a pursuer of substance, would grasp a shadow. ^rmtes yj "jhe hints which we have thrown out may, we think, ciuuds. enable our readers to reconcile the three documents which we possess concerning the life of Socrates. If we look first at the Aristophanic portrait, we shall find that it is indeed a broad and extravagant caricature, but drawn by a consummate artist, who, even in distorting the expression of his original, shows that he has studied it. We could not consistently bestow this praise upon him if he had, as some of his commentators pretend, represented Socrates as a natural philosopher. But the name of the play of which he is the hero is almost the only excuse for such a notion. And who that knows anything of the genius of Aristophanes, or of the delicacy of the Athenian taste, will suspect him of perpetrating, or his audience of tolerating, the wretched conceit that a man worships the clouds, because he is fond of gazing at the stars ? Far rather the airy nymphs whom the philosopher is said to have substituted for the gods of his country, are the patronesses of those attempts to catch the thin, delicate, evanescent meaning® and shadows of the meanings of nurds which might so plausibly he imputed to one who estimated SOCBATES. 133 philology highly for its own sake, and found it so indispensable a weapon in his warfare with the Sophists. The basket, too, in Senates not which the philosopher is found hanging between heaven and byPAmto-d earth, because he wishes to mingle his thoughts with the con- phone*, as a genial air, indicates no sort of apprehension on the part of the physics °f poet that Socrates looked upon himself as a mere particle of the general life of the world, and desired to be reunited with his native element; but, on the contrary, points to that doctrine of the withdrawment of the spirit from the phantasms of the world, which we have spoken of as forming so capital an article in the moral creed of Socrates, and of which his idea respecting the condition of the soul after death is only the expansion and ful¬ filment. The maps and geometrical instruments which the old Athenian found in the phrontisterium partly prove that illustra¬ tions from subjects with which the education of the Athenian youth made them familiar, were frequently in the philosopher's mouth, and partly seem intended as a joke at the iSocratie attempt to red ace morality to a science. The dialogue re¬ specting the cause of thunder is evidently intended far more as a caricature of the philosopher's method of discourse than as an expositiou of any of his particular opinions; the chief object being to leave an impression on the hearer's mind, that Socrates substituted some special daemon of his own (which the poet, to keep his metaphors consistent, and to strike an oblique blow at the really physical speculators, calls At roe) for Jupiter. It is necessary to make these remarks in justification of Aristophanes, lor if in these parts of his play he has wished to represent Socrates as a naturalist, the whole plot of it is absurd and'in- appropriate. Why should Strepsiades go to a natural philoso¬ pher that he may learn how to cheat his creditors ? or how should such a teacher give Pheidippides lessons in beating his father ? But the most remarkable feature in the whole play—the contest between the just and the unjust principle—is at once decisive as to the meaning of Aristophanes. The ingenious satirist, with the quick, intuitive discernment which might be expected from an Athenian, and such an Athenian, has perceived the conflict between an uplooking and a downlooking mind to be the most characteristic and important peculiarity of the system he was ridiculing. 18. The one point in the life of Socrates of which Aristo- TheSocrates phanes shows himself to have been utterly ignorant, is the object of it; and this is the one point upon which Xenophon is anxious to give us information. This worthy disciple is too anxious to show us Socrates in his dignity, and therefore we miss the hearty humorist who may be seen, though disguised, in the comedian's picture. It was natural that a soldier should be 134 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. more struck with the positive conclusions at which Socrates arrived upon direct practical matters, than with his method of arriving at them. It was equally natural that the professed apologist should be eager to exhibit his master in the way that would be most intelligible to plain persons, who had been puz¬ zled with reports of his strange argumentations, and who had fancied that some great mischief must lurk in them. But if we bear these facts in mind, and look upon Xeuophon as rather the expounder of the Socratic discipline than of the man himself, or of his principles, we shall probably be much more struck with the agreements than with the differences between him and the other biographers. Homage to an invisible guide and teacher, the distinction between the principle in man that looks upward and that which gravitates to the earth, the recognition of restraints upon the animal nature as means for the enfranchise¬ ment of the true man, we shall find in every page of the Memo¬ rabilia. Standing alone, Xenophon would be unsatisfactory— nay, even misleading. His Socrates would be almost as much a mere bundle of fine qualities or true opinions as his Cyrus. But he is most useful in giving clearness and steadiness to the apprehensions which we derive from other, and, on the whole, better sources. We see clearly in him that Socrates did from first to last keep a moral end before him. We see that he was, to all intents and purposes, a practical man. And this discovery, instead of making it more difficult to interpret the accounts of him which some think inconsistent with it, renders those ac¬ counts more intelligible and more consistent with themselves than we should otherwise have thought them. The 19. In the Socrates of Plato we find both the Aristophanic sicrates. Xenophontic Socrates—the mere humorist and debater, and the mere moralist—uniting to form the real man. It has often been said that the brilliant imagination of this philosopher created a hero between whom and the actual Socrates there were, perhaps, very few points of resemblance. Certainly it would be a hopeless task to vindicate Plato from the charge of a brilliant, and more than a brilliant, imagination. But two meanings may be given to this word. If it signifies a contempt of reason and probability, the gift, we apprehend, must belong in a much lower degree to Plato than to those who conceive it possible for a person living in the very city wherein Socrates had been for years walking and talking, to have palmed upon his countrymen a false or fantastic image of him. If, on the contrary, by imagination we understand the power of giving to that which would be otherwise a mere shadow, substance and life, it must surely be a most serviceable ally to him who would collect and harmonise the remembrances of an actual character, THE SOCEATICS. 135 no less than to him who would call into being one that never existed. Strong affection may supersede the necessity of such a faculty in a mere biographer; or rather, perhaps, may awaken it. But one who has not only to describe the thoughts, words, and acts of a friend, but to show how they bore upon the state of his country, and how they will bear upon men's speculations aud lives for ages to come, has need that no ordinary measure of this faculty should be imparted to him. This is the work of Plato. It was Socrates, as the guide into a particular line and course of thought, whom he proposed to exhibit. But in order to do this, it was absolutely necessary that he should be brought livingly before us; that we should see, not his opinions, but himself; that we should be able to trace the workings of his mind, to see how he acted upon others and they upon him. By any other means Plato would have been unable to give us the true Socrates; and without presenting us the true Socrates he could never have brought out with any clearness and distinctness the different sides of his own philosophy. SECTION III. THE SOCEATICS. 1. The immediate outgrowths of the Socratic philosophy and The discipline were three schools, ordinarily distinguished as the £3^™"* Cyrenaic, Cynic, aud Megaric. These may be said to be the Aristip'pus, parents of the most conspicuous theories with which later Greece was occupied. The Cyrenaic doctrine, having mingled with a Annicens. tributary stream flowing from the physics of Dempcritus, termi¬ nated in Epicurism. The Cynic combined with the Megarian to constitute Stoicism. The Megarian, moreover, contributed one element to the important speculations which had their home at a much later period at Alexandria. It is interesting, there¬ fore, to trace the leading thoughts of each, and to show how they originated with Socrates. 2. Aristippus of Cyrene seems to have been a man of a singu- AristippuR, larly easy, happy temperament. Pleasures excited him not, flourislJ5!j pains passed lightly over him. Eew men, one would have B,c" thought, would have had less sympathy with Socrates, who was a hard fighter, all his life long, with himself and with the world. Nevertheless this earnest thinker had charms even for Aris¬ tippus. Socrates said that we are not to yield to circumstances, but are the masters of them ; and the light spirit which no cir¬ cumstance affected or oppressed found an interpretation for the maxim in his own experience. The perturbations and restless¬ ness of the thoughtless, unrecollected man were frequent topics for the pity and warnings of Socrates; could there be a more 136 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. natural inference than that freedom from annoyance, a dismissal of all careful and turbulent anxieties, is the great end of philo¬ sophy ? In addition to these, the well-known commonplaces of his master's discourse, Aristippus could no doubt quote authentic fragments of his conversations, in which he had seemed to assume pleasure as the end of life, and to adjust his other maxims to this conclusion. He could tell, we may be sure, of cases in which Socrates, addressing himself to his own lazy, voluptuous habits of mind, and reprehending them, had yet seemed to make it his object to prove, not that they were leading to a wrong end, but that they were ill-chosen means for accomplishing that end. Aristippus, therefore, easily persuaded himself that he had a good title to call himself a Socratic—nay, that he was the best and most complete interpreter of the Socratic views—when he announced the great discovery that pleasure and pain are the ultimate principles of human life; that the pursuit of the one and the avoidance of the other is and must be the business of a!rcaiiin^6 eyei7 man- Whatever honour belongs to the first formal pro¬ linuria" mulgator of a doctrine which has occupied so prominent a place '•aerates?' ^ philosophy of all ages as this, must in all justice be given to Aristippus. That in which he is distinguished from later and less practical reasoners of the same class is in the distinct and honest assertion that the momentary, concrete gratification, and not the complex notion of happiness, is and must be the object of men's desires and labours. It was easy for Aristippus to adjust some other portions of the Socratic creed to this doc¬ trine. If the choice of what is agreeable, and the rejection of what is disagreeable, be the great virtue of the human soul, how conveniently might the language of Socrates respecting the con¬ nection of virtue with reason and knowledge be pressed into the service of the new sect! Of course it is the intellectual faculty which prefers and discards; and why should not these acts of judgment be the same with those acts of reason, that perception of what is and what is not, to which the master had so con¬ stantly referred ? And as for the apparent self-restraint and bodily privations of Socrates, these were in no real contradiction to the Cyrenaie theory, which admits, of course, all varieties of taste, and may well permit one man to seek mental pleasure at the expense of corporeal,—another, corporeal at the loss of mental. This school underwent several changes. In the hands of Theodorus pleasure and pain ceased to be real outward objects, and self-seeking and self-glorification became the defined, acknowledged ends of the wise man. In Hegesias the hope of attaining pleasure is exchanged for a mere invention of con¬ trivances to avoid pain. Anniceris seems to have taken off the rough edges of the doctrine, and to have prepared the way for THE SOCRATICS. 137 its merging in the more general notions about happiness which were matured by Epicurus. 3. The Cynic school—as it presents itself in the persons of Jchhe0^y.nic Antisthenes, its founder, and Diogenes, its only very notorious Antisthenes disciple—is the formal opposite of the Cyrenaic. Yet they neg added one to the numerous illustrations of the old maxim, which Mr. Coleridge has observed to be of all maxims the most preg¬ nant for the philosopher and the philosophical historian,—" Ex¬ tremes meet." Both, in fact, started from the same Socratic Antisthenes, maxim ; both may probably have alleged the same discourses in u c vindication of their system. The wise man should not submit 49(^374 to circumstances, but rule them, said Aristippus; his whole D~„.enes business is to arrange his circumstances that they may produce 1 ' the maximum of pleasure and the minimum of pain. A man is 4X2-323. to be superior to his circvunstanccs, said Antisthenes, and there¬ fore he is by all means to overcome his sensibility to pleasure or pain, and endeavour to live solely within himself, cultivating that nobler part of him which is not affected by outward impulses and impressions. If the first could allege passages from the discourses of Socrates in support of his theory, the latter could more confidently appeal to the whole course of his life, to his habitual endeavours after a victory over mere sensations. The Cynics were, in fact, more disciplinarians than doctrinists. They had a hard dogmatism of their own, but they were much more ambitious to show their own indifference to passing acci¬ dents than to discover principles and reasons for such an indif¬ ference. Of the two professors of the school, Antisthenes seems to have been the honester, Diogenes the more original. The first was hard and narrow, but apparently sincere; the second was an ostentatious coxcomb, from whose proud and insolent spirit were emitted now and then sparks of what might have been genius if it had been accompanied with simplicity of character and a true purpose. 4. Euclides of Megara was unquestionably a more sagacious The and subtle man than any of those we have named. He was attracted to Socrates by no hope, either of obtaining a theory Euclides, respecting life, or of discovering a scheme of self-culture, but by modoru"' his unrivalled skill in disputation. Had Euclides lived thirty stiipo. years earlier, he would have been an Eleatic, or else a Sophist. But in nothing is the effect of the Socratic teaching, and the change it had wrought upon the minds of his countrymen, more remarkable than in the moral tone which it imparted to the thoughts of those who would otherwise have been debaters merely. To argue wys the taste and the vocation of the Mega- rian school, but their arguments were all irresistibly drawn to the question, " What is the Good ?" In pursuing this inquiry, 138 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. they were naturally led to those pregnant positions of Socrates respecting evil, as a departure from, and rebellion against, what is, which constituted, as we have seen, the ultimate, and, in one way, the most characteristic part of his philosophy. This prin¬ ciple, in fact, disjoined from all the living processes by which Socrates had arrived at it, and by which he sought to make other men conscious of it, and exhibited in naked opposition to all other ideas of virtue or goodness, constituted the Megarian doc¬ trine. All their labours were employed in disproving the obvious and apparently irresistible opinion, that those things whereof the senses give us information are the most real and certain. "We have heard how Zeno defended the doctrine of his friend and master Parmenides by showing the utter instability of sensible presumptions and conclusions. The Megarian school adopted the same method. The difference lay in the characters of the respective periods; the purpose of Zeno vi as to support the metaphysical idea of Oneness,—of the Megarian, to support the moral idea of absolute, unchangeable Being. Degeneracy 5. The history of this school is melancholy and instructive, school. Euclides, though the bias of his mind was to disputation, felt the grandeur of the moral lessons which he had learned from Socrates. In Eubulides positive faith was superseded by delight in his own subtlety, and in the confutation of antagonist argu¬ ments. The mere forms of the understanding, apart from all vital principles or results, were the objects of admiration and reverence to Diodorus Cronos. Lastly, Stilpo seems to have lost the characteristic idea of the Megarian school altogether, while he carried its characteristic infirmity to its greatest height. Not to establish the existence of objective truth, but to show how an intellect may be formed which shall be most impassive to influences from without, and least disturbed by affections from within, was his problem. One of his pupils was Zeno of Cittium, the author of Stoicism. section rv. PLATO. Tiip dream 1. Once upon a time, the biographer of the Greek philosophers of Socrates, reports,1 Socrates dreamed a dream. He found an unfledged cygnet upon his knee. In a few moments it became Avinged and flew away, uttering a very sweet sound. The next day a young man came to him, who was said to reckon Solon among his nearer ancestors, and looked back through him to Codrus and to the god Poseidon. The name of this young man was Plato. 1 Diog. Laert. lib. iii. cap. i. 6.7. PLATO. 139 2. Before lie came to Socrates, this youth had been a writer Plato's early of dithyrambics, and songs, and tragedies. He had studied l,fe- under Ariston, the Argive, a celebrated wrestler. Some say that he won his name from the breadth of his chest, and that he gained a prize for wrestling at the Isthmian games. But, what¬ ever his earlier studies may have been, the day in which he settled on the knees of Socrates was the one which determined the course of his after-life. Nothing that he had learnt before that time was assuredly wasted, but the discourses of Socrates gave his studies a meaning and a direction. From him Plato learnt to understand himself, and thence to understand his pre¬ decessors and contemporaries. Prom him he learnt what it behoved a Greek to seek for, what it behoved a man to seek for, what perils and temptations beset the one and the other if he enters upon the search. 3. So completely has Plato identified himself with his master, The paucity that it is difficult to discover with any certainty the events and cir- concerning cumstances of his own life. Less is recorded of him than of many his life- of the most insignificant of Greek sophists. "What is recorded rests upon very unsatisfactory evidence. The epistles which are called by his name have long been rejected as spurious, though some fragments of information respecting him may be derived from them. The most interesting of these concern his expedi¬ tions into Sicily, his connection with the elder tyrant Dionysius, his experiments for the reformation of the younger, his hope of realising some ideal polity through the influence of a dissolute and worthless tyrant, his direct influence upon the character and fortunes of the stern aristocrat, the conspirator, the despot Dion. Though it may not be possible to arrange the parts, of this history, we may perhaps admit that Plato had an intense longing to prove that he was no mere dreamer; that what he believed was capable of realisation. We have not enough facts to point a moral respecting the infirmity of a noble mind in yielding to the hope of great results through such instruments. He may never have entertained any flattering expectations, but may simply, and perhaps reluctantly, have fulfilled a task that was imposed upon him. How far it was necessary that his polity should be tried in Syracuse, or anywhere else, in order that the truth of its principles might be tested, we may under¬ stand better when we have considered what that polity was. The question which immediately concerns us is, whether Plato, when he became fledged, flew away into the air, and left his master upon the earth, as some have fancied, and as the old tradition seems to intimate, or whether he was the truest and most faithful expounder of his master's doctrines, the true Socratic, because he was not the founder of a Socratic system, but a living and original investigator. 140 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. Relation between tbe Socratic schools and Pluto. How Socrates escaped narrowness and the temptation to theorise. 4. Plato "conversed with both Aristippus and Antisthenes. With Euclides he enjoyed a closer intimacy than with either of them, for to Megara he and other disciples fled after the death of Socrates, when it seemed less safe to dwell in Athens. It would be rash to say that the direction of his own thoughts was determined by his observation of these three men, for it is a notion apparently well supported by internal evidence, that his Pfuedrus and his Laches were written in the lifetime of his master. Yet it seems impossible to doubt that he had very early noticed the tendency in his different fellow-disciples to adopt certain sentences which fell from their teacher's lips, and from these to form systems and schools, and that he had considered very deeply whether there was no course by which he might escape from the like temptation. If Socrates had compounded his creed out of the different systems then prevalent in Greece, it could surprise no one that the elements thus artificially put together should reassert their independence, and in some new shape, perhaps, be claimed as the property of the minds to which they were severally most adapted. Everything that he had seen of his master made this supposition impossible. Whether he had studied the doctrines of other schools or no, it is evident that every thought which he uttered came fresh and living from himself, or, rather, was the united fruit of his own reflections and of those of the persons with whom he conversed. It was evident that he had been able to minister to other minds, because he knew so well what was passing in his own, and had sought out every principle as the solution of an actual difficulty. But it is fair to suppose that every philosopher is in some sort an inquirer into the workings of his own mind—nay, that his philosophy, so far as it is sincere, is an exhibition of his own mind. How then was Socrates, who was so remarkably himself \ preserved from that narrowness and exelusiveness into which Aristippus and Antisthenes, both sincere men in their way, had obviously fallen ? 5. Plato could only answer the question by supposing that it was the healthy habit of always connecting his own thoughts with outward circumstances, and with the puzzles of the age in which he was living, which prevented the Socratic doctrines, in their owner's hands, from ever stagnating into a mere theory. The obvious resource for making a philosophy complete and general, and suited to all times, was to strip it of those accidental features which had adapted it so happily to a particular crisis. Plato was convinced, by reflection and experience, that precisely the opposite course was the safe one. The poetry of Homer could be read and enjoyed in the age of Pericles, not because it stood aloof from all temporary and local accidents, but because it was enveloped in them. It was exactly when men were pre- PLATO. 141 seated to them as they were in an entirely different state of manners, that they were able to realise them as their brethren and their countrymen. Reasons will no doubt occur in multi¬ tudes to the reader why the analogy of poetry is inapplicable to philosophy : it is sufficient for our purpose that they did not weigh with Plato. No one knew so well as he—no one felt so strongly—the essential difference between poetry and philosophy; he even was betrayed into exaggerations in his attempt practically to assert it. But he was convinced that it did not consist in this, that the poet obtains immortality for thoughts which he utters by adapting himself to the feelings of the age in which he lives, and the philosopher by divesting himself of them all. He thought he could see that the abandonment of all living and practical sympathies, the attempt to divorce himself from human interests, gives to the philosopher that narrow and bounded character from which he hopes by these means to deliver him¬ self. If, then, Grecian wisdom was not to retrograde from the point to which Socrates had brought it, or if it was ever to become useful in other countries and periods, Plato concluded that it must not resolve itself into speculations or declamations about this or that scheme of life, this or that principle of action or pursuit, but must be content to exhibit itself in the conver¬ sations of actual men, not of some imaginary day, but of that day, talking about the matters of which they did talk when they met in the streets or at their feasts. He would not take the least pains to forget the people among when he was living, or the transactions that were occupying them, or adopt any more universal mode of thought and speech than that which was com¬ mon among them. 6. The Dialogue of Plato is not then, as some have represented why Plato it, an artistical invention, in which the philosopher sacrificed his Dialogues, severe judgment to his imagination, or to a desire of reputation for dramatic skill with his contemporaries or with posterity, or to the ambition of presenting truths in an agreeable form. It is evident that he regarded it as a necessary mean for the eluci¬ dation of the truths with which he believed himself to be pos¬ sessed ; and that he is not at all more anxious to impress any one principle upon his readers than this, that in the Dialogue, rightly used, we have the induction to all principles. It is straDge, indeed, that Plato should be accused of sacrificing the interest of his disciples to a selfish desire of fame, by that method which has the effect of leading them onwards step by step in self-inquiry ; or that he should be supposed to have used this as a way of conciliating their favour, when, in fact, it has caused more conscious vexation and irritation to every superficial talker of that day, than any which his genius could have devised. A 142 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. mere artist endeavours to carry us at once into noble contem¬ plations, which make us conscious of our own greatness and dignity. It is Plato's desire that we should feel our own way into these contemplations, ascending into them through rugged aud thorny paths, discovering how many frivolous difficulties suggest themselves to us, which must be cleared away before we Character can see anything as it is. His Dialogues are literally an educa- Duiogoes. tion, explaining to us how we are to deal with our own minds, how far we are to humour them, how far we are to resist them; how they are to entertain the glimpses of light which sometimes fall upon them; how they are to make their way through the complications and darkness in which they so often feel them¬ selves lost. Nowhere but in the sacred oracles do we find an author so cognisant of his own perplexities, so little anxious to hide them from us; nay, so anxious to awaken us to the con¬ sciousness of them, in order that we may be delivered from them. Herein lies the art of Plato. Most consummate art it is, we admit; superior in the depth of insight which must have led to it, and in the influence which it exerts, to that which is displayed in almost any human composition. Still it is not art, in the sense commonly given to that word; it has no indepen¬ dent purpose of pleasing. It does not work underground, leaving the ordinary man to feel its effects simply, and the thoughtful man to judge of its character by its effects. On the contrary, it anxiously draws your attention to its own methods and contrivances; that you should enter into them, and under¬ stand all the springs and valves that are at work, is as much the writer's ambition, as that you should accept any one of the fiual results. Indeed, he does not acknowledge the results as yours, till in the region of your own inner being you have gone through the processes which lead to them. a cham 7. Plato above all men must be studied in Plato. A hearty unwindmff ant^ sympathising acquaintance with one Dialogue will do more itself. n to initiate a student into what is blunderingly called his system, than the reports of all philosophical critics and historians. There you find no digests of doctrine, no collections of ready- manufactured notions, to be adopted and carried away. Every one is alive and at work. The actors too are not, as in our best Dialogues—in those of Berkeley, for instance—personages with significant names; they are real Plnedruses, (xorgiases, and Protagorases, discoursing, in a place which is ascertained to us by an accurate and vivid description, about some passing ques¬ tion in the folds of which are found to be contained the deepest and highest principles of our being. These are drawn forth, nor \ii»l 'ntly by any predetermination that such and such i'lcts shall gno forth such aud such a moral, but by the ordinary PLATO. 143 accidents of conversation, amidst explanations and contradic¬ tions, the confusion of disciples, the anger of doctors, clumsy attempts at reconciliation by good-natured bystanders. The dialogue is often a Siris. Like Berkeley's admirable treatise, it may be bound here on earth to no worthier a stake than the properties and virtues of tar-water. Oftentimes the starting-point may be one far less worthy than this, the lying speech of some rhetorician in support of some mischievous and vulgar paradox. Yet the chain is unwound with a skill of which our modest countryman would have cheerfully confessed that his was but a feeble copy, till its highest link is felt to be about the throne of Him whose name it was the privilege of Berkeley to utter, the honesty of Plato to declare unutterable. 8. Thus far we have described Plato as reasserting the entire His principle of Socrates against those who had dismembered it. £d ecu asm. But a notion has gone forth, and has received support from an able and eloquent French commentator of our day, that Plato was an Eclectic ; in other words, that his object on every occasion was to set in opposition two imperfect principles, and either, by merely showing their inadequacy, to suggest the hint, or, by clear exposition, to develope the form, of a third idea which should include them both. This is the most plausible shape which the theory has taken. Another and common way in which it is stated is, that Plato framed to himself the notion of a phi¬ losophy which, taking its start from the doctrine of Socrates, should adopt into itself all the other Greek philosophies, whether metaphysical or moral, and that accordingly we do find in him not only an attempt to harmonise the doctrines of the schools which took their name from Socrates, but also of those which preceded him. In both these statements there is, as it seems to us, much truth: yet truth put into a form which is exceedingly likely to mislead a reader, and utterly to pervert his notions respecting the real object of the Greek teacher. We suspect that, in considering these theories, we may both arrive at a clearer apprehension of Plato's meaning, and gain some light which will profit us in all our future in¬ quiries. 9. One main object of Plato in using the dialogue was, that Moral he might discover the latent meaning of words, and might lead the'primary the inquirer to recognise this meaning as that which had been narpose of implied in them from their origin, and had been floating in the a °* minds of those who had given them quite a different signification. Hereby he was carrying out the method which Socrates, as we have seen, had been throughout his life maturing, and to which we have traced the success of all his experiment* in moral science. For this practice was grounded upon a faith which is GKECIAN PHILOSOPHY. ripened day by day into certainty, that there is in every man that which apprehends and recognises truth ; that the truth is continually near him; and again, that his view of it is con¬ tinually interrupted and distorted by the phantoms which are presented to his senses. In drawing forth this truth out of the mind of the student, and teaching him to realise it as his own, consisted, as Plato believed, the great duty of the Socratie teacher ; to this all his labours were to be bent; so far as he did this work faithfully, he might hope to be rewarded with greater illumination. Never, however, was it to be forgotten that the discipline was a moral as well as an intellectual one, nay, that it was primarily and essentially moral; that he must resist the attractions and bribery of sense in order to escape her im¬ positions. Now the process we have described leads to a result which often looks like the result of Eclecticism. An opinion seems to be rejected as false, an opinion that is set in opposition to it is shown also to be unsatisfactory, and then at last a truth is seen, or suspected to be hidden somewhere, which both alike had been aiming ineffectually to reach. The reader of Plato's Dialogues will be encountered again and again with instances of this sort. But let him beware of hurrying to the conclusion, that the reconcilement of these opinions, or the construction of another opinion which shall be more comprehensive than both, was the aim of the teacher. If he will quietly accompany him along the road, he will find that in such conversations as these, distinction is much more his object than accommodation. To dis¬ tinguish between those images which the mind shapes for itself out of the objects of sense when it is sense-ridden and sense- posscssed, and that sound meaning and reality which it is capable of perceiving when it has sought to purge itself of its natural and habitual delusions—to teach it the art of rejecting as well as choosing, and to put it in the posture for either one act or the other; this is the intention of Plato. It may be that he has done more to introduce harmony and unity into moral specula¬ tions than any philosopher who ever lived ; we fully believe that he has. But he begins with cultivating in us the habit of moral distinction. He begins with leading us to feel that truth and falsehood are radical ultimate contradictions which cannot be accounted for or resolved into any others. To see that which is, as it verily is, this is the highest privilege of the best and wisest man; to see things as they are not, confused, seusualised, cor¬ rupted, this is the misery and curse of the thoughtless, slavish victim of inclination. To open that invard eye by which the reality of things is discerned in other men, is the vocation and privilege of him who has himself served an apprenticeship to truth, and feels that he is her servant. PLATO. 145 10. Such, we conceive, is the object of one large class of the Purely Plutonic Dialogues, which are the induction or vestibule to the rest. In these Plato is distinctly and emphatically Socratic. They must, indeed, differ in an important respect from the actual conversations of Socrates, in that the end must always have been more present to the mind of the writer, than it could have been to that of the speaker. In Socrates the strongest feeling seems to have been, u I am certain there is something which is not appearance or phantasy, which man did not shape out for himself, but which will remain when all phantasies have disappeared, which is, and which I must recognise if I would be anything but a phantom or shadow myself." This was the con¬ clusion of a practical working mind. By earnest meditation upon this conclusion, Plato came to feel that if there is an unseen reality in all things, a truth, a substance in things, of which the eye sees only the shape and colour, there must be a truth and substance which has none of those sensible adjuncts, which is in itself, and the beholding of which is the function and , highest attainment of the purified spirit. Now the outward shell of this opinion so closely resembles the doctrine of Euclides that we cannot wonder that some critics, in their desire to reduce the philosophy of Plato into fragments, should have pro¬ nounced several of the earlier Dialogues to be not in fact his, but productions of the Megarian school. All in which they found this substance, this to qv, put forward as the end of human investigations, they naturally connected with a system which had the assertion that Good and Being are identical for its pro¬ minent characteristic. Those who agree with us in the view we have taken will at once see the plausibility of the critic's notion, and its utier untenableness. In no part of Plato's works is the These distinction between him and the Megarians so conspicuous as in D^,0i>'uts this where he is asserting their own principle. For by adhering Mepan m. closely to the method of Socrates, by making his Dialogues not the declaration of a truth, but a mental exercise to arrive at it, he has not only divested the doctrine of all its dryness and prickliness, but he has shown how it is connected with those other more obvious notions to which the Megarian set it in rude opposition. Pleasure is not the good, they said ; self-denial is not the good; Being is the good. Xes, said Plato, but there is a Being in pleasure, there is a reality in it as well as a falsehood in it. Whatever man has found an expression for in language, whatever man has pursued as an object in life, there is in that a truth, a substance, which may be distinguished from the lying phantom that surrounds and counterfeits it. And so far as a Opinions man does this, so far does he put himself into the right condition recuuule(1- of mind for arriving ultimately at the perception of that Truth, YOL. I. L 146 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. that Being which is encompassed with no accidents. But then, in order to attain or to cultivate this state of mind, there must be a discipline, a curbing, and contradiction of the lower nature, and therefore this too is a good, ot u'ittk^ucs Without, then, any purpose of combining opinions, nay, " "" while resolutely maintaining boundaries, and using a most subtle test for the discrimination of the true from the apparent, Plato had actually reduced the three doctrines which assumed the name of Socratie into a certain relation and harmony. It now became him to consider how far this same doctrine and method might be applied to the earlier philosophers of Greece; how far his master had been anticipated by Xenophanes, Heraclitus, Parmenides, or Pythagoras; how far he had thrown back a light upon them which might make their speculations more intelligible and consistent with each other. Here com¬ mences, in our judgment, the second class of the Platonic Dialogues, that in which the link between Moral and Metaphy¬ sical Philosophy, between the doctrine of Being which Socrates had asserted, and the question respecting Unity, which had been so great an occupation of the Greek mind, is illustrated and developed. 32. Our readers will not have forgotten that the leader of the Eleatie school, Xenophanes, was in one respect distinguished from his successors. His language at first sight seems remark¬ ably to accord with that of Socrates. That which he supposed to be the true object of man's contemplation was God, or " The Being." Yet, while doing justice to the course of thought by which he arrived at this conclusion, we were obliged to admit that he was essentially a destructive thinker; that he reduced his Being to a mere negation of human qualities and attributes ; and that Parmenides found a happier expression for the results of his inquiries when he said that they simply led to the affir- Ditterence mation of Oneness. How, then, did the doctrine of Socrates between differ from that of Xenophanes ? It was separated from it by a andSocrates whole heaven. The Being of Xenophanes was altogether exclusive; the Being of Socrates was altogether inclusive. If the language of men contained such words as "just," " merciful," " good," if it attributed these names to certain acts, then, whether these words had been understood or no, whether they had been rightly applied or no, there was a reality corresponding to them, there was a "justice," a "mercy," a "goodness," and all these centred and united themselves in the Being. No Sophist could embarrass him with the question, " Seeing man also uses the words ' unjust,' ' unmerciful,' ' bad,' why should not these also have their appropriate archetypes ? and why may not these, as much as the others, dwell in that permanent and PLATO. 147 all-containing substance ?" For it was assumed in the very hypothesis that all these are departures from that which is, that they are intrinsically falsehoods. Now, it was by reflection upon this difl'erence, so delicate yet so vital, so strikingly marking the man who was fighting against all popular opinions and faith from the man who was finding out substance and life in all, that Plato seems to have gained his first insight into that doctrine of Ideas which constitutes the most native and peculiar portion of ideas, his philosophy, that which may not wrongly be called its purely Platonic portion. We are perfectly willing to admit the asser¬ tion which the other disciples of Socrates seem to have made with no little vehemence, and which Aristotle has adopted from them, that no such principle as this was enunciated by Socrates in any of his discourses. Yet we believe as undoubtedly, that by his steady adoption of the Socratic method, Plato arrived at this principle, and that they failed in apprehending it only because they neglected that method, in endeavouring to make this remark clear, we shall also perhaps be able to give our readers such insight as a treatise like this may hope to give into the subject itself. 13. The Greek word for appearance and for opinion is the Pnrtif ti e shall we persuade our people that these different qualities exist, magistrates. an(j constitute a fitness for the different offices in the state ? We must tell them a story, says Plato, in order that we may bring home this conviction to their minds. We must inform them that they were all made originally out of the earth, which, on that account, they are to love as their common mother; reckoning themselves brethren in consequence of their relation to her. That however it pleased the gods to introduce different materials into their composition, making some of gold, some of silver, some of inferior metals; that it is important that these should not be confounded, but should be kept distinct and applied to distinct uses, in order that the society may receive benefit from each of them. Such is the parable by which our author teaches us that he looks upon himself not as the contriver of some imaginary scheme, but only as following out the inten¬ tions of Providence in the institution of society. of ^is time we seem to have been forgetting our original tn th<* question respecting Justice. But we find in the fourth book individual, that the arrangements of the State, and even our long discussion Fourth book Up0n music, have been preparing the way for a more clear development of this idea. We have discovered three classes in society, and we have seen that each of these classes embodies a certain characteristic quality, which through it becomes the quality of the whole fellowship. The class of magistrates ex¬ presses to us the very idea of Wisdom, superintending, distin¬ guishing, arranging; the class of guardians, the very idea of Fortitude, sustaining, amalgamating, preserving; the inferior classes, while they keep their position, the very idea of Tem¬ perance, self-restraining, and submitting. Without any of these it is obvious that a society could not exist, and the permanence of its existence depends upon the degree in which the qualities Musir and of each class interpenetrate the rest. But then do not these justice. imply the existence of still another quality—of some principle or power which fuses together all the classes and all these qualities —which belongs not primarily or particularly to one class, but PLATO. 165 must by its very nature be predicated of the whole ? This is evidently that musical principle which we have been seeking by all our education to instil. But what shall be the name of it ? Is not this that Justice which we have been trying to understand, the meaning of ? Do we not translate the rude outward notion of Simonides into a practical, satisfactory idea, when instead of making justice consist in giving every man his due and in speak¬ ing the truth, we describe it as that which determines the true relation of all things and persons to each other, the very law and harmony of the world. Yet may we not go still a little deeper ? Our first object was to discover the nature and effect of justice, not in society, but in the individual. At every step of our progress we seem to have found proof that these two con¬ siderations are inseparable ; that the law of society must be the law of the individual. Now, perhaps, we are in a condition to explain this fact more particularly. Our inquiry has brought to light three classes as the necessary constituents of the State; a class of magistrates, a class of guardians, a class occupied in supplying the animal wants of the whole body. Whence the necessity for this distribution of society ? Is it not that there is a similar distribution of parts in the man himself ? Is there not in him Reason, Energy, or Will, Cupidity, or an animal nature ? And if these are not to exist in perpetual discord, the man in perpetual misery, must there not be that in him which preserves each of these parts in its proper relation to the rest, giving the supremacy to Reason, preserving the strength and purity of Will, subjecting Cupidity? Is not Justice then neces¬ sary to each of us ? 35. This point being ascertained, Socrates is willing to finish Thcgrea the dialogue. But Glaucon and Adeimantus remind him that society" justice being, according to him, the principle of harmony or unity in the commonwealth, he is bound to explain the other conditions of this unity. For if any inevitable circumstances make this union impracticable, justice itself is impracticable; and if for the commonwealth, then, according to the whole tenour of the argument, for the individual also; so that we should be obliged at last to acquiesce in a conclusion not very unlike that sophistical one which we have been labouring to confute. The four next books, then, from the beginning of the fifth to the end of the ninth, are occupied with these questions: first, in what sense are family relationships compatible with the unity of a commonwealth ? secondly, how far can it consist with individual selfishness and ambition ? thirdly, how can it consist with that law of decay and degeneracy to which all societies seem to have been subject ? 36. What Plato's statements are upon the first of these sub- GHECIAJ* PHIXOSOPIIY. jects we have no need to inform any reader. Those who know scarcely anything else of him have heard that he has somewhere spoken of the two sexes as intended to perform exactly the same duties and exercises, and that he has connected with this doc¬ trine another (which indeed in a logical mind will generally be inseparable from it), of a community in wives and children. muiUwn°m" They have heard also that these notions actually enter into the composition of his perfect commonwealth, and that he wishes to supersede all the existing relations of father and child, wife and husband, which lie, as we suppose, at the foundation of all moral apprehensions and all political order. The question, then, naturally suggests itself, not whether we are prepared to offer any justification for this part of his speculations, but how, while such a huge and hideous blot exists in them, we can venture to speak of them as important; above all, can devote so much time to the examination of them ? Many readers and admirers of Plato have dwelt with much satisfaction on the fact, that in the Lam (a later work, undoubtedly, than the Republic) he appears to ha\e changed his views, and to recognise the sanctity of human relationships as they exist. We confess that we do not regard the passages referred to as a recantation. Even if Plato considered them so himself (of which there is no proof), we feel convinced that he would have relapsed into his former opinion, if he had again devoted himself to the task of studying the idea The doctrine of a commonwealth. The Laws, it seems to us, are intended to and"8: explaiQ the conditions under which any particular nation exists; why whence proceeds the coercive power by which the evils of its tmm tiiat of members are restrained; how it is to be preserved as a distinct theRepubiic community. For this end Plato perceived the importance of distinct relationships ; he could not help seeing that they lie at the very foundation of national life; that with the loss of them it would perish. The Republic, on the other hand, is not an inquiry respecting the conditions of a particular state. Phrases may occur in it again and again which seem to define this as its object; but others, far more pregnant in their meaning, and oftentimes uttered unconsciously, show that another and grander aim was present to the mind of the writer, and was haunting him when he could not realise it. He felt that there should be some body which expresses, not the law of a confined, definite national life, but the law of society itself, the principle of its unity. He felt that such a body as this is implied in the existence of every national community, but yet transcends it, and is not subject to its limitations. We could easily produce roofs of this feeling from every book of the Republic, but we now none in which it comes forth more strikingly than in that fifth book of which we are now speaking. The idea of a universal PLATO. 167 Greek society is there formally put forth, yet it is evident that this does not satisfy the mind of Plato ; he has the dream of something still more comprehensive: a feeble sophist would have tried to express the dream in big words ; he is content to suggest the nearest practical approximation to an expression of it that his circumstances made possible. But with this universal society Plato docs not see how distinct relationships are com¬ patible. Perfect community seems the very law of its being; whatsoever interferes with this seems to frustrate its intention. 37. Here, then, we see at once the ignorance and knowledge Advancers of Plato. How such a universal society as this could grow out error to us. of a national community, out of a family, and could preserve uninjured, in harmony with itself, both those holy institutions which had been its cradle, this he did not know; this wisdom was reserved for the shepherds of Palestine. To them it was only communicated by degrees, and their chief duty consisted in keeping that which had been divinely given them in the sure confidence that more would be added. But this was permitted to the sage of Greece—he was allowed to feel the necessity of a universal community to the life of man; he was permitted to feel that it was a great living truth implied in the existence of society, though yet undeveloped. To such insight and honesty of purpose, rejecting no light that has been vouchsafed, it is granted, that even the crudities and ignorances into which he fell in the search after truth shall be for the benefit of future generations, nay for the practical correction and exposure of these very crudities when they are reproduced by men of a different spirit. The fifth book of the Republic is a curious anticipation of every scheme of universal society which has been propounded by religious fanatics or political theorists from the propagation of Christianity to the present day. It remains a standing practical testimony from the wisest man in the ancient world, that this is the only consistent law, and must be the ultimate law of every such society, whensoever it attempts to exist alone, as a merely spiritual or cosmical family. Rejecting, then, with indignation the errare mehercule malo of the Roman academician, and loving Plato only as far as he loved truth, we may yet find a worth even in this unfortunate passage of his writings. 38. The portion of the Republic comprehended in the sixth How a and seventh books is second to no part of it in interest. The difficulty to be solved in it is the compatibility of such a State is com- as we have described with the selfish notions of men. Plato selfishness.11 does not blink the question. He at once declares his conviction sixth book, that such a State could only be administered by philosophers; and he then goes on to explain what he means by a philosopher; 168 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. why it is that the persons generally bearing that name are unfit to be practical politicians ; what their real relation to the rest of their countrymen is. Here then we have the full expo¬ sition and development of that doctrine which we found lying at the root of Soeratic teaching; that the selfish, self-seeking principle, leading men to animal gratifications, is the source of disorder and confusion in the life of man, not really the moving spring of it; that there is in man something higher, which is not satisfied with itself, but which seeks after converse with the Good. The philosopher is the man who is holding this con¬ verse ; whose mind is fixed on the true end and meaning of things, upon the substance, the reality of them. The rest are following images and shadows, but still in the pursuit of these are confessing their want of a Good, and are blindly feeling after it. The philosopher, if he descends to the pursuit of their shadows, becomes worthy of their contempt, for there is a per¬ petual contradiction between the higher aims of which he is conscious and the grovelling course he has actually taken. If, on the other hand, he steadily keeps his own idea in sight, he is necessarily unintelligible to them, and on that account they despise him. But suppose, having worked his own way out of the mine in which they are dwelling, and no longer receiving light through the little crannies which transmit it broken and confused, and lead men utterly astray as to the fountain from which it has flowed, he has come out into the open sunlight, and by it seen all objects as they are, he neither glorifies himself by The phiio- living apart from them, nor yet submits to confuse his light with dutyetothe darkness, kut goes down amongst them that he may lead multitude, them by the same track which he has himself trodden into the clear day—would he not then be fulfilling his function as a philosopher, and yet be most truly a politician ? If the question Seventh occurs to you, what is this upward road ? Plato is ready to con- k0014, sider it with you. There is a certain education recognised among men; they teach arithmetic, geometry, as well as the gymnastics and music we spoke of before, and they evidently attach a high value to these studies. Are they wrong ? surely not. They are wrong only in this, that throughout their whole lives they are seeking shadows instead of substances, and that they have made all these sciences helpful to their low ambition. Arithmetic and geometry have been resorted to merely for secular com¬ mercial ends; they might be made the means of purifying the mind to a perception of the truth of things. What is the appropriate function of each of these sciences, with a view to this object, he carefully inquires: and this inquiry brings out the necessity of that grand, deeper science of Dialectics, which directly leads to the contemplation of truth as truth, of good as PLATO. 169 good, in its pure essence. Now a nation thus guided and educated comes into the condition of such a republic as we have described. Its wisest, deepest-minded men will be its magis¬ trates ; the community will have one end; that principle of justice, which assigns to each his proper place, imparts a sense of proportion and harmony to all, will be diffused through it and actuate it. Thus, then, the existence of ambition and selfishness does not upset the idea of our Republic, does not prove that it is not implied in the nature of society, does not show that it may not be at some time or somewhere realised. 39. We come next to that law of decay in societies which Lawof decay most speculators have recognised, and which the Pythagorean in 80c,eties- philosophers fancied they could express in certain numerical ninthLooki. ratios. Plato has given a very valuable turn to the inquiry by connecting it with the cardinal doctrine of the Republic, that the life of men and the life of States explain each other. In con¬ formity with this doctrine, he maintains that there is a demo- cratical, an oligarchical, and a tyrannical form of character answering to those respective forms of government. This form of character is obviously a departure from some true and original model. The same may be shown of the governments ; and it is possible in each case to trace the process of degeneration, and to show how that which takes place in society, and that which takes place in the individual, react upon each other. In this part of the dialogue, Plato proves that his faculty of close, lively, practical observation had not been impaired but strengthened by his converse with transcendent realities. It would be hard to find a passage in any ancient work on which a modern statesman might more profitably meditate, or in which he would be more sure to find hints explaining to him the facts of his daily experience, than the eighth and ninth books of the Republic. The result of the investigation is the same as in the former case. This law of degeneracy exists in the common¬ wealths of the earth, just because they have not understood and steadfastly contemplated that original model, that perfect idea of a commonwealth, which is also the original model and perfect idea of a human character. It is a contradiction and absurdity then to allege the fact of this degeneracy as a proof that no such model is to be found. But after all these inquiries does the thought still linger about the mind, where is it to be found ? Plato answers (book ix. p. fin.), AXV ivovpayw laiog irapubeiypa avaKEirai Tip fiovXop£yu> opdr cal bpwvri eavroy karoiKi^tiy. Is it wonderful that such words should have suggested to some of the Christian fathers the recollection of those words in the Epistle to the Hebrews, which describe the hopes of the head of the covenanted people, Eyap r»)v roue OepeXiovs l-^°vaav 170 GRECIAN FIULOSOPIIY. Art and poetry. tt6\iv tfg re\vlrt]q Kai stimovpyoq a 0£oc ; or those which describe this hope as accomplished, TI/i<5v to itoXirevfta iv ovpavoic vwupx^1 ? Tenth hook. 40. There is still one subject upon which it is needful to say a few words, especially as Plato has devoted his last book to the full exposition of it: we mean his opinion respecting the imitative arts generally, and especially respecting poetry, so far as it is included atnong those arts. It is evident that our author attached great importance to these opinions, and yet that he was never wholly satisfied with them. He touches upon the question almost as soon as he has sketched the first outline of his society; he recurs to it again when his task seems completed, partly as if he felt there was no security for the reception of his idea while any doubt overhung this point, partly as if there was something in it which he had not fully penetrated. Again, in the introduction to the Timeeus, he offers a kind of apology to the poets for his severity, and appears to think that they may have an important vocation, though he does not clearly understand what it is. It is observable that the grounds upon which he places his arguments in the third and in the tenth books, are not precisely the same. In both, indeed, he dwells much upon the fact that the poet must adapt himself to the opinions of mankind respecting actions and character, otherwise they will not acknowledge the verisimilitude of his picture; hence he must need pervert the truth of things, and can never exalt those minds to which he accommodates himself. But in the last he appears to see a peculiar mischief in poetry from its ten¬ dency to destroy the harmony of character, to weaken self- control, and thus to undermine the justice and order of the commonwealth by the honour which it bestows upon all excited and passionate feelings. The latter argument might lead one to suspect that Plato was at least in part determined to these views by the circumstances of his own age. The exaltation of oMiisoMi8 Pa9s'on) waQt of balance and harmony in characters, the time. preference of weak, earthly creatures to calm and stately ideals, were the great characteristics of the Euripidean, as distinguished from the Sophoclean drama. Add to this the influence of a poetical age (an influence felt most when that age had departed) in fostering the worship of mere creative power, and the notion of the mind of man being the origin of all that is, which lay, as we have seen, at the root of Greek sophistry, and which it had been the great aim of Socrates throughout his life to combat. Still Plato's attack upon Homer, and his eagerness to disprove the common opinion that the Greeks were indebted to him for much of their organisation and cultivation, are proofs that he was not merely affected by these temporary considerations. How far lit* was influenced by the cir- PLATO. 171 "We leave it then as a hint for our reader's reflection, whether this reluctant condemnation of poetry by one who had been himself a poet in the formal sense of the word, and in the best sense continued a poet always, may not be explained in the same way as we explained just now his theory respecting relationship. Poetry seems to belong primarily and almost exclusively to national life. The sense of national union gives the first national, impulse to it; when that sense is weakened it withers, with its revival it starts to life again; without it men would never become conscious of their own powers, their own affections, their own wants; aud in the consciousness of these consist the joy and freedom of their life as the citizens of a state. By calling this forth in the Greeks, Homer may be said to have made them a nation, a nation full of life, full of turbulence. But is there nothing better than this mere consciousness of power ? Is there no higher condition of society than this of being citizens of a state ? The Rejmblic is an answer to the question. It teaches that far beyond this consciousness of power lies the contemplation of truth and goodness, and the assimilation of the soul to these. It shows that far beyond the mere feeling of energy to dare, to act, to revenge, lies the perception of order and harmony, an intimate fellowship with a Being above us, and the beings around us. It teaches that there is a universal society, of which this contemplation and assimilation are the ground, this per¬ ception of order and harmony the life, of which this fellowship is the result and the realisation. "With this community, says Plato, poetry hath little to do. Praise of the gods, eulogies of great men, these are the only fields for its exercise. Strictly speaking, we think he is right; that is to say, if it were possible for us, as it was necessary for him, to separate (how important it is to distinguish we hope we have explained) the national life from the universal life, the national society from the universal, poetry, which is the soul of the first, would, except in the cases named by him, be excluded from the other. If we would connect all the vital energies of which poetry is the expression, with those deeper insights, that perfect moral state and moral life which belong to the higher region, we must also understand, and by understanding realise, for ourselves at least, and, so far as is permitted us, for mankind, the law by which the universal and the national societies sustain each other. 41. The Rqmblic ends nobly with a discussion on immortality, immortality which has been less popular than that in the Phcedo, because the scenery of it is less solemn and affecting, but which for its own merits seems entitled to even more attention. "We are far, indeed, from thinking so lightly as some have done of those arguments from reminiscence, and from the law of interchange 172 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. between light and darkness, death and life, winch 'occur in the dying conversation of Socrates. On the contrary, they seem to us pregnant with the deepest meaning. But we cannot help thinking that when Plato had once realised in his own mind the connection between the life of the individual and the life of society, he felt he had a stronger ground to fix his hope of im¬ mortality upon—that he had found the point where the witness in the heart meets the demands of the reason. The sense of belonging to a community, stretching behind and before, out¬ lasting the deaths of generations of men, is an evidence to each man of his individual immortality, which you may be quite unable to translate into syllogisms, but which happily supersedes the necessity of them. Plato only went to the roots of this feeling, when, having shown that the existence of the individual and of society are alike based upon the idea of justice, and are alike sustained by the contemplation of that which is true and permanent, and alike die a moral death when they contradict the principles of their being, he affirmed that the accident of phy¬ sical death can as little change the condition of ODe as of the other, and that as they have lived here must be their life hereafter.1 1 As the Rrpnbltr, like so many other of the Platonic Dialogues, closes with a my thus, and as the passage in the third book on Lying brings the whole Bubject of the use which Plato thought it lawful to make of fables and legends directly before us, it may be as well to make one remark on this subject. Throughout this dialogue, even more than in his other writings, it is evident that, dearly as he loved truth for its own sake, and firmly as he believed it could be contemplated in its pure essence, he vet felt that there was no cri¬ terion of truth so sure as that it governed pru< tiee and was the law of lite. To substitute a pure idealism for the faith of hi> country was never his object or his dream. He hated such attempts, not more for their hardness and cruelty than for their utter inconsistency with his whole doctrine. He left them to men who did not believe that ideas were substantial, who thought they were mere creations of the mind and had nothmg to do with living acts. While then he was very jealous of all those stories which evidently hindered men from acknowledging goodness and truth as the ultimate ends of their existence, he was equally certain that, somehow or other, all great principles must have an investiture of farts, and cannot be fully or satisfactorily pre¬ sented to man except in facts. And if no such series of facts embodying and revealing truths were within his reach, rather than leave it to he fancied that his truths were bare naked conceptions of his mind, he would invent a clothing for them : it was the least evil of the two. But it was an evil; it exposed him to fearful contradictions; it often put his love for truth in the greatest jeopardy. Then what pretence have those to the name of Platonists who vrtsh to believe that there is no series of facts containing a revelation of supersensual and transcendent truths, who think it an a prion probability that the deep want of such facts which Plato experienced has not been satis¬ fied ; who are determined even hy the most violent treatment of historical evidence to prove that whenever a supposed fact manifests a principle, it must be a fable P PLATO. 173 42. "We have dwelt so long, for reasons which we have ex- Plato, how plained already, upon this great summary of the ethical, meta- g0rr"an.ytha" physical, ami political philosophy of Greece, that we can afford time but for one remark, which is necessary to show how the doctrine of Plato is connected with that of the great predecessor whose labours, we suppose, it was his intention to review. That there is a Pythagorean character in the Republic, the book on music, the passages on geometry and arithmetic, and certain mystical sentences respecting the law of decay in a State— which have defied the skill of commentators—prove abundantly. But if we look well at the work, we shall find that the whole of it may in one sense be called Pythagorean. For the discovery of the musical law which gives internal wholeness to a State, as distinguished from that external law by which its parts are prevented from falling asunder, is in fact the object of the treatise. Wherein then does he differ from Pythagoras ? Pre¬ cisely in this—that while he gives music and arithmetic their due honour as instruments for cultivating in man the feeling of his own position and relations, he does not deduce that position and those relations from any combinations of notes or series of numbers. He makes Justice—a moral principle—the music of his commonwealth. And this is the more remarkable and the more honourable, because it is evident that be felt the temptation to be a cabbalist, and never divested himself of the belief (perhaps no deep thinker was ever able quite to divest himself of it) that there is something profoundly and mysteriously interwoven with the life of man in the relations of lines, of numbers, and of sounds. It was a great merit thus to keep the practical ground so steadily, and never to forget that this is really the highest ground. By doing so he was enabled to perform the same service in one sphere which he had already performed in another, to discover the political principle which Pythagoras had been seeking for amidst the laws that connect us with nature, as he had discerned the scientific principle which Parmenides had been groping after amidst the forms of our own minds. 43. It is a great satisfaction to us that our duty, as historians Ph>sicsor of moral and metaphysical inquiries, does not call upon us, or Pla,°- even permit us, to say many words on the subject of Plato's Physics. Still the Timceus is so curiously connected with the The Tim;pus Republic by the exquisite introduction to it, in which Critias tells the story of the submerged State, so like in all respects to that which Socrates had described the day before, (here we have the doctrine of reminiscence obviously brought into play, and a new evidence that our philosopher considered the Republic as no work of imagination, but the discovery of a truth implied and forgotten in the constitution of all societies,) and so much 174 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. importance baa been attached, both in early and later times, to this dialogue, as if it contained the very heart of Platonism, that we cannot venture entirely to pass it over. With respect to the link between the Politics and the Physics of Plato, we Peculiarities would not speak confidently. He may have perceived a closer ,,f Jt' relation between the moral Koayoc, which he had been investi¬ gating in the Republic, and the material universe which Tim®us creates, than we are able to trace. But this we think is evident, that he did enter upon his new task with a kind of consciousness that it behoved him to fill up a gap in his speculations, and to complete his review of the ancient philosophy, and at the same time with a secret apprehension that the light which had hitherto guided him might forsake him in this region. It is strange at all events that, while undertaking to develope a subject so im¬ portant in Greek eyes as the creation and organisation of nature, he should make Socrates merely a listener. To a faithful student of Plato it must seem still more strange that he should on this occasion utterly desert his customary method, that the dialogue form should be merely used to throw a graceful dramatical veil over the introduction, and that in the expository part it should be exchanged for the haranguing style to which Plato was in general so averse. Use that has 44. And yet it is to this cause more than any other that the been made nmaus owe9 jts reputation among those who undertake to furnish summaries and synopses of Platonieal doctrine. Else¬ where they found him balancing opinions, often refusing to pronounce a verdict upon their respective merits—most un¬ necessarily tedious (as they think) in tracing the road to a conclusion, most unaccountably and ill-naturedly forgetful of the duty of clothing it in precise, available, transferable formulas. Here, on the contrary, though his language may be more obscure than it is in other places ; though there may be more allusions to ill-understood portions of (Jreek speculation than in all the rest; though, lastly, his teachings refer to a question upon which we all believe that he could have only very partial illumination ; still the manifest convenience of catching so Protean a philosopher for one moment in a rigid definite state, has overweighed all these considerations, and has made the Platonic cosmogony the grand storehouse from which diligent redacteurs have been wont to collect their notions of the mind and the works of Plato. Nay, it has even been a plausible and popular theory, ingeniously accounting for the uncertainty of the other Dialogues, that they were only intended as a vestibule to the inner oracle of the Tiuneus. Having sullieiently explained our views respecting these so-called uncertainties, and having endeavoured to show how much the method of Plato is part and PLATO. 175 parcel of Plato himself, we must needs regard this particular work with very different feelings. Not pretending to behold with indifference the splendid theory which it developes, aware how closely that theory is connected with some of those which exercised the strongest influence upon the minds of men, especially in the first ages of the Christian Church, and being very willing to accept for Plato the compliments which natural philosophers have paid him for his intuition of truths hereafter to be established, we must yet confess that the Timeeus seems to us chiefly valuable because it illustrates the worth of the principle from which it is so signal a departure. In every other dialogue, Plato is teaching us how to discover a universal law in any particular fact which falls under our notice ; here we have huge hypotheses to begin with, and all facts fitted and disposed according to them. 45. For whatever there is of truth in these hypotheses he is His indebted to his previous studies in another direction. Having theolo-iy" °f arrived by his own sure course of upward investigation at the with physics doctrine of ideas, he was able to see that the world must be created according to an idea. But having attained this point, his light forsook him ; he was not able to apply his dialectic to the elimination of this idea, from the names or facts in which it was imbedded. He had simply to trust to his imagination to construct a theory. Whereas in other cases he is a philoso¬ pher seeking for light, and when he could not perceive the tract of it, showing where it ought to be, and from what unrisen sun it must flow ; here he is a presumptuous theologian, assuming himself capable of declaring that which must be revealed, and thereby losing the right way to that which may be discovered. Bacon does him no injustice in respect to his Physics when piato and he says that he confused and corrupted them with theology; Bacon, when he implicitly includes him among the giants who piled hill on hill in hopes of reaching heaven. Would that our countryman, for the honour of his own character, for the sake of the ages which were to follow him, had been as willing to recognise the truth of Plato, as he was acute in detecting his falsehood; as honest in acknowledging him for a guide, as he was right in pointing him out for a beacon. He would then have seen that the Timaus was in contradiction to the principle of induction, because it was inconsistent with the principle of Plato. He would have seen that in one solitary instance the Greek sage was betrayed by that ambition of completeness and circularity (which far more than the desire of fame deserves to be called the last infirmity of noble minds) into the examination of a subject on which he could only dogmatise, and could dog¬ matise only by forsaking his own method. He would have 176 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. confessed that the Novum Organum was but the extension of that method to a new class of subjects. He would have taught his disciples that the course of investigation which promised them such new discoveries in the world of sense—which was grounded upon the great principle that man is but a seeker, which is prosperous in proportion as he endeavours simply to behold that which is, and not to darken it by the mists of his own conceptions—had been ages before marked out as the only one by which they might safely hope to become acquainted with the truths of their own being. He would solemnly have conjured them to remember that a heathen, uninstructed by that revelation which deals directly with these transcendent truths and lays them open to every peasant, had yet perceived that they must be the most precious which a man can know, and that only in knowing them he is truly a man. He would have told them, that if ever that study, in which the heathen sage forgot his usual wisdom, should become the only one in which Chris¬ tians care to be proficients, if ever ex reseratione viarvm semus et arcensione majore lit minis natures aliquid incredulitatis et noctis anirnis nostris erga divina mysteria oboriatur—or there should grow up a feeling towards these mysteries which is worse than unbelief, if it be not another form of unbelief, a stupid acqui¬ escence in them without the acknowledgment that they answer to any cravings in the heart, any necessities of the reason, any predictions of the imagination, then, for the sake of the age and country upon which such a disease had fallen, for the sake of all that should follow it, for the sake ot physical knowledge itself, which can never long flourish apart from moral light, it would be most desirable that men should resume the study of the Athenian philosopher, should realise the wants of their minds by observing those which he experienced in his, should consider in what way we' can find an adequate provision for both. DIVISION in.—ARISTOTLE. SECTION I. ARISTOTLE THE BEGINNER OF A NEW EPOCH. Thea^ of 1. When we speak of Plato as the ideal philosopher, we of Ideal"a?e sometimes forget that the people of Greece, his own fellow- citizens especially, were pursuing ideals during the whole time in which he and his master flourished. Socrates was born in 468 B.C. Plato died 347 B.C. Pericles had begun to take part in public affairs one year before the birth of Socrates; Olynthus was taken by Philip of Macedon the very year in which Plato ARISTOTLE THE BEGINNER OF A NETV EPOCH. 177 died. If one could find an expression for this period of 120 years, it would surely be this, that sculptors, painters, poets, politicians, cities, mobs, were all occupied with some ideal of beauty, wisdom, freedom, self-government, were striving to realise it, or setting it before themselves in some dream, or playing with it to bewilder their fellow-men. The philosopher, if he belonged to mankind, belonged as remarkably to his own time; he interpreted, methodised, justified its cravings, showed that they had a true foundation, and must have an ultimate satis¬ faction. 2. It is quite clear that we enter upon a different stage of The the history when Philip appears in it. His name is a sign that J^^oniai1 the age of individual energy, when pregnant events were trans¬ acted in insignificant localities, when the lowest party contests were developing the most permanent and universal principles, had passed away. His name is a signal that an age has come of concentrated organising power, of successful assaults upon freedom, of grand conceptions, of extensive conquests, of what has well been called material sublimity. This age needed its own philosophical expounder and representative. One was pro¬ vided for it, who was destined to exercise a mightier influence upon after times than upon his own. 3. In the year 367 a young man arrived in Athens who was Aristotle: born at Sta^ira in Chalcidiee. His father was a physician at y^rs. the court ot Amyntas II., king of Macedonia. This youth had already been brought to that court, and had met there Philip, the son of the king, who was a few years younger than himself. But when he was seventeen years of age, no court attractions could keep him from the city in which Plato dwelt, and in which all wisdom was to be found. Perhaps he was almost ashamed of a country which Athenians still affected to consider semi- barbarous. 4. The most scrupulous Athenian could have detected nothing An Athenian barbarous in the young Aristotle, for a certain defect which was 8tudent- observable in his pronunciation1 was owing to a lisp. Some difference might be seen between him and an ordinary student, in that he was more attentive to his person, setting off, it would appear, his short and slender figure with the advantages of a somewhat fastidious costume.2 Small quick eyes, and a sarcastic curl about his lips, were noted as characteristics of him, perhaps the only important characteristics, till Plato, who appears to have been absent on his Sicilian journey, returned and found the most promising pupil who had ever appeared in his school, one 1 rgavAbs rV ipwvqv Sjs (prjcri Ti/i68eos 6 'AOrpaios Iv ITe^l Bluu. - 'AA\a Ka\ hrxvotnteAi)!, , ki\ fj.iKg6nfJ.aros" ItrdTfTi re iiriar\fj.f Kal SaKTuAiois, Kal Kovpa. VOL. I. N 178 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY, whom he surnamed "the reader," and whose philosophical devotion he found it necessary to check rather than excite. The tutor of 5. Nevertheless Speusippus, not Aristotle, succeeded Plato exan er. ^ca(jemy Aristotle left Athens just at the time, as we have mentioned already, when the triumphs of Philip were becoming terrible to the liberties of Greece. Pive years after he was at the court of Philip educating his son Alexander. It is evident that the influence of Aristotle upon Alexander's mind must have been prodigious ; that all his subsequent history depended upon the period which elapsed between his fourteenth and his seventeeth year. He came into the hands of his master a raw untamed youth, with impulses which no man could under¬ stand or govern. He left him a Greek prince, uniting the vigour and accomplishments of the republican period, with the schemes and capacities of his father, with a desire to conquer the world, and with an intellect that was able to effect what he desired. It is not necessary to inquire whether the particular projects of Alexander were inspired or favoured by Aristotle. Even if they were discouraged, it would not be less true that the direction of mind which made the conception or the achievement of them possible, was received from the teacher by one who, without this culture, might have aspired no higher than to be a victor in one of those Olympic contests from which a not very remote ancestor had been excluded. His later 6. Alexander bestowed upon his master the only reward for ,,fe- these precious gifts which he really prized: he enabled him to make his history of animals a book which should be one of instruction and wonder to all after generations—not least to that of Cuvier and Owen. Every nation which he conquered enriched Aristotle with some new and more valuable facts. It was in Athens that Aristotle husbanded and meditated upon these treasures. There all his great works were written. There he gathered about him a circle of devoted pupils, who listened to his more popular and his more systematic instruction ; there he commented upon his predecessors, corresponded with Alex¬ ander, endured the misunderstandings of him and his court, suffered domestic sorrows, which he felt as a man, and which give us a personal interest in him ; Anally underwent the popular charge of impiety, which had caused the banishment of Anaxa- goras and the death of Socrates. On this charge Aristotle was summoned before the Areopagus; he declined to appear, and was condemned to death. He retired to Chalcis, and died there in 322 B.C. ( 179 ) SECTION II. RELATION OF ARISTOTLE TO PLATO. 1. A student passing from the works of Plato to those ot The Aristotle is struck first of all with the entire absence of that dramatic form and that dramatic feeling with which he has become Treatise, familiar. The living human beings with whom he has conversed have passed away. Protagoras, Prodicus, and Hippias, are no longer lounging upon their couches amidst groups of admiring {)upils ; we have no walks along the wall of the city, no readings >esides the Ilissus, no lively symposia giving occasion to high discourses about love, no Critias recalling the stories he had heard in the days of his youth, before he became a tyrant, of ancient and glorious republics ; above all, no Socrates forming a centre to these various groups, while yet he stands out clear and distinct in his individual character, showing that the most subtle of dialecticians may be the most thoroughly humorous and humane of men. Some little sorrow for the loss of so many clear and beautiful pictures will be felt perhaps by every one. But by far the greater portion of readers will believe that they have an ample compensation in the precision and philosophical dignity of the treatise for the richness and variety of the dialogue. To hear solemn questions treated solemnly; to hear opinions calmly discussed without the interruption of personalities; above all, to have a profound and considerate judge, able, and not unwilling, to pronounce a positive decision upon the evidence before him ; this they think a great advantage, and this, and far more than this, they find in Aristotle. 2. Still we are of opinion that a person who is able to render was justice to the method of the master, will, on the whole, be the ^j®gytle most likely to appreciate the disciple; at all events we shall not practical understand either well if we content ourselves with a vague J|^l'lrl" notion that one was a consummate artist, the other a profound practical philosopher. That Plato did not adopt his dialogue form for any artistieal purpose, but simply because it was ne¬ cessary for the development of his idea of science, we have con¬ tended already. And we feel it equally necessary, in order that we may claim for Aristotle the true and very noble position which of right belongs to him, not to let it be supposed that his pretensions to be either practical or profound rest upon his want of those qualities, and his abandonment of that method, by which Plato is distinguished. In common parlance we are wont to consider those most practical whose studies are most connected with real, living, passing questions. 2sow it was the actual opposition of Sophists, which drove Socrates and Plato to seek 180 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. for principles not yet recognised, lest they should lose those which they had. Aristotle had the advantage of being able calmly to examine sophistical arguments, because it was the hour in the school for that particular subject to be lectured upon. It was a question of life and death in Plato's day, whether we have something permanent to rest on or not; for men in every town of Greece were abusing the name of Heraclitus in support of the doctrine of a perpetual flux. Aristotle could label this question physical or metaphysical, and patiently balance it against some opposite theory. The Parmenideans forced Plato to in¬ vestigate the nature and conditions of science, for they threatened it with a hopeless stationariness. Aristotle is under no such alarm; he has merely to make out a system of analytics. It was because the body of Socrates was about to pass through death, that he was led to consider the meaning, and nature, and enduring properties of the soul. Aristotle begins his treatise on the same subject, with inquiring whether it is to be considered in reference to any particular person at all or abstractedly, and whether we are to speak of it physically or dialeetically. "Without determining which of the two courses we have in¬ dicated is the best, we think it must be a violence upon ordinary usage to say that the latter is the more practical, profound? Either is the quality of depth precisely that one which we conceive ought to be predicated of Aristotle, when it is our object to contrast him with his predecessor. It was the neces¬ sary consequence of Plato's situation, and of the task which had been committed to him, that he was always seeking for princi¬ ples. The most simple every-day facts puzzled him; nothing that human beings were interested in was beneath his attention: but then it was the meaning of these things, the truth implied in them, which he was continually inquiring alter. He found the commonest word that men speak, the commonest act that men do, unintelligible, except by the light which comes from another region than that in which they are habitually dwelling. Of this feeling there are no traces in Aristotle. To collect all possible facts, to arrange and classify them, was his ambition, and perhaps his appointed function: no one is less tempted to suspect any deep meaning in facts, or to grope after it. In like manner, to get words pressed and settled into a definition is his highest aim : the thought that there is a life in words, that they are connected with the life in us, and may lead at all to the in¬ terpretation of its marvels, never was admitted into his mind, or at least never tarried there. In this disposition there may be a comfort and an advantage ; but it certainly is not that upon which persons who are careful in the use of language would bestow the epithet profound," RELATION OF ARISTOTLE TO PLATO. 181 4. Another prejudice in reference to these great men it is How far necessary to remove, or we shall not understand their relative ^"erenced positions. It is often fancied—and Aristotle seems not altogether Socrates, anxious to do away the impression—that Plato's disciple forsook him when he forsook his master; that the later philosophy is in some important respects a return to the simple faith of Socrates. If what we have just said be correct, this notion must be not only wide of the truth, but in direct contradiction to it. The personality of Plato was precisely that quality of his mind and of his writings which he had inherited from Socrates. That he so seldom deviated into abstractions,—that he preserved so strongly the feeling, " we are actual men, wrestling against evil tendencies within, and evil powers without, capable of being educated, and of educating each other into a longing after, and perception of, the perfect Goodness and Truththis he owed to Socrates. His own especial work was to connect this personal struggle with the orderly development of principles. It was precisely then with the Socrates in Plato that Aristotle was in¬ capable of feeling sympathy. That he had a general reverence for his good sense, that he recognised him as the useful and victorious opposer of what was mischievous and unphilosophical, and that he sincerely believed him not to have held certain offensive opinions of his disciple: this we can easily imagine. But that he the least admired the Socratic method, or that all his wisdom could avail to teach him into what conclusions that method must necessarily lead one who habitually followed it, we cannot believe. 5. Though these remarks seem for a moment derogatory to Feeiinus of the fame of this wonderful man, they will be found upon reflec- towards6 tion to relieve his character from some unjust imputations, to PJat0- set his actual merits in a clearer light, and to explain the kind of influence which he has exerted, and must always exert, over mankind. There are passages in his works which, in the opinion of over-watchful and sensitive critics, indicate a personal jealousy and dislike of Plato. They remark that he does not introduce his comments upon him in a manly, philosophical spirit, but generally with some of those affected phrases of reluctance which display often more than the strongest vituperation the ill-will that is lurking within. Possibly far less meaning would have been seen in these passages, if the gossiping anecdote- mongers of later Greece had not illustrated them by stories of dissensions between the master and the pupil, which, though obviously derived from a very vulgar invention, or a memory generally treacherous, because always trivial, still unconsciously influence our minds when we have once heard them, and prevent us from fairly looking at the evidence which gives them their 182 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. only plausibility. Separated from these stories, the quotations •we think prove no more than that Aristotle felt a certain irrita¬ tion and displeasure when he perceived there was something in the words of Plato which his large intellect and immense infor¬ mation did not enable him to comprehend. To be continually haunted with a consciousness of this kind, " In all definable qualities I am equal, nay superior to my predecessor; I have reduced subjects into far greater order, I analyse far more per¬ fectly, I have a far greater store of facts at my command; and yet there is in him something quite undefinable, which seems to make an incredible difference between usthis may, no doubt, have been very vexatious even to an honest and great mind. For it was not merely the personal humiliation of such a reflec¬ tion which would be grievous to him, it would jar against his strongest conviction that nothing ought to be incapable of defi¬ nition, and that whatsoever does defy it can scarcely be of any great worth. While, then, it is no doubt possible that petty quarrels may have been stirred up between two such men by admirers and flatterers, who were equally incapable of under¬ standing either, we have no need of that supposition to account for the sneers and taunts (if such they must be called) which now and then displease us in Aristotle. Dialectics of conf°rmity with these remarks, it will not be difficult to piato: why show wherein the peculiarity of the Stagirite philosophy con- him and t'o s^et^» how ^ grew out of the Platonic, how far they are contra- imdiscipies. dictory, how far one occupies a space which the other had left void. We have seen by what steps Plato was led into his high estimate of dialectics. He watched his master maintaining a safe moral position against the attacks of the sophists. To assert realities against appearances and counterfeits was his single aim. Keeping this aim steadily before him, he almost unconsciously wrought out a method entirely different from that of previous philosophers. As Plato reflected upon the end which Socrates had proposed to himself, he perceived the full practical meaning of that truth which in terms had been asserted by Xenophanes and others,—that Being is the object of all our inquiries. He saw at the same time how necessary it was to connect the end with the method ; for till that method had been practised, Being had been a word, a notion, a negation,—not an object to be really beheld and striven after. Hence the immense importance of bringing that method forward; of presenting it substantively, as it were, to his pupils; not allowing them merely to contem¬ plate it as leading to certain results, but as the safe and universal means of arriving at any results. We have alluded to a class of dialogues having this purpose ; and these, or something answer¬ ing to them (approaching, it is possible, the nature of ordinary RELATION OF ARISTOTLE TO PLATO. 183 exposition, though we can scarcely believe that Plato ever aban¬ doned the dialogue as his vehicle of instruction), must have been the peculiar study of the Academy, as such, and expressly of the more advanced disciples.1 Hence there will have grown up among these pupils a feeling respecting dialectics which Plato would have been anxious to discourage, and yet which his own works continually tended to foster. Seeing it used as a key to unlock the secrets of social life, of moral life, of physical life, and seeing likewise the pains which their master took that they should examine the wards of the key, it was most natural that they should think a much fuller and more systematic develop¬ ment of this all-important science was desirable, and even neces¬ sary. It would occur to them that there was something like confusion and irregularity in the proceedings of their great teacher. Had he not strangely mixed together inquiries respect¬ ing the grounds of morality with statements respecting the nature of science ? Surely it would have been much better, much more orderly, that these questions should have been kept distinct, and referred to particular heads. And were there not also some indications of narrowness in Plato, which a more accu¬ rate habit of distinction would have delivered him from ? Had not his aversion to some of the usual abuses of rhetoric led him Ambition to undervalue the whole art, when it was undoubtedly capable, °[rfrne*p?r like every other, of being reduced to strict laws, and must ment and deserve to be contemplated without any reference to its acci- sys,em- dental results ? The same might be said of his doctrine respect¬ ing poetry ; the same, still more strongly, of his ill-concealed indifference to physical speculations. If all these subjects could be directly looked at in themselves as distinct branches of human culture, how much increase of knowledge might be expected in each, how much increase of clearness respecting the capacities and limitations of the human intellect! 7. Such thoughts, we suppose, may have been at work in the ^stes'ius minds of many who frequented the school of Plato. In few they desire, will have borne any fruit, in most of these few the unripe or blighted fruit of some feeble theories, professing to universalise the system of Plato, really proving that their authors knew nothing either of Plato or of themselves. But there was one who was able to make the thoughts of the rest intelligible. To him Platonism will have appeared a needful preparation for a 1 In the Life of Aristotle, by Mr. Blakesley (published in the Encyclopedia Metropolitana), it has been shown, we think most satisfactorily, that the acroamalic treatises of Aristotle differed from the exoteric not in the abstruse- ness or mysteriousness of their subject-matter, but in this, that the one formed part of a course or system, while the others were casual discussions or lectures on a particular thesis. The remark in the text is an extension and adaptation of this doctrine to the case of Plato. 184 GBEClAN PHILOSOPHY. complete and circular philosophy. Its unsystematic character, its imaginative flights, its disregard of certain provinces of thought, will have seemed to him indications of rudeness and infancy. And he will have conceived the thought of assigning to each study its true position, that one which Plato declared and proved to be so important, occupying the first place, being exhibited in its full proportions, and determining the character and treatment of the rest. Dialectics, then, was in some sense the centre of both philosophies. Nor would it be correct to say that Aristotle consciously altered the signification which the word dialectics had borne in the discourses of his predecessor. He only wished to give the study more distinctness and promi¬ nence, to exhibit the processes and operations of which it treated apart from any particular applications and results. But in ful¬ filling this desire, the character of the pursuit became inevitably changed. The feeling of Plato was, There are certain objects presented to my mind; they may be sensible objects, as trees; they may be objects for the understanding merely, as names ; but objects they are still,—things thrown in my way; and I must know what they mean, I must find out the truth of them, which lie "^0r end I must have dialectics. The object has vanished necessarily from before the eyes and mind of Aristotle ; he has begun to the"*10118 devote the whole energy of his mind to the contemplation of riatonicai dialectics in themselves. What is the consequence ? The sense principle. 0f requiring them as the means of escape from the impositions which intercept our views of things as they are, become3 more and more weakened, till at last it disappears altogether. That principle which it had been the business of Plato's life to assert against Protagoras and his school, that the mind is not its own standard, that the aspects under which objects present themselves to us do not constitute our knowledge of them, but that we may arrive at an acquaintance with them as they are in them¬ selves ; this principle, which had given his dialectics all their meaning, is no longer felt with any potency by his disciple. On the contrary, it is precisely the aspects under which we see and judge of things that he proposes to investigate. He wants to know what are the rules and conditions under which the mind, by its own constitution, considers and discourses. He makes the mind a centre, referring everything to itself, just as those did with whom Plato contended. But he differed from them in this, that their intention was knavish, his most honest. They set up the doctrine that all things are merely as they seem to us, for the purpose of unsettling all faith, and proving the judg¬ ment of each individual to be a lawful standard. He sought to convince men that all is not unstable and fluctuating, by show¬ ing them that there is a fixed rule to which human judgments RELATION OF ARISTOTLE TO PLATO. 185 must conform, which limits the exercises of individual taste and caprice, which tests and reduces to order those appearances which the Sophist pretended were infinite. 8. From this statement it will be easily apparent that the The definition of dialectics in Plato and Aristotle may be almost the dialectics of 11 . realities and same, and yet that the whole scope and object ot the science affirmations, indicated by this common definition will be different. One as much as the other could say, Dialectics is that science which discovers the difference between the false and the true. But the false in Plato is the semblance which any object presents to the seusualised mind ; the true, the very substance and meaning of that object. The false in Aristotle is a wrong affirmation concerning any matter whereof the mind takes cognizance; the true, a right affirmation concerning the same matter. Hence the dialectic of the one treats of the way whereby we obtain to a clear and vital perception of things ; the dialectic of the other treats of the way in which we discourse of things. W ords to the one are the means whereby we ascend to an apprehension of realities of which there are no sensible exponents. Words to the other are the formulas wherein we set forth our notions and judgments. The one desires to ascertain of what hidden mean¬ ing the word is an index; the other desires to prevent the word from transgressing certain boundaries which he has fixed for it. Hence it happened that the sense and leading maxim of Plato's philosophy became not only more distasteful, but positively more unintelligible to his wisest disciple, than to many who had never studied in the Academy, or who had set themselves in direct opposition to it. When Aristotle had matured his system of dialectics, there was something in it so perfect and satisfactory, that he could not even dream of anything lying out of its circle, and incapable of being brought under its rules. He felt that he had discovered all the forms under which it is possible to set down any proposition in words, and what there could be besides this, what opening there could be for another region entirely out of the government of these forms, he had no conception. At any rate, if there were such a one, it must be a vague, unin¬ habited world. To suppose it peopled wjth other, and those most real and distinct forms, was the extravagance of philoso¬ phical delirium. Accordingly, when he speaks of the doctrine of substantial ideas—of ideas, that is to say, which are the grounds of all our forms of thought, and consequently cannot be subject to them—he is reduced to the strange, and for so con¬ summate a logician, most disagreeable necessity of begging the whole question, of arguiDg that, since these ideas ought to be included under some of the ascertained conditions of logic, and by the hypothesis are not included under any, they must be fictitious. 186 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. 9. As we proceed we shall have occasion to notice how this primary difference affected the views of these philosophers upon all questions which came under their notice. At present we speak of it in order to show that the methods having a perfectly distinct object, do not of necessity interfere with each other; that the Platonic doctrine is not absurd, because Aristotle could find no place for it in his system ; that the labours of Aristotle are not useless or ill-directed, because they do not supply, as he fancied they did, any satisfaction to the inquiries which Plato had awakened. SECTION III. THE LOGICAL TREATISES OF ARISTOTLE. The 1* Every orderly examination of Aristotle must then, we con- io^ie°theian ce*ve' start from his treatises on logic. That these are key to his not the most interesting of the works which he has bequeathed philosophy. the world we may easily admit; but, unless something is un¬ derstood of their nature and purpose, it is scarcely possible to understand the character, the value, and the necessary limitation of his opinions on ethics, on politics, on rhetoric, on poetry. We shall presently quote the opinion of an eminent writer on physical science, to prove that a just estimate of Aristotle's labours in that department depends upon our knowledge of the importance which he attached to the forms of logic. And the settlement of the long-dobated question which falls more within the province of this sketch, what precise meaning he attached to the word Metaphysics, or what portion of his thoughts his dis¬ ciples referred to under that name, can, we think, be hoped for only from a previous examination of his dialectics. Complete- 2. In the Berlin edition of Aristotle, the Categories occupy nessof these the first place. Some doubt has been entertained respecting the genuineness of this treatise, which modern inquiries appear to have removed. It would in many cases afford a reasonable ground of suspicion against a work, that it exactly filled up a gap in a set of acknowledged works by the same author, so that with it they form a complete system of instruction upon the subject which they treat. But it is a set-off against this consi¬ deration, that roundness is the great characteristic of Aristotle ; and that it is less hard to imagine how a perfect series of his logical writings can have come down to us, than to believe any pupil capable of supplying a void which he had left in it. The difficulty, too, of supposing one man to possess the full mastery of this subject indicated by the successive works which he has left, is diminished when we remember that theoriginal conceptionof the study was not his but Zeno's. How naturally that conception arose in a mind which had once entered into the great principle The worth of hotb phi¬ losophies. THE LOGICAL TREATISES OF ARISTOTLE. 187 of Xenophanes and Parmenides, that the mind has laws of its own, and is independent of the appearances and determinations of the senses, we have explained already. What more than this discovery, and the application of it in confuting sensible con¬ clusions, may be owing to Zeno, we do not know. It is not impossible that some of the Sophists, while they turned the art to the worst purposes, may have done something for the refine¬ ment and improvement of it. In the school of Euelides, not only the practice, but the principles of logic must have been studied and elucidated. With these materials to work upon, it seems nowise incredible that one trained in the school of Plato to the greatest subtlety and precision of thought, and possessing in himself a comprehension and a diligence quite unparalleled, should have been able to produce a design and an edifice which after ages have found it scarcely possible to alter or amend. He had not to raise a science from its foundations ; but lateri- tiam invenit, marmoream relirpiit, may, perhaps, be said of him with as strict truth as of almost any architect that the world has seen. 3. How the work on the Categories seems to be a fitting ves- The tibule to this building. On entering it, we feel at once that the Categories: purpose to which it is consecrated is altogether different from work.'0'"16 that which Plato has been teaching us to regard as all-important, and we feel that it is a true purpose still. There is a way of penetrating into the nature and essence of things, whether those which present an outward image to my senses, or those, equally real, ^vhich merely utter themselves to my mind. With this way Aristotle does not concern himself. But it is equally certain that our mind forms notions and conceptions about the things belonging to both these kinds which it contemplates, and it may be that these conceptions themselves are subject to cer¬ tain rules. They may be defined and classified; there may be a general set of conceptions to which all particular conceptions will refer themselves. This Aristotle affirms to be the case. Under the ten notions of Substance, Quantity, Quality, Eelation, Time, Place, Position, Possession, Action, Passion, he says you may reduce all your notions. Now a Platonist is very likely to ask, " But what do these words Substance, Quantity, &c. themselves signify ?" " How do I know what Substance is, better than I know what a man or a horse is ?" " Quantity, better than I know what three cubits long is ?" And these are questions which, as we shall find hereafter, had need to be asked, and were asked with effect and advantage when the Aristotelian province of thought had endeavoured to bring all other provinces within it. But for any further purpose thau for destroying this preten¬ sion they are impertinent. When I study an actual man, or an actual horse, the substance is doubtless the x or unknown 188 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. quantity which I am inquiring after; to assume that X know it, is to stop all investigation. But I understand the name sub- Btance, as well as I understand the name man or horse. And who told you that, because there is a science of things, there is not a science of names ? that there are not laws of dependence and affinity among them ? and that conformity or nonconformity to these laws is not exactly what we mean by coherent or incoherent discourse ? There is no alternative between the assertion, that the desire so deeply implanted in us of arrange¬ ment and classification, is a mere disease, or the belief that it arises from the sense of certain limitations and conditions to which our minds themselves are subject, and is another name for the wish to understand what they are. Such a work 4. The rules of grammar, the terminology of every art and necessary. scj,ence5 the very attempt to be intelligible, presume these. And there is no safety from the efforts of men to invent divisions and schemes of thought, no safety for the great principles and laws, which these dividers and schemers are continually narrowing and stifling, but iu the clear and steady perception of certain necessary boundaries not imposed upon us by our fellow-men, but by the nature of our own understandings. Let, then, the reader carefully consider this work on the Categories. Let him ask himself whether it has not the effect of clearing his mind, and that in no ordinary degree, respecting his own modes of speech; whether it does not lead him to feel, more than he did before, that his words, winged though they be, can take no chance flight, but must move along an appointed preordained path ; and, therefore, whether there be not a witness in himself that Aristotle has a distinct and reasonable end of his own, which it is very much for our interest to be acquainted with. Logic based 5. From the investigation of these general forms under which on facts. we reduce all the notions that enter our minds, he proceeds in his treatise riepi 'Epgrtvetag, to inquire respecting the mode of our affirmations and denials. In this treatise he developes the nature and limitations of propositions, the meaning of contraries and contradictories, the force of affirmations and denials, in im¬ possible, contingent, and necessary matter. We have no excuse for dwelling on works of a merely formal character, but we men¬ tion them for the purpose of pressing the important remark of Archbishop Whateley on our readers, that the two books of 'AvaXum-a Opdrepa develope the syllogistic principle and process. Aristotle is not the mere inventor of an art, but the masterly expounder of the facts upon which that art rests, and but for which it would have no meaning. He does not teach us how to make propositions, but what propositions are, and necessarily must be, according to the conditions of the human intellect. THE LOGICAL TREATISES OF ARISTOTLE. 189 He does not tell us how to make syllogisms, but how we do syllogise, when we do not violate the laws of our mind as much as we should violate the laws of our body, if we tried to walk upon our heads instead of upon our feet. 6. But Aristotle perceived that this analysis of our mental operations was not sufficient. He had told us how we discourse, but he had not told us how we know. Are these forms of logic themselves knowledge ? Is the syllogistic demonstration the same thing with science ? Or, is one kind of it science ? Or, are the results of it science ? Or, are there certain premises assumed in it which also do or may belong to science ? What are these ? how do we get at them ? Such are the important inquiries which occupy Aristotle in his 'AvaXvrtKa vortpa. We shall endeavour to seize a few of those points in the investigation which will best enable the reader to estimate the character of Aristotle's mind, and to see how he stands related as well to his great master, as to the expounder of the inductive philosophy. 7. The treatise opens tbus :—IId<7a ^<£atn;aAia rat ttacta pdBri- oig titavoijriKri ek -Trpovirapxovffrjg yiverai yvwoEiog' 07£p0L yap $ia irpoyivwirKopEviov iroiovvrai rijv btbaoKa- Xiav, ol piv Xap&avovTEQ we irapa Ivvievtmv, oi Se beiKvyvreg to KadoXov did roii $rj\ov elvai to i:a8' EKaorow tlig afiriog sal oi Pijrop(tt» ovfiTTEtdovatv' #j yap Sta TrapabeiypaTWi/ o eoti iirayivyrj fj hi' Evdvpi}paru)v oirep earl trvXXoyiopog. There are two very important words in the opening clause of this sentence which we imagine were carefully distinguished in the school from which Aristotle came, SiSaoKaXia and paSyoig. We feel confident, also, that the last being, by the force of its name, the method of learning and acquisition, would have uniformly taken precedence of the other, which points to the communication of knowledge. That the order is here changed, that faBaofcaXta is put foremost as if it included the other within itself, is a very significant cir¬ cumstance, which is an explanation of much that follows. Plato, it is well known, had a profound reverence for mathematics. He How piato was wont to say, " Let no man undisciplined in geometry enter the halls of philosophy." Now we cannot account for this admi- their views ration unless we suppose him to have perceived in the mathema- „aTicshe tical process something akin to his own method. But this resem¬ blance certainly does not lie in that which we are wont to call the mathematical demonstration, it does not lie in the machinery of axioms, definitions, hypotheses, propositions. This machinery, valuable as it is, has scarcely a Socratic element in it. What remains ? Plato, we conceive, would have answered, Exactly 190 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. that which is the essence of mathematics, exactly the /ia ^ia. Wisdom is the knowledge about certain causes and principles. The question seems to follow of course, What kinds of causes or principles ? But this question Aristotle thinks that he has answered implicitly already. Sense and experience take cognizance of individual cases; Experience wisdom rises to the first causes and the first principles—those wisdom, ^at are most universal, those that lie furthest from mere casual observation. We must continue in his own very striking words: "Through Wonder, men both now and heretofore began to philosophise. At first, indeed, they wondered at the more difficult things which lay close by them, then went on by little and little, inquiring concerning greater things, as concerning the changes of the moon, or about the sun, and the stars, and the generation of the universe. But he that is at a loss and that wonders, thinks that he is ignorant. Wherefore also the lover of wisdom (the philosopher) is in some sort a lover of fables, for the fable consists of wonders. Now, seeing they philo¬ sophised for the sake of escaping ignorance, it is evident that they pursued knowledge for the sake of knowing, and not for the sake of any advantage. The fact supports this conclusion ; this kind of wisdom began to be sought out, when things sufficient for occupation and leisure were already provided. Just as we say that a man is free who exists for his own sake and not for the sake of another, so this is the only knowledge which is perfectly free, for it is the only one which exists purely THE METAPHYSICS OF AHISTOTLE. 199 for its own sake. "Wherefore the possession of it may be justly considered as not pertaining to man. For oftentimes the nature of men is servile; so that, according to Simonides, ' God alone would have this prize, and it is unworthy not to seek that (to be content with that) knowledge which is appropriate to him.' " If indeed the poets say truly that the Divine Nature is envious, Simonides must be right, and all over-learned people must be unhappy. But the Divine Nature cannot be envious ; rather, as the proverb says, ' the poets lienor is it fitting to think any study more honourable than this, for that which is most godlike is also most honourable. Now science may be godlike in two ways ; godlike because it is that thing which God hath above all others, or because it is itself the knowledge of the Divine. This fulfils both these conditions, for God seems to be a sort of beginning of causes, and God will possess this kind of knowledge alone or chiefly. All kinds of knowledge then are more needful than this (for common purposes), but none is better." •4. The wise man now presented to us is not the old Greek The "Wise sage who could overreach his fellows and build up a tyranny ; he ^'siotic. is not the anxious questioner in all different directions," Where is wisdom found ?" he is not the Sophist who brings all different kinds of knowledge to the market, and sells them to the highest bidder, under a pledge that they will procure him power and the fruits of power ; he is not the Socratic philosopher asking all the things that he sees for the meaning or truth which is latent in them; he is not the Platonic philosopher seeking for that which keeps knowledge, society, nature, at one. He is a man who must be carefully distinguished from, and opposed to, the man of business or practice (a person, nevertheless, to be highly prized in his way), who has a function altogether his own, a function which raises him to an almost Divine level, and makes him the one fit beholder of that which is Divine. If we ask what this is, the answer we receive is, the Divine is the Cause, that which lies beneath all other causes, that which is not subject to accident, movement, the law of growth; that which is the original root of all things. Here we have the Aristotelian theology. 5. But this theology is by the definition Metaphysics. It ™e8lotelian comes after physics in the order of its discovery : after physics theology a o" because it is implied in them; after physics because it is beyond metaplijaics, them. Yet for this very reason it cannot be separated from them ; you do not know what it is except by considering it in its relation to them. "We have been careful hitherto to use the name as little as we might, at least in our sketch of Greek 200 GEECIAN PHILOSOPHY. inquirers. It is dangerous to anticipate a name. The time will come, we may be sure, when it will be imposed if it is wanted. Soon a definer of boundaries will certainly appear, to say, " This is Morals This is Physics;" "This is Metaphysics," "When he appears, if he is a man who shows he has a right to be heard, we must of course listen to him. But his accurate limitations will be far less intelligible to us, we shall not appreciate them as they deserve, if we have not allowed previous students to take their own course and explain themselves. In general, however grateful we may be to our teacher for telling us what we are to call and are not to call each thing that conies before us, we must be careful of taking him as the interpreter of his prede¬ cessors. He has a service of his own to render us, but it is involved in the nature of this sendee that he should be an over- strict disciplinarian, insisting that guerilla troops whose worth consists in their sudden and irregular appearance, should con¬ form to the rules of regular warfare ; compelling those whose order is quite as strict as his own, but altogether different from it, to adopt his signs and divisions under peril of being treated as disobedient and. lawless. Review of 6. This remark is especially applicable to an able review of philosophies previous Greek philosophers, which is contained in the first book of the Metaphysics. Causes, Aristotle says, are four¬ fold : 1. The substance of a thing, or that which constitutes it. 2. The matter of a thing, or that which is the needful condition of it. 3. The source whence the motion of anything proceeds. 4. The reason, or purpose, or good of its existence. No one can deny the value of this classification for Aristotelian purposes, nor that it may help, if used with moderation, to clear the mind of any student respecting his own objects. But Aristotle be¬ lieves that one or other of these courses of inquiry was followed by each school of Greek thinkers, and was considered by that school as the only and all-sufficient method. Thus the Ionic philosophers studied the matter of things in hopes of discovering a primary element to which all other things might be referred. Those of this class who selected fire as their element, were natu¬ rally led by the effects which they observed resulting from that power, to speculate upon the meaning and mystery of Motion. Hence a new kind of inquiry was started, which proceeded, however, much in the spirit of those respecting elements, till Anaxagoras discovered the necessity of an Intelligence to set physical agents in movement. As, however, he had only recourse to this ultimate principle when other instruments failed him, the Atomic theory, which furnished a more plausible explanation of the facts of nature than his Homaeomeriae, easily supplanted them. Between this theory and that which affirmed Numbers THE METAPHYSICS OF ARISTOTLE. 201 to be the first principles of things, Aristotle appears to detect a connection, one not well supported by chronology. That doctrine of numbers he considers the first form of the inquiry after the essence or substance of things. The archetypal ideas of the Platonists, who regarded numbers as a kind of intervening powers between sensible things and pure essences, is the second and higher form of it. The inquiry respecting the object or purpose of things had not, he imagines, been pursued distinctly by any class of his predecessors, but it had entered somewhat confusedly into the speculations of them all. 7. Now if Socrates was, as we have maintained, the keystone Objection to of Greek speculations—an opinion which derives support from ^'assifica-8 many passages in Aristotle himself—this historical sketch, how- tion. ever ingenious, cannot be correct. For in it Socrates is merely an interloper; of right therefore only mentioned in a parenthesis, as chiefly devoting himself to ethical inquiries, Plato's in¬ tellectual descent being traced, not through him, to the Ionian and Heraclitan schools. Throughout this treatise Aristotle shows a want of sympathy with his predecessors, which must have made it impossible for him to understand those complicated thoughts and anxieties, even if he had not been determined to arrange them, and therefore became needlessly irritated with those whose vagrant habits defied arrangement. But his hints respecting other men are very important helps in becoming acquainted with himself. The Metaphysics of Aristotle are troublesome reading, partly from the frequent repetitions which occur in them, partly from the difficulty of discovering a sequence in the books. Nevertheless they should be read by any student who wishes to investigate the questions which have occupied men in later times. We shall illustrate our previous remarks by tracing a very rude outline of the subjects which are discussed in them, and recording some of the solutions Aristotle has given of the difficulties which he starts. 8. A kind of appendix which follows the first book contains a The proof that causes are not infinite, that there is consequently a ®1^dort,lc possibility of carrying on that inquiry in which past philosophers practical had engaged. The same short book contains some important ra remarks upon the manner in which the search was to be con¬ ducted, upon the contributions to truth which each school may have made, upon the advantages which a philosopher may derive from attending even to popular notions, upon the dislike which some have to exact mathematical reasoning, and the determina¬ tion of others to have nothing else, and upon the proper limita¬ tion of mathematical accuracy to things without matter. We have here also the clear announcement of a principle which the student of Aristotle has need to keep constantly in recollection, 202 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. QewpijTtKijg nev rt.Xoc AXqdem, 7rpoKrt/ojc epyov. He adds an explanation, which still further illustrates his meaning, and makes the difference between him and his master more con¬ spicuous, that the practical man has nothing to do with the eternal or the absolute, but only with the relative. This book ends with a promise of an inquiry into the meaning of the word Nature, which is not, however, fulfilled in that which is com¬ monly placed next to it. for°aoiutk>n ^is second book is a collection of doubts or questions to ' be hereafter resolved. The first doubt is, whether it is the business of one science, or of more, to inquire into all kinds of causes or principles. This question involves the very subject of the whole treatise. So many different subjects seem to be included in that province to which the general name aofta has been given—matters purely belonging to the senses, the causes of motion, the nature of Being, the reason and purpose of things —how is it possible to suppose a single science dealing with principles apparently not admitting either of analogy or con¬ trast ? Secondly, are we to look upon the most comprehensive Genera to which individual things can be referred, or upon the atoms of which they consist, as their Principles ? The third question is connected with this, is there anything besides individual things ? If not, how can they be known, for are not individual things infinite, and is not knowledge of that which is one and universal? Fourthly, are the principles of things perishable, and of things imperishable, the same ? Fifthly (which is the great question of all), are Being and Unity the essences of things that are, and not distinguishable from them; or are we to seek for the to ov and to iv as if they had each a dis¬ tinct nature ? Sixthly, are numbers, bodies, planes, and points, substances or not ? Such are the general controversies of which we are to hope for some settlement in the books that follow. The 10. The third book may be considered an answer to the first the'Phi lo™* question. There is a science which contemplates Existence as sopher, and Existence, and whatever appertains to it in reference to it; not the Sophist. other sciences, merely the attributes of certain particular existences. There are, he says, certain things peculiar to Being as Being, and these are things concerning which it is the phi¬ losopher's function to investigate the truth. The dialectician and the sophist resemble indeed the philosopher ; Being is the common subject-matter to all three. They discourse concerning the subjects which are in a peculiar sense his property. The dialectical liivapts differs from the philosophical in its nature ; the sophistical in the intention of him who uses it, tart Ik 7} SiaXcKTtKrl vEtpaoTiKi) vepiwvri j, which we must trans¬ late matter; secondly, fioprpi), or form. The matter of a thing Form and is its necessary condition. But this matter is not its essence ; Multer* something else is implied in it, something which it presents or makes manifest. Applying this principle to the questions which occupied the third class of philosophers mentioned in the in¬ troductory book—the Platonists namely, and the Pythagoreans —it appears that this form is the true eldog of which they dreamed. It is the essential thing in each thing; it is that in virtue of which substance is possible, without which it is in¬ conceivable. But it does not exist apart from each particular subject; it is that which enters into the definition of every subject, and without which the definition would be no definition; obviously, therefore, it must be viewed in that subject, and cannot be contemplated as a distinct, peculiar essence. Tested by this rule it is obvious also that all notions of an ideal form of hollowness or of pugnosedness (we use Aristotle's favourite illustration) must be out of the question; these cannot be, pri¬ marily at least, subjects for a definition; they presuppose some¬ thing whereof they are properties, and in that, and that only, can you look for an elcog. All notion again of Being as distinct from the particular person who, or the thing which, is, falls to the ground. Socrates and the being of Socrates are identical; the avroeKaarov, of which he had talked, is nothing else but this elcog, or form, inherent in the thing itself. 15. The mode in which this same principle is applied to ^o^iion; another class of inquiries, those which relate to the genesis or bifida'], first origin of things, requires a more minute examination. automatic. In considering any production we find, first, something whence it has been generated; secondly, something by which it has been generated; thirdly, the result or the thing itself. There are three modes of production—natural, artificial, automatic. In natural productions we discern at once a matter; nay, in the largest sense. Nature itself may be defined that out of which things are produced. Everything that becomes has a nature, which is only another way of saying that it has a v\i]; and that in each thing which might not have been is this i/Xy. Now the result formed out of this matter or nature is any given substance —a vegetable, a beast, a man. But what is the producing, generating cause in each case ? Clearly something akin in kind to the result. A man generates a man. Then there is implied in the resulting thing a productive force distinct from the matter upon which it works. And this is our eUog. And it is the 206 GBECIAJf PHILOSOPHY. combination of this tlSoe with the v\tj which both produces a substance and constitutes it. Look now at artificial productions. Here the el&>c is still the producing power. It is in the soul. The art of the physician, the plan of the architect, is that tlcuc which produces actual health or an actual house. Here, how¬ ever, a distinction arises. In these artificial productions is sup¬ posed a v6tjctic and a iroinoiq. The vorjaic is the perception and internal entertainment of the form ; the ttoirjaig the creation out of the given matter. But we mentioned a third mode of pro¬ duction not strictly natural or artificial, but by the action of the thing itself. For instance, a cure may take place by the application of warmth; a body may become warm by rubbing; this warmth then in the body is either itself a portion of health, or something is consequent upon it like itself, which is a portion of health. Evidently this implies the previous presence either of nature or of an artificer. Evidently also there is a necessity that this kind of generative influence should combine with another. There must be a productive power, there must be something out of which it is produced. In every case, then, there will be an vXjj and an elcog. That which is generated is the whole substance, consisting of matter and form. But the form, properly speaking, is not generated. It is reproduced in each particular subject in combination with a certain matter, and it becomes a new and peculiar form in virtue of that combination. There is necessary then to every production a certain form and a certain matter; and all the qualities appertaining to this sub¬ stance which is produced must inhere (not actually but potentially) in the substance producing, and mar/ belong to the form when they are produced. 16. It remains to consider how this doctrine bears upon the inquiries of those philosophers who busied themselves with the search after a primary element: the inquiries of those who sought for the to ol iycua are reserved for another discussion. But before we can enter upon this subject several of the doubts in our second book must be resolved. First, as to the meaning Whoie?d °* words Part and Whole. The first and most obvious sig¬ nification of part has relation to quantity, but this has nothing to do with our subject. What we want to know is the connexion of the idea of Part with substance. Assuming the division of substance into vXij and tiSos, we should say that in a brass statue the brass formed part of the statue, as the complex of form and matter, but not of the statue considered as a Form. Now as Form is the proper subject of a definition, seeing it can be described in itself, and since that which is material cannot be so described, it comes to pass that in certain cases we necessarily speak of the parts as constituting the whole, and in other cases THE METAPHYSICS OF ARISTOTLE. 207 not. "We define a circle without reference to its parts. We define a syllable by the letters or elements -which compose it; for the parts of the circle are material parts, the parts of the syllable are formal, logical parts. Of course if you look upon a syllable as composed of certain letters in wax, or even of sounds in the air, its divisions become material and do not fall within the scope of a logical definition. Again, in a material division vou assume the whole as preceding the part. On the contrary, logically and formally, the part precedes the whole. For instance, if you define the life of an auimal you will describe it by some of its functions. None of its other functions can be performed without sensation. This particular faculty of sensation, there¬ fore, will be assumed in the existence of the whole animal. This principle holds equally in reference to msthetic matter (that which the senses take account of), as in noetic (the figures of mathematics). Generally, therefore, it maybe affirmed that the question as to the priority of "part" and "whole" depend upon the distinction between matter and form, and that you cannot settle it if that distinction be disregarded. At the same time, Aristotle admits the difficulty of defining simply with reference to form, and not to the complex substance, which consists of it and of matter together. He acknowledges that the attempt to divide matter from substance and to look upon things sensible as not sensible, has led to all the Pythagorean and Platonical inventions which he regards with so much dislike. 17. Another question, in which these philosophers are also Generaand involved, follows immediately upon this. How are substances individuals, connected with kinds ? If there be certain types after which all sensible things are formed, these types would seem to be universals, and those things with which the senses converse, particulars. All possible differences and properties which can be discovered in the most marked individual of any kind must then upon this showing be included in those primitive, universal forms ; but, according to logic, precisely the opposite is the case. The genus is divested of the difference which goes to the com¬ position of the species, and of the properties which go to the composition of the individual. Your genera can never be types of the individual. By their very nature they are deficient in all that characterises him. The eldog then which forms the essential in each thing, which makes it be that which it is, must be looked upon as individualised by the v\ij with which it is connected. Apart from the modification which it thus uudergoes it is only a logical existence, the highest genus to which it is ultimately referred being pre-eminently that which can only be contem¬ plated by and in the mind. Such we take to be the meaning of 208 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. ' Aristotle, and from it the doctrine seems to follow very closely with which he winds up this book, and which applies the meaning of it to those who had dealt mainly with the uA»j. Any fact or thing being given, I have no further occasion to trouble myself about the fact, the on. This the sense, or something corresponding to sense, supplies. I am not to ask what is the musical man when 1 see a musical man. He is that which I behold, and nothing else. My business is with the cion, the cause. Why is he this or that ? And the answer is in the cleoc, the form or constitution. This is the ultimate reason of that which each thing is. Consequently I do not get nearer the cause or reason of things by reducing them into their natural The seekers elements. The analysis may be physically proper or useful, but dement ^ ^oes n0^ ^eat^ me *° *^at ^"hich I am in search. Everything confuted, which is, and which I can either behold with my senses or my mind, is not the A or the B whereof it is composed, but is something else ; the synthesis of the A and the B involves the presence of a form or existence, which cannot be found in either of them separately. So that find out as many primary elements as you will, you do not thereby find an <4px>)- Energies. 18. Our main business then is to discover the meaning of this eJSoc, and the relation which exists between it and the vXrj. The seventh book takes up this subject, and carries forward a hint which was given in the last—one which is, perhaps, the most pregnant of all the hints in Aristotle's writings, and that which has most effect upon his whole philosophy. The elSog or fxop-ntia/ili/, yet would be ill translated by that which we often oppose to potentiality,—actuality. ElSos expresses the substance of each thing viewed in repose,—its form or constitution; ivtpytia its substance, considered as active and generative; imtXixfta seems to be the synthesis or harmony of these two ideas. The effectio of Cicero, therefore, represents the most important side of it, but not the whole. 212 GEECIAH PHILOSOPHY. Aristotle proceeds to show wherein Energy is better and more glorious than tvva/iic; as, for instance, because tvvapis is the same of contraries. The capacity of health and sickness is the san^e; of stillness and movement; of being raised up and of falling down. But one of these must be good, and therefore the energy which determines which of these contraries shall have effect must be better than the Faculty or Capacity. Two consequences follow. The Energy is that which makes things be evil which have only the possibility or potentiality of evil in them. Secondly, in those things which are primary and eternal there is no evil, no fault, no decay; the capacity for evil lies in Nature. The importance of these two axioms will be felt by every moral and theological student. Another proposition, which has been extensively applied in another direction, is added respecting discovery. It is, that Discovery means the bringing things into Energy which exist potentially ; because Knowing is an Energy. 25. This book concludes with another reference to the relation Distinction between truth and being, falsehood and not-being. Truth and of subjects, falsehood being the accordance or discordance of our judgment with the actual state of things, there are three cases which may fall under our notice. First, things always united and insepa¬ rable, or things always separable and never united. Respecting these the judgment must be uniform ; the same will be truth in all cases, falsehood in all cases. Secondly, things which may be either separated or united. Here comes in the possibility of that being true to-day which is false to-morrow; of that being true under one aspect which is false under another. Thirdly, things perfectly simple, things admitting neither of division nor combination. To these the words true and false do not apply, but merely knowledge and ignorance. You either know such things or you do not. Respecting these there is no mistake, no deception possible ; but merely the presence or absence of know¬ ledge. All sensible objects whose existence you ascertain by touch or sight are of this kind; the want of touch or sight, not a false opinion, excluding them from you. 26. In the ninth book we come again upon the question of On.'nes*. unity. The name One is used, he says, in four ways. It means denmtiitns that which is continuous by nature, a whole, an individual thing, oflt> that which is predicated of a tvko/e. The general sense of the Indivisible is common to all these. And again unity in any of these senses we may attribute to some particular substance which is inseparable in place, in form, in thought, as well as to some actually indivisible whole. The fundamental notion of unity he conceives to be that of a measure to quantities ; without such a measure quantity is inconceivable. There may be some- THE JtETAPHYSICS OF AEISTOTLE. 213 tiling actually indivisible; there may be that which is indivisible to our senses; an actual unity in form, and a supposititious unity in matter. Each will bear the name, because each will be used as a measure. The need of such a measure he asserts, in opposition to the Protagorean notion of man being the measure of all things, which he treats as a silly truism, putting on the form of a paradox, and producing "the effects of a falsehood. 27. The existence of a distinct absolute unity is denied on No absolute precisely the same ground as the existence of a distinct absolute Un,ty' substance. The One is always some one thing or nature. In colours, if you suppose them all to originate from white, white is the one. In voices, the elementary vowel, and so in all other cases. Of course, then, the Ionic attempt to discover some matter, such as air or fire, which shall be unity, is as unreason¬ able as the Parmenidean, Pythagorean, and Platonic attempts to invest unity itself with a formal and separate character. 28. " The One" is the undivided, or the indivisible; this is plurality, the primary notion of it, to which all others may be reduced. " The many" then will mean the divided or the divisible; from which, as more cognizable by the senses, the One will be in¬ ferred. The question occurs next, how the one and the many are opposed to each other; whether the " many" and the " few" are not equally opposed, and whether, if this be the case, unity is not merely an element of plurality. This question introduces a discussion respecting the different modes of opposition; the opposition of contradiction, of things in relation, of privation, of strict contrariety. Possibly there has been some confusion of different lectures or reports in this part of the book ; for in the lengthened explanation we seem to lose sight of the original subject. Our readers cannot fail to have remarked how much the idea of a " law of opposition" in things entered into all Greek speculations, so as to seem to many the foundation of them. Aristotle contemplates the subject from the logical side; the forms of opposition which he discovers in our minds deter¬ mine his view of the actual opposition which exists in nature. And in this way his remarks on this point, though apparently irrelevant, throw considerable light on his doctrine respecting unity. What our understanding wants in order to explain to itself' the existence of multitude, this he called "the One." Unity was therefore, in his mind, identical with Singleness. 29. The next book is for the most part a recapitulation of puzzles and solutions already given ; not, however, to be passed over on that account, for Aristotle's repetitions of himself, or the reports of his different pupils, generally clear away many difficulties : and here, especially, the remarks on the nature and 214 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. limitations of the primary philosophy, and his confutation of the two cardinal sophisms of Protagoras, are, in many respects, more complete than those in the third book. We shall, however, Motion. notice merely his analysis of Motion and his remarks on the idea of the Infinite. Motion is neither an energy nor yet merely a potency; but it must be contemplated, alternately, as each. A lump of brass is potentially a statue; the energy which is to make it one is in the mind of the sculptor. The motion, i. e. the transition from its condition as brass to its condition as a statue, is not found in the brass, neither is it found in the mind ; it is that which gives the potentiality of the brass its meaning and connects it with the energy. Or to express this in a formula. " Motion is the entelechy (the per¬ fecting power or principle) of the potential as potential." He admits the difficulty of finding an expression for this idea; but he shows, by an examination of previous attempts, that his own, however awkward, is the only one which is satisfactory, ihe infinite. 30. On the subject of the Infinite, which had so much exer¬ cised the minds of previous Greek speculators, and had been resorted to as an ultimate solution of so many difficulties, he aims at no precision of language. By its very nature it excludes precision. To bring it into a scheme, or regard it as a helpful definition of nature or the universe, is, in his judgment, absurd ; it can only be looked upon as marking the ne plus ultra to which human thoughts and inquiries can reach, or, at least, have already reached. The limitations by which alone you are able to deal with the subjects that fall under human cognizance it excludes by its very name. His opinion on this point is characteristic of his mind, and it has an important bearing upon the history of metaphysics. Scarcely any more interesting question occu¬ pied the Greek mind than that which was at issue between the schools of Pythagoras and Xenophanes, whether it is more true and reverential to speak of God as the to nepag, or as the In¬ finite. Aristotle's concluding remark on the subject of the Infinite should be quoted for the casual light which the latter clause of it throws on his idea of Time, an idea which the stu¬ dent of modern philosophy has so much need to reflect on :— to <5' &TTEipov ov ravTOv iv ueyiOet cat kivtjoei kat \p6vtf ws pia rig * wore, 6 Src'os aft, davp.a 5e yt {nrapxfi. i) yctp vov ivfpytla faWj, fKfivos Si i] tvtpyEta- tvepyfia 5e Kad' aimjv fKttvov igKTTij Kal aiStos. Met. xi. 7. THE METAPHYSICS OF ABISTOTLE. 217 tradiction in things, but had not taken account of that third element, matter, which is the only explanation of the evil and disorder in the universe, and that they had substituted many original principles for the one. 36. In the two last books, their doctrines (respecting ideas Reai object and numbers) are again discussed at great length, and with ®^J(,sthew; Aristotle's wonted ingenuity. It cannot be expected that we should go over arguments to which we have so often adverted, and which we are less anxious to present fully and formally than to fit our readers for studying them in the places where they occur. But we may take this opportunity of remarking, that the continual renewal of these discussions with the Platonists and Pythagoreans is very important in helping us to determine the nature and connection of these particular treatises, as well as the character of Aristotle's whole mind and system. It is evident that he felt the refutation of these opinions, and the substitution of something else for them, to be in a manner the business of his life. At all events, it was the needful preliminary to his more positive proceedings : while his mind was haunted with these notions, the system—physical, metaphysical, or moral—which he proposed to rear, had, it seemed to him, a dubious and infirm foundation. "We look, therefore, upon the metaphysical treatises (whether capable or not of being reduced into a formal sequence and unity) as having this subject for their centre. To show what ideas are not, and what they are ; to establish the doctrine, that the tT^oc is not distinct from the particular individual substance—existing apart and connecting it with some higher substance—but merely its inherent form ; to connect the eldoc, which is the constituent principle of each thing, with the iyepyeia, whereby it is called into existence, and thus to make the same answer satisfactorily to the two Greek inquiries respecting the nature of being and origin of matter ; to explain the nature and conditions of the v\tj, and by depriving it of all intrinsical substantial properties, and reducing it into a mere potency, practically to get rid of the old Ionic investiga¬ tions ; then finally to hint at a principle of which bis moral writings are the full exposition, that the final Cause, or the ov eveKa, is also connected with the eiSoc and erepyeia • that the good or purpose of each class of substances is known when we know what its nature and proper energy are : this is the object at which he is aiming most consistently amidst all his windings and recapitulations in the books of Metaphysics. 37. But this object is connected on the one side with Logic, Metaphysics on the other (as the scholiast is so anxious to inform us) with —how Theology. Though we have not seen our way to adopt Bitter's method of identifying the logical treatises with the metaphySical (a plan inconsistent with the very words of the third book) ; 218 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. though, as it seems to us, we should sacrifice by such a course much insight into the habits of the philosopher's mind, and the growth of his opinions, which we obey by studyiug them dis¬ tinctly, and yet acknowledging the most intimate connection between them, we believe Aristotle to be primarily and at heart a logician ; to have become thoroughly enamoured of the forms of logic, and convinced that they supplied a satisfactory expo¬ sition of the facts of the world; and then gradually to have worked out in his mind an Ontological system, which gave the rationale of those forms and interpreted their relation to dif¬ ferent phenomena. Now, if it be true, as we have maintained, that the mathematician has another set of laws, discovered to him in the course of his inquiries, from those with which the logician is conversant, we need not be surprised either that the arguments of Aristotle against Ideas should be so constantly mixed with allusions to the Pythagorean Btudy of Lines or Numbers, or that that study should actually have been the base of the principle which he is endeavouring to subvert. How 38. It is on all accounts a more important inquiry how connected Theology became interwoven with either set of speculations. Theology. We think it cannot be denied that the recognition of an absolute Being, of an absolute Good, was that which gave life to the whole doctrine of Plato, and without which it is unmean¬ ing ; that, on the contrary, it is merely the crowning result, or at least the necessary postulate, of Aristotle's philosophy. In strict consistency with this difference, it was a Being to satisfy the wants of Man which Plato sighed for; it was a first Cause of Things to which Aristotle did homage. The first would part with no indication or symbol of the truth that God has held intercourse with men, has made himself known to them; the second was content with seeking in nature and logic for demon¬ strations of his attributes and his unity. When we use personal language to describe the God of whom Plato speaks, we feel that we are using that which suits best with his feelings and his principles, even when, through reverence or ignorance, he forbears to use it himself. When we use personal language to describe the Deity of Aristotle, we feel that it is improper and unsuitable, even if, through deference to ordinary notions, or the difficulty of inventing any other, he resorts to it himself. Theology then can have no connection with the ethics of Aristotle. section n. ARISTOTELIAN PSYCHOLOGY. Aristotelian 1. The light which the metaphysical treatises throw upon the basedon01 point to which we last referred, makes them an important in- Theoiogy; troduction to Aristotle's ethical system. A. Ill STO TEL IAN PSYCHOLOGY. 219 We might have concluded from his Dialectics, that he utterly rejected the Platonical doctrine of Ideas as a scientific exposition. It would not follow that he should discard that belief in some ideal of excellence which had impregnated all mythologies, and had never been banished from the hearts of men. But the Aristotelian conception of God as a ground of nature simply, leads us at once to perceive that no recognition of his perfection can have the least connection in his mind with a scheme of practical life and conduct. It is not with Plato, or any philosopher who had attempted to give the rationale of men's dreams on this matter, that he will feel a want of sym¬ pathy ; he actually has not discovered in himself, and does not recognise in his brethren, the want which all ages had been contriving in so many forms to express. And then it becomes an interesting question, what groundwork in the Aristotelian ethics will replace that Theology which is so obviously the foun¬ dation of the Platonic ? 2. The answer to this question brings us to a very important but on the treatise of Aristotle, which embodies more of what has, in our "be'souuf day, been commonly called metaphysics, especially here and in Scotland, than the works professedly bearing that title. We mean the three books on the Soul. The first of these books is occupied as usual with an examination of previous theories on the subject. He despatches very elaborately the different notions respecting the soul which Democritus, Empedoeles, or the Pythagoreans had encouraged. He shows why we can never be satisfied with calling it motion, or the principle of motion, or the primary element or number. He then proceeds in the second book to develope his own doctrine. The soul belongs to the category of entities. It has then, of course, asouithecha- matter and a form ; the matter here, as elsewhere, coincides with olivine'* its Cvvctfiic; the form is iyre\e\eia. The soul is neither of these creatures, separately, but the result of both. There go to the forming of sight the energy of vision, and the faculty of vision^ ana there is, in addition to both, an organ, aD actual eye. What is true of this sense is true of the whole substance oi which it may be said to form a part. The soul, possessing both its energy and its faculty distinct from the organ through which both are manifested, does yet require such an organ. The soul is not a body, but neither is it without a body. Generally, it is the dis¬ tinction of a living creature (faov), that it has a ^rvxv- 3. But all living creatures have not a soul exercising the same Distinction Swafitiq. We may define all the faculties which can exist inofsoul8, any living creature to be these: first, the faculty of receiving nourishment (QptirriKT]); secondly, the faculty of sensation (AioAtjrnoj) ; thirdly, the faculty of motion in place (icivijmq) ; 220 GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. fourthly, the faculty of impulse or desire (opck-rurij) ; fifthly, the faculty of intelligence (Siavoijruo/). The threptic faculty is the lowest of these, and is present in all cases. The soul, therefore, as endued with this one faculty, may be attributed to vegetables. Wherever any of the higher faculties are present, there all the lower will exist also. Under each of these heads a very inter¬ esting discussion arises respecting the character and limits of the particular faculty. The question, for instance, under the first head is, whether the life in each plant or thing must be considered as the active or only the passive instrument in self- sustentation ? Under the head of sensation many more com¬ plicated points arise, and Aristotle enters into the whole theory of the subject, examining the operation of each sense in detail. This, it may be remembered, is the discussion which is carried on with so much liveliness and profundity in one part of the Thecetetus. The opinions there attributed to Protagoras (and so far as the doctrine of sensation goes, apart from its moral consequences, not denied by Plato) is nearly the same as that maintained by Aristotle. Sensation is neither in the organ of sense nor in the object, but is generated between both, and is the effect of the medium through which they hold communion with each other. The question as to the motive faculty involves us at once in a consideration of that which is higher than itself. Movement must depend upon impulse. This will be true in all creatures. And in spite of the effect of the appearances which are produced upon or by means of the senses, in generating impulses or desires, we must not impute a governing power to sensation ; we must rather think that the nature of the faculty of impulse determines how these shall influence it, than that it is determined by them. It would seem, then, that each creature has a nature, which is expressly seen in this faculty of impulse. Wherein then does man differ from other creatures ? Neither, it would seem, in the absence of this impulsive faculty, nor in its being less properly his nature than it is that of other animals, but rather in his having the dianoetic faculty to direct it and act with it. In the coincidence and conspiracy then of these two faculties will consist the true nature of man. Thus, the soul may be considered as containing three portions, logically not materially separate, one absolutely without reason, the other rational, another participant of reason. In this psychological system we discover the root of the Aristotelian ethics of which we were in search: they begin in Psychology and terminate in Politics. THE ARISTOTELIAN ETHICS. 221 SECTION vn. THE ARISTOTELIAN ETHICS. 1. At the outset of the Nicomachaean Ethics (which has The always been regarded as the most complete exposition of his views on this subject), Aristotle tells us that Ethics is an intro¬ duction to Politics. The two, therefore, are not identified in his mind as they are in Plato's; it is quite possible, nay necessary, to treat of them distinctly. According to his uniform method, he seeks for the grounds of combination and society in the nature of man. He cannot tolerate Plato's simplicity in admitting outward necessities and accidents to be the occasions of society ; for this simplicity necessarily involves another pro¬ ceeding which seemed to him not simple but pregnant with all Plato's idealism, that of supposing some higher Unity than that which is expressed in the character of any particular society to be involved in the constitution of Society itself. A principle of equality and adjustment is that which seems to him to pervade all things, to be in a manner a law of the universe, and to be especially the secret of human order and government. The like principle, taking a different form, is the mainspring of his ethical system. Virtue lies in a mean; in a sense it may be said to be a mean, so that, on the one hand, Government, which is also a mean, is naturally occupied in sustaining the virtue of particular men, and on the other, this Virtue is itself the great conservation of government. This observation ought to be made, as without it the connection between these two spheres, which is as much acknowledged by Aristotle as by his master, will not be apparent. Many difficulties also will present them¬ selves to the reader as insurmountable, if he looks at the ethics as an entire system, and does not remember that a directing educating power is for practical purposes presumed to reside in a governing body, the functions and nature of which have not yet been defined. 2. But we are not to suppose that Virtue, or the attainment Happiness of this mean, is in Aristotle's judgment the formal object at |^eri^l,'ct of which either the life of each particular man, or society at large, pursuit. is aiming. AVhen once the notion of an absolute good, which " those dear" and troublesome men, the Platonists, had intro¬ duced, was taken out of the way, there remained one obvious and generally admitted end of all human desires and searchings. Happiness is emphatically the human reXog. But if human, then the definition of this happiness must be sought in that which is peculiarly the characteristic of the human class. It cannot exist in any of those powers or faculties which are 222 GBECIAN PHILOSOPHY. common to it with other classes ; not therefore in the threptic or the jesthetic powers merely and chiefly. And anyhow, it must be in some exercises or energies that it will consist, for in these the soul or life of every creature makes itself manifest. It must be then in the energies of our best and highest nature, exercised not at intervals, but through a whole life, a life pos¬ sessing so much of external prosperity as shall permit them a free scope. The human 3. But all energies must have a certain direction; the right virtue. direction of its energies constitutes the virtve of each class. What then will be specifically the human virtue ? It must of course be in the man, and, according to our psychology, the optfrc (the impulsive faculty) is the constitutive faculty of the human soul, though its excellence consists in its subjection to the dia- noetic faculty. Virtue then will imply the presence and har¬ mony of both these ; still it will be found most positively and characteristically in the former. It must be then a habit. But of what kind ? To what does it point ? What is its aim, seeing that an absolute good, or an ideal, is out of the question, and that happiness cannot be the aim, because it is the very nature of happiness which we are now resolving into its ele¬ ments ? We are not, Aristotle says, to trouble ourselves about scientific accuracy in our definitions; our purpose is purely practical; we want to form an actual man of a certain character, not a theoretic man. Excesses. 4. Well, then, practically speaking, excess is in every case that to which you attribute mischief and derangement. There is an excess called Timidity, and an excess called Fool hardiness, an excess called Prodigality, and an excess called Narrowness The Mean, or Avarice. But the extremes suppose a mean. This is the end at which our habit aims. Virtue generally lies in this. But we are aiming at action ; and actions are not general, but specific; how then shall we arrive at the notion of specific virtues ? Their species will be determined by their distinct objects. Certain tendencies and habits will be conversant with external pleasures. Certain others with passions of the mind itself; in each case it will be found that the practical pur¬ pose defines the virtue. But though a general description may be given both of the excesses and the means which correspond to them, a description which will be really applicable in all cases, it must ever be remembered that the excess itself may be different for each man, actually different according to his actual circumstances, different in its effects and influence upon him according to his greater proneness to one side or the other. For instance, liberality will be practically a different quality in the rich man and the poor man, and the temptation to profusion THE ABISTOTELIAN ETHIC3. 223 will be that whicb is to be most resisted by one, to meanness by another. Virtue will be therefore in a mean, that is one to im, and not one which can bo absolutely and invariably ascer¬ tained by rule. 5. Hence it follows that this habit supposes the exercise of a Predetermi- faculty of choice or predetermination. But what is predeter- natlon- mination ? Is it the same as the act of willing ? Clearly not: that has reference to ends, this to the choice of means for the attainment of ends. It implies a right end, and a right deter¬ mination of the will to that end. It may be called fye&c fiovXevnki) (the reader will observe how steadily his psycholo¬ gical axiom which we have spoken of is kept in view throughout the scheme). But to what cases does this will or counsel refer, and how far is it dependent upon ourselves ? Clearly we do not consult about things absolute or eternal, nor about things within the sphere of accident. What remain are all such things as are done by us or with our concurrence. Now of such some may be doubtless taken from under our control by actual vio¬ lence practised upon us; such cases give rise to various ques¬ tions of casuistry, as to the course which a virtuous man will choose, whether he will submit to do wrong or to die, each of which cases must be determined on its own merits. With respect to ordinary cases, the doubt arises, whether inclination is not itself a force upon the will and on the reason both. Such a notion Aristotle disposes of, first, by the remark that an influence upon the impulse or will cannot by any reasonable man be confounded with a force by which its operations are hindered; and secondly, by admitting that an incapacity for particular action may doubtless he produced in any man by these influences, but that this incapacity is itself the result of a previous habit which need not have been formed. Habits then are in our own power, actions not always. 6. Having settled these foundations, the particular ethical Specific virtues come next under his consideration. Here lies a field for churacters- the exercise of his always acute and often delicate habits of observation. It is alien from the temper of mind which Shak- speare has wrought into us, to contemplate any character as the mere development of a single specific quality. We do not like to hear of a man as the Magnificent, or the Magnanimous, or the Modest, or the Temperate, or the Just. But, doubtless, there was something in this which suited well with Greek habits. Aristides, Themistocles, Cimon, if they had not a dis¬ tinct purpose of realising a particular form of character, yet drop more readily into certain moulds than the traditionary characters in the story either of ancient Home or modern Europe. How a similar tendency was revived at one period 224 GUECTAN PHILOSOPHY. in Christian society, and how its revival was connected with a scholastic reverence for Aristotle, we may have to notice here¬ after. Justice. 7. Among these virtues it behoves us especially to take notice of two, because they throw some light upon the entire system, and upon ethical inquiries generally. The first is Justice (Siicatoouvri). Is not this virtue itself an abstract of all the virtues ? We have seen how Plato answers the question in his Republic. Aristotle treats it differently, yet so as to make us see how much he had felt the influence of his master's ideas, even when he rejected them. In one sense (he says) StKaioovvt) may indeed be said to be a complex of virtues. For as it is the habit which mainly disposes us to obey the laws, and as laws prohibit excesses of all kinds, and encourage virtues of all kinds, this will have respect to them all. But yet there is such an offence as overreaching, and there must be a specific virtue answering to this. The specific virtue will bear relation to the general. Inequality, in matters appertaining to property, will be the evil. Evenness or equality will be the virtue. This evenness or equality implies, on each side, an excess, a more and a less; a more and a less, however, in reference to given persons. The conservation of the right proportion or relation of things to persons, and the restoration of the balance when it has been violated, is then that at which this virtue especially aims. Take away the restriction to property, and this virtue would seem to be in a remarkable manner the very virtue of virtues; so emphati¬ cally is it the preserver of the mean. But that very restriction makes it more difficult to tell how far this virtue belongs to the individual, and how far to the State, so that Sucauxrvyri, though bearing a much more limited meaning, becomes, to our author as to his master, a kind of debatable ground between the two regions. At all events SiKaiovvri must be looked upon as the ethical virtue of a statesman. Moderation. 8. The other virtue we must speak of is crauppoenyrj. As this is opposed to aKo\ta, by vovg. Tixvij is what in modern language would be called the creative power or faculty, the poetic organ in its highest and lowest sense. 'EiriaTfipT] is the converse of this. It deals with that which cannot be otherwise, it does not fashion anew hut perceives; what it deals with are universals, not particulars. Aristotelian science is, as we have seen already, conversant with conclusions, not premises ; but there must be some faculty which deals with premises, a tact, intuition, or spiritual sense; this is vovg. The sphere of this faculty would seem to be very limited, for as it is bounded on one side by knurr>//*>/, it is bounded on the other by crofia.. This faculty, we wero told in the Metaphysics, was con¬ versant with hpxai or principles; it might therefore seem to cover the whole ground which is assigned to vovg. But that which affirms things to be so and so without a reasoning pro¬ cess, is undoubtedlwlistinct from that faculty which, through long and winding labyrinths, searches for causes. Now, when the vovg is said to deal with premises, the first kind of operation is indicated ; when the trop6vr](rig, the last of the five, is different, and yet has something of the character of the preceding. Its sphere is with the altering and the alterable, like Ttjfvtfa yet it is not productive or creative, but perceptive TOL. i. Q 226 GEECIAN PHILOSOPHY. and distinguishing. So far it resembles £7r«rrcc civilization, and perhaps also of speculation, was appointed to there°Ug " receive into itself different streams of thought, which bad been running, in various directions, during all the period between the birth of Moses and the birth of our Lord. Was it possible that these streams should really mingle ? Could it be at all ascertained which had descended from the highest ground ? To what river the rest were tributary ? 3. The Gymnosophist or Brahmin was a subject of curious Feebleness speculation to the observers and geographers of Greece; but, of each' except in the case of Pyrrho, there is no instance of any effect upon Greek thought and speculation proceeding from him. The dualism of the Persians had actually entered largely and practi¬ cally into the thoughts of Socrates and his great disciple. Neither in its own native form, nor in any other, was it likely to affect the minds of men who had ceased to feel there was a conflict in themselves—who merely discoursed and criticised. The Egyptian animal worship had become too gross for any symbolism. If symbolism took no form but that, it would only affect Greeks with disgust. None of these different doctrines then could subdue the Greek mind to itself, or even change its direction. And, certainly, the teachers of Alexandria could as little interpiet the faith of any people of the East or West^ They knew nothing really of Plato or Aristotle; they could comment upon them ably; they had never thought or felt with them at all. 4. In time another element was added to those which the The Roman patronage of the Ptolemies had collected. The Boman appeared coniiueror on the Egyptian soil; Egypt became a Boman province. A sufficient proof seemed to be afforded by this fact, that there was something stronger in the world than Greek subtilty. 5. Yet here, as elsewhere, the Boman conqueror did homage submit* to to tbe Greek slave. No countryman of Cicero would have dared the 0reek* to express his thoughts or conceptions in an Alexandrian school which the legions of his country protected or overawed. 25G the jewish philosophy. However conscious he might be of a capacity in government, which was utterly unknown to the Greek of any age, he could yet feel that the Greeks of the lowest age had in this depart¬ ment of philosophy a right to be his masters and dictators. Nowhere less than in Egypt were his maxims respecting duty and obedience likely to be heeded. Among all the motley classes which composed the population of Alexandria, there were scarcely any but the Roman soldiers upon whom they would make the slightest impression. The Jew. 6. Among all those who visited the city of the Ptolemies the Jew is perhaps the last in whom men generally would expect to find an expounder or reconciler of the thoughts which had possessed or disturbed the minds of other people. "Was he not prevented from his very calling and position from meddling with the words and acts of the uncireumcised ? Was he not bound especially to regard their search after wisdom as profane and dangerous ? Did not the Divine lore which he had received exclude and condemn all other? We have partly consi¬ dered these questions already, so far as the principle of them is concerned ; we have now to consider what answer facts return to them. SECTION II. THE JEWISH PHILOSOPHY. Ecciesias- 1. The books which we call apocryphal, with the exception Wisdom of6 °f two books of Maccabees, contain little that is interesting Solomon, or valuable as history. The books of Ecclesiasticus and the Wisdom of Solomon are in the strict and formal sense of the word philosophical. Amidst much that seems to most AVestern readers trivial and inflated, the passages which speak of AVisdom as a teacher, of AVisdom as an object of passionate love, of Wisdom as that for which all things else are to be sacrificed, possess a beauty which every one confesses. The fervour of these passages has been caught in a study of those which belong really to the age of Solomon ; they are commentaries upon his writings, but not mere commentaries; the writer was not a book student only or chiefly; he has himself pursued wisdom, and lived under her discipline. There is a devout recognition of the sacredness of Jewish history in these books. The Divine Ruler of the nation is looked upon as the Ruler of the spirit of each individual man ; every fact in the revelation is treasured up as needful for the education and meditation of the seeker for wisdom. And yet it is not only the language which separates these books from the Scriptures, and connects them ith Greek Phiio, bom thought; there is a Platonic character about them, such as we about oa not mee^ iQ Cicero, or even in Cicero's groat pupil. b.c. zO. Intellectual y the son of Sirach, whoever he may have been. T1IE JEWISH PHILOSOPHY. 257 was beyond measure inferior to Aristotle or to Cicero, yet we can¬ not help believing that Plato would have sympathised with him more than with them,and have found him capable of apprehending positions which all their intimate acquaintance with the technical phraseology of the schools could not have enabled them to mast er. 2. "When these apocryphal books were written, the Jew, how- pbiio. ever, had probably not claimed his connection with the philoso¬ phers of G reece and of the world. About the beginning of the Christian era, a Jew was teaching in Alexandria, who, while he retained the profoundest reverence for the Divine oracles of his country, acknowledged the Indian Gyumosophist, the Greek phi¬ losopher, the Egyptian symbolizer,as having received wisdom from the Source of wisdom, as having been led, so far as they were led, out of the pursuit of visible and sensible things, by One who is seeking to bring man's spirit into communion with Himself. 3. There are few particulars known respecting the early life Hismeir'ai of Philo, this Alexandrian Jew. His own narrative of his em- h,story bassy to Caligula, for the purpose of representing the state of his countrymen in Egypt, is a curious document both for Roman and Jewish history, but it throws no light upon his own life, except so far that it shows that when a very old man he retained his patriotic sympathies, had not destroyed his practical powers by speculation, and possessed to a great degree the confidence of his Jewish fellow-citizens. What else is known of Philo must be gathered from his books; those books which exercised so great an influence over the early Christian church, and which have procured him the name of the Theosopher. 4. An examination of the meaning of this word will be the An admirer best help to the explanation of the writings which have es- philosophy, tablished his claim to it. The word philosopher is of continual recurrence in Philo's writings. He speaks of the lover and pursuer of wisdom as the spiritual or divine man; who has quitted the downward path, and is seeking his proper object. But the seeker of wisdom is also the seeker of God. Wisdom is not an aggregate of conclusions; it is not the human soul, it is not a something diffused through all things; it is the I Am who spoke to Moses in the bush—the Instructor and Inspirer of all the prophets—He who gave the law on Sinai. 5. Philo confessed, as any Jew must, an absolute Being ; one The Divine dwelling in light which no man hath seen or can see. How such Word* a Being should converse with man, how there could be sympathy between Him and a creature, was the wonder of the Hebrew psalmist and prophet. But he believed while he wondered. Philo saw that such an intercourse was as much implied in all the Hebrew records; as much implied in the nature of God Himself as His self-existence and self-concentration. The two VOL. I. s 258 TLIE ALEXANDRIAN PHILOSOPHY. truths could not be reconciled in a theory. A Divine "Word, a Logos, speaking to the mind and spirit which was opened to hear the voice, was, Philo thought, the reconciliation. Such a speaker he traced in all the most obvious and minute expressions of the divine book, in all the steps of the Hebrew history. Th<» teacher 6. It is this principle, worked out through all the Scripture of men. narratives, which constitutes the peculiarity of Philo's writings. This is his philosophy or theosophy. On this ground he can contemplate with interest the Brahminical aspirations after ab¬ sorption in the divine essence; the struggles of men to know the divine, the beautiful, the good ; their eagerness to escape from sensual defilements and the prison-house of the body; their sense of moral obligation ; their mythological or natural allegories. The path of sensuality and darkness is that which most men tread ; a few have been led along the upward path ; a few in all countries and generations have been wisdom-seekers, or seekers of God ; they have been so because the Divine Word or Wisdom has looked upon them, choosing them for the know¬ ledge and service of Himself. Philo's great 7. From the hints which we threw out when we left the D,ent!>" Jewish Prophets to enter upon the wide field of Gentile specu¬ lation, it may be fancied that we shall gladly rest in Alexandrian theosophy as the end and consummation of our inquiries. We spoke of the Divine Word who had taught the prophets as the one source from which, as they and we believe, all illumination proceeded. Philo, holding that faith, has discovered a standing point, from which he can regard with affectionate sympathy a number of earnest thoughts which have occupied the hearts of men in different ages. He has escaped the temptation of sup¬ posing that any general theory or system can unite these thoughts ; from the temptation, that is to say, of killing them, that he may harmonise them. He has told us what the phi¬ losopher is pursuing, and who is guiding him in the pursuit. But there are several serious questions to be asked before we cau give ourselves up to the hopes which the Alexandrian teacher seems to hold out. What has he done to explain the great puzzle of the Bhagavad Gita—how practical life can be reconciled with the life of the Brahminical sage ? What link is there between his mysticism and the dry business-like reflections of Khoung-fou-tseu ? What one step has he taken towards solving the problem of Plato's republic ? If the Aristotelian " theory" is abundantly honoured in his books, what hint is there which cau explain Aristotle's assertion that politics is the architectonical science, or can bring his reverence for human relationships into consent with the communism of his master ? If the Roman sense of duty meets with some respect from the Alexandrian, how can he enable any Roman to understand his THE JEWISH PHILOSOPHY. 259 feeling, that a divine power had been building up his city for generations; to foretell whether the battle of Actium and the death of the Egyptian queen would be the means of restoring or destroying its order ; to guess whether Augustus, or some ruler of quite a different kind, would be the founder of a uni¬ versal kingdom in which freemen could dwell ? 8. On all these points Philo is silent. The meditations of phiio'sirr«it the philosopher or theosopher are everything to him ; the con- deficiencies, dition of the universe, except as it consists of philosophers or theosophers, nothing. He cannot, therefore, satisfy the demands of philosophy, for that in its highest, as well as its humblest form, is occupied with questions, not about itself, nor about the class which professes it, but about nature, man, God. Did this incapacity arise from his adhering too closely to his own records ? They speak from first to last of a polity ; they describe the gradual growth of one under Divine superintendence, out of a single family. Of this growth Philo sees nothing. The shep¬ herd life of Abraham—the acts of Moses and Joshua—are nothing, except as tbey suggest divine allegories, from which the theosopher may derive nourishment. Is it not possible, then, that he failed to explain Plato, and the teachers of the old world, precisely because he had not a sufficiently simple appre¬ hension of the books which he studied so profoundly, and admired so earnestly, and in which he thought that he could find the essence of all philosophy ? 1. A society arose in the days of Philo which said that it was A Jew the expansion and fulfilment of the polity, the beginnings of foruXwric which are recorded in the Hebrew histories. A teacher who 1,1,11 ty had lately become one of the officers in that society, was accused mUie'6 by a synagogue of the Alexandrians, before the High Priest and (,<,tv1^n,'on Sanhedrim at Jerusalem, of speaking blasphemous words against ai.solute the temple and the law,—of saying that One was come who U€1"R- would change the customs which Moses had delivered. He defended himself, not by interpreting the story in an allegorical sense, but by showing in a plain narrative how in each period there had been a fresh unfolding of a divine kingdom, through human agents,—how each period assumed and made necessary the manifestation of One who should prove its foundation to be actually divine and actually human. That witness was stoned, as those who spoke like him in former days had been. 2. Another Jew, who was present at his death and took part a Jew in it, shortly after incurred the hatred of his countrymen by • • 11 • • /> r\ l -n i l 1* mi ihl* Sf.llVD Of inviting heathen citizens of Corinth, ot Dphesus, and ot Ihessa- utier lonica, to become members of the society which had begun in wiUuid'vuie Palestine, and which at first had only included circumcised men. iwuum Hi* disciples at Corinth were full of the Greek passion for Fu3u"' 260 THE ALEXANDRIAN PHILOSOPHY. wisdom ; they fancied that he and an Alexandrian teacher were rival sophists, each desirous to palm his own doctrine or theory upon them, and to bind them together in a sect called after their name. He told them that that teacher and himself had come to proclaim a hidden and divine wisdom, but a wisdom which had shone forth in weakness, of which the only perfect manifestation was in a Man who had been crucified. He told them that their fellowship included the weakest, the most ignorant, the most evil; that the members of it formed one body in one Head, and that whoever sought to divide them, or boasted of some wisdom of his own, was their enemy and destroyer. He told the people of the city in which Heraclitus had dwelt, that all spiritual blessings were theirs,—all the mysteries of divine knowledge ; and yet that they were com¬ posed of all the kindreds and tribes of the earth, the invisible and the visible worlds being reconciled in Him who anited divine glory with human nothingness. At Jerusalem he said that this divine society was the flower and consummation of that which their fathers had possessed,—of that which had begun in Abraham's tent. Finally, to the Jews and Gentiles of Home he asserted the worth of outward law, because it made men con¬ scious of internal evil,—because it made them realize the opposi¬ tion between the flesh, which flies from what is right and true, and the spirit, which desires but cannot attain—because it drives man to seek a righteousness above his own, which condemns his evil nature, justifies and satisfies the cravings of his inner man. rpr.inri!eror an Galiltean fisherman, living in the country tiu-oid and where Greek philosophy began, proclaimed the reconciliation the New. 0f ^hat Revelation which had been from the beginning, with the Light which had shined afresh upon the world, declared that the Word was with God and was God; that in Him was Life, and the Life was theLight of men; uttered a divine Name which expressed The Being and The Unity; saw a city descending out of heaven, of which this Unity was the centre and the ground. 4. There are some readers who fancy that ancient and modern history are divided by the so-called fall of the Western Empire. The historian of philosophy cannot adopt their arrangement. The poiut at which we arrived is the one at which the curtain falls on the speculations of the old world. When it rises again we shali find a set of new actors, occupied with questions closely connected with all which we have been considering, but in many important respects different from them. A new element we shall find has been infused into the minds of Pagans and Jews, as well as of Christians. If we agree with Philo that the speculations of men in the ages before Christ were under the guidance of a Teacher who knew what was in man, we need not fear to enter upon the more complicated and embarrassing inquiries of the later time. IMPORTANT WORKS Febniai7'1855' Jti Science anil ©encral Citeratnrc, PUBLISHED BY RICHARD GRIFFIN AND COMPANY, Publishers to the University op Glasgow, 5 Warwick Square, PATERNOSTER ROW, LONDON. BUCHANAN-STREET, GLASGOW. Arts and Manufactures. Book of Trades. ----- Encyclopaedia of Pino Arts, ©lassifieti Snbex. Miscellaneous—continued. Groat Speeches of tho Groat Statesmen, - Page 6 Phillips's Metallurgy. — Troatiso on Oold-Mining. Biography, History, and Antiquities. ncient History- unpWU'a Naval History. - brenolygical Tables. - - ... raphy, - graphy. - tern Religious Biography, - l«ry. »1 History, - Kadie » Oriei Ecclesiastical Hist . Hale's History of tho Jews, ... Hinds's Early Christianity. ... History of Greece. ------ History of the Ottoman Empire. - History 'if Rome. ------ Jeremle's Church History. Focoekv s India in Greece. ... Procter's History of the Crusades, Barosay's Roman Antiquities. Stoddart's Introduction lo History, - Language and Metaphysics. Coleridge on Method. .... D'Orsey's Spelling by Dlctatioi Encyclopedia of Ml History of Greek L — Roman Maurice's M Mental Science. Beiil's Intellectual i Stodilart s Universa Smedley's Occult Sc Whately's lope. Philosophy. 1 Roman Philosophy, - Metaphysical Philosophy, id BclentlOc Anocdoto, VirgUli Opera, illiistlated edition, - Religious and Moral. Abbott's Works, - Channlng's Theological Works, Cyclopaedia of Religious Anecdote, Cyclopaedia of Religious Biography, Cyclopaedia of Rollgious Denominations, Cruden's Concordance, - Dewey's Theological Works - Eadie s Analytical Concordanco, - Biblical Cyclopaedia, - Biblical Dictionary, Commentary on the Epheslans. Jamieson's scripture Readings (or tho Yot Klngsloy's National Sermons. - Wolfe's Messianic Prophecies, The Sciences, Mathematics, and Natural History. Alry's Contributions to Encyclopedia Motropolltana, 2 Trigonometry. Balfour's Manual of Botany, - Book of Nature. Davy's Agricultural Chemistry. Encyclopaedia of Astronomy, - Experimental Phi Herschol's Con Nlchol's Cyclopaslla Phillips's Manual el Schoedler and Wedlock' a .7the Physical Sctcncos Manual of tho Natural Physical Belt Ic Trent Thomson's Cyclopaedia of Chemistry, Whim's Natural History of NEW WORKS AND NEW EDITIONS ABBOTT.—MORAL AND EDUCATIONAL WORKS: Comprising the Young Christian, Teacher. M'aj to do Good, Ac. Svo. /is. cloth. AIRY.—CONTRIBUTIONS TO TIIE ENCYCLOPEDIA ME- TROPOLITANA : viz. Trigonometry. Figure of the Earth, and Tides and Waves. One Volume, 4to, KJs. (id. cloth. AIRY.—TRIGONOMETRY. A TREATISE ON TRIGONOMETRY. By G. B. Airy, F.R.S., Astronomer Royal. new edition. Edited by Professor Blackbi kn. Crown Svo, cloth, 2s. 6d. ANCIENT HISTORY, Comprising the Political, Social, and Literary Histories of Rovif,, Gkefce, Egypt, Assyria, Persia, 4co. Ae. By Arnold, Taikoi rd, Ramsay, Eadie.Rkmh ari>. Whew i,LI., Ao., Ac, Id vols., crown Svo, cloth, gilt, M■ Is. ANECDOTES—LITERARY AND SCIENTIFIC. CYCLOPAEDIA OF LITERARY AND SCIENTIFIC ANECDOTE. Edited bv Wm. Keddie, Esq., Sec. Glasgow Philoso. Society. Cr. Svo, 5fl. cloth. ANECDOTES—RELIGIOUS. CYCLOPEDIA OF RELIGIOUS ANECDOTE; A vast Collection of Facts, Narratives, and Examples, vvith Copious Index, and Introductory Essay by Rev. Dr. Chf.eveu. To which is added a Complete Series of Scriptural Texts illustrated by the Anecdotes. 4th edition. Crown Svo, /is. cloth. BALFOUR.—BOTANY; An Introduction to the Study of the Structure, Physiology, and Classification of Plants- By John II. BaLfoi r, M.D., F.R.S.K., Professor of Botany in the University of Edinburgh. Numerous Illustrations, Third Edition, revised arid enlarged by J. W. Williams, M.D., Lecturer on Botany at the Original School of Medicine, Dublin. Crown 8\o, IDs. (id. BIOGRAPHY, CYCLOPAEDIA OF; Containing a Complete Series of Original Memoirs of the most Remarkable Indi¬ viduals of all Times and Nations. By Alison, Brewster, Birton, Creasy, Eadie, Knight, Nichol, Spai ding. Wornityi, ami other Contributors. With 15(1 Illustrations of Birth-places, &o. &o. Post Svo, 12s. fid. cloth. BOOK OF NATURE: THE BOOK OF NATURE; a Comprehensive Introduction to the Na¬ tural and Physical Si ie.nces. From the German of Professor Schiilhi er, with numerous Additions, by Henry Medlock, F.C.S. Second edition, convcti*d and enlarged. With Copious Index, and 501) Engravings, post Svo, cloth, 10s. (id. BOOK OF TRADES; Or, Circle ot the Useful Arts. Illustrated by Engravings and Woodcuts, Eleventh Edition, lfinio, 4s. (id. cloth. BRITISH ELOQUENCE: The Literart, Political, and Sacrf.d Oratory of (lie Nineteenth Cexti ry, in a series of tooleap Hvo volumes, its. (id. each, cloth. Jhitcrary Oratory—A Senes of Literary Addresses, hv Bui.wfr Litton, Broui.tiam, M acai lay, Masson, Stepiiln, and others. Foolscap Nvo, lid. el. Political Oratory.—The Great Speeches of the Great Statesnn n from the Close ot the War to the Passing ol the Retorm Bill. Foolscap Svo, its. fid., cloth. BROUGHAM.—WORKS. The Critkal, Historical, and Miscellaneous Works of Hfnry, Lord Brougham, F.R.S. Now first Collected under the direct rare and superinten¬ dence of his Lordship, in 10 post Svn Yolumts, each ,~s. cloth. Vol. 1.—Lives of Philosophers of the Reign ot George III. 2.—Lives of Men of Letters of the Reign of George HI. :j, 4.—Historical Sketchesof tho Statesmen who flourished in the Reign of George IN. 5, (i, 7.—Dissertations and Addre-seson Literature, Philosophy, and Natural Theology. 8.—Speeches on Important Subjects, with Historical Introductions. 0, 10.—Critical and Historical Dissertations, from the Edinburgh Review. BRYCE.—UNIVERSAL GAZETTEER. A Cyclopedia of Political and Physical Geography, with Pronunciation and numerous Illustrations. Bj Jayies Bryce, A.M., F.G.S. PostNvo. * PUBLISHED BT RICHARD GRIFFIN AND CO. 3 CAMPBELL.—BRITISH NAVAL HISTORY. Lives of the British Admirals and Naval History of Great Britain from the Days of C;esar to the Present Time. Fifth Edition, with numerous engravings, foolscap 8vo, lis. O'd. cloth, or 4s. extra gilt. CHANNING.—THEOLOGICAL WORKS. Complete in One Volume, post Kvo, 5s. cloth. CHANNING.—LITERARY WORKS. Complete in One Volume, post 8vo, 5s. cloth. CHRONOLOGICAL TABLES. Crown 8vo, cloth, Is. each. BIBLICAL AND EARLY ORIENTAL HISTORY. GREECE AND MACEDONIA. ROME TO THE FALL OF THE "WESTERN EMPIRE. COLERIDGE.—METHOD. Introductory Dissertation to the Encyclopedia Metropolitana on the Science of Method,with a Synopsis. By Samuel Taylor Coleridge. Crown 8vo, 2s. <1. COX.—BIBLICAL ANTIQUITIES. A MANUAL OF BIBLICAL ANTIQUITIES, OR ILLUSTRATIONS OF THE HOLY SCRIPTURES. By the Rev. F. A. Cox, D.D., LL.D. WithMaps and nearly 200 Illustrations, crown 8vo, 7s. (id. cloth. COX.—SACRED HISTORY AND BIOGRAPHY, From the Antediluvian Period to the Time of the Prophet Maluchi. Edited by Rev. F. A. Cox, D.D., LL.D. Crown 8vo, Us. cloth. CRUDEN.—CONCORDANCE To the Holy Scriptures. Condensed and Revised from the larger Work of Cruden. By Rev. Professor Eadie, D.D., LL.D. Thirteenth edition, bvo, 5s. cloth. CURIOSITIES OF BIOGRAPHY ; Or, Memoirs of Extraordinary Characters. By rouerr Malcolm. 1(10 Characteristic Cuts. Foolscap 8vo, 2s. 6d. cloth. DALGAIRNS—COOKERY. The Practice of Cookery Adapted to the Business of Every-Day Life. By Mrs. Daloairns. Thirteenth Edition, enlarged, foolscap Svo, 4s. tid. cloth. DAVY.—AGRICULTURAL CHEMISTRY. ELEMENTS OF AGRICULTURAL CHEMISTRY. Bv Sir II. Davy, Bart, P.R.S ,&c. New edition, Revised,by JohnShier, A.M., LL.D. Xvo.ils.Ud.ol. DEWEY.—THEOLOGICAL WORKS. Complete in One Volume, post Kvo, 5s cloth. D'ORSEY.—SPELLING BY DICTATION; A Series of Progressive Exercises in English Orthography, Illustrated by 15110 Quotations. By Rev. A. J. D. D'orsey, High School, Glasgow. 18mo, Is. doth. EADIE.—BIBLICAL CYCLOPAEDIA ; Or, Dictionary of Eastern Antiquities, Geography, Natural History, Sacred Annals and Biography, Theology, and Biblical Literature. By the Rev. 1'rofe.ssor Eadie, D.D., LL.D. With Maps and numerous Pictorial illustrations, tilth edition, revised, post 8vo, 7s. 6d. cloth. EADIE.—CONCORDANCE. An Analytical Concordance to the Holy Scriptures, with the Text in full. By the Rev. Professor Eadie, D.D., LL.D. Post bvo. EADIE.—DICTIONARY OF THE BIBLE, For the Use of Young Persons. Bv the Rev. Professor Eadie, D.D., LL.D. With 120 Illustrations, third edition, lfemo, 2s. 6d. cl. or 3s. tid. cape morocco gilt. EADIE.—EARLY ORIENTAL HISTORY; Comprising the History' of Egypt, Assyria, Persia, Media, Pbrygia, and Phrenicia. By Rev. Prof. Eadie, D.D., LL.D. Numerous Illustrations, crown Svo, 8s. cloth. EADIE.— EPHESIANS. A Commentary on the Greek Text of the Epistle of Pvttto the Kphlsuns. By Rev. Professor Eadie, D.D., LL.D. 8vo, 14s. cloth. 4 new works and new editions ENCYCLOPAEDIA METROPOLITANA, Original 4to Edition. astronomy, by Barlow. Herschf.i.l. and Airy. 21 Plates. 14s. EXPERIMENTAL SCIENCE, by Barlow, Lunn, Roget, and Harvey. 39 Plates. II. 13. FINE ARTS, by Narrien, Westmacott, Gwilt, &c. 55 Plates. 1Z. Is. MANUFACTURES AND MACHINERY, by Barlow and Babbage. 87 Plates. 21.2s. MATHEMATICS, by Airy, De Morgan, Hall, Moseley, Dr. Peacock, &c. 17 Plates. II. Is. MECHANICAL PHILOSOPHY, by Barlow and Herschell. 78 Plates. 11. lis. fid. MEDICAL SCIENCE, by South, Bowman, Williams. &c. 18 Plates. 14s. MENTAL PHILOSOPHY, by Coleridge, Whately, Maurice, &c. 14s. NATURAL HISTORY, by Howards, Phillips, &c. 131 Plates. 1Z. 15s. USEFUL ARTS, by Don, Lowe, Senior, &c. 10 Plates. 14s. ENCYCLOPEDIA METROPOLITANA, NEW AND REVISED EDITION. The Second Edition of the Encyclopedia Metropolitana will be handsomely printed in a Seriesof Cabinet Volumes, each containing a Complete Trea¬ tise, in crown Svo. The work will be thoroughly revised, many new Treatises added, the Articles all provided w ith comprehensive Indexes, or Analytical Tables of Con¬ tents, and abundantly illustrated by Maps, Woodcuts, and Engravings. Vol. 1—MF.THOD. S.T.Coleridge. 2s. 2.—UNIVERSAL GRAMMAR. Sir John Stoddart. 5s. 3.—LOGIC. Archbishop Whately. 3s. 4.—RH KTORIC. ARCHBisnopWHATELY.3s.6d. 5.—EARLY CHRISTIANITY. Bishop Hinds, fis. 6— POLITICAL ECONOMY. Nassau w. Senior. 4s. 7.—HISTORY OF THE JEWS. Archdeacon Hale. 2s. 6d. -8 —SACRED HISTORY AND BIOGRAPHY.Dr, Cox. 6s. 9.—GREEK LITERATURE. SirT. N. Talfoird,&c. 7s.6d. -10.—ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY. Rev. F. D. Maurice. 5s. h._ UNIVERSAL HISTORY. Sir John Stoddart. 5s. •12.—ROMAN ANTIQUITIES. Professor Ramsay. 8s. 6d. • 13.—BOTANY. Propessor Balfour. 10s.fid. 14—ELECTRO-METALLURGY. James Napier. 3s. 6d. -15.-EARLY HISTORY OF GREECE. Sir T. N. Talfourd, A:c. .is. -16.—PHOTOGRAPHY. Robert Hunt. 6s. 17.—VETERINARY ART. W.C.Spooner. 3s. -18.—EARLY ORIENTAL HISTORY. Professor Eadie. 8s. -19.—HISTORY OF THE ROMAN REPUBLIC. Dr. arnold,&c.8e.6d. -20.-B1BLICAL ANTIQUITIES. Dr. Cox. 7s. 6d. •21.—METALLURGY. J.A.Phillips. 12s.6d. 22.—THE CHURCH IN THE SECOND AND THIRD CENTURIES. Professor Jeremie. 4s. -23.—HISTORY OF GREECE & MACEDONIA.Dean Lyall, &c. 8s. -24.—ROMAN LITERATURE. Dr.Arnold,Nc.Ifts.fid. -25—HISTORY OF THE ROMAN EMPIRE. Dr.Arnold,6cc. llis.6d. "26.—DECLINE AND FALL OF ROME. Bishop Russel, &c. 109.6d- -27.—GREEK AND ROMAN PHILOSOPHY. Bishop of London, &c. bs. 28.—PHILOSOPHY OF THE FIRST SIX CENTURIES. Rev. F. D. Maurice. 3s.6d. "29.—HISTORY OF THE OTTOMAN EMPIRE. Col. Procter, &c. 7s. 6d. 30.—TRIGONOMETRY. Professor Airy. 2s. 6d. 31—OCCULT SCIENCES. Rbv. E. Smedley, &e. -32.—GEOLOGY. Professor Phillips. PUBLISHED BY R1CUARD GRIFFIN AND CO. 5 ECCLESIASTICAL HISTORY. First Division.- HISTORY OF THE CHRISTIAN CIIURCH IN THE FIRST CENTURY. By Right Rev. Samuel Hinds, D.D., Bishop of Norwich, and Row J. H. Newman, B D. Crown Bvo, 6s. cloth. Second Division.—CHRISTIANITY IN THE MIDDLE AGES, part I.-THE CHRISTIAN CHURCH IN THE SECOND AND THIRD CENTURIES, by James A. Jerf.mie, D.D., Regius Professorof Divinity in the University of Cambridge. 4s., cloth. Part II. THE CHRISTIAN CHURCH FROM THE FOURTH TO THE TWELFTH CENTURY. By Rev. J. M. Guildinu, Rev. J. B. S. Carwithen, B.D., &c. Third Division.—THE RISE, ACCOMPLISHMENT, & CONSEQUENCES OF THE REFORM ATI ON; being the History of the Church from theThirteenth Century to the present time. By Right Reverend Dr. Hampden, Bishop of Hereford, Rev. J. E. Riddle, M.A., iic. &c. GREEK AND ROMAN PHILOSOPHY AND SCIENCE. HISTORY OF GREEK AND ROMAN PHILOSOPHY AND SCIENCE. By the Rev. Dr. Blomfield. William Lowndes, Esq., M.A., Q.C., Hew J. W. Blakeslf.y, M.A., Andrew Findlater, A.M., Rev. Professor Jeremie, Rev. Professor \\ heweli., and other Contributors. Crown 8vo, 6s. cloth. GREECE.—HISTORY OF. History of Greece from the Earliest Period to the absorption of Greece in the Roman Empire. By E. Pococke, Esq., Rev. J. B. Ottley, M.A., Sir Thomas N. Talpourd, D.C.L., the late J.T. Rutt, Esq., William Roe Lyall, D.D., Rev. J. H. B. MoiNTAIN, D.D., Rev. G. C. Rknouard, B.D., and others. Illus¬ trated by numerous Wood Engravings. 2 vols, crown 8vo, 17s. cloth. 1. Early History of Greece. 150 Engravings, 9s. eloth. 2. History of Greece and Macedonia. 100 Engravings, 8s. GREEK LITERATURE. A HISTORY OF GREEK LITERATURE. By Sir T. N. Talfourd, Right Rev. Dr. Blomfield, Bishop of London, Rev. H. Thompson, M.A., and other Contributors. With Chronological Tables and Index. Crown 8vo, 7s. 6d. cloth. GRIFFIN'S PORTABLE CYCLOPEDIAS. A series of Alphabetical Reference Books adapted to the wants of the present age; beautiiully printed and embellished. Post 8vo, cloth. Vol. 1.—BIBLICAL KNOWLEDGE. Pmoi kssor Kadie. 7s. 6d. * 2.—CHEMISTRY and MINERALOGY. Dr. Thomson. 12s.lid. 3.—UNIVERSAL BIOGRAPHY. Alison, Brewster, Ac. 12s. 6d 4.-UNIVERSAL HISTORY. M'Burney and Neil. Ills. 6d. 5.—PHYSICAL SCIENCES. Professor Niciiol. 6—UNIVERSAL GAZETTEER. James Bryce, F.G.S, HALE.—HISTORY OF THE JEWS, From the Time of Alexander the Great to the Destruction of Jerusalem by Titus. By Archdeacon Hale, Master of the Charter House. Crown 8\o, 2s. 6d. cloth. HERSCHEL.—CONTRIBUTIONS TO THE ENCYCLOPAEDIA M ETROPOLITANA: viz. Physical Astronomy, Light, and Sound. 4to, cloth, 15s. HINDS.—EARLY CHRISTIANITY. THE RISE AND EARLY PROGRESS OF CHRISTIANITY. By Right Rev. Dr. Hinds, Bishop of Norwich. New Edition, Revised, crown 8vo, 5s. cloth. HORATII OPERA. THE COMPLETE WORKS OF HORACE, from the Text of Orellius, with 250 Illustrations from the most authentic sources, and Introductory Dissertation on the Life and Poetry of Horace, by the Rev. Henry Thompson, M.A., late Scholar of Cambridge, Vicar of Chard. Crown Bvo, 7s. 6d. antique binding. HUNT.—PHOTOGRAPHY. Embracing the Daguerreotype, Calotype, and all the published Photographic Erecesses. By Rodert Hunt, F.R.S. Fourth edition, enlarged. Numerous ingravings, crown 8vo, 6s. cloth. JAMIESON.—RELIGIOUS BIOGRAPHY. POPULAR CYCLOPAEDIA OF MODERN RELIGIOUS BIOGRAPHY. By the Rev. Robert Jamieson, D.D. Second Edition, crown Mo, 5s., eloth. <5 NEW WORKS ANT) NEW EDITIONS JEREMIE.—CHURCH HISTORY. HISTORY OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCH IN THE SECOND AND THIRD CENTURIES, By J auks Amiru x Jerkmil, D.D., Regius Professor of Divinity, Cambridge. Crown Hvo, 4«. cloth. KERR.—MANUFACTURE OF SUGAR ; A Practical Treatise on the Cultivation ol the Sugar Cane and the Manufacture of Sugar. By Thomas Kerr, oi Barhadoes. Crown Hvo, 5s. cloth. KINGSLEY.—NATIONAL SERMONS. By the Rev. Charles Kim.nley, Canon of Middleham, and Rector of Everslcy, author oi Yeast, Alton Loeke, Ac. First and Second Series, leap, hvo, each 5s. el, MANUFACTURES AND MACHINERY. THE ENCYCLOPAEDIA OF ARTS, MANUFACTURES, AND MA¬ CHINERY By Professor Barlow . With an Introductory Dissertation, by Professor Babbage. New edition, with87Pages oi Engravings. 4to, 42s.hall russia. MATHEMATICS. THE ENCYCLOPAEDIA OF PURE MATHEMATICS, comprehending a complete Course of Mathematical Science By Proh-,sors Airv, Barlow, De Morgan, II at r, Hawiiton, Levy, Moskley, Dr. Lardner, F.R.S., and Rev. Dr. Peacock, Dean of Ely. With 17 Engravings, ill Is. cloth. MAURICE.—MORAL AND METAPHYSICAL PHILOSOPHY: Anciem Philosophy, comprising the Hebrew, Egvptian, Hindoo, Chinese, Persian, (jrecian, Jioman and Ah saudrian Sy.sti ms of Philosophy. By Rev. F. D, Mai rick, M.A. Chaplain to Lincoln's Inn. Third Ediiion, er. Svo, 5s. cloth. Philosophy of the First Six Centuries. Crown Sw», 'is. tid. cloth. Philosophy of the Middle Ages. Crown Svo. In th- Prt vs. Modern Philosophy. Crown bvo. In the Pre.**. MENTAL SCIENCE. Sa.vu.el Taylor Coleridge on METHOD ; Archbishop \\ hately sTrea¬ tises on LOGIC and RHETORIC. Crown 8vo, 5s. cloth. MITCHISON.—SCOTTISH SONG. A IIAND-BOOK OF THE SONGS OF SCOTLAND, containing the best Songs ot BuriLs, Ac. Set to Music. With Notes, and Lite of WTL* n. By William Miti'hison. Crown S\«», 2s. fid. cloth. MORRISON.—BOOK-KEEPING; A Complete System ot Practical Book-keeping hy Single Entry, Double Entry, and a New Method. Bj C. Morrison. Eighth edition, Svo., fes. halt-hound. NAPIER.—ELECTRO-METALLURGY; Containing an Account of the most Improved Methods of Depositing Copper, Silver, Gold, and other metals, with numerous Illustrations. By J ames NiriES, F.(US. Second edition, revised and enlarged. Crown Hvo, 3s. fid. cloth. NAPIER. —DYEING. A Manual of Dyking, Practical and Theoretical. By James Napiir, F.C.S. With Engravings. Post Svo, 7s. tid. cloth. NAPIER.—DYEING RECEIPTS. A Manual of Dyeing Rkeiitn, with Specimens ol Cloth. By James Napilii, F.C.S. Post Svo, 7s. tid. cloth. NATURAL SCIENCES. I.ntrodi ctory Manual ov the N.vTl Ral Sciences, comprising Geology, Botany, and Zoology. By Professors Si hoedler and MedloCK. Numerous Illustrations, crown Svo, 5s. cloth. NICHOL.—PHYSICAL SCIENCES. A L'h lopiedi a of the Physical SciENi es, comprising Acoustics—Astronoinv— Dynainies — Eli ctricity — Heat — Hydiodjnamies — Magnetism — Philosophy ot Mathematics—Meteorology—Optics—Pneumatics—Statics. By J. P. Nkhoi, LL.D., Protessor of Astronomy in the University ot Glasgow. With Numerous Illustrations. Tost Svo. OTTOMAN EMPIRE.—HISTORY OF. History of tne Ottoman Empire, including a Sketch of the Gr< ck Empire and the Crusades. By Col.Piiuniu,ftev.J.E. riddif.andJ. M'Conh hv . <'r.bvo,7s.t!d. PL'BLISIIED BY RICHARD GRIFFIN AND CO. 7 PHILLIPS.—METALLURGY; A Manual of Metallurgy: being an Account of Assaying, Mining, Smelting, Ac., by J. A. Phillips, F.C.S. Second Edition, revised and enlarged, with above 21 III Engravings. Crown Svo, 12s. (id. cloth. PHILLIPS.—GOLD MINING ; A POPULAR TREATISE «.n GOLD-MINING, and ASSAYING. By J. A. Phillips. F.C.S., K.G.S. With Illustrations, second edit., fols. Svo, 2s. tid. cloth. PHILLIPS.—GEOLOGY. A M vsual ok Geology, Practical and Theoretical, with Numerous Illustrations. By John Phillips, M.A., F.R.s., F.G.s., Deputy Reader of Geology in the University of Oxford. Crown 8vo. PHYSICAL SCIENCES. Introductory Manual of the Physical Sciences, comprising Natural Philo¬ sophy, Astronomy, and Chemistry. Bv Professors Schoedi.KR and Medlock. Numerous Illustrations, crown Svo, cloth, 5s. POCOCKE.—INDIA IN GREECE, Or, TRUTH IN MYTHOLOGY, containing an Account of the Sources of the Hellenic Race, the Colonisation of Egypt and Palestine I'romMndin, the Wars of the Grand Lama, and the Bud'histic Propaganda in Greece. By E. Pococke, Esq. Illustrated l>y Numerous Maps of India and Greece, p<,sf Svo.'l2s.cloth. POLSON—PRINCIPLES OF THE LAW OF NATIONS, With Practical Notes on the Law of Blockade, and on Contraband in War. By Archer Polsun, Esq., Lincoln's Inn. To which is added DIPLOMACY. By Thomas HaRtweli. Horne, B.L). Crown 8\o, 3s. tid. cloth. POPE.—POETICAL WORKS. COMPLETE POETICAL WORKS and TRANSLATIONS of ALEXAN¬ DER POPE. Portrait and Vignette. New Edition, Svo, 5s. cloth. POPULAR LIBRARY; A Miscellany of Amnsempntand Instruction; numerous Engravings. 12mo.3s. fid.cl PROCTER—CRUSADES. HISTORY OF THE CRUSADES; their Rise, Progress, and Results. By Colonel Procter. With Illustrations atter Gilbert, Act*. Crown Svo, 5s. cloth RAMSAY.—ROMAN ANTIQUITIES; A Manual of Roman Antiquities. By William Ramsay, M.A., Professor of Humanity in the University of Glasgow. W ith Map, numerous Engravings, and very copious Index. Third edition, crown 8vo, 8s. 6<1. cloth. REID.—INTELLECTUAL POWERS. Essats on the Intellectual Powers of Man. By Thomas Reid, D.D. New edition, crown Svo, 5s. RELIGIOUS DENOMINATIONS. A CYCLOP/EDIA OF RELIGIOUS DENOMINATIONS. An Authentic Account of the various Religions prevailing throughout the World, written by Members of the respective Bodies. Second edition, crown 8vo, 5s. cloth. ROME—HISTORY OF. HISTORY OF ROME, from the Foundation of the City of Rome to the Extinc¬ tion of the Western Empire. By Rev. Thomas Arnold I).D.,rbe Rev. Professor Jeremie, D.D., Sir Thomas Noon Talfourd, D.C.L., and others. Illus¬ trated by numerous Engravings. Three Volumes, crown Svo, cl. extra, £1 9s. lid. 1. The Roman Republic, 8s. b'd. cloth. 2. The Roman Empire, His. «d. cloth. 3. The Decline and Fall of the Roman Power, 10s. (id. cloth. ROMAN LITERATURE. A HISTORY OF ROMAN LITERATURE. By Rev. Thomas Arnold, D.D Rev. Henry Thompson, M.A., Rev. J. H. Newman, B.D., the Rev. J. M. Neale. M.A.. and other Contributors. Crown Svo, Ills. Cd. cloth. SCHOEDLER AND MEDLOCIC'S SCIENTIFIC TREATISES, For ScHOOt.S. New Editions, post Svo, cloth. ASTRONOMY. With 51 Engravings. Is. (id. BOTANY. With 121 Engravings. Is. lid. CHEMISTRY- Second Edition. With 50 Engravings. 2s. MINERALOGY and GEOLOGY. With 128 Engravings. 2s. lid. NATURAL PHILOSOPHY. With 150 Engravings. 2s. 6d. ZOOLOGY and PHYSIOLOGY. With 84 Engravings. 2s. 8 NEW WORKS AND NEW EDITIONS. SCRIPTURE READINGS-JAMIESON. The Bible Familiarly Explained to the Young. Edited by the Rev. Dr. Jamieson. With Illustrations!, foolscap 8*0, 3s. fid. cloth. SENIOR.—POLITICAL ECONOMY; The Science which Treats of the Nature, Production, and Distribution of Wealth. By Nassau w. Senior, M.A. Third edition, crown 8vo, 4s. cloth. SMEDLEY.—OCCULT SCIENCES. A Compendium ok the Occult Sciences, comprising Supernatural Beings— Exercise of Occult Powers—Localities—Monsters—Divination—Cliarms—Wonder¬ ful Plants and Remedies — Miscellaneous Superstitions, &c. &c., by Rev. E. Smedley. M.A., &c. Crown 8vo. SPOONER.—VETERINARY ART. A Practical Treatise on the Diseases of the Horse. By W. C. Spooner, Esq. With 50 Engravings. Crown 8vn, 3s. cloth. STODDART.—INTRODUCTION TO HISTORY; Two Dissertations—First: On the Uses of History1 as a Study. Second: On the Separation of the Early Facts of History from Fable. By Sir John Stoddart, LL.D. Crown 8vo, 5s. cloth, STODDART.—UNIVERSAL GRAMMAR, Or, the Pure Science of Language. By Sir John Stoddart, LL.D. Third edition, revised, crown 8»o, 5s. cloth. THOMSON.—CHEMISTRY. A CYCLOPAEDIA OF CHEMISTRY, Practical and Theoretical, with its Applications to Mineralogy, Physiology, and the Arts. Bv R. D. Thomson, M.D., F.R.S., F.C.S., Professor of Chemistry at St. Thomas's Hospital College, London. With numerous Illustrations, post 8vo, lis. fid. cloth. UNIVERSAL HISTORY. A CYCLOPYEDIA OF HISTORY. A COMPLETE SERIES OF CHRONO¬ LOGICAL TABLES from the Beginning of the World to the Present Time, on a New Plan, comprehending an arrangement according to Dates, and an Alphabetical arrangement. Post 8vo. Ms. fid., cloth. VIRGILII OPERA. THE COMPLETE WORKS OF VIRGIL, from the text of Heyne and Wagner, with 3011 Illustrations, from the most authentic sources, and Introductory Disserta¬ tion on the Life and Poetry of Virgil. By Rev. Henry Thompson, M.A., late scholar of Cambridge, Vicar of Chard, 8ic. Crown 8vo, 8s. lid., antique binding. WHATELY.—LOGIC. Original Edition, complete, forming part of the Encyclopedia Metropolitans. With Synopsis and Index. Crown 8vo, 2s. sewed, or .'is. cloth. WHATELY.—RHETORIC. Original Edition, complete, forming part of the Kncvelopcedia Metropolitana. With Synopsis and Index. Crown 8vo, 2s. fid. sewed, of iis. fid. cloth. WHITE.—THE NATURAL HISTORY OF SELBORNE. THE NATURAL HISTORY OF SELBORNE. By Rev. Gilbert White, A.M. New edition, greatly enlarged by Captain Thomas Brown, F.L.S., &c. With coloured Illustrations, foolscap Rvo, cloth, 3s. fid., or richly gilt, 4s. WITTICH.—PHYSICAL GEOGRAPHY. Curiosities op Physical Geography. A Description of the mast Remarkable Natural Phenomena. By William Wittich. New edition. Small 8vo,2s.6d. cloth. WOLFE.—MESSIANIC PROPHECIES THF, MESSIAH, as PREDICTED in the PENTATEUCH and PSALMS; being a new Translation and Critical Exposition of these Sacred Oracles. By J. R. WOLFE, author of the " Practical Hebrew Grammar." 8vo. Ms. fid. cloth. ZOOLOGY—ILLUSTRATIONS OF. A Series of Ninety Engravings, comprehending about a Thousand Figures of Qua¬ drupeds, Birds, Fish, Reptiles, Mollusca, Insects, Crustacea, Polyps, &c., engraved by J. W. Lowry and Thomas Landseer, after Sowerby. Charles Landseer, and others. The Descriptions by John Flint South, Esq.,"F.L.S., J. E. Gray, Esq., F.L.S., J. F. Stefhens, Esq., F.L.S., F.Z.S., and others. Im. 4to, 31s. fid. el. gt. Cabinet Edition of the Encyclopaedia Motropolitana—continued. Vol. XXV., price 10s. Gd., cloth lettered, HISTORY OF THE ROMAN EMPIRE. By the Itev. Thus. Arnold, D.D., lute Head Master, Rugby School, and Others. With Numerous Illustrations. Vol. XXVI., price 10s. Gd., cloth lettered, HISTORY OF THE DECLINE AND FALL OF THE ROMAN POWER. By the Right Rev. Bishop Russcl, Vdp* -f /\/ ' > &V V 'v ... ■ . ' -y "'t ■"" if A Kur s ■■ ~j ■ ,y» /. , ' > /r Y f '' /■ : "r^V> •" " '. ! ' ■" ' : 1. , V , •»» 'vvrv'W TV , r « .•••• >. v «rt \ v ■ ,,v... - ■' ' iiD ■ ■ 1 \ H ... « j,, mm iilil Nui' ' ■■ "■•■'■ ' " \ ■ ^ . "N X - ■ •