.,^\^iXxtm<,U^M^ m PRINCETON, N. J. HORACE HART, PRINTER TO THE UNIVERSITY Natural Religion €$t (Btffort) Butuvte DELIVERED BEFORE THE UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW IN 1888 F. MAX MULLER, K.M. FOREIGN MEMBER OF THE FRENCH INSTITUTE LONDON LONGMANS, GREEN, AND CO. AND NEW YORK : 15 EAST 16th STREET 1889 [ All rights reserved-] PEEPACE, When I had delivered my first course of Gifford Lectures in the University of Glasgow, I was asked by my friends to publish them exactly as I had delivered them, and not to delay their publication by trying to make them more complete. I have followed their advice, and I now present these lectures to the public at large, if not exactly as I delivered them, at least as I had prepared them for delivery. I was under the impression that, according to Lord Gifford's Will, each course was to consist of not less than twenty lectures. I therefore allowed myself that number for my introductory course, and I confess I found even that number barely sufficient for what I had chosen as my subject, namely, (1) The definition of Natural Religion, (2) The proper method of its treatment, and (3) The materials available for its study. In order to discuss these preliminary questions with any approach to systematic completeness, I could not avoid touching on subjects which I had discussed in some of my former publications, such as ' The Science of Language,' ' The Science of Thought,' and ' The Hibbert Lectures on the Origin and Growth of Religion.' I might have left out what to some of my readers will seem to be mere repetition, but I could not have done so without spoiling VI PREFACE. the whole plan of my lectures. Nor would it have seemed respectful either to my audience or to my critics if, in reiterating some of my statements and opinions, I had not endeavoured, to the best of my power, to vindicate their truth and to answer any bond fide objections which have been raised against them during the last years. No one can be more conscious than myself of the magnitude of the task with which the University of Glasgow has entrusted me, and of my own inadequate- ness to perform it as it ought to be performed. This first course of lectures is but a small contribution towards an immense subject, and it is such as from the nature of my own special studies I felt best qualified to give. But the subject admits of very different treatments; and in nothing has Lord Gifford shown himself more judicious than in founding not one, but several lectureships in Natural Religion, so that inquiries which were so near his heart might not suffer from one-sided treatment. I look forward to the lectures of my learned colleagues at Edin- burgh, St. Andrews, and Aberdeen, not only for in- struction, but also for correction ; though on some points, I may hope, for confirmation also of my own views on a subject which has been confided to our united care, and which more than any other requires for its safety a multitude of counsellors. F. MAX MULLER. Oxfokd, April 20, 1889. Extracts from the Trust Disposition and Set- tlement of the late Adam Gifford, sometime one of the Senators of the College of Justice, Scotland, dated 21st August, 1885. I AD AM GIFFORD, sometime one of the Senators of the j College of Justice, Scotland, now residing at Granton House, near Edinburgh, being desirous to revise, consolidate, alter, and amend my trust- settlements and testamentary writings, and having fully and maturely considered my means and estate, and the circumstances in which I am placed, and the just claims and expectations of my son and relatives, and the modes in which my surplus funds may be most usefully and beneficially expended, and considering myself bound to apply part of my means in advancing the public welfare and the cause of tiuth, do hereby make my Trust-deed and latter Will and Testament — that is to say, I give my body to the earth as it was before, in order that the enduring blocks and materials thereof may be employed in new combinations ; and I give my soul to God, in Whom and with Whom it always was, to be in Him and with Him for ever in closer and more conscious union ; and with regard to my earthly means and estate, I do hereby, give, grant, dispone, convey, and make over and leave and bequeath All and Whole my whole means and estate, heritable and moveable, real and personal, of every description, now belonging to, or that shall belong to me at the time of my death, with all writs and vouchers thereof, to and in favour of Herbert James Gifford, my son ; John Gifford, Esquire, my brother ; Walter Alexander Raleigh, my nephew, presently residing in London ; Adam West Gifford, W. S., my nephew ; Andrew Scott, C. A., in Edin- burgh, husband of my niece ; and Thomas Raleigh, Esquire, barrister-at-law, London, and the survivors and survivor of them accepting, and the heirs of the last survivor, and to such other person or persons as I may name, or as may be assumed or appointed by competent authority, a majority Vlll LOED GIFFORD'S WILL. Defini- tion of ' Residue. being always a quorum, as trustees for the ends, uses, and purposes aftermentioned, but in trust only for the purposes following : (Here follow the first ten purposes). And I de- clare the preceding ten purposes of this trust to be preferable, and I direct that these ten purposes be fulfilled in the first place before any others, and before any residue of my estate, or any part thereof, is disposed of, and before any residue is ascertained or struck, declaring that it is only what may remain of my means and estate after the said ten purposes are fulfilled that I call herein the ' residue ' of my estate, and , out of which I direct the lectureships aftermentioned to be founded and endowed. And in regard that, in so far as I can at present see or anticipate, there will be a large ' residue' of my means and estate in the sense in which I have above explained the word, being that which remains after fulfilling the above ten purposes, and being of opinion that I am bound if there is a ' residue ' as so explained, to employ it, or part of it, for the good of my fellow-men, and having considered how I may best do so, I direct the ' residue' to be disposed of as follows : — I having been for many years deeply and firmly convinced that the true knowledge of God, that is, of the Being, Nature, and Attributes of the Infinite, of the All, of the First and the Only Cause, that is, the One and Only Substance and Being, and the true and felt knowledge (not mere nominal knowledge) of the relations of man and of the universe to Him, and of the true foundations of all ethics or morals, being, I say, convinced that this knowledge, when really felt and acted on, is the means of man's highest wellbeing, and the security of his upward progress, I have resolved, from the ' residue ' of my estate as aforesaid, to institute and found, in connection, if possible, with the Scottish Universities, lectureships or classes for the promotion of the study of said subjects, and for the teaching and diffusion of sound views regarding them, among the whole population of Scotland. Therefore, I direct and appoint my said trustees from the ' residue ' of my said estate, after fulfilling the said ten prefer- able purposes, to pay the following sums, or to assign and make over property of that value to the following bodies in trust : — First, To the Senatus Academicus of the University of Edinburgh, and failing them, by declinature or otherwise, LORD GIFFOKD'S WILL. ix to the Dean and Faculty of Advocates of the College of £25,000 to Justice of Scotland, the sum of £25,000. Second, To the Edinburgh Senatus Academicus of the University of Glasgow, and fail- Vniver~ ing them, by declinature or otherwise, to the Faculty ofslty' Physicians and Surgeons of Glasgow, the sum of £20,000. f 2Sf°° Third, To the Senatus Academicus of the University of xjmver?0" Aberdeen, whom failing, by declinature or otherwise, to the mty. Faculty of Advocates of Aberdeen, the sum of £20,000. £20,000 to And Fourth, to the Senatus Academicus of the University of Aberdeen St. Andrews, whom failing, by declinature or otherwise, to Univer- the Physicians and Surgeons of St. Andrews, and of the'slty' district twelve miles round it, the sum of £15,000 sterling, £l5>°o° amounting the said four sums in all to the sum of £80,000 Andrews sterling ; but said bequests are made, and said sums are to Univer- be paid in trust only for the following purpose, that is to say, sity. forthe purpose of establishing in each of the four cities of Edinburgh, Glasgow, Aberdeen, and St. Andrews, a Lecture- To found ship or Popular Chair for < Promoting, Advancing, Teaching, chair of and Diffusing the study of Natural Theology,' in the widest Thto™1 sense of that term, in other words, 'The Knowledge of God, ° °gy* the Infinite, the All, the First and Only Cause, the One and the Sole Substance, the Sole Being, the Sole Reality, and the Sole Existence, the Knowledge of His Nature and Attributes, the Knowledge of the Relations which men and the whole universe bear to Him, the Knowledge of the Nature and Foundation of Ethics or Morals, and of all Obligations and Duties thence arising/ The Senatus Academicus in each of the four Universities, or the bodies substituted to them re- spectively^ shall be the patrons of the several lectureships, and the administrators of the said respective endowments, and of the affairs of each lectureship in each city. I call them for shortness simply the ' patrons.' Now I leave all the details and arrangements of each lectureship in the hands and in the discretion of the ' patrons ' respectively, who shall have full power from time to time to adjust and regulate the same in conformity as closely as possible to the following brief prin- ciples and directions which shall be binding on each and all of the ' patrons ' as far as practicable and possible. I only indicate leading principles. First, The endowment or capital Conditions. fund of each lectureship shall be preserved entire, and be LORD GIFFOKD'S WILL. Capital preserved entire. Patrons may delay institu- tion of chair, &c. Lecturers appointed for two years. Qualifica- tions of lecturers. Subject to be treated as a Natu- ral .Science. invested securely upon or in the purchase of lands or heritages which are likely to continue of the same value, or increase in value, or in such other way as Statute may permit, merely the annual proceeds or interest shall be expended in maintaining the respective lectureships. Second, The ' patrons ' may delay the institution of the lectureships, and may from time to time intermit the appointment of lecturers and the delivery of lectures for one or more years for the purpose of accumulating the income or enlarging capital. Third, The lecturers shall be appointed from time to time each for a period of only two years and no longer, but the same lecturer may be reappointed for other two periods of two years each, provided that no one person shall hold the office of lecturer in the same city for more than six years in all, it being desirable that the subject be promoted and illus- trated by different minds. Fourth, The lecturers appointed shall be subjected to no test of any kind, and shall not be required to take any oath, or to emit or subscribe any declaration of belief, or to make any promise of any kind : they may be of any denomination whatever, or of no de- nomination at all (and many earnest and high-minded men prefer to belong to no ecclesiastical denomination); they may be of any religion or way of thinking, or, as is sometimes said, they may be of no religion, or they may be so-called sceptics or agnostics or freethinkers, provided only that the 'patrons' will use diligence to secure that they be able reverent men, true thinkers, sincere lovers of and earnest inquirers after truth. Fifth, I wish the lecturers to treat their subject as a strictly natural science, the greatest of all possible ^ sciences, indeed, in one sense, the only science, that of Infinite Being, without reference to or reliance upon any supposed special exceptional or so-called miraculous revela- tion. I wish it considered just as astronomy or chemistry is. I have intentionally indicated, in describing the subject of the lectures^ the general aspect which personally I would expect the lect'urers to bear, but the lecturers shall be under no restraint whatever in their treatment of their theme ; for example, they may freely discuss (and it may be well to do so) all questions about man's conceptions of God or the Infinite, their origin, nature, and truth, whether he can LORD GIFFORDS WILL. XI have any such conceptions, whether God is under any or what limitations, and so on, as I am persuaded that nothing but good can result from free discussion. /Sixth, The lectures Lectures shall be public and popular, that is, open not only tot°bepoPu- students of the Universities, but to the whole community ' c ' without matriculation, as T think that the subject should be studied and known by all whether receiving University instruction or not. I think such knowledge, if real, lies at the root of all wellbeing. I suggest that the fee should be as small as is consistent with the due management of the lectureships, and the due appreciation of the lectures. Be- sides a general and popular audience, I advise that the lecturers also have a special class of students conducted in the usual way, and instructed by examination and thesis, written and oral. Seventh, As to the number of the lectures, Number of much must be left to the discretion of the lecturer, I should lectures, think the subject cannot be treated even in abstract in less than twenty lectures, and they may be many times that number. Eighth, The ' patrons ' if and when they see fit Publica- may make grants from the free income of the endowments tlon of for or towards the publication in a cheap form of any of the lectures, or any part thereof, or abstracts thereof, which they may think likely to be useful. Ninth, The ' patrons ' re- Accounts spectively shall all annually submit their accounts to some to J® one chartered accountant in Edinburgh, to be named from annuaiiy. time to time by the Lord Ordinary on the Bills, whom failing, to the Accountant of the Court of Session, who shall pre- pare and certify a short abstract of the accounts and invest- ments, to be recorded in the Books of Council and Session, or elsewhere, for preservation. And my desire and hope is that these lectureships and lectures may promote and advance among all classes of the community the true know- ledge of Him Who is, and there is none and nothing besides Him, in Whom we live and move and have our being, and in Whom all things consist, and of man's real relationship to Him Whom truly to know is life everlasting. If the residue of my estate, in the sense before defined, should turn out in- sufficient to pay the whole sums above provided for the four lectureships (of which shortcoming, however, I trust there is no danger), then each lectureship shall suffer a propor- XII LORD GIFFORD's WILL. If surplus after pay- ing the Univer- sities, One half to H. J. Gifford in liferent. Other half to unmarried nieces. Testing Clause. tional diminution ; and if, on the other hand, there is any surplus over and above the said sum of £80,000 sterling, it shall belong one half to my son, the said Herbert James Gifford, in liferent, and to his issue other than the heirs of entail in fee, whom failing, to my unmarried nieces equally in fee ; and the other half shall belong equally among my unmarried nieces. And I revoke all settlements and codicils previous to the date hereof if this receives effect, providing that any payments made to legatees during my life shall be accounted as part payment of their provisions. And I con- sent to registration hereof for preservation, and I dispense with delivery thereof. — In witness whereof, these presents, written on this and the six preceding pages by the said Adam West Gifford, in so far as not written and filled in by my own hand, are, with the marginal notes on pages four and five (and the word ' secluding ' on the eleventh line from top of page third, being written on an erasure), subscribed by me at Granton House, Edinburgh, this twenty-first day of August Eighteen hundred and eighty-five years, before these witnesses, James Foulis, Doctor of Medicine, residing in Heriot Eow, Edinburgh, and John Campbell, cab driver, residing at No. 5 Mackenzie Place, Edinburgh. Ad. Gifford. James Foulis, M.D., Heriot Eow, Edinburgh, witness. John Campbell, cab driver, 5 Mackenzie Place, witness. TABLE OF CONTENTS. PAGE Preface v Loed Gifford's Will vii LECTURE I. Introductory Lecture on Lord Gifford's Be- quest 1-26 LECTURE II. Definition of Religion. Definition of religion, why wanted. — Great differences in denning religion.— Is Buddhism a religion ?— Definition of definition. — Etymological definition.— Historical definition. — Dogmatic definition. — Etymological definition of religio.— His- torical definition of religio. — Later meanings of religio. — Dogmatic definitions. — Religion and theology. — Dogmatic and practical religion.— Comparative theology.— Schleiermacher's definition of religion. — Religion, either belief or body of doctrines . . 27-50 LECTURE III. Examination of Definitions. . Natural and revealed religions. — Comparative theology. — Modus cognoscendi et colendi Deum. — Feeling or knowledge as mo- tive of action. — The object of religion must be defined.— Fichto on atheism. — Goethe and Lavater. — Different classes of defini- tions.— Practical religion.— Kant. — Caird— Pfleiderer. — Marti- neau. — Schenkel and Newman. —Theoretical religion. — Re- ligion as sentiment or knowledge. — Teichmuller.— Author of XIV TABLE OF CONTENTS. Al.K ' Natural Religion.' — Goethe. — Mill. — Spinoza, 1632-77. — Schleiermacher, 1768-1834.— Hegel, 1770-1831.— Fichte, 1762- 1814.— How to account for these different definitions . 51-72 LECTURE IV. Positivist Definitions of Religion. Wundt.— Feuerbach.— Gruppe.— Selfishness as source of re- ligion.— Gruppe's definition too narrow.— Universality of religion.— Angle of vision.— Darwin on Tierra del Fuego.— Niebuhr and Bunsen.— Lubbock v. Quatrefages.— Preconceived ideas.— Names for religion.— Words for religion in Chinese ; in Arabic— Dharma.— Veda.— Bhakti.— Sraddha, faith. 73-102 LECTUEE V. My own Definition of Religion. Is Buddhism a religion ?— Buddhism, as theoretical, not in- cluded under any definition.— Ma lunky a -put ta and Bud- dha.—Yam aka, on life after death.— Dialogue between the king of Kosala and the nun K he ma.— Buddhism, as practical, not included under any definition.— The doctrine of Karma.— Definition of religion.— Religion an experience.— Experience consists of sensations, percepts, concepts, and names.— Sensa- tion and perception inexplicable.— The working of our mind.— No percept without language ; Helmholtz.— Perceptions always finite.— Finite and definite —The finite implies the infinite.— The infinite in space.— The infinite in time.— The infinite as cause.— Misunderstandings.— Savages without words for finite and infinite.— The Duke of Argyll's definition of religion.— Early names of the infinite.— Mana.— Manito.— Does the Vedic religion begin with sacrifice ?— Germs of the infinite in the Veda.— The infinitely great.— The infinitely small.— Infinite inseparable from finite.— The concept of cause . . 103-140 LECTUEE VI. The Infinite in Nature, in Man, and in the Self. Positivist objections.— Historical evolution.— Positivist point of view.— Rig-veda.— The dawn.— End and endless. -Endless in the Avesta.— Theogonic elements.— How thv perception of TABLE OF CONTENTS. XV PAGE the infinite led to religious ideas. — Tangible, semi-tangible, intangible objects. — Trees. — Mountains. — Rivers.— Earth. — Clouds, stars, moon, sun, sky.— Demi-gods and great gods. — The infinite in man as an object. — The something behind man. — The infinite behind man. — Religious ideas springing from it. — Animism. — Seelencitlt. — Strange names ; Totemism. — The infinite in man as a subject. — Psychological deities.— Sense, imagina- tion, intellect, language. — Devatas. — Atma. — Natural reli- gion, as physical, anthropological, and psychological . 141-165 LECTURE VII. Religion different from Science. Religious character. — Religion and science. — What imparts a religious character. — Moral influences of physical phenomena. — Vedic prayers. — Early morality. — Moral influence of ancestral spirits. —Ancestral law in China.— Moral influence of psycho- logical deities. — Temple to Mens. — Eros and Psyche. — Con- science.— Remorse. — Have we a conscience? — Sacrifices an element of religion.— Priesthood. — Study of the Veda.— Final definition of religion ....... 166-191 LECTURE VIII. The Historical Method. Criticisms of my definition. — Pfleiderer.— Gruppe. — Religion a psychological necessity. — History v. Theory. — Theory. — Corns- alitas. — Eminentia. — Negatio.— Cosmological, teleological, ontologi- cal arguments. — Historical method. — Archaeology. — Theoretic school. — Historical school. — Study of language. — Historical school. — Acatus. — Theoretic school. — Brinton on palaeolithic language. — Advantages of both theories. — Science of religion. — Historical school. — Semitic, Aryan, Chinese religions.— Re- ligions without books ....... 192-220 LECTURE IX. Historical Treatment of Religious Questions. Is religion possible ?— -History and theory inseparable. — Agnosticism. — Epicurean view of the gods. — Chance and pur- pose ; Darwin. — Atheism. — Intuitive knowledge of the gods. — xvi TABLE OF CONTENTS. PAGE Philosophical treatment.— Vision in the Bhagavadgita.— Revelation.— Historical traces in the Veda.— The old problems in their simpler form • 221-238 LECTURE X. i — COMPAEATIVE STUDY OF RELIGIOUS PROBLEMS. Modern problems to be traced back.— Creation.— The logic of facts. _ Cosmological argument. — Aryan savages. —Why ?— Answers to the cosmological question.— Emanation.— Emana- tion or srishtl— Golden egg.— Teleological argument.— An- thropomorphism— Ontological argument.— A creator.— Origin of the idea of cause.— Religions without a creator.— The theory of evolution.— Meaning of evolution.— Darwin admits a creator.— Herder, the precursor of Darwin.— Evolution in the beginning of our century.— Gottfried Hermann.— Kant on the Chimpanzee. — Darwin. — Oken. — Reaction. — Historical school, its true character.— Stanley.— Necessity of an historical study of religion.— Criticisms answered . . . 239-279 LECTURE XI. Materials for the Study of Natural Religion. Language, Myth, Customs and Laws, Sacred Books.— Lan- guage as evidence.— Survey of languages.— A_ryan Family.— English. —Veda = o?5a.— Anglo-Saxon. — Gothic— Continental Saxon.— Scandinavian.— Thorr and Thursday.— Tyr and Tues- day. — Wodan and Wednesday. — High German. — Celtic. — Italic. — Hellenic. — Slavonic. — North-Western Division. — South-Eastern Division.— Indie class, Vedic Hymns, Brah- manas, Sutras, Pawinean Sanskrit.— Inscriptions of Piyadasi, third century b. c— Buddhist Sanskrit.— Renaissance of San- skrit literature.— Prakrit.— Vernaculars.— Sacred Books.— Iranic class. — Cuneiform Persian inscriptions. — Pehlevi. — Bask, Etruscan.— Semitic Family.— Aramaic— Chaldaic and Syriac —Hebraic— Arabic— Ethiopic 280-310 LECTURE XII. • Principles of Classification. Languages not Aryan and not Semitic— Morphological classification.- Genealogical as different from morphological TABLE OF CONTENTS. XV11 PAGE classification. — Degrees of relationship. — Morphological classifi- cation.— Radical stage. — Terminational stage. — Inflectional stage. — Transitions from one stage to another. — Chinese. — Rask's and Prichard's classification. — Vocalic harmony . 311-327 LECTURE XIII. Languages not Aeyan and not Semitic. The Ural-Altaic family. — Samoyedic. — Altaic languages. — Tungusic class. — Mongolic class. — Turkic class. — Turkish grammar. — Finno-Ugric class. — Fins. — Estonians. — Tamulic languages. — Munda languages. — Taic languages. — Gangetic lan- guages.— Lohitic languages.— Languages of Farther India. — Languages of the Caucasus. — Egyptian. — Africa. — America. — Oceanic languages. — Malay. — Polynesia. — Melanesia . 328-350 LECTURE XIV. Language and Thought. What should we be without language. — Definition of think- ing.— What are we thinking of? — Thinking in German or English. — Why we cannot think without words. — Communica- tion, not language. — Images. — Involuntary and voluntary sounds. — The Bow-wow, Pooh-pooh, and Yo-heho theories. — Roots. — Words derived from conceptual roots. — Are concepts possible without words ? — Berkeley. — Process of naming. — Origin of concepts. — Former theories. — The clamor concomitans. — The conceptual foundation of language. — Our conceptual world 351-384 LECTURE XV. Dynamic Stage. Lessons of language. — Roots express our acts. — Some acts conceived as passive. — Subjective acts predicated of other agents. — Subjective acts predicated of objects. — Dynamic stage. — Animism. — Egypt.— Semitic names. — Finland. — Hidatsas in North America. — Growth of language. — Causality. — Objections answered.— Gender.— Dyaus, as a masculine . . . 385-410 B XVlli TABLE OF CONTENTS. LECTURE XVI. Mythology. Myths-Meaning of mythology-Etymology of „S*os-Myth, *"" a word Eos -Mythology universal-Comparative mythology schto S ^f^^^-^P-ative philology. -Etymological school-Analogical school—Psychological school-Compara- ive mythology A. Barth— Etymological school-Analogical school-Psychological school.-I. The Etymological School- Names of gods-Dialectic varieties-Obsolete names-The Dawn— Religious germs-Moral germs— Ahana = Athene- Daphne— Benfey's theory of Athene .... 411-447 LECTUEE XVII. The Genealogical School. Identification and comparison— Sarad and Ceres— Mytho- logical etymologies— Changes in the character of gods— Acci- dental similarities of names-Foreign gods-Mythological names which admit of no etymology-The names of gods- The etymological meaning must be physical— Learned and popular etymologies of Greeks and Romans. - Haritas and Chantes.-Fors, Fortuna— Nomina and cognomina . 448-483 LECTUEE XVIII. The Analogical and Pyschological Schools. II. The Analogical School— Characters common to gods and heroes of different names— Rudra, Apollon, Wuotan— Myths agreeing in one and differing in other names— Varuna and Ormazd.-III. The Psychological School. - Volker-psycho- logie— Advantages in England, India, Colonies, Missionary Societies— Work done in America— The time meaning of Manito ... * r,n • . 484-518 LECTUEE XIX. On Customs and Laws. Materials for the study of customs and laws— Customs based on religious ideas— Customs generating religious ideas— Sol- TABLE OF CONTENTS. XIX PAGE lennis. — Annual festivals. — Istar and Tammuz. — Zeus Xenios. — How customs should be studied ..... 519-537 LECTURE XX. Sacred Books. What is a sacred book ? — The five birthplaces of sacred books. — Survey of sacred books. — India. — The Veda. — Bud- dhism. — Influence of the Kshatriyas, the nobility. — Media and Persia. — China. — Palestine. — Judaism. — Christianity. — Mohammedanism. — The Eight Religions. — Book-religions.— The invention of writing. — Influence of writing on religion. — Individual and national religions. — Mohammed. — Christ. — Buddha. — Confucius. — Lao-gze. — Zoroaster. — Moses. — Sacred books, when consigned to writing. — The founders of religions are never the writers of sacred books. — The Veda originally not written. — The Avesta originally not written. — The Tripifoka not Buddha's work. — Confucius, writer, not author, of the Kings. — The Old Testament.— The New Testament. — Mohammed could neither read nor write. — Religions with and without sacred books. — Conclusion 538-577 Index 579-608 NATURAL THEOLOGY. LECTURE I. LORD GIFFORD'S munificent endowment of a Lectureship of Natural Theology, to which I have had the undeserved honour of being elected by the Senate of this ancient and illustrious University, must be reckoned among the signs of the times, preg- nant with meaning. This lectureship, with three others in the Univer- sities of Edinburgh, St. Andrews, and Aberdeen, was founded, as you know, by the late Lord Gifford, a Scotch lawyer, who by ability, hard work, and self- denial had amassed a large fortune, and attained the dignified position of a seat on the Bench. I have not been able to gather from his friends much information about his personal character and the private circumstances of his life. Nor do they all agree in the estimate they formed of him. Some represented him to me as a keen, hardworking, and judicious man, engrossed by his professional work, yet with a yearning for quietness, for some hours of idleness that should allow him to meditate on the great problems of life, those ancient problems which the practical man may wave away from B 2 LECTURE I. year to year, but which knock at our door louder and louder as we grow old, and will not allow them- selves to be turned into the street, like beggars and vagabonds. We all know the practical man of the world, who tells us that he has no time to listen to these inward questionings, that he is satisfied with what the Church teaches or with what men wiser than himself have settled for him, that he has tried to do his duty to his neighbours, and that he trusts to God's mercy for all the rest. Men like to entrench themselves in their little castles, to keep their bridges drawn and their portcullis ready to fall on any un- welcome guests. Or, to quote the words of my friend, Matthew Arnold, — 'I knew the mass of men conceal'd Their thoughts, for fear that, if reveal *d, They would by other men be met With blank indifference, or with blame reprov'd : I knew they lived and mov'd Trick'd in disguises, alien to the rest Of men, and alien to themselves.' But this was not the impression which Lord GifFord left on the mind of those who knew him best. Some of his relations and a few of his more intimate friends seem to have been startled at times by the fervour and earnestness with which he spoke to them on re- ligious and philosophical topics. Even when he was in full practice as a lawyer, the first thing he did, I am told, when he returned from the Parliament House on Saturdays, was to lock the door of his library, and devote himself to his own favourite authors, never looking at a professional book or paper till it was necessary to begin work on Monday. He had a sepa- rate set of books altogether in his bedroom, amongst LORD GIFFORD'S REQUEST. 3 which he spent every moment of his spare time during session, and probably almost his whole vacation. He was devoted to Plato as well as to Spinoza, and read philosophy both ancient and modern in all directions, as well as poetry and the best current literature of the day. But the world at large knew him chiefly as a suc- cessful lawyer, as a man always ready to help in any useful and charitable work, and satisfied to accept the traditional forms of public worship, as a necessary tribute which every member of a religious as well as of a political community must pay for the mainten- ance of order, peace, and charity. During the last seven years of his life, when confined to the sick-room by creeping paralysis, his mind, always active, bright, and serene, became more and more absorbed in the study of the various systems of philosophy and reli- gion, both Christian and non-Christian, and he made no secret to his own relatives of his having been led by these studies to surrender some of the opinions which they and he himself had been brought up to consider as essential to Christianity. There can be no doubt that he deliberately rejected all miracles, whether as a judge, on account of want of evidence, or as a Christian, because they seemed to him in open conflict with the exalted spirit of Christ's own teach- ing. Yet he remained always a truly devout Christian, trusting more in the great miracle of Christ's life and teaching on earth than in the small miracles ascribed to him by many of his followers. Some of his lectures and manuscript notes are still in existence, and may possibly some day be published, and throw light on the gradual development of his religious opinions, R 2 4 LECTURE I. After his elevation to the Bench gave him com- parative leisure, he lectured from time to time on aesthetic, literary, philosophical subjects ; but he never seems to have given offence, and those who knew him, little suspected this hard-working lawyer of having his whole soul engrossed by Spinoza's Ethics or the metaphysics of religion. And yet when his Will was opened, the one thing which that excellent man, after making ample provi- sion for his family, had evidently had most at heart, was to help the world to a clearer insight into the great problems of life than he himself in his busy career had been allowed to gain, to spread more correct and more enlightened views on the origin, the historical growth, and the true purpose of religion, and thus to help in the future towards an honest understanding between those who now stand opposed to each other, the believers and unbelievers, as they are called, unaware that as we all see through a glass darkly, we can only speak through our words faintly, and not always, rightly. Allow me to quote some extracts from this remark- able Will:— ' /, Adam Gifford, sometime one of the Senators of the College of Justice, Scotland, . . . having fully and maturely considered my means and estcde . . • and the just claims and expectations of my son and relations . . . and considering myself bound to apply part of my means in advancing the public welfare and., the cause of truth, do hereby make my 'Trust- deed' and latter Will and Testament, that is to ,niy, I give my body to the earth as it was before, in order that the enduring blocks and materials thereof may LORD GIFFORDS BEQUEST. 5 be employed in new combinations ; and I give my soul to God, in Whom and with Whom it always was, to be in Him and ivith Him for ever in closer and more conscious union' When Lord Gifford proceeds to declare that, after having provided for his relatives, he feels himself bound to employ what is over and above, for the good of his fellow men, he says, — ' I, having been for many years deeply and firmly convinced that the true knowledge of God, that is, of the Being, Nature, and Attributes of the Infinite, of the All, of the First and only Cause, that is, the One and Only Substance and Being, and the true and felt knowledge {not merely nominal knowledge) of the relations of man and of the universe to Him, and of the true foundations ofcdl ethics and morals, — being, I say, convinced that this knowledge, when really felt and acted on, is the means of mans highest well-being, and the security of his upward progress, I have re- solved . . . to institute and found . . . lectureships or classes for the promotion of the study of said sub- jects, and for the teaching and diffusion of sound views regarding them, among the whole population of Scotland! In a later paragraph of his Will, he defines more fully what he understands by Natural Theology and by sound views, and what subjects he wishes particu- larly to be taught. { Natural Theology ] he says, 'in the widest sense of that term, is the Knowledge of God, the Infinite, the All, the First and Only Cause, the One and the Sole Substance, the Sole Being, the Sole Reality, and the Sole Existence, the Knowledge of His Nd~ b LECTURE I. ture and Attributes, the Knowledge of the Relations which men and the whole universe hear to Him, the Knowledge of the Nature and Foundation of Ethics and Morals, and of all Obligations and Duties hence arising.' If Lord GifFord had said no more than this in his Will, we might have thought that he had been in- fluenced by the high and noble, yet not very un- common, motives of a man who wishes to see his own peculiar views of religion perpetuated for the benefit of mankind. He would have ranked among the pious founders and benefactors of this country, by the side of Chichele, Wolsey, Henry the Eighth, and other patrons of the Church in former ages. But no ; and here we see the wisdom and large- mindedness of Lord Gifford. ' The lecturers', he says, ' shall be subjected to no test of any hind, and shall not be required to take any oath, or to emit or subscribe any declaration of belief, or to make any -promise of any kind; they may be of any denomination whatever, or of no denomination at all [and many earnest and high- minded men prefer to belong to no ecclesiastical denomination) ; they may be of any religion or way of thinking, or, as is sometimes said, they may be of no religion, or they may be so-called sceptics or agnostics or freethinkers, provided only that the " patrons" will use diligence to secure that they be able, reverent men, true thinkers, sincere lovers of and earnest inquirers after truth.' And further — ' I wish the lecturers to treed their subject as a strictly natural science, the greatest of cdl p^ossible LORD GIFFORD S BEQUEST. 7 sciences, indeed, in one sense, the only science, that of Infinite Being, without reference to or reliance upon any supposed exceptional and so-called miraculous revelation, I wish it considered just as astronomy or chemistry is. I have intentionally indicated, in describing the subject of the lectures, the general aspect which personally I would expect the lectures to bear; but the lecturers shall be under no restraint whatever in their treatment of their theme; for example, they may freely discuss — (and it may be well to do so)— all questions about mans conceptions of God or the Infinite, their origin, nature, and truth, whether he can have any such conceptions, whether God is under any or what limitations, and so on, as I am persuaded that nothing but good can result from free discussion' You will now understand why I call the foundation of these Lectureships a sign, and a very important sign, of the times. Our nineteenth century, which will soon have passed away, has been described as a cen- tury of progress and enlightenment in all branches of human knowledge, in science, in scholarship, in philo- sophy, and in art. In religion alone it is said that we have remained stationary. While everything else has been improved, while new discoveries have been made which have changed the whole face of the earth, while our philosophy, our laws, even our morality, bear the impress of the nineteenth century, nay, of all the nineteen centuries which have passed over them since the beginning of our era, it is said, and not without a certain kind of pride, that our religion has remained unchanged, at least in all its essential elements, » LECTURE I. Whether this is really so, depends on the meaning which we attach to the essential elements of religion, and in religion, more than in anything else, essential elements are but too often treated as non-essential, and, what is worse, non-essential as essential. The his- torian would have no great difficulty in showing that the Christianity of the Council of Nicaea is not in all essential points exactly the same as the Christianity of the Sermon of the Mount, and that the reformers of the sixteenth century at all events did not consider the Christianity of Papal Rome essentially the same as that of the Council of Nicaea. There has been change, whether we call it growth or decay, during the nineteen centuries that Christ's religion has swayed the destinies of the world. Yet the fact remains, that while in all other spheres of human thought, what is new is welcomed, anything new in religion is generally frowned upon. Nay, even when we seem to see healthy growth and natural progress in religion, it generally assumes the form of retro- gression, of a return to the original intentions of the founder of a religion, of a restoration or reform, in the etymological sense of that word, that is, of a going back to the original form. Why should that be so ? Why should there be pro- gress in everything else, only not in religion? The usual answer that religion rests on a divine and miraculous revelation, and therefore cannot be im- proved, is neither true nor honest. And to use such an argument in this place would be disloyal to the memory of the Founder of this lectureship; who wished religion to be treated ' without reference to or reliance upon any supposed exceptional and so-called miracu- LORD GIFFORD's BEQUEST. 9 lous revelation.' But those who use that argument seem really to forget that they are contradicting them- selves. They hold the Old as well as the New Testament to have been divinely revealed, and yet they would not deny that the New Testament repre- sents a decided progress as compared with the Old. Through the whole of the Gospels there seems to sound that one deep note, 'Ye have heard that it was said by them of old time — But I say unto you.' Nay, we might go further. We know that some of the fundamental doctrines of Christianity were in the eyes of the Jews irreligious. The idea of a divine sonship was not only new to the Jews, it was blas- phemy in their eyes, and worthy of death. And yet that very idea has become the corner-stone of a new religion, which new religion calls itself not the de- struction, but the fulfilment of the old. There is nothing in the idea of revelation that excludes progress, for whatever definition of revelation we may adopt, it always represents a communication between the Divine on one side and the Human on the other. Let us grant that the divine element in revelation, that is, whatever of truth there is in revelation, is immutable, yet the human element, the recipient, must always be liable to the accidents and infirmities of human nature. That human element can never be eliminated in any religion, certainly not in our own, unless we claim infallibility not only for the founder of our religion and his disciples, but for their disciples also, and for a whole succession of the suc- cessors and vicars of Christ. To ignore that human element in all religions is like ignoring the eye as the recipient and determinant of the colours of light. AW 10 LECTURE I. know more of the sun than our forefathers, though the same sun shone on them which shines on us ; and if astronomy has benefitted by its telescopes, which have strengthened the powers of the human eye, theology also ought not to despise whatever can strengthen the far-sightedness of human reason in its endeavours to gain a truer and purer idea of the Divine. A veil will always remain. No astronomer ventures to look at the sun without darkening his lens, and man will have to look at what is beyond through a glass darkly. But as in every other pur- suit, so in religion also, we want less and less of darkness, more and more of light ; we want, call it life, or growth, or development, or progress ; we do not want mere rest, mere stagnation, mere death. Now, I say once more, the foundation of this lectureship of Natural Theology seems to me a sign of the times, pregnant with meaning. Lord GifTord, intelligent observer of the world as he was, must have been struck with the immense advances which all other sciences had been making during his life- time, and the increasing benefits which they had conferred on society at large. And so he says in the clearest words : '/ wish Natural Theology to be treated by my lecturers as astronomy or chemistry is, as a strictly natural science, the greatest of all possible sciences, indeed, in one sense, the only science."1 What does that mean ? It seems to me to mean that this observant and clear-headed Scotch lawyer, though he could follow the progress of human know- ledge from a distance only, had convinced himself LORD GIFFORD's BEQUEST. 11 that theology should not stand aloof from the on- ward stream of human knowledge, that it should not be treated according to rules of evidence and principles of criticism different from those to which all other sciences, and more particularly his own science, the Science of Law, owed their strength, their life, and their vigorous growth, but that it should take its place as a science among sciences, undismayed by dangers, and trusting in the inevit- able triumph of truth. Whatever other Universities might say, he wished the Scotch Universities to take the lead, and to stretch out the right hand of fellowship to the newest among the sciences, the last-born child of the nineteenth century, the Science of Religion. Some people profess to be frightened at the very name of the Science of Religion ; but if they ap- proached this new science more closely, they would soon find that there is nothing behind that name that need frighten them. What does this science consist in ? First of all, in a careful collection of all the facts of religion ; secondly, in a comparison of religions with a view of bringing to light what is peculiar to each, and what they all share in common ; thirdly, in an attempt to discover, on the strength of the evidence thus collected, what is the true nature, the origin, and purpose of all religion. I ask, then, Where is the danger ? And why should our Universities hesitate to recognise the Science of Religion as much as the Science of Language, or the Science of Thought? The first Universities which provided chairs for the comparative study of the religions of the world were those of little, plucky 12 LECTURE T. Holland. In 1880 France followed their example, and M. Reville was appointed the first professor of the Science of Religion at the College de France. In 1886 a special school was founded at the Scale des Hautes JStudes in Paris for the study of religions. In Germany lectures on the great religions of the world were generally given by the professors who taught the languages in which the sacred writings were composed. This is an excellent plan, perhaps the best that could be devised. The professor of Arabic would lecture on the Qur'an, the professor of Persian on the Avesta, the professor of Sanskrit on the Veda, the professor of Hebrew on the Old Testa- ment. Lately, however, separate chairs have been created for Comparative Theology in Germany also, and even in the Roman Catholic University of Frei- burg this new study has now found a worthy repre- sentative 1. It may seem strange to some that Lord Gifford should have expressed a wish that the Science of Religion should be treated as a strictly natural science. He may have thought of the method of the natural sciences only ; but it seems to me not un- likely that he meant more, and that looking on man as an integral part, nay as the very crown of nature, he wished religion to be treated as a spontaneous and necessarv outcome of the mind of man, when brought under the genial influence of surrounding nature. If re- ligion, such as we find it in all ages and among all races of men, is a natural product of the human mind — and who denies this ?— and if the human mind, in its his- 1 Die allgemeine vergleichende Religionswisseyischaft im akademischen Stu- tli urn unserer fk&t, von Dr. E. Hardy, Freiburg im Breisgau. 1887. LORD GIFFORD's BEQUEST. 13 torical development, cannot be dissevered from that nature on whose breasts it feeds and lives and grows, the Science of Religion has certainly as perfect a right as the Science of Language to be classed as one of the natural sciences. But that view does by no means exclude an his- torical study of religion ; nay, to my mind, the more interesting, if not the more important part of the Science of Religion, is certainly concerned with what we call the historical development of religious thought and language. It is the same with the Science of Language. That science is certainly one of the natural sciences, but we should never forget that it is full of interest also when treated as an historical science. The line of demarcation between the natural and the historical sciences is not so easy to draw as some philosophers imagine, who would claim even the Science of Language as an exclusively historical science. All depends here as elsewhere on a proper definition of the terms which we employ. If we once clearly understand what we mean by the natural and what by the historical sciences, we shall quickly understand each other ; or, if we differ still, we may at all events agree to differ. Without it, all wrangling pro or con is mere waste of time, and may be carried on ad infinitum 1. From my own point of view, which I need not vindicate again, I am able to accept Lord Gifford's designation of the Science of Religion as a natural science in both meanings of which that name admits. I share with him the conviction that the same treat- 1 Lecture on the Science qf Language, vol. i. p. 1; 'The Science <>i Language as one of the Physical Sciences.' 14 LECTURE I. nient which has caused the natural sciences to gain their greatest triumphs, namely, a critical collection of facts, will be the most appropriate treatment of the Science of Religion ; nor should I differ from him in looking on man, in his purely phenomenal character, as a part of nature, nay, as her highest achievement, so that, if religion can be shown to be a natural out- come of our faculties, we may readily accept the Science of Religion as one of the natural sciences, in the most comprehensive meaning of that term. Any- how, I hope I shall best carry out the intentions of the founder of this lectureship by devoting these lectures, firstly, to a careful collection of the facts of religion ; secondly, to an intercomparison of these facts ; and thirdly, to an interpretation of their meaning. But Lord Gilford has not only indicated what he wished chiefly to be taught in these lectures on Natural Theology ; he has been even more careful to indicate the spirit by which he hoped that his lecturers would be guided. And this seems to me the most remarkable feature of his bequest. Lord Gifford was evidently what the world would call a devout and religious man, and you have heard how in his Will he expressed his conviction that a true knowledge of God is the means of man's highest well-being and the security of his upward progress. Yet so strong was his conviction that all scientific inquiry must be perfectly free, if it is to be useful, that he would hear of no restrictions in the choice of his lecturers. ' They may be of any denomination whatever,' he says, 'or of no denomination at all ; they may be of any religion or of no religion at all ; they may be so- called sceptics or freethinkers, so long as they have lord gifford's bequest. 15 proved themselves sincere lovers of and earnest in- quirers after truth? Now in this large-hearted charity, and at the same moment, in this unshaken faith in the indestructible character of religion, we may surety recognise a sign of the times. Would such a Will have been possible fifty years ago ? Would any English, would any Scotch University at that time have accepted a lectureship on such conditions ? I doubt it ; and I see in the ready acceptance of these conditions on the part of the Scotch Universities the best proof that in the study and true appreciation of religion also, our nineteenth century has not been stationary. When it was first suggested that one of these Gifford readerships might be offered to me, I replied at once to my friends at Edinburgh, Glasgow, and St. Andrews, that I could not become a candidate. It so happened that I was informed at the same time that my own University might again require my services, and I felt very strongly that at my time of life I ought not to undertake new duties, but rather finish, if possible, the work which I had in hand. If I tell you that I was pledged to a new edition of the Rig-veda, which consists of six volumes quarto, of about a thousand pages each, and that besides that, I was engaged in putting a finishing touch to an English translation of the hymns of that Veda, — to say nothing of new editions of several of my other books, which, like myself, had grown old and anti- quated, you will readily believe that, strongly as I felt tempted, and highly as I felt honoured that I should have been thought of as a fit candidate, I thought it wise not to enter on a new campaign. 16 LECTURE I. But when I was informed by your Principal that, though not a candidate, I had been elected, and unanimously elected, by the Senate of your Uni- versity, I had not strength enough to say No. Whether I acted wisely or foolishly, the future must show. But when I had once said Yes, I must con- fess it was to me like the beginning of a new life. Some of the work on which I was engaged had to be thrown overboard ; but I had now an opportunity, and a splendid opportunity, for summing up the whole work of my life. Forgive me if, for a short while, I speak of myself. I know it is very wrong, and may sound very selfish. But I am anxious to explain to you what the main outline of the work of my life has been, and why I hope that in these lectures I may be able to gather up what seems to me worth preserving, and at the same time to place before you the final outcome of life-long labours, devoted to what the ancient Greeks called tcl [xkyivTa, the greatest things. As a student at Leipzig, in the year 1841, I began my studies as a classical scholar, as a pupil of Gottfried Hermann, Haupt, Westermann, Nobbe, and Stallbaum. These were great names at the time, and excellent teachers ; but even before I had taken my degree, I was tempted away by philosophy, attending the lec- tures of Christian H. Weisse, Drobisch, Hartenstein, and Lotze. Leipzig was then richer in great teachers than any other University in Germany. Hartenstein represented the classical Kantian school ; Drobisch was a follower of Herbart ; Weisse made propaganda for Hegelian isni ; Lotze, then quite a young Privat- docent, started a philosophical system of his own, lord gifford's bequest. 17 which now begins, I believe, to attract attention in Scotland also. I imagined at that time I was a Hegelian, and I well remember when I passed my final Examination at Leipzig, and had been wrangling for a long time with my Examiner, Professor Drobisch, all in Latin, on the respective merits of Hegel and Herbart, Drobisch, who was then Dean of the Philo- sophical Faculty, and who I believe is lecturing still at Leipzig, addressed me in the following words : Vir doctissime, quamvis nostris sententiis toto coelo dis- temus, tot/men te creo atque pronuntio magisbrwni Artium et Doctor em Philosophiae in Universitate nostra. The dissertation which I wrote in 1843, in order to obtain my Doctor's degree, was ' On the Third Book of Spinoza's Ethics, De Affeetihas! In the meantime, like many other youug philo- sophers, I had been attracted by Schelling's fame to Berlin, where I attended his lectures, and soon be- come personally acquainted with the old sage. He was at that time an old man, more of a poet and prophet than of a philosopher ; and his lectures on the philosophy of mythology and religion opened many new views to my mind. But, though I admired the depth and the wide range of his ideas, I could not help being struck by what seemed to me his un- founded statements with regard to the ancient reli- gions of the East. I had at Leipzig studied Arabic under Fleischer, and Sanskrit under Brockhaus, and I was then reading Persian with Riickert at Berlin. Though I was a mere boy, Schelling was quite will- ing to listen to some of my criticisms, and at his request I then translated for him some of the most important Upanishads, which form part of the ancient 18 LECTURE I. Vedic literature. I have never been able to recover that translation, and it was not till 1879 that I published a new, and, I hope, more accurate translation of these theosophic treatises, in my Sacred Books of the East. I soon came to see, however, that these Upani- shads were only the latest outcome of Vedic litera- ture, and that in order to know their antecedents, in order to be able to appreciate the historical growth of the Indian mind during the Vedic age, we must study the ancient hymns of the Veda. I re- member having a most interesting discussion on the relative importance of the Vedic hymns and the Upanishads with Schopenhauer at Frankfort. He considered that the Upanishads were the only por- tion of the Veda which deserved our study, and that all the rest was priestly rubbish (Priester-wirthschaft). His own philosophy, he declared, was founded on the Upanishads, which, as he says in one of his books, 'have been the solace of my life, and will be the solace of my death1.' To me it seemed that an historical study of the Vedic religion ought to begin with the hymns of the Rig-veda, as containing in thought and language the antecedents of the Upani- shads. The first book only of the Rig-veda, the collection of hymns, had then been published by Frederick Rosen, and Rosen had died before even that first volume was printed. I felt convinced that all mythological and religious theories would remain without a solid foundation till the whole of the Rier- veda had been published. This idea took complete possession of me, and young as I was, and, I ought to 1 Upanishads, translated by Max Miiller. Sacred Books of the East, vol. i. p. lxi. lord gtfford's bequest. 19 add, reckless as I was, instead of beginning my work- as a lecturer in one of the German Universities, I went to Paris to attend Bnrnouf's lectures, and to copy and collate the MSS. of the Veda and its volu- minous commentary. It was hard work, very uphill work indeed, for Sanskrit was not known then as it- is now, and the whole literature on which Sayawa's great commentary on the Rig-veda is founded, was then almost entirely a terra incognita, and had first to be discovered, and to be studied from MSS. in the Bibliotheque Royale, as it was then called, or in Bnr- nouf's private library. I often thought that I should have to give it up, and return as a Privatdocent to a German University, for I am not ashamed to say that during all that time at Paris, I had to maintain myself, as I have done ever since, with these three fingers. However, encouraged and helped by Bur- nouf, I persevered, and when I was ready to begin the printing of the first volume, I came to England, as I thought for a few weeks only, to collate some MSS. at the East India House in Leadenhall Street, and to make the acquaintance of Professor Wilson, at that time the Nestor of real Sanskrit scholars in Europe. New clouds, however, were then gathering on my horizon. The Imperial Academy of St. Peters- burg, even at that time deeply interested in Indian literature, had voted large funds for bringing out an edition of the Rig-veda with Saya>?a's commentary, and had asked the East India Company for the loan of those very MSS. which I had come to London to copy and collate. At the same time Professor Wilson, in the name of the East India Company, had sent invitations to the most learned Pandits in India, c 2 20 LECTURE T. asking them whether they would undertake an edition of the Rig-veda in India. All my plans seemed thus to collapse ; but I need not trouble you with my personal troubles. Suffice it to say that the Pandits of India declined to undertake the edition of the text and commentary of the Rig-veda, for the simple reason that the study of Veclic literature had at that time been entirely neglected in India ; that the Directors of the late East India Company thought it unfair that the MSS. of the Rig-veda should be sent to the Imperial Academy at St. Petersburg at the very time when I had come to London to make use of them ; and that, on the recommendation of my old friend, Professor Wilson, the East India Company entrusted me with the publication of the Rig-veda at their expense. I did not accept this offer with a light heart. It meant giving up my University career in Germany, and more than that, it meant severe drudgery and the very smallest pay for many years to come. I had no illusions about Saya?ia's commentary. I knew it was the sine qua non for all scholarlike study of the Veda ; but I had seen enough of it to know that it certainly did not contain the key to a real under- standing of the ancient hymns of the Veda. Besides that, even the Veda was to me only a means to an end, namely, a philosophy of mythology and religion, based on more trustworthy materials than those on which Schelling had been able to build his later philo- sophy of religion and mythology. Thus, while I determined to work for others in bringing out as complete and correct an edition of the Rig-veda and its commentary as was then pos- LORD GIFFORD'S BEQUEST. 21 sible, I made up my mind at the same time to carry on my own work. Having then settled at Oxford, and having been appointed to lecture on Modern Literature and Language, I devoted my leisure to a study of the Science of Language. A study of lan- guage is absolutely necessary as an introduction to the study of philosophy as well as of religion. Whatever further research may teach us about the true nature of language, it is clear, from a purely practical point of view, that language supplies at least the tools of thought, and that a knowledge of these tools is as essential to a philosopher, as a know- ledge of his ship and his oars is to a sailor. The Science of Language, as I treated it in my Lectures at Oxford, is pre-eminently an analytical science. We take languages as we find them, we trace them back to their earliest forms, and classify them, and then analyse every word till we arrive at elements which resist further analysis. These elements we call roots, and leave them, for the present, as ultimate facts. In tracing the upward growth of words we arrive at a stage where we can clearly see the branching off of a large number of meanings, springing from the same stem. And among these earliest ramifications we meet with a number of names familiar to us from what is called the mythology of ancient nations. We soon discover that these mythological expressions are by no means restricted to religious ideas, but that there is a period in the growth of language in which everything may or must assume a mythological ex- pression. It was the object of the second volume of my Lectures on the Science of Language, to establish the fact that mythology, in its true sense, was an 22 LECTURE I. inevitable phase in the development of the human mind, and that we could solve many of its riddles with the help of such indications as were supplied to us by a careful study of the general growth of lan- guage. I called this peculiar phase or affection of language a kind of disease, though, like many dis- eases, it ought really to be recognised as a recuperative crisis in the youthful constitution of the human mind. In some few cases only, to which, on account of their perplexing nature, I called particular atten- tion, could mythology rightly be considered as a disease, as a premature hardening, so to say, of the organic tissues of language, namely, when a word had lost its original meaning, and was afterwards inter- preted, or rather misinterpreted, in accordance with the ideas of a later age. I tried to work out this principle in a number of essays which formed the foundation of what is now called Comparative My- thology or the Science of Mythology. In spite of much opposition, arising chiefly from a failure on the part of my critics to understand the principles which I followed and to comprehend the objects I had in view, that Science of Mythology is now as firmly established as the Science of Language1, and I can honestly say that nothing has strengthened my faith in it so much as a gallant and powerful charge lately made against it by a most learned and conscientious critic, I mean Professor Gruppe, in his Griechische Culte und Alythen, 1887. I shall often have to refer to this book in the course of my lectures, I shall often have to express my en- tire dissent from it ; but, before we come to blows, I 1 See A. Barth, Bulletin de la Mythologie Aryenne, in the Revue dc VHistoire des Religions, 1880. p. 109. LORD GIFFORD'S BEQUEST. 23 like thus publicly to shake hands with an antagonist who is learned, serious, honest, and honourable. These mythological researches led me back natur- ally to the problem with which I had started, the pro- blem of the origin and growth of religion. And here it was a similar summons to that which has brought me here to-day, namely, an invitation to deliver the tirst course of the Hibbert Lectures in London, in 1878, that enabled me to lay before a large public the principles of the Science of Religion and Comparative Theology1, as applied to the origin and growth of religion in India. It was while engaged in these researches that I began to feel the absolute necessity of our possess- ing trustworthy translations, not only of the Veda, but of all the Sacred Books of the East. I had by that time finished the edition of the Rig-veda and its commentary, and it was expected that I should publish a complete translation of it. But here I broke down, for reasons which those who know any- thing of the present state of Vedic scholarship will readily understand. The accumulation of material was too great for a single and no longer a young scholar. The one scholar in Germany who by his lexicographic labours would seem to have been best qualified for that task, Professor Roth, declared honestly that a translation of the Veda is a task not for this, but for the next century. I had still many things to finish, and I felt the time had come for drawing in my sails. Having lectured for twenty-five years at Oxford, I thought I had a right to be relieved ; nay, I felt it a duty 1 Hibiert Lectures, Longmans, 1882. 24 LECTURE I. to the University to make room for younger and more vigorous men. I then formed a small society, consisting of the best Oriental scholars in Europe and India, and we began to publish a series of translations of the Sacred Books of the East, which by this time amounts to thirty volumes, and will ultimately com- prise forty- eight. While engaged in conducting this undertaking, I felt it necessary, before resuming my study of religion, to define more clearly my own philosophical position. I had from the very first made it sufficiently clear, I thought, that to my mind language and thought were inseparable, that thought was language minus sound, instead of language being, as was commonly supposed, thought plus sound. It was from that point of view that I felt justified in treat- ing mythology as I had done, namely, as an affection, or even as a disease, of language, and it was in the same sense that I had tried to read in the annals of language some of the secrets of the growth of reli- gion. The common illusion that language is different from thought, and thought different from language, seemed to me one of the best illustrations of modern philosophical mythology ; but I found that even pro- fessed philosophers clung to that myth with the same tenacity with which they cling to their belief in faculties and forces, as different from their manifesta- tions. They had so little understood the fundamental principle on which my system rested, namely, the absolute identity of language and thought, that one of them, Professor Gruppe, published his large work on Mythology, chiefly in order to show that instead of explaining mythology as a peculiarity of language, LORD GIFFOIID'S BEQUEST. 25 I ought to have explained it as a peculiarity of thought. What is one to say to this kind of criti- cism, which ignores, or rather runs its head against, the very walls of the fortress which it means to besiege ? I thus was almost compelled to publish my last book, the Science of Thought, in which I collected all the facts that had been brought to light by the Science of Language, in support of a theory held by the most eminent philosophers from Plato to Hegel *, namely, that Logos is the same thing, whether you translate it by language or by thought, and that as there is no language without reason, neither is there any reason without language. I hope to treat this question more fully in some of my later lectures. At present I only wished to show what is the red thread which holds my literary work together, and to explain to you why, when I received the invitation to lecture on Natural Theology in this University, I felt that, if life and health were granted me, this was the very work I ought still to accomplish. I want, if possible, to show you how the road which leads from the Science of Language to the Science of Mythology and to the Science of Thought, is the only safe road on which to approach the Science of Religion. This Science of Religion will thus become the test, and I hope the confirmation, of previous theories on language, mythology, and thought ; and the work which I began at Leipzig in 1843, will, if my life is spared, be brought to its final consummation in the Lectures which you have allowed me to give in the University of Glasgow. The task with which you have entrusted me is 1 See Contemporary Review, October, 1888 : 'My Predecessors.' 26 LECTURE I. enormous— far beyond the powers of any one man, and I know full well, far beyond my own powers. All I can promise you is to help to clear the ground and to lay the foundation ; but to erect a building, such as Lord Gifford shadowed forth in his Last Will, to raise a temple wide enough, strong enough, high enough for all the religious aspirations of the human race, that we must leave to future generations —to younger, to stronger, and to better hands. LECTURE II. DEFINITION OF RELIGION. Definition of Religion, why wanted. IF the Science of Religion is to be treated as one of the natural sciences, it is clear that we must begin with a careful collection of facts, illustrating the origin, the growth, and the decay of religion. But we shall find it impossible to do so, unless we first enter on a preliminary and, I must add, a some- what difficult inquiry, namely, What is meant by religion. Unless we can come to a clear understanding on that point, we shall find it impossible to determine what facts to include, and what facts to exclude in collecting our evidence for the study of religion. What then is religion ? To many people this will sound a very easy question, as easy as the question, What is man ? Practical people object to such questions, and consider any attempt to answer them as mere waste of time. Now it is quite true that there is a kind of public opinion, which for all ordi- nary purposes settles the meaning of words, and by which we may allow ourselves to be guided in the daily concerns of life. But in philosophical discussions this is strictly forbidden. What is philosophy but a perpetual criticism and correction of language, and the history of philosophy but a succession of new definitions assigned to old and familiar terms ? 28 LECTURE II. Great differences in defining* Religion. Besides, there is anything but agreement on the true meaning of religion. Most people, whatever their opinions might be on other points, would probably hold that religion must always have something to do with God or the gods. But even that is not the case. Buddhism, for instance, which is a creed professed by the largest number of human beings, recognises, as taught by Buddha &akyamuni, no god, or at all events no creator of the universe, and it has been held in consequence that Buddhism could not be called re- ligion. Is Buddhism a Religion? Now it is quite true, we may so define religion that the name could not be applied to Buddhism ; but the question is, who has the right so to narrow the defini- tion of the word ' religion ' that it should cease to be applicable to the creed of the majority of mankind? You see that the right of definition is a most sacred right, and has to be carefully guarded, if we wish to avoid the danger of mere logomachies. How often have I been asked, Do you call Buddha's religion a re- ligion, do you call DarwinV philosophy philosophy, or Wagner's music music ? What can we answer under such provocation, except, Define what you mean by religion, define what you mean by philosophy, define what you mean by music, and then, and then only, we may possibly come to an agreement as to whether Buddha's doctrines may be called religion, Darwin's writings philosophy, and Wagner's compositions music. I know full well that nothing irritates an adversary so much as to be asked for a definition ; and yet it is well known, or ought to be well known, that defini- DEFINITION OF RELIGION. ^9 tion formed the very 'foundation of the philosophy of the ancients, of Socrates, Plato and Aristotle, while the absence of proper definitions has been and is still the curse of modern philosophy1. Definition of Definition. But before we can give a definition of religion, we must first give a definition of definition itself, however pedantic such a request may appear. There are at least three kinds of definitions, the etymological, the historical, and the dogmatic. Etymological Definition. Many people still imagine that an etymology is in itself a definition. This was an impression which prevailed widely in early times 2, before the true principles of etymology had been discovered ; and it prevails even now, though there is no longer any excuse for it. Homer, for instance, is very fond of etymologies which are to account for the peculiar character of certain gods and heroes. Plato extends this practice even more widely, though he often leaves us in doubt whether he is really serious in his etymo- logies or not. You know how in his Cratylus (410) he derives a?/p, air, from aiptiv, to raise, as the element which raises things from the earth ; How he explains aldrjp, ether, as aecOeijp, because this element is always running in a flux about the air (ael del aepa pecov). He derives deoi, the gods, also from the same root delv, to run, because he suspected, as he says 3, ' that the sun, moon, earth, stars, and heaven, which are still the 1 See Mill, Three Essays on Religion, p. 4. 2 Cf. Sarikhyatattvakaiimudi, § 4 ; tannirvafcanaw fea lakshanam, 'the etymological interpretation is the definition.' 3 Cratylus, 397 C. 30 LECTURE II. gods of many barbarians, were the only gods known to the aboriginal Hellenes ; and seeing that they were always moving and running, from this their running nature, they called them gods or runners ; and after- wards,, when they had discovered all the other gods, they retained the old name.' Aristotle was more sparing in his etymological definitions, yet he too derived aldrjp, the ether, from ael Oelv, because it was always running and moving1. The Komans followed the example of the Greeks 2. Poets like Lucretius and Ovid indulged in etymologies, whenever they seemed to agree with their opinions, and to the latest times Koman lawyers delighted in supporting their definitions of legal terms by more or less fanciful derivations. In India also these etymological definitions were recognised from the earliest times. They are generally introduced in the following way : ' This is the saddle- hood of a saddle that we sit on it ' ; ' this is the road- hood of a road that we ride 3 on it ' ; ' this is the heaven-hood of heaven that it has been heaved on high.' Only, while these etymologies are historically correct, any etymology is welcome to the authors of the Brahma^a or the Nirukta. if only it explains some meaning of the word. In some cases these etymological definitions are very useful, but they require the greatest caution. First of all, many popular etymologies 4 are phonetic- ally untenable and historically wrong. God, for in- 1 T)e Mundo, ed. Didot, vol. iii. p. 628. 1. 28 ; Sta to del 6eii>. 2 Lersch, Die Sprachphilosopliie der Alten, vol. iii ; Cic. Nat, Deor. iii. 24. 3 See Academy, Dec. 1888 ; also Plutarch, Fragm. 21. 27. 4 Varro. LI. v. 7. ed. Egger. • Quattuor explicandi gradus : in- fimus is quo etiam populus venit. Quis enim non videt unde areni- fodinae et viocurus?' Lersch, 1. c. vol. iii. p. 126. DEFINITION OF RELIGION. 31 stance, cannot be derived from good, because phonetic laws will not allow it, and because the two words run parallel, and never approach one another, as far as we can follow their history. But even where an etymology is unassailable on phonetic and historical grounds, it can never give us more than the first starting-point of a word. It may teach us how the object to be named was first conceived, but no more. We know, for in- stance, that deus in Latin represents the Sanskrit (leva, perhaps also the Greek 6e6s, though neither of these etymologies is in strict accordance with phonetic rules1, and that deva meant originally, bright. This is extremely important as showing us that one of the many conceptions of the Divine started from the con- cept of bright and beneficent beings, such as sun, and moon, and stars, in opposition to the dark and deadly aspects of the night; but to imagine that this could help us to understand the concept of God in the mind of such a thinker as Pascal, would be absurd. We can never be too grateful, if we can discover the germinal idea of a word, if we can prove, for instance, that dens was originally no more than a bright being, that a priest was originally an elder, a minister a servant, a bishop an overseer ; but if we were to give these etymologies as more than historical curiosities, and mistake them for definitions, we should only prove our ignorance of the nature of language, which is in a constant state of ebb and flow, and exhibits to us the process of continuous evolution better than any other part of nature. 1 See Selected Essays, i. p. 215. I still hold to the opinions there expressed. 32 LECTURE IT. Historical Definition. We now come to historical definitions. What I call an historical definition is an account of these very changes which take place in the meaning of a word, so long as it is left to the silent and unconscious influences which proceed from the vast community of the speakers of one and the same language. Thus an historical definition of deus would have to show the various changes which led from cleva, bright, as ap- plied to the sun, the dawn and other heavenly pheno- mena, to the Devas, as powers within or behind these heavenly bodies, and lastly to the beneficent agents in nature or above nature, whom the Hindus called Devas, and the Romans dii. As the biography of a man may be called his best definition, what I call biographies of words are perhaps the most useful de- finitions which it is in our power to give. Dogmatic Definition. Lastly come the dogmatic definitions, by which I mean definitions given on the authority of individuals, who, whatever a word may have meant etymologically, and whatever it may have come to mean historically, declare that, for their own purposes, they intend to use it in such and such a sense. This is chiefly done by philosophers, lawyers, and men of science, who feel unable to use important words with all the vagueness of their etymological and historical meaning, and determine once for all, generally by the old logical method of settling their genus and their specific difference, in what exact sense they ought to be em- ployed in future. Let us now see how these three kinds of definition DEFINITION OF RELIGION. 33 have been applied to the word with which we have to deal, namely religion. Etymological Definition of Religio. The etymological definition of religion has attracted considerable interest among theologians, owing to that kind of tacit persuasion that the etymology of the word must somehow or other help to disclose its real meaning. It is well known that Lactantius derived religio from religare, to bind or hold back, and he did so, not simply as a philologist, but as a theologian. ' We are born,' he says, ' under the con- dition that, when born, we should offer to God our justly due services, should know Him only, and follow Him only. We are tied to God and bound to Him (religati) by the bond of piety, and from this has religion itself received its name, and not, as Cicero has interpreted it, from attention (a rele- gehdo)1.' Before we examine this etymology, it will be use- ful to give the etymology which Lactantius ascribes to Cicero, and which he is bold enough to reject. Cicero says : ' Those who carefully took in hand all things pertaining to the worship of the gods, were called religiosi, from reUgere, — as neat people (elegantes) were so called from elegere2, to pick out; likewise diligent people, diligentes, from diligere, to choose, to value, and intelligent people from Intel- 1 Lactantius, Instttut. Div. iv. 28, 'Hac conditione gignimur, ut generati nos Deo justa et debita obsequia praebeamus, hunc solum noverimus, hunc sequamur. Hoc vinculo pietatis obstricti Deo et religati sumua ; unde ipsa religio nomen accepit, non, ut Cicero in- terpretatus est, a relegendo.' 2 Rather from a lost verb elegare. 34 LECTURE 11. ligere, to understand ; for in all these words there is the meaning of legere, to gather, to choose, the same as in rellgiobus 1. Let us first clear the ground of some statements which are repeated again and again, but which have really no foundation. It is often said that Varro2 supports the etymology of Lactantius, but Varro simply treats of legere and legio, and thus supports indirectly the etymology of Cicero, rather than that of Lactantius. Festus, again, if he is to be quoted at all as having given an etymology of rellgio, sides with Cicero, and not with Lactantius, for he says that people are called religiosi if they make a choice (delectus) of what has to be done or to be omitted in the worship of the gods, according to the custom of the state, and do not entangle themselves in superstitions 3. Of later writers St. Augustin follows sometimes the one, sometimes the other derivation, as it suits his purpose ; while among modern theologians it has actually been maintained that rcligio was descended from vellgare as well as from relegere, so as to com- bine the meanings of both 4. From a purely philological point of view it cannot 1 Cicero, De Nat. Dear. ii. 28, 'Qui autem omnia quae ad cultum deorum pertinerent diligenter retractarent et tamquam relegerent sunt dicti religiosi ex relegendo, ut elegantes ex eligendo, itemque ex diligendo diligentes, et intelligendo intelligentes. His enim in verbis omnibus inest vis legendi eadem quae in religiose' 2 Varro, Be ling. lat. v. 68 ; ed. Egger. Legio, ' quod leguntur milites in delectu ;' Nitzsch, Studien mid Kritikcn, i. p. 527. 3 Festus, p. 236, 'Religiosi dicuntur, qui faciendarum praeter- mittendarumque rerum divinarum secundum morem civitatis de- lectum habent nee se superstitionibus implicant.' 4 'Relegendo se sentit religatum,' von Drey, as quoted by Nitzscb, I.e. DEFINITION OP RELIGION. 35 be denied that religio might have sprung from religa re quite as well as from rdegere. The ordinary objection that from religare we should have religatio, and not religio, has no real weight, for we find by the side of opinari such words as opinio, not opinatio, and necopinus ; and by the side of rebellare, rebellis and rebellio. In lictor also, if it meant originally a man who binds the criminal, we should have to admit a root ligere, by the side of ligare. The real objection to our deriving religio from religare is the fact that in classical Latin religare is never used in the sense of binding or holding back. In that sense we should have expected obligatio, or possibly obligio, but not religio. Cicero's etymology is therefore decidedly preferable, as more in accordance with Latin idiom. Relegere would be the opposite of neglegere or negligere1, and as neglegere meant 'not to care,' relegere would naturally have meant 'to care,' 'to regard,' ' to revere'2. From a verse quoted by Nigidius Figulus from an ancient writer, and preserved by Gellius (iv. 9), we learn that religeus was actually used, as opposed to religiosus. He said: Religentem esse oportet, religiosus ne fuas, 'it is right to be reverent, but do not be religious,' that is, superstitious 3. 1 The change of e into i is historical. We find neglego and negligo, mteUego and intelligo. The spelling with e is the old spelling' but there are modern compounds also which have always e, such as pcrl'go, inxielego. 2 M. M. Hibbert Lectures, p. 22. 3 Gellius, ed. Hertz, iv. «J. Adjectives in osus generally imply an excess, as vinosus, muUcrosus. Thus Nigidius Figulus said : 'Hoc in- clmamentum semper hujuscemodi verborum, ut vinosus. mulierosus, religiosus significat copiam quandam immodicam red super qua dicitur. Quocirca religiosus is appellabatur qui nimia et super- stitiosa rehgione sese alligaverat, eaque res vitio assignabatur.' -bed D 2 36 LECTURE II. The German word Anclacht, literally thoughtful- ness, then reverence, has sometimes been compared with religio, but there is a slight difference, for Andacht conveys the meaning of meditation rather than of regard and reverence. There is one more etymological definition of religion which Gellius (iv. 9) ascribes to one Masurius Sabinus. He derived religiosum, in the sense of sacred, from relinquere, to leave or put aside, as something too sacred for ordinary purposes1. As phonetic laws would not allow of this derivation, we need not discuss it further. So much for the etymology of religio, which in its first conception can only have meant respect, care, reverence. Historical Definition of Religio. We now come to what I called the historical defini- tion, or what others might prefer to call an historical description of the fates of the word religio, while con- fined to its own native soil. Most words, particularly those which form the subject of controversies, have had a history of their own. Their meaning has changed from century to century, often from genera- tion to generation ; nay, like the expression of the human face, the expression of a word also may change from moment to moment. In one sense our historical definition may be called the biography of praeter ista,' thus Gellius continues, -quae Nigidius elicit, alio quo- dam diverticulo significations, religiosus pro casto atque observant! cohibentique sese certis legibus finibusque dici coeptus.' 1 'Masurius autem Sabinus in commentariis quos de indigenia composuit, religiosum, inquit, est quod propter sanctitatem aliquam remotum ac sepositum a nobis est, verbum a relinquendo dictum, tamquam caerimonia a carendo.' Gellius, ed. Hertz, iv. 9. DEFINITION OP RELIGION. 37 a word, and if only it can be recovered with any approach to completeness, such a biography conveys to us more information than can be gathered from any logical or etymological definition. So long as the word religio remains on Roman soil, all changes of meaning seem perfectly intelligible, if only we take into account the influence of those forces which determine the growth of meaning in all words. Afterwards, when the word religio is trans- ferred from a Roman to a Christian atmosphere, from classical to mediaeval Latin and the modern Romanic dialects, from popular parlance to technical theology, the case becomes different. We then enter on purely dogmatic or self-willed definitions, the natural growth of language seems arrested, and all we can do is to register the various meanings which have been assigned to the word religion by philosophers and theologians of authority and influence. Tracing the history of religio, we find it used in Latin in its original and wider sense of regard or respect, in such expressions as religio jurisjurandi, reverence for an oath, as distinguished from metus deorum, fear of the gods1. Religio and metus occur frequently together, for instance, Cic. ii.inVerr. 4, 45, 101, ut earn (cupidita- tem) non metus, non religio contineret, where we can translate the two words metus and religio by fear and awe, fear expressing the fear of men or of conse- quences, awe the fear of the gods It is said in another place that when the moon was suddenly eclipsed on a 1 Cic. Font. ix. 30. 'An vero istas nationes religione jurisjurandi ac metu deorum immortalium in testimoniis dicendis commoveri arbitramini, quae tantum a ceterarum gentium more ac natura dissentiunt,' 38 LECTURE II. clear night, the whole army was perturbed religione et metu, by awe and fear. Such expressions also as religio est facer e aliquid do not refer to religious scruples 1 only, but to any qualms of conscience. After a time, however, religio became more and more defined as the feeling of awe inspired by thoughts of divine powers. Thus Cicero2 states, religio est quae mperioris cujusdam naturae quam divinam vocant curam caerimoniamque affevt, 'Religion is what brings with it the care and cult of some higher power which they call divine.' As we find here religio and caerimonia placed side by side, we find likewise cultus and religio 3 joined, the former expressing the outward, the latter the inward worship of the gods. A distinction is soon made also between religion and superstition, as Cicero says, nee vero super- stitions tollerida4 religio tollitur, 'though super- stition should be removed, religion is not.' Lastly, religio, and also the plural religiones5, became the recognised names of outward religious acts, of cult and ceremony. Thus Cicero ° distinctly explains religio by cidtus deorum, and he declares 7 that the religion of the Romans is divided into sacra, 1 Liv. ii. 62, 'Ut numine aliquo defensa castra oppugnare iterum religio fuerit.' 2 Invent, ii. 53, 161. ,. . ,. 3 Cic. JV. D. i. 43, 121, 'Quis aut cultu aut religione dignaa judi- care (imagines).' 4 Be Div. ii. 72, 148. 5 Cic. ii. Verr. v. 13, 34, ' Contra fas, contra auspicia, contra omnes divinas atque humanas religiones.' c iV. D. ii. 3, 8, ' Religione, id est cultu deorum. multo supenores. 7 De Nat. Deor. iii. 1, 'Quumque omnis populi Romani religio in sacra et auspicia divisa sit, et tertium adjunctum sit, si quid praedictionis caussa ex portentis et monstris Sibyllae interpretes haruspicesve monuerunt. ' DEFINITION OF RELIGION. 39 sacrifices, and auBpida, observations of the flight of birds, to which a third part has been added, namely, when the interpreters of the Sibyl or the haruspices declared something for the sake of prophecy from portenta and monstra. The ausjneia he supposes to have been founded by Romulus, the sacra by Numa. In another place he distinguishes superstition from religion, quae deorum cultu pio continetur1, 'which consists in the devout worship of the gods.' We meet even with such expressions as veligio deorum im- mortalium 2, i. e. the worship of the immortal gods. So far we can watch the natural development of the word veligio in Latin. It began with the mean- ing of care, attention, reverence, awe ; it then took the moral sense of scruple and conscience ; and lastly became more and more exclusively applied to the inward feeling of reverence for the gods and to the outward manifestation of that reverence in worship and sacrifice. There are some late writers who use religio in the sense of faith ; for instance, Cassiodorus (died 562, A.D.), Religionem cogere non possumus, quia nemo eogitur ut invitus credat 33 ' We cannot force religion, for no one is ever forced to believe against his will ' : but in classical Latin religio never has that meaning. Thus ends the biography of the word religio, so long as it lived its natural life, unchequered by technical definition. We can clearly see that what the Romans expressed by religio was chiefly the moral or practical, not the speculative or philo- sophical side of religion. The questions as to the 1 N. D. i. 42, 117. - Cic. Lad. 25. 96. 3 Variorum Libri, ii. 27. 40 LECTURE IT. existence, the character and powers of their gods, did not trouble their minds, so long as they were left to themselves ; still less did they make their sense of moral obligation, which they called religio, dependent on their faith in the gods only. They had a feeling of awe in their hearts at the sight of anything that seemed to them overpowering and beyond the grasp of their senses and their understanding. They did not care much whence that feeling arose, but they called it religio, that is, considering, thinking twice, hesitating ; that was enough for them. The idea that the gods had implanted that feeling in their hearts, or that a thing was wrong or right because the gods had forbidden or commanded it, did not occur to them, till they had come in contact with Greek philosophy. Their religion, if we may use that word in its later and far more general sense, was very much what Spinoza in his Tractatus theologico-politicus thinks that practical religion ought always to be, simple piety and obedience, as distinguished from philosophy and love of knowledge. The gods were accepted without any misgivings, their approval of what was right and good was taken for granted, and no further questions were asked. So great is the difference between religio, as understood by the Romans, and religio as commonly understood, by us, that religio Romana would never have conveyed to Cato the idea of his knowledge of Jupiter, Mars, or Vesta, and the duties he owed to them, but rather that of ancient Roman piety. There is a well-known verse by Schiller: ' Which religion I have ? There is none of all you may mention. Which I embrace, and the cause? Truly, religion it is,' DEFINITION OF RELIGION. 41 Here he uses religion in the first line in a purely modern sense, in the second line in a truly classical sense. .What he meant was that he was held back by awe, by reverence and humility, from deciding on the truth of any single form of faith, and this the Romans too might have called religion. French has in some expressions retained the class- ical meaning of religio. In such a phrase as II a line religion inviolable pour sa parole we recognise the Latin religio jurisjurandi1. Later meanings of Religio. We now have to follow the word religio in its later wanderings. Transferred to a Christian soil, religion became really a foreign word, and as such had to be defined by those who used it. and chiefly by theolo- gians and philosophers. We naturally look first to the Old and New Testament to see in what sense religion is used there. But in the translation of the Old Testament the word religion never occurs, and in the New Testament it occurs three times only ; and in one of these passages the translation varies between religion and superstition. In the Acts of the Apostles, xxvi. 5, we read : ' I lived a Pharisee after the most straitest sect of our religion.' Here religion, in the Vulgate, religio, corresponds to the Greek Op-qaKeta, which means outward worship of the gods. In the Epistle of St. James (i. 26, 27), we have dprjo-Kcia, reli- gious worship, and the adjective 6pr\o-Kos, which is rendered by religious, in the Vulgate by religiosus. In the Epistle to the Galatians (i. 13, 14) the trans- 1 See Littre", s.v. He also cites such expressions as il a une religion et un sele pour les Merits du roi, or il sefait urn religion d'icouter les rations. 42 LECTURE IT. lation the 'Jews' religion' is meant to render the Greek 'lovba'lanos, which is retained in the Vulgate as Judaismus. Lastly, in the Acts, xxv. 19, ' they had certain questions against him of their own supersti- tion, and of one Jesus, which was dead, whom Paul affirmed to be alive,' we have in Greek heicnhai\xovia, which really means the fear of the gods, and which the Vulgate translates rightly by superstitio, the Ke vised Version less correctly by religion \ In all these passages, what is intended by religio, as used in the Vulgate, is a system of religious belief and worship ; no longer what was meant by religio in its classical sense. The nearest approach to religio in its original meaning is found in the Greek evaefieia. The verb o-efio\iai 2, expressed at first being awestruck, standing back with awe. Thus o-e/3as \x e^et eicropoWra meant ' awe holds me back while I behold.' It after- wards is used for reverence towards the gods. Thus cvo-ifieia Ztjvos is used by Sophocles (Electra, 1097) in the sense of reverence towards Zeus, and the same word with the preposition eh occurs in the sense of piety towards parents, as in Plato's Kepublic, 615 C, evcrefieia eh Oeovs kcll yoveas. After Homer we find o-ejBoixai used with the accusative, like veneror, for instance, o-ef/3o/xai Oeovs, I worship the gods. At first the Greeks used heiaihai^ovia^ fear of the 1 Other Biblical expressions for religion are v. In Latin theologia was taken by Varro in the sense of what we call religion, there being according to him three kinds of theology, the mythical, the pltysical, and the civil. The mythical theology contained the fables about the gods, and many things, we are told, contrary to the dignity of immortal beings. The physical theology was described by him as beyond the capacity of the vulgar, while he considered the civil theology, the received religion of Rome, as best for a good citizen to believe. In Christian phraseology theologos meets us first as the name of the author of the Apocalypse, John the Divine, or the theologos. This name, however, wre are told, was given to him, not simply because he was 1 See Grappe, Die griechischen Quite, ]>[>. t>32-637. 46 LECTUKE II. what we call a theologian, but because he maintained the divinity of the Logos. In the third and fourth centuries theologos is said to have meant usually one who defended that doctrine. Later, and particularly during the middle ages, theo- logy came to mean religious doctrine in general, as studied by theologians or priests, and Abelard's Theo- logia Christiana was meant to represent what was afterwards called Summa theologlae, a body of sys- tematical knowledge concerning Christian religion 1. Dogmatic and Practical Religion. The fashion which prevailed for some time, par- ticularly in Germany, of using religion in the sense of practical and moral religion, while re- serving theology as a name of dogmatic religion, is objectionable, and can only create confusion. We may distinguish between dogmatic and practical religion, and we may equally distinguish between dogmatic and practiced theology. But as a theo- logian is now always used in the sense of a man who studies religion professionally or who belongs to the faculty of theology, it will be best to reserve theology as a name of this study. A mere believer in the dogmas of any religion is not yet a theologian. I therefore propose to retain religion in its general sense, comprising both dogmatic and practical religion, and reserve theology as the name for a scientific study of both. This will prevent all misunderstanding, unless we prefer to drop the name of theology altogether, and replace it by the name of the Science of Religion. 1 8eo Flint, in Encyckp, Brit. s.v. Theology. DEFINITION OF RELIGION. 47 Comparative Theology. It is likewise a mere abuse of technical terms to speak of Comparative Religion. There is religion and there is a science of religion, just as there is language and a science of language. But no one would speak of Comparative Language ; neither ought we to speak of Comparative Religion. It is different with mythology. Mythology may be used, not only for a collection of myths, but likewise for a scientific treatment of them, and in the latter sense therefore it would be correct to speak of Comparative Mythology. Wo have thus far distinguished between : Religion, dogmatic and practical, and Theology, dogmatic and practical. To some philosophers, and theologians also, such a division between practical and dogmatic religion seems objectionable, nay, impossible, because they maintain that morality cannot possibly exist without some be- lief in a divine, or, at least, a rational government of the world, and that dogma again would be useless, unless it became the motive of practical morality. This may be true, but we need not enter into that question at present, for by simply qualifying religion as either dogmatic or practical, we only distinguish, we do not separate ; and without committing our- selves as yet to any opinion as to whether morality can exist without dogma or dogma without morality, we do no more by our nomenclature than admit the existence of a common element in both. Schleiermacher's Definition of Religion. Some philosophers, however, and particularly Schlei- ermacher, claim the right of using religion in a still 48 LECTURE II. higher sense. " They deny that religion is either dog- matic or moral : they deny also that a combination of dogma and morality would give us religion. They point out that when we say that a man is without religion, we do not mean simply that he does not believe in Judaism, Christianity, or any other form of faith, or declines to submit to their moral codes. We mean really that he is without any religious senti- ment. Schleiermacher explains religious sentiment as being the immediate consciousness that all that seems finite is infinite, that all that seems temporal is eternal. ' To seek and find what is infinite and eternal in all that lives and moves, in all changes and chances, in all doing and suffering, in fact by an im- mediate sentiment to have and know life itself as the infinite and eternal life, that,' he says, ' is religion.' — ' From that point of view, if once reached, all events become real miracles, all miracles become real events ; all experience becomes revelation, all revelation ex- perience.'— ' If we do not see our own miracles around us, if we do not perceive within us our own revela- tions, if our soul does not yearn to draw in the beauty of the whole world and to be pervaded by its spirit ; if in the highest moments of our life we do not feel ourselves impelled by the divine spirit and speaking and acting from our own holy inspiration, if we do not at least feel all that we feel as an immediate in- fluence of the universe, and yet discover in it some- thing that is our own, that cannot be imitated, but can prove its pure origin within ourselves, we have no religion.' We shall have to consider this meaning of religion when we come to examine the Upanishads, the Ve- DEFINITION OF RELIGION. 49 danta philosophy, the poetry of the Sufis, and the speculations of the mediaeval mystics ; but it seems to me that it would be better if a different name could be assigned to what may be the highest height which religion can reach, but is nevertheless a com- plete transfiguration rather of human nature than a system of doctrines about the Divine, and a code of precepts inspired by our belief in the Divine. In German it is called Religiositat ; in English religious- ness or devotion might be used in the same sense. Religion, either belief or body of doctrines. We have still one remark to make with regard to the ordinary use of the word ' religion,' before we can feel ourselves properly equipped for grappling with the great historical definitions of religion which have to be examined. Like many terms of the same character, religion can be used either for our own intellectual possession of theoretic dogmas and moral principles, or as a name of a body of doctrines and precepts collected by authority, chiefly for the pur- pose of teaching these doctrines and practices. Thus we may say that a person has changed the Jewish for the Christian religion, that is to say, that he has changed his own religious convictions. But we may also say that a person is studying the Buddhist re- ligion, either by reading the sacred books of the Buddhists or by watching the life of the Buddhists in Ceylon or China, without allowing these studies to exercise the least effect on his own convictions. This ambiguity can hardly be avoided, and we have to make allowance for it in all branches of knowledge. We speak of logic, meaning either the laws of thought as E 50 LECTURE II. we know and follow them ourselves, or a body of doctrines, contained in essays and manuals ; and we shall have to bear in mind the same double meaning when we speak of religion. A strict adherence to the terminology, as we have now explained it, will help us, I hope, to avoid many misunderstandings, and enable us at the same time to assign to each of the various definitions of religion its proper place. LECTURE III. EXAMINATION OF DEFINITIONS. Natural and Revealed Religions. MOST of the earlier definitions of religion which we shall have to examine, have reference to Judaism and Christianity only. These two religions were considered, in Europe at least, as different in kind from all the rest, being classed as supernatural and revealed, in opposition to all other religions which were treated as not-revealed, as natural, and by some theologians even as inspired by the powers of evil. In an historical study of religion, however, such a distinction is untenable1, for we shall find that the claim of revelation or the assertion of a supernatural origin is by no means peculiar to Christianity and Judaism. Most of the great religions of the world were by their followers believed to have been revealed, and the arguments by which such a belief was sup- ported are much the same among all theologians. As the founders of most religions professed to teach what no eye had seen nor ear heard, they could not invoke the ordinary authorities for the truth of their doctrines, but had to appeal to supernatural sources of knowledge. And even in cases where the founders 1 See Flint, Theism, p. 323. E 2 52 LECTURE ITT. themselves made no such claim, but took their stand on the testimony of the spirit of truth only, their fol- lowers would soon ascribe to them a higher authority, so as to render all questionings and all opposition to their doctrines impossible. This applies to all or nearly all religions, and the claim of a supernatural origin, so far from being exceptional, is really one of the most natural tendencies of natural religion. The student of Comparative Theology therefore can claim no privilege, no exceptional position of any kind, for his own religion, whatever that religion may be. For his purposes all religions are natural and historical. Even the claim of a supernatural character is treated by him as a natural and perfectly intelli- gible claim, which may be important as a subjective element, but can never be allowed to affect the ob- jective character of any religion. Comparative Theology. In that respect Comparative Theology has but fol- lowed the example of what used to be called Natural Theology, which was always denned as the study of religion, independent of revelation. It professed to comprise all that could be known of God by the aid of the human understanding alone. This system of natural religion, such as we find it elaborated, for in- stance, by Raymundus de Sabunde (or Sebonde), was intended at first to serve as an introduction only to revealed religion1. But it soon became independent, » Thus we read in the Theologia XatumUs sive Liber CreaUn-anon speciaiiter de homine et de natura ejus in quantum homo et dehis quae sunt ei necessaria ad cognoscendum seipsum et deum, et omne Sum ad quod homo tenetur et obligatur turn Deo quam .proximo, Argentinae, 1496, 'Liber creaturarum est porta, via, janua, intio- EXAMINATION OF DEFINITIONS. 53 and Natural Religion, in its purity and reasonable- ness, threatened to excel all revealed religion. In the last century all religions began to be treated as sects, if not as corruptions, of Natural Religion, and a study which at first was looked upon as a powerful aid to faith, was afterwards discouraged as dangerous to the interests of true religion. Natural Theology differed, however, from what is now called Comparative Theology in that it paid but scant attention to the historical religions of the world, framing its ideal of what natural religion ought to be,' from the inner consciousness only. But in the same way as towards the beginning of our century General Grammar, which taught what, according to the rules of logic, language ought to be, was replaced by Comparative Grammar, which showed what language really had been, the study of Natural or General Theology also had to make room for the study of Comparative Theology, or what may be called the Science of Religions, as distinguished from the Science of Religion. While Natural Theology treated of religion in the abstract, or of what religion might or should have been, Comparative Theology studies religions as they have been, and tries to discover what is peculiar to each and what is common to all, with a silent conviction that what is common to all religions, whether revealed or not, may possibly con- stitute the essential elements of true religion. Modus cognoscendi et colendi Deum. The first definition with which we have to deal, and which is perhaps the most widely accepted among ductorium et lumen quoddam ad lihruni sacrae Bcripturae in quo sunt verba Dei, et ideo ille praesupponit istum.' (Titulua ccxii. 54 LECTUKE TIL Christian theologians, existed, as we shall see, with a very slight alteration, among non-Christian as well as among Christian theologians. In most theological manuals we find religion defined as modus cognoscendi et colendi Deum, ' a mode of knowing and worshipping God.' Though accepted by most theologians as unob- jectionable, this definition has not escaped criticism. It is said 1 that a definition should trace whatever has to be defined back to one genus prosrimum, not to two ; that if religion is a mode of knowing God, well and good ; but that it cannot be at the same time a mode of worshipping God. This may be true in logic, but what can we do if, as a matter of fact, the same name has been given to our knowledge as well as to our worship of God ? In that case the definition of religio as modus cognoscendi et colendi Deum would at all events be historically correct. But that is not all. There are surely many concepts which have two sides, nay, which become complete only when we compre- hend these two or more sides as sides of one and the same concept. We may define a triangle by its three angles as well as by its three sides. Our definition of logic becomes complete only if we define it both as a knowledge and as an art. Even while engaged in studying logic and gaining a knowledge of the laws of thought, we practise these very laws, while afterwards in practising the laws, we know also as logicians that we know them. It is the same in medicine, in law, and in most of what we call the applied sciences. 1 This is powerfully stated by Teichmuller in his Religionsphilo- sophie, 1886, p. 16. EXAMINATION OF DEFINITIONS. 55 Knowledge and practice, e7rto-r?j/x?/ and ri-^vrj, are mostly inseparable. And this realty holds true in religion more than anywhere else. Is not religion as mere knowledge or faith said to be ' dead, being alone 1,' that is, being without works ? And would not works, however per- fect and useful, cease to be religions, if performed without a motive, without a knowledge of God ? Peeling1 or Knowledge as motive of action. But we may even go a step further. A]l our acts are stimulated either by feeling or by knowledge, by percepts or by concepts. A feeling of pain makes us act in one way, a feeling of pleasure in another. A mere perception of distance makes the crow fly direct, that is by the shortest road, and induces a peasant to cross a field diagonally, instead of laterally. A know- ledge of geometry produces the same action, only lined with intelligence. An engineer does what the crow does, only he does it, not simply by intuition, but because he knows that the hypothenuse of any triangle is, nay, must always be, shorter than the two other sides together. In this way every act of ours may be shown, I believe, to be under the influence of either feeling or knowledge, and thus the active side of religion also could easily be shown to be insepar- able from, though of course not identical with, the theoretic side. The logical fault, therefore, of tracing religion to two proximo, genera instead of one, if fault it be, would have its historical justification in the fact that active religion, whether worship or morality, is, in its beginning at all events, inseparable from religious 1 Ep. James iii. 17. 56 LECTURE III. knowledge, while in most cases religious knowledge would by its very nature lead to religious acts. The object of religion must be denned. There is, however, a much more serious difficulty in this definition, and this may best be discovered, if we examine the same definition as we find it in a very similar wording in the writings of a heathen philo- sopher, namely Seneca. He defines religion as Gog- noscere Deum et imitari\ ' to know God and imitate him.' Now let us remark that Seneca does not say, to know the gods and imitate them, but to know God and imitate him. We must indeed not lay too much stress on this, for it is well known how promiscuously philosophers of his age used dens either in the singular or the plural. Thus the same Seneca 2 says : ' I do not obey God, but I assent to him with all my heart ; he worships the gods best who imitates them.' Now, if Seneca had in his definition of religion spoken of an imitation of the gods, we should probably have de- tected at onced the serious fault which his definition shares in common with that of our own theological manuals. We shall see that in defining religion, both definitions leave the most important part, namely, the object of religion, undefined. If Seneca had ex- plained religion as a knowledge and imitation of Mars, Bacchus, or Venus, we should have said at once, But how do you know that there are such beings as Mars, Bacchus, or Venus 1 What do you know about their character and their proceedings, 1 Imitation of God had been prescribed by Pythagoras also, and ^Yitll some restriction (as far as nature permits) by Plato. 2 Epist. i. !»5, 96, 6pos 0eov, are often used as synony- mous with religion. Teichmuller. One of the most eminent of modern philosophers l who have lately been writing on the philosophy of religion, Professor Teichmuller of Dorpat, whose recent death has been a serious loss to our studies, combines the sentiments of fear and reverence in his definition of religion, and adds to it a third, namely the senti- ment of moral goodness. Religion, he says, consists, (1) Of personal feelings of fear, of complete dependence on unknown powers, which form a motive leading man to seek comfort in a view of the world not supported by experience. (2) It consists of aesthetic feelings, which surrender themselves in admiration to the Beautiful, and lead to the erection of an ideal world. (3) It consists of moral feelings, which lead to an 1 ReUgiomphihsophie, Breslau. 1886. EXAMINATION OF DEFINITIONS. 65 attempt to construct such a system of the universe as should in turn make them (our moral feelings) in- telligible 1. Author of Natural Religion. The author of Natural Religion, whoever he may be, lays the chief stress on the sentiment of admira- tion, defining religion as a habitual and permanent feeling of admiration. Goethe. Goethe preferred reverence instead of admira- tion, though he speaks of the result rather than of the nature of religion. ' A threefold reverence,' he writes, ' has to be called forth in man by religion : a reverence for what is above, for what is around, and for what is beneath us. The last is the most difficult, and has been realised by Christianity only, because it alone has been able to recognise even misery and poverty, scorn and contempt, shame and disgrace, suffering and death as divine; nay to honour and cherish even sin and crime, not as impediments, but as helps to the Saint.' Mill. Mill also, in his Three Essays on Religion, pub- lished after his death, in 1874, would seem to trace back religion to a feeling of admiration, or, as he expresses it, to a craving for an ideal object. ' So long as human life is insufficient,' he writes, 'to satisfy human aspirations, so long there will be a craving for higher things which finds its most obvious satisfaction in religion.' And again : ' The essence of ' Teichmiiller, I.e., p. 22. On page 91, he gives a more concise definition of religion as 'the disposition (Gesinnung) which, being joined to God-consciousness, symbolises itself in the common function of knowledge, feeling, and action.' F 66 LECTURE III. religion is the strong and earnest direction of the emotions and desires towards an ideal object, recog- nised as of the highest excellence, and^ as rightfully paramount over all selfish objects of desire1.' After having examined these two classes of defini- tions, which look exclusively to either the practical or the theoretical side of religion, we have still to say a few words on the views taken of religion by one of the most theological of philosophers, Spinoza, and by one of the most philosophical of theologians, Schleiermacher. Spinoza, 1632-77. Though Spinoza defines true religion and piety as love of God, founded on a knowledge of his divine perfections— a definition with which Leibniz seems t0 agree— yet he considers that with us practical reli- gion should come first, should in fact remain the only religion for the majority of mankind, while a higher and&philosophical faith should be reserved for the few. What Spinoza means by practical religion^ is simple obedience to divine commands, while the higher reli- gion consists in the intellectual love of God, insepar- able from a true philosophical knowledge of God and man, and leading to that true blessedness which arises from the consciousness of our own God-given powers. The former he considers as based entirely on sacred books and historical revelation, the latter on the highest knowledge which can only be the work of our own mind. The former ought to be beneficial, the latter ought to be true ; the former is to serve for the public good, the latter is to lead to that peace and 1 Three Essays, p. 104. EXAMINATION OF DEFINITIONS. 67 love of God, which passeth all understanding. Spinoza's view of religion does not in this respect differ much from that of the Brahmans. As they look upon the first and second period in a man's life as a discipline to subdue our human passions and weaknesses, Spinoza too expects practical religion to curb the' passions and thus to prepare man for a higher life Only after this has been achieved is the mind prepared for a purer light. In India this progress from a lower to a higher religion was supposed to take place in the same individual, when passing through the four stages of his life, the four asramas. In Spinoza's time, and in the society by which he was surrounded, such a hope was impossible. Few only might find the way to the highest beatitude ; but even for those who rested half-way, practical religion supplied, as Spinoza thought, all those comforts which human nature requires in every stage of its growth. This was the man who not more than 200 years ago was considered the most dangerous heretic by his Jewish co-religionists. Schleiermacher, 1768-1834. Let us now hear what Schleiermacher has to say on religion, he who has likewise been spoken of as a most dangerous heretic by his Christian co-religionists. I mentioned already that he recognised true religion neither in thoughts nor in deeds, nor in both combined, but rather in a certain disposition or tone or character of the whole man, in what is called in German religiose Shmmung. Religion was to him a kind of music pervading all our sentiments, our thoughts and our F 2 68 LECTUBE III. acts ' Religion,' he say s \ ' is neither knowing nor doing, but an inclination and determination of our sentiments, which manifests itself in an absolute feeling of de- pendence on God.' Or again : ' Religion consists m our consciousness of absolute dependence on something which, though it determines us, we cannot determine in turn2.' , . .. He tries to describe this feeling or this disposition and inclination of the mind or the heart in ever vary- ing expressions. He calls it ' a sentiment, sense, taste of the Infinite.' In his Second Discourse on Religion, he is anxious to show that religion is neither meta- physics nor ethics, nor a mixture of both, though something of each is mixed up with all positive religions. 'Religion is not knowledge, because the measure of knowledge is not the measure of piety. Observation may be said to belong to religion, but the observation of religion is different from that of science. It does not aim at knowing the finite m relation to the infinite, nor the nature of the highest cause by itself or in relation to finite causes. It strives to view'the universe, to watch it reverently in its own manifestations and acts, and to let itself be grasped and filled in childlike passivity by its immediate influences. Religion is the immediate consciousness of all that is finite within the infinite, of all that is temporal within the eternal.' "This intuition, however,' he adds, 'without senti- ment would be nothing, and cannot have either the right origin or the right force. Sentiment also with- out intuition would be nothing, and both together are « Christliche Glaubenskkre, § 3. 2 Hibbert Lectures, p. 19. EXAMINATION OF DEFINITIONS. 69 something only when they are undivided, and because they are originally undivided.' Hegel, 17 70-1 831. In opposition to this sentiment of dependence and devotion which, according to Schleiermacher and his numerous disciples, constitutes the essential character of religion, Hegel defines religion as perfect freedom. If the sense of dependence constituted religion, he says, the dog might be called the most religious animal K Religion, with Hegel, is perfect freedom ; it is in fact the Divine Spirit as becoming conscious of Himself through the finite spirit. Or again, 'Religion is the knowledge acquired by the finite spirit of its essence as absolute spirit.' Pichte, 1"762-1814. With equal boldness does another philosopher, Fichte, define religion, not as sentiment, but as knowledge. 'Religion is knowledge,' he says. 'It gives to man a clear insight into himself, answers the highest questions, and thus imparts to us a complete harmony with ourselves, and a thorough sanctification to our mind2.' 1 What was considered a rather coarse joke of Hegel's has now become a serious doctrine. 'The feeling of religious devotion,' Darwin writes, ' is a highly complex one, consisting of love, com- plete submission to an exalted and mysterious superior, a strong sense of dependence, fear, reverence, gratitude, hope for the future, and perhaps other elements. No being could experience so complex an emotion until advanced in his intellectual and moral faculties to at least a moderately high level. Nevertheless we see some dis- tant approach to this state of mind in the deep love of a dog for his master, associated with complete submission, some fear, and per- haps other feelings.' M. Houzian (Etudes sur les Faculty's Mentales des Animaux, pp. 271-273) thinks that there are many persons and even peoples not so religious as dogs.' The monkeys of the Sun da Isles, we are told, gather shortly before sunrise in the highest tree- tops, and salute the rising sun with clamorous shouts. Open Court, 1889, p. 1458. 2 Hibbert Lectures, p. 15. We must here remember that knowledge 70 LECTURE III. How to account for these different definitions. It may seem difficult to understand how it is pos- sible that men whose knowledge and whose honesty of purpose admit of no doubt should have arrived at such different, nay contradictory, definitions of religion. How could Schleiermacher see in religion absolute de- pendence, when Hegel perceives in it the most abso- lute freedom? How could Fichte define religion as the highest knowledge, while Agnostics in ancient as well as in modern times have represented the object of religion as beyond the sphere of human know- ledge ? Such contradictions have often been pointed out and made use of in order to prove the vanity of all human knowledge, or, at all events, the futility of philosophy, when applied to religious problems. But there is no reason to despair. I believe that the Science of Thought, as based on the Science of Lan- guage, supplies a solution to this as to many other riddles of philosophy. There is but one solution for them all, and this consists in our denning the words which we use in philosophical discussions. At first sight dependence seems indeed the very opposite of freedom ; but we have only to define de- pendence as trust, and then dependence or trust in God as the wisest, the most perfect and most power- has been used in very different senses, varying from mere ac- quaintance with a subject to a perfect understanding of it. Thus while most theologians use belief as different from or even as opposed to knowledge, Dr." Flint, in his Lectures on Theism (p. 86, Appen- dix X, On Intuition, Feeling, Belief, and Knowledge in Beligion\ declares that ' belief is inseparable from knowledge, and ought to be precisely co-extensive with knowledge.' This may throw light on the real intention of his definition of religion. 'Perhaps/ he says, ' if we say that religion is man's belief in a being or beings, mightier than himself and inaccessible to his senses, but not indifferent to his sentiments and actions, we have a definition of the kind required.' (Theism, p. 32.) But can belief in what is inaccessible to our senses be rightly called knowledge? EXAMINATION OF DEFINITIONS. 71 fnl Being, is changed at once into a perfect consensus or accord with the will of God, nay into perfect and unhesitating atoneness with even His most inscrutable counsels. So long as man stands face to face to God, conscious only of his own physical weakness and of the overwhelming power of what is above, and be- neath, and around him, he may feel himself dependent only, a creature, a slave, a mere nothing ; but when he has discovered the omnipresence of the Divine, not only without but within himself, then that feeling of dependence is inevitably changed into a feeling of union, trust, and love, and he begins to understand what was called of old the liberty of the children of God. So again, when the Agnostic says that we cannot know God, when he calls God the Unknown, nay even the Unknowable, he is perfectly right so long as he uses the verb to knoiv in its ordinary sense. To know, in its ordinary sense, means first to perceive through the senses, and then to conceive by means of language. All our phenomenal knowledge is such and cannot be otherwise. Nihil est in intellects quod non ante, or rather, quod non simul fuerit in sensu1; and nihil est in intellects quod non simul fuerit in lingua. Now to know the Divine by this knowledge, by the same knowledge with which we know a stone, or a tree, or a dog, would be tantamount to annihilating the Divine. A known God, in that sense, would ijiso facto cease to be God. It would become a phenomenal object, an idol, if you like, or a fetish, or a totem, but not what tve mean by God. Scitur Deus ncsciendo. 1 This saying, commonly ascribed to Locke, I have traced back to Sir Thomas Bodley. I have seen it quoted also by M. Moms, in a letter to Descartes, March 5, 1649 (Descartes, (Euvres, vol. x. p. 213), as cet axiome d'Aristote, il n'y a rim dans V intellect qvi n'ait passd par les sens. 72 LECTUEE III. But as soon as we recognise that the very concept of phenomenal is impossible without the correlative concept of the noumenal, or, in other words, that there can be no appearance without something that appears, and, behind its appearance, is or exists by and in and for itself ; as soon as we have learnt to recognise the invisible in the visible, the eternal in the temporal, the infinite in the finite, the Divine Presence in nature and in man, then we can under- stand what Fichte meant when he called religion the highest knowledge, for it is religion in its truest sense which opens our eyes and makes us perceive the nou- menal in the phenomenal, the supernatural in the natural, and thus changes the very veil of nature into a never-ceasing revelation of the Divine. All religions may be called endeavours to give expression to that sense of the real presence of the Divine in nature and in man. Philosophers called that sense the sensus numinis, and when Aristotle said that ' all things are full of the gods \ whatsoever appears before our sight, or our hearing, or any other sense,' he meant what we mean, that by knowing the finite we know the infinite, by knowing nature we know God, by knowing our- selves we come to know the Highest Self, that Self which poets and prophets have called by many names, but which, by its very essence, is and must be above all names, the Unknown, in one sense, and yet the fountain of all knowledge, in the truest sense of the word. 1 Atb teal twv iraXaioJv eiireiv rives Trpor)x^€0av °TI TWTa ravra kari 6ewv 7r\ea ra teal Si' 6(f)9a\^aiu IvSaWofxeva rjniv nal Si' atiorjs real Trdarjs aiadrfffews. Arist. ed. Didot, iii. p. 636, 1. 38. Be Munch, cap. vi, LECTURE IV. Positivist Definitions of Religion. RESIDES the definitions which we have hitherto examined, and which all proceed from men who took an historical and impartial view of religion, there is another class which betray a decidedly polemical spirit, and which proceed chiefly from what are called positivist philosophers. Even they cannot deny that religion has a deep foundation in human nature, but they look upon it as a mistake, as a disease, as some- thing that ought not to be, and they ascribe its origin, not to the noblest, but rather to the meanest and most selfish motives of our human nature. Wundt. Professor Wundt, for instance, a most eminent German physiologist and psychologist, declares that all percepts and sentiments become religious as soon as they have reference to some ideal existence which can supply the wishes and requirements of the human heart l. It cannot be denied that this is one side of religion ; but it is not the whole of it, nor would it be true to say that all wishes, even the most selfish and sordid, were ever supposed to receive their fulfilment from that ideal existence which is postulated by religion. l Teichmuller, Religionsphiloscyhie, xxxiii ; Gruppe, Die Griechischen Quite unci Mijthen, 1887, p. 246. 74 LECTURE IV Feuerbach. Feuerbach was more decided still, and declared that the gods were nothing but the wishes of men, conceived as realised. But there are wishes and wishes, and even admitting that some of the ancient gods represented the very lowest wishes of men realised, there would be others also, representing the realisation of the highest ideals which the human mind can conceive. Generally speaking, positivist philosophers have added little to an historical study of religion. They have told us, not so much what religion has been, as what, according to their view of the development of the human mind, it ought or it ought not to have been. Gruppe. There is one exception, however. In a decidedly learned work, published in 1887, Die Griechischen Culte UTid My then, Professor Gruppe has put forward a view of religion which deserves the most careful consideration, and which I, at all events, cannot pass over in silence, considering that the greater part of his first volume, consisting of more than 700 pages, is directed against myself. His book is certainly in- structive, and though I differ from Professor Gruppe on almost every point, I cannot but admire his learning, nor should I ever wish for a better and more valiant antagonist. Let us hear then the worst that can be said of religion. Selfishness the Source of Religion. According to Dr. Gruppe, who may well be taken as the most powerful representative of the extreme EXAMINATION OF DEFINITIONS. 75 positive and, at the same time, negative school of philosophy, religion exists simply because it satisfies certain selfish instincts of man. It has no other raison d'etre. The rapid spreading of religion all over the world is likewise ascribed to a social instinct which is supposed to be gratified by certain advan- tages which all religions provide. Religions, we are told, do not only give pleasure, but they enable the individual members of a society to develop their faculties far better than the mere laws of family and state would allow. By an inner bond of thought and feeling which unites a religious community, the individual gains more power of resistance in the struggle of all against all. It is only because it answers these requirements of society that religion flourishes. It keeps the poor and miserable quiet by promising them pleasures in the world to come, and thus enables the rich and noble to enjoy their pleasures on earth in safety. It alone can strengthen law and morality in a state of society where there is no equality, and it would probably cease to exist altogether, if all inequalities on earth could be re- moved. Without accusing the founders of religion of selfish motives in the lowest sense, Professor Gruppe is nevertheless convinced that they were all uncon- scious egotists. They enjoyed the reverence shown them by the multitude to that extent that they did not shrink, as he thinks, even from a martyr's death. But generally, while professing to found a new king- dom of heaven, they succeeded in founding a kingdom of this world. The three true causes of the wide and rapid spread of religion are therefore (I.e., p. 273), according to him — 76 LECTURE IV. (1) the unconscious vanity of its founders, (2) a belief in the happiness which it procures to its believers, and (3) the substantial advantages which society derives from it. This would really, so far as I can judge, leave the question of the origin of religion in the mind of its founders unsolved ; but this, we are told, is of little consequence, for the mere fancy of any single individual would have answered the purpose. Besides, it is asserted (p. 276) that all historical reli- gions presuppose older religions, and are reformations rather than original intellectual creations, while the first conception of religious thought required no more than a high degree of personal energy to induce people to believe what was irrational, and to do in their primitive sacrifices what was absurd. Here, again, however, the question why any single in- dividual should have invented what was so utterly irrational, remains unanswered. Professor Gruppe's formal definition of religion I must give in his own words : — ' We call religious belief a belief in a state or in a being which, properly speaking, lies outside the sphere of human striving and attainment, but can be brought into this sphere in a particular way, namely, by means of sacrificial ceremonies, prayers, penances and self-denial. It might seem possible that on the strength of such a belief an individual should simply for his own benefit invent means by which such a possibility could be realised. But in history the re- ligious belief always meets us as a doctrine, professing to be able to produce the union with those beings, EXAMINATION OF DEFINITIONS. 77 and the attainment of that state for a large number of men. Such a doctrine we call religion.' His definition too narrow. You see that it would be difficult to take a lower view of religion. However, as I remarked before, everybody is at liberty to give his own dogmatic definition of religion. The only question is whether the definition given by Professor Gruppe, and eagerly adopted by those who claim the name of positivist philosophers, comprehends really all that in the history of the world has been comprehended under the name of religion. That there have been, and that possibly there are even now, human beings to whom religion is nothing but disguised selfishness, may be true ; but that there have been, and that possibly there are even now, human beings willing and able to surrender their own will to a Divine Will, can hardly be doubted even by Professor Gruppe. His definition of religion is therefore at all events too narrow, and it might possibly be found to apply to religion, not in its original, but in its most depraved state ; not as conceived by the founders of religion and by those who were found willing to become martyrs to their convictions, but as adopted by those who under the cloak of religion were bent on gratifying the lowest passions of human nature. On this point Professor Gruppe is not quite explicit, and we must wait for the appearance of his next volumes, before we can believe that the impression left on our mind by his first volume is really quite correct. So far as he has gone at present, his argument seems to be this, that religion is something so irra- 78 LECTURE IV. tional, not to say, so absurd, that it could have been invented once and once only in the whole history of mankind. He denies altogether that religion is a general characteristic of man, and that there is any excuse for it either in human nature or in its sur- roundings. Once, or possibly twice only, he main- tains, did such a paradox as religion enter into the heart of man. All similarities therefore which have been discovered between religions are ascribed by Professor Gruppe to an historical transmission, which began probably not much earlier than the seventh centuiy B.C. We are not told as yet where and when this monstrous birth took place, but everything seems to point to Phoenicia, or possibly to India (1. c, p. 499). We are given to understand in several places that the Nile has borrowed from the Ganges, not the Ganges from the Nile (pp. 499, 502, 507). The greater antiquity of the Egyptian literature is questioned again and again, and in Babylon also no trustworthy dates are admitted before the seventh century (p. 345). That missionaries could have travelled to Greece, Italy, and Central Europe from the South is said to be proved by discoveries of articles dropped on their journeys by early commer- cial caravans. That Eastern Asia, China, and Japan could have been reached by early missionaries from India, is said to be proved by the success of Buddhist missionaries at a later time ; and that from Eastern Asia the transit to America was not altogether impos- sible is now admitted, we are told, by the most competent authorities. Again, we are reminded that the Mohammedan religion found its way in later times from Eastern Asia to Australia, on one side, and to EXAMINATION OF DEFINITIONS. 79 Madagascar and Africa on the other, so that there really was no physical impediment that could have prevented the spread of the earliest religion in the same directions. Even Northern Asia, we are told, was in later times touched by Persian influences, and might therefore have been reached by the emissaries of those who had made the first discovery of religion. At all events, no difficulties in the historical spreading of this religion, when once discovered, could compare, according to Professor Gruppe, with the difficulty of accounting for the discovery of something so opposed to all the laws of thought as religion. One man, he thinks, in the whole history of the world, may have committed that logical suicide (p. 277), possibly two, if America could not have been reached from China, but certainly no more. This is Professor Gruppe's theory, which sounds almost incredible in the nineteenth century after Christ, but which is put forward and defended with so much earnestness and so much learning that it requires and deserves a careful answer. When philo- sophers had proved, or imagined they had proved, that religion in some form or other was inevitable, and inseparable from human nature, to be told that reli- gion would never have arisen but for the chance discovery of one single individual— and he a fool- is startling. When archaeologists had proved, or imagined they had proved, that the images of Egyptian deities went back to 4000 B.C. and that some of the statues of Babylon could not be much more modern \ to be told that in Babylon evervthin^ before the seventh century is nothing but constructive 1 Sayce, Hibbert Lectures, p. 33. 80 LECTURE IV. chronology, and that in Egypt all dates before 1000 b. o. are uncertain, was enough to rouse considerable indignation. Still one cannot help respecting the opinions of a man, who, besides being a classical scholar, has made himself master of Hebrew, and has not shrunk from studying Sanskrit, Zend, Hierogly- phics and Cuneiform Inscriptions, before he ventured on his dangerous voyage of discovery. In spite of all drawbacks, I can strongly recommend his book as containing most useful information. I myself feel most grateful for it, for I am convinced that if my own system can resist so powerful and well delivered an attack as Professor Gruppe's, it need fear no serious danger in future. There is another advantage to be derived from the study of Professor Gruppe's work. If other writers tell us the best that can be said of religion, he tells us the worst. Most writers who are honest enough to point out the weak points of religion, and who do not shut their eyes to the infinite mischief that has been wrought in its name, always plead for its purifi- cation and reformation, not for its total abolition. They see the rubbish, but they also see the grains of gold even in the most degraded forms of religion. Not so Professor Gruppe. Looking on all religion as an outrage on human reason, he hopes that the time may come when religion will have clean vanished from the earth, and when the world will have become so perfect that no more perfect world could be imagined or desired. It is well that we should see ourselves as we are seen by others, and no one cer- tainly has enabled us to do that better than Professor Gruppe. EXAMINATION OF DEFINITIONS. 81 We have now finished our historical survey of the most important definitions of religion, though I am well aware that there are others which would have deserved and would have repaid a careful examina- tion \ This survey has taken up much of our time, but the advantages which accrue from a careful defini- tion of religion, and of all the words which we use in philosophical discussions, will be perceived again and again at every step of our inquiries. Universality of Religion. Let us to-day take one instance only. No question has excited so much interest and has produced so much heat and passion as that of the universality of religion. Are there at present any human beings without religion, or does history tell us of any ? You may read book after book on the subject, and you will ask how it is possible that on so simple a matter of fact there can be any difference of opinion. But not only is there difference of opinion, but there is flat contradiction. The same tribes who are described by some observers as deeply religious, are described by others as without an idea of anything super- natural. How is this to be accounted for ? Angle of Vision. Some allowance must, no doubt, be made for the angle of vision which varies in every observer. This does not necessarily arise from dishonesty, as is so 1 St,riSUf ,(?e,fines religion as a feeling for or touch with the Uni- verse Gefuhl fur das Universum) ; H. Lang as love of the Infinite ; a/ J i oil°mp?,0n m his work on Thc ReKwous Sentiments of the Human Mind, 18&8, as the aggregate of those sentiments in the human mind arising in connection with the relations assumed to subsisl between the order of nature (inclusive of the observer) and a postulated supernatural. r G 82 LECTURE IV. often supposed, but simply from a weakness inherent in human nature. We all are inclined to see what we expect or wish to see, and if we see what we expect or wish to see, we are naturally less incredulous and less critical than if we see what we did not expect or did not wish for. We are all liable to this, and we have all to learn to be doubly incredulous when we meet with unexpected confirmations of our own favourite theories. I shall give you two illus- trations only of what I mean, cases where men, famous for their honesty and their critical disposi- tion, were completely deceived in what they saw and heard. Darwin on Tierra del Pueffo. One is the case of Darwin. We know how from his early youth his mind was dominated by the idea of evolution, and how his researches led him to look everywhere for evidence in support of that theory and for an explanation of its working. ^ He wished to find men as low as animals, or, if possible, even on a slightly lower stage than that reached by some of the higher animals. When he visited the coasts of South America he thought he had found in the inhabitants of Tierra del Fuego what he was look- ing for, and he accordingly described these people as like the devils which come on the stage in such plays as the Freischiitz. 'Viewing such men,' he writes, ' one can hardly believe that they are fellow-creatures, and inhabitants of the same world. Their language scarcely deserves to be called articulate. Captain Cook compared it to a man clearing his throat ; but certainly no European ever cleared his throat with EXAMINATION OF DEFINITIONS. 83 so many hoarse, guttural, and clicking sounds.' With regard to the physical features of these Fuegians also Darwin must either have been very unlucky in the specimens he met, or he must even then have used his own somewhat coloured Darwinian spectacles. Captain Snow speaks of exactly the same race, which Darwin describes as hideous devils, as really beautiful representatives of the human race, and Professor Virchow, who exhibited a number of natives from Tierra del Fuego at Berlin, protested warmly against the supposition that they were by nature an inferior race. But more than that. Their very language which had been described by Captain Cook and by Darwin as worse than the noise of a man clearing his throat, has lately been studied by Giacomo Bove, who describes it as ' sweet, pleasing, and full of vowels,' and who states that the number of words forming their dictionary amounts to 32,430. If we remember that Shakespeare could say all he wished to say— and who has poured out a greater wealth of thought and feeling than Shakespeare ?- with about 15,000 words, a race possessed of more than double that number of words can hardly be said to be below the level reached by some of the higher animals. I have quoted this case on several occasions, not in order to question Darwin's honesty, but simply to illustrate one cause of error to which all human observations are liable— a disposition to see what we expect and wish to see. Darwin was honest enough to con- fess his error, and that is more than can be said of many other observers. And I feel therefore all the more bound to state that there are some dialects spoken in Tierra del Fuego, such as the Alacalu or G 2 84 LECTURE IV. Ona, which Signor Bove himself declares to be harsh and guttural l. ITielmlir and Bunsen. Lest I should appear unfair in quoting Darwin only, let me tell you what happened to Niebuhr. The story was told me by my friend Bunsen, who was his secretary when Niebuhr was Prussian Mimster at Rome. Niebuhr was very anxious to discover traces of Greek in Italian, as spoken by the common people in the South of Italy. He thought that the occupation of the country' by the Greeks, when the South of Italy was called Magna Graecia, ought to have left at least a few vestiges behind, just as the occupation of Britain by the Romans can be proved by such words as Chester in Dorchester, Lat. castrum; coin in Lincoln, Lat. eolonia; cheese, Lat. casern; street, Lat. strata, scil. via*. Finding himself one day with Bunsen in a small boat, and being caught by a storm, Niebuhr listened attentively to the sailors, who were rowing with all their might and shouting what sounded to Niebuhr's ears like ttAo'ij. ' Listen, he said to Bunsen, 'they call for *AA| or euvkor, Ulnkoia), a fair voyage. There you have a survival of the Greek spoken in Magna Graecia. Bunsen listened attentively. He saw that one of the sailors looked very English, and that the others simp y repeated what he said and what seemed to them to possess a certain charm ; and he soon discovered that what to Niebuhr sounded like wXo'ij or ei-TtAo.,, was really the English, ' Pull away.' • Sec Bove, Patagonia, Terra id Fuom, Eapporto del Tenente Giaeomc EXAMINATION OF DEFINITIONS. 85 If such things can happen to Niebuhr and Darwin, we must not be surprised if they happen to smaller men ; and, to return to our subject, we must not be surprised if some missionaries find no trace of religion where anthropologists see the place swarming with ghosts and totems and fetishes ; while other mission- aries discover deep religious feelings in savages whom anthropologists declare perfectly incapable of any- thing beyond the most primitive sensuous perceptions. Lubbock v. Quatrefages. But though a certain bias must be admitted in writers on anthropology, that does not suffice to account for such books as Sir John Lubbock's Prehistoric Times, as illustrated by Ancient Remains and the Manners and Customs of Modern Savages, 1865, as compared with Quatrefages, L'espece humaine, 1877, and Roskoff, Religionswesen der rohesten Naturvolker, 1880. Sir John Lubbock collects all the evidence that can possibly prove the existence even now of tribes without religion, while Quatrefages and Roskoff sifting the same materials, show on the contrary that there is no trustworthy evidence whatsoever to sup- port such a theory *. Neither the facts adduced by Roskoff, nor the arguments founded on these facts,, have ever been controverted, and until that has been done — and I doubt whether it can be — this controversy ought to be considered at an end. My friend, Dr. Tylor, also made some time ago a very useful collection to show how the same people who by one missionary are said to worship either one or many 1 Introcl. to the Science of Belly ion, p. 277. 86 LECTURE IV. gods, are declared by another to have no idea and no name of a Divine Being, and how even the same person sometimes makes two equally confident assertions which flatly contradict each other. Thus in one place Sparr- mann1 is very doubtful whether the Hottentots believe in a Supreme Being, and tells us that the Khoi-Khoi themselves declared that they were too stupid to understand anything, and never heard of a Supreme Being ; while in another place the same Sparrmann argues that the Khoi-Khoi must believe in a supreme, very powerful, but fiendish Being, from whom they expect rain, thunder, lightning and cold. Liechten- stein, again, while denying in one place that there is any trace of religious worship among the Khosa Kafirs, admits in another that they believe in a Supreme Being who created the world, though, if we are to believe Van der Kamp (died 1811), they have no name for such a being. Preconceived Ideas. It may seem strange why there should be so much animus in these discussions, and why missionaries and anthropologists should not be satisfied with simply stating the facts, such as they are. But there is a reason for it. It seems important to some people to prove that religion is a necessity of the human mind, or, as it was formerly expressed, is innate, or, as Cicero says, is engraved by nature on our minds -. To them, therefore, it seems of vital interest to prove that no race of men has ever been found without some kind 1 Theophilus Hahn, Tsuni-Goam, the Supreme Being of the Khoi-Khoi, 1881, p. 45. . _ 2 Cic. Be Nat. B. i. 17, 45, 'Natura insculpsit in mentibus ut Deos aeternos et beatos haberemus.' EXAMINATION OF DEFINITIONS. 87 of religion, as little as any human beings have ever been found without the cravings of hunger and thirst. Other philosophers, on the contrary, like Professor Gruppe, are anxious to prove that religion is not an essential ingredient of human nature, but an acquired social habit ; and in their eyes the actual existence of non-religious races acquires an immense importance, as confirming their view of human nature. In this they totally forget that all human beings, whether we call them savages or not, may formerly have had a whole pantheon of supernatural beings and have forgotten or surrendered it, just as the Hindus, in becoming Buddhists, surrendered their belief in the ancient Devas. But this would be against another article of the anthropologist faith, namely that savages, who are really far more changeable than civilised races, are stereotyped once for all, and unchangeable. Sometimes these two parties change sides in a very strange way. When the Missionary wants to prove that no human being can be without some spark of religion, he sees religion everywhere, even in what is called totemism and fetishism ; while, if he wants to show how necessary it is to teach and convert these irreligious races, he cannot paint their abject state in too strong colours, and he is apt to treat even their belief in an invisible and nameless god, as mere hallu- cination. Nor is the anthropologist free from such temptations. If he wants to prove that, like the child, every race of men was at one time atheistic, then neither totems, nor fetishes, not even prayers or sacrifices are any proof in his eyes of an ineradicable religious instinct. If, on the contrary, he is anxious to show that the religions of the highest races are but 88 LECTUKE IV. an evolution of lower types of faith, or, as Darwin would wish us to belie ve,Nbi^at even animals possess something like religious feeling then a sigh, a tear, a sudden silence, an involuntary interjection, or even a curse, become proof positive of thV- existence of germs of religion, though in a most rudimentary state. We ought to be as cautious at least as Cicero, who, after he has introduced Velleius as upholding the universality of religion1, makes Cotta say that such important questions cannot be settled by majorities, provided even that we knew the religions of all races of men 2. Though we know a good deal more of the world than was known at the time of Plutarch, yet we should probably hesitate to say what he says, ' that you may indeed find towns without walls, without letters, without kings, without houses, without wealth, not requiring coined money, ignorant of theatres and gymnasia. But there is no one who has seen or who ever will see a town without temples and without gods, not employing prayers, oaths, or oracles, and not performing sacrifices to render thanks for good things or to avert misfortunes 3.' The historian of religion must try to be as free as possible from all preconceived opinions. He may be convinced, as a philosopher, that it is impos- sible for any human being to be without something like what we mean by religion, but as every child is born both without religion and without language, the possibility at least ought to be admitted that some 1 Cic. Ik Sot. Dear. i. 16, 43, 'Quae est enim gens, aut quod genus hominum quod non habeat sine doctrina anticipationem quandam deoruni ? ' 2 Cic, /. (., iii. 4, 11, 'Placet igitur tantas res opinione stultorum j udicari ? ' 3 Plutarch. Adv. Cohten, cap. 31. EXAMINATION OF DEFINITIONS. 89 races might have remained in a state of childish idiotcy, might be without religion, without language, nay, without reason. In most cases, however, which I have been able to examine where some authorities maintained that certain savage tribes had never heard of religion, while other observers declared that they had discovered in their language names for good and evil spirits, these strange contradictions could always be accounted for by the absence of a proper definition of religion. If religion can be used, and has been used, in so many different and even contradictory senses as we saw in our last lecture, we need not wonder that there should be so much conflict of opinion when it has to be determined whether Negroes or Australians do or do not possess religion. If religion is defined as a modus cognoscendi et volendi Deum, even Buddhism would not be a religion. If it is defined as a surrender of the finite will to the infinite, even Judaism, at least in its earliest form, would hardly deserve the name of religion. If a belief in a more perfect future life is considered an essential element of religion, then the faith of the early Greeks would not be a religion1. If temples and sacrifices are indispensable for religion, the ancient Germans, and some of the Polynesian tribes 2, even at present, would be without a religion. This is but one instance to show how much all our inquiries into the history of religion, and all our 1 Mill, Three Essays, p. 121. 2 Chamisso, Werke, ii. p. 258, ' Es giebt auf Ulea und den Ostlichereii Inseln (Lamureck, etc.) weder Tempel noch Priester, und es finden keine feierlichen Opfcr statt, Auf Mogemug, Eap und Ngoli sind eigene Tempel erbaut, Opfer werden dargebracht, und es giebt einen religiosen Dienst.' 90 LECTURE IV. theories on the origin of religion, depend on a clear and correct definition of what we mean by religion, of what is included, in and what is excluded from the sphere of that name. Names for Religion. Before, however, I proceed to give you what seems to me the right definition of religion, at all events from an historical point of view, — a definition, I mean, of what religion has been, rather than of what, accord- ing to the opinions of various philosophers, it ought to be, I have a few words to say on the names for reli- gion in foreign, and particularly in Oriental languages. It is surprising to find how difficult it is to discover words in these languages which correspond exactly to our concept of religion. This difficulty applies, no doubt, to many words, and it is a very useful lesson which the study of foreign languages teaches us. When we first begin to learn a new language, all seems easy. The dictionary gives us the corresponding words, the grammar the corresponding forms. But the more we learn of a foreign language, the more difficult do we find it to discover words that will really square our own words. There is always something too much or too little. We enter really into a new atmosphere as soon as we speak in a new language, and there are associations playing round every one of our own expressions which, like the light and shade of the clouds, like the rustling of the leaves, and like the freshness of the air, determine, without being per- ceived, the whole character of a landscape. So common a word as philosopher, for instance, has a much narrower meaning in German than in English. EXAMINATION OF DEFINITIONS. 9] A man like Darwin would not be called ein Pkilo- soph in German, but ein Naturforscher. Philosophie in German has remained restricted to Logic, Psycho- logy, Ethics, Metaphysics, Aesthetics; and we have Darwin's own confession that of all these subjects he was absolutely ignorant. It is a standing joke among German philosophers against English philosophy, that in England you can buy philosophical instruments. The joke loses its point as soon as it is known that philosophy in English means likewise the study of nature, such as chemistry, optics, acoustics and all the rest, and that therefore what in German are called plxysicalische Instrumente may well be called philosophical instruments in English. There are many such words in all languages which are the despair of the translator. A very common word in German is zweckmdssig, that is, anything so contrived that it answers its purpose. From it, Zweckmassigkeit, which we may translate by appropriateness, but which means a great deal more. We can speak of the innere Zweckmas- sigkeit eines Organismus, that is, an organism in which everything is so contrived that it answers exactly the purpose for which it was intended ; but I know no word in English or French which fully conveys that meaning 1. However, the modern languages of Europe have so many of their antecedents in common, that in a rough and ready way one can be made to answer as well as another to express our thoughts. We lose a little 1 Dr. Martineau (Study of Religion, ii. p. 154) translates it by •adaptation to internal ends,' or ' internal conformity to an end,' but he generally retains the German expression 92 LECTURE IV. when we exchange a shilling for a German Mark, and we lose more when we accept a franc for a shilling ; still, if we are not too exacting, we can make our way through the world with one coinage as well as with the other. But when we leave Europe to travel in Eastern countries, the exchange becomes more and more difficult, both with our monetary and with our in- tellectual coinage. It sounds hardly credible, but if you take so rich a language as Sanskrit, and a liter- ature so full of religion as that of India, you look in vain for a word for religion. To a certain extent this is our own fault. If we put so many ill- defined meanings into a word as have been put into religion, we must not be surprised if we do not find exactly the same conglomerate elsewhere. Here it is where thinking in two languages often proves very useful, by making us aware of the presence of the many amorphous particles of thought which will not pass through the sieve of another language. But it is strange, nevertheless, that a word which seems to us so simple and so clear as religion, should be without its exact counterpart in any language. Words for Keliglon in Chinese. It may easily be imagined that if so rich a language as Sanskrit is deficient in names corresponding exactly to our idea of religion, other languages do not supply us with better equivalents for that word. In Chinese, for instance, there is, as Professor Legge informs us, no word corresponding exactly to our word religion. To Confucianism there is applied more especially EXAMINATION OF DEFINITIONS. 93 the character Chido, meaning ' the Teaching or In- struction,' Doctvina. To Buddhism the character Fa is commonly given, meaning ' Law.' Fo FA, ' the Law of Buddha,' is Buddhism. Taoism is Tdo, ' the Way.' These are often spoken of as San Chido, ' The Three Systems of Teaching, ' for which phrase the best rendering seems to be ' the Three Religions.' But if the three be spoken of discriminatingly, the different terms are appropriate to them severally. The authors of the famous Nestorian Inscription applied all the three names to Christianity. Now it is with them ' the Doctrine,' now ' the Law,' and now ' the Way.' They found it difficult, they say, to fix on a distinctive name for it, and finally determined to call it Citing Chido, ' the Illustrious Doctrine,' using the terms which Lao-tze employs, when he says he would call his subject or system the Tdo or Way. The general term for 'having faith' is lisin, in- dicating the idea of ' believing.' Words for Religion in Arabic. In Arabic, which reflects more advanced and subtle thought on religious topics than most languages, there is, nevertheless, no word that can be considered a real equivalent of our word religion. Bin, ac- cording to Lane, implies obedience and submission to the law, and is used in Arabic for religion in the widest sense, both historical and practical. Ahla-d- din, however, people of religion, is a term restricted to those who profess to found their faith upon re- vealed scriptures, Mohammedans, Jews, and Christians, 94 LECTURE IV. while the followers of natural religion are classed with the followers of philosophical systems, as ahlu- bahwd, people of opinions. Dharma. I know the difficulty of finding a word for religion in Sanskrit from practical experience. Some years ago an enlightened and very zealous gentleman in India, Behramji M. Malabari, conceived the plan of having my Hibbert Lectures ' On the Origin and Growth of Religion' translated not only into Sanskrit, but into the principal vernaculars of the country. The question was, how to translate the title. If the book had been on the origin of any particular religion, such as the teaching of Buddha or Mohammed or Christ, there would have been no difficulty. But the idea of religion in general had not presented itself clearly to the Hindu mind, and hence there was no recognised name for it. After long consideration, we settled that it should be simply Dharma-vyakhyana, 'an explanation of Dharma,' that is, the Law, and under that title translations of my Hibbert Lectures have appeared in Bengali, Guzarati, and Marathi, and more will appear in Sanskrit, Hindi, and Tamil. This dharma certainly means religion in one sense, but in one sense only. It means law, and a law-book therefore is called Dharma-sastra. The same word dharma may be used to express dogma or objective religion, but it cannot include the subjective disposi- tion which we likewise comprehend under the name of religion. In the Rig-veda dharma, law, does not yet occur, EXAMINATION OF DEFINITIONS. 95 but only the other form dharman. With the accent on the first syllable dharman means one who holds and upholds; with the accent on the last, dharma1 means support, fid-cram ; then law and order, what holds things as they are and as they ought to be. The gods are looked upon as the givers and guardians of these d harm as or laws. In later Sanskrit dharma has the same meaning of law, then of duty and virtue, that is, of law performed. Lastly, it has been used in the sense of the nature or essence of a thing, as we might say the law or character of a thing, the elbos. When Manu (II. 12) in his Law-book explains dharma, he represents it as consisting of the Veda (revelation), of Smriti (tradition), of Sada&ara (the behaviour of good people), and of what is dear to oneself, that is, what meets with the approval of our own con- science. It was with the Buddhists that dharma became more exclusively the name of the doctrines taught by Buddha, which contained all that was supposed necessary for salvation. The three great treasures of the Buddhists are Buddha, the Church (saiigha), and the Law (dharma) ; and when a man embraced Buddhism, he recited the formula, 'I take refuge with Buddha, with the Church, and with the Law, as preached by Buddha.' But through all these phases dharma always retains something of its etymological meanings. It is what holds us in the right path, and keeps us from what is wrong. It is the law that comes to us from without, not the law or the will, or whatever else we may call it, that comes from within. 1 Rv. V. 15, 2. 96 LECTURE IT. Veda. A Brahman, when speaking of his own religion, might use the word Veda. Veda means originally knowledge, but it has been restricted so as to signify exclusively what a Brahman considers as sacred and revealed knowledge. Instead of Veda we find in Sanskrit another curious word for revelation, namely, #ruti, which means hearing, from sru, to hear, the Greek k\v(*>. It is most carefully denned by Hindu theologians, so as to exclude all secular knowledge, and so as to comprehend such knowledge only as is received by direct inspiration from a divine source. Even the Laws of Manu, though invested with a sacred character, are not iSfruti, but only Smriti, which means remembering or tradition, not revelation ; so that whenever there should be a conflict between Smriti and £ruti, Snmti is at once overruled by &ruti. All these expressions, however, refer clearly to objective religion only, to a body of doctrines placed before us for acceptance or rejection. They do not render what we mean by subjective or inward religion, an idea that seemed quite strange, and proved therefore untranslatable, to my Hindu translators. Bhakti. There is, however, in later Sanskrit one expression which comes very near to what we mean by subjective religion, namely bhakti, devotion and faith. The verb bhat/, bhagrati, from which bhakti is derived, means first of all to divide, to distribute, to give. We read in the Rig-veda of the gods distri- buting gifts to men, and also of rich people giving presents to their friends and followers. The same EXAMINATION OF DEFINITIONS. 97 verb, however, particularly if used in the Atmanepada or the middle, takes also the meaning of giving some- thing to oneself, that is, choosing it for oneself, holding it, loving it. From meaning to choose, to love, hh&g took the more special meaning of loving, venerating, and worshipping a deity. Bhakta, the participle, thus came to mean a devoted worshipper, and bhakti faith, devotion, and love. Bhakti, in the sense of loving devotion directed towards a certain deity, does not occur in the Vedic literature, except in some of the Upanishads. It gains more and more ground, however, in the Bhaga- vadgita, where it means the loving worship paid to Krishna,, and it then comes so near to the Christian conception of faith and ]ove that several Sanskrit scholars as well as missionaries have expressed their conviction that the idea of bhakti must have been borrowed by the Brahmans from Christianity l. It is strange that these scholars should not see that what is natural in one country is natural in another also. If fear, reverence, and worship of the Supreme God could become devotion and love with Semitic people, why not in India also ? Besides, we can see in India the same development of thought as in Palestine. No doubt the gods are feared and reverenced in India, but they are also addressed as friends, and sentiments such as ' thou art like a father to a son,' are by no means unfrequent in the earliest portions of the Rig- vecla. We read in the very first hymn of the Rig- veda, ' Be easy of access to us, as a father to his son.' In the Upanishads, when the different gods of the See Die Bhagavctdgttd, iibersetzt und erliiutert von Dr. F. 98 LECTURE IV. Veda have been superseded by the Supreme Lord, the f.svara, the feelings of love and devotion are trans- ferred to him. And at a still later time, when Krishna, was worshipped as the manifestation of the Supreme Spirit, we see in the Bhagavadgita every expression that human love is capable of, lavished on him. I shall read you first an extract from the #veta- svatara Upanishad l : '1. Some wise men, being deluded, speak of Nature, and others of Time (as the cause of every- thing) ; but it is the greatness of God by which this Brahma- wheel (the world) is made to turn. 7. Let us know that highest great Lord of lords, the highest deity of deities, the master of masters, the highest above, as God, the Lord of the world, the adorable. 10. That only God who spontaneously covered himself, like a spider, with threads drawn from nature (pradhana, the chief cause), may he grant us entrance into Brahman. 11. He is the one God, hidden in all things, per- vading all,— the Self within all beings, watching over all works, dwelling in all beings, the witness, the perceiver, the only one, free from all qualities. 12. He is the one ruler of many who are above their acts2; he who makes the one seed manifold. The wise who perceive him within their self, to them belongs eternal happiness, not to others. 20. When man shall roll up the sky like a hide, then only will there be an end of misery, unless that God has first been known. 1 UpanishadSj translated by M. M., in Sacred Book* of (he East, xv. 260. 2 Nishkriva, without acts, i. e. not really active, but passive ; merely looking on while the organs perform their acts. EXAMINATION OF DEFINITIONS. 99 23. If these truths have been told to a high- minded man, who feels the highest devotion (bhakti) for God \ and as for God so for his Guru, then they will shine forth, then they will shine forth indeed.' Here then we have in the Upanishads the idea of bhakti or devotion clearly pronounced, and as no one has as yet ventured to put the date of the #vetasvatara 2 Upanishad later than the beginning of our era, it is clearly impossible to admit here the idea of early Christian influences. The date of the Bhagavadgita, in which KWstma L« represented as the Supreme Spirit, and loving devo- tion for him is demanded as the only means of salva- tion, is more doubtful 3. Still, even if, chronologically, Christian influences were possible at the time when that poem was finished, there is no necessity for ad- mitting them. I do not wonder at readers, unaccus- tomed to Oriental literature, being startled when they read in the Bhagavadgita IX. 29 : ' They who worship me (bha^anti) with devotion or love (bhaktya), they are in me and I in them (mayi te, teshu Mpy aham) V But such coincidences between the thoughts of the New Testament and the thoughts of Eastern sages, will meet us again and again, because human 1 Saudilya (Sutra 18) explains deva as a god, not as fsvara, the Lord. 2 Professor Weber in one of his earliest treatises (Indische Studies, i. 421 seq.) has indeed discovered in the name Svetasvatara, i.e. white mule, something that may remind us of a Syro-Christiaii Mission, but I doubt whether he would still like to be held respon- sible for such an opinion. With the same right Krishna might remind us of an Ethiopian missionary. 3 See the Bhagavadgita, translated by K. T. Telang, Sacred Books of the East, viii. 34, 1882. 4 St. John vi. 57 ; xvii. 23. H 1 100 LECTURE IV. nature is after all the same in all countries and at all times. A whole system of religious philosophy has been built up in later times, founded on the principle of bhakti or love, namely the Sutras of >S'a?ic?ilya \ who in his second Sutra explains bhakti as affection fixed on God. And at the present moment no system is more popular in Bengal than that of ifaitanya. ifaitanya was born in 1486, and he did much to popularize and humanize the old Brahmanic doctrines 2. With him bhakti or love became the foundation of every- thing, and different steps are laid down through which a worshipper may reach the highest perfection. The exoteric steps consist in discipline, (1) social discipline (svadharma&arar^a) ; (2) discipline of the intellect and a surrender of all to Krishna, (Kn'sh?ia- karmarpa?ia) ; (3) mendicity (svadharmatyaga) ; (4) philosophic culture (#;7anamkra bhakti) ; (5) simplicity of the heart (gwanasunyabhakti) ; and (6) dispassion (santabhava). Then follow the higher or esoteric steps, viz. loving devotion (preinabhakti), consisting in humility (dasya), friendship (sakhya), and tenderness (vatsalya) ; and, as the crowning step, sweetness and love (madhu- rabhava, kantabhava), represented by the highest and purest love between husband and wife. Bhakti, therefore, may be used as an equivalent of religion in the sense of devotion and love, but it is, comparatively speaking, a modern word in Sanskrit. 1 Edited by Ballantyne in the Bibliotheca Indica, 1861, and trans- lated by Prof. Cowell in the same collection, No. 409. 2 See Yogendra Chandra Ghosh, Chaitanyas Ethics, Calcutta, 18b4 ; A. de Grubernatis, Giornale della Societa Asiat. Italiana, 18S8. p. 116 ; and A'aitanya-A-androdaya, ed. Rajendralal Mitra, Bibl Indica. EXAMINATION OF DEFINITIONS. 101 Sraddha. faith. There is, however, a very ancient word for faith. It is a very important word, for while bhakti is a purely Indian concept, and even in India of later growth, sraddha, faith, is a very old word, and must have existed before the Aryan nations separated *. Think what that implies. We read in the Rig-veda I. 55, 5 : c When the fiery Indra hurls down the thunderbolt, then people believe in him.' Adha Arana srat dadhati tvishimate Indraya va^ram nighanighnate vadham. Here you have in one line the whole secret of natural religion. When people see the manifestation of power in the storm and lightning, then they believe in Indra. It is not said that they perceive Indra, or that they find out by reasoning that there must be a god, called Indra : no, they believe in him, they accept him, they do not doubt his existence. Or again, Rv. I. 102, 2 : ' Sun and moon move in regular succession, that we may have faith, 0 Indra.' Asme surya/randramase abhiAakshe Sraddhe kam indra ka.rsda.fi vitarturam. Here we have no longer faith in Indra or any par- ticular deity, but faith in general, and that faith is taken as the result of our seeing the regular rising and setting of sun and moon. Faith, therefore, is represented as reposing on terror produced by the overpowering convulsions of nature, and on trust, called forth by the discovery of law and order in nature. Few of the best living 1 Hibbert Lectures, p. 300. According to Sandilya (Sutra 24), bhakti is not identical with sraddha, because sraddha, belief, is merely subsidiary to ceremonial works ; but not so is faith in tsvara. 102 LECTURE IV. philosophers have anything better to say on the origin of faith. And now let us consider this word sraddha a little more closely. It is letter by letter the same as the Latin credo, and our creed. When the Brahmans said srad-dadhe, the Romans said credidi; when the Brahmans said sr add hit am, the Romans said ere- ditum. The two words are therefore clearly the same ; but if you ask me what sraddha meant etymologically, I can only say, We do not know. Professor Darmesteter derives it from srad, in the sense of heart, and dha, to place. Phonetically this etymology might be defended, though srad, by the side of hrid, the regular word for heart in Sanskrit, would be without analogy. But Professor Darmesteter has not con- sidered that srad occurs elsewhere by itself, and that there it cannot possibly mean heart. For instance, Rv. VIII. 75, 2, srat visva varya kWdhi, ' Make all our wishes true ! ' Here srad cannot possibly be taken as a dialectic form of hrid. How srat should come to mean true, and sraddha, to make true, to accept as true, we do not know. But this only shows how old a word sraddha really is, and how early in the history of the human mind the idea must have sprung up that we may accept as true what can neither be confirmed by our senses nor proved by our reasoning, but what is nevertheless irresistible. Here you see how we may discover embedded in the very deepest strata of language the germs of religion —for there can be no name for believing before the first rays of faith have dawned in the human heart. LECTURE V. MY OWN DEFINITION OF RELIGION. Former Definitions. TT7E have now examined the most important and T » most characteristic definitions of religion. We have seen how some of them looked chiefly to the practical character, others to the theoretic character of religion, while some philosophers, such as Schleier- macher, would recognise the true essence of religion neither in its practical nor in its theoretic manifesta- tions, but only in a complete change of our nature, in a loving devotion to and almost union with the Supreme Being. Do not suppose that I look upon all these defini- tions as wrong, or that I intend to criticise them one by one. On the contrary, I believe that most of them con- tain some truth, some very important truth, but they all seem to me to be vulnerable in one and the same point, namely in taking the object of religious thought for granted and therefore leaving it undefined. This may be defensible, if in defining religion we only think of our own, or of the religion of the present age. But if the historical school has proved anything, it has established the fact, to which I alluded at the end of my last lecture, that in religion as in language there is continuity, there is an unbroken chain which 104 LECTURE V. connects our thoughts and our words with the first thoughts conceived and with the first words uttered by the earliest ancestors of our race. A definition of religion ought therefore to be applicable, not only to what religion is now, but to what religion was in its origin, and in its earliest developments. Keligion may change, and it has changed, as we know ; but however much it may change, it can never break entirely with its past, it can never be severed from its deepest roots, and it is in these deepest roots that we ought to seek, as it seems to me, the true essence of religion. But it is not only religion in its origin which the ordinary definitions would fail to comprehend. There are several of the historical developments of religion also which could hardly be brought within their gage. Is Buddhism a religion? If you tried, for instance, to bring Buddhism within the compass of any of the definitions hitherto exam- ined, you would find it impossible to do so, and yet, as you know, the largest number of human beings have trusted to Buddha's teaching as their only means of salvation. Those who define religion as a theory, as a mode of knowledge, must necessarily, as I pointed out before, supply an object that is to be known, whether they call it gods or god, the father, the creator, the Supreme Being, or the Supreme Will. Buddhism, as theoretical, not incliided under any definition. But in Buddhism — I mean in Southern Buddhism, which ought to be carefully distinguished from Northern Buddhism or Bodhism — there is no mention of God as a creator or ruler of the world1; on the 1 See the account of Brahman as a Creator in Selected Essays, ii. 297. MY OWN DEFINITION. 105 contrary, a belief in creation is condemned, if not as heresy, at all events as a conceit highly reprimanded by Buddha himself. Gods or Devas are mentioned indeed, but only as subordinate, legendary beings, accepted as part of the traditional phraseology of the times. From a kind of compassion they seem to have been accommodated with a new position as servants and worshippers of the Buddha. Several of the great questions of religion, besides that of the existence of a Deity or Creator, are banished once for all from the discussions, nay from the thoughts of orthodox Bud- dhists. Some of Buddha's own disciples are introduced as blaming the master for not enlightening them on such questions as whether the world is eternal or had a beginning, whether Buddha and those who, like him, have arrived at perfect knowledge, will live after death or not? Whether the living soul is identical with the body or not ? Malunkya-putta and Buddha. After Malunkya-putta had expostulated with Buddha for leaving his disciples in uncertainty on such im- portant points, Buddha answers1 : How did I speak to thee formerly, Malunkya- putta ? Did I say : Come, and be my disciple, and I will teach thee whether the world is eternal or not, whether the world is finite or infinite, whether the living principle is identical with the body or different from it, whether the perfect man lives after death or does not, whether he lives and does not live at the 1 Mr. Rhys Davids, in his translation of the Milinda-pariha (i. 199), calls him the son of the Malunkya woman (Malunkyfi-putta). but he mentions Malunka as a various reading. Professor Oldenberg (Buddha. p. 231") gives the name as Malukya-putta, or simply Malukya. 106 LECTURE V. same time, or whether he neither lives nor does not live. Malunkya-putta replied: Master, you did not say so. Then Buddha continued : Then, did you say to me, I will become thy disciple, but answer me all these questions ? Malunkya-putta confesses that he did not. After that Buddha proceeds : A man was once wounded by a poisoned arrow. His friends and rela- tions called in an experienced physician. What, if the wounded person had said, I shall not allow my wound to be treated till I know who the man is by whom I was wounded, whether he is a nobleman, or a Brahmawa, or a Vaisya, or a #udra. Or what, if he said, I shall not allow my wound to be treated till I know how the man is called by whom I was wounded, to what family he belongs, whether he is tall or short or of middle stature, and what the weapon was like by which I was wounded. What would be the end of it ? The man surely would die of his wound. Buddha then lets Malunkya-putta see that when he came to him he was like the wounded man who wished to be healed, and he finishes his lesson by saying : Let what has not been revealed by me re- main unrevealed, and let what has been revealed by me remain revealed. It was natural that the opponents of the Buddhists should make this reticence of Buddha on points of the highest importance a ground of attack. We find the question fully discussed, for instance, in the Mi- linda-panha1, a theological and philosophical dialogue 1 Translated by Mr. Rhys Davids in the Sacred Books of the East. MY OWN DEFINITION. 107 in which the Yavana King, Milinda (Menandros, about 100 B. a), exchanges his views on Buddhism with Nagasena. Here the King says : 'Venerable Nagasena, it was said by the Blessed One : " In respect of the truths, Ananda, the Tatha- gata has no such thing as the closed fist of a teacher who keeps something back." But on the other hand, he made no reply to the question put by the son of the Malunkya woman. This problem, Nagasena, will be one of two ends, on one of which it must rest, for he must have refrained from answering either out of ignorance, or out of wish to conceal something. If the first statement be true, it must have been out of ignorance. Bat if he knew, and still did not reply, then the first statement must be false. This too is a doubled-pointed dilemma. It is now put to you, and you have to solve it. ' The Blessed One, O king, made that first statement to Ananda, and he did not reply to Malunkya-putta's question. But that was neither out of ignorance, nor for the sake of concealing anything. There are four kinds of ways in which a problem may be explained. And which are the four? There is the problem to which an explanation can be given that shall be direct and final. There is the problem which can be answered by going into details. There is the problem which can be answered by asking another. And there is the problem which can be put on one side. ' And which is the problem which can be put on one side ? It is such as this — " Is the universe ever- lasting ? " " Is it not everlasting ? " " Has it an end?" "Has it no end?" "Is it both endless and unending ? " " Is it neither the one nor the other ? " 108 LECTURE V. "Are the soul and the body the same thing?" "Is the soul distinct from the body?" "Does a Tatha- gata exist after death?" "Does he not exist after death?" " Does he both exist and not exist after death ? " " Does he neither exist nor not exist after death ? " ; Now it was on such a question, that ought to be put on one side, that the Blessed One gave no reply to Malunkya-putta. And why ought such a question to be put on one side ? Because there is no reason or object for answering it. That is why it should be put aside. For the Blessed Buddhas lift not up their voice without a reason and without an object. ' Very good, Nagasena. Thus is it, and I accept it as you say.' Buddha does not imply that he could not have answered these questions or revealed these mysteries, if he had chosen. He professes the same philosophical abstinence, or e^ox?/, or agnosticism, as it is now called, as Socrates, and he utters the strongest con- demnation of those of his disciples who ventured to give either a positive or a negative answer. Yamaka, on Life after Death. Thus one of them, called Yamaka, taught openly that a monk, if free from sin, would cease to exist after death. But for this he was found guilty of heresy, and had to be converted to the true view, namely to abstain from expressing any opinion on a subject which is beyond our knowledge l. Dialogue between the King of Kosala and the nun Khema. The question whether the Buddha himself, the 1 Oldenberg, Buddha, p. 237- MY OWN DEFINITION. 109 founder of what we call Buddhism, continued to exist after death was naturally a question of a more than purely speculative interest. It touched the hearts of his disciples, and there must have been the strongest inclination on their part to answer it in the affirma- tive. The Northern Buddhists admit the existence of Buddha and of all Buddhas after the end of their earthly career. But the Southern Buddhists abstain. Thus in a dialogue between Pasenadi, the King of Kosala, and the nun Khema, the King is introduced as asking the question again and again, whether Buddha exists after death, or, as we should say, whether the founder of that religion enjoyed eternal life. But the nun is immovable. She simply repeats the old answer : ' The perfect Buddha has not revealed it.' And when questioned further, why the perfect Buddha should have left so momentous a question unanswered, she says ] : 0 great King, have you an arithmetician or a master of the mint or an accountant who could count the grains of sand of the Ganges, and could say, there are there so many grains, so many hundreds, so many thousands, or so many hundreds of thousands of grains ? The King replied, I have not, 0 reverend lady. Or have you, O great King, the nun continued, an arithmetician, a master of the mint, or an accountant who could measure the water in the great ocean, and could say, there are there so many pints of water, so many hundreds, so many thousands, or so many hundreds of thousands of pints 1 The King replied, I have not, O reverend lady. 1 Oldenberg, Buddha, p. 284. HO LECTURE V. And why not 1 she said. The great ocean is deep, immeasurable, unfathomable. And in the same man- ner, O King, if one tried to conceive the nature of the perfect Buddha by the predicates of corporeity, these predicates would be impossible in the perfect Buddha, their very root would be annihilated, they would be cut down, like a palm-tree, and removed, so that they could never rise again. The perfect Buddha, O King, is released from having his nature to be counted by the numbers of the corporeal world ; he is deep, im- measurable, unfathomable, like the great ocean. To say that the perfect Buddha is beyond death, is wrong ; to say that he is not beyond death is wrong likewise ; to say that he is at the same time beyond and not be- yond, is wrong ; and to say that he is neither beyond nor not beyond 1 is wrong again. With this answer the King must be satisfied, and millions of human beings who call themselves Bud- dhists have had to be satisfied. They have no God, no creator or ruler whom they could know, there is no modus cognoscendi et colendi Deum for them ; and yet who would say that they have no religion 1 Buddhism, as practical, not included under any definition. And so again, if we tried to apply to Buddhism those definitions which see in religion not so much a theory as a practice, which, for instance, as Kant's definition, explain it as a recognition of all our duties as divine commands, how would Buddhism then be brought in ? The Doctrine of Karma. The essence of Buddhist morality is a belief in 1 W eva hoti na na hoti tathagato param maia/ia 'ti pi na upeti. MY OWN DEFINITION. HI Karma, that is, of work done in this or in a former life, which must go on producing effects till the last penny is paid. The same thought pervades much of the Brahmanic literature, and it is still one of the most familiar ideas among the Hindus of the present day. We find the first traces of this belief in Karma in the Upanishads. Thus we read in the Brihadarau- yaka 1 III. 2, 1 : ' Y%»avalkya,' said Garatkarava Artabhaga, ' when the speech of a dead person enters into the fire, breath into the air, the eye into the sun, the mind into the moon, the hearing into space, into the earth the body, into the ether the self, into the shrubs the hairs of the body, into the trees the hairs of the head, when the blood and the seed are deposited in the water, where is then that person V Y%>7avalkya said : 'Take my hand, my friend. We two alone shall know of this ; let this question of ours not be (discussed) in public.' Then the two went out and argued, and what they said was Karma, work, and what they praised was Karma, work, namely that a man becomes good by good work, and bad by bad work. And after that (raratkarava Artabhaga held his peace. Among the Buddhists, however, the belief in Karma took a most prominent place. In the very first verse of the Dhammapada 2, we read : 'All that we are is the result of what we have thought : it is founded on our thoughts, it is made up of our thoughts. If a man speaks or acts with an evil 1 Sacred Books of the East, xv. 126. 3 Sacred Books of th< East, x. 3. 112 LECTURE V. thought, pain follows him, as the wheel follows the foot of the ox that draws the carriage.' And again, verse 127: ' Not in the sky, not in the midst of the sea, nor if we enter into the clefts of the mountains, is there known a spot in the whole world where a man might be freed from an evil deed.' There can be no doubt that this faith has produced very beneficial results, and that it would explain many things which to us remain the riddles of life — but is it religion 1 While to us the inequalities with which men are born into the world seem often unjust, they can be justified at once by adopting the doctrine of Karma. We are born as what we deserved to be born 2, we are paying our penalty or are receiving our reward in this life for former acts. This makes the sufferer more patient, for he feels that he is wiping out an old debt, while the happy man knows that he is living on the interest of his capital of good works, and that he must try to lay by more capital for a future life. It may be said that in the absence of all proof of such a theory, and with the total extinction of any recollection of our former good or evil deeds, very little practical effect could be expected from this assumption. But this is not the case, for the assumption has become a belief, as strong as any belief in a religious dogma. Besides, though it cannot be proved, it helps to explain many difficulties, and this gives it a strong hold on man's convictions. The Buddhist trusting in Karma 1 ' My possessions are my Karma, my inheritance is my Karma, my mother's womb is my Karma,' etc. ; see Oldenberg, Buddha, p. 248, quotation from the Anguttara Nikaya, Pa?7Aaka Nipata. MY OWN DEFINITION. 113 can honestly say, Whatever is, is right, and the same belief which makes him see in what he now suffers and enjoys the natural outcome of his former works, will support him in trying to avoid evil and to do good for its own sake, knowing that whatever may befall in this life, no good and no evil word, thought, or deed, can ever be lost in the life of the uni- verse. Of course, like every honest belief, this belief in Karma too may degenerate into superstition. I read not long ago in a Ceylon paper, that when an Eng- lish judge condemned a Buddhist to death, the cul- prit said quietly : ' Thank you, my lord, you also will die.' He then went on to threaten the judge. ' You will become a bullock in your next life,' he said, ' and I shall then be a driver, and I'll drive you up the Kadujanava Pass,'— one of the steepest of the steep paths of Ceylon. While Christian teachers comfort the afflicted by telling them that all injustice in this life will be remedied in the next, that Lazarus will be in Abraham's bosom and the rich man in torments, Buddha teaches those who seem to suffer unjustly in this life that they have deserved their punishment by their former deeds, that they must be grateful to pay off their old debts, and that they should try to lay in a store of good works for the time to come. While ordinary mortals must be satisfied with this general belief, Buddha himself and those who have reached a high stage of enlightenment, are supposed to possess the power of remembering their former states of existence ; and many of the most touching legends in the Buddhist canon are the recollections of his 114 LECTURE V. former existences by Buddha himself, the so-called Gatakas. All this is most excellent, and, I believe, has proved most extensively useful ; but when we are asked whether it could be accommodated under any of the definitions of religion which we have passed in review, we have to answer that it cannot. Let us then attempt our own definition. My own definition of Religion. A definition, as logicians tell us, ought to begin with the summum genus, to which what we have to define belongs, and should then proceed to narrow the sphere of the summum genus by those differences which distinguish our object from all other objects belonging to the same genus. Religion an Experience. I well remember Professor Weisse, the Hegelian Professor at Leipzig, beginning his lectures on the Philosophy of Religion, by telling us that religion was, first of all, an experience. To many of his hearers this seemed at the time a mere truism, but one comes to learn that some truisms are not only true, but also very important. Unless religion can be proved to be an experience, in the ordinary sense of that word, and as sharing the essential qualities of all other experience, it will always lack the solid foundation on which all our knowledge rests. Religion, if it is to hold its place as a legitimate element of our consciousness, must, like all other knowledge, begin with sensuous experi- ence. If that foundation is wanting, there can be MY OWN DEFINITION. 115 neither natural nor supernatural religion, for the supernatural is not what is unnatural, but what is superimposed on the natural. In that sense I hold as strongly as ever, and in spite of all the false interpre- tations that have been put on it, that Nihil est in fide quod non ante fuerit in sensu. In order to explain my meaning more clearly, it will be necessary to show in greater detail, of what all our experience, all our states of consciousness, all our Ego- knowledge really consists, and how even our highest aspirations have their roots in the universal soil of sensuous experience. Our experience consists of sensations, percepts, concepts, and names. All that we have or know consists of sensations, percepts, concepts, and names. But though these four phases of knowledge may be distinguished, they can- not be separated as entirely independent functions of our mind. They form parts of one whole, members of one living organism. In the actual work of thought, as carried on by educated men, we deal with names as the embodiments of concepts, we deal with concepts as the result of percepts, and we deal with percepts as the residue of sensations. The process which changes sensations into percepts, and percepts into concepts and names belongs to the very earliest age in the history of the human mind. In learning our language we enter at once on an inheritance which has been amassed by our predecessors during thou- sands of years, and to which we ourselves may add something, but very little in comparison with what we receive ready-made. It has been argued thnt even with us sensations may exist by themselves, I 2 116 LECTURE V. as when we feel a blow, taste what is bitter, smell what is nauseous, see what is dark, hear what is loud. They exist, no doubt ; but as soon as we become conscious of them, know them, think them, they are more than sensations ; they have become percepts, concepts, and names. From the very expressions which we use for these sensations, it is clear that as soon as we not only suffer a dumb pain, but are becoming conscious of it, we have raised the momen- tary feeling into a permanent image, into something that causes what we call the percept of a blow, — of something that bites, and is therefore called bitter, or of something that is like sea-sickness, and is there- fore called nauseous, or of something like the night, and is therefore called dark, or of something like a shout, and is therefore called loud. However, let it be granted that, like dumb animals, we may stare at the blue sky or the green forest, without knowing anything about blue or green or colour ; even then that state of receptive passiveness should at all events not be called thought, but have its own distinctive name. Real thought (anta/dvarana, inward-doing) begins when we leave that merely passive stage of staring or dreaming, when we do what no one can do for us, namely, combine the percepts of sensations into concepts by discovering something they share in common, and embody that common property in a sign or a name. Sensation and perception inexplicable. This process of conceiving and naming, or naming and conceiving, though it leads on to the most mar- vellous results, is in itself extremely simple and per- MY OWN DEFINITION. 117 fectly intelligible, whereas the previous process, that of feeling and perceiving, is not only mysterious, but altogether beyond our powers of comprehension. Formerly people took the very opposite view. It was supposed that sensation and perception were so simple and natural as to require no philosophical ex- planation at all, while understanding and reason and all the rest were looked upon as powers so mysterious that, like language, they could only be explained as divine gifts. All this is changed now. All that is done by ourselves, call it conception or naming or adding and subtracting, our understanding, our reason, our language, our intellect, all this we can account for ; and though we may make occasional mistakes in un- ravelling the network of language and reason, true philosophy does not and need not despair of disen- tangling in the end the threads with which we our- selves or our forefathers have woven the woof and warp of our thoughts. But the problem of sensation we must leave to be dealt with by other hands. We accept the discoveries of physical science. We believe that what is meant by seeing is really an ethereal tremor striking the retina and conveyed by the optic nerve to specialised cells of cerebral tissue. But how that tremor becomes a sensation of light, or to put it into more technical language, ' how * the excitation from the peripheral end of the afferent nerve reaches its termination in the sensifacient sen- sorium,' passes all understanding. Touch, odour, taste, colour, and sound are our sensations. We know them, and grow more perfect in our knowledge 1 What t\ Religion? by C. N.3 p. 54 ; quotation from Huxley's Science and Culture. 118 LECTURE V. of them from the first years of our childhood, till our organs of sense become blunted again by old age, fade away and perish by death. We also know that what causes these sensations are vibrations of some unknown medium which in the case of light has been called ether. But what relation there is between the effect, namely, our sensation of red, and the cause, namely, the 500 millions of millions of vibrations of ether in one second, neither philosophy nor physical science has yet been able to explain. We can only accept the fact, that vibration is translated into sen- sation, but how it is so translated will probably remain a mystery for ever. How strange, therefore, that these sensations, which are the most wonderful elements of our mind, should have been looked upon as common, as low and material, compared with our own workmanship, the concepts and names, through which we handle them. If anything deserves the name of a revelation, it is our sensations, what is, as even Kant says, given us , what we cannot produce ourselves, but must accept as coming from a power other than ourselves. If we ascribe these sensations to matter, what can justify us in looking down on matter as something inferior, or, as some philosophers and founders of religion have held, as something vile, nay, as the very work of the devil ? What should we be with- out what we call the material or objective world, which, though it has been blasphemed against as the work of the devil, has also been called the creation of God? We might exist without it, but all that we prize most highly, our knowledge, our science, our philosophy, our morality, our whole intellectual and MY OWN DEFINITION. 119 spiritual life would, without an objective material world, be a mere blank. What does even Kant say, he who was so anxious to reestablish the claims of pure reason to her ancient possessions against the levelling tendencies of Locke and Hume : ' Concepts without intuitions are empty,' he says ; ' intuitions without concepts are blind 1,' that is to say, Without our senses our mind would be empty, without our mind our senses would be blind.' To compare and weigh mind against sense, to call the one sublime, the other low, would be absurd. The one is as necessary as the other; only while what the senses bring to us, whether you call it divine or diabolic or neither, is certainly beyond all human comprehension, what the mind makes of it is perfectly intelligible. The working of our mind. Let us look into the workshop of what we call our mind. What is brought ml Sensations, or some- thing which we feel. We may go a step further, and ask what is meant by sensation, and our answer would be that feeling in the highest sense is resisting. In the fight of all against all, or, as others call it, under the pressure of the universe, resistance produces what may be called vibration, a coming and going, a yielding and return- ing, according to the pressure which impinges upon us and is repelled by us. Our very existence has been called by Schopenhauer resistance or will. There are different kinds of pressure. Some may pass us without being even perceived, others may crush and almost annihilate us. Our first sensations 1 Science of Thought, p. 143. 120 LECTURE V. may be simply sensations of pain or pleasure, accord- ing as we have to resist the impacts made upon us with violent effort, or are able to acquiesce in them without any effort. But there are also many kinds of pressure which give neither pain nor pleasure, but which produce in us a rhythmic movement, a yielding at first and then a corresponding recovery, a kind of swing-swang, which we call vibration, and which, in a sensuous and self-conscious being, is sensation in the widest sense of the word, though not yet percep- tion. We may stare at the blue sky, the green forest, the red flowers ; we may watch the flight of the clouds and listen to the song of birds ; or we may be startled by a clap of thunder, frightened by a flash of light- ning, and driven away by the terror of falling trees. We may be in a state of perturbation or of rest, and we may act under the influence of what we thus see and hear. We may even be said to act rationally, just as a dog is said to act rationally when, on seeing his master raise his whip, he runs away. No percept without language. Helmholtz. But, though we may imagine such a state, and though I do not like to contradict collectors of psychological curiosities who maintain they have actually experienced it, I hold myself as strongly as ever that not until we have a name and concept of sky, can we truly be said to see the sky ; not till we have a name for blue, do we know that the sky is blue. Philosophers have long known this, but the best students of physical science also, some of the highest authorities on optics and acoustics, have at last come to see the same. ' Only after the per- MY OWN DEFINITION. 121 ceptions of the senses have become fixed by language, are they, (the senses), that is to say. are we brought to a conscious possession and a real understanding of them V These are not the speculations of a meta- physician or of a student of language, they are the ipsissima verba of one who stands foremost among experimental philosophers, and who in England as well as in Germany is recognised as one of the high- est authorities on optics and acoustics, that is, on the sensuous perceptions of sight and hearing — they are quoted from Professor Helmholtz. Perceptions always finite. Let us now consider the general character of our percepts. There is one characteristic which is com- mon to all of them, and therefore to all our concepts and names, — to all we know, — they are always finite in themselves ; or, if you like, the objects to which they refer are taken as finite. Some critics have objected to the term finite, and maintained that I ought to have used definite instead. Finite and definite. I see no objection whatever to using definite instead of finite ; my only reason for preferring finite was that it seemed to me wider than definite, wdrich is fre- quently used in the restricted sense of what has been defined by logical terms. The important point, how- ever, is not the name, so long as we see clearly that all objects which we perceive and afterwards conceive and name must be circumscribed, must have been separated from their surroundings, must be measur- 1 Science of Thought, p. 151. 122 LECTURE V. able, and can thus only become perceivable and knowable and namable. And this applies not only to finiteness in space and time, but also to finiteness in quality. We know now that all shades of colour, even those which our unassisted eye cannot distinguish, are clue to so mauy and no more vibrations of ether within a given time. They are therefore finite in their very nature. The same applies to every tone which we hear. It con- sists of a finite or definite, i. e. a limited, or count- able number of vibrations in a second. And as our perceptions of material objects, such as stones or trees or animals, must be outlined, must have a beginning and an end, our concepts and names also are possible only with well denned groups, or, at all events, with groups that ought to be well defined, if they are to answer their purpose. It is for this reason that con- cepts can be represented, as they have been by Euler and others, by spheres of greater or smaller extent, the definition determining the extension of a concept as a circumference determines the extension of a sphere. The finite implies the infinite. But if finiteness is thus a necessary characteristic of our ordinary knowledge, it requires but little re- flection to perceive that limitation or finiteness, in whatever sense we use it, always implies a something beyond. We are told that our mind is so constituted, whether it is our fault or not, that we cannot conceive an absolute limit. Beyond every limit we must always take it for granted that there is something else. But what is the reason of this ? The reason why we can- MY OWN DEFINITION. 123 not conceive an absolute limit is because we never perceive an absolute limit ; or, in other words, because in perceiving the finite we always perceive the infi- nite also. Descartes, who has so often been called the founder of modern philosophy, declares without any hesitation : ' I ought not to think that I perceive the infinite only by the negation of the finite, as I per- ceive rest and darkness by negation of motion and light ; on the contrary, I clearly ^>e?'ceive that there is more of reality in infinite substance than in finite, and therefore that, in a certain sense, the idea of the infinite is prior to me to the finite.' The infinite in space. I do not go quite so far as Descartes, but it seems to me beyond the reach of doubt, that even in our earliest and simplest perceptions we always perceive the finite and the infinite simultaneously, though it takes a long time before we clearly conceive and name the two as simply finite and infinite. If we perceive a square we can only perceive it by per- ceiving at the same time the space beyond the square. If we perceive the horizon, we perceive at the same time that which hems in our senses from going be- yond the horizon. There is no limit which has not two sides, one turned towards us, the other turned towards what is beyond ; and it is that Beyond which from the earliest days has formed the only real foun- dation of all that we call transcendental in our per- ceptual as well as in our conceptual knowledge, though no doubt it has also been peopled with the manifold creations of our poetic imagination. To the early nations the West, the setting of the sun, 124 LECTURE V. was the extreme limit of the world— to the Buddhists the golden gate that opens to receive the setting sun in the West has become the Eastern gate of a more distant West, of Sukhavati, the land of bliss. The infinite in time. And what applies to space applies to time. As we cannot perceive and therefore conceive anything in space without a something beyond, we cannot per- ceive or conceive anything in time without a some- thing beyond, a before and an after. Here, too, imagination has stretched its view as far as language will carry it. The number of years by which Hindus and Buddhists have tried to measure the infinitude of time are simply appalling— yet beyond the giddy height and depth which they have reached, there always remained that eternal Beyond from which no human mind can escape. The infinite as cause. Closely connected with the infinite, as it is postu- lated in space and time, is a third infinite, namely, that of cause. This has been called by some philoso- phers a mere illusion, a mere weakness of the human mind. There are some strong-minded philosophers who hold that a world is possible in which there is no cause and no effect, and in which two and two would not make four. But wherever that Erehivon may be, in our sublunary world, and I may add in our sublunary language, two and two will always make four, and as we can never shake off the chain of causality, we shall always be forced to admit not only a beyond beyond all beyonds, but also a cause beyond all causes. If therefore our ordinary sensations and perceptions MY OWN DEFINITION. 125 are at the same time both of the finite and of the infinite, they naturally call forth and leave in our mind and in our language the concept of finite, and at the same time the concept of infinite. I speak here of a logical and psychological necessity only ; and not yet of the realisation of these concepts of finite and infinite in history. Misunderstanding's , It is extraordinary how difficult it is to avoid mis- understandings even on the part of honest critics, to say nothing of dishonest opponents. In answer to what I tried to show, that every single perception, so far as it is finite, involves, whether we are conscious of it or not, some perception of the infinite — which is really only a freer rendering of the old scholastic formula, (minis detevminatio est negatio, I am told that there are many savage tribes even now who do not possess a word for finite and infinite. Is that an answer ? Savages without words for finite and infinite. No one can doubt that the idea of the infinite, as a pure abstraction, is one of the latest, and that when we trace religion back to a perception of the infinite in nature or in man, we can mean no more than that the infinite, as hidden in the finite, left some impres- sion on our senses and on our mind from the very first dawn of human intelligence, and that it is that very impression which, after passing through a long hiber- nation, grows and grows, and bursts forth at the very last, like the butterfly from the chrysalis, as the infinite in its most general, most abstract, most purified sense. It is very easy to be positive about the languages of 126 LECTURE V. ancient savages, for we know so little about them. But supposing that languages spoken by ancient savages were known in which no words occur for the boundless sky or the shoreless sea, this would not in the least affect our position. On the contrary, the more savage tribes can be produced without names and concepts for what is endless, deathless, or infinite, the stronger the proof that these concepts were only gradually evolved out of percepts in which they were contained, but from which they had not yet been separated. The Duke of Argyll's Definition of Religion. I must try to define my position as clearly as pos- sible. I hold that the only justification for a belief in a Beyond of any kind whatever, lies in the original perception of something infinite which is involved in a large class of our ordinary sensuous and finite per- ceptions. But I hold equally strongly that this perception of a Beyond remained undeveloped for a long time, that it assumed its first form in the num- berless names of what we call deities, till at last it threw off its husk and disclosed the ripe grain, namely the name and concept of a Beyond, of an Infinite, or, in the highest sense, of a Supreme Being. Here is the point where I differ, for instance, from the Duke of Argyll. In his great work, The Unity of Nature, the Duke arrives at the conclusion that re- ligion begins with ' a belief in supernatural beings, in living agencies, other and higher than our own ' (p. 466), and he maintains that ' to conceive of the energies that are outside of man as like the energies that he feels within him, is simply to think of the un- MY OWN DEFINITION. 127 known in terms of the familiar and the known.' ' To think this,' he writes, ' can never have been to man any matter of difficult attainment. It must have been, in the very nature of things, the earliest, the simplest, and the most necessary of all conceptions ' (p. 474). We shall see hereafter that this definition contains a great deal of truth. The reason why I cannot accept it is that it makes religion begin with concepts, and not with percepts, and it is with percepts that all our knowledge, even the most abstract, ought to begin. We cannot perceive supernatural beings, or living agencies, but we can perceive the sky, and in per- ceiving it as finite, perceive at the same time the necessary complement of the Infinite. There are many steps which must have preceded such concepts as £ energies without, being like the energies within us.' To conceive and name energies within us is a process unknown to the large majority of mankind even at the present day, and to think of energies without as like the energies within, is very different from seeing the sky or the fire, and conceiving and naming such beings as Dyaus or Zeus, as Indra or Agni, The Duke speaks of a belief in superhuman beings, and considers such concepts as a being and a superhuman being as very early and very simple. But the very verb to be is a very late creation, and the noun being much later still. Even Cicero looked still in vain for such a word as ens or essentia 1. It is, on the contrary, one of the most interesting sub- jects for the historian of religion to see how the more abstract concept of superhuman beings was slowly evolved out of such concrete and full concepts as Dya us, ' Seneca, Epist. 58. 128 LECTUKE V. sky, A'gni, fire, Vdyu, wind, Surya, sun. Instead of the more general concept coming first and being gradually invested with differentiating attributes, history shows that the differentiated and almost dra- matic characters came first, and, by being divested of their various attributes, left behind them the more general, but, at the same time, more exalted concepts of beings or superhuman beings. There is no trace whatever, so far as I know, of any of the early nations having first elaborated the concepts and names of superhuman beings, and then having connected them with various attributes. Among most nations also, so far as historical evidence enables us to judge, a belief in many superhuman beings preceded a belief in one superhuman being, and for a long time what seem to us two contradictory beliefs, a belief in one and a belief in many gods, were held to be perfectly compatible in the same religion. The Duke of Argyll, unless his own words misrepresent him, represents the connection of these superhuman beings with material objects as a later phase. ' The nature of that connec- tion,' he writes, ' may not be always, it may not even in any case, be perfectly clear and definite. Some- times the material object is an embodiment, sometimes it is a symbol, often it may be only an abode. Nor is it wonderful that there should be a like variety in the particular objects which have come to be so regarded. Sometimes they are such material objects as the heavenly bodies. Sometimes they are natural pro- ductions of our own planet, such as particular trees, or particular animals, or particular things in them- selves inanimate, such as springs, or streams, or moun- tains. Sometimes they are manufactured articles, MY OWN DEFINITION. 129 stones or blocks of wood, cut into some shape which have a meaning either obvious or traditional ' (p. 480). There are manifestly two ways only in which the truth of such statements can be tested. We have to ask whether they rest on historical facts or on any logical necessity. Tevtium non datur. Now, I can see no logical necessity for admitting even the possi- bility of any concepts which are not founded on previous percepts. On the contrary, if only we define these terms properly, the existence of concepts with- out previous percepts would become self-contradictory. And as to facts, I have no hesitation in saying that, so far as our knowledge of ancient religions reaches at present, they do not support the opinion that religion began anywhere with the general concept of super- human beings, and that at a later time only these mere beings were connected with differentiating qualities. Logically, no doubt, the general comes first, and the particular follows ; but what is first by itself is not first to us, and in the growth of concepts the historical process is generally the reverse of the logical. I hold that before man could speak even of the infinite sky or Dyaus, he must actually have per- ceived something infinite, and must have been brought in sensuous contact with something not finite like everything else ; but to conceive an infinite being, or even a number of infinite beings, is a very different process, which comes in earlier, it is true, than we expected, but still much later than the naming and conceiving of the infinite sky, the infinite earth, the infinite sea. While the Duke considers that religious thought began with the conception of superhuman beings, and 130 LECTURE V. that these were afterwards connected with dis- tinguishing mythological attributes, it seems to me that we must learn the very opposite lesson from history, namely that religious thought began with the naming of a large number of clearly marked and differentiated beings, such as Sky, Dawn, Thunder, Lightning, Storm, Mountains, Trees, etc., and that the concept of superhuman beings arose afterwards, as a concept common to all, when divested of their characteristic differences. In the Veda we look in vain for words of so abstract a character as super- human beings or personal agencies. Even the words for gods in general, such as deva, bright, vasu, brilliant, asura, living, are still full of physical meaning in the more ancient hymns. We are confronted from the first with such strongly marked dramatic characters as Dyaus, the bright sky, Varuna, the dark sky, Marut, the storms, Agni, the fire, Us has, the dawn. We can understand the origin of these mythological characters, because in their material aspect at least, whatever may have been suspected behind them, they offered themselves to the eyes and ears of those who framed their names and believed in their existence. But mere superhuman beings, without definite attri- butes, never presented themselves to their senses, and could never, therefore, have found an entrance into their intellect. Dyaus in the Veda was originally a name of the sky, but of an active and subjective sky. The purely material characteristics of the sky are still there, faintly visible ; but they slowly vanish, and in the end there remains the name only, which coupled with pita, father, appears in the earliest Aryan prayers, as D y a u s h p i t a, Jujjiter, Heaven-father, and MY OWN DEFINITION. 131 in the end, even in the language of philosophers, as the Supreme Being. And what applies to the name of Dyaus, applies likewise to the names of other gods. They are names of material objects or phenomena of nature, though all of them with the background of the infinite behind them. They lose their individual character very gradually, and in the end only stand before us sublimised into superhuman beings or per- sonal agencies. The germ of the superhuman, or, as I like to call it by a more general name, of the in- finite element, was there from the first, but it was involved as yet in sensuous perception, not yet evolved in a conceptual name. Early Names of the Infinite. But though these conceptual names of superhuman beings and living agencies are clearly, from an historical point of vieAV, of later growth, it is true nevertheless that we meet with names for the Beyond or the Infinite in documents of great antiquity. I see, however, that some remarks of mine on the early occurrence of names for the Infinite, have caused some misapprehension, which I must try to remove. I expressed my surprise that such a name as Acliti should occur in the Rig-veda, for, so far as we know at present, Aditi is derived from the negative a and dita, bound, so that it seems to have expressed from the beginning an unbound, unbounded, or infinite being. But the Rig-veda, though it is the most ancient document of Aryan thought within our reach, contains relics of different ages, and even its most ancient relics are relics of Aryan thought only, and are separated by an immeasurable distance from what people are pleased to call the beginning of all things. k 2 132 LECTURE V. We can clearly see the linguistic and intellectual detritus on which the Veda rests, and though the occurrence of such words as Adit i will always remain startling, it can never be used to prove that the Vedic Rishis or their distant Aryan ancestors began life with a clear conception and definite name of the Infinite in the abstract. Mana. My remarks on Mana also have been supposed to mean something very different from what I intended. Mana1 is the name, not of any individual super- human being, but it is used, we are told, by most of the Pacific races, in the sense of a supernatural power, distinct from all physical powers, yet acting every- where in nature, and believed to be conciliated by prayers and sacrifices. If that name is spread over the whole Pacific, we are justified in supposing that it existed before the final separation of the Polynesian races, and such a date, however vague, may. when we deal with illiterate races, be called an early date. But this is very different from supposing that Mana was the most primitive concept of the whole Polynesian race, and that its whole religion and mythology were founded on it. The mythological and religious language of this race, so far from being what people call primitive or primordial, shows so many antecedents, so much that is already petrified, decayed, and unintelligible, that the Vedic language may be called primitive as compared with it. I never could share the opinion that the thoughts of savage races, simply because they are the thoughts 1 Hibbert Lectures, p. 55. MY OWN DEFINITION. 133 of savage races, carry us back into a more distant antiquity than the thoughts of civilised and literate nations. These so-called savages are, so far as we know, not a day older or younger on the surface of the earth than the present inhabitants of India, China, or even of England. They have probably passed through more changes and chances than our own ancestors, unless we assume that by some special providence they were kept stationary or preserved in spirits for the special benefit of future anthropologists. In the eyes of an historian, therefore, a word like Mana, though extremely curious and instructive, can claim no greater antiquity than the stratum of lan- guage in which it has been found. It may be an ancient survival, a mediaeval revival, or a modern imagination, but it cannot possibly be forced into an argument to prove that religion began anywhere with a belief in supernatural beings or living agencies, and not with a naming of the great phenomena of nature behind which such beings or agencies were suspected. Manito. The last word which I mentioned as a name for a supreme being without any physical attributes was Manito. This word, used by the Red Indians as a name of the Supreme Spirit, has been proved to mean originally no more than Beyond. Here, therefore, there seemed to be another proof that religion among savage people might begin with such abstract concepts as that of Beyond. The fact itself was so curious that I thought it right to point it out, though as we know the word Manito and its various dialectic forms in documents of the last century only, I never under- 134 LECTURE V. stood by what right it could possibly be transferred to the primitive periods of humanity. And here a very useful lesson has been read to anthropologists, in whose eyes every nineteenth- century savage becomes an antediluvian. For, according to the most recent researches, there seems to be little doubt that Manito was introduced in the last century only by Christian Missionaries as a name for the Supreme Being, and had never been used before in that sense by the Red Indians themselves l. 1 hope I have thus made it clear that in citing these names of the Infinite, whether in the Veda, or among the Pacific tribes, or among the Red Indians, I never intended to imply that they could have repre- sented under any circumstances the earliest phases of religious thought. The perception of the Infinite, which is the necessary foundation of all religious thought, is something quite different. It is the per- ception of the infinite within the finite, and hence, whenever these perceptions are raised to a conceptual level and named, the names of the finite remain and become imperceptibly the names of the Infinite. Does the Vedic Religion begin with Sacrifice? Let us now consider another objection. The per- ception of the Infinite, it has been said 2, can have nothing to do with the origin of religion, because the Vedic religion begins not with faith in infinite beings, but with sacrifice. These are bold statements. First of all, it should never be forgotten that the deities invoked in the 1 See Brinton, Myths of the New World, p. 53. 2 Gruppe, p. 221. MY OWN DEFINITION. 135 Veda must have existed long before the hymns which we possess were composed. Some of them exist in other Aryan languages and must therefore have been framed prior even to the Aryan separation. The origin of their names lies, therefore, far beyond the Vedic age, and if they were originally names of finite phenomena, conceived as infinite in the evolution of religious thought, whatever the Vedic hymns and Brahmatias might say to the contrary, would be of very little weight. But, secondly, what possible mean- ing can we connect with the statement that the Vedic religion begins with sacrifice ? When sacrifices come in, for whom are they meant? Surely for somebody, for beings who are the object of faith, for beings different from things we can touch or see, for infinite beings, if only in the sense that their life has no end, and that they are in that sense, immortal, endless, infinite. And what can be the meaning of such a sentence (p. 221) as this, that in the Veda ' the faithful knows that the lighting of the matutinal sacrificial fire drives away the demons of night, and supports the approaching sun-god in his fight against them. He has been taught by his ancestors that the sacrificial potion and the intoxicating Soma invigorate Indra for his fight with the dragon, and he sacrifices gladly, because he hates the night, which is full of dangers, and because he loves the break of day. For this reason, and not from a desire for the infinite, does he call the bright deities his friends and the sky his father. And when the faithful has performed his sacrificial rite, he expects that heaven will do his part, increase the cattle of the faithful, fertilise his fields and destroy his enemies. 136 LECTURE V. In this very finite sphere does the religion of those early days have its being.' If we dissolve these assertions into their constituent elements, we shall find that they have absolutely no bearing whatever on the question at issue. We wanted to know how the concept of any so-called gods or divine powers arose, of beings to whom at a later time sacrifices may be offered ; and we are told that the faithful knows that his sacrifice will support the sun-god in his fight against the demons of night ! (p. 276.) But here everything which we wish to account for is taken for granted. When people had arrived at the conception of a sun-god and of noc- turnal demons, the whole battle of the human intellect was won. But who ever told them of a sun-god, or, as we should say, what perceptions led them on to such a concept and such a name? Then again, whence came that idea that a sacrifice could invigorate the sun-god ? We are told that man learnt it from his ancestors. Yes, but we want to know how his ances- tors learnt it. We are really speaking of two totally different periods in the development of human thought. If man has once arrived at the idea of bright deities, we can understand why he should call them his friends ; but why did he call anything bright deities ? Then again, the idea that an intoxicating beverage like Soma, taken by the sacrifice!', should invigorate the god fighting against the dragon, is so late, so secondary, even in so late and so secondary a phase of religion as we see represented in the Veda, that it is difficult enough to discover all the missing links in the intellectual chain that led to it. But to suppose that religion could begin with Indra drinking Soma MY OWN DEFINITION. 137 offered at a sacrifice, is like supposing that the Aryan language could begin with French. And is it really a very finite sphere of thought, if people have actually brought themselves to believe, not only that there are bright gods in heaven, but that these gods in heaven can hear our prayers, and that, though unseen themselves, they are able to in- crease the cattle of the faithful and destroy their enemies? Where in all our finite experience is there any evidence for such thoughts, thoughts which become intelligible only by patient research, just as French words become intelligible only, if we trace them back through various phases to Latin, and from Latin to some Aryan root the meaning of which is sometimes so different that, without a knowledge of the inter- mediate links, we could never believe that the two had any organic relationship at all. Germs of the Infinite in the Veda. Any one who is able to understand the Veda, will find no difficulty in discovering the true germs of the infinite in the conception of what the Vedic poets call devas. It makes no difference whether we call those poets primitive or modern, savage or civilised, so long as we know what thoughts they were capable of. Now the thought of the infinite, in space and time at least, was certainly not beyond their grasp. When a Vedic poet, such as Vasish^Aa, stood on a high mountain in the land of tne Seven Rivers, as he called the Punjab, and let his eye travel across land and water as far as it could reach, had he not a per- ception of the infinite ? When a Greek hero, such as Odysseus, was tossed 138 LECTUKE V. about on the vast commotion of the waves, seeing no stars and no land anywhere, had he no perception of the infinite 1 And are we so different from them ? The Infinitely Great. When we ourselves. — savages as we are, according to Bacon, in spite of all our syllogisms 1, — have learnt to look upon the boundless earth with its boundless ocean, no longer as a stupendous mass, but as a small globe or globule, moving with other globes across the infinite firmament ; wrhen wider infinitudes than the infinite firmament open before us, and the sun, which was once so near and dear to us, becomes a fiery mass, the magnitude of which defies our power of imagina- tion ; when afterwards, the magnitude of the sun and its distance from us, which is expressed in millions of miles, dwindle down again into nothing as compared with the nearest star, which, we are told, lies twenty millions of millions of miles from our earth, so that a ray of light, if travelling with the velocity of 187,000 miles in a second, would take more than three years in reaching us ; — nay even this is not yet all, — when we are assured by high astronomical authorities that there are more than one thousand millions of such stars which our telescopes have discovered, and that there may be millions of millions of suns within our sidereal system which are as yet beyond the reach of our best telescopes ; and that even that sidereal system need not be regarded as single within the universe, but that thousands of millions of sidereal systems may be recognised in the galaxy 2 — if we listen to all this, do we not feel the overwhelming pressure of the 1 See De Bonald, Mel i. 100. 'J See E. A. Proctor, in Secular Thought, April 21, 1888. MY OWN DEFINITION. 139 infinite, the same infinite which had impressed the mind of Vasish^Aa and Odysseus, and from which no one can escape who has eyes to see or ears to hear ? The Infinitely Small. But there is another infinite, the infinitely small, which is even more wonderful than the infinitely distant and great. When we turn away our eyes from the immensity which surrounds us, and look at one small drop of water taken from the boundless ocean, a new universe seems to open before us. There are in that drop of water atoms of atoms moving about, some visible, some invisible, some hardly imaginable. A high authority, Sir Henry Roscoe, has told us ' that the chemists are now able to ascer- tain the relative position of atoms so minute that millions upon millions of them can stand upon a needle's point.5 Is not that infinitude of atoms as wonderful as the infinitude of stars? Infinite Inseparable from Finite. I maintain then that the infinite is the necessary complement of the finite in every human mind, that it was involved in the first perceptions and became part of the silent clockwork within us, though it may have taken thousands of years before the necessity was felt to give it its final expression, as the Infinite, or the Unknown, or the Beyond. The Concept of Caixse. And it is the same with the idea of cause and causality. There may be ancient, there may be modern savages, who have no such word as cause. Does that prove that they had no other expression for that concept 1 When we now speak of the cause of the world, we could in the childhood of our thought and 140 LECTUKE V. language have said no more than ' the father or pro- genitor of heaven and earth,' r/anita dyavap?^thi- vyoA ; or, if our thought dwelt more on the forming and shaping of the world, the carpenter of heaven and earth, tvash^a (tUtlov) dyavapvuthivyoA. When afterwards it was felt to be less important to dwell on the act of begetting or shaping, when in fact it was felt desirable to drop these special features, human thought and language reduced the begetter and shaper to a mere maker or creator. And when those names also were felt to be too full of meaning, they were lightened once more till they conveyed no more than author, source, origin, principle, cause. This is the historical and genetic account of the concept of cause. It began with a real maker, like unto ourselves when we do a thing and see that it is done ; it ended with something that is neither human, nor divine, nor even real in the sense of perceptible by the senses — a mere cause. I hope that I have thus made it clear in what sense I consider the perception of the infinite to have, from the very beginning, formed an ingredient, or if you like, a necessary complement to all finite know- ledge 1. I am quite willing to admit that finite and infinite are not always quite adequate terms to express all that we want to express, and that I sometimes should prefer visible and invisible, known and un- known, definite and indefinite. But every one of these expressions proves even more inadequate in certain circumstances than finite and infinite, and if technical terms have once been properly defined, I do not see how they can be misunderstood. 1 This point has been carefully reasoned out by D. G. Thompson in his Religious Sentiments, London, 1888. LECTURE VI. THE INFINITE IN NATURE, IN MAN, AND IN THE SELF. Positivist Objections. WHEN it has been my chief endeavour to show that religion did not begin with abstract con- cepts and a belief in purely extra-mundane beings, but that its deepest roots can be traced back to the universal stratum of sensuous perception, it is some- what hard to be told that ' I must necessarily admit an extra-mundane Logos in man, and derive mytho- logy and religion from extra-mundane causes ' (Gruppe, p. 218). Still more extraordinary does it seem that the ground on which this charge is founded should be my holding in some modified form the opinion of Schleiermacher, Wuttke, Hellwald, and others, that ' the infinite can be known in the finite only, and that it should be known here always and everywhere.' Again, I am told (p. 222) that if I trace the concept of the infinite back to the most primitive percepts of not quite finite things, I must mean by the infinite ' a potentia of the infinite, the infinitely infinite, the infinite per se, the absolute.' If these words have any meaning at all, they would show a complete mis- apprehension of my position. I spoke of the sensuous pressure of the infinite which is contained in the simplest perceptions of our senses, while I represented the pure concept of the infinite, to say nothing of the absolute, as the very last result of a long historical 142 LECTURE VI. process of intellectual evolution. To fix the exact time when the indications of the infinite, which are latent in all sensuous perceptions, became recognised either in mythology or religion, and lastly in philo- sophy, is completely beyond our power. It is enough if we can show that the rudiments of later mytholo- gical, religious and philosophical expressions were present in what I call the early pressure of the infinite upon our senses. I do not object if, from another point of view, this may be called an intellectual pres- sure 1 also ; but what is really important is to under- stand that mankind did not begin with the abstract concepts of infinity, still less of the absolute, whatever that may mean, but with the simplest perceptions which, in addition to their finite contents, implied likewise something beyond the finite. The question, again, whether this evolution of thought, beginning with the simplest perceptions, and ending with the highest abstractions, was teleological or not — whether it was purposed, whether it was meant to lead us on to a higher conception of the world — does not concern us at present. It is enough for us that it was real, that it is strictly historical, and that it is at the same time intelligible. Whether it was meant or intended, by whom it was intended, and for what it was intended, these are questions which need not disturb our equanimity. So far as I can see, the evidence for and against a teleological interpretation is equally feeble, but, at all events it need not disquiet those who are only concerned with the establishment of facts, and with a suggestion of their possible origin. 1 ' Aber dieser Druck ist ein intellectueller.' Gruppe, p. 225. THE INFINITE IN NATURE, MAN, AND THE SELF. 143 Historical Evolution. My principal object has always been to discover an historical evolution or a continuous growth in religion as well as in language. It seems strange, therefore, that while in England some Darwinians, though not Darwin himself, have attacked me for not bein^ a thorough-going evolutionist, Professor Gruppe should try so very hard to prove that I am an evolutionist, and that therefore I am behind the time, as time is understood in certain quarters. Evolution, we are told (pp. 233, 235), is but the disguised sister of Hegelian speculation. We ought to be transforma- tionists, and no longer evolutionists. I do not know what transformations may still await us, but for the present I certainly am and mean to remain an evolu- tionist in the study of language, mythology, and reli- gion— that is to say, I shall always try to discover in them an intelligible historical growth. That I have not ascribed any evolutionary power to ideas or con- cepts by themselves, apart from the persons by whom they are held, and uninfluenced by the objective world by which they are determined, I need hardly attempt to prove, considering that I have always adopted as the foundation of all philosophy Kant's well-known principle, that concepts without intuitions are empty, intuitions without concepts are blind. There are misapprehensions against which it is difficult to de- fend oneself, because it seems incredible that they should ever have been raised. Positivist Point of View. Nor do I believe that Professor Gruppe or anybody else really thinks me capable of believing in self- evolving Hegelian ideas, floating about in metaphysical 144 LECTURE VI. air or blown into our face like soap bubbles by an extra-mundane Logos. On the contrary, he knows, and he says so himself, that my starting-point is from a positivist point of view impregnable1, and it is exactly this impregnable character of the position I have taken that has roused so much anger among positivist philosophers. But now comes the strangest of all arguments. The premisses from which I start are admitted to be impregnable, but as the facts in the history of religion are against them, it follows that after all, my premisses, positivist though they may be, must be wrong. It is generally supposed that when we come to facts, all controversy must end, but we shall see that facts as well as fictions require careful handling. Rig"-veda. I had taken some of my facts from the Rig-veda, not because I consider that these hymns can bring us near to the very cradle of religious concepts, but simply because we possess no literary documents, so far as I know, that can bring us nearer to it, at least on Aryan ground. I maintained that when the Vedic Rishis celebrated the rivers, the dawn, . the sky, or Indra, the god of the sky, they did not simply mean the objects which they saw, but also something be- yond, call it unknown, indefinite, infinite, or divine. Here I am flatly contradicted. ' The Hindu of the older Rig-veda/ we are told (p. 221), ' does not adore the Infinite which lies within or behind the dawn, but the dawn herself, whosoever that may be.' Yes, 'who- 1 G-ruppe, p. 222, ? vy\nfSpep.i'n}si Jupiter tonans. At a later time, when these answers seemed no longer satisfactory, new answers were attempted, and science explained lightning as a discharge of elec- tricity, thunder as a tension of the air, rain as the condensation of vapour. WThat had to be explained 1 Sayce, Hibbert Lectures, pp. 96, 156, 168 LECTURE VII. remained throughout the same; the difference arose from the new spirit of inquiry. We must not forget, however, that even in our own scientific age prayers are still offered for rain, that is to say, that the religious view of nature has held its own, if not against, at least by the side of the scientific view. And this will help us to mark off the domain of religion from that of science. Both deal with that which lies behind or beyond our knowledge, but while science looks for causes of events, whatever these causes may be, religion is satisfied with admitting agents for actions, who assume different aspects accord* ing to the poetical genius of every race. What imparts a Religious Character. But we must restrict the sphere of religion, so far as it is founded on perceptions of the infinite, still further. The mere admission that there in an agent behind the rain, the lightning, the thunder, behind night and day, behind sun and moon, is not yet religion. It may be called mythology throughout, but in some cases it is not even that. If we say the wind blows, we hardly speak mythologically, though, no doubt, a very small addition of poetical imagination may change the wind into an Aeolus, or, as in modern illustrated books, into an angel with wings, blowing a visible puff of air out of his mouth. That would be mythology, but not yet religion. In order to avoid all confusion of thought, we must reserve the adjective religious for those perceptions of the unknown or the infinite which influence man's actions and his whole moral nature. The mere reasoning, for instance, which would lead a sailor to RELIGION DIFFERENT FROM SCIENCE. 169 spread his sail so as to catch the wind blowing from the West, from the setting of the sun, would not yet constitute a religious act, even though the West- wind had been called Zephyrus \ and become known as the son of Eos and Astraeos. We should have entered the domain of mythology, but not yet that of religion. But when in the Iliad (xxiii. 192) the funeral pile with the corpse of Patroklos on it, does not burn, and Achilles prays to the two winds, Boreas and Zephyros, and promises them beautiful offerings (Upa kclXcl) if they will come and kindle the flames, we shall then have to admit that we are at least on the threshold of religion, though as yet on the threshold only. For though sacrifices are generally considered as religious acts, they are sometimes mere customs which in the beginning had little or nothing of religion about them. When, however, men begin to feel constrained to do what they do not like to do, or to abstain from what they would like to do, for the sake of some unknown powers which they have discovered behind the storm or the sky or the sun or the moon, then we are at last on religious ground. Moral Influences of Physical Phenomena. It has often been considered very strange that a mere perception of the powers of nature should have influenced the acts of men, or that even a belief in personal agents, as manifested in such phenomena as the rising and setting of the sun, the changes of day and night, of the seasons and of the year, or again in 1 See M. M., ' ZephjTOS und Gahusha,' in Techmer's Internationale Zeitschrift fur Allgemeine Sprachwissenschaft, 1 Band, 1 Heft, 1884. 170 LECTURE VII. storm and rain, in thunder and lightning, should have supplied motives for virtuous efforts. I am far from maintaining that natural phenomena by themselves would have sufficed to call out moral sentiments, ideas of right and wrong in man. This is a subject that belongs to the student in ethics, and on which I do not at present mean to touch. Thus Dr. Martineau writes in his Study of Religion, i. 16 : ' The enquiries on which we are now entering have been preceded by a treatment of ethical theory (in his work, The Types of Ethical Theory, 1885), the results of which will here be assumed as known. This order of exposition undoubtedly implies that I do not regard moral rules as depending upon prior religious belief • and that I do regard the consciousness of duty as an originating condition of religion.' Professor Flint also, in his works on Theism and Antitheistic Theories, re- gards ethics as quite independent of religion, though he admits the powerful influence which religion may exercise on morality. In his chapter on Secularism (p. 242) he goes so far as to say that morality which ignores religion is inherently weak because inherently self-contradictory. But when these sentiments had once been called forth, in however rudimentary a form, the contemplation of natural phenomena, whether in their unbroken order or in their violent disturbance, might well have reacted upon them and developed them in a new direction. It has often been said l that fear made the gods, but it is equally true to say that the gods, even in their purely physical character, made men fear. When man had once learnt to fear the gods of the sky in their terrible aspect, and to admire 1 ' Primus in orbe deos fecit timor,' Statius, Tfieb. iii. 661. RELIGION DIFFERENT FROM SCIENCE. 171 them in their beneficent character, what was more natural than that this relation between man and the gods should call out the same feelings of fear and awe, but also of respect and gratitude, which a child feels towards his parents. If a child could implore his father to spare him, or thank his mother for acts of kindness, why should not man have implored the father of the sky to restrain the storm, or thanked the mother Earth for her kindly gifts ? It is sometimes supposed that it was peculiar to the Aryan nations only to interpret the signs and wonders of nature in a religious sense. But it seems to me that the same spirit pervades all the pages of the Old Testament. Every deluge was accepted as a punish- ment, and the bow in the cloud was interpreted as a token of a covenant between God and man. In the Psalms the anger of the Lord is constantly perceived in the great commotions of the sky and the earth. ' The earth shook and trembled, the foundations also of the hills moved and were shaken, because He was wroth.' It is quite true that not every natural phenomenon, nor every god, would evoke such feelings of fear and awe. Hermes and Hephaestos, Venus and Mars were not likely at first to react on the moral character of those who believed in them and celebrated their achievements. But the gods of thunder and lightning, the god of rain and sunshine, as soon as they had been recognised, could hardly help being addressed by sup- plicants to grant them their favour and their pro- tection. You know the old prayer of the Athenians 1 : vcrov, vaov, ob cfiike Zeu, Kara TrjS apovpas tG>v ' kOiivaiuiv kcu 1 Lecf. S. L. ii. 476. 172 LECTURE VII. tQ>v ireblwv, ' Rain, rain, O dear Zeus, on the land of the Athenians and on the fields.' Here we might translate Zeus by sky, but the vocative $iAe Zev, dear Zeus, at once brings in the personal element. Vedic Prayers. In the Veda also we can see how a poet first appeals to the mighty works achieved by Indra, the god of storm and thunder and lightning, and asks people to believe in him ; and how he implores the same god not to hurt his children, because he believes in him. 'Look1 at this great and mighty work,' he says, ' and believe in the power of Indra.' And again : ' Do not hurt our nearest kin, O Indra, for we believe in thy great power.' When the gods have thus been invoked as powerful beings, able to injure man, but also willing to protect him, a mutual relation between gods and men is soon established, and people profess to do what is right in order to please the gods, and to avoid evil in order to escape their anger. Early Morality. This is the earliest morality founded on a belief in physical deities. It may not be a very exalted morality ; it is very much founded on the principle of Bo ut des. But it contained o-erms which might otow and improve till men could say, as Fichte said, that all ' moral action flows from the love of God gently and quickly, as light flows from the sun.' 1 Ilibbert Lectures, p. 307. RELIGION DIFFERENT FROM SCIENCE. 173 Moral Influence of Ancestral Spirits. That a belief in ancestral spirits might likewise influence human actions, requires hardly any proof. I believe it could be shown that the earliest ideas of right and wrong in a legal sense arose from that belief. It was the father who had laid down what should be done during his life-time, he being generally the stronger and the wiser man. And after his death, whenever doubts arose as to what was right and what was wrong to be done, an appeal to what the father had settled and laid down would often decide the question. Early law-books are very commonly ascribed to some distant ancestor, some Unkulunkulu, or, as in India, to Manu, the father of mankind, of whom it was said that ' whatever Manu declared, was medicine,' that is, was a remedy, and a prescrip- tion that ought to be followed by his children. Sir Henry Maine, in his work on Ancient Law (p. 125), has well explained how law was originally the parent's word, and how in Greece the so-called Oepicrres were the awards of judges, whether chiefs of families, of tribes, or of confederacies. They were not laws in our sense of the word, but dooms, de- cisions, and they were supposed to have a divine character and even a divine origin, because they were inspired by Justice, the daughter of Zeus, and only pronounced by the ancient judges. Sir Henry Maine has illustrated this first phase in the history of law by a comparison with Indian Law. Ancestral Law in China. Let me give you another illustration from China, taken from a recent work on China, its social, poli- tical and religious life, by M. Eug. Simon. M. Simon, 174 LECTURE VII. who has long lived in China, tells us that the whole social system in China is based on the Family Council and Tribunal. The incidents of the Family Council, he writes, which assembles at stated periods, are roughly as follows : 'The Father and Mother appear in the family as- sembly, attended by their family. The names of the predecessors of the family are first recalled indi- vidually to the recollection of the family. ' Food is then presented to their memory as a token of duties performed by those present, in consequence of duties performed by those departed, and as a pledge for the conduct of those to come. ' The food, the result of a typical reward for duties performed, is then eaten, with portions laid aside for those in need. ' This is the first part. In the second, the father, seated between his wife and the eldest of the family, opens the Books of Record. ' These family books, which every Chinese family must keep, render unnecessary State interference or control, and are considered as legal documents. ' One contains matter relating- to civil life, births, marriages, deaths, &c. ; the others, the family judg- ments, records and biographies of the dead, their Wills, &c. 'The necessary records having been entered, the book containing historical record is opened, and the life and action of those departed commented on. The minds of all being steadied by such reflections, the meeting becomes a council, and balances its affairs, enquiring first into obligations outside the family, and then to those relating to the interior RELIGION DIFFERENT FROM SCIENCE. 175 management. The family would consider itself dis- honoured were occasion given of right of demand for State or outside interference. Lastly, misdemeanours are enquired into : the accused is at once separated from others present, for trial, or, if information has to be obtained or proofs collected, he is remanded to the next or to a special meeting. ' Conceive the training in this method for every child. This is the paternal authority — an authority based only on judgment and method, and therefore acting with a power and a love that we cannot understand. ' Thus is to be seen the base of the union of adminis- trative and judicial functions in the same hands. 'This method of judicial sifting of evidence before action, is to be universally found at the origin of all religion and government, and is the source of the method of knowledge, and only by such a process can the family protection exist and prosper. ' Confucius says of this method : ' " He who understands the ceremonies of the offerings to Heaven and Earth, and the meaning of the several offerings to ancestors, would find the government of a kingdom as easy as to look into the palm of his hand." ' A belief in ancestral spirits, therefore, may easily become the foundation of a system of morality, or, at all events, of law. With the Chinese, Filial Piety or reverence for parents and ancestors has been recog- nised from the earliest times as the root of all religion and government. The Hsiao King or ' Classic of Filial Piety ' is one of their most sacred books *. 1 See Sacred Books of the East, vol. iii. 176 LECTURE VII. Moral Influence of Psychological Deities. Whether we can ascribe a similar moral influence to psychological religion also, is more difficult to say. It has certainly developed into some kind of religion in India, where meditation on the self within us and the recognition of its true relation to the Supreme Self forms to the present day the highest stage that can be reached by the faithful. In other countries that highest stage is generally divided from religion, properly so called, and handed over to the philosopher and the mystic. But apart from that, we often see isolated germs of psychological thought fall on re- ligious and moral soil, and develop into mythology and even worship. Temple to Mens. In Rome, for instance, we read that about the time of the battle on Lake Thrasymene, or, according to others, one hundred years later, a temple was built to 31ens, Mind, in order that the Roman citizens might always be of good mind1. There were other temples dedicated to Pi etas, filial piety, Pudicitia, chastity, Virtus, manliness, Spes, hope, Fides, faithfulness. And not only were these deities worshipped in temples, but such were, for a time at least, their power and influence that Regulus would rather die than break his fides or his troth. At a later time, during the Second Punic War, Hannibal allowed ten Roman soldiers to proceed to Rome on their word of honour. Eight only returned, but the other two were declared infamous by the Roman Censors, and such was then still the power of public 1 Ovid, Fast. vi. 241 ; Liv. xxii. 9 and 10 ; Cic. X. D. ii. 22 ; Leg. ii. 11 ; Hartimg, Religion der Romer, ii. 262. RELIGION DIFFERENT FROM SCIENCE. 177 opinion that both are said to have committed suicide, because no one would treat them any longer as Roman citizens. Eros and Psyche. In Greece also some traces may be discovered of psychological mythology, if not of religion. The best known instance is that of Eros and Psyche, Love and Soul. In the form in which that legend is presented to us by Apuleius it is, no doubt, modern — nearly as modern in conception as on the frescoes of the Far- nesina Palace. But it contains old elements — how old, it is difficult to say, considering how freely even men like Socrates still claimed the right of inventing or modifying a myth, if it helped to teach some philo- sophical lesson. Conscience. And even in our own language there are survivals of psychological mythology and morality. There is a well-known line quoted from Menander, Monost. 654 : Bporots airaa-Lv ?/ tivveibrjcns 6eos, ' To all mortals conscience is a god.' It is not difficult to understand what Menander (342-290 b. c.) really meant by this verse, but it is a curious verse for several reasons, and in particular because avveih-qais is not the common word for con- science in classical Greek, though it is the recognised term in the New Testament. In classical Greek crvveibrjo-is means consciousness rather than conscience, and the question we have to answer first is how such words as cruvoiha and o-wei'8770-19, from meaning to be conscious or cognisant, came to mean to be conscientious. The psychological process N 178 LECTURE VII. seems to have been something like this. In primitive times a man might often do what seemed wrong to others, but not to himself. In that case, he himself would hardly remember what he had done. If asked, he would not be conscious of having, for instance, taken an apple from a garden, because he was in the habit of doing so and saw no harm in it. If, however, he had once been told by others that he ought not to take an apple which belonged to some one else, or even if some unexplained instinct had told him that in taking it away he was doing what was disapproved by others or dangerous to himself, then he would be conscious of his act, and his consciousness of having done an act which by some authority or other had been judged to be wrong, would gradually become what we call a conscience. Again, if two confederates had committed a criminal act, they would, if cross-examined, appear as avveiboTes, as knowing what they had done, and thus o-weidco? would assume the meaning of an accomplice. Even in our courts of law a man is said to look conscious, that is, guilty, and this conscious look would again be the outer manifestation of what we now call con- science. Thus conscience came to be a recognised name of what was originally a consciousness or a knowledge, however acquired, of what was right and wrong. But this was not the only name by which this well- known state of feeling could be apprehended, and to say that, because there is in Sanskrit no word corre- sponding to conscience, therefore the Hindus did not know what conscience means, is absurd. Socrates did not use the word a-vveCbrjcns, but when he spoke of RELIGION DIFFERENT FROM SCIENCE. 179 the baiiJLoviov, the spirit within him, he meant the same thing, though he called it by a higher name, a name that comes very near to what the early Chris- tians meant by the Holy Ghost. In ancient languages, like Sanskrit, we must expect more primitive expressions for that inward state of consciousness of right and wrong. In Sanskrit we find hri, which means glow, blush, and shame *. This flushing or blushing was the out- ward sign of an inward commotion. A man being- charged with a dishonourable act, blushed ; that was quite the same as when in later times he had learnt to control the beating of his heart, and only looked con- scious or foolish. A language therefore which has a name for blushing and shame has to all intents and purposes a name for conscience. A man who is said to blush at a thing, or at the very thought of a thing, may be said to be warned or kept by his conscience from doing a thing. I doubt whether the German nations had a name like conscience before they came in contact with the Romans. As conscientia was a translation of avveC- brjo-is, Geivissen seems a mere imitation of conscientia. In Gothic it is midwissei. But the German had the word shame, which, if it was derived from a root skam or kam, meaning to cover, expressed again the outward sign of conscience, the covering of the 1 The Rev. W. Gill informs me that in Mangaia (Hervcy Group) they say, Kua renga koa, ' You are yellow,' or more fully, Kua renga koe i te akama, ' You are yellow with shame.' The brownish complexion of the nation seems to turn more yellow, while with us the white com- plexion becomes suffused with red. To turn white or pale is with us a sign of fear rather than of shame. I have myself watched a native of India with a light brown complexion, turning ashy grey when convicted of having told an untruth. N 2 180 LECTURE VII. face to hide the flush, or to avoid the searching look of the judge. Remorse. If there had been no word at all for conscience in Latin, an expression like that of Lucretius (iii. 839), peccata remordent, ' sins bite back,' would be sufficient to show that he at least knew what conscience meant. One such expression of a single poet may lead to an abundant growth of thought and language in the same direction. Thus, though remorsus is not a classical Latin word, it rises to the surface in mediaeval Latin, it becomes recognised as remors in French, as remorse in English. And as we find conseientia trans- lated in German by Geivissen, and in Old English by Inwyt, we find remorse rendered literally in Old English by Ayenbite, that is, againbite, the two words together forming the title of one of the most important books of the fourteenth century, the Ayenbite of Inwyt by Dan Michel 1. In German too we speak of Geivissens- bisse, the bitings of conscience, that is, remorse. In watching the growth of these names, which were all intended for one and the same state of mind, we can see how easily these acts of ours lead to the admission of a separate mental organ or faculty, or, as the Brahmans boldly called it, a deity. Have we a Conscience? Because I am conscious of having done what to me seems either right or wrong, I am supposed to possess a consciousness, or, as applied to moral questions, a con- science, which tells me what is right or wrong. But why should a man be supposed to possess such an organ 1 Edited by Richard Morris, for the Early English Text Society, No. 23. RELIGION DIFFERENT FROM SCIENCE. 181 or faculty, or why should we appeal to a man's con- science, as something apart from the man 1 If a man is tall, he does not possess something called tallness. If he is hopeful, there is not inside him a power called hope ; if he is ashamed, it is not something indepen- dent of him that makes him ashamed. Even his blushes are only the effect of the quicker movement of the heart, and what makes the heart move more quickly is the quick rushing in of perceptions and imaginations caused by circumstances which are stronger than himself. We are justified therefore in saying that we are conscious of having done wrong ; but as soon as we go a step further and say that we have a conscience which tells us what is right or wrong, we go beyond the facts, such as we know them. Conscience never tells us what is right or wrong, but simply whether we have done what from some source or other we know to be right or wrong. Nothing is more common now than to call conscience an inward monitor, or even the voice of God x ; to speak of conscience as the arbiter of right and wrong, nay, even as the source of all truth, and the highest witness of the existence of God 2. But all this is philosophical mythology. If we possessed within us a faculty, or an oracle, or deity to tell us what is true, and what is right and wrong, how could Pascal have said that good and evil, truth and falsehood, differ with a few degrees of latitude? How could there be that infinite diversity of opinion as to what is true and what is right or wrong ? We must learn that from other sources, and when we have learnt it from 1 See Flint, Theism, p. 216. 2 Goldwin Smith, in MacmiUaris Magazine, Feb. 187^. 182 LECTURE VII. our teachers and by our own experience and judgment, then and then only do we become conscious of having done what is right or wrong. If we like to call that consciousness or that shame or that joy, conscience, we may do so, provided we remember that we use poetical and mythological language, and that such language, unless properly guarded, may exercise a powerful influence on our character, whether for evil or for good. That almighty conscience may be a god to all mortals, as Menander says, but it may likewise become a dumb idol 1. Sacrifices an Element of Religion. It may seem strange that in trying to make my own definition of religion as comprehensive as pos- sible, I should nevertheless have left out what to many people seems an essential, to some the most essential element of religion, namely, sacrifice. It cannot be denied that sacrifice has assumed con- siderable prominence in most religions. Cicero, as we saw, defined religion simply as cultus deorum ; but it is a well-known fact that there were religions without sacrifices in ancient times, and that in modern times the most enlightened minds have completely freed themselves from all sacrificial obligations, in the usual sense of that word. 1 This question has been powerfully argued by Professor Lorimer in his Institutes of Law, Second Edition, 1880, pp. 186 seq. 'I am glad,' he writes, ' that the doctrine of conscience is not taught, in this sense (as being an exceptional organ to decide what is right or wrong), by the present learned occupant of the Chair of Moral Philosophy in Edinburgh.' It is, however, strongly held by the Professor of Divinity, Dr. Flint, who in Iris Lectures on Theism vp. 216) writes : ' It is not more certain that by the eye we see colours, and that by the ear we hear sounds, than that by conscience we discern good and evil.' See also an able pamphlet by Wayfarer, What the Conscience is, London, 1878. RELIGION DIFFERENT FROM SCIENCE. 183 Priesthood. I go even further, and maintain that the priesthood also ought not to be considered as essential to religion, though it may be an inevitable outcome of it. The office of the priest, it should be remembered, is always vicarious, a fact which, with the increase of priestly power, may be forgotten in later times, but which is self-evident in the early periods of all religions. If we look on religion as originally the property of each individual soul, the priest would have no locus standi at all. Or if we trace religion back to the family, the father or head of the family is ipso facto the priest. When families grew into clans, and clans into tribes and confederacies, a necessity would arise of delegating to some heads of families the performance of duties which, from having been the spontaneous acts of individuals, had become the traditional acts of families and clans. The origin of a separate priest- hood varies so much in different countries that it is almost impossible to speak about it in general terms. In some countries the office of the priest would remain united to that of the king ; in others an individual of exceptional gifts as a poet and prophet would obtain for himself and his descendants the privileges of a spiritual ruler. These are questions concerning the history of different nations into which we cannot enter at present. What is important for us is to understand clearly that the first origin of religion, — and it is with this alone that we are dealing now, — does not necessitate, but on the contrary, does really exclude the admission of priests. The same applies to sacrifices. What are called in later times sacrifices or sacred acts must all in their 184 LECTUKE VII. beginning have been natural and spontaneous acts. We can easily trace back all prayers to the same feeling which would lead a child to ask for gifts from his father ; and whoever understands the thoughts of a child in offering to his father a flower or a broken toy, whether from a feeling of gratitude or from a hope of further favours, will not look for any more remote motives prompting the offering of more or less valuable gifts to the gods, after such gods had once been conceived. Expiatory or purificatory offerings and sacrifices can be traced back to the same source, and have really nothing irrational in them, nothing that requires explanation; nothing with which we cannot fully sympathise ourselves. But all these prayers and praises and offerings and purifications, even in their simplest form, always pre- suppose the belief in those superhuman or supernatural beings whom we have accustomed ourselves to call gods, and it would violate all rules of thought to place the sacrifice first, and the conception of a person to whom a sacrifice is offered, last. Study of the Veda. It seems to me that the study of the Veda is chiefly responsible for this delusion, that religion begins with sacrifice. At first it was the fashion to represent the hymns of the Rig-veda as the most primitive utter- ances of religious thought, recalling a period when there was as yet no system of religion, no creeds, no priesthood, no sacrifice. I remember myself speaking of the Rig-veda as the true theogony of the Aryan race, and I do not mean in the least to retract that statement. But it is one thing to say that the Veda brings us as near to the theogonic process of the RELIGION DIFFERENT FROM SCIENCE. 185 Aryan world as any literary document will ever bring us, and quite another to imagine that the Veda was composed by the first man who escaped from the glacial period, or by the first poet who could stammer forth human language. Why will people always imagine the impossible to be possible ? However, it was but natural that after expectations had been raised to the highest pitch, there should be a reaction. The Veda, as I have always said, in spite of its wonderful antiquity, is like an oak in which we can count ring after ring, testifying to an infinite succes- sion of intellectual springs and winters. Not only are priests and sacrifices presupposed in many a hymn, but most elaborate sacrifices performed by ever so many distinct priests are mentioned, at all events in the more modern hymns. Because it was clear that some of the hymns had been composed in connection with these sacrifices, it has of late become the fashion to maintain that all had been, that in fact the whole Vedic poetry was the product of a priestly caste, requiring song and poetry for the enlivenment of their sacrifices. It is quite true that the hymns collected in what are called the Ya(/ur and Sama-veda, have no other object than to be employed at sacrifices. But it is equally true that the collection of the Rig-veda had no such sacrificial purpose. And, what is far more important is what every scholar knows, namely that even many of the passages taken from the Rig-veda and embodied in the two other purely sacrificial Vedas, are so turned and twisted in order to make them useful for liturgical purposes that no one could sup- pose for a moment that they were first composed for 186 LECTURE VII. liturgical, and afterwards collected for hymnological purposes. This idea, however, that, because some hymns were meant from the first to accompany the sacrifices, all Vedic hymns were the production of Vedic priests ; that, in fact, the Hindus first elaborated a most complete and complicated ceremonial, and then only set to work to invent the gods to whom their sacrifices should be offered and to compose hymns of praise to celebrate the greatness of these gods,— this idea, I say, has so completely taken possession of certain philosophers, that they now appeal to the Veda as the best proof that sacrifice must everywhere have come first, and hymns to the gods, nay, according to some, even belief in the gods, afterwards. Gods, we are told, are not gods till they are worshipped (Gruppe, I. c, p. 81). If such theories can be proved by facts in any part of the globe, let it be so ; but to quote the Veda in support of them, is impossible. And what applies to sacrifices offered to the gods of nature, applies with equal force to the offerings presented to ancestral spirits. We have been told of late that sacrifices arose really from carousals, and I do not deny that there is some truth in this, only that, as usual, it is spoiled by exaggera- tion. Nothing is more natural than that, after the death of a father, his place at dinner should be kept vacant, or that his share of food should actually be placed on the exact spot where he used to sit. That may seem childish, but it is perfectly human. Again, that a few drops of whatever served for drink at a meal should be poured on the ground in memory of the departed, is perfectly intelligible. But in that case, a belief in ancestral spirits was as necessary a RELIGION DIFFERENT FROM SCIENCE. 187 condition of such pious acts as a belief in gods is pre- supposed by sacrificial offerings. What, however, quite staggers me, is the idea lately broached, that not only did all religion take its origin in these carousals \ but that the first idea of sacri- fice arose from some person persuading the people that by lighting in the morning the fire on the altar, they could assist the sun in his daily or yearly fight against his enemies. Where could they have got a belief in the sun as a fighter and as having enemies'? And how would it have been possible to convince them, in spite of all evidence to the contrary, that the small rush-light on their hearth could in- vigorate the power of the sun 1 It is perfectly true that such ideas appear in the Veda, but they appear there preceded by many antecedent ideas, which make them not only less grotesque, but render them almost intelligible. But to imagine that such thoughts could be primitive, and that they could help us to account psychologically for the evolution of religious and sacrificial ideas in the world at large, is certainly to my mind passing strange. Well may the author of such a theory say that so absurd a thing could have happened once only in the history of the world, and that therefore all religions of the civilised races of mankind came from the country in which this strange hallucination took possession of one weak-minded in- dividual (p. 277). Although, therefore, a definition of religion which should exclude sacrifices and priesthood would cer- tainly be deficient, I hold that both the sacrificial and 1 * Der Cultusact war nicht etwa nur mit einem Gelage verbimden, sondern er war recht eigentlich em Gelage.' Gruppe, p. 277. 188 LECTUKE VII. priestly character of religion is sufficiently secured by our restricting the perception of the infinite to such manifestations as are able to influence the moral character of man. It is the moral character of man that shows itself in those acts of fear, reverence, gratitude, love, and contrition which we comprehend under the general name of sacrifice, and the delegation of these sacrificial acts to agents, better qualified or more worthy to perform them than the rest, may like- wise be traced back to a sense of humility on the part of the people at large, or what we now call the laity. If now we gather up the threads of our argument, and endeavour to give our own definition of religion, it would be this : ' Religion consists in the perception of the infinite under such manifestations as are able to influence the moral character of man! I look upon this as a definition of religion in its origin, but if we once admit a continuity in the historical growth of religion, the same definition ought to remain applicable to all the later developments through which religion has passed. In order to remain applicable to all these later developments, our definition of religion must necessarily leave out what- ever is peculiar to one or other of these later develop- ments only ; and it may happen therefore that what seem to some of us the most valuable characteristics of religion, are missing in our definition of it. To those who maintain that religion is chiefly a modus cognoscendi Deum, a mode of knowing God, we should reply that there is no conceptual knowledge which is not based first of all on perceptual knowledge, and that Deus or God is not the only object of reli- RELIGION DIFFERENT FROM SCIENCE. 189 aion, that in fact so narrow a definition would exclude all dualistic and polytheistic religions as well as all those forms of faith which shrink from comprehending the Divine under the limits of mere human person- ality. To those who cling to the idea of religion as chiefly a mode of worshipping God, modus colendi Deum, our answer would be that so long as worship is a genuine expression of moral sentiments, it is included in our definition ; while when it has ceased to be so, it is no longer religion, but superstition only. Kant's definition that ' religion consists in our re- cognising all our duties as divine commandments ' is comprehended in our own, for that definition represents only a later and higher stage of that original per- ception of something unseen and infinite which determines our moral acts. Nay, if we go a step higher still, and recognise religion as the surrender of the finite will to the infinite, we have here again the fullest realisation of that primeval perception of the infinite as a power, not entirely different from our- selves, that makes for righteousness. And while thus the highest conceptions of religion can be traced back as natural developments to that broad conception of religion on which our definition is based, we shall find that the lowest forms of religion likewise are easily comprehended under it. Roskoff, in his learned work Das Religionsivesen der rohesten Naturvolker, 1880, (The religion of the rudest races,) which contains a most elaborate and exhaustive reply to Sir John Lubbock's theories, defines the religion of these uncivilised tribes in the most general terms as 'what lifts them above the real world.' Much the 190 LECTURE VII. same definition of religion is given by Hegel also. Here we have only to replace real by finite, and we shall see that what he means is exactly what we mean by a ' perception of something infinite beyond the finite world,' only that we qualify that perception of the infinite and restrict it to that class of perceptions which can influence the moral character of man. I know in fact of no definition of religion— and I have dwelt in my lectures on the most important only— which cannot be accommodated within the wide boundaries of our own, and, what is even more important, I know of no religion, whether ancient or modern, that cannot be caught in that wide net. Even Buddhism— I mean Southern Buddhism, which refused to be caught by any other definition— cannot escape. Though Buddha declined to dogmatise on the Beyond, and though from his unwillingness to predicate anything about it, it dwindled down in the minds of some of his followers to a mere Nothing, yet even that Nothing was not the finite or material world, but lay beyond it, undefined, if not infinite. Buddha was lifted beyond the real world ; and the practical side of Buddhism also, its belief in trans- migration and the never-resting wheel of the world, presupposed a look that had pierced beyond the finite, nay, had raised the perception of the endless con- tinuance of works or Karma into the most potent faith that could influence the moral character of man. ' We are what we are,' as Buddha says in the very first verse of his Dhammapada, ' by what we have thought and done. As the cart follows on the heels of the ox that draws it, so do our thoughts and deeds follow us.' The experience of this finite world could RELIGION DIFFERENT FROM SCIENCE. 191 not have taught him that lesson. It was a look back- ward and forward beyond the horizon of our ex- perience— though not in his case, a look upward — that alone could have taught Buddha that faith in absolute justice and eternal right which has made his religion the wonder of the world. LECTURE VIII. THE HISTORICAL METHOD. Criticism of My Definition. THE definition of religion at which we arrived in our last lecture has received the support of a large number both of philosophers and historians ; but for that very reason, it would seem, it has also provoked a great amount of very determined opposition. Now we ought always to be truly grateful for adverse criticism. It generally gives us something, it teaches us something which we did not know before, whereas assent and laudation, though they may give us more confidence in our own opinions, add but seldom to our own or to the general stock of knowledge. After all, every one of us is only a labourer, each having his special work assigned to him in raising the temple of knowledge. It is of that temple alone that every honest workman ought to think, and not of himself, for he is but one in a million of hewers of wood and drawers of water. If he is planing and polishing his beam carelessly, or if he is spilling the water on the way, he should be thankful for his own sake, and still more for the sake of the great work which is entrusted to him, if his fellow-labourers will warn him, correct him, advise him, and help him in his work. Who knows now the workmen that built the pyramids, or even THE HISTORICAL METHOD. 193 the architect that devised them 1 But if one single block of granite had been placed at a wrong angle, the very pyramid would probably have collapsed long- ago, or would have remained blemished for ever % Pfleiderer's Criticism. I feel truly grateful therefore for the criticisms which have been passed by Professor Pfleiderer and others on my former definition of religion, and I fully admit their justness. I had defined religion simply as ' a perception of the infinite,' without adding the restriction ' a perception of the infinite under such manifestations as are able to influence the moral character of man.' The fact was that in my former writings I was chiefly concerned with dogmatic religion. I was anxious to discover the origin of religious concepts, names, and theories, and I left the question of their influence on moral actions for further consideration. We cannot do or say everything at the same time, and it is perhaps hardly fair that we should be supposed to have negatived what we simply had left unmentioned. Still, I plead guilty to having not laid sufficient emphasis on the practical side of religion ; I admit that mere theories about the in- finite, unless they influence human conduct, have no right to the name of religion, and I have tried now to remedy that defect by restricting the name of religion to those perceptions of the infinite which are able to influence the moral character of man. Professor Gruppe. But a much more determined attack came from a different quarter. As I had meant to treat the Science of Religion in a strictly scientific spirit, 1 had care- 194 LECTURE VIII. fully excluded all theories which ascribe the origin of religion either to innate ideas or to supernatural revelation. I had placed myself completely on what is called the positivist platform. ' We are told,' I said 1, ' that all knowledge, in order to be knowledge, must pass through two gates and two gates only, the gate of the senses, and the gate of reason. Keligious knowledge also, whether true or false, must have passed through these two gates. At these two gates therefore we take our stand. Whatever claims to have entered in by any other gate, whether that gate be called primeval revelation or religious instinct, must be rejected as contraband of thought ; and what- ever claims to have entered in by the gate of reason, without having first passed through the gate of the senses, must equally be rejected, as without sufficient warrant, or ordered at least to go back to the first gate, in order to produce there its full credentials V Religion a Psychological Necessity ? Of course, if the psychological analysis of the earliest religious concepts as I had given it is correct, — and no one, I believe, has denied the simple facts on which it rests — it follows that religion is a psycho- logical necessity, and not, as positivist philosophers maintain, a mere hallucination or a priestly fraud. This, I believe, is the real reason why my own ex- planation of religion, though admitted to be im- 1 Hibbert Lectures, 226 ; Gruppe, p. 218. 3 ' Das ist das beriihmte Miiller'sclie System, welches eine bcson- ders eingehende Wurdigung erfordert, nicht allein wegen der per- sbnlichen Bedeutung seines Urhebers, sondern mehr noch weil es der bered teste mid systematischeste Ausdrack einer Auffassung ist, von welcher aus eine ganze Reihe hervorragender religionsgeschicht- lichef Werke anderer Forscher geschrieben sind.' Gruppe, p. 220. THE HISTORICAL METHOD. 195 pregnable, has been so fiercely condemned by theposi- tivists themselves. But it is one thing to condemn, another to refute. I should have thought that my critics would have welcomed my admission, Nihil ed in fide quod non anteafuerit in sensu, with open arms. But no, they will hear of no psychological, of no his- torical explanation of one of the greatest psychological and historical facts in the world, namely religion. If anything, however, is absurd, it is surely to imagine that by shutting our eyes, we can annihilate facts. Is not religion as solid a fact as language, law, art, science, and all the rest ? We may, if we like, disapprove of every one of these achievements of the human mind ; but even then we cannot get rid of the problem as to how they came to exist. Unless, therefore, some intelligible arguments can be advanced against what I have put forward as the conditio sine quel non of all religion, I shall for the present consider the follow- ing points as firmly established : — 1. That, like all other experience, our religious experience begins with the senses ; 2. That though the senses seem to deliver to us finite experiences only, many, if not all, of them can be shown to involve something beyond the known, something unknown, something which I claim the liberty to call infinite ; 3. That in this way the human mind was led to the recognition of undefined, infinite agents or agencies beyond, behind, and within our finite experience ; and 4. That the feelings of fear, awe, reverence and love excited by the manifestations of some of these agents or powers began to react on the human mind, o 2 196 LECTURE Villi and thus produced what we call Natural Religion in its lowest and simplest form,- -fear, awe, reverence, and love of the gods1. History v. Theory. After we have once established these premisses, there are two ways open for the study of Natural Religion. We may try to find out by means of abstract reasoning what ideas would naturally spring from these simple premisses, how the perception of the Infinite could be realised in language, and what could or could not be predicated of those undefined 1 I doubt whether the writer of an interesting article in the Scots Magazine, Feb. 1889, can have attended all my lectures at Glasgow. He says that my definition of religion seemed to him to labour under four objections : 1. 'That it is not traced back to the promiscuum (read proximum) genus, just as much and just as little as the definition modus cognoscendi, etc' But my definition traces religion back to one proximum genus only, and not to two. It traces it back to experience, and nothing else, not to both cognoscere and colere. 2. ' That it is expressed in terms which require definition.' I say no, unless I have laboured in vain in trying to show that the ex- perience of the infinite is as palpable as that of the finite. The in- finite in this its simplest and most primitive sense seems to me t<> require no further definition, nay to admit of none, whereas the concept of Deus is so full of historical ingredients that it almost dories definition. 3. He doubts ' whether my definition of religion, though it may include Buddhism, would include Fetishism.' Fetishism is, as I believe to have shown, the very last corruption of religion ; but even in that corrupt form religion is based on the perception of some- thing beyond the actual in the actual. And even if the fetish is coerced by blows instead of being importuned by prayers, the moral element is still present in the act of the worshipper. 4. My critic says ' that there are some religions which do not affect moral character, but only move the individual to the me- chanical performance of certain external acts.' Yes, but these are again corruptions of religion, and perfectly intelligible in their downward movement. Would any one say that a Megatherion ought not to be defined as a living animal, because we know it in its petrified form only ? THE HISTORICAL METHOD. 197 agents or agencies that had been discovered behind, or above, or within nature. Theory. It might be asked, for instance, whether the human mind could be satisfied with an indefinite number of such beings, or whether after a time the mere love of simplicity would lead on to the admission of one supreme being only. Again, it might be asked whether anything beyond mere existence could be predicated of the infinite, or whether, after the existence of supernatural powers has been admitted and their number fixed, any further qualities could be ascribed to them. We know that the answer, which was given, quite regardless as yet of historical facts, has been that it could be done in three ways, and in three ways only. Causalitas. First, these beings might be looked upon, not as identical with nature, but as behind nature ; not as what is, but as the cause of what is ; or, in the earliest stages of human thought and language, as makers, shapers, fathers, and rulers of the world. This is the conception of the divine per viam causal 'if at is. Eminentia. Secondly, as they were conceived as powerful and perfect, whatever qualities seemed most excellent in human nature, might be safely ascribed to them in a supreme degree. This is the conception of the divine per viam eminent iae. Negatio. Thirdly, whatever seemed imperfect in human nature, or at all events, weak and limited, could 198 LECTUKE VITT. safely be negatived of divine beings, per warn nega- tion is. Cosmological, Teleological, Ontological Arguments. Again, the so-called proofs of the existence of divine beings or in the end of one Supreme God, the Cosmological, Teleological, and Ontological, might be examined and reasoned out, without any reference to the history of religious thought. All this might be done, and has been done and well done, and I have little doubt that some of the lecturers on Lord GifFord's foundation will do full credit to this side of our subject, to what is generally called the Philosophy of Religion. Historical Method. I myself, however, am not going to follow this course, and this for various reasons. First of all, the philosophy of religion has such eminent representa- tives in Scotland, and more particularly in this University, that I should feel it presumptuous on my part to treat a subject which has been much better treated in this place than I could hope to do. Secondly, all my own special studies have been devoted to the history of religion, and I can hardly be mistaken in supposing that it was for this reason that I was chosen to fill this lectureship. Thirdly, I must openly confess that I have great faith in history, as showing to us, if not the best possible, at all events the only real arguments in support of the tenets of Natural Religion. To the philosopher the existence of God may seem to rest on a syllogism ; in the eyes of the historian it rests on the whole evolution of human thought. THE HISTORICAL METHOD. 199 The opinions elaborated by the whole of mankind ' with all their fluctuations and contradictions,' seem to me to carry a certain weight, and, at all events, to convey more instruction than the system of any or even of all of our living philosophers. Nor is it necessary that an historical study should exclude contemporary history. The philosophers of to-day will to-morrow be philosophers of yesterday, and if they have added anything original to the in- herited stock of human knowledge, they will take their proper place in the historical Council of the world. Whatever questions I have had to deal with, I have always found their historical treatment and solution the most satisfactory. If we do not under- stand a thing, if we hardly know what it is, what it means, and how to call it, it is always open to us to try to find out how it has come to be what it is. It is wonderful how this method clears our thoughts, and how it helps us to disentangle the most hopeless tangles which those who came before us have left to us as our inheritance. This historical method has regenerated the study of language, it has infused a new spirit into the study of ancient law; why should it not render the same kind of help to an independent study of religion 1 Archaeology. Nowhere, perhaps, can we see more clearly the different spirit in which these two schools, the histor- ical and the theoretical, set to work than in what is called by preference the Science of Man, Anthro- pology, or the Science of People, Ethnology; or 200 LECTURE VII [. more generally the science of old things, 0f the works of ancient men, Archaeology. Theoretic School. The Theoretic School begins, as usual, with an ideal conception of what man must have been in the beginning. According to some, he was the image of his Maker, a perfect being, but soon destined to fall to the level of ordinary humanity. According to others, he began as a savage, whatever that may mean, not much above the level of the beasts of the field, and then had to work his way up through successive stages, which are supposed to follow each other by a kind of inherent necessity. First comes the stage of the hunter and fisherman, then that of the breeder of cattle, the tiller of the soil, and lastly that of the founder of cities. But while one school of anthropologists would thus derive civilisation by a gradual evolution from the lowest savagery, another school considers the savage as a stationary and quiescent being, so much so that it bids us recognise in the savage of to-day the un- changed representative of the primordial savage, and encourages us to study the original features of man in such survivals as the Bushmen, the Papuans and the Cherokees. These two views might seem con- tradictory, unless we distinguish between stationary savages and progressive savages, or define at least the meaning of the word, before we allow it to enter into our scientific currency. Again, as man is defined as an animal which uses tools, we are told that, according to the various materials of which these tools were made, man must THE HISTORICAL METHOD. ^01 by necessity have passed through what are called the three stages or ages of stone, bronze, and iron, raising himself by means of his more and more perfect tools to what we might call the age of steel and steam and electricity, in which for the present civil- isation seems to culminate. Whatever discoveries are made by excavating the ruins of ancient cities, by opening tombs, by ransacking kitchen-middens, by exploring once more the flint-mines of prehistoric races, all must submit to the fundamental theory, and each specimen of bone or stone or bronze or iron must take the place drawn out for it within the lines and limits of an infallible system. Historical School. The Historical School takes the very opposite line. It begins with no theoretical expectations, with no logical necessities, but takes its spade and shovel to see what there is left of old things. It describes them, arranges them, classifies them, and thus hopes in the end to understand and to explain them. Thus when Schliemann began his work at Hissarlik, he dug away, noted the depth at which each relic was found, placed similar relics side by side, unconcerned whether iron comes before bronze, or bronze before flint. Here are the facts, he seems to say to the students of archaeology — now arrange them and draw your own conclusions from them. Let me quote the words of a young and very careful archaeologist, Mr. Arthur Evans, in describing this kind of work, and the results which we obtain from it l : ' In the topmost stratum of Hissarlik,' lie writes. 1 Academy, December 20, 1883. 202 LECTURE VIII. ' (which some people like to call Troy,) extending six feet down, we find remains of the Eoman and Mace- donian Ilios, and the Aeolic colony ; and the frag- ments of archaic Greek pottery discovered (hardly distinguishable from that of Spata and Mykenai) take ns back already to the end of the first millen- nium before our era. ' Below this, one superposed above the other, lie the remains of no less than six successive prehistoric settlements, reaching down to over fifty feet below the surface of the hill. The formation of this vast superincumbent mass by artificial and natural causes must have taken a long series of centuries ; and yet, when we come to examine the lowest deposits, the remains of the first and second cities, we are struck at once with the relatively high state of civilisation at which the inhabitants of this spot had already arrived. ' The food-remains show a people acquainted with agriculture and cattle-rearino- as well as with hunt- ing and fishing. The use of bronze was known, though stone-implements continued to be used for certain purposes, and the bronze implements do not show any of the refined forms — notably the fibulae — characteristic of the later Bronze Age. ' Trade and commerce evidently were not wanting. Articles de luxe of gold, enamel, and ivory were already being imported from lands more directly under Babylonian and Egyptian influence, and jade- axeheads came by prehistoric trade routes from the Kuen-Lun, in China. The local potters were already acquainted with the use of the wheel, and the city- walls and temples of the Second City evince con- siderable progress in the art of building.' THE HISTORICAL METHOD. 203 Such is the method of the Historical School, and such the results which it obtains. It runs its shaft down from above ; the Theoretical School runs its shaft up from below. It may be that they are both doing good work, but such is the strength of tempera- ment and taste, even among scientific men, that you will rarely see the same person working in both mines ; nay, that not seldom you hear the same disparaging remarks made by one party of the other, which you may be accustomed to hear from the promoters of rival gold mines in India or in the South of Africa. Study of Language (Historical School). Let us now cast a glance at the work which these two schools, the historical and the theoretical, have done in the study of language. The Historical School in trying to solve the problem of the origin and growth of language, takes language as it finds it. It takes the living languages in their various dialects, and traces each word back from century to century, until from the English, for instance, now spoken in the streets, we arrive at the Saxon of Alfred, the Old Saxon of the Continent, and the Gothic of Ulfilas, as spoken on the Danube in the fourth century. Even here we do not stop. For finding that Gothic is but a dialect of the great Teutonic stem of language, that Teutonic again is but a dialect of the great Aryan family of speech, we trace Teutonic and its collateral branches, Greek, Latin, Celtic, Slavonic, Persian, and Sanskrit, back to that Proto-Aryan form of speech which contained the seeds of all we now see before us developed 204 LECTURE VIII. into germs, plants, flowers, and fruits in the various languages of the Aryan race. After having settled this historical outline of the growth of our family of speech, the Aryan, we take any word, or a hundred, or a thousand words, and analyse them, or take them to pieces. That words can be taken to pieces, every grammar teaches us. The Sanskrit name for grammar is Vyakara?ia, which means ' taking to pieces.' This process, how- ever, of taking them to pieces scientifically and correctly, dissecting limb from limb, is often as diffi- cult and laborious as any anatomical preparation. Acutus. Well, let us take quite a modern word — the American cute, sharp. We all know that cute is only a shortening of acute, and that acute is the Latin acutus, sharp. In acutus, again, we easily recognise the frequent derivative tits, as in cornutus, horned, from cornu, horn. This leaves us acu, as in acu-s, a needle. In this word the u can again be separated, for we know that it is a very common derivative, in such words as pec-u, cattle, Sanskrit pasu, from PA#, to tether ; or tanu, thin, Greek ravv-s, Latin tenu-i-s, from TAN, to stretch. Thus we arrive in the end at AK, and here our analysis must stop, for if we were to divide AK into A and K, we should get, as even Plato knew (Theaetetus, 205), mere letters, and no longer significant sounds or syllables Now what is this AK ? We call it a root, which is, of course, a metaphor only. What we really mean by a root is the residuum of our analysis, and a residuum which itself resists all further analysis. But what is impor- tant is that these roots represent not a mere theoretic THE HISTOKICAL METHOD. 205 postulate, but a fact, an historical fact, and, at the same time, an ultimate fact. With these ultimate facts—that is, with a limited number of predicative syllables, to which every word in any of the Aryan languages can be traced back, or, as we may also express it, from which every word in these languages can be derived— the historical school of comparative philology is satisfied, at least to a certain extent ; but it has also to account for certain pronouns and adverbs and prepositions, which arc not derived from predicative, but from demonstrative roots, and wThich have supplied, at the same time, many of those derivative elements, like tus in acu-tus, which we generally call suffixes or terminations. After this analysis is finished, the historical student has done his work. AK, he says, conveys the concept of sharp, sharpness, being sharp or pointed. How it came to do that we cannot tell, or, at least, we cannot find out by historical analysis. If we like to guess on the sub- ject, Plato has shown us how to do it, and no one is likely to do it more ingeniously than he. But that it did convey that concept, we can prove by words derived from AK in Sanskrit, Greek, Latin, in Celtic, Slavonic, and Teutonic speech. For instance : Sanskrit asu, quick (originally sharp), Greek wm, Lat. oc-ior, Lat. ac-er} eager, acus, acuo, acies, acumen; Greek ckpi, the highest point, A.-S. cecg-, also to egg on; ciKcav, a javelin, acidus, sharp, bitter, ague, a sharp fever, ear of corn, Old High German ahir, Gothic ahs, Lat. (lea*, aceris, husk of grain, and many more. Theoretic School. Let us now look at the Theoretical rJchoul and its treatment of language. How could language arise i 206 LECTURE VIII. it says ; and it answers, Why, we see it every day. We have only to watch a child, and we shall see that a child utters certain sounds of pain and joy, and very soon after imitates the sounds which it hears. It says Ah! when it is surprised or pleased; it says Bah ! when it sees a lamb, Boiv-wow ! when it sees a dog ; and it soon says See-saw, when it swings its doll. Language, we are told, could not arise in any other way ; so that involuntary interjections and imitations must be considered as the ultimate, or rather the primary facts of language, while their transition into real words is, we are assured, a mere question of time. This theory, or rather these three theories, which have been called the Pooh-pooh, Bow-wow, and Yo-heo theories, are said to be easily confirmed by a number of words in all languages, which still exhibit most clearly the signs of such an origin ; and still further, by the fact that these supposed rudiments of human speech exist; even at an earlier stage, in the development of animal life, namely, in the sounds uttered by dogs, parrots, and other animals ; though, curiously enough, far more fully and frequently by our most distant ancestors, the birds, than by those who claim to be our nearest relatives, the apes. It is not surprising, therefore, that all who believe in a possible transition from an ape to a man should gladly have embraced this theory of the origin of language. The only misfortune is that such a theory, though it easily explains utterances which really require no explanation at all, such as boiv-tvow and cuckoo ; pooh-pooh and fie ! yo-heo and see-saw, or even words THE HISTORICAL METHOD. 207 such as crashing, cracking, creaking, crunching, scrunching, leaves us entirely in the lurch as soon as we come to deal with real words — I mean words expressive of general concepts, such as man, tree, name, law — in fact, nine-tenths of our dictionary. The Theoretical School has certainly one great advantage. It goes to the very bottom of the ques- tion, and explains the very origin of language, as it took place in the nursery of the first Pithecanthropos or Anthropopithecos, and it explains it in so simple a way that every child can understand it. If a child can say Bow-wow, what difference is there between that and saying Dog ? If a child can say Fie, why should it not say ' I disapprove ' 1 If a child says Ding- dong, why should it not say Bell ? All these, we are told, are differences of degree only, whatever that may mean, and with a sufficient allowance of time, there is nothing that will not become anything. The Historical School cannot match such perform- ances. When by a most laborious analysis it has reduced one language, or one family of languages, to its constituent elements, it cannot claim to have accounted for the origin of all language, but only of one or two or three families of human speech. When it has placed before us the roots of one lan- guage, or one family of languages, it has come to the end of its work. It can do no more than leave these roots as ultimate facts, though between these roots and the first friendly grunts that passed between anthropopithecos and pithecanthropos, there may bo millions of millions of years. Then why not adopt the Bow-wow, the Pooh-pooh, and the Yo-heo theories, which explain everything so 208 LECTURE TUT. easily and so completely? For the simple reason that real language, when we trace it back to its real constituent elements, shows no trace whatever of these mere imitations of so-called natural sounds. They exist not as part and parcel of real language, but simply by the side of it. Even admitting the possi- bility that they might have grown into some kind of language, the fact remains that they have not done so *. What we call roots do not only show no out- ward similarity with these natural sounds,— that would be the smaller difficulty, — but they are totally different in nature ; and this is the point which so few anthropologists seem able to see. These roots are not simply perceptual, like all Bow-wow, Pooh-pooh, and Yo-heo utterances ; but they are conceptual in char- acter, as the elements of conceptual language ought to be, if they are to help us to explain what has to be explained, namely, conceptual speech. Brin ton on Palaeolithic Language. This has evidently been perceived by Dr. Brinton, now Professor of American Linguistics in the Univer- sity of Pennsylvania. He knows that interjections and all the rest will not grow into real language. But he thinks that the American languages will help us to get behind the scene, and he has drawn up a picture of what, following their guidance, he imagines the language of Palaeolithic Man to have been2. ' It was far more rudimentary,' he writes, ' than any 1 On the possibility of such a transition, see Science of Thought pp. 3UD-315, a chapter for which I have been much blamed by scholars', while anthropologists have construed a limited concession into a complete surrender. '-' The Language <>f Palaeolithic Man, by Daniel G. Brinton. M D. Head before the American Philosophical Society, October 5, 128b. THE HISTORICAL METHOD. 209 language known to us. It had no grammatical form. So fluctuating were its phonetics, and so much de- pended on gesture, tone, and stress, that its words could not have been reduced to writing, nor arranged in alphabetic order.' To give an idea of what ho sup- poses the phonetic chaos of that palaeolithic language to have been, he mentions that in the Araucanian of Chili the following letters are permutable. B may become W, W F, F U, U TJ, U 1, I E, E G, G GH, GH Hu i. But that is not all. ' These palaeolithic words often signified logical contradictories, and which of the antithetic meanings was intended could be guessed only from the accent or a sign.' This will delight Dr. Abel. ' It possessed no prepositions nor conjunctions, no numerals, no pronouns of any kind, no forms to express singular and plural, male nor female, past nor present. The different vowel sounds and the different consonantal groups conveyed specific significance, and were of more import than the syllables which they formed.' This last rather mysterious theory of vowels and consonants being more significant than the syllables which consist of them is illustrated by some remarks made by Bishop Faraud 2, on the Tinne or Athapascan language, spoken widely in British America, and closely allied to the Apache «and Navaho dialects, spoken in the United States. Being, as we are told, a thorough master of Tinne, the Bishop states that its significant radicals are the five primitive vowels, A, E, I, 0, U. Of these A expresses matter, E existence, 1 Dr. Darapsky, Zr* Lengua Araucana, Santiago de Chile, 1888, p. 15. 2 JJix-hiiit ans chez les Sauvages, p. 85. J' 210 LECTURE VIII. I force or energy, O existence doubtful, and U exist- ence absent, non-existence, negation, or succession. These vowels are put in action by single or double consonants, which have more or less value in propor- tion as the vowel is more or less strong:. Father Petitot1 tells us that there are ' sixty -three consonants, divided into nine classes, each of which conveys a series of related or associated ideas in the native mind. Labials express the idea of time and space, as age, length, distance, and also whiteness— the last- mentioned, perhaps, through association with the white hair of age, or the endless snow-fields of their winter. The dentals express ail that relates to force, &c &c.' Here I stop, and though I am afraid it will sound most audacious, I cannot help expressing my convic- tion that all this is simply wrong, and that language could never have been built up with such materials, as little as it was built up with interjections. I know this audacity will seem quite intolerable. My only excuse is that I could produce books published during the prehistoric times of Comparative Philology, in which English and other Aryan languages have been reduced as triumphantly to significant vowels and significant consonants. The Historical School therefore leads us up to a certain point, up to where all is safe, but beyond which all is darkness, at least without the light of hypothetical illustration. It never pretends to prove that the roots which it leaves as ultimate facts were the primordial elements of human speech. It admits the possibility of aeons after aeons between the first man, 1 Petitot, THctionnaire de la Langue D.'nte Dindjie, THE HISTORICAL METHOD. 211 fresh from the hands of nature, and the roots of the Aryan or Semitic family of speech. All it does is to venture on a guess. We found that nearly all the concepts expressed by these roots are significant of acts. Now as the great difficulty, which is hardly ever realised by anthropologists, consists in our having to account for the origin of concepts, and sounds ex- pressive of concepts, and not merely of percepts, and sounds expressive of percepts, the suggestion first made by Noire' is that these roots were originally sounds uttered by men while performing certain acts in common. How little the real character of this theory has been understood is best shown by the fact that it has been actually mistaken for what is called the Yo-heoic theory. No doubt it is a sugges- tion, and no more, for who would dare to speak with positive certainty on matters so distant from us in time, and still more distant from us in thought ? All we can say is that such a suggestion would fulfil three essential conditions ; it would explain the simul- taneous origin of concepts and roots ; it would account for their intelligibility among fellow- workers, and it would explain what has to be explained, viz. con- ceptual, not perceptual language ; language such as it is, not language such as it might have been. If any one has anything better to suggest, let him do so ; if not, Ills utere mecum. Advantages of both Theories. I certainly do not wish to throw unmerited con- tempt on the Theoretical School. Far from it. We want the theorist quite as much as the historian. The one must check the other, nay, even help the other, P 2 212 LECTURE VIII. just as every government wants an opposition to keep it in order, or, I ought perhaps to say, to give it from time to time new life and vigour. I only wished to show, by an example or two, what is the real differ- ence between these two schools, and what I meant when I said that, whether by temperament, or by education, or by conviction, I myself have always belonged to the Historical School. Science of Religion. If now we return to the Science of Religion, we shall find here again the same difference of treatment between the historian and the theorist. The theorist begins by assuring us that all men were originally savages, or, to use a milder term, children. Therefore, if we wish to study the origin of religion, we must study children and savages. Now at the present moment some savages in Africa, Australia, and elsewhere are supposed to be fetish- worshippers and nothing else. Therefore we are assured that five thousand or ten thousand years ago religion must have begun with a worship of fetishes — that is, of stones, and shells, and sticks, and other inanimate objects. Again, children are very apt not only to beat their dolls, but even to punish a chair or a table, if they have hurt themselves against it. This shows that they ascribe life and personality — nay, something like human nature — to inanimate objects. Hence we are told that savages would naturally do the same, or have actually done the same from the earliest time to the present day. A savage is, in fact, the most obliging creature, for he does everything that any THE HISTORICAL METHOD. 213 anthropologist wishes him to do. But, even then, the question of all questions, why he does what he is sup- posed to do, is never asked. We are told that he worships a stone as his god, but how he came to possess the idea of God, and to predicate it of a stone, is called a metaphysical question of no interest to the student of anthropology — that is, of man. Never- theless it is the primary question that is of interest, and the most vital interest to us. If then we press for an answer to this all-important question, we are informed that animism, personifica- tion, and anthropomorphism are the three well-known agencies which fully account for the fact that the ancient inhabitants of India, Greece, and Italy be- lieved that there was life in the rivers, the mountains, and the sky ; that the sun, and the moon, and the dawn were cognisant of the deeds of men, and, finally, that Jupiter and Juno, Mars and Venus, were endowed with the form and the beauty, the feelings and pas- sions of men .... We might as well be told that all animals are hungry, because they have an appetite. We read in many of the most popular works of the day how, from the stage of fetishism, there was a natural and necessary progress to polytheism, mono- theism, and atheism, and after these stages have been erected one above the other, all that remains is to fill each stage with illustrations taken from every race that ever had a religion, whether these races were ancient or modern, savage or civilised, genealogically related to each other, or perfect strangers. Again, I must guard most decidedly against being supposed to wish to throw contempt or ridicule on this 214 LECTURE VIII. school. Far from it. I differ from it ; I have no taste for it ; I think it is often very misleading. But to compare the thoughts and imaginations of savages and civilised races, of the ancient Egyptians, for instance, and the modern Hottentots, has its value, if carried out by real scholars. We learn as much by contrast as by comparison, and the bold adventures of the Theoretic School have often proved a useful warning at all events to later explorers. Historical School. Let us now see how the Historical School goes to work in treating of the origin and growth of religion. It begins by collecting all the evidence that is ac- cessible, and classifies it. First of all, religions are divided into those that have sacred books, and those that have not. Secondly, the religions which can be studied in books of recognised or canonical authority, are arranged genealogically. Semitic Religions. The New Testament is traced back to the 01d; the Koran to both the New and Old Testaments. This gives us one class of religions, the Semitic. Aryan Religions. Then, again, the sacred books of Buddhism and £ainisin, of Zoroastrianism, and of Brabmanism are classed together as Aryan, because they all draw their vital elements from one and the same Proto- Aryan source. This gives us a second class of religions, the Aryan. Chinese Religions. Outside the pale of the Semitic and Aryan re- THE HISTORICAL METHOD. 215 ligions, we have the two book-religions of China, the old national traditions collected by Confucius, and the moral and metaphysical system of Lao-jze. These two constitute a third class of Chinese re- ligions. The study of religions which have sacred books is in some respects easy, because we have in these books authoritative evidence on which our further reasonings and conclusions can be based. But, in other respects, the very existence of these books creates new difficulties, because, after all, religions do not live in books only, or even chiefly, but in human hearts ; and when we have to deal with Vedas, and Avestas, and Tripifoikas, Old and New Testaments, and Korans, we are often tempted into taking the book for the religion. Still the study of book-religions, if we once have mastered their language, admits at all events of a critical and scholarlike study, while a study of native religions which have no books, no articles, no tests, no councils, no pope, withdraws itself almost entirely from a definitely scientific treatment. Any one who attempts to describe the religion of the ancient Greeks and Romans — I mean their real faith, not their mythology, their ceremonial, or their philo- sophy— knows the immense difficulty of such a task. And yet we have here a large literature, spread over many centuries, wTe know their language, we can even examine the ruins of their temples. Religions without Books. Think alter that, how infinitely greater must be the difficulty of forming a right conception, say. of 216 LECTURE VIII. the religion of the Red Indians, the Africans, the Australians. Their religions are probably as old as their languages, that is, as old as our own language ; but we know nothing of their antecedents, nothing except the mere surface of to-day, and that immense surface explored in a few isolated spots only, here and there, and often by men utterly incapable of understanding the language and the thoughts of the people. The mistakes committed by students of these savage religions would fill volumes, as has been shown by Roskoff in his answer to Sir John Lubbock 1. And yet we are asked to believe by the followers of the Theoretic School that this mere surface detritus is in reality the granite that underlies all the religions of the ancient world, more primitive than the Old Testament, more intelligible than the Veda, more instructive than the mythological lan- guage of Greece and Rome. It may be so. The religious map of the world may show as violent convulsions as the geological map of the earth, and what is now on the surface may belong to the lowest azoic rocks. But this would have to be proved, and cannot be simply taken for granted. What I have ventured to say on several occasions to the en- thusiastic believers in this contorted evolution of religious thought is, let us wait till we know a little more of Hottentots aud Papuans ; let us wait till we know at least their language, for otherwise we may go hopelessly wrong. The Historical School, in the meantime, is carrying on its more modest work by publishing and trans- lating the ancient records of the great religions of 1 See Roskoft'. Bas Religionswesen der rohesten NaturvoUcer, 1880. THE HISTORICAL METHOD. 217 the world, undisturbed by the sneers of those who do not find in the Sacred Books of the East what they, in their ignorance, expected. They can hardly be aware of what is thought of their daintiness. Would geologists turn up their noses at a kitchen-midden, because it did not contain their own favourite lolly- pops 1 And yet that is what some students of ancient religion seem inclined to do, when the ancient iftshis of the Veda are not as complacent as the primeval savages, and do not think exactly what synthetic philosophers think they ought to have thought. Where there are no sacred texts to edit and to translate, the true disciples of the Historical School- men such as, for instance, Castre'n in Finland, Bishop Caldwell or Dr. Hahn in South Africa, Horatio Hale or Dr. Brinton in North America— do not shrink from the drudgery of learning the dialects spoken by savage tribes, gaining their confidence, and gathering at last from their lips some records of their popular traditions, their ceremonial customs, some prayers, it may be, and some confession of their ancient faith. But even with all these materials at his disposal, the historical student never forgets that these commu- nications on religious subjects gathered from the lips even of a Cetwayo, can hardly be more trustworthy than a description of the doctrines of Christianity, gathered by the same Cetwayo during his stay in England from the lips of a London coal-heaver. He does not rush at once to the conclusion that in the Legends of the Eskimos any more than in the hymns of the Vedic Aryas, he can find the solution of all the riddles in the science of religion. He only says that we are not likely to find any evidence much 218 LECTURE Yin. more trustworthy, and that therefore we are justified in deriving certain lessons from these materials. And what is the chief lesson to be learnt from all these materials '? It is this, that they contain certain words and concepts and imaginations which are as yet inexplicable, which seem simply irrational, and require for their full explanation antecedents which are lost to us ; but that they contain also many words and concepts and imaginations which are perfectly intelligible, which presuppose no ante- cedents, and which, whatever their date may be, may be called primary in that sense. However strange it may seem to us, if we simply follow the evidence placed before us, there can be little doubt that the perception of the Unknown or the Infinite was with many races as ancient as the perception of the Known or the Finite, that the two were, in fact, inseparable. To men who lived on an island, the ocean was the Unknown, the Infinite, and became in the end their God. To men who lived in valleys, the rivers that fed them and whose sources were unapproachable, the mountains that protected them, and whose crests were inaccessible, the sky that overshadowed them, and whose power and beauty were incomprehensible, these were their un- known beings, their infinite beings, their bright and kind beings, what some of them called their Devas, the Bright, the same word which, after passing through many changes, still breathes in our own word, Divinity. This unconscious process of theogony is historically attested, is intelligible, requires no antecedents, and may in that sense be called a primary process. How THE HISTORICAL METHOD. 219 old it is, chronologically, who would venture to ask or to tell? All that the Historical School ventures to assert is that it explains one side of the origin of religion, namely, the gradual process of naming or conceiving the Infinite. While the Theoretic School takes the predicate of God, when applied to a fetish, as requiring no explanation, the Historical School sees in it the problem of all problems, the result of a long-continued evolution of thought, beginning with the vague consciousness of something invisible, unknown, and unlimited, which gradually assumes a more and more definite shape through similes, names, myths, and legends, till at last it is divested again of all names, and lives within us as the in- visible, inconceivable, unnameable — the infinite God. Even if it should be possible to discover traces of fetishism in really ancient documents, in Egyptian and Eabylonian inscriptions, in Chinese legends, or in Yedic hymns, an accurate student of the historical growth of religious ideas would always ask for its antecedents. Fetishism, from its very nature, cannot be primitive, because it always presupposes the pre- vious growth of the divine predicate. As to the fetishism of modern negroes, we know now that it represents the very lowest stage which religion can reach, whether in Africa or any other part of the world, and I know of no case, even among the most degraded of Negro tribes, where remnants of a higher religious belief have not been discovered by the side of this degraded belief in amulets, talismans, and fetishes. The idea of De Brosses and his followers, that fetishism could reveal to us the very primordial of religious thought, will remain for ever one of the 220 LECTURE VIII. strangest cases of self-delusion, and one of the boldest anachronisms committed by students of the history of religion. I need hardly say that though in the science of religion as in the science of language, all my sym- pathies are with the Historical School, I do not mean to deny that the Theoretical School has like- wise done some good work. The very opposition roused by such men as Schelling and Hegel has been of immense assistance. Let both schools work on, carefully and honestly, and who knows but that their ways, which seem so divergent at present, may meet in the end. LECTURE IX. HISTORICAL TREATMENT OF RELIGIOUS QUESTIONS. Is Religion Possible? IT has often been said, What can be the good of an historical study of religious questions ? We do not want to know what Manu, or Buddha, or Socrates, or Christ thought about the questions which trouble us. We want to know whether any living man can give us an answer that will satisfy the requirements of our own age, or prescribe a remedy which will cure the complaints of our own society. The burning question of the day is not what religion has been, or how it came to be what it is. The real question is the possibility of an}' religion at all, whether natural or supernatural ; and if that question has once been answered in the negative, as it has been by some of the most popular philosophers of our century, why not let the dead bury the dead 1 The fact that, as far as history can reach, no single human being has ever, from his childhood to his old age, been without something that may be called religion, would carry very little weight. The limitation, 'as far as history can reach,' would at once be construed into a confession of our ignorance, so long as there remained a single nook or corner on earth that had not been explored by anthro- 222 LECTURE IX. pologists. In other cases, again, where the existence of a religion cannot be denied, the religion of the child would be explained as an hereditary taint, that of the old man as mere dotage or second child- hood. The fact again that, so long as we know anything of the different races of mankind, we find them always in possession of something that may be called religion, — a fact which may now be readily granted, — and that out of the sum total of human beings now living on this earth (that number varies from 1400 to 1500 millions1 — if you can realise such a sum or even such a difference) those who are ignorant and those who deny the existence of any supernatural beings form a mere vanishing quantity, would make no impression whatever on those who consider that the very word supernatural has no right to exist and should be expunged in oar dictionary. I do not wish to prejudge any of these questions ; and in choosing for my own task a careful study of the historical development of religious thought among the principal nations of the world, I claim for it at first no more than that it may serve at least as a useful preparation for a final solution of the difficult problems which the great philosophers of our age have placed before us. It would be strange indeed if in religion alone we could learn nothing from those who have come before us, or even from those who differ from us. My own experience has been, on the contrary, that nothing helps us so much to understand and to value our own religion as a study 1 MM. Selected Essays, ii. 228; Lehrbuch der Religi&nsgescMchte vm Vhanti pl< 309. - Ibid. {>. 141. 230 LECTURE IX. of evidence, and no more. These are called1 praty- aksha, sensuous perception, anumana, inference, and sab da, the word, particularly the sacred word or the Veda. You see therefore that this philosophy, though it is suspected of being atheistic, tries to appear orthodox. It begins by defining perception or the evidence of the senses, by the following aphorism (I. 90) : ' Perception is the discernment which por- trays the form of that with which it is being brought into contact.' The author then proceeds to defend his definition of sensuous perception against those who object that it is not wide enough, because it does not include the perceptions of the Yogins, the people who by means of fasting and other kinds of penance bring them- selves to have ecstatic visions. Kapila rejoins that these perceptions of the Yogins are not perceptions of things outside them with which their senses can be brought into contact. And if it should be said that these Yogins, in their state of exaltation, might have perceptions arising from con- tact with hidden or invisible things or things which exist as past and future, though not as present 2, his own definition would then be wide enough to compre- hend them. After this, Kapila proceeds to meet another objec- tion. The critics of his definition of sensuous percep- tion seem to have pointed out to him that his defini- tion was not wide enough to include the ecstatic visions having Is vara, the Lord, for their object. 1 Sankliya-sutras, I. 3 ; cf. R. Garbe, Die Theorie der iwdisehi n Eationalisten , 1888. 2 Yoga-sfttras, III. 16. HISTORICAL TREATMENT OF RELIGIOUS QUESTIONS. 231 Some Yogins must have pretended to have had such visions by means of something like sensuous percep- tion (Yoga-sutras, II. 44-45). But Kapila declines to entertain these objections or to modify his definition accordingly, because, as he says, the existence of such a Lord has never been established (Sankhya-sutras, I. 92). From his own point of view the concept of an Isvara or Lord, as defined by the Yogins, would be self-contradictory (I. 95), and, as he points out in a subsequent chapter (V. 10), would not be established by sensuous evidence, by induction, or by revelation 1. He does not deny thereby the existence of a Lord, but only of such a Lord as the Yogins assert, namely, a being that can be reached by sensuous contact and perceived by ecstatic vision 2. Vision in the Bhagavadgita. How prevalent a belief in such ecstatic visions of a deity became in the religious philosophy of the Indian people, we see from the famous episode in the Bhagavadgita, where KWsh?ia appears in his true nature before the eyes of Ar^/una. Aiv/una said 3 to Krishna, : ' I have heard from you about the production and dissolution of things, and also about this your inexhaustible greatness. O highest 1 The commentator says, fsvare tavat pratyaksham nastityanu- lnanasabdav eva pramawe vaktavye, te ka, na sambhavata ity arthafr This shows that my interpretation of Sutra I. 92 was right, not that of Ballantyne and Cowell, who suppose that Kapila refers to the perceptions possessed by Isvara. * Ballantyne translates, that any Lord exists is not proved, but Kapila restricts his remark to the Isvara of the Yoga-philosophy, and the commentator warns us against taking this as a general denial of the existence of a Lord. See also Yoga-sutras, I. 23 seq. ; and Zeitschrift dry Dmtschen Morgenltindiscfien Gesellschaft, vii. 304. 3 Bhagavadgita, translated by Telang, S. B E. viii. 92. I have abbreviated the extract and tried to make it more intelligible. 232 LECTURE IX. Lord, I wish now to see your divine form. If, O Lord, you think that it is possible for me to look upon it, then, O Lord of the possessors of mystic powers, show your inexhaustible form to me.' The Deity said : ' In hundreds and in thousands see my forms, various, divine ; see wonders in numbers unseen before. Within my body see to-day the whole universe. But you will not be able to see me with merely this eye of yours. I give you an eye divine.' Having spoken thus the great Lord showed his supreme divine form. If in the heavens, the lustre of a thousand suns burst forth all at once, that would be like the lustre of that mighty one. Then Aiv/una said : ' 0 God, I see within your body the gods, as also all the groups of various beings ; and the lord Brahman seated on his lotus seat, and all the sages and religious snakes. I see you who are of countless forms, possessed of many arms, chests, mouths, and eyes on all sides. And, O Lord of the universe ! O you of all forms ! I do not see your end or middle or beginning. I see you bearing a coronet and a mace and a discus, — a mass of glory, brilliant on all sides, difficult to look at, having on all sides the effulgence of a blazing fire of sun, and indefinable. ... I believe you to be the eternal Being. I see you . . . having the sun and moon for eyes, having a mouth like a blazing fire, and heating the universe with your radiance. The space between heaven and earth and all the quarters are pervaded by you alone. Looking at this wonder- ful and terrible form of yours the three worlds arc affrighted.' HISTORICAL TREATMENT OF RELIGIOUS QUESTIONS. 233 In Sanskrit all this sounds very grand, and when the vision is over, Krishna, assumes again his own human form. ' I cannot be seen,' he says, ' in this form by any one but yom even by the help of the study of the Vedas or of sacrifices, nor by gifts, nor by actions, nor by fierce penances. Be not alarmed, be not perplexed, at seeing this form of mine., fearful like this. Free from fear and with delightful heart, see now again that same form of mine.' The visions of Santa Theresa and of even more modern saints are so like the earlier visions of Indian heroes that we cannot be far wrong in ascribing both to the same source and treating them both with the same indulgence. Revelation. In close connection with this question, the possi- bility of an intuitive knowledge of God, another question also, that of the possibility of a revelation, of a communication of divine or absolute truth to man, — a question so hotly discussed at present, — meets us again and again in our wanderings through the history of religion. In the Veda the inspiring influence of the gods is simply taken for granted. The gods are said to have roused and sharpened the mind of the poets \ and in the end the gods them- selves were called seers and poets. As soon as the Vedic religion became systematised, and had to be defended against the doubts of friends and foes, the Erahmans elaborated an apologetic philosophy which seems to me unsurpassed in subtlety and acuteness by any other defence of a divinely inspired book. The whole of the Veda was represented as divine in ' Hibbert Lectures, p. 141 ; Rv. VI. 47, 10 ; I. 31, 1. 234 LECTURE IX. its origin, and therefore beyond the reach of doubt. It was not to be looked on as the work of men, but only as seen by inspired poets. It was supposed to date from all eternity, and to be so prehistoric in character that when unfortunately the names of real kings and real cities occurred in some of the Vedic hymns, as they do, they had to be explained away as meaning something quite different. Historical traces in the Veda. We find, for instance, in the Rig-veda III. 53, 14, the following verse : Kim te kn'nvanti Kf'kateshu gava/*, na asiram duhre na tapanti ^ gharmam, A na/j bhara Pramagandasya veda/i, Naiftasakham maghavan randhaya naft. This means : What are thy cows doing among the Kikatas ? They yield no milk, they heat no kettle ; Bring us the wealth of Pramaganda, subdue, O Maghavan, Nai/casakha ! These Kika£as are evidently a tribe which did not worship Indra and which Inclra is asked to subdue. The name does not occur again in the Rig-veda, but it is said to have been the old name of Magadha or Behar on the Ganges, the future birthplace of Bud- dhism. According to others the northern part of Behar was properly called Magadha, while the southern portion only was called Kika^a K Whatever they were, they must have been a real race, Pramaganda must have been a real king, and Nai&asiikha, even if it meant originally, as Ludwig thinks, of low birth, must have referred to some real historical character. But all this is denied by orthodox theologians. If ' J. Bird, Historical Researches, p. 2. HISTORICAL TREATMENT OP RELIGIOUS QUESTIONS. 235 it were so, they say, the Veda would not be nitya, eternal, or as we say, prehistoric. ' It has been said/ they argue, 'that the Veda has not a divine, but a human origin, and that in the same way as the Mahabharata was composed by Vyasa, the Ramayana by Valmiki, the Raglmvamsa by Kalidasa, so the Kanaka, Kauthuma, and Taittiriyaka, which are portions of the Veda, were composed by K&tha, Kuthuma, and Tittiri. And even if these names were only meant to signify that the families of Ka^a, Kuthuma, and Tittiri were in traditionary possession of these portions of the Veda, yet the fact that his- torical and real persons are mentioned in the Veda would by itself be sufficient to prove that the Veda cannot be considered as prehistoric. Now there are passages, like : " Babara, the descendant of Pravahana wished;" " Kusurubindu, the descendant of Udda- laka wished," etc. The Veda therefore must have had a beginning like all other existing things.' So far the opponent who denies the eternity of the Veda. All this, however, is stoutly denied by (raimini, the representative of the most orthodox philosophy in India. ' The Veda,' he says, ' was the word before the beginning ; it existed before all other words, such as Ka^a, Kuthuma, Tittiri, etc., so that titles of certain parts of the Veda, such as Kanaka, Kauthuma, Tait- tiriyaka, etc. contain merely the names of those who hauded down the Veda by tradition. As to such names as Babara, the son of Pravahana, they must not be taken as the names of historical persons ; but Babara is really another name of Vayu, the wind, who makes a sound like babara, and whose nature it 236 LECTURE IX. is to drive things forward, hence called pravahana (provehere). In the same manner all other historical and geographical names should be explained, ety- mologically, not historically.' This is only a small specimen of what forensic theology can achieve, and could achieve long before our own time. It enables us to see both what was originally intended by such words as God-given, God- inspired, $ruti, what has been heard, Revelation, what has been unfolded, and what was made of these words afterwards. It was the sense of an over-powering truth which led to the admission of a revelation. But while in the beginning truth made revelation, it soon came to pass that revelation was supposed to make truth. When we see this happening in every part of the world, when we can watch the psychological process which leads in the most natural way to a belief in supernatural inspiration, it will hardly be said that an historical study of religion may be useful to the antiquarian, but cannot help us to solve the burning questions of the day. But this is not what I am pleading forat present. At present I want to prove no more than that an historical study of the religions of the world possesses this one great advantage, that it familiarises us with the old problems of the philosophy of religion, and fits us for a more fearless treatment of them in their modern form. The old Problems in their simpler Form. And by showing us the various phases through which many of these problems have passed before they assumed their present form, it teaches us another and most important lesson, namely, that in attempting to solve these problems we must not attempt to solve HISTORICAL TREATMENT OF RKLIGIOUS QUESTIONS. 237 them in their modern form only, and with all the perplexities which they present to us in their often obscure metaphysical phraseology, but that we must trace them back, as far as we can, to their first begin- nings and to their simplest form. It is with these religious problems as it is with the problems of language. Who could account for lan- guage, if he only knew the language of to-day % If we knew none of the antecedents of English, as it now exists in its 250,000 words, many of them with different meanings, many of them again having one and the same meaning, even the wisest of us could say no more than what Plato said in the Cratylus, namely that language could not possibly have been invented by man1. And now that we know by what simple process language was, if not invented, at all events produced and elaborated by man, does it lower language, because it was not invented by the gods, or does it lower man because he was not presented by the gods with a language ready made ? I believe not, and I hold the same with regard to religion. If we see with what natural feelings and simple senti- ments religion began, and then follow its course till it reaches that perfect, or at all events that complete state in which we find it in later times, we shall hardly think that we degrade religion by accepting it as the most precious product of the human mind, nor shall we consider man as robbed of his dignity, be- 1 Rousseau makes the same confession. ' Quant a moi,' he writes, 'cfh;i\v des difficulty qui so multiplient, et convaincu de I'impossi- bilifce presque demontree que les langues aient pu naltre ei sYtablir par des moyens purement humains, je laisse a qui voudra d'entre- prendre la discussion de ce difficile probleme.' See De Bonald, Recherches Philosophises, p. 117. 238 LECTURE IX. cause on the day of his birth the gods did not descend from heaven to present him with a religion ready made or reduced to settled creeds and finished articles of faith, but left him to grow and to learn to stand on his own legs, and to fight his own battle in the struggle for truth. LECTURE X. COMPARATIVE STUDY OF RELIGIOUS PROBLEMS. The Problem of Creation. WHEN we study the same problem, first in the heated controversies of our own time, and then look at it from a more elevated position which allows us to watch its historical progress, in all its varying aspects, it seems often difficult to believe that the problem is really the same. And yet, if history teaches us anything, it teaches us that there is continuity in the growth of thought as in the growth of lan- guage. Let us look at the problem of creation. The question which the Vedic poet asked (X. 31, 7) when he said, ' What was the forest, what was the tree from which they hewed heaven and earth,' is in reality the same question which we ask to-day, and which has received ever so many answers from century to century, and will receive as many more, so long as heaven and earth remain. It is true these early questioners would hardly understand our language, if we tried to put them off with the nebular theories of Kant and La- place, with Lyall's explanation of the formation of the crust of the earth, or with Huxley's account of the transition of inorganic into organic protoplasm. But 240 LECTUliE X. what they were in search of was after all the same, and what they called wood, out of which heaven and earth were hewn, was but another name for v A.??, wood. materies, wood, then material and matter, something behind or antecedent to the phenomenal world, as it appears before our eyes. The Logic of Pacts. It is sometimes quite startling, after we have tried to unravel the subtle webs of philosophy, such as the so-called Gosmological, Ontological, and Teleologl< ovfifxiyes? 254 LECTURE X. Aryan authorities, could possibly settle that question in one way or the other. All I wish to show is that an historical study of the theory of creation, and of the reasons for which it was either held or rejected in different countries and in different ages, is the best preparation, nay, an indispensable preparation, before we approach the solution of the problem itself, if indeed it admits of any solution at the hand of created beings. Astronomers study the Ptolemaic before they ap- proach the Copernican system, and they become most hrmly convinced of the truth of the latter after they have themselves discovered the flaws inherent in the former system. Origin of the idea of cause. We can see how at a very early period in the growth of the human mind, the idea of a father, of a maker and fashioner of the world, was inevitable, and it is equally inevitable at the present day with large classes of people whose mind has not yet risen beyond the level of those early sages. They speak a lan- guage of their own, and with them father or maker expresses all they have to express. The ideas which an honest peasant connects with the fatherhood of God do not differ much from what the natives of California declared in their simple lan- guage, when asked as to their faith in any higher powers. 'Their God,' they declared, 'had neither father nor mother, and his origin was quite unknown. But he is present everywhere, he sees everything even at midnight, though himself invisible to human eyes. He is the friend of all good people, and punishes the evil-doers.' COMPARATIVE STUDY OF RELIGIOUS PROBLEMS. 255 If our metaphysicians define God as Causa sui, do they say much more than what the Californians meant when they said that their God had neither father nor mother ? or what the Vedic poets meant when they spoke of one who was the father of the father ? l It will hardly be believed that these Californians, with a creed to my mind more perfect than that of most nations, are classed by Sir John Lubbock among the races without any religion 2. At a later time, when the human intellect had reached a higher stage, it was no doubt inevitable that many characteristics of father and maker should have to be eliminated in order to make room for the higher concept of an author of the world. Nay, the time would come when a thinker like Heraclitus would revolt against the very idea of a manufacturer of the world, and would assert that none of the beings who were then called gods could have performed so stupendous a work. This idea of any being manufac- turing the world, as a potter on his wheel, became so repugnant to more enlightened minds, that Buddha, as we saw, declared it irreverent even to ask that question, much more to attempt to answer it. And if we turn our eyes away from that Indian sage, who became the founder of one of the great religions of the world, and ask what Des Cartes, the founder of modern philosophy, has to say on the same subject, we find a wonderful similarity of thought, in spite of great diversity of expression. ' Knowing as I do,' he writes, ' that my nature is extremely weak 1 Rv. I. 164, 16, B&h pitu/; pita asat. VI. 16, 35. - Roskoff, Das Beligwnsvoesen der rohestenNaturoolker,^. 66 ; Lubbock, Civilisation, pp. 176, 271. 256 LECTUKE X. and limited, while that of God is immeasurable, in- comprehensible, and infinite, I have no difficulty in acknowledging that he has command of an infinitude of things of which my mind cannot compass the causes ; and this alone suffices to convince me that the whole class of causes supplied by the end in view is useless in regard to natural things ; for it seems to me, it would be rash in me to investigate and undertake to recover the impenetrable ends of God V If we watch these changes of thought among men anxious for truth and for truth only, we learn at all events to approach this question in a calm and per- fectly judicial spirit. We are not carried away into mere denunciation, but are inclined to listen with equanimity both to those who assert and to those who deny the theory of creation in the ordinary sense of that word. Religions without a Creator. Unless it were known that some of the lowest as well as some of the highest races, the Negroes of Africa2, for instance, and the Buddhists of Ceylon, either ignored or rejected the idea of creation alto- gether, and yet possessed religions of great efficacy and extreme subtlety, we should doubt whether reli- gion was even possible without a belief in a Creator. But it is a fact that the very denial of a creating God arose in many cases from a too exalted conception of the deity, whether on moral or philosophical grounds. From a moral point of view it has been asserted again and again that so imperfect a world as this ought 1 Meditations, ed. Cousin, i. 297 ; Martineau, Study of Religion, i. 2/2. Reville, Lea Religions des Pmples no)i-civilises, i. 271. COMPARATIVE STUDY OF RELIGIOUS PROBLEMS. ^57 not to be looked upon as the work of a perfect Being ; while from a philosophical point of view it has been uro-ed that a belief in a Creator would involve a belief that there was a time when there was a divine cause, but no effect. The denial of a Creator, therefore, so far from being necessarily anti-religious, may be traced back to re- ligion itself, that is, to a feeling that shrinks from assigning to a Supreme Being anything unworthy of it or contradicting its essential attributes. The Theory of Evolution. If this had been clearly seen, and if our modern philosophers had learnt from history that a man who does not admit a creator is not ipso facto an atheist, a controversy which in England at least has of late excited the most passionate heat, might have been carried on with perfect scientific composure — I allude, of course, to the theory of evolution, as revived by Darwin. It was disheartening to hear the followers of Darwin stigmatised as atheists, because they rejected the theory of a Creator in the ordinary acceptation of that word. It was equally painful to see the opponents of Darwin's theories treated as mere bigots, because, if they did not accept the theory of evolution, they must believe in the account of creation as given in Genesis. Is there no room left then in our modern schools of philosophy for men like Descartes ? It was owing to a want of what I should like to call ' historical preparedness ' that all this unseemly squabbling about evolution was stirred up. In Germany the idea of evolution had so completely s 258 LECTURE X. pervaded the popular literature and become so familiar to every thinking man that I was as much surprised at the excitement caused by the ' Origin of Species,' as by the ferment stirred up by ' Essays and Eeviews.' Darwin's book ushered in a new intellectual spring, but it produced no cataclysm in the world of science. As, however, we have lately been told again, after it seemed that the principal disputants had become more reasonable, that Darwin's theory of evolution forms a kind of deluge, dividing ante-diluvian from post-diluvian science, a few remarks on the real history and meaning of evolution may not be out of place at the point which we have reached in our own argument. We want to establish the advantages which the Historical has over the Theoretic Method, whether in the Science of Religion or in every other department of human knowledge. Let us see then what advantages it would have conferred, if it had been adopted by the principal disputants in the Darwinian controversy. Meaning of Evolution. Let us, first of all, see clearly what this word evolu- tion really means, if applied to nature or to anything else. Evolution is really the same as history, if we take it in its objective sense. Subjectively, history ([aropia) meant originally inquiry, or a desire to know ; it then came to mean knowledge, obtained by inquiry ; and lastly, in a purely objective sense, the objects of such knowledge. Natural History was originally an inquiry about nature (fj -nepl (frvaecos laropia) ; then knowledge of COMPARATIVE STUDY OF RELIGIOUS PROBLEMS. 259 nature, while we now use Natural History in the sense of the facts of nature. The same with political history. It meant at first an inquiry into political events, then a knowledge and likewise a coherent account of such events, and lastly, these political events themselves, as known by historians and philo- sophers. History, however, if it is worthy of its name, is more than a mere acquaintance with facts and dates. It is the study of a continuous process in the events of the world, the discovery of cause and effect, and, in the end, of a law that holds the world together. Apply this historical study to nature, and try to dis- cover in it an uninterrupted succession of cause and effect, a continuity which holds the whole of nature together ; and what is this but what is now called evolution* Evolution, if only properly understood, has always seemed to me a very old friend ; it is history, or what used to be called pragmatic history, under a new name. What used to be called the history of language, is now called its evolution. What used to be studied under the name of the his- tory of law and religion, is now presented to us as the evolution of law and religion. Suppose there were no evolution in language, in law or in religion, would there be a history"? Would they admit of any scientific treatment at all ? Nay, is not evolution, if we look at it sharply, nothing but an alias for causality in all our experience, and, in the end, from Kant's point of view, a necessity inherent in all rational thought 1 Entivickelung is a very old word in German, and seemed very harmless ; but when it appeared in its English disguise as evolution, it was S 2 260 LECTURE X. supposed to portend revolution, and all that is terrible and destructive. I can understand a man not be- lieving in gravitation, but a rational being denying evolution in its true sense ceases ipso facto to be a rational being. Darwin admits a Creator. We saw that with regard to the origin of the world, evolutionary theories were much older than any others. And yet when Darwin and others brought forward their accumulated knowledge in support of what may almost be called the primeval theory of evolution, the outcry against it became so overwhelm- ing that even Darwin himself seems to have been frightened, and glad to avail himself, as he tells us, of the support of an eminent theologian. Darwin writes 1 : ' I see no good reason why the views given in this volume should shock the reli- gious feelings of any one ... A celebrated author and divine has written to me that he has gradually learnt to see that it is just as noble a conception of the Deity to believe that He created a few original forms capable of self-development into other and needful forms, as to believe that he organised a fresh act of creation to supply the voids caused by the action of his laws.' Herder, the precursor of Darwin. Darwin has often been blamed by his disciples for what they consider a ' timid concession to the pre- judices of theologians/ and yet there are theologians to whom even that concession does not seem to no 1 Science of Thought, p. 105 COMPARATIVE STUDY OF RELIGIOUS PROBLEMS. 261 far enough — so well are they acquainted, as they imagine, with 'the impenetrable ends of God.' I do not know who that celebrated author and di- vine may have been, but Darwin, if he had been better acquainted with the history of philosophy during the last century, ought to have known a most celebrated author and divine, the friend of Goethe and Schiller and Kant, who not only gave the sanction of his office, which was as high as that of any bishop in England, to the theory of evolution, but worked it out himself in so comprehensive a spirit, and, at the same time, in so much detail that in reading his books we seem to be reading an edition of Darwin, only published a hundred years ago. I am speaking of Herder, who was the head of the church in Saxe- Weimar, and at the same time one of the greatest philosophers and writers that Germany has ever produced. He was born in the same year as Lamarck, 1744, and died in 1803, Lamarck in 1829. I must read you a few extracts from his Ideen zur Plt'do- sophie der Menschheit (1784) in order to show you that I am by no means exaggerating when I call Herder the Darwin of the eighteenth century. Herder traces the process of evolution from in- organic to organic nature, from the crystal through plants and animals to man, the younger brother of the animals, as he calls him. ' From stone to crystal,' he writes \ ' from crystal to metals, from metals to the creation of plants, from plants to animals, and from these to man, we see the form of organisation rising higher and higher, and with it the forces and .impulses of the creature becoming 1 Ideen zur Geschichte d, ,■ M< nschfa it, Funftea Buch, p. 122. 262 LECTURE X. differentiated, till all that can be comprehended in one became united in the human form. With man the series stops ; we know of no creature above him, more complex and perfect in its organisation. Man seems to be the highest form which an earth-organism can reach.' When Herder touches the problem of the beginning of life, he allows himself some poetic licence. ' In the sight of the eternal Being,' he writes, ' the shape of a small particle of ice, as it forms itself, and of a flake of snow on its surface, has some analogous relationship to the formation of the embryo.' (p. 49.) 1 The plant is a higher kind of organisation than all formations of the earth, and the kingdom of plants has so wide an extension that it loses itself in those formations, and on the other hand approaches the animal kingdom in several of its germs and varieties. The plant possesses a kind of life and stages of life, it has sex, fructification, birth and death. The surface of the earth was ready for it before it was ready for animals and men. The plant pushes forward before them, and with its grasses, mildew, and mosses clings to those barren rocks which have not yet been trodden by the foot of any living thing.' Herder then traces the transition from plants to plant-animals. ' The nutritive organs,' he says (p. 63), ' are already separated in them ; they have something analogous to animal sensation and voluntary motion ; but their principal organic power is still nutrition and propagation.' He then proceeds to molluscs, insects, cold-blooded and warm-blooded animals, and points to the elements in which they live, or what is some- times ailed their environment, as a determining cause COMPARATIVE STUDY OF RELIGIOUS PROBLEMS. 263 of their peculiar organisation. ' The bird,' he says (p. 51), ' flies in the air ; every deviation of its form from that of terrestrial animals can be accounted for by its element. As soon as it touches the earth again, even if only in some monstrous intermediate form, as in bats and vampires, it assimilates itself to the human skeleton. The fish swimming in the water has its hands and feet grown together in fins and a tail, and there is little articulation in its limbs. As soon as it dwells on land, it develops, like the manatee, at least its forefeet, and the female develops mamiDte. The sea-bear and sea-lion show clearly their four feet, though they are not able as yet to use their hind feet, but drag their five toes like rags of fins behind. They creep along quietly to warm themselves in the rays of the sun, and have advanced a step beyond the dulness of the misshapen seal. Thus there is progress from the dust of worms, from the chalk- houses of molluscs, and from the webs of insects towards more fully articulated and higher organisations.' . . . 'Each species takes care of itself (p. 45), as if it were the only one in existence ; but by its side there is another species which limits it, and in this mutual relation of different and opposite species nature in its creative power found the means of preserving the whole.' Herder then proceeds to show how in this struggle for existence whole species of animals and of men may have perished, while yet a general equilibrium was maintained. Man is in Herders eyes no more than the brother of the animals (p. 44). Nay, he goes further, and in order to bring down tho pride of man 264 LECTURE X. he reminds him (p. 54) that he is nothing but a digestive tube (an ascidian), like his lowest brethren. He tells Buffon (p. 85) that he is wasting his eloquence in vain in denying the uniformity of organism in ape and man, and that the facts which he has collected himself refute him. And yet the same Herder sees as clearly as any- body the specific difference of man and animal. After showing (p. 57) how irritations of the senses produce a reaction and a corresponding impulse, how sensa- tions result in thought, and how there is in every living organism a perpetual progress, he points to language as a divine gift by which alone our slum- bering reason was awakened, or by which the mere faculty which by itself would have remained dead for ever, became living force (p. 101). 'Animals,' he says (p. 104), 'are truly called in the East the Silent ones of the earth; for with the organisation of language only did man receive the breath of the deity, the seed of reason and eternal perfection, an echo of that creative call to the lordship of the earth, in fact the divine art of ideas, the mother of all arts.' These ideas enunciated by Herder became the intel- lectual property of the whole of Germany, and reigned supreme in schools and universities during the early part of this century. In the school of Oken, in the first philosophy of Schelling, in the eloquent treatises of Goethe, all was evolution, development, or, as it was called in more general language, Das Werden, the Becoming. The same spirit, though in a higher sense, pervaded the philosophy of Hegel. According to him the whole world, as conceived by man, was an evolu- tion, a development by logical necessity, to which all COMPARATIVE STUDY OF RELIGIOUS PROBLEMS. 265 facts must bow. If they would not, then tant pis pour lesfaits. Evolution in the beginning- of our century. I do not remember the heyday of that school, but I still remember its last despairing struggles. I still remember at school and at University rumours of carbon, half solid, half liquid, the famous Urschleim, now called Protoplasm1, the substance out of which everything was evolved. I remember the more or less amusing discussions about the loss of the tail, and about races supposed to be still in possession of that ancestral appendage. I do not know whether Lord Monboddo's works are still read in Scotland, but whoever wishes for evidence in support of our descent from hairy and tailed ancestors, will find more startling evidence in his portly quartos than in any of Darwin's publications. Gottfried Hermann. T well remember my own particular teacher, the great Greek scholar Gottfried Hermann2, giving great otfence to his theological colleagues by publishing an essay in 1840 in which he tried to prove the descent of man from an ape. Allow me to quote a few extracts from this rare and little-noticed essay. As the female is always less perfect than the male, Her- mann, now nearly fifty years ago, argued that the law of development required that Eve must have existed 1 The deep-sea ooze which Haeckel took for the physical basis of all life and the Protogenes Haeckelii have both been surrendered long ago. 2 'Evam ante Adamum creatam fuisse, sive de quodam communi apud Mosen et Hesiodum errore circa creationem generis humani,' in Ilgen's Zeitschriftfur die histvr. Theologie, 1840. B. x. pp. 61-70. 266 LECTURE X. before Adam, not Adam before Eve. Quoting the words of Ennius, Simia quam similis, turpissima bestia, nobis, he goes on in his own peculiar Latin : — ' Ex hac nobili gente quid dubitemus unam ali- quando simiam exortam putare, quae paullo minus belluina facie et indole esset? Ea, sive illam Evam sive Pandoram appellare placet, quum ex alio simio gravida facta esset, peperit, ut saepenumero fieri con- stat, filium matri quam patri similiorem, qui primus homo fuit. ' Haec ergo est hominis generisque humani origo, non ilia quidem valde honesta. sed paullo tamen honestior multoque probabilior, quam si ex luto aqua permixto, cui anima fuerit inspirata, genus duce- remus.' Surely Gottfried Hermann was a bolder man than even Darwin, and to me, who had attended his lec- tures at Leipzig in 1841. Darwin's Descent of Man. published in 1871, was naturally far less novel and far less startling by its theory than by the new facts by which that theory was once more supported. Kant on the Chimpanzee. Kant's philosophy also had long familiarised students of Anthropology with the same ideas. For he, too. towards the end of his Anthropologic, had spoken of a future period in the development of nature, when an Oran-Utang or Chimpanzee may develop his organs of locomotion, touch, and speech to the perfection of human organs, raise his brain to an organ of thought, and slowly elevate himself by social culture. I cannot admire such airy speculations, even if they come from Kant, but I ask, Is there anything in Darwin so COMPARATIVE STUDY OF RELIGIOUS PROBLEMS. 267 much more startling and novel than these theories of Herder, Gottfried Hermann, and Kant ? Darwin. Darwin felt compelled by the enormous weight of analogy to adopt the theory that man is the genea- logical descendant of some kind of ape. Haeckel adds that the statement that man was developed from lower vertebrates, and proximately from genuine apes, is a special deduction which follows with absolute certainty from the general induction of the theory of descent K Even if that were so, it would remain a deduction from a general intuition of a theory of descent ; it would remain a theoretical conviction of an eminent zoologist. But we must not forget that another eminent zoologist, who yields to no one either in knowledge or in outspoken honesty, I mean Virchow, has never on this point allowed himself to be carried away by mere analogy, or even by the powerful pleading of Darwin. We know how able and persuasive a pleader Darwin could be, but all his eloquence was in vain against the conscientious con- victions of Virchow. When Darwin wished to show how man could have been born of an animal which was hairy and remained so during life, he could not well maintain that an animal without hair was fitter to survive than an animal with hair. He therefore appealed to sexual selection, and wished us to believe that our female semi-human progenitrix lost her hair by some accident, became thus, as Hermann would have said, minus belluina facie et indole, minus belluina, sed 1 See Roskoff, Religionswesen, p. 165. 268 LECTUKE X. magi s bella, so that in the process of time this partial or complete baldness, call it leprosy or leucoderma, was perpetuated from mother to son, and made us what we are. Oken. These theories put forward by Herder and Kant, and more or less seriously advocated by Gottfried Her- mann, found the most enthusiastic defender in Oken. Oken (1779-1851) was not satisfied with deriving man from an animal. He and his disciples taught that the transition from inorganic to organic nature was likewise a mere matter of development. The first step, according to him, was the formation of rising bubbles, such as we see in champagne, which he at that time called infusoria, and the manifold repetition of which led, as he taught, to the formation of plants and animals. The plant was represented by him as an imperfect animal, the animal as an im- perfect man. To doubt that the various races of men were descended from one pair was considered at that time, and even so late as the days of Prichard, not only a theological, but a biological heresy. All variety was traced back to unity — and in the beginning there was nothing but Being ; which Being, coming in conflict with Not-being, entered upon the process of Becoming, of development, of evolution. Reaction. While this philosophy was still being preached in some German universities, a sharp reaction took place in others, followed by the quick ascendency of that Historical School of which I spoke in a former lecture. It was heralded in Germany by such men as Niebuhr, Savigny, Bopp, Grimm, Otfried Miiller, Johannes COMPARATIVE STUDY OF RELIGIOUS PROBLEMS. 269 Midler, the two Humboldts, and many others whose names are less widely known in England, but who did excellent work, each in his own special line. Historical School : its true character. It would be a great mistake to suppose that the Historical School was exclusively concerned with the history of problems, that it cared for the past only, and not for the present and the future. On the contrary, that school wants to show that there is no break between the past and the present, but that an uninterrupted continuity connects what has been thought of old with what is being thought at present. History is to teach us to understand what is, by teaching us to understand what has been. All our present difficulties are difficulties of our own making. All the tangles at which we are so impatiently pulling were made either by ourselves, or by those who came before us. Who else should have made them 1 The Historical School, knowing how hopeless it is to pull and tear at a tangled reel by main force, quietly takes us behind the scenes, and shows us how first one thread and then another and a third, and in the end hundreds and thousands of threads went wrong, and became entangled, but how in the begin- ning they lay before man's eyes as even and as regular as on a weaver's loom. Men who possess the historical instinct, and who, whenever they have to deal with any of the grave problems of our age, always ask how certain diffi- culties and apparent contradictions first arose, are what we should call practical men ; and, as a rule, they are far more successful in unravelling knotty questions than the philosopher who has a theory and 270 LECTUKE X. a remedy ready for everything, and who actually prides himself on his ignorance of the past. Stanley. I think I can best make my meaning clear by taking a well-known instance. Whether Dean Stanley was what is now called a scientific historian, a very laborious student of ancient chronicles and charters, is not for me to say ; but if I were asked to define his mind, and his attitude towards all the burning- questions of the day, whether in politics, or morality, or religion, I should say it was historical. He was a true disciple of the Historical School. I could show it by examining the position he took in dealing with some of the highest questions of theology. But I prefer, as an easier illustration, to consider his treat- ment of one of the less exciting questions, the ques- tion of vestments. Incredible as it may sound to us, it is a fact nevertheless that not many years ago a controversy about surplices, and albs, and dalmatics, and stoles was raging all over England. The ques- tion by whom, at what time, and in what place, the surplice should be worn, divided brother from brother, and father from child, as if that piece of white linen possessed some mysterious power, or could exercise some miraculous influence on the spirit of the wearer. Any one who knew Stanley would know how little he cared for vestments or garments, and how difficult he would have found it to take sides, either right or left, in a controversy about millinery or ritual. But what did he do ? ' Let us look at the surplice his- torically,' he said. What is a surplice ?— and first of all, what is the historical origin or the etymology of the word? Surplice is the Latin super-petticium. COMPARATIVE STUDY OF RELIGIOUS PROBLEMS. 271 Super-pell icium means what is worn over a fur or fur-jacket, which was called pelliciwm. Now this fur-jacket was not worn by the primitive Christians in Rome, or Constantinople, or Jerusalem, nor is there any mention of such a vestment at the time of the Apostles. What, then, is the history of that fur- jacket ? So far as we know, it .was a warm jacket worn by peasants in countries of colder climate, worn in many countries to the present day. Like most of the garments which we now consider as exclusively ecclesiastical, it was worn by clergy and laity alike. As this fur-jacket was apt to get dirty and unsightly, a kind of smock-frock or blouse, that could be washed from time to time, was worn over it — and this was called the supev-pellicium, the surplice. Stanley thought it sufficient gently to remind the wearer of the surplice that what he was so proud of was only the lineal descendant of a German peasant's blouse ; and I believe he was right, and his historical explanation certainly produced a better effect on all who had a sense of history and of humour than the most elaborate argument on the mystical meaning of that robe of purity and innocence. Nor did this historical denouement take away from the true character of the surplice. Being worn over the every-day garment, the shabby and dirty fur-coat, it was a sign of real respect both for the sacred building in which it was worn, and for the congregation of the faithful whose minister the wearer of the surplice was. That was the real meaning of the white and pure surplice, and we find here as elsewhere that we never lose anything that is worth having, bv historical truth. 272 LECTURE X. Stanley rendered the same service to other vest- ments. Under the wand of the historian, the alb turned out to be the old Roman tunic or shirt, and the deacon officiating in his alb was recognised as a servant working in his shirt-sleeves. The dalmatic, again, was traced back to the shirt with long sleeves worn by the Dalmatian peasants, which became re- cognised as the dress of the deacon about the time of Constantine. The chasuble 1 turned out to be a great-coat, worn originally by laity and clergy alike ; while the cope, descended from the copa or capa, also called pluviale, was translated by Stanley as a ' waterproof.' The mitre was identified with the caps and turbans worn in the East by princes and nobles, and to this day by the peasant women. The division into two points was shown to be the mark of the crease which is the consequence of its having been folded and carried under the arm, like an opera- hat. The stole, lastly, in the sense of a scarf, had a still humbler origin. It was the substitute for the ovarium or handkerchief, used for blowing the nose. No doubt, the possession and use of a handkerchief was in early times restricted to the ' higher circles.' It is so to the present day in Borneo, for instance, where only the king is allowed to carry a hand- kerchief and to blow his nose in that way. In like manner then as in Borneo the handkerchief became the insignia of royalty, it rose in the Roman Church to become the distinctive garment of the deacon. 1 Chasuble, Low Lat. casabula, a little house ; cassock, Ital. casacca, a little house. Super-peUicium, from peUis, skin ; but plush, Fr. peluche, from pilucius, hairy, Lat. pilus, hair. Wig, Old Ital. piluccare, to j>luck the hair; Sardinian pilucca, a mass of hair: Span, peluca ; Port, peruca; Ital. parruca ; Fr. perruqm ; Germ. Per&cke; Dutch peruyh ; Old Engl, perwigge, periwig, ivig. COMPARATIVE STUDY OP RELIGIOUS PROBLEMS. 273 I know that some of these explanations have been contested, perhaps rightly contested, but the general drift of the argument remains unaffected by such reservations. I only quote them in order to explain what I meant by Stanley's historical attitude, the very attitude which all who belong to the Historical School, and are guided by an historical spirit, like to assume when brought face to face with the problems of the day. What I maintain then is that a study of the history of philosophy would in this as in other instances have proved an immense advantage. It would have prevented on the one hand the foolish outcry against Darwin's works, as if they had broached an unheard- of heresy, and it would have moderated on the other the extravagant and ignorant panegyrics \ detested, I feel sure, by no one more than by Darwin himself. Darwin's real merit consisted, not in discovering evolution, but in suggesting new explanations of evolution, such as natural selection, survival of the fittest, influence of environment, sexual selection, etc. These explanations, whether they are still adequate or not, give to Darwin his commanding position in the history of natural philosophy. We know at present that, from a physiological point of view, the transition from any other animal to man has not been established ; and we likewise know that, if it ever were established, it would leave us exactly as we are, divided by language, as by an impassable Rubicon, from every other animal. The nearer the 1 'Eav 8' kirl pLiKpoh tis aepvvvrjrai, roaovr' a-ne\ti tov TifxTJs tivus 5ia ravra Tv\eiv, aiar' aneiponaXos irpus i$o£(v dvai. Demosth, Androl., p. 6ir: T 274 LECTURE X. approach between the physical nature of an ape and that of a man, the wider and the more wonderful will that gulf appear which language has fixed between them 1. Necessity of Historical Study of Religion. If therefore I maintain the necessity of an historical and comparative study of religion, or venture to re- present it as the best preparation for the study of what is called the philosophy of religion, what I mean is that it acclimatises and invigorates our mind, and produces that judicial temper which is so essential in the treatment of religious problems. Whatever philo- sophy may have to teach us hereafter, it will prove useful in the mean time to have learnt from history at least so elementary a lesson as that no opinion is true, simply because it has been held either by the greatest intellects or by the largest number of human beings at different periods in the history of the world. No one can spend years of his life in the study of the religions of the world, beginning with the lowest and ending with the highest forms, no one can watch the sincerity of religious endeavour, the warmth of religious feeling, the nobleness of religious conduct among races whom we are inclined to call either pagan or savage, without learning at all events a lesson of humility. Anybody, be he Jew, Christian, 1 Mr. Romanes, in his recent work on Mental Evolution in Man, 1888, has summed up the old arguments in favour of a possible transition from animal to human intellect with great ingenuity, but he has not refuted the facts on the other side, and in several cases hardly apprehended their force. Even his conception of evolution seems to me far from correct. Again , when he states that I admit not more than 121 roots as the residue of an analysis of Aryan speech, he mistakes roots for radical concepts, and Aryan for Sanskrit. Whatever we may hope to achieve in future, we have not as yet reduced the number of Sanskrit roots to less than 800. COMPARATIVE STUDY OF RELIGIOUS PROBLEMS. 275 Mohammedan or Brahman, if he has a spark of modesty left, must feel that it would be nothing short of a miracle that his own religion alone should be perfect throughout, while that of every other be- liever should be false and wrong from beginning to end. History teaches us that religions change and must change with the constant changes of thought and language in the progress of the human race. The Vedic religion led on to the religion of the Upanishads, the religion of the Upanishads led on to the doctrines which Buddha embodied in a new religion. Not only the Jewish religion, but the religion of Greece and Rome also, had to yield to Christianity as more on a level with the height of thought reached after long struggles by the leading nations of the world. It is wonderful, no doubt, to see religions belonging to an almost prehistoric stratum of thought, such as ancient Brahmanism, surviving to the present day in a modified, yet not always more elevated form. But even this becomes historically intelligible, if we con- sider that society consists of different intellectual strata. Some of the reformers of our own religion four hundred years ago stood on an eminence which even now is far beyond the reach of the majority. In theology, as in geology, the whole scale of super- imposed strata is often exhibited on the surface of the present day, and there may still be Silurians walking about among us in broad daylight. It seems as if an historical study of religion alone could enable us to understand those Silurians, nay help us to sym- pathise with them, and to honour them for the excellent use which they often make of the small talent com- mitted to them. T 2 276 LECTURE X. Criticisms answered. After having said so much in support of the His- torical School, more particularly for a right study of re- ligion. I feel bound in conclusion to notice some recent criticisms which seem to me to arise from a complete misapprehension of the character of that school. It has been observed by an eminent Scotch theologian \ that the tendency to substitute history for science, and the historical method for the scientific method, is prevalent in the present day in theology, as well as in ethics and jurisprudence, social philosophy and political economy. ' Obviously, however,' he says, ' it rests on exaggeration and illusion, and confounds things which ought to be distinguished. Neither history of the objects of a science, nor history of the ideas or doc- trines of a science, is science, and the historical method of itself can only give us, in connexion with science, either or both of these forms of history. It is therefore inherently absurd to suppose that the historical method can be sufficient in such theological disciplines as Natural Theology and Christian Dog- matics. In reality it is not directly or immediately available in the study of these disciplines at all, and that just because it does not directly or immediately yield theory, doctrine, science. Only he who knows both the history of the objects and the history of the ideas of a science, and especially of a psychological, social, or religious science, can be expected to advance the science.' Is not that an admission which covers all we claim for the Historical School, namely that it alone is able to advance the science of religion1? But 1 R. Flint, in Encyclopedia Britannica, s. v. Theology, p. 266. COMPARATIVE STUDY OF RELIGIOUS PROBLEMS. 277 he goes on : — ' In the sphere of religion, as in every other sphere, to confound history with science is to eliminate and destroy science; but in no sphere is knowledge of history more a condition of the attain- ment of science, and historical research, properly con- ducted, more serviceable to scientific investigation, than in that of religion.' I claim no more, and should be quite satisfied by this admission. And lastly : ' To the historical method we owe, not only the historical disciplines of theology, but also in a considerable measure the recent progress of its positive or theoretical disciplines. It can never, however, be, as some fanatical disciples of the his- torical school would have us to suppose, the method of these last.' This is, as you will perceive, very strong language, arising no doubt from a very strong conviction. But you will generally find that if one philosopher, who is not a fool, calls another philosopher who is not a fool either, absurd, there is some misunderstanding between the two. Now the historical school, because it calls itself historical, does not profess to devote itself to the history only of any given science. There are, for instance, the inductive sciences, and there is a history of the inductive sciences. Now the historical school never intended to limit itself to the study of the history of these sciences. That is a subject by itself. What the historical school meant to teach was that no actual problem of any science should be studied without a reference to what had been said or written on that problem from the day on which it was first started to the present day. I see no other, 278 LEOTUKE X. or at all events, no better means by which the mind could be strengthened and matured for grappling with any problem. The very mistakes of those who came before us, serve us often as finger-posts for our own line of research. Suppose a man were to study Comparative Philology without making himself ac- quainted with the labours of Bopp, and Pott, and Grimm, with their false as well as their true dis- coveries, what a waste of time would it entail on him to explore afresh all the avenues which they had explored and many of which they had found to lead to nothing! Or suppose a man should attempt the etymology of a modern word, without tracing it back, first of all, to its earliest form that is within our reach. We should then have again such etymologies as ear of corn being the same as ear, while, if we only go as far back as Gothic, we find ahs for ear of corn, but auso for ear. Nor should it be supposed that history ends with the last century. The principle of the historical school is not to ignore the present, but to try to understand the present by means of the past. A man may be a philosopher, no doubt, without knowing Plato or Aristotle or Descartes or Kant; but unless he is a man of marvellous intuition, he will never acquire that sure judgment and that sense of pro- portion which can only be acquired by an acquaintance with many minds. His philosophy will be in great danger of becoming an anachronism. But whatever may be possible in other sciences, let no one venture on the open sea of religious dis- cussion without having the compass of history steadily before his eyes. Let no one attempt to study Natural COMPARATIVE STUDY OF RELIGIOUS PROBLEMS. 279 Religion without having served his apprenticeship as a patient student of the history of the religions of the world. I cannot sum up the advantages of historical study and of the historical spirit in dealing with all the' problems of life better than in the words of Mr. John Morley : ' It gives us a view of the ground we stand on. It gives us a solid backing of precedent and experiences. It teaches us where we are. It protects us against imposture and surprise ! ' x John Morley, On the Study of Literature, p. 11. LECTURE XI. THE MATERIALS FOR THE STUDY OF NATURAL RELIGION. Language, Myth, Customs and Laws, Sacred Books. TTAVING first determined by means of definition ±± the exact limits of Natural Religion, and having afterwards explained the reasons why the Historical Method seems to be the most advantageous for a truly scientific treatment of the religions of the world, we have now to find out what materials there are accessible to us from which to study the growth and decay of Natural Religion in the widest sense of the word. These materials may be divided into four classes. First comes language, which in its continuous growth leads us back to the earliest periods of thought, or, at all events, to periods which cannot be reached by any other kind of evidence. The second class is formed by what it is the fashion to call mythology, which, as I shall show, is really an inevitable phase in the development of language and thought. The third class of evidence comprises religious customs and laws, which may be studied either in historical documents, or by actual observation of such MATERIALS FOE THE STUDY OP NATURAL RELIGION. 281 customs and laws as are still prevalent among civilised as well as uncivilised races. The fourth class consists of the /Sacred Books of the great religions of the world. Language as Evidence. If, as I hope to show, every word was originally a deed, was, in fact, a creative act, calling into life a concept which did not exist before, it will sound less surprising that it is possible to discover in words, taken by themselves, a record of the most primitive thoughts of mankind. It is true that a dictionary by itself conveys no meaning, and that it is only in a sentence that words become significant. But we know now that originally every word was a sentence. When a man said sar-it, river, he really said, 'run- ning (s a r) here (it)'; when he said dar-u, tree, he said, 'splitting (da r) here (u).' But men who called their trees ' splitting here,' or what is split, must have been men who had learnt to use trees for certain purposes, and who probably possessed some tools, however rude, to help them in carrying out their work. Men who called their horse a quick runner, as-va, equus, Ittitos, must have been men to whom the horse had become useful as a runner, for there were many wild animals quicker than the horse, though they were not even singled out for a name, but were comprehended under the general term of wild animals. You will see now how, if we can but find an en- trance into the ancient workshop of language, we can still listen there to the earliest thoughts of man. But where is that workshop ? In order to answer that question, I shall have to 282 LECTURE XI. devote some of my next lectures to giving you a short account of the discoveries made by the students of the Science of Language. That science has opened before us a new world, and it will be necessary for me to place before you a map of that new world, though in the broadest outline only, in order that you may be able to watch the earliest migrations, not only of language, but of thought, of myth, of religion, and of law and custom. Survey of Languages. Aryan Family. Let us begin with Europe, and in Europe with England1. English. Have you ever asked yourselves what it means that we speak English, what a language is, what the English language is, where it sprang up or how it was made, and how it came to be spoken in these distant isles, and from thence again over nearly the whole civilised world ? Nothing seems to me so wonderful as the power which man possesses of ceasing to wonder at what is most wonderful. It has been said with great truth that a sign or wonder can never exist twice, for when it happened the second time we should call it quite natural, and cease to wonder at it. Some philosophers go even further and maintain that a sign or wonder ceases to exist the moment it does exist, because whenever it exists, there must have been a sufficient 1 I have left here this short survey of languages, which I found it necessary to give in my first course of lectures, in order to avoid the necessity of explaining again and again the names and the relationship of the languages in which the religions of the world found their expression. Readers who require fuller information, may consult my Lectures on the Science of Language. MATEKIALS FOR THE STUDY OF NATURAL RELIGION. 283 reason for it, and whatever has a sufficient reason, ceases to be wonderful. Well, whatever the reason may be, we certainly all of us seem to have acquired what Orientals consider a proof of the highest breed- ing, namely to wonder at nothing, to be surprised by nothing, the old Nil admirari. Here we find ourselves in a small island, adjacent to what is a mere promontory of the vast Asiatic continent. And in this small island which we call Great Britain, and in this mere promontory which we call the Continent of Europe, we speak a language which is to all intents and purposes the same as that which is spoken in Ceylon, an island adjacent to the southern promontory of the same Asiatic continent, called the Dekhan or Southern India. This discovery of the unity of language in India and England is only about a hundred years old, and when it was first announced, it startled some of the most learned and judicious men to that extent that Dugald Stewart, for instance, declared it was an utter impossibility, and that Sanskrit must be an invention of those arch-deceivers, the Brahmans, who wanted to make themselves as good as ourselves, and as old as ourselves ; nay, a great deal better and a great deal older too. We have recovered from that surprise, and we find now at the beginning of most Latin and Greek grammars a few paragraphs about the Indo-European or Aryan family of speech, and a statement that much may be learnt from Sanskrit, the sacred lan- guage of the inhabitants of India, as to the ante- cedents of our own language, and as to how Latin and Greek became what they are. 284 LECTURE XI. But there are still greater miracles in English such as we find it spoken at the present day, if only we had eyes to see and ears to hear them. English is said to consist of 250,000 words, and most of these words are capable of ever so many changes which we call declension, conjugation, degrees of comparison, composition, and all the rest. That is to say, there is ready made for every one of us an instrument with at least several millions of keys on which we play, as if it were a pianoforte with ninety- six keys. When uncivilised people hear an organ for the first time, they generally feel a curiosity to open it, to see how it acts, and what it is made of. But this gigantic organ which we call our language, we never try to open, we never ask how it was made or who made it. No, we take it for granted or given, and we think we may thump and hammer on it to our heart's content, trusting that it will always remain in tune. Veda, 018a. But though the relationship between the languages of India, Persia, Armenia, Greek, Latin, Celtic, Slavonic, and Teutonic has now become part and parcel of the general stock of knowledge, it is seldom realised how close that relationship really is. It is known that the roots of all these languages are the same, that their grammatical articulation is the same, that a number of important words, such as the numerals, names for father, mother, sky, sun and moon, horse and cow, are the same. But it was only a study of Sanskrit, and of the most ancient, the Vedic Sanskrit, which enabled scholars to discover that MATERIALS FOR THE STUDY OF NATURAL RELIGION. 285 so mysterious a change as that which we observe, for instance, in the vowels of to ivit, to know, and / ivot, I know, or in German in Ich weiss, I know, and Wir wissen, we know, has its first cause in a change of accent which took place in the most ancient Sanskrit. We must remember that the accent exists, or, at all events, is marked in Vedic Sanskrit only, that it was in fact unknown to scholars till the Veda began to be studied, and we shall then understand what it means that a change of accent observed in Sanskrit three thousand years ago, still determines the vowels of words which we use to-day. I wot is the AS. wdt, the Gothic wait, I know. We have the infinitive preserved in the phrase to wit. This wit is the Sanskrit vid, to know. From it is formed in Sanskrit a perfect ve'da, having the meaning of the present, just like the Greek olba, i. e. Faida. The change of i into ai or e is due to the accent, which in Sanskrit falls in the singular on the first syllable. This diphthong ai in Sanskrit, ai in Gothic, becomes regularly a in AS., and o in English. But that is not all. Why did the Greeks say otba in the singular, but lo-^v in the plural ? In Greek the accent does not move, it remains throughout on the first syllable. But in Sanskrit the accent which is on the first syllable in the singular, must migrate in the plural to the last syllable. Why it did so, is a question difficult to answer, but the most natural reason seems to be that the differentiating terminations in the plural continued to be felt as such, and therefore retained their stress longer than those of the singular. Hence we say ve'da, vettha, veda, but vidmas, vida, vid us. This rule and this rule alone enables 286 LECTURE XL us to account for la-fiev in ancient Greek, for Teh weiss and Wir wissen in modern German. This will give you an idea of the solidarity, as the French call it, that binds the languages, and, if the languages, then the thoughts of all the members of the Aryan people together. And now as to their various degrees of relationship. Anglo-Saxon. English, as now spoken, may be traced back in one uninterrupted line to Anglo-Saxon. Of Anglo-Saxon we have the earliest documents in the seventh cen- tury, such as the Beowulf, an ancient epic of Teutonic origin. The language in which that poem is written was brought to England, or rather to the British isles, by emigrants and conquerors who came from the Con- tinent. They were, as you know, Jutes, Saxons, and Angles, and they all spoke, not High German, but Low German. Low German does not mean vulgar German, but the German spoken in the low-lands of Germany. This Low German is in fact one of the four principal branches of the Teutonic class of the Aryan family, the other branches being Gothic, Scan- dinavian, and High German. Gothic. Gothic was spoken on the Danube in the fourth century, and it has left us the oldest specimens of Teutonic speech, the translation of the Bible of Ulfilas, who died in 381. Continental Saxon. Low German comprises the Saxon of the Continent, preserved to us in the Heljand, a poem of the ninth MATERIALS FOR THE STUDY OF NATURAL RELIGION. 287 century ; the Anglo-Saxon, which we have already mentioned ; the Old Frisian, known to us by docu- ments of the thirteenth century, and slowly dying out at the present day; and lastly the Old Dutch, or Low Franconian, of which we have specimens in the so- called Carolingian Psalms, ascribed to the ninth cen- tury, and which is afterwards represented by Middle Dutch, Modern Dutch, Flemish, and the spoken Low Franconian. Scandinavian. The third branch, the Scandinavian, is represented by the Old Scandinavian literature between 800 and 1000 A.D., and is divided into (1) West-Nordish, i.e. Icelandic, and Norwegian, with a literature dating from the eleventh century ; and the East-Nordish, that is, Swedish and Danish. The ancient literature of Iceland, the two Eddas and numerous Sagas, will be of great importance to us for mythological purposes. These three branches have one common character- istic feature, they are all under what is called 'Grimm's Law,' that is to say, to put it broadly, they offer an aspirate where the other Aryan languages have a tenuis, they offer a tenuis where the others have a media, and they offer a media where the others have an aspirate. We must not suppose, because Gothic is in so de- cided a minority, as compared to Sanskrit, Greek, Latin, Celtic, or Slavonic, that therefore its aspirate is a corruption of a more ancient tenuis, or its media a corruption of a more primitive aspirate, or its tenuis a corruption of a former media. Looked upon as merely phonetic corruptions, such changes as t to th, th to d, and d to t in one and the same language would defy 288 LECTURE XT. all principles of phonetic .science. Gothic is as old and as independent a national dialect of Aryan speech as Sanskrit, and, as such, had as much right to fix on tenuis, aspirate, and media for the discrimination of certain roots as Sanskrit had in fixing on media, tenuis, and aspirate. Thus the three roots which appear in Sanskrit as tar, rlhar, and d a r, would from the beginning appear in Gothic as thar, dar, and tar, but one and the same language would never change tar into tha r, dhar into da r, and dar into tar. We know Gothic at a later time than Sanskrit, but that does not make Gothic a less primitive language than Sanskrit. And what applies to language, applies to mythology also. We know Vedic mythology at a much earlier date than Teutonic mythology, but that does not prove that the names and characters of the Teutonic gods were borrowed from the Veda. Thorr and Thursday. It is quite true, for instance, that if we want to know the original meaning of the Icelandic god Thorr, we have to trace back that word to the Anglo-Saxon Thunor, the modern thunder. It is true also that we have only to replace th by t, in order to be able to identify thunor with the Latin ton-are. But that does not prove that the Teutonic god Thorr, who still lives in the name of Thursday, dies Jovis, was not as old a god as any of the Vedic deities, and that from the very beginning he did not thunder with an initial aspirate, instead of an initial tenuis. Tyr and Tuesday. If we apply Grimm's Law, we generally begin with what we are accustomed to call the classical languages, MATERIALS FOR THE STUDY OF NATURAL RELTGION. 289 Sanskrit, Greek, and Latin. If therefore we find Dyu, nom. Dyaus in Sanskrit, Zevs for Aytvs in Greek, Iu-jpiter for Dyu-piter in Latin, we trace them back to Gothic, Icelandic, Anglo-Saxon, in fact, to Low German, by simply replacing the media by the tenuis. This gives us the Icelandic Tyr, which is preserved in Ti/sdagr, dies Martis, and in Tuesday, the Anglo- Saxon Tiwesdceg. But all this gives us no right to treat Tyr as a later corruption of the Vedic Dyaus. Wodan and Wednesday. Comparison, no doubt, helps us in discovering the origin of the names of the Aryan gods, and as the ancient mythology of the Veda is more richly de- veloped, or, at all events, has been more carefully pre- served than that of any other Aryan race, we gener- ally look upon the Sanskrit names as the most primitive. But historically this is a false position. We may, for instance, derive the name of the Teutonic god Wodan or Odin from a Sanskrit root which, if we replaced d by dh, would be vadh, to strike. From it we have the Vedic vadh-ar, thunderbolt, the Anglo- Saxon iveder, storm and weather, and from it we may guess the original purport of Wod-an to have been the god of the thunderstorm, who still lives in the name of Wednesday, as W6dnes-dceg. But there is no god in the Veda who could be represented as the exact prototype of Wodan, though there are several Vedic gods running parallel to him, just as the Gothic lan- guage runs parallel to Vedic Sanskrit. High German. Distinct from these three branches of the Teutonic class is the fourth, the High German, which as a rule u 290 LECTURE XI. represents classical tenuis by media, classical aspirate by tenuis, and classical media by an aspirate. In other respects, however, High German is very close to Low German, so that many scholars now group Low and High German together as West-Teutonic, and Gothic and Scandinavian as East-Teutonic. Old High German is known to us from about 700 to 1100 ; it is then succeeded by Middle High German from 1100 to 1500, and this by Modern High German spoken and written to the present day. Celtic. Besides the Low German which took possession of Britain in historic times, chiefly after the fall of the Roman dominion, another branch of Aryan speech overspread these isles in prehistoric times, the Celtic. The Celts too came from the Continent, where we find them migrating from East to West through Gaul and Spain, occasionally bursting into the Balkan and the Italian peninsulas, and sending out one colony as far as Galatia in Asia. The Celtic class is divided into two branches, the Cymric and the Goidelic. The former comprises Welsh, the extinct Cornish, and the Armorican of Brittany; the Goidelic, the Irish, Gaelic, and Manx. There are besides the ancient inscriptions of Gaul which are sometimes treated as a third branch, the Gallic. Interesting as the Celtic languages are for etjanological and grammatical purposes, their litera- ture is recent, not going back beyond the eighth century a. D. Whatever there is of mythology and ancient religion has evidently passed through a Christian and Romanic filtering, and has to be used MATERIALS FOR THE STUDY OF NATURAL RELIGION. 291 therefore with extreme caution for comparative purposes1. Italic. The next class of Aryan speech which has likewise reached the shores of the British isles, is the Italic. The literary language of Rome was but one of several dialects, elaborated by the Aryas when they settled in Italy. Eesides the Latin we find the Oscan and the Umbrian, and several smaller dialects of which we possess monumental fragments. After reaching its classical culmination, Latin became the lingua vul- garis of the civilised portion of Western Europe, and developed new vulgar and afterwards literary lan- guages in Italy, Gaul, Spain, Portugal, in the Grisons, and, by colonies, in Roumania. We have the earliest documents of French in the ninth century, of Pro- vencal in the tenth, of Italian, Spanish, and Portuguese in the twelfth. The language of England was touched twice by the waves of the Latin river, the first time through the Roman legions who took possession of Britain, the second time through the Norman conquerors, warriors of Teutonic extraction and Scandinavian blood, who after their conquest of Normandy had exchanged their Teutonic speech for that of Northern Gaul. They brought with them into England a Romanic languao-e, Romanic thought, manners, and tastes, but little of Romanic blood. There may be some Celtic admixture in the Teutonic blood of England ; but the grammar, the blood of the English language, has remained Teu- tonic throughout. o 1 See Professor Rhys, Hibbert Lectures, 1886. U 2 292 LECTURE XI. Hellenic. The next class is the Hellenic, And here we must guard against what was formerly a very common view, namely that the Aryas who came to people Greece and Italy were more closely related than the other scions of the Aryan family. Many scholars went so far as to suppose that the ancestors of the Greeks and Romans remained united for a time after they had become separated from the rest. There is no foundation, however, for this hypothesis, at least not so far as language is concerned. Greek shows greater similarity with Sanskrit than with Latin, Latin shows greater similarity with Celtic than with Greek. This is a point of great importance to us in our mythological and religious researches. In historical times the Latin language and the Roman mythology and religion have borrowed so much from Greek that scholars are apt to forget that the borrower was not altogether a pauper, that there was in fact a fully developed religion and mythology in Italy before the contact with Greece, and that it is this prehistoric phase of Italian life which is of chief interest to the student of ancient folk-lore. The Hellenic class, in its four dialects, the Doric, Aeolic, Attic, and Ionic, is so well known that I need say no more about it in this place. Slavonic. We have still one more class of Aryan languages in Europe, the Slavonic, or, as I prefer to call it, the Windic. I prefer the name of Windic, because the oldest name under which the tribes speaking those MATERIALS FOR THE STUDY OF NATURAL RELIGION. 293 languages became known to us, is not Slaves, but Winidae. This class is divided into three branches, the Lettic, the South-East Slavonic, and the West Slavonic. The Lettic comprises (1) the Lettish, now spoken in Kurland and Livonia, the Baltic provinces of Russia. Its literature dates from the sixteenth century. (2) The Lithuanian, spoken in Eastern Prussia and in Russia, by about a million of people. Its literature dates from 1547, of which date we possess a small catechism. (3) The old Prussian, which became extinct in the seventeenth century, and left behind a few fragments only of the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries. The South-East Slavonic comprises the old Bul- garian, in which we possess the translation of the Bible, of the ninth century, which is still used as the ' authorised version' ; the Slovenian, Servian, and Croatian (sometimes comprehended under the common designation of Illyrian), with literary remains of the tenth century, and the Russian, the literary language of the Russian Empire. The West Slavonic consists of the Polish, with a literature dating from the fourteenth century ; the Bohemian, with a literature dating from the tenth century, and the dialects still spoken by Wends and Sorbs in Lusatia. North- Western Division. These five classes of Aryan speech which we have hitherto passed in review belong all to Europe, and form together what I call the North-Western division of the Aryan family. 294 LECTUKE XI. Various attempts have been made to prove that before they became settled in their present seats, some of them remained together for a longer time than the rest, and therefore shared certain features in common which are absent in others. To me it seems that all these attempts have been in vain, and that all the evidence that is brought forward in support of what has been called a genealogical tree of the Aryan languages can be fully accounted for, if we admit that the dialectic varieties which afterwards grew into national languages existed before the Aryan Separation, that whatever forms seemed fittest to this or that clan survived, but that, after the family was once broken up, each dialect went its own way, un- concerned about its neighbours. Every other hypo- thesis creates as many difficulties as it is meant to solve. That geographical contact has nothing to do with grammatical similarity we see most clearly in Greek and Latin, which, though very close neighbours, are really as distinct as any other two Aryan lan- guages. Celtic shows certain features in common with Latin, Latin with Greek, Teutonic with Lettic, but not one of these casual coincidences requires for its explanation more than the admission of that common dialectic fermentation which preceded here as elsewhere the formation of national languages. South- Eastern Branch. It is useful, however, particularly for comparative purposes, to distinguish between those five branches which together form the North -Western division of the Aryan family, and the South- Fa stern division which consists of the languages of India and Persia. There MATERIALS FOR THE STUDY OF NATURAL RELIGION. 295 is one language which is now supposed to hold an intermediate position between these two divisions, the Armenian, but its exact relationship is still a matter of controversy. Why this division into a North- Western and South- Eastern branch is useful historically, we shall see when we come to consider the question of what intel- lectual level had been reached by the Aryan family before they separated. As it is quite clear that in historical times no exchange took place between the Aryas who travelled in a South-Eastern direction to Persia and India, and those who had followed a North-Western direction towards Europe, every word which they share in common, and particularly all words connected with mythology and religion, can be claimed as the common property of the whole Aryan race before its first dispersion. The languages belonging to this South-Eastern division are of special interest to us, as the principal sacred books are composed in them. Europe has never produced a religion. All religions have their cradle in the East, and the languages of India and Persia have become the vehicles of three of the greatest religions of the world, Bralvniauism, Buddhism, in its three divisions of Southern Buddhism, Northern Buddhism, and (7ainism, and Zoroastrianism. These languages, therefore, will require more careful consideration. Indie Class. Vedic Hymns. Let us begin with India. The oldest monument of Indian speech is the Veda. It is curious that wher- ever we have sacred books, they represent to us the oldest language of the country. It is so in India, it 296 LECTURE XT. is the same in Persia, in China, in Palestine, and very nearly so in Arabia. How the Veda, which is referred to about 1500 B.C., was preserved to the present day is a kind of fairy story which I must pass by, as we are at present concerned with the history of the language only ; but we shall have to consider it when we come to examine the fourth class of our materials for studying Natural Religion, viz. the Sacred Books. The language of the Veda must of course have been at one time the spoken language of those who composed the Vedic hymns, probably in the North- West of India. But in the history of India, that lan- guage is always the sacred language, and it possesses words, grammatical forms, and syntactical construc- tions, unknown in later Sanskrit. Brahma// as. The next stage of this language is still Vedic, but whereas the Vedic hymns are all in metre, the next stage shows us the prose of the Brahma?ias, works intended for the elucidation of the Vedic hymns and the Vedic sacrifices. The Sanskrit of these Brahmawas is more settled and regular than that of the hymns, but it still represents a period of language prior to that which is presupposed by the grammar of Pacini, or, what used to be called, classical Sanskrit. Sutras. The next phase of Sanskrit is that of the SiUras, which is likewise in some points different from the Sanskrit which Pa?iini would consider as regular, but approaches to it so closely that the chronological inter- val separating the two can only have been very small. The whole of this literature, which has been pre- MATERIALS FOR THE STUDY OF NATURAL RELIGION. 297 served to us in its three stages, is exclusively a priestly literature, and what seems at first sight almost in- credible, the whole of it was preserved for a long time by oral tradition only. The hymns must at a very early time have become the subject of the most careful study. Not only every word, but every letter and every accent were settled in the teaching of the schools, and the only marvel is that so many irregular forms should have escaped the levelling influence of teachers from generation to generation. Still, with all its irregularities, the Vedic language, as we know it, has clearly passed through a grammatical discipline, and we actually possess, dating from the third or the Sutra period, a number of treatises, the so-called Pratisakhyas, which show us with what extraordinary minuteness the hymns of the Veda had been analysed. Pa/'inean Sanskrit. With the Sutras this stream of Vedic language comes to an end. The famous grammar of Pibiini, which is generally referred to the fourth century B. c, treats the Vedic Sanskrit as already exceptional and antiquated, and presupposes a language and a literature of a different character. We must never forget that in ancient times literature gives us generally specimens of one dialect only, and that this literary dialect, being lifted out of the living stream of language, becomes what is called classical, that is stagnant and dead. The other non-literary dialects withdraw themselves from our observation, but if after a time a new language rises to the surface and brings with it a new liter- 298 LECTURE XI. ature, that new language is always a sister dialect rather, and not a direct descendant of the old classical language. The language for which Pacini's rules are intended is not Vedic Sanskrit, but a Sanskrit nevertheless closely allied to it. From Panini's time to the present day that Sanskrit, as a new literary language, has remained perfectly stationary, for the simple reason that any infraction of Pacini's rules, any deviation from the classical type as fixed by him, would have been considered, and is considered to the present day, a grammatical blunder. Inscriptions of Piyadasi, Third Century B.C. If we only knew the language of India in these two channels, the Vedic and the Paninean, all would be intelligible. But the marvel is that when for the first time we come across an historical specimen of the spoken language of India, that language is totally different. The first truly historical documents in India are the inscriptions of Piyadasi or Asoka in the middle of the third century B.C. These in- scriptions we have now before us as they were written at the time. They contain edicts intended to be understood by the people, and we are safe in supposing that the language in which they are composed must have been, if read out, intelligible to the people. I cannot describe the state of that language better than by representing it to you as a spoken vulgar dialect of Sanskrit, just as Italian was a spoken vulgar dialect of Latin. Thus, Avhile the Vedic and the Paninean Sanskrit present to us two old dialects, regulated by careful grammatical study and reserved MATERIALS FOR THE STUDY OF NATURAL RELIGION. 299 for literary purposes, these inscriptions of the third century B.C. represent to us the living dialects of the people, reduced by phonetic wear and tear to a mere ghost of their former self. And that is not all. While the Sanskrit of the Veda as well as the Sanskrit of Pacini is rendered uniform by rule, the language, as recorded in these inscriptions, allows an unbounded variety, such as would not be tolerated in any purely literary language. We have here the language of India as it was actually spoken in the third century B. c, and its discovery was no small surprise to the believers in one uniform classical Sanskrit. Buddhist Sanskrit. Nor is this all. While Brahmanism disdained to use any language but Sanskrit for religious subjects, Buddhism, which was at that time the rising and growing religion of India, availed itself of the spoken dialects in order to influence the great masses of the people ; and so we find that one collection of the sacred writings of the Buddhists, commonly called the Northern, is composed in an irregular dialect, closely resembling the dialect of Asoka's inscriptions, while the second collection, commonly called the Southern, is written in another vulgar dialect, but essentially differing from the former by having evi- dently received a more careful grammatical polish. The former dialect is generally called the Gdthd dialect, or Mixed Sanskrit, the latter is called Pali, and may be called MdgadM, though it ought not to be confused with the later Prakrit dialect of the same name. These two dialects we can fix his- 300 LECTURE XI. torically, at least so far that we may assign to the literature, composed in the Gatha dialect, a date anterior to the Christian era, because we have Chinese translations of some of the books of the Northern canon about that time. The text of the Southern canon, after having been handed down by word of mouth, was reduced to writing in 88 B.C.1 What chiefly distinguishes the Southern Pali text from the Northern Gatha text is that the former has clearly undergone a strict grammatical revision, while the latter has not. Renaissance of Sanskrit Literature. After the end of the first century A.D., Sanskrit, that is to say, the Pawinean Sanskrit, comes more and more to the front, and we see it used for the ordinary purposes of life, and likewise for public inscriptions. What we generally understand by Sanskrit literature begins about 400 A.D., and to about the same period we may refer the grammatical cultivation of the Prakrit dialects. Prakrit. These Prakrit dialects are probably the lineal descendants of the uugrammatical dialects, preserved to us in the inscriptions of Asoka, and again in some of the texts of the Northern Buddhist canon. But whereas at that time they were like wild-growing plants, they have now been trimmed and shorn and regulated by strict grammatical rules, after the pattern of Pacini's grammar. In that form they are used in the Sanskrit plays, much in the same manner 1 Vinaya-pitaka, in Sacred Books of the East, vol. xiii, p. xxxv. MATERIALS FOR THE STUDY OF NATURAL RELIGION. 301 as the Italian dialects were used in the Comeclia delle arte, where the Doctor always speaks Bolognese, Arleckmo Bergarnese, Pantaleone Venetian, while the pure Tuscan or Roman was reserved for the Amorosos and Inamoratas1. Vernaculars. But again, while the classical Sanskrit and the now equally classical Prakrit remained henceforth stationary, the old springs of language were not stopped, but poured on chiefly in two great channels, the Western and the Eastern, the former represented in our time by Sindhi, Gujarat! , Panjabi, and Western Hindi, the Eastern by Bihari, Bengali, Uriya, and Asami. The Nepali in the North shows more affinity with the Western, the Marathi in the South with the Eastern division. Sacred Books. It is necessary to keep this outline of the growth and the ramification of language clearly before our mind, for the Sacred Books with which we shall deal have grown, as it were, on the branches of this tree of speech. We have the hymns of the Veda, the Brahmawas, and Sutras preserved to us in Vedic Sanskrit. We have the Law Book of Manu and the Pura?ias composed in literary Sanskrit, according to Pacini's pattern. We have the Southern canon of Buddhism in Pali, the Angas of the £ainas in old Maharashfri, and the Northern canon of the Bud- dhists in ungrammatical Prakrit. We shall see that there is even a certain parallelism between the 1 Cf. M. M. , On Bengali, in Report of the British Association for 1847, p. 322. 302 LECTURE XI. growth of language and the growth of religion, and that without a knowledge of the historical develop- ment of the language many points in the history of the religions of India would remain unintelligible. Iranic Class. The last class of the Aryan family which we have still to examine is the Iranic. Here we find much the same phenomena as in India. The most ancient specimen of the language is found in the sacred book of Persia, the Avesta. It is called Zend, which, though it is an entire misnomer, will probably remain the recognised name. It is supposed with considerable probability that this ancient dialect was that of Media rather than of Persia. Cuneiform Persian Inscriptions. When, however, we get the first glimpse of the lan- guage of Persia in contemporary documents, I mean in the cuneiform inscriptions of Cyrus, Darius, and Xerxes, we find there a language closely allied to that of the sacred writings of Zoroaster, yet different from it. These inscriptions cover the time of the Achae- menian dynasty from about 500 to 336 B.C. Pehlevi. Then follows a break of more than five centuries ; but when we meet again with a new literature at the time of the Sassanian dynasty in the first half of the third century a.d., the language, then called Pehlevi, is a decayed Persian, written no longer in cuneiform letters, but in a Semitic alphabet and syllabary. The Pehlevi literature, chiefly concerned with the explana- tion of the Avesta and with religious questions, lasts MATERIALS FOR THE STUDY OF NATURAL RELIGION. 303 till about 900 a.d. With 1000 a.d. begins the modern Persian, as we have it in its purity in the great epic of Firdusi, the SMhn&meh, while in later times it becomes more and more mixed with Arabic words through the influence of the Mohammedan religion. These are the principal languages of the Aryan family, and those which are of special interest to us in the study of religion. There are some other lan- guages, such as Armenian and Ossetian in Asia, and Albanian in Europe, which are clearly of Aryan de- scent, but which have not yet been referred with perfect precision to any of the great classes of that family. Modern Albanian is supposed to represent the ancient Illyrian. Armenian may constitute a lan- guage by itself, more closely related, as shown by Hiibschmann, to the North- Western than to the South-Eastern division. Bask and Etruscan. Before we leave the Aryan family, we should still mention two languages, not Aryan in character, but surrounded on all sides by people of Aryan speech, and well-nigh absorbed by them, those of the Basks and the Etruscans. The Basks, interesting as they are for linguistic purposes, yield us little information with regard to what their ancient religion may have been. The Etruscans, on the contrary, have left us ample materials in monuments and inscriptions, though it must be confessed that not until a really safe key to their language has been discovered, will there be any chance of our understanding the true character of their religion. 304 LECTURE XI. Semitic Family. Quite independent of this enormous stream of lan- guage which dominates India, Persia, Armenia and nearly the whole of Europe, there is another stream, the Semitic, running in a bed of its own from the very beginning, and feeding two, if not three of the great religions of the world, that of the Jews, that of the Christians, and that of the Mohammedans. The Semitic family may be divided into three branches, the Aramaic, the Hebraic and the Arabic, or into two, the Northern, comprising the Aramaic and Hebraic, and the Southern, the Arabic. Aramaic. The Aramaic comprises the ancient language of Assyria and Babylon, so far as it has been discovered and deciphered in the cuneiform inscriptions. The grammatical structure of this ancient language is not yet sufficiently made out to enable scholars to trace its exact relation to the later Aramaic. Geographi- cally, however, the ancient language of Mesopotamia may for the present be classed as Aramaic. If some of these cuneiform inscriptions go back, as some scholars maintain, to 4000 B.C., they would represent the oldest remnants of Semitic speech. And if that Semitic literature was preceded, as seems very gener- ally admitted, by another civilisation, not Semitic, and generally called Sumero-Accaclian, we should get an insight into a past more distant than even that which is claimed for Egypt and China. It may be so, but even though chronologically the religious ideas conveyed to us by the sacred hymns of Babylon should prove to be so much earlier than those of any of MATERIALS FOR THE STUDY OF NATURAL RELIGION. 305 the Aryan races, I must say at once that they appear to me much more advanced, much more modern in point of civilisation. They presuppose towns, temples, idols, a knowledge of metals and all kinds of precious stones, familiarity with writing, and a number of abstract ideas which we should look for in vain in the Vedic hymns. Linguistically also there is little in these inscriptions which we should call much more primitive than what we see in the grammatical structure of Syriac, Arabic, or Hebrew. Many diffi- culties have here still to be cleared up. An important mine however for religious studies has no doubt been opened there, and several of the antecedents of Hebrew tradition have already been discovered in the cunei- form literature of Babylon. If, as we read, Abraham came from Ur of the Chaldees, his language ought to have been akin to that of the cuneiform inscriptions. But his name and all connected with him passed in later times through the channel of a different language, which we now call Hebrew; and the date at which whatever was known of him was reduced to writing- in that form in which we now possess it is still un- certain, but at all events much later than was formerly supposed. Chaldee and Syriac. In historical times we find Aramaic spoken in the kingdoms of Babylon and Assyria, and spreading thence into Syria and Palestine. Owing to the politi- cal and literary ascendancy of these kingdoms, Ara- maic seems for a time to have been a kind of lingua franca extending its influence to Persia, Syria, Asia Minor, Egypt, and even to Arabia. It has been usual to distinguish between the Ara- 306 LECTURE XI. maic as used by the Jews, and the Aramaic as used in later times by Christian writers, the former being- called Gkaldee, the latter Syriac. It may be true that the name Chaldee owes its origin to the mistaken notion of its having been introduced into Palestine by the Jews returning from the Babylonian captivity. But the name has been too long in possession to make it advisable to replace it by a new name, such as Western Aramaic. This Jewish Chaldee shows^tself first in some of the books of the Old Testament, such as Ezra and Daniel. Afterwards we find it in the Targums or Chaldee translations of the Pentateuch (Onkelos) and the Prophets (Jonathan), which were read in the Syna- gogues long before they were finally collected in about the fourth and fifth centuries a.d. The Jerusalem Tar- gums and the Jerusalem Talmud represent the Chaldee as spoken at that time by the Jews in Jerusalem and in Galilee. Christ and his disciples must have em- ployed the same Aramaic dialect, though they also used Greek in addressing the people at large. The conquests of the Arabs and the spreading of their language interfered with the literary cultivation of Chaldee as early as the seventh century ; but it con- tinued to be employed by some Jewish writers down to the tenth century. The Samaritans translated the Pentateuch into their own Aramaic dialect, which differs but little from that of the Jews. The Mandaeans also, a somewhat mixed Christian sect in Babylonia, spoke and wrote a Chaldee dialect, which is preserved in their writings and in the jargon of a few surviving members of that sect. MATERIALS FOR THE STUDY OF NATURAL RELIGION. 307 Syriac, though spoken long before the rise of Christianity, owes its literary cultivation chiefly to Christian writers. The Old and New Testaments were translated into Syriac (the Peshito) in the second century, and became the recognised text in the school of Edessa and elsewhere. A large literature accumulated from the third to the seventh century, and extended its influence to Persia and the Eastern Roman Empire. The Arabic conquests, however, put an end to the literary cultivation of this language ill aJso, though it lived on both as a written and spoken dialect to the twelfth century, and afterwards, as a language of the learned, to the present day. The Neo-Syriac dialects, still spoken in some parts of Mesopotamia, chiefly by Nestorian Christians in the neighbourhood of Mosul, and in Kurdistan as far as Lake Urmia, are not directly derived from the literary Syriac, but represent remnants of the spoken Aramaic. One of these dialects has lately received some literary cultivation through the exertions of Christian missionaries. Hebraic. The second branch, the Hebraic, comprises Phe- nician and Carthaginian, as known to us from inscriptions dating from about 600 B.C., and the Hebreiv of the Old Testament. The Moabites spoke Hebrew, as may be seen from the language of the inscription of King Mesha, about 900 B.C. The Philistines also seem to have spoken the same language, though, it may be, with dialectic varieties. About the time of the Maccabees, Hebrew and its cognate dialects ceased to be spoken by the people at large, though Hebrew remained the language x i 308 LECTURE XI. of the learned long after the destruction of Jerusalem by Titus. Even at present the Jews employ an artificial and corrupt Hebrew for literary discussions and among themselves. Arabic. The third branch, the Arabic, has its home in the Arabian peninsula, where it is still spoken by the bulk of the inhabitants, and from whence it spread over Asia, Africa, and Europe at the time of the Mohammedan conquests. There was a popular Arabic literature long before Mohammed (Mo'allakat), and there are inscriptions in the north of the Hijaz, commonly called Thamudic, which are supposed to be of an ante-Christian date. Arabic inscriptions continue to be found, attesting the use of Arabic as a cultivated language, long before the age of Mohammed. The trilingual inscription of Zabad (Aramaic, Arabic, Greek) dates from 513 A. D. ; a bilingual inscription of Harran (Arabic and Greek) from 568 A. D. A new impulse was given to the literary life of the Arabs by the new religion preached by Mohammed and his successors. The language of the Qur'an became a new type of literary excellence by the side of the ancient Bedouin poetry. In the second century after the Hejra grammatical studies fixed the rules of classical Arabic permanently, and after 1200 years the Qur'an is still read and understood by all educated Arabs. The spoken Arabic, however, differs dialectically in Egypt, Algeria, Syria, and Arabia. One Arabic dialect continues to be spoken in Malta. Sabaean or Himyaritic. Iii the South of the Arabian peninsula there existed MATERIALS FOR THE STUDY OF NATURAL RELIGION. 309 an ancient Sabaean civilisation, remnants of which have been discovered in colossal monuments and in numerous inscriptions, written in a peculiar alphabet, generally called Himyaritic. Their age is doubtful, but some of them are supposed to date from before our era and to extend to the fourth century A.D. It is possible to distinguish traces of different dialects in these Sabaean inscriptions, but they are all closely connected with Arabic. The Sabaean language was probably spoken in the South of the Arabian peninsula till the advent of Mohammedanism, which made Arabia the language of the whole of Yemen. Ethiopic. In very early times a colony from Arabia, or, more correctly, from Sabaea, seems to have crossed to Africa. Here, south of Egypt and Nubia, an ancient and very primitive Semitic dialect, closely allied to Sabaean and Arabic, has maintained itself to the present day, the Ethiopic or Abyssinian, or Geez. We have translations of the Bible in Ethiopic, dating from the third or fourth century. Other works followed, all of a theological character. There are inscriptions also in ancient Ethiopic, dating from the days of the kingdom of Axum, which have been referred to 350, and 500 A.D. This ancient Ethiopic ceased to be spoken in the ninth century, but it remained in use as a literary language for a long time. Beginning with the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries, a new language appears, the Amharic. In it the Semitic type has been intensely modified, probably owing to the fact that the tribes who spoke it were of Hamitic 310 LECTURE XI. origin. It is a spreading language, and has given rise in modern times to a new literature. Other dialects, such as Tigre, EhJdli, and Harrari, so called from the localities in which they are spoken, have not yet been sufficiently explored to enable Semitic scholars to pronounce an opinion whether they are varieties of Amharic, or representatives of more ancient independent dialects 1. The family likeness of the Semitic is quite as strong as that of the Aryan languages, nay even stronger. Their phonetic character is marked by the preponderance of guttural sounds, their etymological character by the triliteral form of most of the roots, and the manner in which these roots are modified by pronominal suffixes and prefixes ; their grammatical character by the fixity of the vowels for expressing the principal modifications of meaning, a fixity which made it possible to dispense with writing the vowel signs. These characteristic features are so strongly developed that they render it quite impossible to imagine that a Semitic language could ever have sprung from an Aryan or an Aryan from a Semitic. Whether both could have sprung from a common source is a question that has often been asked, and has generally been answered according to personal predilections. Most scholars, I believe, would admit that it could not be shown that a common origin in far distant times is altogether impossible. But the evidence both for and against is by necessity so intangible and evanescent that it does not come within the sphere of practical linguistics. 1 The latest and best account of the Semitic languages is given by Noldeke in the Cyclop. Britannica. LECTURE XII. PRINCIPLES OF CLASSIFICATION. Languages not Aryan and not Semitic. THE two families of language which we have hitherto examined, the Aryan and Semitic, are the most important to the student of religion. Not only are the principal Sacred Books of the East, with the exception of those of China, composed in Sanskrit, Pah, Prakrit, Zend, Pehlevi, Hebrew, Greek, and Arabic, but the religious and mythological phrase- ology of the leading nations of Europe— Greeks, Ro- mans, Germans, Slaves and Celts— are all embodied in Aryan and Semitic speech. It was necessary therefore to give a fuller account of these two families, so as to avoid the necessity of explaining again and again the linguistic evidence on which so much in the study of the great religions of the world depends. With regard to the remaining families of speech, however, it will be sufficient if I place before you a short outline only. Though outside the pale of the Aryan and Semitic languages the progress of Com- parative Philology has been very slow, still we know in many cases which languages in Asia, Africa, Poly- nesia and America are related and which are not, and to know this is of course of the greatest help in the study of religion. When we meet with the same re- ligious ideas or religious customs in distant parts of the world, the question whether they are the result of 312 LECTURE XII. our universal human nature or whether they have been transferred from one race to another, depends chiefly on the question whether there is a more or less distant relationship between the languages. If we know that the languages spoken on the East-coast of Africa from several degrees north of the equator to nearly the Cape belong to one and the same strongly marked family, that of the so-called Bantu languages, coincidences between the religious and mythological ideas of the races speaking these languages admit of an historical interpretation, and need not be accepted as the simple result of our common human faculties. If it could be proved that the Hottentots, the southern neighbours of these Bantu races, were really, as maintained by Lepsius and others, emigrants from Egypt> this again would throw a new light on certain coincidences in their customs and those of the ancient Egyptians. The Hurons ! of the Anderdon reserve, visited by Mr. Horatio Hale in 1872 and 1874, tell the story of the earth being sustained by a tortoise, yet no one would think that they borrowed it from India. They likewise know of two supernatural beings who were to prepare the world to be the abode of man. The one was good, the other bad. The bad brother cre- ated monstrous creatures, the good brother innocent and useful animals, and though he could not destroy the evil animals altogether, he reduced them in size, so that man would be able to master them. What- ever beneficent work the good brother accomplished was counteracted by the bad brother. At last the two brothers fought, the evil spirit was overcome by 1 Horatio Hale in Journal of American Folklore, vol. i. p. ISO. PRINCIPLES OF CLASSIFICATION. 313 the good, but retired to the West where, as he de- clared, all men would go after death. All this might be taken from the A vesta ; yet though the two brothers are actually styled by the Hurons the ; Good Mind ' and the ' Bad Mind ' (in Zend, Vanheus Mainyus, Anro Mainyus), no one would suppose that the Hurons borrowed from Zoroaster or Zoroaster from the Hurons. It is essential also that students of religion and mythology should possess a general knowledge of the grammatical character of the languages, for it has been clearly shown that such peculiarities as, for instance, the distinction of masculine, feminine, and neuter nouns, have been productive of a whole class of legends which are absent when the idea of gender has not been realised in language. My own conviction has always been that a truly scientific study of religion and mythology is impossible unless we know the language which forms the soil from which religion and mytho- logy spring K All attempts therefore to study the re- ligions, particularly of uncivilised tribes, whose dialects are but little known and whose linguistic affinities with other tribes are not yet clearly established, must be looked upon for the present as provisional only. These studies, though full of promise, are at the same time full of danger also. Morphological Classification of Languages. It may be well to keep in mind that languages may be and have been classified, not only genealogically, 1 Professor Tiele, one of the highest authorities on Comparative Theology, agrees with me as to the intimate relationship between language, religion, and nationality. But he very wisely puts in a reservation, namely that, 'the farther history advances, the more does religion become independent of both language and nationality.' 314 LECTURE XTI. but morphologically also, and that a morphological similarity between certain languages, though it does in no way prove their common descent, indicates a common bent in the thoughts of those who speak them. I have already mentioned the grammatical distinction of gender as an important element in the formation of mythology and religion. Other elements of the same kind are the manner in which certain languages keep the radical portion of every word from phonetic corruption, while others allow it to become absorbed and almost lost. Words which dis- play their radical elements retain a certain perspicuity, and are less liable therefore to mythological misunder- standings. Thus the Semitic languages in which the triliteral skeleton is generally clearly discernible in every word have produced less of poetical mythology than the Aryan languages. The power of forming abstract nouns, of employing compound words, of using impersonal verbs, has often to be appealed to in the interpretation of mythological and religious modes of expression. I saw a curious instance of the almost unconscious influence which peculiarities of language may exer- cise on the expression of religious dogma in the case of a Mohawk who came to Oxford to study medicine, and who gave me lessons in his native language. In that language it is impossible to say the father, or the son ; we must always say my, thy, or his father or son. Thus we cannot say ' I believe in God, the father,' but we must say, ' I believe in God, our father.' Again, instead of saying ' I believe in God, the son,' we have to say, ' I believe in God, his son.' But when we come to say ' I believe in God, the Holy PRINCIPLES OF CLASSIFICATION. 315 Ghost,' we cannot, as in English, leave the question of the procession of the Spirit from the father, or from the father and the son, an open one. We must say, either ' his Holy Ghost,' or ' their Holy Ghost.' That is to say, language would force a Mohawk to declare himself for the single or double procession, a question which most of us may leave to be settled by theolo- gians by profession. Genealogical as different from Morphological Classification. The Aryan and Semitic languages are held together, as we saw, by the closest ties of a real genealogical relationship. They both presuppose the existence of a finished system of grammar, previous to the first divergence of their dialects. Their history is from the very beginning a history of decay rather than of growth, and hence the unmistakeable family-likeness which pervades every one even of their latest descendants. The languages of the Sepoy and that of the English soldier are, in one sense, one and the same language. They are both built up of materials which were defi- nitely shaped before the Teutonic and Indie branches separated. No new root has been added to either since their first separation ; and the grammatical forms which are of more modern growth in English or Hindustani are, if closely examined, new combina- tions only of elements which existed from the be- ginning in all the Aryan dialects. In the termination of the English he is, and in the inaudible termination of the French il est, we recognise the result of an act performed before the first separation of the Aryan family, the combination of the predicative root AS with the demonstrative element ta, or ti ; an act per- 316 LECTURE XII. formed once for all, and continuing to be felt to the present day. It was the custom of Nebuchadnezzar to have his name stamped on every brick that was used during his reign in erecting his colossal palaces. Those palaces fell to ruins, but from the ruins the ancient materials were carried away for building new cities ; and, on examining the bricks in the walls of the modern city of Bagdad on the borders of the Tigris, travellers have discovered on every one the clear traces of that royal signature. It is the same if we examine the structure of modern languages. They too were built up with the materials taken from the ruins of the ancient languages, and every word, if properly examined, displays the royal stamp impressed upon it from the first by the founders of the Aryan and the Semitic empires of speech. Degrees of Relationship. The relationship of languages, however, is not always so close. Languages may diverge before their gram- matical system has become fixed and hardened by tradition or literary culture ; and in that case they cannot be expected to show the same marked features of a common descent, as, for instance, the Neo-Latin dialects, French, Italian, and Spanish. They may have much in common, but they will likewise display an aftergrowth in words and gram- matical forms peculiar to each dialect. With regard to words, for instance, we see that even languages so intimately related to each other as the six Romanic dialects, diverged in some of the commonest expres- sions. Instead of the Latin word f rater, the French PRINCIPLES OF CLASSIFICATION. 317 frere, we find in Spanish hermano. There was a very good reason for this change. The Latin word frater, changed into fray and frayle, had been applied to express a brother, in the sense of a friar. It was felt inconvenient that the same word should express two ideas which it was sometimes necessary to distinguish, and therefore, by a kind of natural elimination, frater was given up as the name of brother in Spanish, and re- placed from the dialectical stores of Latin by (jermanus. In the same manner the Latin word for shepherd, pastor, was so constantly applied to the shepherd of the souls, or the clergyman, le pasteur, that a new word was wanted for the real shepherd. Thus berbi- cariu8s from berbex or vervex, a wether, was used instead o£ pastor, and changed into the French berger. Instead of the Spanish enfevmo, ill, we find in French malade, in Italian malato. Languages so closely re- lated as Greek and Latin have fixed on different expressions for son, daughter, brother, woman, man, sky, earth, moon, hand, mouth, tree, bird, &C.1 That is to say, out of a large number of synonymes which were supplied by the numerous dialects of the Aryan family, the Greeks perpetuated one, the Romans another. It is clear that when the working of this principle of natural selection is allowed to extend more widely, languages, though proceeding from the same source, may in time acquire a totally different nomenclature for the commonest objects. The number of real synonymes is frequently exaggerated, and if we are told that in Icelandic, for instance, there are 120 names for island, or in Arabic 500 names for lion 2, 1 S(M' Letter "n the Turanian Languages, p. 62. a Renan, Histuirc des Langues semitiques, p. 137 318 LECTUBE XII. and 1000 names for sword1, many of these are no doubt purely poetical. But even where there are in a language only four or five names for the same objects, it is clear that four languages might be derived from it, each in appearance quite distinct from the rest2. The same applies to grammar. When the Romanic languages, for instance, formed their new future by placing the auxiliary verb habere, to have, after the infinitive, it was quite open to any one of them to fix upon some other expedient for expressing the future. The French might have chosen je vais dire or je dir- vais (I wade to say) instead of je dir-ai, and in this case the future in French would have been totally distinct from the future in Italian. If such changes are possible in literary languages of such long stand- ing as French and Italian, we must be prepared for a great deal more in languages which, as I said, diverged before any definite settlement had taken place, either in their grammar or their dictionary. If we were to expect in them the definite criteria of a genealogical relationship which unites the members of the Aryan and Semitic families of speech, we should necessarily be disappointed. Such criteria could hardly be ex- pected to exist in these languages. But there are criteria for determining even these more distant degrees of relationship in the vast realm of speech ; and they are sufficient at least to arrest for the present the hasty conclusions of those who would deny the possibility of a common origin of any lan- guages more removed from each other than French and 1 Pococke, Notes to Abulfaragius, p. 153 ; Stoddart, Glossology, p. 352. See infra, p. 438. 2 See Terrien Poncel, Du Language, p. 213. PRINCIPLES OF CLASSIFICATION. 319 Italian, Sanskrit and Greek, Hebrew and Arabic. This will be more clearly seen after we have examined the principles of what I call the Morphological Classifica- tion of human speech. Morphological Classification. As all languages, so far as we can judge at present, can be reduced in the end to roots, predicative and demonstrative, it is clear that, according to the man- ner in which roots are put together, we may expect to find three kinds of languages, or three stages in the gradual formation of speech. 1. Roots may be used as words, each root preserving its full independence. 2. Two roots maybe joined together to form words, and in these compounds one root may lose its inde- pendence. 3. Two roots maybe joined together to form words, and in these compounds both roots may lose their independence. What applies to two roots, applies to three or four or more. The principle is the same, though it would lead to a more varied subdivision. Radical Stage. The first stage, in which each root preserves its in- dependence, and in which there is no formal distinction between a root and a word, I call the Radical Stage. Languages while belonging to this first or Radical Stage have sometimes been called Monosyllabic or Isolating. Terminational Stage. The second stage, in which two or more roots coalesce to form a word, the one retaining its radical 320 LECTURE XII. independence, the other sinking down to a mere termination, I call the Terminational Stage. The languages belonging to it have generally been called agglutinative, from gluten, glue. Inflectional Stage. The third stage, in which roots coalesce so that neither the one nor the other retains its substantive independence, I call the Inflectional Stage. The lan- guages belonging to it have sometimes been distin- guished by the name of amalgamating or organic. The first stage excludes phonetic corruption alto- gether. The second stage excludes phonetic corruption in the principal root, but allows it in the secondary or determinative elements. The third stage allows phonetic corruption both in the principal root and in the terminations. Transitions from one stage to another. It is perfectly true that few languages only, if we can trace their history during any length of time, remain stationary in one of these stages. Even Chinese, as has been shown by Dr. Edkins, exhibits in its modern dialects traces of incipient agglutination, if not of inflection. The Ugric languages show the most decided traces of phonetic corruption1, and in consequence clear tendencies toward inflexion, while the modern Aryan languages, such as French and English, avail themselves of agglutinative expedients for contriving 1 Thus, to quote Professor Hunfalvy, sydcim, heart, iu Finnish has been changed to sydm, in Vogul. to sim, in Hungarian to sziiv and szu. The Ostjak. jdgot, bow, is jaut and jajt in Yogul. , jout-se in Finnish, ij and iv in Hungarian. The Ostjak. kauh, kouh or hxu, stone, is kav or kciv in Vogul., kjvi in Finnish, ko in Hungarian. PRINCIPLES OF CLASSIFICATION. 321 new grammatical forms. So far I quite agree with Professor Hunfalvy, who has so strongly protested against substituting a morphological for a genealogical classification of languages. Such a substitution is impossible, and was never contemplated. The two classifications are both useful, each for its own pur- poses, but the genealogical classification should always be considered the more important. Nor was it even supposed that the two classifica- tions could run parallel. We saw how an isolating language, like Chinese, might in the end produce inflectional forms, and I hold as strongly as ever that every inflectional language must have passed through an agglutinative stage, and that this agglutination is always preceded by the isolating stage. It should be quite clearly understood therefore that morphological similarity is no proof whatever of real historical relationship. It may indicate such relation- ship, but a very different kind of evidence is required in addition, to establish the common descent of lan- guages standing on the same morphological stage. This may require some further illustration. Chinese. In the first morphological stage every word can be called a root, before it is used as part of a sentence. This stage is best represented by Chinese, and to a certain extent by ancient Egyptian. There is no formal distinction in ancient Chinese between a noun, a verb, an adjective, an adverb, and a preposition. The same root, according to its position in a sentence, may be employed to convey the meaning of great, greatness, greatly, to grow, and to be great. All depends on Y 322 LECTURE XII. position, not on grammatical terminations. Thus ngb td ni means 'I beat thee,' and ni td ago would mean ' thou beatest me.' Ngo gin means ; a bad man ; ' gin ngtf would mean 'the man is bad.' When we say in Latin baculo, with a stick, we should have to say in Chinese y 6dng\ Here y might be taken for a mere preposition, like the English with. But in Chinese this y is a root ; it is the same word which, if used as a verb, would mean ' to employ.' Therefore in Chinese y 6dng means literally ' employ stick.' Or again, where we say in English at home, or in Latin do mi, the Chinese say ud-li, uti meaning house, and li originally inside2. The name for day in modern Chinese is gi-tse, which meant originally son of the sun3, or, connected with the sun. As long as every word, or part of a word, is felt to express its own radical meaning, a language belongs to the first or radical stage. As soon as such words as tse in gi-tse, day, li in ud-li, at home, or y in y-l'dng, with the stick, lose their etymological meaning and become mere signs of derivation or of case, language enters into the second or terminational stage. And this transition from one class into another does not, as Professor Hunfalvy supposes, vitiate our division. On the contrary, it confirms it from an historical point of view. In some respects the ancient language of Egypt, as revealed to us in the earliest hieroglyphic inscriptions, 1 Endlicher, Chinesische Grammatik, s. 223. 2 Ibid,, s. 339. 3 In this word tse (tseu) does not signify son ; it is an addition of frequent occurrence after nouns, adjectives, and verbs. Thus, lao, old, + tseu is father ; net, the interior, + tseu is wife ; hiayig, scent, + tseu is clove ; hoa, to beg, + tseu, a mendicant ; hi, to act, + tseu, an actor. — Stanislas Julien. PRINCIPLES OF CLASSIFICATION. 323 may be classed with Chinese. But the points of similarity are chiefly negative. They arise from the absence of grammatical differentiation and articula- tion, and from the possibility in consequence of the same word or root being used as a substantive, adjec- tive, verb, or adverb. But there is no trace of any material relationship between the two languages. Chinese stands by itself as a language which has changed very little since we know it in its most ancient literary records. Some scholars maintain that even in its earliest stage it shows signs of previous phonetic corruption. This may be so, and it seems confirmed by the evidence of local dialects. But we can hardly imagine that its grammatical simplicity, or rather its freedom from all grammar, in our sense of the word, could be due, as in the case of English, to a long-continued process of elimination of useless ele- ments. Here we must wait for the results of further researches. The age claimed for the ancient Chinese literature seems to me as yet unsupported by any such evidence as would carry conviction to a student of Greek, Latin, or Sanskrit literature. Even if we admit that much of the ancient literature which was systematically destroyed by the Emperor of Khin, B.C. 213, may have been recovered from oral tradition and scattered MSS., we cannot claim for the works of Confucius and Lao-^ze an earlier date than that of their compilers. They may contain much older materials, but they give them to us as understood in the sixth century B.C., and they too may not altogether have escaped the effects of the burning of books under the Emperor of Khm. Y 2 324 LECTURE XII. Ural-Altaic Languages. West of China there stretches a cluster of languages which are on the point of leaving or have left the isolating stage, which show the development of agglu- tination in high perfection, and in some instances rise to the level of inflectional grammar. They are called Ural-Altaic or Ugro-Tataric. In one of my earliest essays, 'A Letter on the Turanian Languages,' 1854, I proposed to comprehend these languages under the name of Turanian. I went even further, and distin- guished them as Forth-Turanian, in opposition to what in my youth I ventured to call the South-Tura- nian languages, namely the Tamulic, Taic, Gangetic, Lohitic, and Malaic. During the last thirty years, however, the principles of the Science of Language have been worked out with so much greater exact- ness, and the study of some of these languages has made such rapid progress, that I should not venture at present to suggest such wide generalisations, at all events so far as the Tamulic, Taic, Gangetic, Lohitic, and Malaic languages are concerned. It is different, however, with the languages I com- prehended as North-Turanian. They share not only common morphological features, but they are held together by a real genealogical relationship, though not a relationship so close as that which holds the Aryan or Semitic languages together. Rask's and Frichard's Classification. Though I am responsible for the name Turanian, and for the first attempt at a classification of the Turanian languages in the widest sense, similar at- tempts to comprehend the languages of Asia and PRINCIPLES OF CLASSIFICATION. 325 Europe, which are not either Aryan or Semitic, under a common name had been made long ago by Rask, by Pilchard and others. Rask admitted three families, the Thracian (Aryan), the Semitic, and the Scythian, the latter comprising most of what I call the Turanian languages. During his travels in India, Rask, in a letter dated 30th July, 1821, claimed for the first time the Dra vidian languages also, Tamil, Telugu, etc., as decidedly Scythian l. The name Allophylian, proposed by Pri chard, is in some respects better than Turanian. Rask's Scythian and Prichard's Allophylian race was supposed to have occupied Europe and Asia before the advent of the Aryan and Semitic races, a theory which has lately been revived by Westergaard, Norris, Lenormant, and Oppert, who hold that a Turanian civilisation preceded likewise the Semitic civilisation of Babylon and Nineveh, that the cunei- form letters were invented by that Turanian race, and that remnants of its literature have been preserved in the second class of the Cuneiform Inscriptions, called sometimes Scythian, sometimes Median, and possibly in that large class of inscriptions now called Akkadian or Sumerian 2. Whatever may be thought of these far-reaching 1 Professor De Lagarde has stated that F. Ruckert lectured at Berlin in 1843 on the relationship of the Providian and Turanian languages, and that I received the first impulse from him. It may be so, though I am not aware of it. Anyhow, the first impulse came from Rask; Samlede Afhandlinger af I,'. K. Rask, Kobenhavn, 1836, pp. 323 seq. 2 Tho affinity of Akkadian and Sumerian with the Finno-Ugric languages lias been disproved by Donner. Their affinity with the Altaic Languages is maintained by Hommel, ' Die Sumero-Akkaden, • •in altaisches Volk,' in Correspondez-Blatt der deutschen Ges. fur Antkro- pologie, xv. Jahrg. No. 8, 1884. p. 63. 326 LECTURE XII. theories, no one, I believe, doubts any longer a close relationship between Mongolia and Turkic, a wider relationship between these two and Tungusic, and a still wider one between these three and Finnic and Samoyedic. Hence the Mongolic, Turkic, and Tun- gusic languages have been comprehended under the name of Altaic, the Finnic languages are called Ugric (including Hungarian), while Samoyedic forms, ac- cording to some, a more independent nucleus. All five groups together constitute what is called the Ugro-Altaic family. Vocalic Harmony. There is one peculiarity common to many of the Ugro-Altaic languages which deserves a short notice, the law of Vocalic Harmony. According to this law the vowels of every word must be changed and modu- lated so as to harmonise with the key-note struck by its chief vowel. This law pervades the Tungusic, Mongolic, Turkic, Samoyedic, and Finnic classes ; and even in dialects where it is disappearing, it has often left traces of its former existence behind. The same law has been traced in the Tamulic languages also, particularly in Telugu, and in these languages it is not only the radical vowel that determines the vowels of the suffixes, but the vowel of a suffix also may react on the radical vowel 1. The vowels in Turkish, for instance, are divided into two classes, sharp said flat. If a verb contains a sharp vowel in its radical portion, the vowels of the terminations are all sharp, while the same terminations, if following a root with a flat vowel, modulate their vowels into a flat key. Thus 1 Cf. Caldwell, Dravidian Grammar, second eel., p. 7b. PRINCIPLES OF CLASSIFICATION. 327 we have sev-mek, to love, but bak-mak, to regard, mek or male being the termination of the infinitive. Thus we say ev-ler, the houses, but at-lar, the horses, lev or lar being the termination of the plural. No Aryan or Semitic language has preserved a similar freedom in the harmonic arrangement of its o vowels, while traces of it have been found among the most distant members of the Turanian family, as in Hungarian, Mongolian, Turkish, the Yakut, spoken in the north of Siberia, in Telugu, Tulu1, and in dialects spoken on the eastern frontier of India. ' ' In Tulu final short u is left unchanged only after words con- taining labial vowels [bududu, having left) ; it is changed into >"> after all other vowels jpandudii, having said).' — Dr. Gundert. LECTURE XIII. The Ural-Altaic Family. W E now proceed to examine the principal lan- guages belonging to the Ural-Altaic family. The Samoyedic. The tribes speaking Samoyedic dialects are spread along the Yenisei and Ob rivers, and were pushed more and more North by their Mongolic successors. They have now dwindled down to about 16,000 souls. Five dialects, however, have been distinguished in their language by Castren, the Yurakian, Tawgyan, Yeniseian, Osty'ako-Samoyede, and Kamassinian, with several local varieties. The vocalic harmony is most carefully preserved in the Kamassinian dialect, but seems formerly to have existed in all. The Samoyedic has no gender of nouns, but three numbers singular, dual, and plural, and eight cases. The verb has two tenses, an Aorist (present and future) and a Preterite. Eesides the indicative, there is a subjunctive and an imperative. Altaic Languages. This name comprehends the Tungusic, Mongolic, and Turkic languages. Some of the Tungusic and Mongolic dialects represent the lowest phase of agglu- tination, which in some cases is as yet no more than juxtaposition, while in Turkish agglutination has LANGUAGES, NOT AEYAN AND NOT SEMITIC. 329 really entered into the inflectional phase. The vocalic harmony prevails throughout. Tungusic Class. The Tungudc branch extends from China north- ward to Siberia and westward to 113°, where the river Tunguska partly marks its frontier. The Tun- gusic tribes in Eastern Siberia are under Russian sway. They consist of about 70,000 souls ; some are called Tchapogires, some Orotongs. Other Tungusic tribes belong to the Chinese empire, and are known by the name of MandsJm, a name taken after they had conquered China in 1644, and founded the present imperial dynasty. Their country is called Mand- shuria. Mongolic Class. The original seats of the people who speak Mon- golic dialects lie near the Lake Baikal and in the eastern parts of Siberia, where we find them as early as the ninth century after Christ. They were divided into three classes, the Mongols proper, the Bur Hits, and the Olots or Kalmnks. Chingis-Khan (1227) united them into a nation and founded the Mongolian empire, which included, however, not only Mongolic, but likewise Tungusic and Turkic (commonly, though wrongly, called Tataric) tribes. The name of Tatar soon became the terror of Asia and Europe, and, changed into Tartar, as if derived from Tartarus, it was applied promiscuously to all the nomadic warriors whom Asia then poured forth over Europe. Originally Tatar was a name of the Mongolic races, but through their political ascendancy in Asia after Chingis-Khan, it became usual to call all the tribes which were under Mongolian sway by 330 LECTURE XI EI. the name of Tatar. In linguistic works Tataric is now used in two several senses. Following the example of writers of the Middle Ages, Tataric, like Scythian in Greek, has been fixed upon as the general term comprising all languages spoken by the nomadic tribes of Asia. Secondly, Tataric, by a strange freak, has become the name of that class of languages of which the Turkish is the most prominent member. While the Mongolic class — that which in fact has the greatest claims to the name of Tataric — is never so called, it has become an almost universal custom to apply this name to the third or Turkic branch of the Ural-Altaic division ; and the races belonging to this branch have in many instances themselves adopted the name. The conquests of the Mongols, or the descendants of Chingis-Khan, were not confined, however, to these Turkish tribes. They conquered China in the East, where they founded the Mongolic dynasty of Yuan, and in the West, after subduing the Khalifs of Bagdad and the Sultans of Iconium, they conquered Moscow, and devastated the greater part of Russia. In 1240 they invaded Poland, in 1241 Silesia. Here they recoiled before the united armies of Germany, Poland, and Silesia. They retired into Moravia, and, having exhausted that country, occupied Hungary. At that time they had to choose a new Khan, which could only be done at Karakorum, the old capital of their empire. Thither they withdrew to elect an emperor to govern an empire which then extended from China to Poland, from India to Siberia. But a realm of such vast proportions could not be long held together, and towards the end of the LANGUAGES, NOT ARYAN AND NOT SEMITIC. 331 thirteenth century it broke up into several independent states, all under Mongolian princes, but no longer under one Khan of Khans. Thus new independent Mongolic empires arose in China, Turkestan, Siberia, Southern Russia, and Persia. In 1360 the Mongolian dynasty was driven out of China ; in the fifteenth century they lost their hold on Russia. In Central Asia they rallied once more under Timur (1369), whose sway was again acknowledged from Kara- korum to Persia and Anatolia. But, in 1468, this empire also fell by its own weight, and for want of powerful rulers like Chingis-Khan or Timur. In Jagatai alone — the country extending from the Aral Lake to the Hindu-Kush between the rivers Oxus and Yaxartes (Jihon and Sihon), and once governed by Jagatai, the son of Chingis-Khan — the Mongolian dynasty maintained itself, and thence it was that Baber, a descendant of Timur, conquered India, and founded there a Mongolian dynasty, surviving up to our own times in the Great Moguls of Delhi. Most Mongolic tribes are now under the sway of the nations whom they once had conquered, the Tungusic sove- reigns of China, the Russian Czars, and the Turkish Sultans. The Mongolic language, although spoken (but not continuously) from China as far as the Volga, has given rise to but few dialects. Next to the Tungusic, the Mongolic is the poorest language of the Ural- Altaic family, and the scantiness of grammatical ter- minations accounts for the fact that, as a language, it has remained very much unchanged. There is, however, a distinction between the language as spoken by the Eastern, Western, and Northern tribes ; and incipient 332 LECTUKE XIII. traces of grammatical life have lately been discovered by Castren, the great Swedish traveller and Turanian philologist, in the spoken dialect of the Buriats. In it the persons of the verb are distinguished by affixes, while, according to the rules of Mongolic grammar, no other dialect distinguishes in the verb between amo, amas, ama£. Turkic Class. Much more important are the Turkic languages, most prominent among which is the Turkish itself, or the Osmanli of Constantinople. The different Turkic dialects, of which the Osmanli is one, occupy one of the largest linguistic areas, extending from the Lena and the Polar Sea down to the Adriatic. Turkish Grammar. It is a real pleasure to read a Turkish grammar, even though one may have no wish to acquire it practically. The ingenious manner in which the numerous grammatical forms are brought out, the regularity which pervades the system of declension and conjugation, the transparency and intelligibility of the whole structure, must strike all who have a sense for that wonderful power of the human mind which is displayed in language. Given so small a number of graphic and demonstrative roots as would hardly suffice to express the commonest wants of human beings, to produce an instrument that shall render the faintest shades of feeling and thought ; given a vague infinitive or a stern imperative, to derive from it such moods as an optative or subjunc- tive, and tenses such as an aorist or paulo-post future ; given incoherent utterances, to arrange them into a LANGUAGES, NOT ARYAN AND NOT SEMITIC. 333 system where all is uniform and regular, all combined and harmonious, — such is the work of the human mind which we see realised in language. But in most languages nothing of this early process remains visible. They stand before us like solid rocks, and the micro- scope of the philologist alone can reveal the remains of organic life with which they are built up. In the grammar of the Turkic languages, on the contrary, we have before us a language of perfectly transparent structure, and a grammar the inner work- ings of which we can study, as if watching the building of cells in a crystal beehive. An eminent Orientalist remarked, ' We might imagine Turkish to be the result of the deliberations of some eminent society of learned men;' but no such society could have devised what the mind of man produced, left to itself in the steppes of Tartary, and guided only by its innate laws, or by an instinctive power as wonderful as any within the realm of nature. Finno-Ugric Class. We now proceed to the Finnic class, which, accord- ing to Castren, is divided into four branches. (1) The Ugric, comprising Ostjakian, Vogulian, and Hungarian. (2) The Bulgaria 13 comprising Tcheremissian and Mordvinian. 1 The name Bulgaric is not borrowed from Bulgaria, on the Danube ; Bulgaria, on the contrary, received its name (replacing Moesia) from Bulgaric armies by whom it was conquered in the seventh century. Bulgarian tribes marched from the Volga to the Don, and after remaining for a time under the sovereignty of the Avars on the Don and Dnieper, they advanced to the Danube in 635, and founded there the Bulgarian kingdom. This has retained its name to the present day, though the original Bulgarians have long been absorbed and replaced by Slavonic inhabitants, and both brought under Turkish sway since 1302. 334 LECTURE XIII. (3) The Permic, comprising Permian, Syrjanian, Votjakian. (4) The Finnic, comprising Finnish, Estonian. Lap- ponian, Karelian, Livonian, Wotian. Pins. For our own purposes the Fins and Estonians are the most interesting among the Finno-Ugric tribes. The Fins call themselves Suomalainen, i. e. in- habitants of fens. They are settled in the province of Finland (formerly belonging to Sweden, but since 1809 annexed to Russia), and in parts of the govern- ments of Archangel and Olonetz. Their literature and, above all, their popular poetry bear witness to a high intellectual development in times which we may call almost mythical, and in places more favourable to the glow of poetical feelings than their present abode, the last refuge Europe could afford them. The epic songs still live among the poorest, recorded by oral tradition alone, and preserving all the features of a perfect metre and of a more ancient language. A national feeling has lately arisen amongst the Fins, despite of Russian supremacy; and the labours of Sjogren, Lonnrot, Castren, Kellgren, Donner and others, receiving hence a powerful impulse, have produced results truly surprising. From the mouths of the aged an epic poem has been collected equalling the Iliad in length and completeness — nay, if we can forget for a moment all that we in our youth learned to call beautiful, not less beautiful. A Fin is not a Greek, and Wainamoi'nen was not a Homeric rhapsodos. But if the poet may take his colours from that nature by which he is surrounded, if he may depict the men with whom he lives, the Kalevala LANGUAGES, NOT ARYAN AND NOT SEMITIC. 335 possesses merits not dissimilar from those of the Iliad, and will claim its place as the fifth national epic of the world, side by side with the Ionian songs, with the MahdbMrata, the Shdhmmeh, and the Mbdunge. If we want to study the circumstances under which short ballads may grow up and become amalga- mated after a time into a real epic poem, nothing can be more instructive than the history of the collection of the Kalevala. We have here facts before us, not mere surmises, as in the case of the Homeric poems and the Nibelunge. We can still see how some poems were lost, others were modified ; how certain heroes and episodes became popular, and attracted and ab- sorbed what had been originally told of other heroes and other episodes. Lonnrot could watch the effect of a good and of a bad memory among the people who repeated the songs to him, and he makes no secret of having himself used the same freedom in the final arrangement of these poems which the people used from whom he learnt them. This early literary culti- vation has not been without a powerful influence on the language. It has imparted permanence to its forms and a traditional character to its words, so that at first sight we might almost doubt whether the grammar of this language had not left the agglutina- tive stage altogether. The agglutinative type, how- ever, yet remains, and its grammar shows a luxuriance of grammatical combination second only to Turkish and Hungarian. Like Turkish it observes the ■ har- mony of vowels,' a feature which lends a peculiar charm to its poetry. The yield of this popular poetry for mythological and religious researches is very considerable. 336 LECTURE XIII. The Estonians. The Ests or Estonians, neighbours of the Fins, and speaking a language closely allied to the Finnish, possess likewise large fragments of ancient national poetry. Dr. Kreutzwald has been able to put together a kind of epic poem, called Kalewipoeg, the Son of Kalew, not so grand and perfect as the Kalevala, yet interesting as a parallel. The languages which I formerly comprehended under the general name of South-Turanian, should, for the present at least, be treated as independent branches of speech. Tamulic Languages. There can be no doubt about the Tamulic or Dra vi- dian languages constituting a well-defined family, held together by strongly marked grammatical features. Tamil, Telugu, Canarese, and Malayalam occupy nearly the whole of the Indian peninsula. Some scattered dialects, still spoken north of the Dekhan, such as those of the Gonds, Uraon-Kols, Rdjmahals, and Brahuis, show that the race speaking Tamulic languages occupied formerly more northern seats, and was driven from the North to the South by the Aryan colonists of the country. Munda Languages. There is another cluster of languages, the Munda or Kol, which were formerly classed with the Tamulic, but which, as I was the first to prove in my Letter on the Turanian Languages1, constitute by themselves an independent family of speech. The dialects of the Santhals, Kols, Hos, BJmmij belong to this class. 1 Letter to Chevalier Bunsen, ' On the Turanian Languages,' in Bunsen's Christianity and Mankind, vol. iii. p. 263. 1854. LANGUAGES, NOT ARYAN AND NOT SEMITIC. 337 These dialects, which I had called Munda, Sir G. Campbell proposed to call Kolarian. Taic Languages. Iii the same Letter on the Turanian Languages, I comprehended under the name of Taic, the Siamese, and its congeners, such as Laos, Shan (Tenasserim), Ahom, Khamti, and Kassia. Gangetic Languages. Under Gangetic I classed Tibetan, with such related dialects as Lepclia, Murnri, Magar, Gurung, etc. Lohitic Languages. Under Lohitic I arranged Burmese with Boclo, Garo, Xdcja, Singjyho, and similar dialects. The Lohitic and Gangetic languages together are sometimes spoken of as Bhotiya. Languages of Farther India. There are still the languages of what used to be called Farther India, but these languages, now spoken by Anamites, Peguans, Cambodjans, and others, have been so little explored in the spirit of comparative philology that it must suffice for the present to men- tion their names. For our own purposes, the study of Natural Religion, they have yielded as yet very little. They have long been under the influence of either China, Tibet, or India, and have hardly attracted the attention of the collector of sacred folk-lore. Languages of the Caucasus. The same remark applies to the languages spoken in the Caucasus, such as the Georgian, Lazian, Suanian, z 338 . LECTUKE XIII. Mingrelian, Abchasian, Circassian, Thush, etc. They have been studied, but they have not yet been classified with any degree of success, and they yield us hardly any information on the natural growth of religious ideas. Language and Religion. We have thus surveyed the principal languages of Europe and Asia, more particularly those which have supplied the living soil for the growth of mythology and religion. I have intentionally con- fined my remarks to languages, without saying much of those who spoke them. Blood and hair and bones can teach us nothing or very little about religion, and the more carefully the two sciences of ethnology and philology are kept apart, the better, I believe, it will be for both. We know, from history, that races may give up their own language and adopt that of their conquerors, or, in some cases, of the conquered. Much more is this the case with religion. Our interest therefore is with re- ligion, whoever the people were who believed in it, just as we classify languages regardless of the people by whom they were spoken. Buddhism, for instance, •is an Aryan religion, and its origin would be unin- telligible on any but an Aryan substratum of language and thought. But it has been adopted by races whose languages belong to a totally different family, and whose intellectual peculiarities have completely changed the original character of Buddha's teaching. Who could understand Buddhism if he knew it in its Chinese, Mongolian, or Japanese form only ? In the case of Christianity we have a Semitic re- LANGUAGES, NOT ARYAN AND NOT SEMITIC. 339 ligion which has become Aryan in every sense of the word. And again, I ask, who could understand the original character of Christianity, unless he knew the language which gave rise to such names and concepts as Elohim and Jehovah and Messiah, unless he knew its antecedents in the Old Testament 1 It may happen that whole nations, most interesting to us in their ethnological and political character, are of no account whatever in the study of religion. Japan, for instance, so far as it is Buddhist, can teach us nothing except by showing us how a re- ligion, most spiritual in its origin, may become formal and ceremonial and unmeaning, if transferred to an uncongenial soil. Fortunately, however, something of the native religion of Japan also has been pre- served to us in the Shintoism of the past and of the present day. It is by this that Japan supplies a really important chapter in the history of Natural Keligion. What applies to Japan, applies likewise to such countries as Tibet, Burmah, and Siam, all of which have adopted the religion of Buddha, and can be of real interest to us by the remnants of their ancient popular religion only, which survive here and there in superstitions, customs, and legends. Egyptian. A larger harvest awaits the student of religion in Egypt. Here, however, both ethnology and philology offer us as yet but little help. Whether the ancient language of Egypt shows any traces of real relation- ship with Aryan and Semitic speech, is a question which has been asked again and again, but has never been satisfactorily answered. Similarities with Se- z 2 340 LECTURE XIII. mitic grammar there are, and there are coincidences between Egyptian and Aryan roots which are some- times startling. Some scholars have gone so far as to recognise in the language of Egypt the most primitive form of human speech, previous even to its differen- tiation as Aryan and Semitic. That Egypt was open from the earliest times to ethnic influences from the Semitic, the Aryan, and likewise from the African world, cannot be denied. But, for the present, we must be careful not to dogmatise on these problems, and it will be best to treat the Egyptian religion, for the study of which we possess such ample materials, as an independent nucleus of religious thought. The adjacent languages of Northern Africa are like- wise as yet in what may be called an unclassified state. In ancient times the language of Carthage and other Phenician settlements on the Northern coast was Semitic. But what are called the Sub-Semitic or sometimes the Hamitic languages, the Berber or Libyan (Kabyle, Shilhe, Tuareg or Tamasheg), and some of the aboriginal dialects of Abyssinia or Ethi- opia (the Somali, Galla, Beja or Bihari, Agau, Dan- kali, etc.), must be submitted to a far more searching analysis before they can claim a real right to the name of either Hamitic or Sub- Semitic. Fortunately they are of small importance to us in our investiga- tions of primitive religious concepts and names, as Mohammedanism has effaced nearly every trace of religious beliefs which preceded it in those regions. Africa. There is no time, and there is no necessity, for my laying before you the as yet only partially disen- LANGUAGES, NOT ARYAN AND NOT SEMITIC. 341 tangled network of languages spread over the rest of Africa. For our own purposes it will be sufficient if we distinguish between those linguistic and religious groups to which reference will have to be made in the course of our studies. The Nubas on the Upper Nile, who, according to F. Miiller, constitute with the Fulahs a separate lin- guistic class, need not occupy us at present, because here also little is known of their ancient religion previous to their conversion to Mohammedanism. Lepsius, in his ' Nubische Grammatik,' denies the in- dependent character of the language. There remain therefore : 1. The Hottentots and Bushmen in the South. The best judges now consider these two races, in spite of striking differences in language and religion, as ori- ginally one. 2. The Bantu races, or Kafirs, who extend in an unbroken line on the East-coast from several degrees north of the Equator down to the Hottentots, with whom they are often closely united. They have spread from East to West across the whole continent. The typical form of their language is so pronounced that there can be no doubt as to the relationship of these languages, though it may be that several little explored dialects are at present treated as Bantu which further analysis will have to adjudge to a different class. Dr. Bleek, who was the first to esta- blish the relationship of the best-known Bantu lan- guages on a truly scientific basis, was also the first to show the influence which such languages would na- turally exercise on the religious ideas of those who spoke them. Being without grammatical gender, in 342 LECTURE XII r. our sense of the word, these languages do not lend themselves easily to the personification of the powers of nature. Worship of ancestral spirits is very general among these Bantu tribes. 3. The Negro races, extending from the Western coast of Africa towards the interior. Here much re- mains to be done, and we must hope that future researches will lead to the discovery of several sub- divisions of what are now called Negro languages. Something, however, has been gained, in so far as this ill-defined name of Negro is restricted for the present to the inhabitants of the centre of Africa. What is called fetishism was first observed among these tribes, though it never constituted the original or the ex- clusive character of their religion. Lepsius \ in his ' Nubische Grammatik,' tries to re- duce the population of Africa to three types : — 1. The Northern negroes ; 2. The Southern or Bantu negroes ; B. The Cape negroes. And in accordance with this ethnological system, he arranges the languages also into three zones : — (1) The Southern, south of the Equator, the Bantu dialects, explored chiefly on the west and east coasts, but probably stretching across the whole con- tinent, comprising the Herero,, Pongue, Fernando Po, Kafir ('Osa and Zulu), Tshuana (Soto and Rolon), Suahili, etc. ; (2) the Northern zone, between the Equa- tor and the Sahara, and east as far as the Nile, com- prising Efik, Ibo, Yoruba, Ewe, Akra or Ga, Otyi, Kru, Vei (Mande), Temne, Bullom, Wolof, Fula, Sonrhai. Kanuri, Teda (Tibu), Logone, Wandala, Bagirmi, Maba, 2 M. M., Introduction to the Science of Religion, p. 239. LANGUAGES, NOT ARYAN AND NOT SEMITIC. 343 Konjara, Umale, Dinka, Shilluk, Bongo, Bari, Oigob, Nuba, and Barea ; (3) the Hamitic zone, including the extinct Egyptian and Coptic, the Libyan dialects, such as Tuareg (Kabyl and Amasheg), Hausa, the Kushitic or Ethiopian languages, including the Beja dialects, the Soho, Falasha, Agau, Galla, Dankali. and Somali. The Hottentot and Bushman lanouaofes are referred to the same zone. The Hamitic languages comprised in the third zone, the Egyptian, Libyan, and Kushitic, are considered by Lepsius as alien to Africa. They are all intruders from the East, though reaching Africa at different times and by different roads. The true aboriginal nucleus of African speech is contained in the first zone, and represented by that class of languages which, on account of their strongly marked gram- matical character, has been called the Bantu family. Professor Lepsius attempts to show that the languages of the Northern zone are modifications of the same type which is represented in the Southern zone, these modifications being chiefly due to contact and more or less violent friction with languages belonging to the Hamitic zone, and, to a certain extent, with Se- mitic languages also. America. Imperfect as our present classification of the native languages, and, in consequence, of the native religions of Africa is, still we have advanced so far that no scholar would speak any longer of African languages, and no theologian of African religions. The same applies to America. The division and the mutual relations of the numerous languages spoken on that continent are far from being satis- 344 LECTURE xnr. factorily established. Still, no one speaks any longer of American languages in general, nor would any one venture to treat the various religions of America as varieties of one and the same original type. Progress has been slow, still there has been progress here also. We can distinguish between at least four independent centres of language and likewise of religion, and though future researches may help us to subdivide more minutely, they will hardly tend to remove the landmarks which so far have been established. These four centres of language and religion are : — 1. The Red-Indians or Red -skins in the North. They will for the present have to be treated as one group, though not only in their language, but in their religious ideas and social customs also, different tribes exhibit very marked differences. Totemism, which has often been represented as the common feature of their religion, was originally much more of a social custom than a religious belief, though, like many social customs, it acquired in time some- thing of a religious sanction. Their religion, if we are allowed to generalise, is based on a belief in divine spirits, often in a Supreme Spirit, and the questions of the creation of the world and of man have occupied the thoughts of many of these so-called savages. 2. The next nucleus of an independent religion existed in Mexico, where, if we may trust tradition, two immigrations took place from the North, bringing with them new elements of civilisation. These immi- grants are known by the names of Tolteks and Azteks, the latter driving the former before them into more southern latitudes. Religion and ceremonial had LANGUAGES, NOT ARYAN AND NOT SEMITIC. 345 reached a very high development in Mexico at the time of its discovery and devastation by the Spani- ards. Even philosophical theories on the true nature of the gods were not unknown among the higher classes. 3. Central America seems to have been the seat of an independent civilisation, though strongly influenced by immigrations from the North. One language, the Quiche, has been more carefully studied, and an ancient book, the Popol Vuh, written in that lan- guage, has been published in the original and trans- lated. Some scholars have claimed for it a place among the Sacred Books of the world, and it is cer- tainly a rich mine for studying the traditions of the Mayas, as they existed in the fifteenth century. 4. Peru, the kingdom of the Incas, is chiefly dis- tinguished by its solar religion and solar worship, the very rulers being considered as children of the sun. Here also philosophical opinions seem to have sprung up from a religious soil, and the reasoning of a famous Inca has often been quoted, who maintained that there must be a higher power than their father, the sun, because the sun was not free, but had to perform its appointed course from day to day and from year to year. Besides these four groups, there are still a number of independent tribes of whose language and religion we know something, but not enough to enable us to classify them either by themselves or with other tribes. Such are the Arctic or Hyperborean tribes, more particularly the Eskimos and Greenlanders in the extreme North ; the Arowahes and the once famous Caribes in the north of South America and in the 346 lecture xirr. islands of the Antilles ; the aboriginal inhabitants of Brazil ; the Abipones, so well described by Dobrizhofer (1784) ; and in the South, the Pata- gonians and the inhabitants of Tierra del Fuego. Until the languages of these people have been carefully analysed by real scholars, any attempt at grouping them would prove simply mischievous. We are at present in a stage where our duty is to dis- tinguish, not to confound. Even to speak of the inhabitants of Tierra del Fuego as one race has pro- duced, as we saw, disastrous results, and it is to be hoped that we shall hear no more of a South American language or of a North American religion. It is true that certain legends have been found in the North as well as in the South of America, which seem to point to a common origin. But it will be time to account for such coincidences after the legends of each centre have been studied by them- selves, and after some clearer light has been thrown on the component elements of the population of the whole American continent. How, under present circumstances, scholars could have been bold enough to trace the whole American race to immigrations from Asia or even from Europe, is difficult to understand. The physical possibility, no doubt, was there, whether across the island bridges in the North, or by sea from West or East. We heard but lately how a large vessel, cast off by its crew, drifted safely from America to England (the Hebrides). The same may have happened on either coast of America. But any attempts to recognise in the inhabitants of America descendants of Jews, Phenicians, Chinese, or Celts are for the present LANGUAGES, NOT AHYAN AND NOT SEMITIC. 347 simply hopeless, and are in fact outside the pale of real science. Oceanic Languages. The languages which extend from Madagascar on the East coast of Africa to the Sandwich Islands, West of America, have been far more carefully studied than those of America and Africa. I speak of languages, not of races, for if ethnological classifi- cation has proved a failure anywhere, it has when applied to the mixture of blood that led to the formation of such races as Australians, Papuans, Malays, Polynesians, Melanesians, Micronesians, Ne- gritos, Mincopies, Orang-utans, and all the rest. From the latest work on this family of languages, by Dr. Codrington (' The Melanesian Languages,' Oxford, 1885), it appears that we must admit an original, though very distant, relationship between the Malay, the Polynesian, Melanesian, and Micro- nesian languages, but that in their later development it is possible to distinguish between the Malay, the Polynesian, and the Melanesian (with Micronesia n) as independent branches of a common stem. The dialects of Australia stand as yet apart, as too little known, as well as those of New Guinea, though some dialects, like the Motu of New Guinea, are clearly Melanesian. It follows from this division, that with regard to religion also we must distinguish between a Malay, a Polynesian, a Melanesian, and possibly a New Guinea (Papuan) and Australian centre. Our in- formation, however, from the two last, is very im- perfect. 348 LECTURE XIII. Malay. Owing to the proximity of the Malay islands to India, they have from the earliest times been overrun by immigrants, conquerors, and missionaries from the Asiatic Continent. Their ancient religious opinions are covered up and hidden under super- imposed strata of Hindu, Buddhist, Mohammedan, and Christian faith, and what there is of native growth in Java, Borneo and elsewhere represents probably the mere dregs of a former religion. Polynesia. The Polynesian languages, on the contrary, pre- sent us with an abundant growth both of religion and of poetical mythology. These Polynesian tradi- tions are particularly valuable to the student of com- parative mythology, because they offer striking simi- larities with the legends of Greeks, Romans, Teutons and others, without the possibility of a common origin or of a later historical contact. Melanesia. The Melanesians, so far as we can judge, do not differ much from the Polynesians and Micronesians in the fundamental outlines of their religious opinions, but they are not so rich in imaginative legends. Further research, however, may modify this opinion. As to the Australians and the Papuas of New Guinea, very little has been ascertained as yet of their religion, except what is embodied in their ceremonial observances and social customs. Classification of Languages, why necessary. This linguistic and religious survey, which has LANGUAGES, NOT ARYAN AND NOT SEMITIC. 349 taken up much of our time, will nevertheless, I hope, prove a saving of time in the progress of our work. Imperfect as it is, it will enable us to guard against certain mistakes very common in the Science of Religion. We have established certain broad lines of division in language and religion, and we shall hear no more of what used to be called the religion of savages, or barbarians, or black men, or red men, or Africans, or Americans. The student of religion knows no savages, no barbarians. Some of the races who are called savage or barbarous possess the purest, simplest, and truest views of religion, while some nations who consider themselves in the very van of civilisation, profess religious dogmas of the most degraded and degrading character. The African Zulu who was a match for Bishop Colenso, cannot be classed as an African or black man to- gether with the royal butchers of Dahomey; and the Inca philosopher who searched for something more divine than the sun, cannot be placed by the side of the Blackfoot performing the sun-dance1. Progress in the Science of Religion means at pre- sent discrimination, both with regard to the subject and the object of religious faith. As we speak no longer of the believers in a religion as either savages or barbarians, black men or red men, Africans or Americans, the idea also that we can truly character- ise any religion by such general terms as fetishism, totemism, animism, solarism, shamanism, etc., has long been surrendered by all critical students. In- 1 The Blackfoot Sun-Dance, by Rev. John McLean, in the Pro- ceedings of the Canadian Institute, No. 151 ; 1889. Notes bearing on the use of ordure in rites of a religious character, by John G. Bourke, Washington, 1888. 350 LECTURE XIII. gredients of all these isms may be found in most religions, but not one of them can be fully defined by such vague terms. Religions are everywhere the result of a long historical growth, and, like languages, they retain even in their latest forms traces of the stages through which they have passed. There is fetishism in some forms of Christianity ; there is spiritualism in the creed of some so-called worship- pers of fetishes. Generalisation will come in time, but generalisation without a thorough knowledge of particulars is the ruin of all sciences, and has hitherto proved the greatest danger to the Science of Religion. LECTURE XIV. LANGUAGE AND THOUGHT. "What should we toe without Language ? AFTER we have finished our survey of the lan- guages which are spoken at present over the civilised world, and which have been spoken there so long as we know anything of the presence of the human race on this planet of ours, it is time to ask the question, what language really is. Now I ask, Do you know anything in the whole world more wonderful than language 1 No doubt, even if we were not able to speak, we should still be able to see, to hear, to taste, to smell, and to feel. We could taste what is sweet and like it, and taste what is bitter and dislike it. We might run away from the fire, because it burns, and turn towards the water, because it is cool, or because it quenches our thirst ; but we should have no words to distinguish lire from water, or hot from cold, or sweet from bitter. We should be like children who have burnt their fingers and cry, who have tasted sugar and smile, who have swallowed vinegar and howl. Some people might call this running away from what hurts, and turning towards what is pleasant, rational, just as they say that a dog is rational because he runs away from his master when he raises his stick, and jumps up at him when he holds out a piece of meat. 352 LECTURE XIV. If by a bold metaphor this is to be called reason, we need not object., if only we distinguish between conscious and unconscious, between worded and un- corded reason, and if we remember, that, by using reason in that very enlarged sense, we may be driven in the end to call even the shutting of our eyes at the approach of a blow an act of reasoning. However, with or without language, we might cer- tainly do all this, and a great deal more. We might fight and kill, we might love and protect. We might, if we were very clever, accumulate dispositions and habits which by repeated inheritance would enable our descendants to build nests, or warrens, or bee- hive huts. The strongest might possibly learn to act as sentinels and make themselves obeyed ; the weaker sex might even invent signals of danger and other signs of communication. I doubt not that chivalrous and unchivalrous feel- ings also might be aroused in our breast, such as we see among the higher animals, and that jealousy and revenge as well as friendship and love might influence our actions. But with all this, imagine that we were sitting here, looking at one another with a kind of good- natured bovine stare, but without a single word, not only on our lips, but in our minds ; our mind being in fact a mere negative plate, without our being able to lay hold of any of the outlines drawn on it, by saying this is this, and this is that ! Definition of Thinking1. Some philosophers, as you know, hold that men, like animals, though they possessed no language, LANGUAGE AND THOUGHT. 353 might still sit silent and think. Unfortunately they do not tell us what they mean and what they do not mean by thinking, but it seems clear that they use thinking as synonymous with every kind of mental activity. Des Cartes., when discussing his fundamental principle, Cogito ergo turn, did the same; but, as an honest philosopher, he warned us that he used cogitare in that widest sense l, so as to include sensation, per- ception, memory, imagination, and all the rest. If the meaning of to think is avowedly stretched to that extent, no one would drearn of denying that animals, though speechless, can think, and that we also could think without language, that is to say, without ever having possessed language, without knowing one word from another. What are we thinking- of? But now let us ask those philosophers the simple question, If we can think without language, what are we thinking of? What indeed ? I do not wish to lay a trap, like a cross-examining lawyer. Of course, if you told me what you were thinking of, you could do it only by using a word. Nor do I claim to be a thought-reader, and tell you. without your having told me, what you are thinking off for that, of course, I could only do by using a word. But I ask you to ask yourselves, what you are thinking of, if you are thinking of anything, and I shall join myself in that experiment. Suppose we wTere all thinking, as we call it, of a dog, then as soon as we attempt to answer to ourselves the question, What are we think- * Des Cartes, Meditations, ed. Cousin, vol. i. p. 253 ; ' Qu'esf <•<> qu'une chose qui pense? ("est une ohose qui doute, qui entend, qui concoit, qui affirme, qui nie, qui veut, qui no veut pas, qui imagine aussi, ct qui sent.' A a 354 LECTURE XIV. ing of? we can only do it by saying to ourselves or to others, Dog. It is perfectly true that canis, chien, Hund would do as well, and we need not even pro- nounce any of these words while remembering a certain dog, or while hearing the barking of a number of dogs about us. But though we may suppress the sound or recollection of a word after we have once heard it, or replace it even by another word taken from another language, we cannot possibly become conscious to ourselves of what we are thinking, with- out having the word in reserve, or, as the Italians say, in petto, or, as some savages say, in the stomach. Thinking1 in German or English. If any doubt still remains in your mind on the impossibility of real thought without language, ask yourselves what you mean in asking a foreigner who has long lived in England, whether he thinks in German or in English ? What would you say, if he were to answer, In neither. You would, I believe, think, and think rightly, that he was a fool. Why we cannot think without words. But if that is so, if thought, in the properly re- stricted sense of that word, is impossible without language, you may well ask, why that should be so. Many people suppose that we first form our thoughts, or as they call it our ideas, and that afterwards we go in search of certain sounds, which we attach to our ideas, and which we retain because we find them very useful for the purpose of communication. Now I ask you, is such a process possible or conceivable 1 Do Ave ever find ourselves in possession of a concept, but without a name for it, unless indeed we have for- LANGUAGE AND THOUGHT. 355 gotten, and know that we have forgotten, the name which we formerly possessed ? Or is there anywhere in the whole world a place where we could find empty sounds, such as father and mother, meaning nothing as yet, but ready for use when wanted ? I know some people speak of inexpressible thoughts, but they mean feelings ; others say they may have a clear con- cept of a plant, without knowing its name ; they speak of that plant, Oh, what do you call it ? But is not plant a name, is not vegetable a name, is not object a name, is not it a name, is not even What do you call it, a name ? We often do not know the exact or right name, but in that case we always know the more general name. If we had never seen or heard of an elephant, we should not know its name, but we should know that it was an animal and call it so ; we should know that it was a quadruped, and call it so. If we did not know whether what we saw was an inanimate lump, or a plant, or a bird, fish, or mammal, we should have no name for it beyond the name thing. We could not name it further, because we know no more about it, because we could not bring it under any more definite conceptual name. We may see, hear, and touch the elephant, we may have a more or less exact image of it, but until we can predicate or name some distinguishing feature of it, we could neither name nor know it, in the true sense of that word. To suppose, as is done by most philosophers, that we first find ourselves in command of an army of naked concepts, and that we afterwards array them in verbal uniforms, is impossible for two very simple reasons ; first, because there is no magazine which A a 2 3o6 LECTURE XIV. could supply these verbal uniforms, and secondly, because we never meet with naked concepts ; or, to put it more strongly still, because we never meet with a rabbit without a skin, or an oyster without a shell. The reason why real thought is impossible without language is very simple. What we call language is not, as is commonly supposed, thought plus sound, but what we call thought is really language minus sound. That is to say, when we are once in pos- session of language, we may hum our words, or remember them in perfect silence, as we remember a piece of music without a single vibration of our vocal chords. We may also abbreviate our words, so that such expressions as, ' If Plato is right,' may stand for a whole library. We may in fact eliminate the meaning of the word so that the word only remains as a symbol 1 ; we may even substitute algebraic signs for real words, and thus carry on processes of reckon- ing or reasoning which in their final results are perfectly astonishing. But as little as we can reckon without actual or disguised numerals, can we reason without actual or. disguised words. This is the last result to which the Science of Language has led us, and which has changed the Science of Language into the Science of Thought. ' We think in words3 must become the charter of all exact philosophy in future, and it will form, I believe, at the same time the recon- ciliation of all systems of philosophy in the past. Communication, not language. But surely, it is said, men communicate, and animals too communicate, without language. Yes, 1 Science of Thought, p. 35. LANGUAGE AND THOUGHT. 357 they certainly do, we all do, some more, others less successfully. The Polynesians, as Chamisso 7 tells us in his charming Voyage round the world (1815-1818), are sparing of words, and a wink often takes the place of a long speech. Perhaps it does so even among less savage races. They do not even say Yes, when they can help it, but only move their brow. It is only to a stranger that they will say Inga, yes. But such communication is not thought, if we use our words properly. I go even a step further, and maintain that we are so made that, whether we like it or not, we must show by outward signs what passes within us. There are few people who can so repress their emotions as not to let others see when they are angry or happy. We blush, we tremble, we frown, we pout, we grin, we laugh, we smile, and what can be more tell-tale, and sometimes more eloquent, than these involuntary signs? I have no doubt that animals betray their feelings by similar signs, and that these signs are understood by their fellow-creatures. You have only to disturb an ant-hill, and see what happens. A number of ants will run away on their beaten tracks, they will stop every ant they meet, and every ant, after having been touched and communicated with, will run to the ant-hill to render help with the same alacrity with which a member of the fire-brigade runs towards the place of conflagration after hearing the bugle in the street. We cannot understand how it is done, but that little head of an ant, not larger than the head of a pin, must have been able to express terror and implore help, even as a dog will run up to 1 Chamisso's Werke, vol. i. p. 357. 358 LECTURE XIV. you and express in his face terror, and by his motions implore your help. But when will people learn that emotions are not thoughts, and that if we call anger or joy thought, we simply muddle our own thoughts and confound our own language? I believe that some of these involuntary manifesta- tions of our feelings may in time lead to intentional gestures ; and we know from pantomimes, also from communications that are said to take place in America and Australia between tribes speaking different lan- guages, that this gesture-language may be brought to a very high degree of perfection. But we must not forget that in all cases where this communication by means of gestures has been observed, the parties con- cerned are each in possession of a real language, that in fact they think first in their own conceptual lan- guage and then translate their thoughts back into pantomime \ The subject, however, is curious, and deserves more study than it has hitherto received. We imagine we can understand why a person kneeling down is supposed to implore mercy, why another shaking his fist is supposed to say, Stand off! But these gestures, as used in different countries, have not always the same meaning, and even the expressive 1 In the island of Gomera, one of the islands of the Canary Archipelago, people communicate by means of a whistling language. The island is traversed by many deep ravines and gullies which run out in all directions from the central plateau. They are not bridged, and can often only be crossed with great difficulty, so that people who really live very near to each other in a straight line have to make a circuit of hours when they wish to meet. Whistling has therefore become an excellent means of communication, and has gradually assumed the proportions of a true substitute for speech. But what they whistle is their own language. LANGUAGE AND THOUGHT. 359 signs used by deaf and dumb people are by no means identical all over the globe 1. Children again, long before they are able to speak, can imitate the acts of eating, drinking, riding on their father's knees, and thus express their little wishes ; but a wish is not a thought, as little as fear and horror. If some philosophers like to call these states of feeling thought, they may do so at their own peril, but they ought at all events to let us know, in order that others may be able to discount such license. Images. Some more serious philosophers put in a claim for images. Images, they say, such as our senses leave in our memory, may surely be called thought. They may, no doubt, if only we let others know that in our own philosophical dialect we use thinking in that ex- tended sense. But it is surely better to distinguish and to keep the term imagination for signifying the play of our images. I myself hold it impossible that human beings should have real images without first having framed them in names ; and among physiologists, Helmholtz denies the possibility of our having percep- tions without names. But, of course, if careful ob- servers, such as Mr. Galton, assure us that they have images without knowing what they are images of, and without remembering what they are called, we are bound to believe them, even though we cannot follow them. What they are anxious for is evidently to show that animals, though they have no language, have images, that they combine these images, and that their acts, their sensible, or, as they like to call 1 Mallery, Sign Language among the North- American Indians. 360 LECTURE XIV. them, their rational acts, are determined by them. Let that be so, at least for argument's sake. But even then, is not this imagination or even this reason- ing without language utterly different from imagina- tion and reasoning with language** Suppose a dog, instead of coming to me, as one of my dogs did, ex- pressing his uneasiness and then dragging me on to his rug which was red, and showing me that it was occupied by my other dog, who ought to have been on his own rug which was blue, looking at me re- proachfully till I had ordered the other dog away, and then taking possession with all the pride of an injured innocent of his own red rug — suppose that dog, instead of wheedling and barking were suddenly to stand up on his hind legs and say to me, ' The other dog has taken my rug ; please, Sir, order him away,' should we not almost go out of our mind 1 Or let us place an infant and a grown-up man side by side, the one struggling and crying for a cup of milk, the other saying plainly, ' I should like that cup of milk.' Is not the distance between these two acts immeasurable, the one being merely the result of the direct or reflex action of our senses, the other the result of a growth that has gone on for thousands of years ? The grown-up man also, if he were dying of thirst, might no doubt rush towards the cup and swallow it without saying a word, and we might call the expression of his impetuous features language, and his rushing movements reason. But we should gain nothing by the use of this metaphorical language. There are philosophers who tell us that an infant could not stretch out its arms without £oin£ through a silent syllogism : ' By stretching out our arms we LANGUAGE AND THOUGHT. 361 obtain wheat we wish for ; I wish for this cup of milk, therefore I stretch out my arms.' It may be so, but we know nothing about it and never shall, till the infant is able to speak, that is to say, ceases to be an infant, and then tells us what it thinks. Between the infant, however, and the man who is able to speak, there is not a distance of ten or twenty years only. The language which he has accepted is the result of intellectual labour carried on for thousands of years. The original framing of our words and thoughts is a process which no one but the geologist of language has even the most remote idea of, and to suppose that one human being could, in the space of ten or twenty years, have accumulated the wealth of his grammar and dictionary is like believing that the earth with its mountains and rivers could have been made in six days. It is extraordinary that the same argument, which has been answered ad nauseam, is brought forward again and again. It is quite true that the infant and the parrot are for a time without language, and that both learn to say after a time, 'How do you do?' But the child learns to speak human language, while the parrot never speaks Parrot ese. Involuntary and voluntary sounds. The next step after what has been called the lan- guage of gestures, leads us on to involuntary and voluntary sounds. I call involuntary sounds inter- jections which have a direct natural origin, which express joy, fear, anger, admiration, assent or dissent. To us, accustomed to our own interjections, there seems a natural appropriateness in their sound, but here too a comparative study teaches us that it is not 362 LECTURE XIV. so. No, for instance, does not always mean no ; in Syrianian it means yes. Even in Irish we find for No, not only naicc, but also aicc 1. Voluntary inter- jections I call such imitative sounds as how wow for dog, and moo for cow. Here, too, we find that what seems to us perfectly natural and intelligible, is not always so. Whereas to our ears the dog says bow wow, he says Miff klaff to a German ear. It is extremely difficult to render inarticulate sounds by our alphabet. Many attempts have been made to write down the sounds uttered by birds, but hitherto with small success. A great phonetician, well acquainted with the latest theories of physio- logical phonetics, has spent many days and nights in watching the notes of the nightingale ; and what do you think his rendering has come to 1 The real note of the nightingale, as reduced to alphabetical writing, is : Dailidurei faledirannurei lidundei faledaritturei. You know that before languages were studied scientifically, it was a very general idea that all human speech arose in that way, and that the ultimate elements of our words were imitations of natural sounds or involuntary interjections. I called these theories the Bow-wow and Pooli-pooh theories. Some philosophers have lately added a third theory, which they call the Yo-heho theory, but which is really a subdivision only of the Pooli-pooli theory. By a most extraordinary mistake this theory has been ascribed to Noire, who was really one of its most determined opponents. According to this theory language would have been derived directly from the 1 Zeuss, Grammatica Celtica. Yes in Old Irish is iss ed, ' est hoc,' or simply ed, =€k>th. ita. — Whitley Stokes. LANGUAGE AND THOUGHT. 363 cries uttered by people while engaged in pulling, rubbing, digging, rowing, and similar primitive occu- pations. In this the supporters of this Yo-heho theory have, no doubt, touched on a very important phase in the growth of language and thought, as we shall see presently ; but if they look upon sounds such as Yo-heho as mere interjections, they are still in the bitterness of the Pooh-pooh theory, that is to say, they have not even perceived the difficulty of the problem which they wish to solve. The names Bow-wow, Pooh-pooh, and Yo-heho theo- ries have sometimes been objected to as too homely, and as possibly offensive. But as these theories in their crude form are no longer held by any scholar, these names are really quite harmless, and they are certainly useful, because they tell their own tale. If we are afraid of them, we must use the cumbersome names of Mimetic, Onomatojioetic or Interject ional theory, every one of them requiring an elaborate commentary. The Bow-wow, Pooh-pooh, and Yo-heho theories. These three theories, however, were by no means so illogical as they seem to us now. They were no doubt a ijriori theories, but they had certain facts to support them. There are interjections in every lan- guage, and, by the general analogy of language, some of them have been raised into verbs and adjectives and substantives. Hush, for instance, the German husch, is an interjection which in German is used to drive away birds, to express any quick movement; to attract attention, while in English it is now chiefly 364 LECTURE XIV. employed to enjoin silence. From this interjection, and from no root, are derived in German the adjective husch, meaning quick, and the substantive Husch, quickness, also a blow, a box on the ear. Thus the lines in Shakespeare's Hamlet, And we have done but greenly In hugger mugger to inter him. are translated in German by Und thoricht war's von tins, so unter'm Husch Ihn zu bestatten. We have besides a German feminine substantive, Die Husche, which means a shower of rain, and two verbs, huschen, to move quickly, and husch eln, to scamp one's work. In English to hush has taken the exclusive meaning of to enjoin silence, to quiet. This would be an illustration of the Pooh-pooh theory. The Boiv-woiv theory can claim a number of words, the best known being cuckoo, in Greek kokkv£, in Latin cucMus, in Sanskrit kokila. In Greek we have also a verb kokkv(€lv, redupl. perfect, k€k6kkvkcl, to cry cuckoo. The Yo-heho theory is really a subdivision of the Pooh-pooh theory, but it may be illustrated by bang ! as an interjection that accompanies a blow; to bang, to beat violently, and banged hair, which has lately been much admired. It would be a most interesting subject to collect all the words which, whether in English or in German, or in Latin, Greek and Sanskrit, are formed direct from interjectional elements. And it would teach us better than anything else that, after we have claimed all that can rightly be claimed for this LANGUAGE AND THOUGHT. 365 amorphous stratum of human speech, we have only taken the mere outworks, while the real fortress of language has not been touched. Roots. That fortress could not be taken by storm, but only by a regular siege ; — it will not surrender to a priori arguments, but only to a 'posteriori analysis. This analysis was carried out by the founders of Compara- tive Philology, by Bopp, Grimm, Pott and others ; but it had been attempted more than two thousand years ago by Sanskrit grammarians. They had taken Sanskrit, one of the richest and most primitive of Aryan languages, and by submitting every word of it to a careful analysis, that is to say, by separating all that could be separated and proved to be merely formal, they had succeeded in discovering certain elements which would yield to no further analysis, and which they therefore treated as the ultimate facts of language, and designated as roots. The number of roots admitted by these ancient Sanskrit grammarians was far too large however. We have now reduced their number to about 800, — I believe they will be reduced still further, — and with these we undertake to account for all the really important words which occur in Sanskrit literature. In more modern languages many clusters of words de- rived from one root have become extinct, and their place is taken by secondary and tertiary derivatives of other roots, so that for the English Dictionary (now being published at Oxford), which is said to compre- hend 250,000 words, no more than about 460 roots ' 1 Science of Thought, p. 210. 366 LECTURE XIV. are required to account for all that has been said by Shakespeare, Milton, and Byron. But more than that : the number of independent concepts conveyed by these 800 Sanskrit roots, is not 800, or anything like it, but has been reduced to the small number of 121. With these 121 radical concepts every thought that has ever passed through a human brain can be. and has been expressed. This would have sounded like a wild dream to Plato and Aristotle, nay even to Locke and Kant, and yet it is a fact that can no more be questioned than the fact that the whole kalei- doscope of nature — all that was ever seen in this myriad-shaped world of ours — is made up of about sixty elementary substances. With regard to the meaning of the 800 roots of Sanskrit, we find that most of them express acts, such as striking, digging, rubbing, crushing, pounding, cutting, gathering, mixing, sprinkling, burning, — acts in fact which represent some of the primitive occupa- tions of man, but which by means of generalisation, specialisation, and metaphor have been made to express the most abstract ideas of our advanced society. A root meaning to strike supplied names for a good stroke of business and for striking remarks. To dig came to mean to search for and to inquire. To rub was used for rubbing down, softening, appeas- ing; to burn came to mean to love, and also to be ashamed ; and to gather did excellent service for expressing in primitive logic what we now call observation of facts, the connection of major and minor, or even syllogism. And now we must gather up the threads of our own argument. LANGUAGE AND THOUGHT. 367 We saw that real thought was impossible without words. We have now seen that all words are made of roots, and that these roots expressed originally primitive co-operative acts, such as would be performed by men in the earliest stages of their social life. Words derived from conceptual roots. But this is not all. Let us remember that what shook for the first time the faith of those who thought they could explain all the words of our language as imitations of natural sounds was the strange fact that in the names of animals there was no trace whatever of these sounds. After the cuckoo had been claimed as a case in point, as the great trophy or totem of the Bow-wow theory, everything else collapsed. In the names for dog there was no trace of bow-wow, in the names for horse no trace of neighing, in the names for donkey no trace of braying, in the names for cow no trace of mooing. On the contrary, it was found that every word which was derived from a root ex- pressed a general concept. The name for horse, the Latin equus, the Sanskrit asva, was derived from a root meaning to be sharp or quick ; hence it became clear that the horse had been conceived and named as a runner or racer. From the same root came words for stone, spear, needle, point, sharpness of sight, quickness of thought, to the very 'cuteness of the New World. The serpent was called from a root meaning to creep along, and another name of it, the Sk. a hi, the Greek e^u, came from a root meaning to throttle. Sun, Gothic siinna, is derived from a root su, to bring forth ; son, Gothic sunns, comes from the same 368 LECTUKE XIV. root, in a passive sense, and meant originally the begotten, filius. Hand comes from a root which exists in Gothic as hinthan, to seize. Eye, Gothic augo, Lat. oc-ulus, Sk. aksha, all come from the same root, which meant originally to point, to pierce. Another name for eye in Sanskrit is ne train, which means the leader, from ni, to lead. So we could go on for ever tracing back every word to its root and its radical concept. I do not mean to say that we succeed in every case. There are still many words which have not been brought to disclose their secret history, and there is still plenty of work to do for critical etymologists. There are many words which require no knowledge of Sanskrit at all for their etymological explanation, and which we use constantly without thinking of their etymological meaning. Thus a settle is clearly what we sit on, and so also, though less directly, a saddle ; a road is what we ride on; a stand what we stand on ; a bier is what bears us, a burden what we bear ourselves ; a shaft is what is shaved or planed ; a draft what is drawn, a drift what is driven, a rift what is riven. A thrill of joy, or a thrilling story, both come from to thrill, to pierce, to perforate : but to bore also, whatever its historical origin may have been, is now used to express that slow rotatory worry- ing talk which is apt to make us gnash our teeth \ Well then, you may take it as an established fact that, with the exception of some onomatopoetic sur- vivals, our words are in the main conceptual ; that 1 On the introduction of the word bore, see Academy, Jan. 5, 12, 19, 1889. LANGUAGE AND THOUGHT. 369 they are derived from conceptual roots, or, to put it differently, that our words are concepts. If therefore it is admitted that we cannot think except in con- cepts, it will be easy enough to understand why we cannot think except in words. Are concepts possible without words ? But you may say, Cannot a concept exist without a word 1 Certainly not, though in order to meet every possible objection, we may say that no concept can exist without a sign, whether it be a word or anything else. And if it is asked, whether the con- cept exists first, and the sign comes afterwards, I should say No ; the two are simultaneous : but in strict logic, the sign, being the condition of a concept, may really be said to come first. After a time, words may be dropt, and it is then, when we try to remember the old word that gave birth to our concept, that we are led to imagine that concepts come first, and words afterwards. Berkeley. I know from my own experience how difficult it is to see this clearly. We are so accustomed to think without words, that is to say, after having dropt our words, that we can hardly realise the fact that origin- ally no conceptual thought was possible without these or other signs. No strong man, unless he was told, would believe that originally he could not walk with- out leading-strings. Berkeley seems to have struggled all his ]ife with this problem, and honest as he always is, he gives us the most contradictory conclusions at which he arrived from time to time. It was one of the fundamental principles of his philosophy that Eb 370 LECTURE XIV. concepts, or what were then called general ideas, are impossible except by attaching a word or sign to a percept, or what he called a particular idea. Hence he knew that concepts were impossible without words, and discursive thought impossible without concepts. But in spite of that he was often very angry with these words, and in the Introduction to his ' Treatise concerning the Principles of Human Understanding ' (1710) he wrote: 'Since therefore words are so apt to impose on the understanding [I am resolved in my enquiries to make as little use of them as possibly I can] : whatever ideas I consider I shall endeavour to take them bare and naked into my view, keeping out of my thoughts, so far as I am able, those names which long and constant use have so strictly united with them V Again, in his Common-place Book (Works, ed. Fraser, vol. i. p. 1 52), he says : ' If men would lay aside words in thinking, 'tis impossible they should ever mistake, save only in matters of fact. I mean it seems impossible they should be positive and secure that anything was true which in truth is not so. Certainly I cannot err in matter of simple perception. So far as we can in reasoning go without the help of signs, there we have certain knowledge. Indeed, in long deductions made by signs there may be slips of memory.' Having thus delivered his soul against words — the very signs without which concepts, as he shows, were impossible, or which were at all events strictly united with our thoughts — he breaks forth in another place (vol. iv. p. 455) in the following 1 The Irish bull, enclosed in brackets, was omitted in the second edition. LANGUAGE AND THOUGHT. 371 panegyric : ' Words (by them meaning all sorts of signs) are so necessary, instead of being (when duly used or in their own nature) prejudicial to the advancement of knowledge, or an hindrance to know- ledge, that without them there could in mathematiques themselves be no demonstration.' It seems to me that most modern philosophers are just in the same state of haziness with regard to the relation between thought and language as Berkeley was ; only they are not quite so honest towards them- selves. The Bishop, for instance, in another passage of his Common-place Book (vol. iv. p. 429), after having satisfied himself ' that it would be absurd to use words for recording our thoughts to ourselves or in some private meditations,' interpellates himself by adding the following note, 'Is discursive thought, then, independent of language ? ' He forgot that he had given the answer himself, namely, that it was not and that it could not be. Process of naming". Suppose we see the same colour in snow, milk, chalk, and linen. We cannot single it out, take it away or abstract it from the different sensuous ob- jects in which it occurs, unless we have a sign or handle to do it with, and that sign, for all the ordinary purposes of thinking, is a word, such as white. Until that word is there, we may have different sensations, but no concepts, not even percepts, in the true sense of the word. It is the electric spark of the word which changes something common to various sensations into a percept, as, afterwards, it changes something common to various percepts into a concept, b b 2 372 LECTURE XIV. and something common to various concepts into a higher concept. But whence came that electric spark ] Where did men find that sign to signify many things ; and did not that sign already, in order to be applicable to different perceptions, require something of a compre- hensive or conceptual character ? Origin of concepts. Yes, it did. And here lies the punctum sal i ens of the whole philosophy of language. Long before the question was asked, how man came in possession of words, there was the old question, how man came in possession of concepts. Nearly all philosophers drew the line of demarcation between man and beast at concepts. Up to concepts the two seemed alike. Then the question arose, How did man alone go beyond percepts and arrive at concepts ? The usual answer was that man possessed some peculiar gift or faculty which enabled him to form concepts, and to comprehend the manifold as one. Even now many philosophers are satisfied with that mythology. But this answer is no answer at all. We might as well say that man began to write because he had the faculty of writing. We want to know what forced man to form concepts, whether he liked it or not. Why should he not have been satisfied with what the senses gave him, with seeing this, with hearing that ? WThy should he have gone beyond the single images and looked for the general ? He might have been very happy in the world of sensations, perceptions, and images. Why should he ever have left it ? LANGUAGE AND THOUGHT. 373 What we call the roots of language betray the secret. Almost all of them express, as we saw, the common acts of man. Now before man is conscious as yet of any object, as an object, he cannot help being conscious of his own acts, and as these acts are mostly repeated and continuous acts, he becomes con- scious, without any new effort, of his many or re- peated acts as one. Here lies the genesis of the most primitive and, I may add, the first inevitable con- cepts : they consist in our consciousness of our own repeated acts as one continuous action. To rub, for instance, was not only to rub once, and then again, and then again, but it was the continuous act of rubbing, afterwards of smoothing, softening, appeas- ing; and thus the root, meaning originally to rub, came in time to mean to appease the anger of the gods. There is an uninterrupted chain or develop- ment between our saying, Oh God, have mercy ! and our earliest ancestors' saying, Be rubbed down, be smooth, be softened, ye gods ! Former theories. It will now perhaps become clear why the three old theories of the origin of language and thought, the Pooh-pooh theory, the Boiu-ivotv theory, and the Yo-keho theory, completely fail to explain what has to be explained, namely, how conceptual words arose. Cuckoo would be an imitation of the sound of the cuckoo, bow-wow of the barking of the dog, pooh- pooh of our contempt, yo-heho of our labour ; but with all this we should never get out of the enchanted circle of mere sensuous knowledge. We want con- ceptual sounds. How can we get them ? 374 LECTURE XIV. Now here the advantage of what I shall call in future the Synergastic theory will at once become evident. If, as we know, people in a primitive state accompany most of their common acts by sounds, then the clamor concomitans of these acts is not the sign of a single act, but the inseparable accompaniment of our consciousness of our many repeated acts as one action. Here we see the first dawn of conceptual thought. If this is once clearly perceived, it will likewise be perceived that the difference between this theory of the origin of conceptual language and the old onomatopoetic theories is not one of degree, but of kind, and marks a greater advance in the Science of Language than the Copernican theory did in the Science of Astronomy. Here lies Noire" s real merit. He was the first who saw that the natural genesis of concepts was to be found in the consciousness of our acts. I was able to give the proof of it by showing that nearly all roots in Sanskrit were expressive of our acts. Those who do not see the difficulties which have to be explained when we ask for the origin of our conceptual roots, may consider the old Pooh-pooh and Bow-wow theories quite sufficient. To the true philosopher the Synergastic theory is the only one which approaches or touches the hem of the problem that has to be solved, namely, how concepts arose, and how concepts were expressed. The ' clamor concomitans.' One question only we are unable to answer, namely, why the clamor concomitans of the different acts of men, the consciousness of which constituted their first concepts, should have been exactly what it was. Why LANGUAGE AND THOUGHT. 375 in crushing they should have uttered MAR, in carry- ing VAH, in stretching TAN, in scattering STAR, is beyond our ken. All we can say is that the possi- bilities in uttering and still more in fixing these sounds were almost unlimited, and that though we may imagine that we perceive some reasonableness in some of them, we very soon come to the end of such speculations. Who does not imagine that there is some simi- larity between the root VA, to blow, and the sound of our own breathing, or, if we adopt the mimetic theory, the sound of the wind? But if that is so with VA, what shall we say to DHAM, to blow, and /SVAS, to breathe? That there should be in some cases some vague similarity between the sound of a root and the sound produced by the work which it accompanies is intelligible, and so far the specula- tions on the supposed inherent meaning of certain letters, which begin as early as Plato's Cratylos, are not without some value. Possibly, if we could go back to an earlier stage in the formation of roots, his speculations might seem still better founded. But we must here too learn to be satisfied with what is within the reach of historical knowledge, or, if we must needs stretch our powers of vision beyond, follow the example of Plato and not assume too serious a countenance. A few quotations from Plato will serve to make my meaning clear. ' Now the letter R,' he says \ ' appeared to the im- poser of names an excellent instrument for the ex- pression of motion ; and he frequently used the letter 1 Cratylos, p. 426. 376 LECTURE XIV. for this purpose : for example, in the actual words pziv and por\ he represents motion by r; also in the words Tponos, trembling, rpayvs, rugged ; and again, in words such as dpaveiv, to crush, Kpovuv, to strike, €p€LK€iv, to bruise, dpvTTTeu', to break, Kepiiari^iv, to crumble, pvpLfietv, to whirl : of all the sorts of move- ment he generally finds an expression in the letter R, because, as I imagine, he had observed that the tongue was most agitated and least at rest in the pronuncia- tion of this letter, which he therefore used in order to express motion.' Let us consider these remarks for one moment. Nothing would be easier than to produce an equal number of words in which r occurs, and which ex- press not motion, but rest ; for instance, paxis, rib, bone, spine ; paxos, a hedge ; plyita, to freeze ; pC(a, a root ; pvrov, rein ; pdovvvixt, to strengthen ; pGxrrat;, pillar, &c. Secondly, in several of the words men- tioned by Plato the meaning of motion can easily be shown to be secondary, not primary. If K^pixari^iv, for instance, means to crumble, to cut into small slices, this is because Ktpixa means a small slice, and it does so because it is derived from ndpa, to shave, having been called originally a chip. But I doubt whether a serious refutation of these remarks is justified. They are useful only as showing what latitude there is and must be in this subject. While modern speculators see an imitation of the blowing of the wind in the root VA, Plato sees or rather hears an imitation of what is windy in the sound of the letters