Bs ary nee eS Eis: ee ee Stee ae ape pts pve; F ¢ , ad SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH LONDON : HUMPHREY MILFORD OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS OY OF Pi Agah i> CEp oY Oh pts By ce { 1926 | Ley, OGIGAL § aewine SYMBOLISM AND TRUT AN INTRODUCTION TO THE THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE BY RALPH MONROE iene ibe. D: INSTRUCTOR AND TUTOR IN PHILOSOPHY HARVARD UNIVERSITY CAMBRIDGE HARVARD UNIVERSITY PRESS 1925 COPYRIGHT, 1925 BY HARVARD UNIVERSITY PRESS PRINTED AT THE HARVARD UNIVERSITY PRESS CAMBRIDGE, MASS., U.S. A. TO . B. €. IN GRATITUDE FOR FAITH AND WORKS When I heard the learn’d astronomer; When the proofs, the figures, were ranged in columns before me; When I was shown the charts and the diagrams, to add, divide, and measure them; When I, sitting, heard the astronomer, where he lectured with much applause in the lecture-room, How soon, unaccountable, I became tired and sick; Till rising and gliding out, I wander’d off by myself, In the mystical moist night-air, and from time to time, Look’d up in perfect silence at the stars. Wait Wuitman, Drum Taps, 1865 PREFACE Tue theory of knowledge, occupying as it does the borderland between psychology, logic, and metaphysics, is a peculiarly diffi- cult subject to isolate and study in itself. The materials are widely scattered through philosophical literature, discussions of the problems appear in works of the most diverse character, and any one who attempts to single out the essential questions will be sure to omit some that are important in the eyes of many people and to include others that might be omitted. He will place his emphasis somewhere, with the result that he will fail to stress points that perhaps equally deserve emphasis. By way of remedy therefore he ought to indicate his angle of approach and call attention to what he believes are the major gaps in his treat- ment. The method of the present work is mainly critical and ana- lytic, rather than speculative.’ A single line of attack, which goes at once to the heart of the problem, is chosen—namely, the réle of symbols in knowledge; and about this the entire analysis is organized. Knowledge is inseparable from its expressions; a study of these expressions should therefore throw light on the theory of knowledge as a whole. With this conviction, I begin by examining meaning. But unfortunately the psychology of mean- ing is still in a fluid state, and the most that one who is not a psychologist can do is to point out in a rough way that to which, in his own experience, he gives the name “meaning.” The con- sideration of the logical forms of meanings leads to a discussion of the nature of facts, relations, qualities, universals and indi- 1 See Mr. C. D. Broad’s interesting statement of the difference between critical and speculative philosophy in Contemporary British Philosophy, edited by Professor J. H. Muirhead (1924), pp. 63 ff.; also, Broad’s Scientific Thought, (1923), introduction. Vill PREFACE viduals, classes, description, synthesis and analysis, possibility, and finally to the definition and tests of truth. The question of truth is naturally linked to that of belief, judgment, and nega- tion; and since logical form stands out most clearly in quasi- mathematical deductive systems, a chapter is given to the study of these systems. Metaphysical ideas are kept as far as possible in the back- ground. Speculations concerning the relation of knowledge to an ultimate reality, that is, the issues of idealism and realism, of gnosticism and agnosticism, of monism and pluralism, of the final validity of intuition as opposed to reason, are postponed until the last chapter; for a theory of the relation of knowledge to reality can be successfully held only after the ground has been cleared by an analysis of knowledge as a phenomenon. By exam- ining in detail the elements that make up the complex process, knowledge, I hope to introduce the reader to the wider specu- lative aspects of the subject; but in this direction the line of further thought is merely sketched. Discussions of the theory of knowledge often begin by classi- fying different types of views and proceed to compare these in the effort to distill some truth from each. This method is useful; it sets in order, for one unfamiliar with philosophy, a large amount of material; but it tends to become a study of conflict- ing schools of opinion on the problem of knowledge rather than of the problem itself. No systematic classification of epistemo- logical theories is given here, though an acquaintance with such classifications, and with the history of philosophy, will be help- ful to the reader. The central place of the concept of logical form gives to cer- tain parts of the book a superficial resemblance to Mr. L. Witt- genstein’s recent T'ractatus Logico-Philosophicus. How deep this resemblance goes I am unable to say, but the language is similar. “We make to ourselves (in thought) pictures of facts,” says Mr. PREFACE IX Wittgenstein. ‘‘In the picture and the pictured there must be something identical in order that the one can be a picture of the other at all. What the picture must have in common with the reality in order to be able to represent it after its manner — rightly or falsely —is its form of representation.”’ And Mr. Bertrand Russell adds to this the comment, “‘We speak of a logical picture of a reality when we wish to imply only so much resemblance as is essential to its being a picture in any sense, that is to say, when we wish to imply no more than an identity of logical form.” 4 The positive or descriptive theory of knowledge of the first seven chapters, which attempts cautiously to thread its way be- tween psychology and metaphysics, is no doubt allied to the type of philosophy known in Germany as phénomenologie. But it leans much more heavily towards psychology than does the phinomenologie of E. Husserl’s Logische Untersuchungen. Simi- larly, A. Meinong’s theory of the objective, set forth in his Unter- suchungen zur Gegenstandstheorte und Psychologie, in his studies of Hume and other works, appears to me to remove meaning too completely from its psychological setting and to view as simple what is in reality complex. However, I am at one with the phe- nomenological school in wishing to treat the theory of knowl- edge as an autonomous subject, that is, in desiring to assure it as much autonomy as belongs to any other branch of philosophy or to psychology. It is clear that knowledge cannot be wholly described in psychological terms. Hume attempted this and failed. But it is clear also that nothing is gained by trying to banish from knowledge all concrete psychological factors. Among the topics that might be included in such a critical study of knowledge but that are omitted or only lightly touched here, are the following: the knowledge of other minds and of the 1L. Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (1922), introduction, p. 10. x PREFACE self; the knowledge of values and the relations of theories of truth to theories of moral and aesthetic value; the validity of in- ductive inferences; the nature of scientific hypotheses, especially the place of elegance, economy, and completeness in scientific theories; the knowledge of space and time. (The allusions to space and time made in connection with the discussion of the in- dividual in Chapter III need to be supplemented by a detailed treatment, such as that of Mr. A. N. Whitehead’s The Principles of Natural Knowledge and Mr. C. D. Broad’s Scientific Thought. Particularly is this so at the present time, in view of the theory of relativity.) But what is said here of the fundamental factors in knowledge may suggest ways of approach to these more tangled problems. For the use of the student, a list of selected readings bearing on the subjects discussed in each chapter is given. This makes ‘available for study along with the text some of the widely scat- tered literature of the theory of knowledge, and will aid the stu- dent in obtaining a complete and systematic grasp of this branch of philosophy. R. M. E. CAMBRIDGE, Mass. January, 1925. CONTENTS INTRODUCTION Sods daybed ia SO AIO Og cle 1. The point of view of the theory of knowledge. —2. The positive theory of knowledge distinguished from the metaphysics of knowledge. CHAPTER I 1. Two senses of the term idea: idea and image. Images not the only ele- ments of knowledge. — 2. Images do not mean by resemblance alone. Sym- bols may mean any kind of objects; not restricted to meaning images or the present content of the mind. — 3. Mediate and immediate knowledge. Im- mediate knowledge the presentation of objects, mediate knowledge represen- tation through symbols. — 4. Presentation as a union of sensation and conception: sensations as signs. The passage from presentation to represen- tation. —5. Pure awareness: not the apprehension of sense data. A non-con- ceptual cognition of the real. — 6. Meaning a function of psychical activity: not the association of ideas. —'7. The meaning activity as preparation for an object. Overt action as a sign of belief. Belief and understanding. — 8. The behavioristic analysis of meaning inadequate: does not distinguish habits of meaning from other habits. The meaning activity a suspension of outward action, and hence observable only in introspection. — 9. Summary of the description of meaning. The nature of thought in general. — 10. Syn- tactical meaning: a complex meaning is a synthesis of meanings in a single meaning and represents an object or fact analytically, that is, as a unity of elements. — 11. Simple symbols: unless their meanings are defined they have significance only through reference to experienced objects. Simple symbols an integral part of presentations. — 12. Syntactical meanings built on simple meanings. A group of symbols may be significant when there is no object to which it refers. — 13. Summary. CHAPTER II AMMEN Sey Te ae aan Vax Se) Dama ERR eae oi 1. Symbolic groups as copies of the logical form of complex objects: their likeness to maps. — 2. Logical form determined by characters and relations which belong to objects as such. Symbols being objects share these with the things they mean. — 3. The concept of growping: the same as the concept of function. Demands that the whole be uniquely determined by its parts, and the meaning of a symbolic whole by the meanings of its parts. Symbols reproduce factual groups by symbolic groups. — 4. Numerical identity and diversity as formal characters of objects. These together with grouping de- termine the form of symbols and of facts. Simple symbols not formally dis- tinct; they set the scale of representation. Groups differ formally in multi- xii CONTENTS plicity, or type, or both. — 5. Signs of syntax: symbols of symbolism. A gen- eral schematism for presenting logical forms. Comparisons of form effected by one-to-one correlations. — 6. Alternative analyses of identical objects. Statements of identity not trivial. — 7. The principle of identity: two in- terpretations — as a principle of symbolism and as a statement of fact. Equivalences by definition. — 8. The third distinguishing feature of logical form: the distribution of tautologous symbols or identical elements within groups. — 9. Summary. CHAPTER III UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS: ORDER 1. The objects of knowledge are of double aspect: iniveal Aa; individual. — 2. The antinomy of the universal and the individual: no description reaches the specific essence of the individual. — 3. Spatial and temporal relations do not determine individuals. — 4. The postulate of the identity of indiscernibles: leaves the antinomy of the universal and individual un- solved for finite knowledge. — 5. Representation of the individual through a variable: the variability of proper names. — 6. Universals determinately known: as identities in changing and diverse instances. —7. The struc- tural function of universals: elements of unity in facts. The distinction be- tween terms and elements of unity. The unity of fact indefinable. — 8. The structural function of individuals: they appear only as terms. — 9. Uni- versals as terms: abstraction, beginning in perception and completed in con- ception. — 10. The objectivity of universals: arguments against nominal- ism. — 11. A grammar of symbolism based on the distinction between terms and elements of unity. — 12. Plans of syntax in symbolic systems as deter- mining possibilities for knowledge. Deductive and non-deductive systems. — 13. Nonsense: distinguished from fantasy, absurdity, and contradiction. — 14. Order described in terms of group structure. Asymmetry. — 15. Symmetry: symmetrical relations as relations without sense. — 16. Repre- sentations of order through spatially and temporally ordered symbols am- biguous. — 17. Complex elements of unity. — 18. Summary. CHAPTER IV DESCRIPTION AND ANALYSIS 1. General nature of descriptions: Votes euiee to terms through predicates of these terms. — 2. Descriptions mean complex wholes: in this respect they are like propositions. — 3. Descriptions distinguished from other complex expressions by their form: through a variable they signify a term as modi- fied by a predicate; the term takes a central, rather than a subordinate place, in the structure. — 4. The variable: variable meaning a distinct kind of significance attaching to an uninterpreted element in a whole. A minimal context of logical structure necessary to variables. — 5. The ambiguity of the variable: distinguished from equivocation. Variable meanings must follow the principle of identity. “The,” “a,” “any,” and “‘some,”’ as signs of interpretation. — 6. Descriptions of universals. —7. Examination of Messrs. Russell and Whitehead’s argument, from the triviality or falsity of “Scott is the Author of Waverley,” to prove that descriptions are incomplete 66 108 CONTENTS xiil symbols. Such statements neither trivial nor false. —8. Judgments of analytic form and synthetic effect: they analyze unanalyzed concepts or en- large the meanings of concepts. — 9. Indeterminateness of proper names. — 10. Judgments of synthetic form and analytic effect. — 11. Knowledge in universal terms determinate. The tendency of science to become analytic in form: a completely interpreted science rests on some synthetic judgments.— 12. Descriptions of the non-existent: the significant use of symbols when they refer to no objects. The theory of descriptions as incomplete symbols rests on a narrow conception of meaning. —13. Classes: not the same type of objects as facts. Defined through the primitive idea of totality. — 14. Summary. CHAPTER V LECPaPANDMOALSIT Ly hl chch ae em enue Uae kU TAQ 1. Truth and falsity as properties of symbols. Meaning both necessary and sufficient to truth. Truth and reality. — 2. Examination of the theory that truth is a property of subsistent entities or propositions. The proposition as a tertium quid. — 3. The objective reference of meanings independent of the existence or subsistence of a referent. — 4. Subsistent entities not necessary to the analysis of meaning. Propositions as symbols. — 5. Perception as a criterion of existence. Conceptual constituents in perception. Dreams, illusions, hallucinations. Bare existence alone guaranteed by givenness in perception. — 6. Sensationalism and empiricism contrasted: sense data not the only data. Presentational thinking as a means of knowing the real. The tabula rasa view of mind. —7. Consistency with the whole of knowl- edge as a criterion of existence. Rationalism and irrationalism: limited rationalism. — 8. The empirical categories. Theory and perception as mutually corrective. —9. Tests of truth: distinguished from truth. — 10. The coherence theory. Truth as correspondence implies the distinct- ness of knowledge and reality. Identity of logical form the medium of corre- spondence. — 11. Belief, judgment, and assertion. Belief continuous with understanding. The interest in truth as the motive of belief. Pure specula- tion. — 12. Belief not the addition of the concept of existence: the onto- logical argument. Single words and incomplete phrases as propositions. — 13. Disbelief as belief in negative propositions. Incredulity or scepticism the true opposite of belief. — 14. Signs of belief: the copula. — 15. Rela- tivism and scepticism. The need for belief. The concept of truth as an ap- proach to metaphysics. — 16. Summary. CHAPTER VI NEGATION AND CONTRADICTION .............. 197 1. The paradox of negative truth: negative facts. The negative as a vari- able. — 2. Ambiguity essential to negation: the possible values of a nega- tive as its possible grounds. Incompatibility of propositions not a part of the definition of the most elementary sort of negation. Formal and material simplicity of concepts. — 3. Purely conceptual negation: the possible values of the negative determined by distinctness of meaning irrespective of ob- X1V Format DEDUCTION ..... CONTENTS jects meant. “Determination is negation.” — 4. The principles of identity and contradiction as general rules of symbolism, and as general conditions of the being of objects. — 5. The law of the excluded middle: the inferential negative. — 6. The conditions of the truth and falsity of negatives. Am- biguous truth. The implications of the law of the excluded middle. — 7. Negative judgments: bare denial contrasted with specific denial. — 8. Conceptual validity and truth: formal and material consistency. — 9. Sum- mary. CHAPTER VII 1. The study of pure form through uninterpreted symbols: sets of postu- lates as plans of syntax. — 2. The general principles of symbolism: assumed in all deductive systems. — 3. Substitution as the modus operandi of formal deduction. The rule of completeness of substitution. Equations of struc- ture. Implicational substitutions. — 4. An uninterpreted Boolean Algebra as an illustration of formal deduction. — 5. The class interpretation of the Boolean Algebra. — 6. The meaning of rules of substitution: ranges of variability : functional constants and functional variables. — 7. Operations distinguished from relations. A set of postulates for serial order. — 8. In- ference: its relation to belief and assertion. Completely interpreted deduc- tive systems completely inferential. — 9. Incompletely inferential systems: analogy between the manipulations of a formal deductive system and the thought process in words and images. Reason and imagination. — 10. Sum- mary. CHAPTER VIII THe METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE .. 1. Metaphysical basis of criticisms of knowledge. Scepticism and meta- physics. — 2. Critical agnosticism. Kant and Locke. — 3. The theory of mind-isolation in Kant and Locke. — 4. Positive conclusions from the re- jection of agnosticism. — 5. Appearance and reality: how this distinction must be interpreted. — 6. The relation of the mind to real objects in cog- nition: activity and passivity in knowledge. Idealism. — 7. Critique of idealism. Materialism. — 8. Neutralism. The mental and the physical as aspects of reality. —9. The mental and the physical discovered within a single field of experience. Mind and non-mental objects continuous in cog- nition; specific nature of this continuity. — 10. The problem of the cogni- tion of physical objects distinguished from the mind-body problem. The relevance of perceptual objects to the psycho-physical situation. — 11. The role of thought-activity in knowledge: the general as fulfilling the intentions of thought. Innate ideas. — 12. Is reality logical in form? Intuition and ir- rationalism. — 13. Metaphysical insight. The relation between the form and the detail of reality. A final truth in a growing experience. — 14. Con- clusion. SUPPLEMENTARY READINGS INDEX . 222 266 317 323 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH ole J S ee | ert én eek hi Coe “ee INTRODUCTION I As the various sciences have branched off from the common stem of philosophy, which was in the beginning the pursuit of truth wherever it might be found, the philosophers have been left with certain problems preéminently their own, and among these is the theory of knowledge. It is not probable that the theory of knowledge will ever be a science in the sense in which mathematics, physics, and biology are sciences. There is too much room for difference of opinion, not only in the solution of its problems, but in their statement. Yet progress in this field of thought, as in any other, comes only with the attempt to define the subject-matter more clearly, to cut it off from neighboring fields which threaten it with incursions of irrelevant questions, and to find some ideas that bind the whole together. Just as a physical theory takes its rise from physical facts, so a theory of knowledge is built on the facts of knowledge; but though these facts are before us when we make the simplest statement or perform the most elementary process of reasoning, they are by no means so apt to strike the mind as are the facts of physics or of any other special science. We are mentally far- sighted and tend to neglect that which is closest to us. Everything that can be mentioned is known in some sense. If I deny the existence of two-headed lions or red elephants, I know what I mean by these denials, and therefore these imagi- nary creatures are somehow objects of my knowledge. If I open my eyes on the world about me, I see trees and houses, and people passing in the street; and these are obviously known in some other way than the red elephants and the two-headed lions. The geometer sketches a rough triangle on a bit of note- 4 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH paper, and on this diagram demonstrates that the sum of the three interior angles of the triangle is equal to a straight angle. This exact geometrical proposition is not true of the imperfect penciled triangle; it is true of an ideal Platonic triangle, which is only suggested by the rough figure and is apprehended through the eye of reason rather than the eye of sense. The ideal triangle belongs thus to another class of objects of knowledge, just as do the ideal gas, the frictionless motion, the perfectly rigid and elastic body, of the physicists. Again, what is one to say of dream objects? The events and people of dreams are for the time as intensely real as the events and people in the street out- side at the present moment. What is the reason for our prejudice in favor of the reality of the things of waking life, which fill at best only three-quarters of our experience? Certainly the dream is a form of knowledge. There are evidently many different senses of the term ‘‘knowl- edge.’ We dwell in the medium of the known, which surrounds us as an atmosphere. This very ubiquity makes it difficult to stand off from knowledge and analyze it. Perhaps the simplest way of marking out the subject-matter of the theory of knowl- edge is this: Anything of which it can be said that it is known in any sense is a proper subject of our investigation. The theory of knowledge is interested in these things not as physical, psycho- logical, mathematical, or any other particular sort of objects, but as things known. Although mathematical equations, physi- cal, chemical, and biological laws, historical facts, and a multi- tude of other data which belong to the special sciences are also data of the theory of knowledge, this theory looks on them in a different light from any of the special sciences. What common factors, laws, uniformities, relations, belong to things merely as objects of knowledge? This is the question that must be asked. Thus the theory comprehends in its subject-matter all the special sciences. These are particular cases of knowledge from —— INTRODUCTION 5 which the general principles are to be induced. But it attacks problems that none of these sciences can meet. With Bacon it “takes all knowledge to be its province” and views this province from an angle of its own. It includes much of what is often classi- fied as philosophy of science or logic, for it considers such ques- tions as what is a proposition, what is a scientific law, what are truth, error, assertion, belief, conception, meaning? In short, wherever there are principles of the known qua known, these principles are a part of the theory of knowledge. Meaning, for example, is present in all knowledge, from the simplest perception to the most complex mathematical expres- sion. Any knowledge that does not make use of meaning is an immediate awareness, an intuition, which can give no rational account of itself. Just what meaning is is a thorny question. But if a satisfactory answer can be given, the description of knowl- edge will have been pushed forward some distance. Moreover, one of the most notable facts about knowledge — and this is plainly connected with the presence of meaning — is that it can be expressed. Knowledge can be shut in between the covers of books and passed on from generation to generation; it can be transmitted from mind to mind by word of mouth; it can be em- bodied in the intricate formulae of the exact sciences. The sym- bols which are the outward instruments of this expression must have a close and necessary relation to the thought they convey, and the analysis of these instruments should aid us in bringing the true nature of knowledge into view. It is from this angle that we propose to attack the problem. II The most troublesome intruder in the field of the theory of knowledge is metaphysics, for the questions that usually first suggest themselves to the student of the subject are these: How is knowledge related to reality? Is reality independent of or de- 6 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH pendent on knowledge? Is it genuinely given in knowledge, and if so how? These questions turn on the distinction of subject and object, of a knowing-being with ideas, perceptions, and sensa- tions, and an external world of existences alien to this being. Is this alienation complete? Or is there a rapprochement between reality and the mind in which it makes its appearance? Many philosophers believe that before a theory of knowledge can be stated these problems must be solved. But if this were so, it would be as if the physicist insisted that a theory of the ultimate nature of mass is essential to a state- ment of the laws of mechanics, or as if the biologist refused to examine the laws of heredity without an adequate definition of life. Human knowledge is a fact just as mass, motion, and life are facts. The study of its principles, its elements, its structure, does not presuppose an answer to the more ultimate questions, how is this fact possible? — what is the relation of knowledge to reality? These queries carry one beyond the analysis of knowl- edge itself to a theory of reality, and no one can hope to discover whether or not reality is reached through knowledge until he knows what knowledge is. Though none of these metaphysical questions is prior to the descriptive study of knowledge, no theory would be complete unless it attempted to answer them. A good theory — of any- thing — must consider all the intelligible questions its data sug- gest; and so a complete theory of knowledge will fall into two parts: it will be both a positive analysis and a metaphysics of knowledge, it will both describe knowledge and explain its rela- tion to reality. But the metaphysics of knowledge demands a final concept of reality, and it naturally supervenes on a more restricted inquiry which makes use of a provisional, working concept of the real. Let us call this the posttwe theory of knowl- edge, epistemology proper, which is an examination of knowledge undertaken in the spirit of the laboratory. We must begin by INTRODUCTION 7 viewing knowledge as a natural phenomenon if we are to deter- mine its place in reality. We must proceed inductively and “‘rise by gradual steps to that which is prior and better known in the order of nature,” instead of ‘‘beginning at once by establishing certain abstract generalities.” ! From the point of view of the positive theory of knowledge one can set out without being a realist, an idealist, a monist, a pluralist, a nominalist — without attaching himself to any sys- tem of metaphysics. Metaphysics comes later; it is the coping- stone of the theory and it cannot be securely placed without a careful survey of the facts. The confusion of metaphysics with the positive analysis of knowledge can be traced, in modern thought, to Locke. Locke’s Essay, though it deals with the structure and laws of knowledge, especially with the manner in which ideas are built up from sim- ple impressions into complex systems, is nevertheless shot through with the conception of an unknowable substance which lies beyond ideas. This conception colors the whole work. For Berkeley and Kant, metaphysics is still intertwined with the descriptive treatment of knowledge, though the Critique of Pure Reason in distinguishing the transcendental aesthetic and analytic from the dialectic makes a division that corresponds roughly to these two aspects of the subject. Yet the whole Critique is haunted by a metaphysical ghost — the thing-in-itself. The first modern philosopher who severely restricts himself to the analysis of knowledge without metaphysics is Hume, and this is accidental, the result of his scepticism. Since he believed in no theory of reality, he advanced no theory of the relation of knowledge to reality, but he fell on the contrary into the trap of the purely psychological point of view. The phdénomenologie which has become prominent in recent German philosophy, especially through the writings of A. 1 F. Bacon, Novum Organum, Bk. I, Aphorism 22. 8 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH Meinong and E. Husserl, pursues the analysis of knowledge in the positive spirit; and the same tendency, if not the same mat- ter, is to be found in England in the work of Mr. Bertrand Russell, Mr. A. N. Whitehead, Mr. G. E. Moore, and Mr. C. D. Broad. Yet metaphysics always lurks in the background, even for those who attempt to avoid this type of speculation. The ques- tion of the ultimate validity of knowledge remains to be an- swered; the notion of truth points inevitably to a final concept of the real. A definition of truth cannot fail to invite metaphysi- cal criticism, and it can be defended in the last resort only by arguments that rest on metaphysical premises. Therefore, un- less we are to persist in a partial scepticism such as Hume’s, the separation of the positive theory of knowledge from metaphys- ics cannot be maintained to the end; but it is of immense value as a working distinction in the study of epistemology. CHAPTER I MEANING I Wuavr are the facts that a theory of knowledge needs to organ- ize and explain? It is customary to say that knowledge is built up from ideas. Locke defined knowledge as “‘nothing but the perception of the connection of and agreement, or disagreement and repugnancy, of any of our ideas,”’ and he gave as his reason for this definition that “‘the mind, in all its thoughts and reasonings, hath no other immediate object but its own ideas, which it alone does or can contemplate.” ! If we ask what ideas are, we learn nothing more definite than that they are the mind’s objects. Thus Locke’s statement that “‘our knowledge is conversant only with ideas” affirms that knowledge is conversant only with the mind’s objects — a truism which no one will deny. The term “idea” is robbed of its force by being extended to all the ele- ments of knowledge. There is a narrower and more profitable sense of this term, which makes ideas one class of the ingredients of knowledge, but not the only class. This is the sense in which “idea” is used by the psychologist. An idea is an image, a psychical event, and it must be distinguished from other psychical events, namely sensations and perceptions. The ground of this distinction is difficult to establish. Intrinsically an image and a sensation or perception are much the same. The difference is not, as Hume supposed, one of vividness or intensity. But the things of sen- sation and perception have a type of coherence with one another 1 J. Locke, Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Bk. IV, ch. i, secs. 1, 2. 10 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH which those of the imagination do not have. Sensory and per- ceptual objects obey, not merely “psychical” laws, but also the laws of physics; and so in most cases images can be set apart from sensations and perceptions. The striking thing about ideas in this narrower sense is that they usually refer beyond themselves to other things. They are not as a rule self-contained, but reach out with tentacles of sig- nificance toward other ideas or toward the things of sensation and perception. Locke found this to be characteristic of all ideas in his sense of the term, that is, of all the mind’s objects. They are all symbolic of that which lies beyond the mind’s grasp, says Locke. But since the realities which these ideas sig- nify are not themselves ideas, Locke is at a loss to interpret the meaning of knowledge in terms of these extra-mental realities. He is clear however on one point, that ideas in so far as they are vehicles of knowledge are symbolic; that the area of knowledge is coextensive with the area of significance. In the more restricted sense of “‘idea,”’ it is not necessary to attempt the impossible, to seek beyond knowledge for the mean- ing of ideas. They are to be interpreted as referring to objects sensed or perceived, and often as referring to other ideas or psy- chical states. But as mere meaningless successions of psychical phenomena following the laws of association, ideas (images) are of no special importance in knowledge; they are not conveyors of knowledge. They make their appearance before the mind and pass away, and this is all that can be said about them. However, as mediators between the mind and objects in perception or ob- jects beyond the immediate circle of the mind—in other words, as significant symbols— images are the first instruments of meaning and hence of knowledge. Instead of saying as Locke does that “knowledge is of ideas,” one ought rather to say that knowledge comes through ideas. It would be of slight value to have knowledge of ideas if we did not know through ideas. MEANING 1] Images, then, pass by the easiest possible transition to a second level of knowledge, the level of significance. Without perceptible effort, the mind takes them to refer to something other than themselves, and thus endows them with a function which attaches much less readily to other elements of knowledge — the function of meaning. II What do images signify? The simplest answer is that they sig- nify things they resemble. Though this is true in many in- stances, and is indeed the reason why they are such ready vehicles of meaning, images are not restricted in their signifi- cance to the objects of which they seem to be faint and partial copies. The vagaries of individual processes of imagery are with- out limit, and therefore naive copy theories of the significance of ideas are faulty. The subtlety of the threads that bind ideas to their objects must be recognized. Any image may come to mean any object. The fact that images resemble the experiences which pro- duced them, and that the image of a part of an experience tends to recall the whole, so that they take on meaning with a mini- mum of effort on our part, makes images the primal instruments of knowledge. But they are not the only instruments. Man adds to them and improves on them. He adds speech and writing, and finally the complex symbols of mathematics and logic. Ideas take their place as one among many classes of symbols. It is no doubt possible completely to supplant images as vehi- cles of thought by words or other conventional signs. Yet, when the major burden of significance is carried by symbols other than images, the latter usually arise in the process. In most minds significant imagery is never wholly absent. The traces of our intellectual childhood, when to think of things is to see them vividly in imagination, remain with us in the most abstract 12 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH kinds of thought. Witness the many attempts to visualize Ein- stein’s “spherical universe.” And this is so much the case that we tend to believe that the meanings of words or other written or spoken signs are nothing more than images in the mind, either in our own or another mind. Being in the habit of discov- ering the significance of most signs via the route of imagery, we fail to observe that what is meant by words or other signs is not, as a rule, a set of images, but the things for which these images stand. If I say, “The sun is shining brightly outside my win- dow,” the reader may believe that when he has called up a pic- ture of sunlight streaming through a window he has before him the meaning of this sentence. But the sentence means neither an image in my mind nor in his. It means through these mental events to something else. (This does not deny that some words and sentences mean images only; ¢.g., “my mental picture of China” refers only to ideas in the narrower sense of this term.) It cannot be maintained that all meanings terminate in images and that when this type of symbol is absent there is no meaning. Images as well as other symbols are not confined in their significance to any class of objects. They may stand for my own or another person’s psychical states, for the content of a perception, for other symbols, for objects that have never en- tered any one’s experience; and not only may symbols stand for any kind of object, they may, as will presently be shown, stand for no object and still be significant. Some objects are, to be sure, more accessible than others. I have a closer knowledge of my own feelings and perceptions than of another person’s. The paper on which I write is open to inspection in a way that the other side of the moon is not. But symbols can refer to the inaccessible as well as the accessible; and if there are any objects which symbols cannot mean, these will appear only when we have thoroughly examined the ob- jects they can mean. MEANING 13 The observation that symbols may mean any kind of object frees us from the presupposition that all meanings terminate in the present content of the mind, and at the same time leaves open the question as to the metaphysical status of the objects meant. III We have said that images pass readily to a second level of knowledge, that of significance; and that other objects, spoken sounds, written marks, gestures, also take on significance, though somewhat less easily than images. Below this level of significance (at least of pure significance) is a primary level of acquaintance, and all objects which are sig- nificant are also objects with which we are acquainted. Whether the symbol be a sensation, an image, a perception, whether it be believed to belong to the physical or mental world, this symbol will be something presented, and will belong to the primary as well as the secondary level of knowledge. This immediate way of knowing, by direct presentation, is the basic form of knowledge, and it has been frequently distinguished from a less direct way — knowing of or about objects. I am, for example, presented with the groups of letters and words on this page and through them I know about the subject under discussion; when I say that I know the whiteness of this paper, it is clear that I do not use the verb “‘know”’ in the same sense as when I say that I know Marcus Aurelius was a Roman Emperor. I am acquainted with the one object but not with the other. Knowledge about things springs from acquaintance with them or with other things in terms of which they can be de- scribed; and though it is difficult to explain what it is to be known in the sense of being immediately presented to a mind, without this sort of knowledge we should probably know nothing. We are here in contact with a fundamental concept of our theory, the concept of the presentation of objects. 14 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH Among the objects presented, some take on meaning and be- come symbols, while others remain merely presented. What is given to the mind becomes an instrument by means of which things not given are represented, and thus we begin to pass from immediate to purely mediate knowledge. To know about things is to refer to them through symbols when they are not presented, while to know things immediately is to have them before the mind, not simply as something referred to, but as something given, in which symbolic references terminate. My knowledge that Marcus Aurelius was a Roman Emperor is exhausted by statements I can make or ideas I can entertain. I can speak sig- nificantly of him, I can think about him, but I cannot be pre- sented with him. And this is true of all events in the past and future, of distant places, and probably of other minds. I can, at the moment, reach these only through symbols. On the other hand, my knowledge of the object I call “‘the whiteness of this paper” is not exhausted by what I can say or think about it. This knowledge is more than a significant idea or statement; it is an immediate presentation. The most striking fact in knowledge is that it falls into these two divisions, mediate and immediate; that mediate knowledge is wholly symbolic, a reference to objects through objects, while immediate knowledge, even though it may be partially medi- ated by symbols, is more than reference to objects. It is a unique seizure of objects by the mind. Yet this distinction between mediate and immediate knowledge is not so sharply marked as many contemporary schools of philosophy, especially those which maintain that knowledge is constructed from sense data, would have us believe. IV Objects which are presented are not merely sensed. The unit of cognition is not a sensation but something much richer. Sen- ; : Ce ee ae MEANING 15 sations are discovered as elements in larger wholes, and these larger wholes are perceptions or objective presentations. The datum of the theory of knowledge is much nearer to William James’s stream of thought than to pure sensation. “Most books (of psychology), says James, “‘start with sen- sations, as the simplest mental facts, and proceed synthetically, constructing each higher stage from those below it. But this is abandoning the empirical method of investigation. No one ever had a simple sensation by itself. Consciousness, from our natal day, is of a teeming multiplicity of objects and relations, and what we call simple sensations are results of discriminative at- tention, pushed often to a very high degree.” ! Empiricists rarely mean by “‘experience”’ that which is given wholly through the senses at the moment of experiencing. We experience objects, relations, qualities; we perceive things of cer- tain sorts rather than of no sort in particular; we are presented with situations and facts, rather than with bare sense data. From this full experience certain irreducible elements that come from the senses can be analyzed out; these are elements such as white, hard, smooth; but these elements are not the whole of the experience. They are always bound up with other elements. The cognitive unit, a presentation, is therefore complex. It in- cludes a concept (and often a belief) as well as sensations. If I gaze from my window at the trees bending in the wind, there is much more in my mind than impressions of color, movement, shape, and relative position. I see the trees. My mind leaps be- yond sensations to concepts — concepts of solid three-dimen- sional objects of a certain nature. The fusion of concepts and sensations is the presentation of the object, and neither con- cepts nor sensations by themselves would give the peculiar kind of cognition I call “presentation.” The simplest experience, e.g., that of the color white which is now before me, is more than a 1 W. James, The Principles of Psychology, vol. i, ch. ix, p. 224. 16 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH pure sensation. I recognize something as white, and in doing so bring it under a concept. Thomas Reid, the leader of the Scottish school of common- sense philosophy, which succeeded Hume, adds that belief also is a constituent of perception. We believe “irresistibly,” he says, in the existence of the object perceived. But this is not always the case. An illusion may be present, actually perceived, but not believed; we often doubt our perceptions; seeing is believing only to credulous minds. Though there is a strong tendency to believe our perceptions, this tendency cannot be a constituent of the perception, since perceptions persist when they are doubted or disbelieved. A concept, on the other hand, is a neces- sary part of a presentation. The concepts which enter in perception may function explic- itly, as when I judge that “this is white,” or they may function silently, without conscious judgment, as when I perceive the whiteness. But one knows that he is presented with an object only when he brings it, in some way, under a concept. The fact that immediate knowledge can deceive, that we are as vividly presented with objects in dreams and hallucinations as in other states, bears witness to the presence of concepts in immediate knowledge. It is only because the stuff of perceptions is largely manufactured or elaborated by thought that we can be thus led astray. If there were such things as pure sensations, it could be readily granted that they would not deceive. They could be what they were known to be, and nothing else. But since there are no pure sensations, we must admit that any presentation can be deceptive. The very perception that something is white or hot or hard is subject to error. “Sensation, then,” says James, “so long as we take the ana- lytic point of view, differs from perception only in the extreme simplicity of its object or content. ...A pure sensation is an abstraction.” ! 1 W. James, op. cit., ii, 1 ff. — MEANING 17 It is evident that the presence of concepts in perception blurs the distinction between mediate and immediate knowledge, and especially is this so when we see what a concept is. We shall find that a concept is a symbol taken with the mental attitude that gives it significance. When we conceive of an object we mean it or refer to it, we entertain the idea or symbol of it; and thus the mechanism of conception is the mechanism of symbolism. Im- mediate knowledge, no less than mediate knowledge, presup- poses therefore the functioning of symbols in a mind. A mind enters on perception with predispositions or inten- tions, which determine to a large extent what is perceived; and these predispositions are aroused by symbols — ideas, incipient vocal utterances, word imagery — which are at work in the per- ception.! The sensory elements also operate as signs. When I open my eyes on the room in which I now write, the stimuli present to my senses awaken (through sensations) concepts in my mind; indeed these sensations themselves play the part of 1 The psychologists of the Wiirzburg school, in recording their experiments on the thought-process, speak of these predispositions as determined by the Aufgabe, that is, the problem to be solved in any given case. Something very like an Aufgabe is, I believe, present in any mind engaged in perceiving, and plays an essential part in determining what is perceived. The following passage is quoted from a paper by Dr. C. C. Pratt, entitled “The Present Status of In- trospective Technique,” in The Journal of Philosophy, vol. xxi, no. 9, April 24, 1924: “‘ At the congress for experimental psychology at Giessen in 1904 Kiilpe made a brief report on some experiments of his own on abstraction in which geometrical symbols, the components of which differed with respect to form, color, and arrangement, were used as stimuli. By means of instructions the ob- servers were determined now in the direction of form, now of color, and now of - arrangement. And it turned out that when an observer was under the Aufgabe for color, e.g., he could make at best only a very inadequate report on form and arrangement — in some cases he reported that form and arrangement were not present to consciousness at all. The implications of such a state of af- fairs is far reaching. ... As far as accurate observation and unequivocal report are concerned, an observer is adequate only to those aspects of a given experi- ence which the determining tendency brings clearly into line with the particu- lar Aufgabe of the moment; other aspects of that experience fall at various dis- tances outside of the sphere of immediate observation and hence cannot be made the objects of scientific description.” See O. Kiilpe, “‘Versuche iiber Ab- straktion,” in Bericht ti. den I. Kongress f. exper. Psychol., 1904, pp. 56-69. 18 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH concepts, that is, of symbols. They arouse unuttered judg- ments which are carried by images or fleeting and unspoken words. Through the whole process, I am aware in immediate presentation, not of the sensations alone, but of the objects I thus conceive. I see the desk and the rows of books because these are what the passing sensations mean. If the presence of concepts in immediate knowledge blurs the distinction between the mediately and the immediately known, still it does not obliterate it. As we travel up the scale from pres- entation to representation, we come finally to a kind of knowl- edge in which the object conceived or meant is no longer given along with the symbols through which it is conceived. This is the kind of knowledge embodied in a mathematical expression or a scientific theory; or, more simply still, in a judgment as to the past or future. It is purely symbolic. Between presentation and representation there is a twilight zone in which oné cannot be sure whether the object intended is given or merely conceived. Here most of the errors of perception occur. But the ends of the scale are distinct. At the one end is a direct acquaintance with objects such as is not possible through concepts (or symbols) alone: this is a cognition in which what is meant is grasped in a union of sensation and conception, often attended by belief. At the other end is pure conception, knowledge which is significant reference and nothing more. Vi The statement that concepts (symbols) are always to be ) found in immediate knowledge must be modified if there is any such cognition as M. Henri Bergson’s intuition of the flux of reality. The Bergsonian intuition is a pure awareness more im- mediate than the perception we have described; it does not give presentational knowledge in our sense of the term; it is not an acquaintance with objects, not even with simple qualities. — { ‘| | MEANING 19 One cannot adequately explain what this intuition gives him. He must search for it in his experience and if he finds it must admit his inability to express it. He will be unable to bring it un- der any concept, but must remain content to gesticulate in its direction with words and metaphors. I cannot, in Bergson’s sense, have an intuition of an object, for this would require the concept of an object — the content of the intuition would be con- ceptualized in this general and vague way as “something-or- other.”’ Thus if we grant the existence of such a non-conceptual form of cognition, it will give us neither objects, qualities, rela- tions, things, or events, but will fall into a category of its own, beyond all rational categories. Now there does seem to be a background of pure awareness not unlike the Bergsonian intuition in all presentations. Beyond the objects which are clearly given, beyond what is singled out and conceptualized as “‘experience,”’ there is something which cannot be singled out and conceptualized. This is an amorphous datum which transforms itself, under the working of concepts, into the articulated data of perception. Perceptual knowledge, the knowledge of objects, persons, events, places, relations, qualities, sense data, has a structure. Only after we have examined this structure will the distinction between pure awareness and rational presentation become clear. Pure awareness must be the complete antithesis of con- ceptual knowledge; it must be knowledge in which all symbols have been transcended, knowledge wholly deconceptualized; and yet it must be continuous with perception, and through per- ception, with conception. The presentation of objects must arise from this pure awareness and return to it with no perceptible break. Theories of knowledge which find pure immediacy in sense data do not carry their analysis far enough. The sense datum is something discrete, fixed and referred to by a concept, and be- 20 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH hind the sense datum is the vaguely apprehended whole from which it is discriminated. Even so fluid a datum as Mr. A. N. Whitehead’s event ! is not known in pure immediacy; the event is picked out from a background, and certainly the perception of relations between events demands more than a purely im- mediate knowledge. The attempt to discover the purely immediate leads thus be- yond perception and sensation to what can be described only as the unarticulated awareness of a whole. (And even this descrip- tion is faulty since it makes use of concepts.) But this pure awareness is not a form of knowing which can stand on its own feet. It issues from the whole cognitive act as the final aroma of knowledge, as a sense of oneness with the object known; and the attempt to isolate pure awareness meets with no better suc- cess than the attempt to grasp a pure sensation. Though this intuition passes beyond what can be clearly compressed into concepts, it does not contradict but supplements conceptual knowledge. We must leave till later the discussion of this pure awareness and its relations to other forms of knowledge.? VI From the basic units of presentational knowledge, purely symbolic or conceptual knowledge is constructed. Through sym- bols, themselves presented and significantly linked to objects (and sometimes to no object), we move from the realm of pres- entations to that of representations. It is here that the sciences appear, that logic enters, that the common knowledge of every- day speech comes into being. The world of the purely concep- tual is superimposed on or abstracted from the world of the im- mediately known. The mind reaches out from its data. Words, ideas, and other signs carry it beyond things that are given to 1 A, N. Whitehead, The Principles of Natural Knowledge (1919), ch. vi. 2 See below, ch. VIII, sec. xii. MEANING 21 the imaginary and even to the non-existent, the fantastic, and the impossible. And this brings us to the central problem of the present chapter, the nature of meaning. A symbol, briefly described, is an object which stands for an- other object or is still significant if it stands for no object. This is no definition, and serves merely to raise the question of how a symbol is related to the thing it means and how it can be signifi- cant when it means no existing object. In the first place, the symbol stands in a mind for an object; it takes on significance through psychical activity, and if there were no minds there would be no symbols. Since the symbolic relation is not something given in the external world, any signifi- cance discovered in the events about us is read into these events; and quite apart from the metaphysical question as to whether these events could be if there were no minds, they certainly could not be significant unless they were so interpreted. When one says that clouds mean rain, that a low temperature means ice and snow, he refers to a causal connection between these things, but this relation alone does not make the one a sign of the other. It is because the cause is interpreted as a symbol that the antecedent event takes on significance. Aside from the con- nections of meaning established in a mind, things in the order of nature simply are; they are bound together by laws, but not bound so that any one by its own nature means any other. Berkeley, who interpreted all sense impressions as signs, found it necessary to postulate a Divine Mind communicating with man through this language of natural events. Written marks and spoken sounds are not different in this respect from other objects: without a mind which uses them to refer to things, they would be nothing more than physical occur- rences; and the same is true of images or ideas—unless we took them to be significant, they would pass through the mind as psychical events, conforming to the laws of association but bear- ing no meanings with them. 22 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH Meaning then is something superadded to things by a mind. What is the nature of this activity which adds significance? The commonest answer to this question, familiar especially in English philosophy from Hobbes onward, is that the meaning activity is the association of ideas; and this reappears in James, who says that the meaning of an idea is to be found in its “‘psy- chical fringe.”’ Locke sees the weakness of this view when he speaks of association as a distemper of the mind which leads thought away from its objects rather than toward them. In de- termining the meaning of a word or image, we must rule out ir- relevant associations; much of the “‘psychical fringe”’ must be overlooked; and this being the case, meaning must be something other than association. Though associations sometimes conduct one to the things he means, they more often conduct him away from them, and he can never be sure that the paths of associa- tion are not by-ways rather than high-roads of thought. The associations that play a part in carrying meanings are con- trolled, that is to say, their direction is prescribed by what the psychologists know as a “determining tendency ”’ or an Aufgabe. The word ‘New York” may arouse by association the image of the Statue of Liberty, which may lead to a picture of the guil- lotine and the red flag, but none of these associated ideas is the meaning of ““New York”’; they must be dismissed as irrelevant associations. Images of canyon-like streets and suspended bridges bring the meaning nearer, since they fit the attitude or set of mind the word induces. There is a still more damaging objection to the view that meaning is the association of ideas. Association is a link between images and carries the mind no further than ideas in the nar- rower sense of the term; and yet what is meant by a symbol need not be an idea. ““New York” means the city on the banks of the Hudson, rather than the representation of this city in images, and these images themselves mean something other than images. MEANING 23 They stand for a perceptual object, and the word means what the images mean. The activity of meaning is, more frequently than not, directed beyond ideas, and so it cannot be described in terms of association, which is restricted to ideas. VII The simplest solution for the purposes of the theory of knowl- edge is to accept as unique a meaning activity. This does not im- ply that from the point of view of psychology this activity is unanalyzable; it may well be that it can be reduced to more ele- mentary activities, but it is not necessary for our present purposes to do so. We must confine ourselves to a general description, which is intended to direct the reader to the point in experience where the meaning activity is to be found. Having discovered meaning in its primitive form, we can show how more complex meanings are constructed, and this will lead to the logical and strictly epistemological, rather than psychological, aspects of the subject. To reach out with the mind toward objects, as one does when _ he means them, is to be in a state of preparation for these ob- jects. The meaning activity is one of vague anticipation: the mind is poised expectantly, awaiting something other than the thing, the symbol, which is immediately before it; and this an- ticipation is vague because it is not accompanied by a belief that the object meant will appear or that it exists. When I mean an object I do, in some sense, prepare my mind for a presentation of this object. Though I cannot be said to turn my attention toward the thing I mean, since one cannot attend to something not presented to him, there is no doubt that I do more than at- tend to a symbol or an image. Indeed, I turn my attention away from the symbol or the image, and this constitutes the first step in preparation for the thing meant. Toward every object certain activities are appropriate. I can 24 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH eat bread; I can throw a stone; I can sit on a chair. These activities are appropriate to the object for many reasons, the most important of which are biological reasons: the appropriate activities are those which enable me to adapt myself to the thing; and for any single thing there are many such activities. When a symbol is before the mind, it sets in motion the activ- ities appropriate to an object and this object is then what the symbol means; but it sets these activities in motion only par- tially, it touches nothing more than their psychical roots, so that if the effect of the symbol appears in consciousness, it is as a barely noticeable feeling of tendency. Physiologically, a symbol probably stirs the central part of a chain of nervous connections which constitute a tendency to act in a certain way. The process of understanding a symbol ter- minates in the brain, and for this reason the activities it arouses are implicit, so implicit as to diminish almost to the zero-point both for outward and inward observation. And yet they are ade- quate to carry the reference, the outward reach of the mind, which is significance. Ideas, as well as written and spoken words, set up these cen- tral tendencies to action. Every idea, in James’s opinion, has its motor side; and not only do ideas arouse tendencies to action, they spring from these tendencies, so that the set of the mind in a certain direction determines what images appear and causes irrelevant images to be disregarded. It is this set rather than the image itself which fixes the meaning, and this is why ideas do not mean by resemblance alone. But what if the activities brought into play by a symbol be- come overt? What if they push out beyond the central nervous system and terminate in completed acts? In this case the mind has gone further than merely under- standing the symbol. Understanding has passed into belief, that is, one has begun to behave as if the thing meant were present, MEANING 25 as if the activity which is fitted to it could be successfully per- formed here and now. Understanding and belief being of the same genus, the line which separates them cannot be sharply drawn. Belief is willingness to act on what is understood, while understanding is preparation for activities appropriate to an ob- ject, though these activities are checked far short of perform- ance. If you tell me that it is a good day for a walk in the hills, I understand by putting myself in an attitude of mind suited to a walk in the hills, but this attitude does not amount to belief. Though I need not actually set out on the expedition if I believe the statement, I must nevertheless be more fully prepared to do so than if I merely understand it. I must feel that the walk could be successfully undertaken. Belief is a more complete prepara- tion for activity than understanding: it is understanding with an added psychical pressure in the direction of performance. There- fore, if the effect of a symbol on a mind is to produce overt acts, we can conclude that the symbol is not only understood but also believed. VIII This is not the only possible conclusion, and here the inade- quacy of the behavioristic treatment of meaning comes into view. The extreme behaviorist assumes that there is only one way in which psychical processes can be studied, namely through out- ward action. Now an object that is immediately presented may produce outward activity without either understanding or be- lief. Certainly if one is to believe, he must begin by understand- ing, for he cannot believe what he does not understand even in a vague sense; and so if overt activity does not testify to under- standing, it cannot prove the presence of belief. The crucial question in the behavioristic account of thought is, then, does overt activity indicate understanding? 26 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH Let us suppose that our dog comes for his food when the dinner-bell is rung. The bell has aroused an activity appropriate to an object, and we can assume that the bell means dinner to the dog; and yet we cannot be sure of this. The dog’s act is not different, so far as we can know, from many other habitual acts. He will go to a certain corner each night to sleep, he will bark at certain persons and not at others, he will howl when the moon is full. Are we to say that all of these acts are acts of under- standing? . _ The weakness of the behavioristic theory of meaning is that it affords no criterion by which acts of understanding can be dis- tinguished from other habitual acts, yet no one would be willing to say that all such acts are cases of understanding. The theory leads us to the conclusion that any stimulus to which we react in an habitual way is a symbol. It is true that most signs acquire significance through habit. The connection between the sign and its meaning is based on a conditioned reflex. The object A, food, for example, stirs the activity B, hunger and eating; and if X, the sound of the dinner- bell, accompanies A for a sufficient number of times, X alone will become an adequate stimulus for these activities. This is the pattern of all habits. But there is a distinction between habits which carry meaning and those which do not. Though we should have no speech and writing were it not for our ability to form habits, the formation of a habit does not argue a connection of meaning; there are many habits in our behavior that are not vehicles of significance. Habits of meaning belong to a special class. They are abbrevi- ated habits, habits purely of the mind, not extending beyond the central nervous system. When we understand a word or an idea, we perform no observable acts, unless it be silently to repeat the word. The actions appropriate to the object are confined to the brain, or nearly so; and it is just this mental or inner character MEANING Q7 of habits of meaning which differentiates them from meaning- less habits. A sign causes us to think rather than to go off into a series of immediate and unreflective acts, as do other habit- stimuli. Deliberation, abbreviated action, understanding, rather than overt activity, are the effects produced by symbols. The behaviorists explain that meaning is based on language habits and that meaningless vocal acts or habits develop into language habits, which carry significance when they become associated with “arm, hand, and leg activities and substitutable for them.” ! This is an attempt to formulate a criterion of signifi- cant as opposed to meaningless habits. The substitution of a sign for an object indicates that the sign is understood, that is, that it has become a sign. But substituted how? Substituted where? And here the whole problem of meaning is concealed. The only intelligible answer is, substituted in an internal experience not open to external observation. It is impossible without introspection to say when this substi- tution has taken place. Mr. J. B. Watson’s example of such a substitution is inconclusive: the fact that sounds are uttered in conjunction with arm, hand, and leg activities,— in conjunction with an infant’s reaching for an object held out toward him,— and that the sounds alone are uttered at a later time, either when the object appears or when it is absent, does not show that the sound has been substituted for these activities, that the child has passed from unreflective action to deliberation, and that the sound has come to mean the object. The substitution of a symbol for an object, which is its “‘standing for the object,” is essentially a fact for introspective observation and only secon- darily a fact of behavior. Meaning is an activity that can be described only in intro- spective terms, and even in introspection it is difficult to grasp. 1 J. B. Watson, Psychology from the Standpoint of a Behaviorist (1919), pp. 319 ff. 28 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH Thought is distinguished from action simply on the ground that it is activity which does not work itself out in behavior. If thought is behavior, it is behavior inhibited and yet fully aware of its directions and intentions. The habits on which it is built are private. Though it may be true that the dog genuinely thinks dinner at the sound of the bell, we are not justified in inferring that he does from his behavior alone; and if our own reactions to dinner-bells and to words or images were always overt and fully carried out, if we could not pause to deliberate and so check, short of performance, the tendencies to action aroused by sym- bols, we could not be said to understand language or ideas, but only to react to them as we might to a bright light or a loud noise. The moment of suspension of mind between the immedi- ate stimulus and the activities that follow would be shortened to exclude understanding, and none of the stimuli of habitual ac- tions would become symbols. They would remain merely ob- jects which set in motion conditioned reflexes, and their capacity to mean other objects would be as yet unrealized. No doubt there is an insensible gradation between habits that do not carry meaning and habits that do, and by this gradation an organism passes from action to thought. As the capacity to retain the effect of a stimulus in the mind without overt activity increases, the ability to understand is gained, and the objects to which the organism has before reacted habitually without un- derstanding become symbols of the things toward which these activities are directed. Unless this capacity to suspend reactions and to anticipate an object rather than to behave as if it were present were developed, we should not be able to think but only to act. IX The psychological aspects of meaning can be summarized as follows. A significant reference to an object with an object is ac- complished through a suspension of activity, known in intro- MEANING 29 spection as an intention. A symbol touches a train of psychical connections which, if followed out, lead to activities appropriate to an object. In understanding alone, this train of connections is remotely stirred and is not pushed to its terminal point, but when the suspension of mind breaks over into the actions suited to the object, understanding passes into belief. Belief must be preceded by understanding, and overt activity is not necessarily a sign of belief or of understanding. In this suspension of activ- ity the mind reaches out beyond its immediate field, and the stimulus of this outward reach, whether it be an image, a word, a mark, or a gesture, is a symbol. A general conception of what it is to think can now be framed. Without symbols there is no thought. Thinking is activity, or rather the suspension of activity, through symbols. It is the sub- stitution of symbols, which are in the field of presentation, for the things intended by the symbols, which may be beyond this field; and sometimes thought is carried by symbols that stand for no objects. Thought is not to be classified with sensations, images, feelings, conations, as an element of consciousness. It is built up from these elements, and it may be from others; it is the use of these elements for the purpose of recording and conveying significant references. If psychologists have discovered an imageless thought, they have not discovered a thought which does not rest on the use of symbols. Symbols are the universal instruments of knowledge, and the ancient logicians who defined man as a “rational ani- mal” might well have given another definition, ‘employer of signs,” for man’s rationality consists in his ability to use signs. Without the semi-artificial media of language, writing, and the numerical system, human knowledge as we know it could not have come into existence; and beneath these systems of semi- artificial signs lies a still more primitive system, that of images. To indulge in pure thought is to put in the place of the things 30 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH found in experience a set of substitutes, secondary realities such as marks on a page, vocal noises, psychological images, and to move in this world in a way corresponding to that in which one might have moved among the primary realities. And thought is more than this: it is the extension of the references of symbols beyond the experienced, it is the significant use of signs when there are neither presented nor existent objects for which they stand. These more complex types of meaning remain to be con- sidered. xX It is not difficult to see how things such as colors, shapes, sounds, simple states of mind — anger, fear, pleasure, pain — can be referred to; but one speaks significantly also of “‘the uni- verse,” “‘the world,” “the solar system,” and yet none of these objects has entered experience in its wholeness, nor is there any single activity or set of activities appropriate to it. This is true also of more restricted objects such as ““New York City” or “the British Empire.”’ We cannot mean these things merely by taking a single symbol to stand for them. The mind must reach out toward them in some immensely more complex fashion than it does toward simpler objects. All of our most complex ideas, says Locke, even to the idea of God, are constructed from simpler ideas which are the founda- tions of knowledge; and Locke’s distinction between simple and complex ideas can be extended to all symbols. Objects such as the universe, the other side of the moon, the continent of Europe, are referred to by means of complexes of references to simpler objects. Most of the things with which we are familiar are easily seen to be composed of other things, they can be separated into ele- ments; and if an object as a whole cannot enter experience to be- come the terminus of a meaning, some or all of its components usually can. Though we cannot directly form habits of speech or MEANING 31 thought appropriate to the universe or to New York City, we can come in direct contact with parts or aspects of these objects. These objects can be analyzed and thus can be represented in thought; the whole can be grasped through its elements. The symbolic systems of language, mathematics, and the imagination are peculiarly adapted to this analytical representa- tion of objects. Men think not by means of isolated words, signs or ideas, but by joining these into groups, into propositions, phrases, and sentences, which have a meaning as a whole. This is syntactical meaning. Syntax is literally “taking together,” and symbols taken together are significant, as symbols by themselves cannot be: any phrase, sentence, or complex idea — any group of symbols — has a meaning other than the meanings of its ele- ments but determined by these, and these alone. This gives us the first principle of symbolism, the principle of syntactical sig- nificance: the significance of any group of symbols is a function of the significance of its members. To the elements of a symbolic group correspond elements of the object which might be meant by the group as a whole, and thus, through a symbol that can be analyzed into parts, an object that can be likewise analyzed is represented. The sentence, “‘the sun is shining outside my win- dow,” means a fact composed of the objects meant by “‘sun,”’ 99 66 99 66 “shining,” “outside,” “my,” and “‘window.”’ The fact is these elements, built up according to a definite plan, taken in a certain order, and the meaning of the sentence is a synthesis of separate meanings in a single meaning. XI Before we can employ groups of symbols to represent objects analytically, we must be equipped with simpler instruments of thought. These are simple symbols, whose significance is of the direct sort described above. Simple symbols have no syntactical meaning. Their signifi- 32 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH cance is not a function of that of their parts, if they have sym- bolic parts, but rather a function of the presentation of objects and of a mind which establishes connections of meaning between presented objects. The significance of “Shakespeare”’ is not de- termined by the meanings of “shake” and “‘speare”’: it arises from the direct use of this name for a person. (A simple symbol may have meaning, however, through definition only, that is, it may be defined as equivalent to a symbolic group, e.g., “nectar” is “the food of the gods”’; and in this case the meaning will not be a function of the presentation of an object for which the sym- bol is taken to stand.) The conditions under which simple sym- bols acquire meaning are such that they cannot mean objects which have not appeared in perception, unless they are expressly defined through symbolic groups which mean such objects. Knowledge is built on experience, on presentation, because it is only in experience that these first instruments of knowledge are of use. In order that (undefined) simple symbols may take on meaning for us, we must have performed acts directed toward the things they mean. We must have experienced the symbol with the object, and a conditioned reflex must have been estab- lished, so that when the symbol appears the appropriate activ- ities and the intention directed toward the object will be set up. It was said above that without concepts, that is, significant symbols, there are no presentations of objects, and it should be added that without presentations of objects there are no con- cepts. Simple symbols, that is, single words or ideas and the psychical attitudes which accompany them, play a necessary part in determining the cognitions of their objects, and at the same time the cognitions of these objects play a necessary part in determining the meanings of the simple symbols: they are functions of one another, and it is impossible to say that the presentation of objects precedes in time the use of symbols. Perception is born through the significant use of symbols, and the significant use of symbols, through perception. a i MEANING 33 The significance of a simple symbol, unless it is defined through a symbolic group, rests on three necessary factors: first, the symbolic object proper, the mark, the image, the sound; then the attitude of preparation, the intention or psychical set; and finally the presentation of the object meant. To say that a concept enters in every perception of an object means simply that these three factors are always present in perception. I am never presented with a thing unless I am also presented with a sign appropriate to the thing. Significance of this simplest sort is a part of every experience. Symbols and the mental attitudes which accompany them pick out things, relations, qualities, sense data, from the background of pure awareness and make them objects of knowledge. Signs are a genuine part of presenta- tions, and we come originally to know their meanings apart from presentations by separating them out, rather than by artificially creating and applying them. The artificially created sign is a late product in the evolution of thought. Having been sifted out from the presentation of which it was in the beginning a part, the sign can mean when the object meant is not presented, but it could not mean this object unless the latter had been pre- sented. It is less evident that words are integral parts of presenta- tions than that images are. Words probably appear later than images as carriers of cognitive attitudes. But theories of the de- velopment of language assume that words were originally bound up with perceptions. Those who believe that language arose, in part at least, from ejaculations say that a noun such as “‘ache”’ comes from the ejaculation “‘ach!”’ the cry of pain; the pronoun +>? “me” from the ejaculation “ahem!” by which the speaker in- voluntarily calls attention to his own presence.! Cries and vocal expressions, once parts of an experience, were thus cut off from the whole and became significant in their own right. Certainly 1G. Willis, The Philosophy of Speech (1920), p. 9. 34 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH in our adult perceptions we are often conscious of the passage of words through the mind as a means by which we adjust our- selves to the object perceived. There can be little doubt that all perceptions include a psychi- cal set toward the object. The mind is not purely passive in per- ception, as Locke supposed — not a tabula rasa on which experi- ence writes. Perception is an activity, and mental activity is always directed toward something; it always intends something. This active attitude of intending, which is the second essential of simple meaning, is more prominent in perception than the first, that is, the symbol proper, to which this attitude is at- tached. But the first is nevertheless present. The symbol proper arises somewhere in the course of the perception, and the three elements, symbol, attitude, and object, are united in a whole which is the presentation of the object. Thus, as far back as we can trace our articulated experience, simple concepts are present in it, and these have meaning only through experience because they are of the very stuff of experi- ence. These elementary symbols (concepts) stand for data. When a single word, gesture, or sound has once been taken as significant without definition, a datum has been accepted; and though sub- sequent use of the symbol may lead one to observe that the ob- ject it refers to is complex and can be analyzed into new data signified by other symbols, still no analysis can be pushed so far that all data disappear. But it must not be forgotten that many simple symbols have meaning only through definition. “Santa Claus”? means the same as “the good saint who fills up our b stockings at Christmas”; “the universe” is a name for “the totality of objects, known and unknown”’; “matter” a name for “objects that obey physical laws.” Such defined symbols are abbreviated forms of more complex meanings. They are derived concepts whose objects are not data. MEANING 35 XIT Having once at our command a stock of the simpler instru- ments of meaning given in our commerce with the immediate environment, we can construct new meanings determined by the old. Through these the imagination takes wings and the world of speculation is opened. A symbolic group, if it stands for anything, will stand for a complex object, which may be the kind of object signified by a descriptive phrase such as “‘the center of gravity of the solar system,” or the kind signified by a completed sentence either asserted or unasserted, e.g., “knowledge is power.” The latter type of symbolic group is ordinarily termed a proposition. The peculiarity of a descriptive phrase is that through a complex of predicates or relations it signifies a term, while the meaning of a proposition, on the other hand, is not focussed on a single term.! The constituents of the complex object meant by a symbolic group are signified by simple symbols, and it is clear that these constituents must have been given in experience or must be de- finable through symbolic groups whose simple symbols refer to elements given in experience. ““New York” means “the city at the mouth of the Hudson,” and if the objects meant by “‘city,”’ “at,” “‘mouth,” “of,” and “Hudson” cannot be known di- rectly, they must be defined in terms of objects that can be known directly; that is to say, every symbol (simple or complex) must signify a datum or be reducible to symbols which signify data. And yet a descriptive phrase or proposition whose simple symbols refer to data or are defined in terms of references to data, may as a whole stand for no object; it may state no fact, describe nothing, and still be significant. Thus the phrase, “the hereditary monarchs of the United States,”’ has meaning though it describes no one; the proposition, “‘the gods live on nectar and ambrosia,” states no fact, yet it is significant. 1 See below, ch. IV, for a discussion of this distinction. 36 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH Both reason and imagination rest on this possibility of using symbols significantly when there is nothing to which they refer — a possibility which arises through joining simple symbols into groups. The meaning of the group is a function of nothing but its subordinate meanings and — what is more important still — of its logical form. No object meant need be presented; the being, either in or out of experience, of an object to which the group as a whole refers is irrelevant to the meaning, for group- meanings are determined by meanings alone. Many writers dismiss the possibility of thinking or speaking significantly when there is no object thought or spoken of, by a simple argument. To think when there is nothing thought of is not to think; to mean when there is no object meant is not to mean.! It is denied that symbols can be used significantly when they do not refer to existing objects. This is indeed true of unde- fined simple symbols but it is not true of symbolic groups. The argument rests on the assumption that all meaning is simple reference to an object with an object, and the more subtle type of reference through groups is neglected. Syntactical or group-meaning is, like all meaning, an outward reach of the mind, but it takes an indirect course and may never terminate in an object. A phrase sets up all the anticipations or intentions its single words arouse; when I understand the signifi- cance of “‘a sunny day in spring,” I am stirred psychologically as I would be by “‘sunny,” “day,” and “spring”; I take an atti- tude appropriate to the things meant by each of these words; 1 Plato puts this argument in The Sophist, Jowett’s translation, marginal page 237: Stranger. You mean by assenting to imply that he who says something must say some one thing? Theaetetus. Yes. Stranger. Then he who says “not something”? must absolutely say nothing. Theaetetus. Most assuredly. Stranger. And he who says “‘nothing,”’ is not to be described as speaking; and therefore he who says “‘not-being”’ does not speak at all. MEANING 37 but my attitude is at the same time a unity. I anticipate these elements as forming a whole, and if no such whole exists the atti- tude of mind will still carry the meaning. Through the many references of its members (and its logical form) the symbolic group, as a unity, has a reference, that is, a direction toward something; and even though there is (or has been) in experience no object for which the expression as a whole stands, there will nevertheless be a locus in experience toward which this unitary reference is directed. This is the locus of the objects meant by the elements of the group. There is no “present king of France”’; and yet this phrase tells me where to seek for the object it might mean. A symbolic group means through a complex inten- tion constructed from simpler intentions, and so performs the function of referring, which is the essence of meaning, when as a whole it refers to nothing. Syntactical meaning — a meaning of the whole determined solely by that of the parts and their plan of unity — can be found in any phrase, sentence, mathematical expression; in short, in any group of symbols. Its requisites are: (1) a number of simple symbols referring directly to objects, or defined in terms of such references, and (2) a unity of these symbols and the intentions which attach to them in a single intention. It is not necessary that this complex intention should arise from or terminate in any single object. The manner in which the simple symbols are joined into a unity gives the expression a structure, and it is in the analysis of this structure that the central problems of the theory of knowl- edge appear. It may seem to the reader that the structure of symbolic groups is merely a matter of grammar. What possible light can the study of grammatical forms throw on knowledge? The fact is that grammatical forms are reflections of logical forms; and if the study of the structure of symbolic expressions is grammar, it is what has been called “philosophical grammar” 38 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH —an analysis of the structure of thought. In order to under- stand what is meant by the form of a symbolic complex, it is necessary to probe deep into the nature of knowledge and its objects. But before we turn to this topic, let us put together the facts of knowledge which are now before us. XIII The objects of knowledge are not ideas, unless “idea” be taken in the broad sense of any known object. Ideas in the sense of “images”’ can be distinguished from sensory and perceptual objects, and the objects of knowledge may be either images or sensations and perceptions. Ideas in the narrower sense occupy a special place in thought: they are the most primitive type of symbols, the primary carriers of meaning. Ideas need not signify merely the sensory or perceptual objects they resemble: any idea may mean any thing. Moreover, semi-artificial signs such as those of speech and writing supplement images, and in some cases completely supplant them. It is important to observe that no symbols are restricted to meaning a particular class of ob- jects, least of all to meaning ideas in the narrower sense. The study of the principles of symbolism, which is also the study of the mechanism of conception (for a concept is nothing more nor less than a significant symbol), provides a single point of view from which to approach knowledge. Knowledge as a whole falls into two great divisions: mediate and immediate, knowledge about and acquaintance with objects. The former rests on symbols alone; the latter is a union of sym- bolic knowledge and direct apprehension. The presentation of objects, that is, experience, is always attended by the functioning of symbols (of concepts) in the mind, and intending or meaning an object is a part of every experience. The mind is not a tabula rasa but an active agent in perception, and so the line between mediate and immediate knowledge cannot be sharply drawn. MEANING 39 But immediate knowledge is not sensation, for sensations do not appear by themselves but only as elements in larger cognitive units, in which they usually play the part of signs. All so-called “immediate” knowledge is partly mediated by concepts, with the exception of pure awareness, which is the complete antithesis of conceptual knowledge and the only form of pure immediacy. Pure awareness is not the cognition of objects, relations, qual- ities, or sense data: it is the apprehension of an unarticulated datum. Pure awareness cannot be dissociated from the act of knowledge as a whole. Signs have meaning only through the activity of minds. Nat- ural objects, even images, are not significant unless they are taken to be so by a mind. The meaning activity is a preparation for the object meant, but a preparation which goes no further than the central nervous system, and which appears in con- sciousness as an intention. Belief, which is of the same genus as understanding, is a completer preparation for an object: it is willingness to act as if the object were in existence. Understand- ing arises only when the mind is able to suspend the activities appropriate to a thing, and to deliberate rather than act; and though meaning rests on habit, it is not the association of ideas, nor is it the type of habitual response which leads at once to outward action. Thus it is impossible to describe meaning wholly in terms of behavior. There are two types of meaning, one of which is built on the other: (1) simple and (2) syntactical meaning. Simple symbols are objects taken by a mind to stand for other objects: their sig- nificance is not a function of their parts and, unless their mean- ing is defined, they have meaning only through direct reference to things which are (or have been) experienced. The significance of these undefined simple symbols rests on direct experience be- cause they are an integral part of the presentation of the object to which they refer. 40 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH Complex or syntactical meanings (so called because they are created by taking together simple meanings) are functions of other meanings; and this sort of significance, which attaches to any phrase, sentence, or mathematical expression, rests on the general principle of symbolism, that the meaning of a symbolic group as a whole is determined by the meanings of its elements. A symbolic group represents an object analytically, that is, as a unity of elements with a form; but a symbolic expression may be significant when it stands for no object, for its meaning is a func- tion of meanings only and not, as in the case of an undefined simple symbol, of the presentation of an object. Now that we have a general notion of what meaning is we can enter on a wider problem — that of showing how the structure of symbolic expressions points beyond itself to the structure of the world of fact. The garments in which knowledge is clothed, loose and ill-cut as they often appear, reveal the outlines of the form beneath them; syntax and grammar, which seem to be conventions of human intercourse, spring from the adaptation of the mind to an order which pervades its environment. CHAPTER II LOGICAL FORM I Menrsztx to place a number of symbols together at random does not make them a symbolic group. The phrases of language are not chance combinations of words; they have a structure, and certain word-structures are significant while others are not. The same words in one combination mean one thing, and in an- other combination, another thing. The problem of the structure of significant phrases cannot be solved by showing that any group of words which conforms to the rules of syntax in lan- guage is significant, for this leaves the rules of syntax to be ex- plained. Every symbolic system, whether it be speech, mathematics, logic, or the system of mental images, has its own rules of syn- tax. Within the system some combinations of symbols are signif- icant and others are nonsensical. Some of these principles are arbitrary: they have grown up through usage, as have the mean- ings of the individual signs, and usage can alter them; but they are not all arbitrary. The structure of every symbolic system is the same in general outline; it is modeled on the structure of fact, for every symbolic system, if it represents anything, will represent facts. The meaning of a symbolic group is, for this reason, not purely a matter of choice, as is the meaning of a simple symbol. There are certain objects that the group can signify, and other objects that it cannot signify. The structure of the group fur- nishes a criterion which enables us to determine its possible meanings. At first sight it might seem that groups of symbols 42 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH could represent anything, as can simple symbols. Simple sym- bols are attached to their objects only accidentally, through habit or definition. We can change our conventions for their use as we please. Why is this not also true of symbolic groups? Are not all symbols arbitrary and accidental in their meaning? If this were so, the problem of how symbols represent objects would be speedily solved: we could say merely that we are in the habit of using such and such signs for such and such things, (though we should have difficulty in saying this), and the study of the principles of symbolism would be reduced to the compil- ing of dictionaries. But this is not all. When a group of symbols takes on a meaning through the meanings of its constituents, it becomes in a far-reaching sense a representative of an object, if it stands for an object. The re- lation between a group of symbols and the fact it signifies can be likened to the correspondence of a map to a region of which it is a partial picture. Each element of the map means a feature of the landscape, which is related to other features as the map- elements are related to one another. So, each symbol of a group means a part of the whole fact signified, a part which is related to other parts of the fact as the symbols are related in the group. A phrase, a sentence, a mathematical expression, or a complex idea is as much a picture of a fact as a map is of a country. The difference is that the portraiture is infinitely more subtle. The map reproduces the spatial relations of the country by spatial relations on a smaller scale. The phrase or sentence reproduces the logical relations of the elements in the fact by similar logical relations among the symbols. A phrase or sentence cannot, then, be arbitrary in meaning. It can mean only a fact logically constructed as it is constructed. Its form must be the form of the fact for which it stands. It is not difficult to discover in what respects a photograph or a map resembles its original. The correspondence of the copy LOGICAL FORM 43 with the original is written on the face of both. But the evasive features of logical form are not readily made out. What can there be in common between the sentence, “‘the sun is shining outside my window,” and the fact which the sentence means? II Symbols, whether they be words, gestures, or ideas, are ob- jects. In their rdle as instruments of meaning they are still things. A spoken word is a combination of noises distinct from other noises. A spoken sentence is a collection of combinations of noises with pauses and inflections to indicate its grouping into phrases. A written sentence is a collection of marks on a page, distinct from other marks and other collections. The nature of symbols as objects is not in the foreground of perception when they are used to convey meanings. We are only dimly conscious of the print when we read; we pierce through it, as through a luminous medium, to the meaning. The quality of a voice, the sound of a spoken word, fade into the background of the mind when we attend to a speaker; we hear only what the speaker intends to say. And yet the nature of symbols as ob- jects is not completely forgotten in interpreting them, for it is this that causes them to be recognized as having a structure. There are characters and relations which belong to all objects alike and are the most abstract features of their being, and it is these characters and relations which the symbols — being also objects — reproduce. Logical form is the least common factor of all objects. Any entity which is presented or thought exhibits logical form, and a thing without logical form (if it could be a “‘thing”’) could not be brought within the circle of reason. Where logical form ends, the presentation of objects, analysis, representation, the rational processes, also end; and if any knowledge could remain, it would be knowledge by intuition — the pure awareness which gives us no objects. 44 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH The characters and relations that determine logical form ap- pear when we ask what it means to be an object or a fact. ““Ob- ject”? is the most general of all terms. It applies to everything, whether simple or complex; and a definition of “‘object”’ is im- possible, since it could not be framed without making use of this term. A person, a landscape, a mental state, a quality, a relation, an operation — all are objects. The very statement of the fact that everything is an object is a tautology. “Object” is more inclusive than Aristotle’s “substance” (that is, his “first substance’’). By “substance” Aristotle meant an individual, which could be a subject of predication or could stand in relations to other substances. Objects include not only subjects of predication and terms of relations, but also the predi- cates and relations which can be attached to subjects and terms. Several kinds of objects go together to make up the thing meant by “Caesar was the noblest Roman of them all.” Caesar is an in- dividual subject; Roman is a predicate; noblest of them all is a re- lation — a different kind of object from either of the first two. Each of these, as well as the whole fact, is an entity with a dis- tinct being; each is an object. To assert that a thing is an object is to make the minimum statement about it; it is to affirm merely that z is x. But trivial as this assertion appears, it is implicit in all knowledge of ob- jects; for it informs us that something is singled out, fastened on by the attention, and referred to through symbols. A fact, which could be represented analytically in a symbolic group, is not a bare “this,” an x with no character in particular and no relations to other objects. A fact is a complex of different kinds of objects: it is a thing with characters, or a number of terms in relation; it is a concretion of objects. The whole for which “Brutus killed Caesar” stands is a fact. “Rome was not built in a day,” stands for another fact. “‘ Fairies have wings,” if it stood for anything, would stand for a fact. Taken as wholes, LOGICAL FORM 45 as clusters of objects, facts are themselves objects of an articu- lated sort. Unanalyzed objects are the atoms of thought and facts the molecules; but molecules can play a part not unlike that of atoms, and any given fact can become the foundation of more complex facts. III The first element of structure in a fact is that it is a group — a group whose character as a whole is determined by the nature and relations of its parts. This concept is fundamental in the description of logical form. A group, as the term is used here, is any object constituted of other objects. The fact meant by (2 + 2) is a group, because the whole is a function of the objects meant by 2 and (+). The ob- ject signified by “‘the blue sky” is a group determined by the objects meant by “blue” and “sky.” (‘‘The” does not stand for a constituent of the fact.) ! Similarly, “a precedes b” means a group — a fact constituted of the objects a and 6 and the rela- tion precedes. Some groups are subjects qualified by predicates, others are terms in relation, and still others, terms joined by mathematical or logical operations. In short, any object deter- mined by other objects is a group. The concept of grouping is the same as that of function. To say that a whole is a function of its parts is to call attention to the fact that it is a group. Every whole is a group and every group is a whole; and not only is every fact a group, but every collection of symbols with syntactical meaning is also a group, whose character as a whole is determined by the nature and re- lation of the parts, and whose significance as a whole is a func- tion of the significance of the parts. It must not be supposed that a disunified plurality of ob- jects or symbols is a group in the true sense. There must be a determination of the whole by the parts. The relations between 1 See below, ch. IV, sec. v. 46 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH the parts, if there are relations other than the general unity of the group, are themselves parts or members of the group. Thus a between b and ¢ is determined not only by a, b, and c, but also by the relation between. This determination of the whole by the parts is essential: without this, the plurality of objects is not a group. A factual group must be a single fact and a symbolic group a single symbol. The concept of grouping then presupposes, (1) a plurality of objects (members), which may be terms, or characters and rela- tions, or both; and (2) the union of these so that the members uniquely determine a whole; and in the case of symbolic groups, (3) a union of the meanings of the parts so that they uniquely determine the meaning of the whole. What there is in common between a phrase, a mathematical expression, or a complex idea, and the fact it might represent, now begins to emerge. Both the symbol and the fact are groups. Symbols reproduce groups by groups, as the map reproduces spatial relations by spatial relations. But this gives only the frame-work of the picture. There are an infinite number of dif- ferent symbolic groups and different factual groups, each of which can be distinguished by its logical form alone. The possi- bilities of reproducing different structures of fact by formally distinct symbolic structures are without limit. IV Every entity, simple or complex, is identical with itself and distinct from other entities. Numerical identity and diversity, together with grouping, determine logical form because they are the most abstract, that is to say the “formal,” characters of objects. Differences in logical structure are numerical in nature; they are differences in the number of constituents in groups, and in the number of groups which are members of groups within a whole. Form is in a literal sense number, as the Pythagoreans be- LOGICAL FORM 47 lieved. If, in the apprehension of a fact, everything is disregarded excepting the numerical identity and diversity of its elements, and their grouping into wholes, what remains will be the logical form. Since a simple symbol is not a group, it is not distinguished from other simple symbols by its form, though it is distinguished formally from any complex symbol. These most elementary of signs differ only materially in meaning from one another, that is, through the concrete characters of the intentions which attach to them or of the objects they mean. At the lowest stage of anal- ysis formal distinctions of significance do not appear, €.9.5 proper names are all of the same form. Any analytical representation of an object carries its analysis to the limit of the things meant by the simple symbols, and if any further analysis is possible, this analysis is not contained in the representation. When it is said that the fact meant by “the sunshine on the ocean” is composed of the simple elements, swn- shine, on, and ocean, these elements are not affirmed to be abso- lutely simple, to be irreducible. They are the elementary com- ponents of the fact as it is here expressed; the representation goes no further in analysis. It is evident that the constituents of most facts, as they are expressed in symbols, can be further analyzed. If there is a final limit of analysis, if some data are absolutely simple, most repre- sentations stop short of this limit. A simple symbol represents an object with the smallest possible amount of analysis — with a zero analysis. These symbols set the scale of reproduction. Just as the map may employ one inch for ten miles, so a symbolic ex- pression may use a simple symbol for something which is in real- ity complex; just as another map may depict the same region on a larger scale, so another symbolic group may represent as com- plex what is elsewhere represented as simple. But through simple symbols alone objects cannot be represented as of differ- ent forms. 48 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH When symbols or objects are grouped, the groups will be formally alike or different in several ways: in multiplicity, in type, and in the distribution of identical elements (or tautologous symbols) within the constituent groups. (These terms are arbi- trarily chosen to suggest the concepts they mean.) The multvplicity of a group is determined by the number of major members. However simple or complex the elements of a fact may be, these elements, as they are seen through a symbolic expression, are of a definite number; and the elements of the fact are corre- lated with the constituents of the symbolic group so that for each symbol, simple or complex, in the expression there is a cor- responding part of the fact, and so that the expression as a whole means the fact as a whole. The first layer of facts will be those represented by symbolic groups whose elements are all simple symbols. “The sunshine on the ocean”’ is such a fact; (2 +8) is another such fact. Clearly, neither of these symbolic expressions could mean a fact which could not be analyzed into at least three elements. The major members of these facts (but only of this simplest type of facts) are the unanalyzed objects signified by the simple symbols. The number of these objects determines the multiplicity of the fact, and the number of simple symbols, the multiplicity of the symbolic group.' But the major members are not always simple symbols or the objects meant by simple sym- bols; the major members may be complex, and the multiplicity of the expression or the fact will not then be fixed by the number of simple components. Primary facts, facts of the lowest layer, may enter as wholes with other constituents to form new facts; and these will belong to a second layer. At least some of their constituents will be 1 The article, “‘the,”’ does not represent a constituent of the fact. With it must be classed “a,” “any,” “some,” “every,” “each,” and “‘all.”’ See below, ch. IV, sec. v. Similarly, “‘not” does not stand for a constituent of a fact. See below, ch. VI. LOGICAL FORM 49 themselves complex, and will be signified by groups within groups. This gives the second dimension of logical form — the type of the group. Horizontally, so to speak, a form is deter- mined by the number of its major members; vertically, by the number of groups included within groups. The sentence, “‘the sunshine on the ocean pleases me,’’ repre- sents a fact whose constituents are not unanalyzed objects signi- fied by simple symbols. One of the constituents of this fact is itself an analyzed fact reproduced by a symbolic group. The whole includes a subordinate group, “the sunshine on the ocean,” and this is combined with the things meant by “pleases” and “‘me” to form a fact of higher type. The secondary fact therefore contains a primary fact as one of its constituents. Now the sentence, “‘I am happy because the sunshine on the ocean pleases me,’”’ means a fact of a still higher type. The secondary fact, “the sunshine on the ocean,” has become an element in a new whole through its union with the things meant by “I,” and by “‘happy,” and “because.” (The copula, “is” and its variants, is a sign of assertion; its function is unlike that of any other sign.)} Facts combine and recombine in this way, reaching higher and higher levels of complexity. The result is a multitude of new logical forms — new combinations of symbols with symbols and objects with objects. The major constituents of such facts and symbolic groups are the facts and groups which enter immediately into the whole without being constituents of sub-facts or sub-groups. All the other elements are minor constituents. The fact, ““I am happy because the sunshine on the ocean pleases me,” contains as major constituents the two subordinate facts, “I am happy” and ‘‘the sunshine on the ocean pleases me,” and these are joined by the major relation “because.” These subordinate 1 See below, ch. V, sec. xiii. 50 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH facts in turn contain their major constituents, which are the minor constituents of the larger fact. The analysis proceeds as far as the facts composed of elements meant by the single words, and these facts contain only major constituents. Their elements are the basic materials of the structure. The type of an expression or fact is therefore determined by the number of groups within groups. An expression or fact of the first type has no members which are groups. (2 + 2), (a — b), France fears Germany, are of the first type. An expression or fact of the second type will include as a major member at least one (or more than one) group of the first type; e.g. (a (b—c)), France fears a new war. The other major members of such a fact may, as in these cases, be things meant by simple symbols, or things meant by groups of the first type, e.g. ((a + b) — (e+ d)). In general, an expression or fact of the nth type will include as a major member at least one (though it may include more than one) group of the n — Ist type; and as a consequence, it will in- clude as minor members groups down to the {st type. In determining the multiplicity of a group, its type must be taken into consideration, for it is the number of major constitu- ents (the members entering immediately into the whole without being constituents of sub-groups) which establish the multiplic- ity, and these may be of a higher type than the first. Thus ((a — b) — (b— ¢)) has only three major members, that is, the operation (— ), and the complex terms (a — 6) and (b — c). Its multiplicity is not determined by the number of simple symbols or unanalyzed elements. If facts of a secondary, tertiary, or higher type are alike both in their horizontal and vertical dimensions, they will be of the same form. This means that they must have the same number of major constituents, and that each of these constituents in the one must be constructed of groups within groups exactly as is a corresponding constituent in the other, and vice versa. LOGICAL FORM 51 vi Language exhibits the form of the facts it signifies much less clearly than do some other kinds of expressions. This is because the grouping of words into phrases and sentences is brought about by grammatical rules, which are felt rather than made evident in the group. Nevertheless, every phrase or sentence of any complexity is organized into groups within groups, as is also the fact for which it might stand. The major verb or connec- tive shows the major lines of cleavage; it connects the major symbolic members. These in their turn are composed of minor groups, joined by minor verbs and connectives. Punctuation plays a part here; commas, semicolons, dashes, brackets, peri- ods, etc., indicate what symbols are to be taken together. These are signs of syntax. Signs of syntax are secondary signs — signs of symbolism rather than signs of objects. They do not refer to elements in the fact for which the symbolic group might stand. They refer merely to the symbols. They mean that the symbols with which they are placed are to be treated as a group; that these symbols constitute a significant whole. Mere juxtaposition of symbols, although it is usually a sign that they are a group — and is the only sign of syntax in the system of mental images — is not a sufficient sign in most sys- tems. There must be additional ways of indicating the grouping. In language there are at least four signs of syntax: classification of words and expressions as parts of speech; inflections, case endings, genders, etc.; position; and punctuation. The signs of syntax in algebra, arithmetic, and all quasi-mathematical groups, having been invented for convenience, are simpler than those of language. The form of an algebraic expression is indi- cated by parentheses; thus ( (a + 5) X c) is plainly similar in grouping to ( (d — e) X f). These expressions are of the same logical form — a form which can be described as a group of 52 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH three major members, one of which is a group of three unana- lyzed major members. The parentheses are the signs of syntax, that is, the punctuation of these mathematical expressions. In Messrs. Whitehead and Russell’s Principia Mathematica, the signs of syntax are dots; the larger numbers of dots indicate the more inclusive groups, the smaller numbers, the minor groups. Any signs of syntax must be such that they preserve the integrity of the groups and show what groups are members of other groups. As the forms of facts and the symbols which represent them grow more complex, verbal descriptions become more lengthy. There is a simpler manner of exhibiting forms. If letters are taken to stand for the elements of a fact (or a symbolic group) and parentheses as signs of grouping, any logical form can be presented in a general schematism. ((a R 6b) S c) exhibits the form of the two algebraic expressions given above, ((a + 6) Xc) - and ((d — e) X f), and of the facts for which they might stand. It also exhibits the form of the sentence, “‘Brutus was the friend of Caesar,” and of the fact which this signifies. This sentence, and the fact, fall into major and minor groups as follows: (Bru- tus was (the friend of Caesar) ), and except for spatial order, which can be disregarded here, the symbols are grouped exactly as is the expression ((a Rb) S c). The use in this general schematism of capital letters for some of the group-elements should be noted. Wherever there is a com- bination of elements, the terms combined must be distinguished from the relation or operation which unites the terms. Qualities, relations, and operations enter into, modify, and give unity to groups of terms in a peculiar way, and they can be classed to- gether as elements of unity, which are distinguishable from the terms they unify. A quality is a modifier (or element of unity) in a group of one term, ¢.g., “‘the white knight,” which is of the form (fa). A relation appears in a group of several terms, e.g., LOGICAL FORM 53 “‘a between 6 and c,” and an operation may enter in a group of any number of terms. The capital letters in this general repre- sentation of logical forms stand for symbols or elements of unity, while the small letters stand for terms. Similarity of form between groups, whether it be between facts, between symbols, or between symbols and facts, can be shown by correlating them as follows: Each major constituent of the one must be made to correspond with one and only one major constituent of the other, and vice versa; and if these con- stituents are groups, each of their major members must be made to correspond uniquely, and so on, down to the elements signi- fied by the simple symbols. This correlation will give a perfect parallelism of members, both horizontally and vertically. (Pos- sible complexities in the element or symbol of unity are neg- lected. There will be at least one element or symbol of unity in every group, and although this may be complex, it can be treated as one — as the element of unity.) ! When a symbolic group stands for a fact, such a correlation of the group with the fact is set up by the relation of meaning. This parallelism of groups, of terms and elements of unity, of complex and simple constituents, makes possible a comparison of the structure of groups without counting the number of the members or the layers of superimposed groups. We do not need the concept of the number-series in order to apprehend similar- ities and differences of form, but merely the concept of one-to- one correspondence, on which the number-series is based. The eye effects such a correlation in observing that ((Rab) Sc) and ((Qde) Mf) are of the same form. VI Symbolic groups thus constructed could not have a wholly arbitrary meaning; the principle of syntactical meaning makes it 1 See below, ch. III, sec. xvii, for the additional differences of form intro- duced by the complexity of the element of unity. 54 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH necessary that in form at least they must reproduce the objects they might signify. Given significant simple symbols and a logi- cal form, and the meaning of the whole will be determined by the meanings of the simple symbols and by the logical form. It will be possible to analyze the fact meant (if there is a fact) into groups and simple elements parallel to those of the symbolic ex- pression. Any fact can be analyzed in a number of different ways. Its lines of division and grouping run in different directions, de- pending on the elements chosen as the basis of the analysis. All the possible ways of stating the same fact will represent the dif- ferent lines of structure, the different analyses. The fact, “‘a is > between b and ec,” is the same (if a, b, and c mean the same things in both cases) as “a is to the right of b and ¢ is to the right of a.’ ““Caesar conquered Gaul” and “the first Emperor of Rome triumphed over the region which is modern France and Germany,” are different analyses of the same fact. No fact and no object is exhausted by a single analysis. The analysis directs our attention to certain aspects of the fact, but other aspects of it remain untouched. There is no single logical form which is peculiarly the form of any one fact. Statements of the type, “a is y,”’ where “‘is”” means “‘is identi- cal with,” tell us that a single fact permits different analyses; a large part of our knowledge is embodied in observations of dif- ferences of structure in the same fact. “2 + 3 is 5,” for example, informs us that the object which we signify by “5” can be de- composed into the constituents meant by “2” and “3” and **plus.”’ And if statements of identity were trivial, as they are sometimes said to be, much of our knowledge would be trivial. It is doubtless of no interest, excepting as a case of a general logical principle, to know that “a is a,” and only of slight inter- est to know that “a is b”’; but it is of great interest to know that the same fact can be stated in different ways, that a single ob- ject exhibits a variety of logical forms. LOGICAL FORM 55 VII We have yet to consider the third element of form — the dis- tribution of identical members, or tautologous symbols, among the constituent groups of a fact or a symbolic expression. Meanings must have a certain fixity and continuity. If sym- bols were fluid and capricious in their references they would be of no use, for we should never know exactly to what they re- ferred. In any discourse symbols recur, they appear again and again, and on each recurrence they are given the same interpre- tation. Now, strictly speaking, a repeated symbol is not the same ob- ject. The sound “bird” uttered to-day is not identically the sound “‘bird”’ uttered to-morrow. The image of my friend which is in my mind now is not identical with the image of him which was in my mind an hour ago. Therefore a symbol is something more than a single object which comes before the mind, takes on meaning, and disappears. Recurrence is of the essence of sym- bols. The same word may enter many times in one sentence and many more times in a paragraph. A number or letter may reap- pear in different parts of a single mathematical or logical ex- pression. We cannot say that the word, the number, or the letter is the very same in each instance, but all the instances are like enough to be classified together, though each is a distinct object. The symbol is all the cases of its own recurrence. A symbol then is not a single object, but a class of objects. Symbols are the same symbol only if they exhibit a generic sim- ilarity as objects, and they are distinct symbols if they exhibit a generic difference. Thus a and 6 are distinct symbols because their contours as marks on a page are different, while a and a (if they are not ambiguous) are the same symbol because their con- tours are alike. When we select an object as a symbol, we fasten on one or more of its concrete characters, and only objects with these characters are treated as the same symbol, while objects 56 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH of different characters are treated as distinct symbols. The char- acters that give generic similarity or difference to symbols may be any characters whatsoever. In European languages, for ex- ample, differences of pitch do not differentiate spoken signs, while in Chinese they do. Apart from ambiguity, which must be dealt with as a special factor, a recurrent symbol always means the same object. Re- current symbols are tautologous; they are not symbolically dis- tinct and yet they are not identical as objects. But when it is said that tautologous symbols mean the same object, this “‘sameness”’ is not the sameness of similarity. The object is identically the same. Identity is that which makes an object one and unique. No two objects which are alike can be identical, for they are two and must therefore be at least numerically distinct. The recurrent instances of a symbol, though they are alike, do not signify objects which are merely alike. They mean an identi- cal object. The principle which gives rigidity to the meanings of symbols, that is, that the same symbol, if it stands for an object, stands for an identical object, is the principle of identity. Not only is a symbol a class of objects; it is a class of objects whose meaning is unique. Symbols which have different meanings are different symbols; it is impossible that the same symbol should have more than one meaning. The attempt to interpret a symbol in more than one way gives rise to psychological ambiguity or equivocation; and this must be distinguished from the logical ambiguity of a phrase such as “a man” or “some man.” Logical ambiguity is useful in thought, but equivocation makes precision of conception or statement impossible.! Equivocation is eliminated only when 1 It is true, however, of logically ambiguous symbols, as of all symbols, that they follow the principle of identity. They can have only one meaning. The variable, ‘a man,” if it is given a value, can be given one and only one value. LOGICAL FORM 57 the equivocal symbols are treated as distinct. Though the spoken words “read” and “red” do not differ in their character as objects, they are different symbols in the sentence, “I read a red book,” and they cannot be construed as the same without a distortion of the meaning. Needless to say, images are even more open to ambiguous interpretations than words. Every symbol, then, presupposes the uniqueness of its own meaning, and this is what the principle of identity, a is a, tells us. It states that a, wherever it occurs, is to be interpreted by one and only one object; and if a is significant, but stands for no object, the principle tells us that if a represented an object it could be one and only one. This principle is therefore a general rule of symbolism. Phrases such as “the round square” and names such as “ Phoe- bus Apollo,” which refer to no existent objects, follow the law of identity no less than do phrases such as “the present king of England” or names such as “‘ Julius Caesar.” “A round square” as ““a round square,” “Phoebus Apollo” is “Phoebus Apollo,” in the sense that each of these symbols is to be interpreted in one and only one way, in the sense that each has a meaning of its own different from that of all other symbols not expressly de- fined to have the same meaning. “Round square” plays the same part in the symbolism, wherever it appears, as “round square’; instances of this symbol can replace one another in any expression without altering the meaning of the whole. In short, as a general rule of symbolism, a is a, states that a is the same symbol as a. It declares an intention to interpret a uniquely. The very conception of a symbol as distinct from other symbols and the same in all its instances demands that its meaning be unique. The principle of identity can also be interpreted in another way, that is, as a statement of fact about objects; but this sec- ond interpretation presupposes the first—the interpretation as 58 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH a rule of symbolism. When a stands for an object, a 7s a asserts, not merely that a and a are the same symbol, but that the ob- ject meant has an identity, that it is an object. This is the existential as distinguished from the symbolic interpretation of the principle of identity. And if a is a variable, so that it means any object, a is a affirms that “any object is identical with itself.” Clearly, such a statement of identity is false if it refers to no object; it is not true that “a round square is a round square” in the sense that round squares have identity. However, “a 2s a,” man 7s man,” could not be asserted as 99 66 “Caesar is Caesar, 99 «66 > a,” “Caesar,” “‘man,”’ were “«¢ existential propositions unless construed as the same symbols in each case. It must be assumed that the meaning of a symbol is unique if any object is affirmed to be identical with itself; but it is not necessary to assume that the symbol stands for an object in order to assert that it can have one and only one meaning, for this latter rule is a condition of its use, whether or not it stands for an object. Distinct symbols, symbols whose characters as objects are dissimilar, may be equivalent in meaning; they may stand for an identical object, or if they stand for no object, they may be treated as indistinct in meaning. This treatment will not make them the same symbol, for symbols must be alike as objects to be the same. Thus “red” and “vermilion” are distinct symbols with the same meaning; but they are not tautologous or recur- rent instances of one symbol. Such equivalences may be equiva- lences by definition only, and they will then be statements of special intentions in the use of symbols: the equivalence “a is b” tells us that a and b can be substituted for one another wherever each occurs. This equivalence is a valid definition, but as an assertion of fact it may be false. Thus “Titania” is “the queen of the fairies’; but there are no fairies and no Titania. Definitions do not require the existence of an object defined, for LOGICAL FORM 59 they are primarily concerned with the use of symbols, and a valid definition may be false as a statement of fact. VIII The proposition, a ts a, when it means that any object is iden- tical with itself, is true without exception. There is nothing of which we can speak that is not self-identical. The concept of the identity of an object is said by Hume to be a fiction. Objects weave themselves in and out of experience as do threads in a tapestry, and it is difficult, if not impossible, to know that a thing which appears the same is really the same. But the entire fabric of thought would fall apart if we did not assume that an object fixed as a thing meant can remain identi- cal with itself. Putting aside the question of the reality of these self-identical objects, we must suppose that objects — for knowledge at least — stand still long enough to be referred to and re-referred to, for if this were not so nothing could be represented. All objects, including symbols themselves, would flow together; there would be no differentiation in knowledge. Nothing would remain itself to be an instrument of significance or a thing signified. We could not relocate anything we had previously known, and we should be helplessly blown about by the winds of change. Thought must view the world as if it were made up of points and lines of iden- tity, which combine with and intersect other points and lines, but which do not cease to be themselves. The nearest approximation to a definition of an object (though it is not a definition) is this: that an object is anything with the twin characters of identity and diversity; and this statement is equally true of subjects, predicates, terms, rela- tions, and complex wholes. A universal such as whiteness has its identity ; it is something because it is identical with itself and dis- tinct from other things — from other universals and from each 60 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH of its own instances. A particular, referred to by “this white ob- ject,” for instance, is more obviously self-identical and diverse from other objects. These two formal characters are the sources of unity and plurality in the world. Wherever there is an object it must be a unity — one and identical with itself — and there must be other such unities from which it is distinct. It would be natural to suppose that the identity and diversity of objects arise through special qualities or predicates, or through sets of relations, which attach to objects. But if we at- tempted to carry this idea forward, we should then have to ex- plain why these predicates or sets of relations are unique, why they are themselves and not something else; and we should have made no advance. Identity and diversity are irreducible con- cepts, and the argument which shows most convincingly that they are indefinable is that the characters and relations in terms of which they could be defined (if at all) must themselves be assumed to be self-identical and diverse from all other characters and relations. When symbols copy the forms of objects, they reproduce the identities and diversities among objects, together with the grouping of these identical and diverse elements into wholes. A symbolic group is a black and white portrait of a fact; it leaves out everything but the identities, diversities, and groupings of the original. But the representation of the identities is a projec- tion, rather than a copy; for an identical element, entering and reéntering in several places in a fact, is signified not by an iden- tical symbol but by a recurrent symbol. The identical element is projected into the medium of time (or space) in the representa- tion. What is a single thing in the fact is reproduced by a series of similar things in the significant expression, that is, by a num- ber of instances of the same symbol, and the convention by which this projection is effected is the principle of identity. For this principle affirms that if the instances of a symbol stand for LOGICAL FORM 61 an object, this will be a single object. Tautologous symbols in the representation stand for identities in the fact. An identical element may enter in many different ways in a fact. Many different complexes may be centered about the same object to constitute a whole, and this identical component need not be recurrent in a spatial or temporal sense. ‘‘ Hamlet’s father was Hamlet’s Nemesis,” states a fact in which the same object enters in two different ways: the whole fact is composed of two major groups with an identical constituent in each. It is of the form ((a 8 b) Q (aS c)). Such a fact is like a number of inter- secting lines; it is made up of groups with common members. Still other facts are reflexive they; arise through relations which hold between a term and itself. The identical element in a reflexive fact enters as a major constituent at least twice in the same group. “‘Hamlet feared himself”’ stands for a reflexive fact, for the fact “‘Hamlet feared Hamlet,”’ which is of the form (a R a). Strictly speaking, we ought not to say in such a case that the fact is reflexive; rather, it is the symbolic expression which is reflexive, for here again the expression does not exactly copy the fact. The fact has only one term, while the symbolic group has two, though these two are not distinct. The fact is really of the form (Sa); and it is through the tautologous re- currence of a symbol that we can represent it as of the form (a R a). Thus what is in fact a quality (for a quality is an ele- ment of unity attached to a single term) is symbolized as a rela- tion. “Napoleon loved Napoleon” means the same thing as “Napoleon was egotistical’’; and the possibility of representing an identical term through a recurrent symbol enables us to treat this quality as a relation — a relation between a term and itself. In determining the multiplicity of such reflexive expressions, the different instances of the same symbol must be reckoned as separate terms or members. Thus (a R a) has two terms and is the same in multiplicity as (a R 6). (Qaab), which is the form of 62 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH “*a gives b to a,” where “gives to”’ is a single relation, has three terms and is the same in multiplicity as (Qabc), which is the form of “a gives b to c.” It is clear that the multiplicity of the fact meant by these reflexive groups is not that of the symbolic group; a fact of a lesser multiplicity is represented, through tautologous symbols, as of a greater multiplicity. The manner in which an identical object appears and reap- pears as a component in a single fact is the third distinctive fea- ture of logical form; and facts or symbols of the same form must correspond not only in the number of their constituents, but also in the distribution of identical elements or tautologous sym- bols among the groups. Thus (a R a) and (0 S 6) will represent facts of the same form, which is that of “Napoleon loved Na- poleon” or “Hamlet feared Hamlet.” The symbols ((a R b) S (a Rc)) and ((eQf) L (e Q g)) will stand for facts of the same form — facts such as that signified by “Juliet’s love caused Juliet’s doom.” It is easily seen that the appearance of an identi- cal element in different ways in a fact leads to many new vari- eties of form. These identical elements may also be represented by distinct but equivalent symbols; and here too the symbolic group does not exactly portray the fact, but contains more distinct mem- bers than there are distinct elements in the original. “‘Hamlet mistrusted himself” is composed of three distinct symbolic members, (“‘Hamlet”’ and “‘himself”’ are symbolically distinct), while the fact to which this expression refers contains only two. The expression is redundant in form. Such a group can always be reduced to a more exact copy, or projection, of the form of the fact by replacing the equivalent symbols by instances of the same symbol; and this is what is done in interpreting the expres- sion. Its meaning is the same as that of ‘‘Hamlet mistrusted Hamlet.” The distribution of tautologous symbols or identical elements LOGICAL FORM 63 in the constituent groups of a symbolic expression or a fact takes a place of equal prominence with multiplicity and type in the determination of logical forms. For the distinction between a reflexive and a non-reflexive group, or between a group whose sub-groups contain common members and one whose sub-groups contain no common members (or differently distributed ones), is a formal and not a material distinction. IX Among the more important differences of form which have not been mentioned are those of order — the difference between ““a precedes b” and “‘b precedes a.’’ Order requires no new con- cepts; it is determined by grouping alone.! In the present chapter we have shown how logical form arises from the grouping of self-identical and diverse objects into facts, and of tautologous and distinct symbols into significant wholes. The structure of a symbolic expression copies the structure of the fact which it means, or might mean, through its grouping. The three chief features of logical form are: (1) multiplicity, (2) type, and (3) the distribution of tautologous symbols or identical elements within groups. The multiplicity of a group is determined by the number of major constituents, recurrent sym- bols being counted as separate constituents; the type by the number of groups within groups down to the elementary con- stituents. The major members of any group are those which en- ter immediately into the whole and are not members of minor groups. These major members may be simple or complex. The distribution of identical elements in a fact is not exactly reproduced in the symbolic group; these identical elements, which may not themselves be recurrent, are represented by re- current symbols. Groups of like form must correspond with one another in this respect, as well as in multiplicity and type, and in 1 See below, ch. III, sec. xiv. 64 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH the multiplicities and types of their sub-groups, down to the simple constituents. The principle which permits us to represent identical elements in a fact by recurrent or tautologous symbols is the principle of identity. A symbol is not a single object but a class of like objects, and in any or all of its instances its meaning is unique. The principle of identity tells us that a symbol can have one and only one meaning; and this is the case whether or not the symbol stands for an object. The principle of identity is therefore primarily a general rule of symbolism, but it can also be interpreted as stating a fact — the fact that “any object is identical with itself.” Its use in this sense presupposes its valid- ity as a rule of symbolism; but a statement of identity which is false as an affirmation of the existence of a self-identical object is valid as an affirmation that the same symbol is always used in the same sense. Distinct symbols may be defined as equivalent in meaning, regardless of their reference to existent objects. Identity and diversity are indefinable. Equivocally interpreted symbols are distinct, for a single symbol can (by the principle of identity) have one and only one meaning. Simple symbols are not distinguished from one another by their form, for they are not groups. They represent objects with a zero analysis; they set the scale of reproduction; but the ob- jects which they represent as simple may be in reality complex. These objects are taken as simple merely for the purposes of representation. Any single fact permits many alternative analy- ses; it may have many different forms; and no analysis exhausts a fact. The concept of a group, on which the notion of structure rests, is the same as the concept of function. A group is (1) a plurality of objects and (2) a whole determined by its parts, and the rela- tions between them; and (3) in the case of symbolic groups, the meaning of the whole is determined by the meanings of the LOGICAL FORM 65 parts. Signs of syntax—punctuation, parentheses, etc.— indicate what symbols are to be taken together as significant groups. Logical forms can be represented in a general schematism through letters grouped in parentheses. Thus (Rab) and (Sabc) differ in multiplicity but not in type; ((Sab) Q (Ldf)) and (Rab) differ in type but not in multiplicity; ((Sab) Q (Zdf)) and (Sabc) differ both in multiplicity and in type; and ( (Raab) Sa) and ((Qabc) Sd), though they are alike in every other respect, differ in the distribution of identical (or tautologous) elements. Comparisons of form, since form is numerical in nature, can be effected by a one-to-one correlation of groups without the use of the concept of the number-series. The capital letters in this schematism signify elements which perform a unique function in each group, elements of unity, that is, relations, operations, qualities; and these must be distin- guished from the terms related, qualified, or operated on. Logical form is so woven into speech, and even into the play of the imagination, that it is impossible to utter a phrase or call to mind the images of a past or future experience without throw- ing them into the forms we have described. To say that a fact is not of logical form is to say that no significant assertion can be made about it; it is to say that it is not a fact. Such a “‘fact”’ is placed beyond the reach of thought or rational experience. CHAPTER III UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS: ORDER I Every presented object has two aspects: it is both universal and individual, a “‘what” and a “‘this,’’ an essence and that in which an essence is embodied; and we have not completely de- scribed logical form until we have considered this cleavage of the objects of knowledge into universals and individuals. Objects are not perceived without their natures and their re- lations to other objects being also perceived. Each is a “this” of some quality, or a “this” related to something which is diverse from it; and the minimal cognition of objects — a perception of the distinctness of “this” and “‘that”’ — contains a universal, for distinctness is a universal. If one attempts to grasp the “this” without its qualities or relations, it is no longer a “‘this”’; it becomes so vague as not to be known even as “‘something-or- other.’’ We lose it in the pure awareness where there is neither “this” nor “‘that.’’ And yet no object is perceived as a pure quality or relation. I am not presented with sheer whiteness or betweenness or beforeness. A perceived universal is perceived in something, as qualifying a subject or as relating terms; and this subject or these terms are not themselves merely qualities or re- lations. There is something in perception to which the universal is united. The universal is perceived as individualized. No distinction has given rise to wider divergence of opinion. Plato dismisses the imponderable something in perception which is not universal as an element of imperfection; but this indeter- minate something reappears as the unintelligible “matter” or absolute non-being of his cosmology. In Aristotle’s metaphysics UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS 67 the same imponderable, far from taking the form of absolute non-being, becomes infinite potentiality, infinite possibility of being; but Aristotle finds no actual being which is not also uni- versal. The nominalist, on the one hand, affirms that only the individual is real; and the realist — the extreme realist — that only the universal is real. But if with the Platonic realists we turn our minds away from the things of perception and deny the reality of individuals, we are still confronted with the facts of perception; and though these facts are proclaimed to be “‘opin- ion”’ or “illusion,” the duality of universal and individual, in a very persistent form, continues in knowledge. Nor does the denial of the reality of universals make them any the less im- portant as phenomena of knowledge. The distinction between the “‘ what” and the “this” is omni- present in knowledge whether or not it is in reality. II One of the paradoxes of knowledge is that having made the distinction we attempt to escape from it by describing the in- dividual in universal terms. My house is built of brick and stands on a hill. I return to it after a day’s absence to find that the red walls still top the hill; but what I recognize are the characters and relations, and not the individual thing—my house. If I try to describe its individ- uality, I find that this dissolves into new characters and rela- tions; it continually recedes from my grasp. I have embarked on an apparently endless process of distinction and characteriza- tion. Predicates split off from the individual and leave it intact. The very name of an individual takes on universal significance; 1 This distinction between the universal and the individual is not the same as the distinction between essence and existence, which Mr. F. H. Bradley describes as the separation of the “‘what” from the “‘that.”’ (See F. H. Brad- ley, Appearance and Reality (1893), ch. xv.) An individual, a “this,” may or may not be in existence, yet its individuality, its “this,” will be distinct from its nature, its ‘‘ what.” 68 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH we speak of ‘‘a Solon” or “a Solomon.”’ From “Caesar”’ is de- rived “Caesarian’’; and we refer to “Caesarian pomp” or “‘Caesarian power.” What was “Caesarian” in Caesar was not then the individual himself, but a quality of the individual. A distinction of the “what” from the “this”? always leaves a “this” in which a new “what” can be distinguished. The problem of whether the individual is completely de- scribable in universal terms is one form of the general problem of determinism. Laws are descriptions of phenomena; and de- terminism in one sense means that all phenomena follow laws — that they can be described in universal terms. And if the task of knowledge is completely to describe its objects through laws — to reach a “specific essence”’’ of everything — then knowledge defeats its own purpose by admitting the distinction between universals and individuals, unless it can finally abolish the dis- tinction and identify an individual by its predicates and rela- tions. The pursuit of the “specific essences”’ of individuals makes it equally plausible to assume either that individuals are not iden- tified by their predicates and relations, or that they are. The question raises a genuine antinomy. The fact that every individ- ual can be more and more fully characterized, that the margin of confusion with other individuals is narrowed as more and more predicates are affirmed of it, seems to be evidence that a sufficient number of predicates — perhaps an infinity — would exhaust the individual; but it is equally good evidence that no predicates exhaust it. If I say of the tree beside my window that it is a pine with bark of grayish green, that it stands six feet from the house and thirty feet high, that its branches are covered with moss—if I describe it by these and a thousand other pred- icates, it is still that to which the predicates attach, and I can find more predicates. The universals are like intersecting lines at a focus, excepting that the lines determine a point, while the in- UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS 69 dividual seems to lie outside all intersecting universals; and there is no contradiction in assuming that another individual might have all the same predicates and relations. iI But is an individual not determined by its spatial and tem- poral relations? Is it not impossible that two individuals should be in the same place at the same time? And if we can know where and when an individual is, have we not described it beyond all confusion with other individuals? There is in perception a direct apprehension of the numerical diversity of individuals — of the “this” of one object and the “that” of another — and this perception, taken together with the perception of change, is the basis of the concepts of space and time. This is the sole manner in which an individual is known as distinct from other individuals. Of two peas which are exactly alike in every respect the only difference I can perceive is a bare numerical diversity, which is not a diversity of char- acters and relations, but a pure difference of individuality. To be thus perceived as distinct, individuals must be copresent, and they must neither change nor be in motion. The “this” and the “that”? must form a changeless whole of perception. This nu- merical diversity may, moreover, be given as a relation between several terms; the distinctness may be one of three or four, or possibly half a dozen, individuals. If, along with this perception of numerical diversity, goes a perception of change, the phenomenon is ambiguous; there is a question as to whether a “this” which is present at a later stage of the change is the same as the “this” of an earlier stage. The two individuals are not perceived as distinct, since they are not copresent; and yet they are not perceived as the same. Imagine a uniform field of gray before the eyes and suppose that this be- comes green and then red. Is the “this” of the object the same 70 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH beneath its changing aspects, or is each perceptible difference of quality joined to a different “this’’? Is the individual momen- tary, or does it persist through time? Change, introducing as it does the element of time, is open to two interpretations: it may be that the qualities and relations alone are different, while the individual remains the same; or that both are different. The change may be like the flow of a river, a continuous displacement of one individual by another, or like the approach of two moving bodies, an alteration of qualities and relations without the entrance of new individuals. From one point of view it seems that in each moment of time individuals are destroyed and replaced by new individuals, while from another point of view it seems that the individual must persist, at least for a brief period of time. How are we to recognize either the destruction or the persistence of an individ- ual? How are we to know that the “‘this”’ of one situation is the same as the “this” of another? We can interpret our memory of the historical continuity of our own selves as the perception of an individual persisting through time; but if this is what we mean by the perception of a persisting individual, certainly we know only one individual in this way. Whenever we believe that we are perceiving in the outer world an historically continuous individual, whose qualities and relations alone are changing, it is always possible that Descartes’s playful demon is at work, substituting distinct individuals along with the different quali- ties and relations; and if a changing object is viewed at remote times, it becomes increasingly difficult to believe that the indi- vidual persists through change. Individual objects can be perceived to be distinct and self- identical only if they are held together in a single whole of per- ception. But this does not amount to the scholastic principle of individuation — that the place of an individual at a certain time determines its individuality. This principle reverses the UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS 71 true order-of the concepts of spatio-temporal position and in- dividuality. The reason why individuals cannot be in the same place at the same time is that their numerical diversity and self-identity as individuals — apprehended in a single whole of perception — gives us the meaning of “the same or different places at the same time.” If there were any such thing as an independent space-time, it would probably be true that position in space and time would identify individuals. But it is impossible to view space and time as independent entities with reference to which objects take positions. Space and time are functions of objects; there are “places” in space and “moments” in time because individuals are self-identical and distinct. If I wish to show where and when an individual is, I must do so by referring it to other individuals from which it is numerically diverse, and so on, ad infinitum. The spatio-temporal relations of individuals are not describable without the use of other individuals as a frame of reference, and since the individuals which constitute this frame of reference are not themselves identifiable by their spatial and temporal codrdinates, no individuals are identifiable in this way. Space and time are not peculiarly privileged universals. Like all other universals, they appear only as individualized; and spatial and temporal predicates have no more claim to define the individual- ity of a “this” with which they appear than do other predi- cates. 1V To solve the antinomy of the determination of the individual by the universal, Leibniz makes use of the postulate of “the identity of indiscernibles”’: no individual can share all its pred- icates and relations with another, that is, only that which is dis- tinguishable by predicates is distinct. But this postulate takes advantage of the weakness of our powers of knowledge; it may be that we fail to make distinctions where distinctions exist. 72 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH The postulate needs to be reénforced by another, “the principle of sufficient reason,” from which it follows. This principle as- serts that everything has a reason, and since reasons are univer- sal, that everything (including the individual) is describable in universal terms. Thus the individual is connected logically, deductively, with the universal. But if an individual is determined by its predicates, so that no individuals can have all their characters and relations in com- mon, the process of distinguishing characters and relations in individuals should sometime come to an end. The “specific es- sence”’ of an individual should sometime be reached, unless it takes an infinity of universals to determine an individual. Faced with the apparently endless exfoliation of the “‘what”’ from the ‘this,’ Leibniz added that the number of universals which de- termines an individual is infinite; and this leaves finite knowl- edge no better off, so far as the determination of individuals by universals is concerned, than if the individual were not so determined. If the assumption of the identity of indiscernibles is true for reality, it is nevertheless useless for finite knowledge. The dis- tinction between the universal and the individual persists in its original form for perception and thought. The metaphysical pos- tulate leaves the epistemological difficulty as it was. V; It is possible for knowledge to proceed — and it does as a matter of fact proceed — without answering the question as to whether the individual is describable in terms of universals. The assumption of determinism (or indeterminism), even in this most abstract form, is not essential to thought. It may or may not be true that a sufficient number of predi- cates determines the unique “this” of an object; the individual can still be thought of, it can still be referred to through sym- UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS 73 bols. The individual appears in conceptual knowledge as an 2, as something represented by a variable symbol which we as- sume to have a meaning, though what this meaning is we can- not say. We cannot even assert that this x might not stand for an aggregation of universals, for it is always possible that Leib- niz’s infinity of predicates might be its value. But if we could not employ variables, which are symbols whose meaning is undeter- mined, we could not bring the individual into thought.! Thus knowledge of the individual always takes the form (xR), where x is a variable term and R is a quality of that term, or the form (xy . . . S), where z, y, etc. are variable terms and S is a rela- tion between them. (S or R might also be a mathematical or log- ical operation.) If one asks what it is to which the relation or quality attaches, he is driven to descriptions in terms of other qualities and relations; the term is lost behind essences which are of it but which are never it. In short, the value of the varia- ble continues undetermined. The representation of an individual through a variable elimi- nates a possible confusion between the individuality of a thing and its reality or existence; it makes clear the point that individ- uality may be purely conceptual. If the “this” of an object — the ultimate subject of all its predicates or the final term of all its relations — is simply the real or the existent, the individual is destroyed; it is absorbed in reality. This ultimate subject or term is represented by a variable as distinct from other subjects or terms — as one ofa plurality. The x which gives individuality to one essence is thought of as other than the y which gives in- dividuality to another; the indeterminateness of the z or y is the counterpart in thought of the inexhaustibility of the individual. Thus things of the imagination, which have not been presented and which may or may not exist, are individualized. Witness the characters of one’s favorite novel who, if they live in the 1 See below, ch. IV, sec. iv, for a general discussion of the variable. 74 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH mind, are as inaccessible to complete description as any real persons. It might be thought that a proper name stands definitely for an individual, that the variability which is present in the repre- sentation of individuals is thus eliminated. But if proper names are more closely examined, they are found to be subject to the same indeterminateness which infects all references to individ- uals. The name “Napoleon” or the name “Stratford-on-Avon”’ stands for one and only one individual, but which individual we can know only through description (or else as a mere “this” numerically diverse from a “‘that’’). Napoleon is “the conqueror of Europe,” “the exile of St. Helena,” “‘the defeated general of the Battle of Waterloo”’; Stratford-on-Avon is “the birthplace of Shakespeare.”’ Each is an a to which characters and relations attach, and the proper name no more determines what z this is than does the description; indeed, the meaning of the proper name is equivalent to the meaning of one or more of these de- scriptions of the individual named, and the variability present in the description is not absent in the name. The “this” of an object for which a proper name stands is as elusive as the “this” of any other thing.! Since knowledge presupposes the distinction between the uni- versal and the individual, and since the individual is always (for knowledge) something other than its predicates and relations — represerited in no other way than through a variable x to which these predicates and relations attach — knowledge presupposes its own indeterminateness. Leibniz’s metaphysical principles of “the identity of indiscernibles” and of “sufficient reason” pos- tulate that this indeterminateness would disappear in an infinite knowledge; such a knowledge could assign a value to the x which represents the individual. But for finite thought, only proposi- tions which make no reference to the individual can be free from 1 See below, ch. IV, sec. ix, for a discussion of proper names. UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS 75 this indeterminateness — only propositions which are stated in universal terms can have an invariable meaning. For we can know what we mean by a symbol which stands for a universal, but we can never know what we mean by a symbol which stands for an individual; or rather, we can know only that we mean a “this” which is distinct from a “that.” VI The universal is determinately known, it can be represented in thought by a symbol whose meaning is invariable, because it is presented as self-identical in different ‘“‘thises”’ and “thats,” in different individuals. And when change renders the identity of the individual ambiguous, the universal — or at least some universal — remains what it was. Universals are strands of identity which spread themselves out through time and space; it is of the essence of universals to be recognized as the same in changing and diverse instances. There is also a perception of the distinctness of universals, which is perhaps more primitive than the perception of their identity in different instances. Cutting across the numerical di- versity of individuals, when they are copresent as “this”? and “that,” is a second (numerical) diversity — that of qualities and relations. The “this” is apprehended as distinct from the “that” in some other respect than its individuality. It is a “this of the sort X”’ as distinguished from a ‘‘that of the sort Y.” And if there are several “‘thises” and “thats,” two or more of them taken together may be distinct in some other respect than in- dividuality from two or more others taken together. This will be a perceived difference of relations, ¢.g., if four circles are pre- sented, two including one another and two excluding one an- other, the inclusion and exclusion are aspects in which the groups of two differ. “Inclusion’’ is the “what” of one group, and “exclusion” the “what”’ of the other. 76 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH Such diversities of qualities and relations are numerical, no less than are those of individuals; the universals are “‘two”’ or more. But this second numerical diversity is additional to the first; it is a numerical diversity in numerical diversity. As with individuals, so with universals — they need to be copresent to be known as distinct. But despite the fact that the distinctness of universals is of the same general sort as the distinctness of in- dividuals, the one is not reducible to the other, for the universal is always merely an aspect of the individual, the “what” and the ‘‘this” are always held apart. If I am presented with a white object and a black object, the perception contains two numerical diversities on different levels, the diversity of “this object” and “‘that object” and of “blackness”? and “white- ness.” Along with this perception of differences of qualities and rela- tions may go that of the identity of a quality or relation in dif- ferent individuals. The ‘“‘this” and the “‘that” may be per- ceived as the same in some aspect. When two white objects and a black object are given together there will be, beside the numerical diversity of the three individuals, a diversity of two qualities; but a single quality will be shared by two of these individuals. A self-identical universal will be recognized in dif- ferent instances. Mr. G. E. Moore discards this possibility of a universal being an “‘identity in diversity’ because a self-identical object can be one and one only; and he believes, as a corollary of this, that a self-identical universal could not be split between several in- dividuals and remain self-identical. The individual ‘‘ whiteness” of one white object, he argues, is not identically the “white- ness’’ of another white object. The difficulty arises from a confusion of identity with in- 1 G. E. Moore, “Identity,” in Proc. Arist. Soc. (1900-1901), p. 103; espe- cially pp. 1165 ff. | : UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS ri dividuality. By a self-identical “whiteness”? one does not mean an individual white; and if there is an individual white, this is not a universal but the same thing as is meant by “‘a white ob- ject.”’ Now a white object is obviously not identical with an- other white object, but the “whiteness,” as a universal, is the same in both cases. The fact that a universal occurs with individ- uals which are not identical does not rob it of its own identity. Since identity and individuality are not the same, a single iden- tity can be individualized in many different cases. Each dis- tinct quality or relation is something in itself; it has an identity which makes it what it is, and if it had none it would be a non- entity. But to say that a universal is an identity is not to say that it is an individual. The perception of the numerical diversity of individuals, then, is accompanied by a perception of the diversity or identity of qualities and relations in these different individuals. What of the perception of diverse universals in a single indi- vidual? Obviously, a white object can be both white and round; it can be included in or excluded from another object; univer- sals, themselves static, can be grouped about a static “‘this,”’ so long as no ambiguity concerning the identity of the individual is introduced by changes in the situation. Just as we perceive (in a single whole of experience) the self-same universal as qualifying or relating many different individuals, so we perceive the self- same individual as entering into many different relations and as qualified by many different predicates. But every whole of experience gives way to new wholes; change is of the essence of experience. The self-identity and distinctness of the individual slips away behind what seem to be its changing aspects, and the universal alone continues to be known as the same. The waxing and wan- ing of a light is always light; the approach of two moving bodies, always motion; the alteration of colors in the field of vision, al- 78 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH ways color; the drops of water which displace one another in the flowing river are always of the same chemical composition. It is impossible to determine whether the individual persists, but a changeless universal is the background of the change; and the identity of this universal does not become ambiguous, as does that of the individual. All perceptual distinctions, therefore, excepting an immedi- ately apprehended difference of the “this” of one object and the “that” of another, are distinctions of universals; and all per- ceived identities, excepting the identity of a momentary “this,” are identities of universals. VII What has been said so far of universals and individuals is pre- liminary to another point — to a further characterization of logical form. The idea of the structure of groups is not complete without the concept of a universal and of the part it plays in groups. From the point of view of logical form, universals and individuals are distinguished by their structural functions. A universal is an aspect of a group as a whole. It is that which distinguishes the group from another whose constituents, apart from the universal, are indistinguishable from those of the for- mer except by their bare numerical diversity. The group as a whole is an instance of this universal, which is itself an element in the group, but not an element codrdinate with the others. The universal is an element of unity, while the others are terms. Group-unity is the universal of universals, it is the “what” of every group; and different universals are different kinds of group-unities. To recognize anything as a group is to recognize it as a unity of a specific sort, that is, an instance of a quality, a relation, or an operation. Consider the unity of a simple qualitative fact such as “Iago UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS 79 was wicked.”” Here the predicate and the subject are knit together. The expression does not mean “Jago” and “ wicked- ness”? as a mere plurality, but “ Tago-as-qualified-by-wicked- ness.” And if the fact were a number of terms joined by a rela- tion or a mathematical operation, the relation or operation would be attached to the terms in the same general manner as the quality to the thing qualified. The quality, relation, or oper- ation is not related to its terms, for this would involve an infinite series of relations; we can say only that the terms enter into the peculiar unity which makes them a group or a fact. The fact “clouds precede rain,” for example, is not made up of the ele- ments, clouds, rain, and the relation precedes related to one an- other; for if this were so, there would need to be a third relation which unites the second relation to the original terms and rela- tion, and so on. If the unity of a fact depended on the knowledge of such an endless series of relations, the fact would not be pre- sented as a whole. The unity is given immediately. A relation relates its terms and a quality qualifies its subject once and for all; and this is true of the simplest fact — of a fact, for instance, constituted of the meagre relation of conjunction or the mathe- matical operation of addition. “‘A plus B” cannot mean A and B and plus added together, for this would demand an infinity of new pluses, and the fact would remain incomplete. A plus Bisa new entity, something other than the entities A and B and plus; and it is given when the terms and the operation are given in the unity which makes the whole an instance of addition. That a quality, when it modifies a subject, is of the subject in the sense in which an operation or relation is of its terms, is borne out by our habits of speech. Relations or operations are predicated of their terms as qualities are predicated of their sub- jects. One says “‘x 1s between y and z”’ as readily as “‘x ts white”; x, y, and 2 as a group have betweenness as z alone has whiteness. Thus qualities, relations, and operations, despite their differ- 80 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH ences, are alike in their structural functions.! They can be distinguished from the terms they unite or the subjects they qualify, but at the same time they are cemented to these terms and subjects. The ability to enter with other elements in a group so that the plurality of members becomes a whole is characteristic of uni- versals; and each group contains a universal which performs this function in it. If a fact (a complex object) is presented, the determination of the group by the elements attests the presence of a universal. The form of a fact is a blank into which the con- stituents must fit, and at least one of the places in the blank is for a universal, while the others are for terms. And even the per- ception of bare numerical diversity, either of individuals or uni- versals, is an analysis of a whole into parts which are diverse from one another but have unity through the relation of diver- sity. A fact is therefore something more than a union of any ele- ments whatsoever; it is a union of elements so that a universal enters into terms or subjects. The notion of a group involves not only the concept of members united into a whole, but also the concept of an element (itself a member) which determines the members to be a whole. But the universal is distinct from the terms because it fulfills a different office in the fact; it stands above the terms, pervading the whole and lending to it a distinc- 1 Operations and relations, though they are like qualities in that they unite with terms in the same fashion, are not qualities. From the point of view of form, a quality modifies only one term; it is of the form (Ra). A relation has at least two terms; it is of the form (Sab); and if these terms are not distinct, as in (Saa), the relation still has two terms, so far as the representation goes (though these are not distinct), but the fact has only one. Such reflexive “re- lations”’’ are qualities represented as relations between a term and itself. It is the symbolic group rather than the fact which is relational in form. Opera- tions, on the other hand, may appear with one or more terms. They may be of the form of qualities or of the form of relations. But operational groups are distinguished from qualitative and relational groups by the way in which they are used in symbolic systems; they permit uses which these others do not per- mit. See below, ch. VII, sec. vii, for this distinction. UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS 81 tive coloring. The concept of the unity of a universal and the terms on which it rests must be placed with the concepts of ob- ject, and of identity and diversity, among our indefinables. The Platonic description, “participation,” as nearly charac- terizes this unity as any we know. If one were to revise Kant’s list of the categories, leaving aside the question as to whether they are of the object or of the mind, he would find it necessary to include among the presuppositions of knowledge, not only the notion of the identity and diversity of objects, but also that of the peculiar unity of groups which springs from the presence of a “participating”’ universal. VIII If a universal is any object which can assume the réle of ele- ment of unity in a group, an individual must be an object which can take no other part than that of a term. Individuals alone do not constitute facts; there are no purely individual facts. Through universals we describe and relate in- dividuals, but through individuals nothing is described or brought into relation. ‘‘The table,” “the chair,” “the book,” cannot in themselves unite into a group; by their nature they are capable of playing the part of terms and nothing else; and only when they are related or qualified in some way do they be- come elements in a fact. (Indeed, an individual referred to as “‘a table,” “a chair,”’ or “‘a book,”’ is already an x qualified by a predicate, and has already become an element in a fact.) “The table with the book on it and the chair beside it” is a fact; but “the table the chair the book” is no fact. Words and phrases that signify individuals do not, by themselves, go together to form significant expressions, and here again language reflects the structure of objects. Without predicates, relations, or operations to bring them into groups, individuals (if they are thought of) continue in iso- 82 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH lation, cut off by their individuality from other objects. Such isolated individuals are never known concretely; it is only by the most violent act of abstraction that we can conceive of them. The search for a relation between a universal and the individ- ual which is an instance of it results, therefore, in the discovery that “being an instance of”’ is not a relation. The unity of a uni- versal with individuals is a wholeness within which relations are distinguished; a relation is a species of group-unity; but this unity is not itself related to its terms, and the statement that it is “in” or “of” or “with” its terms serves only to point to it as an indefinable. The minimal object of knowledge is a universal in its instance; the universal, the individual, and their unity are given at once. IX The distinction between terms and elements of unity is not the same, however, as that between individuals and universals; for the terms as well as the element of unity in a fact may be uni- versals, as in “truth is beauty,” “dishonor is worse than death,” ‘the course of true love never did run smooth.” A fact whose terms are universal is not the same kind of fact as one whose terms are individual. The latter is concrete; the former, abstract; but both are nevertheless facts. An abstract fact is an aspect of a concrete fact; or rather, it is an aspect of many such facts. But in perception, facts come to us as individ- ualized, and not as abstract. The ability of universals to fulfill a double function in groups — both as terms and elements of unity — divests them of the separateness which belongs by nature to individuals. In an ab- stract fact such as ‘‘dishonor is worse than death,”’ a universal which might qualify or relate in some instance is referred to apart from its qualifying or relating function, and it becomes a term in a new fact; but the universal remains a universal be- UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS 83 cause it can appear as a qualifying or relating element, rather than as something qualified or related. Thus when I say “‘this paper is white,” I refer by the word “white” to the same object as that to which I refer by “whiteness” when I say “whiteness is the symbol of purity.” The difference is not in the identity of the object meant, but in its function. In the one case it is a term in an abstract fact; in the other, an element of unity ina concrete fact. We tend to speak of facts whose terms are individuals as “particular,” but the word “particular”? is misleading. Every object or fact is in a sense particular, for it has an identity of its own; it is a ““somewhat”’ distinct from other objects, and it can be referred to as “this” object, “this” quality or relation, “this” fact. Particularity in the sense of identity is found everywhere; not only in individuals, but in universals and in facts whose terms are universal. “Dishonor is worse than death” is a particular case of the relation “worse than,” and everything is a particular case of the logical character of “ob- jectivity.”’ If one means by the particularity of an object or fact simply its identity, he ought to speak of particulars of higher and lower orders, for the world is composed of identities of higher and lower orders. A fact that contains as a term some ob- ject that enters as an element of unity in another fact is of a higher order of particularity than this second fact. “Dishonor is worse than death” is not of the same order of particularity as “Judas was dishonorable”’; the latter is the kind of fact from which the former is abstracted. The quality which appears as a qualifying element in the latter is itself a subject of description in the former; ‘‘dishonor”’ is taken now as a substantive instead of as an adjective. In this manner, facts are overlaid, the one on the other, the less particular on the more particular, the terms of those of higher orders of abstraction being separated out from those of 84 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH lower orders of abstraction, till we reach the facts whose terms are the most abstract of all — the facts of logical structure. But any fact at any stage is particular in some sense. The relation between these different orders is like the Aristo- telian relation of matter to form. The lower orders of particulars are the matter of the higher orders; a fact which is particular in relation to one fact is general in relation to another; and the lowest members in the scale are those whose terms are finally and irreducibly particular. That is, they are facts whose terms are capable of being terms and nothing else — whose terms are individuals. These terms are like Aristotle’s prime matter; they are cases of universals, they have form in the Aristotelian sense, but there is nothing in relation to which they are form. Nothing is an instance of them. They are that upon which universals rest, but which themselves rest on nothing. Though the individual which is an instance of a universal is one with the universal in the instance, the process of abstraction — of separating the two for thought — has begun when the uni- versal is distinguished in its instance. To abstract is to disregard an aspect of a presented object; and since all presented objects are of double aspect, both universal and individual, we can dis- regard the latter and refer only to the former. Not only can we. abstract from the individuality of an object; we can also ab- stract from any of its more specific qualities or relations. Thus a green object is a colored object; when I am presented with the relation before, I am also presented with an asymmetrical rela- tion; and I can refer to the color apart from the greenness, or to the asymmetry apart from the beforeness. The very presentation of objects — for they are only presented when they are known both as universal and individual — is the beginning of abstrac- tion. The abstraction which begins in distinguishing a universal in a perceived instance is completed in the realm of conception; ~~ UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS 85 the instruments of conception (symbols) are also the instru- ments of complete abstraction. In perception the sense of the oneness of the object — as an individual in which many univer- sals join — cannot be shut out; but through symbols any of these universals, or for that matter, the individual, can be re- ferred to alone. We can abstract the individual, as an indeter- minate x, from the universal, or the universal from the individ- ual. The abstracted universal is not referred to as it occurs in any special one or in all of its instances; it is meant apart from instances, as an object with an identity of its own. Needless to say, the symbol which carries an abstract refer- ence is not itself abstract; it is a presented object with its own individuality and general nature. And yet the once heated con- troversy over “abstract ideas” turned on a confusion between the abstractness of the symbol and the abstractness of its refer- ence. It is indeed absurd to hold, as Berkeley accuses Locke of holding, that ideas as images (as psychical events) are ab- stract; they are obviously as concrete as any other presented objects. But there is no absurdity in their having an abstract meaning. The problem of abstraction, so far as it touches uni- versals, comes in the end to this: Can we refer to universals as single, self-identical objects distinct from individuals? And this is the problem of the objectivity of universals. X There is no reason to suppose that a universal is any the less an object than the subject it qualifies or the terms it relates. If I say that “the afternoon is warm,” or that “Chicago is between New York and San Francisco,” the warmth is as objective as the afternoon, and the relation between as genuine a constituent of the fact as Chicago, New York, or San Francisco. Unless the concept of an object is taken in a much narrower sense than we have given it, universals cannot be distinguished from individ- 86 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH ual subjects and terms on the ground that the latter are objects while the former are not. Both are in knowledge; both are given as constituents of facts, though neither is given alone. When it is said that universals are not objective, what is meant is that they are not in reality the same kind of object as their terms when these are individuals; universals do not belong in the same metaphysical category as individuals. The nominal- ist views the world as being really a collection of individuals; what are called universals are to him ideas, mental addenda, created by an act of comparing individuals. He believes that white objects exist, but that whiteness does not exist — at least that whiteness exists only in a mind. It is a name for a number of things which are closely alike, that is, for an artificial con- struction, “‘the class of white objects.” In answer to the nominalist, it must first be observed that the question as to whether a universal exists in a mind or in reality (assuming that reality and “‘a mind” are different), is a meta- physical and not an epistemological question. Universals are known in some manner, whether it be as elements in an external or an internal world. They appear in the simplest units of cogni- tion; and whether or not they are contributed by the perceiving subject, they are objects of knowledge in the broadest sense of the term. For the purposes of the positive theory of knowledge, this is enough. We need not ask if reality is a concourse of indi- viduals, or if it is a network of universals without individuals, or if it is a fusion of both. There are, however, many considerations that cast doubt on a metaphysics which affirms that individuals are real and that universals are unreal. First among these is the indeterminate- ness of our knowledge of the individual. If the x which is quali- fied or related by universals is the sole known reality, knowl- edge touches reality only at the tiniest point — only through the fleeting “this” of perception, which can be described in no UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS 87 way. Secondly, it appears beyond question that when one per- ceives a colored object he is presented with the color as well as the colored object. Color is given in the field of vision, and the fact that it might be found elsewhere is no evidence that it is not here. The nominalist will doubtless reply to this by asking how one can perceive an abstraction. The answer is that the color of an object is no more an abstraction than its individuality; the “what”? of an object is no less of the object than its “this.” The very act of perception is the beginning of abstraction; for a pre- sented object is both broken in two for thought (that is, ab- stract) and knit into a unity for perception (that is, concrete). Thirdly, to say as the nominalist does that an object belongs to a class is to notice its similarity to another object, and al- though the discovery of the qualities or the relations of the ob- ject comes through comparison, the result of the comparison is the perception of the universal in the object, that is, as an ele- ment of the whole. And if objects are similar, this similarity is a universal; the likeness of objects, no matter how remote, rests therefore on a universal. In order that the nominalist may main- tain his point that classification is artificial, he must either be- lieve that it is wholly a matter of caprice (and then it is not classification), or that there is some basis for it; and unless he wishes to negate his own view, he must show in the latter case that classification rests on something other than universals. This he does not show. It can be further urged, in favor of the equal right to reality of the universal, that objects which are known as bare identities, as mere “‘thises” and “thats,” still have the property of being objects. The very entrance of a thing on the stage of thought im- plies that it has a minimum of characters and relations — that it is identical with itself and diverse from other things. The con- cept of the individual itself gives rise to a universal — individu- 88 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH ality. Therefore, if universals are unreal, it ought to be added that all objects of thought, including individuals, are unreal; and the distinction between the reality of universals and in- dividuals falls to the ground. The nominalist will then ask, granting that one is presented with whiteness, hardness, and other sensory qualities, is one also presented with relations and operations? These seem to be much less “presentable” than qualities. But if the whole con- tent of the perception were a, b, c, when a is perceived to be be- tween b and c, this mere plurality would not be a perceived fact. Some sort of unity pervades and characterizes the whole; in this case, the relation “‘between.” But perhaps it is less difficult to understand how one can perceive a specific relation than how he can perceive this general unity. Is there a perception of the unity of objects? The only answer to this is that every percep- tion is one of the unity of objects; without a presentation of unity, which is not unlike Kant’s “unity of the manifold,”’ there is no presentation of objects. One is no more aware of objects as dis-unified than he is of a white object without its whiteness. The two cases are exactly parallel. They are cases of the appre- hension of the universal in its union with the individual. As for operations, such as (2 + 2) — they also are kinds of group-unity. If two objects are before me, ““twoness”’ is before me; and when I perceive four objects as a group of “two and two,” I am presented with something which approximates to a case of the operation plus. It is quite as accurate to describe the growth of knowledge by pointing out that the individual is abstracted from the univer- sal, as it is to describe it as an abstraction of the universal from the individual. Knowledge of the individual is not prior to knowledge of the universal; to discover the individual requires an effort of thought. And if universals are “‘ideal,”’ if they enter knowledge only through the working of the mind in sifting ex- UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS 89 perience, the same is true of individuals. As a matter of fact, neither of these descriptions is true. The “this” and the “‘ what”’ blend in the pure awareness which underlies and completes clear cognition; they emerge as distinct in the perception of objects, but the one does not thereby become less objective than the other. To hold, with M. Bergson and Mr. Bradley, that neither qual- ities or relations, or the individual things qualified or related, are real — that all are “‘ideal’’ — is to gain at least the merit of consistency. Nothing short of this will do if one sets out to at- tack the reality of universals. But it is not necessary to prove that universals or individuals, or both, are real in order to vindi- cate their objectivity. If either, or both, are appearances, they are still objects; for an appearance is an object. General propositions, laws, and principles which ignore the individual have a meaning that is as much a part of the world of fact as the meaning of propositions whose terms are bare particulars. Abstraction is possible because universals are self- identical objects which can be singled out and referred to through symbols. XI The analysis of facts into terms and unifying universals is the basis of a general “grammar” of symbolism. Substantive sym- bols (symbols of terms) cannot be taken together to form signif- icant wholes; they must be grouped with adjectival symbols — with symbols of unity. Nor can adjectival symbols alone make up significant expressions; some of the symbols of a group must signify terms, whether these be universal or individual terms. An expression without a symbol of unity, or without terms, would violate a fundamental principle of the structure of fact, and could not possibly have a meaning among facts. This grammar of symbolism is the source of all special gram- mars. Every language, if it contains no other distinctions of 90 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH function among its words, will differentiate substantives from adjectives — “‘adjective”’ being taken to include all modifying or connecting words, that is, adverbs, verbs, conjunctions, etc., as well as adjectives proper. Substantives or adjectives alone will not, in any language, enter into significant unions with one an- other. Thus “‘chair table book,” “large brown on,” are intrinsi- cally without meaning, for they do not conform to the first prin- ciple of symbolic grammar. On the other hand, “book on table” or “large brown chair” are significant phrases (whether or not they stand for objects) because they are properly constructed. Language recognizes not only the distinction between terms and elements of unity, substantives and adjectives, but it recognizes also that the same object, if it is a universal, can play the part of both. A root-word assumes a different form when it enters as a term from the form it assumes as an element of unity. This is the difference between the words “‘nearness” and “‘near,”’ “beauty” and “beautiful,” “run” and “‘running.” These dis- tinct forms of words signify the same object, but they represent this object in different structural relations to other objects, that is, in its adjectival and its substantive functions. The signs of addition, multiplication, subtraction, and divi- sion are the “adjectives” — the symbols of unity — in arith- metic and algebra; the signs for numbers cannot by themselves constitute significant arithmetical or algebraic expressions. They must be joined by operational symbols, for an arithmetical or algebraic fact is made up of numbers operated on in some way. And a similar “‘grammar” is present in symbolic logic. (p-q) or (p vq) is a group in which the dot, in the one case, or the sign (v), in the other, stands for the unifying element, while the let- ters stand for the terms — for propositions united by the rela- tion “‘and” or “‘or.”’ There are many special rules for the construction of signifi- cant symbolic groups, but the general rule — that symbols for UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS 91 terms must be grouped with symbols of unity and that symbols for terms or symbols of unity alone cannot have meaning, if they are grouped — lies beneath all systems of symbols. Any possible symbolic group in any possible system must follow this principle, since any possible fact will be a unity of terms and qualifying or relating universals; the most general rule of sym- bolic syntax rests on a “‘syntax”’ of fact — on the most general way in which objects fit together to form wholes. XII Each symbolic system will have its own special plan of syn- tax; and this plan, if it assumes no very large proportions, can be set forth merely by enumerating the significant groups per- mitted in the system. There may be no special rules for con- structing the groups, though none of the groups can violate the general principle which has just been stated. More extended and useful systems, such as language and arithmetic, are built on syntactical plans which can be embodied in rules. These rules state how the symbols can be taken together as significant wholes and how groups can be derived from one another. Once the syntactical plan of a system is given as a set of rules, expressions of many different forms can be constructed within it, and none of these expressions will be without syntactical meaning so long as it conforms to the plan. The significance of the groups will be a function of the meanings of their elements and of their form; it is necessary only that the elementary sym- bols of the system should stand for existing objects; the groups may or may not represent existing objects. Some systems, notably languages, contain an endless number of groups which fulfill the conditions of syntactical significance but stand for no objects. These systems are non-deductive (or incompletely inferential). If we follow their syntactical rules, we are as apt to be led away from fact (and truth) as to be led to 92 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH fact (and truth). In these systems, there is a discrepancy be- tween significance and truth. But in a deductive system which is completely interpreted there is no such discrepancy. Any group that can be properly derived from the original groups by the rules of syntax will stand for an object, that is, it will be true as well as significant. The conditions of significance and of truth are the same in a completely interpreted deductive system, and the rules of syntax are the rules of deduction.+ But in any case, the syntactical plan of a symbolic system de- termines its range of significance. It determines not what ob- jects actually are represented in the system, but how the sym- bols can be used significantly regardless of whether they stand for objects. It determines an area of concepts. This gives us a criterion of possibility for knowledge. A “pos- sibility for knowledge” in the widest sense need not be a refer- ence to an object; it is any meaning that is conceivable. And any group of symbols — of words, mathematical signs, or ideas — which follows the rules of syntax in a system has a conceivable meaning; the group is a possible concept. Possibility for knowl- edge belongs only to concepts, and if one says that a non-exist- ent object is a possible object of knowledge, this is only a man- ner of speaking. He does not mean that there is any such object to have the predicate “possible”’; he means merely that a signif- icant concept which refers to no object can be framed. “The immortality of the soul’ is conceivable and therefore a possi- bility for knowledge; but the possibility resides not in an actual fact for which this expression stands, but in the fact that the ex- pression has meaning. Aside from this “possibility as an object of knowledge,”’ the test of which is conceivability, there may or may not be an absolute metaphysical possibility, such as that of Leibniz’s infinity of possible worlds. But with this we are not concerned. 1 This is an anticipation of what is more fully set forth in ch. VII. UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS 93 The rules of syntax in a symbolic system therefore mark the limits of possibility for that system. (And in completely inter- preted deductive systems, every possible concept is also true.) But what is conceivable in one system may have no counterpart in another. The general rule of symbolic syntax — that symbols of terms alone or symbols of unity alone cannot form significant wholes — tells us how fact in general must be conceived; it marks the most general limits of possible concepts. XIl The two symbolic systems whose application to fact is at once most sweeping and most familiar are the systems of the imagi- nation (of mental images) and of language. The habits of correct and ordered speech become the habits of correct and ordered thought, so that if a thing can be thought clearly it can be said clearly. We grow unconsciously to accept certain combinations of words as significant, and to reject others as nonsensical because they do not conform to the rules of syn- tax. And yet the possibilities of significant combinations in lan- guage are so wide that almost any chance grouping of words has syntactical meaning. If words are thrown together at random it is more than likely that a significant phrase will be achieved, for no phrase that follows the rules of syntax in language is without meaning. When expressions such as “the round square,” ‘the moon is made of green cheese,” “Socrates is a triangle,” etc., are rejected as meaningless, they are not strictly speaking rejected as non- sense, unless we have passed over the thin line that separates nonsense from falsity and contradiction — that divides the meaningless from the fantastic. It is true that there are no ob- jects which correspond to these expressions, yet the expressions are not totally without meaning. The very fact that we say “a round square is a geometrical contradiction,” that ‘Socrates is 94 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH a triangle” or “the moon is made of green cheese” are fantastic notions, shows that we grasp these expressions as concepts; otherwise we could attribute neither contradiction nor absurd- ity to them. A nonsensical expression, an utterly meaningless collection of symbols, could be neither false, fantastic, or con- tradictory. And yet nonsense cannot be without a semblance of sense. There must be vestiges of significance in the symbols, or else they would not be symbols but mere collections of presented ob- jects. In the pseudo-phrases, “large brown on ” and “chair table book,” for example, the elements are significant but the wholes are without meaning. They present the semblance of wholes but they conform to no rules of syntax. In direct contrast to this type of nonsense stand pseudo-phrases that have a seeming in- telligibility as wholes since they follow syntactical rules, but that are meaningless through the presence of meaningless ele- ments. The lines from Lewis Carroll’s Jabberwocky, a classic of nonsense, exhibit just the proper distribution of significant ele- ments along with meaningless elements to give the whole a structure: “O frabjous day! Callooh! Callay! He chortled in his joy.” So powerful is the sense of significance as a whole that the parts tend to derive meaning through their places in the whole. The interpretation of words — or any symbols other than images — usually takes the route of the imagination, and for this reason it has been maintained that what cannot be imag- ined cannot be thought, that conceivability in images is the only conceivability. The syntax of the imagination is extremely simple. Any images that can be held together before the mind form a signifi- cant group. The distinction between terms and elements of unity is not made explicit, though one never imagines an object composed of parts which are unrelated or unqualified. There are no signs of grouping other than the mere juxtaposition of UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS 95 images, and no juxtapositions of images are excluded as mean- ingless, though many are fantastic and absurd. Yet some images refuse to go together before the mind; there are no counterparts 99 66 in the imagination for “a round square,” “a curved straight line,” etc.; the images corresponding to these words exclude one another’s presence. It is difficult to give any reason for this ex- clusion; but this fact shows that the syntax of the imagination has its limits, and that there are possible concepts in other sys- tems which cannot be translated into the imagination. What is fantastic or absurd, or even contradictory, is not then utterly nonsensical. No properly constructed symbolic expres- sion is void of meaning. The general grammar of symbolism marks out the most general limits of possibility for thought, fol- lowing the most general lines of the structure of objects, while special plans in special systems mark out narrower limits of con- ceptual possibility. What is an impossibility for thought in one set of symbols may not be an impossibility in another set. It is not strange, therefore, that we can “imagine” much less than we can mean. XIV One class of syntactical rules must be especially noticed, that is, the rules of order. The sentence, “Brutus killed Caesar,”’ has a different significance from, “‘Caesar killed Brutus,” and the pseudo-group, “killed Brutus Caesar,”’ has no significance. The spatial or temporal arrangement of the symbols enters here as a factor in the meaning; the order in the symbols mirrors an order in the fact signified. Must we then include the spatial or tem- poral arrangement of symbols as a feature of their logical form? It is less difficult to illustrate than to describe what is meant by the order of a group. Facts of identical constituents may be wholly different in order, they may be of opposite orders. The fact ‘A precedes B” is different and opposite in order to the fact ““B precedes A”’; the facts “A between B and C,” “B 96 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH between A and C,” and ‘‘C between A and B” are distinguished by their orders. Most active verbs and prepositions, if they enter in groups, give us phrases or sentences representing ordered facts. “Hamlet killed Polonius” does not mean the same thing as “‘Polonius killed Hamlet”’; ‘grace before meat”’ is something other than ‘“‘meat before grace.”’ The simplest manner of describing order is to say that all re- lations have a direction, and that a fact whose elements are re- lated in one direction is different (for some relations) from a fact of the same elements related by the same relation in another direction. And the usual manner of representing order in lan- guage and mathematics bears out this description. The symbols of speech and writing themselves have a direction in space and time, and it is through this that the order in the fact is signified. This manner of representing order is a convenient device of sym- bolism, but it does not analyze order; if the order in the fact is not spatial or temporal, it merely represents one kind of order by another. Order is something common to groups which have a direction in space and time and to other groups which are non-spatial and non-temporal, and can only metaphorically be said to have a “direction.” “‘Hamlet believed the ghost” is an ordered fact, but “believing” is not a temporal or spatial relation, though the order it gives to the fact is reflected by the spatial order of the symbols. What is the common structural feature that makes this reflection possible? An asymmetrical (or ordering) relation not only unites its terms, but in uniting them, distinguishes them; it lends to each a distinctive mark, so that the whole is not of the simple form, (Rab), but of the form, (R(Sa)( Qb)). The whole is a group of groups, and the order is the manner in which the terms are dis- tributed in the sub-groups. Thus (R(Sa) (Qb)) and (R(Sb) (Qa)) represent different orders of the same elements. There are as UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS 97 many possible orders as there are possible distributions — in this case, only two. Consider, for example, any fact in which the constitutive re- lation is a transitive verb, ¢.g., ““A knows B.” The relation re- lates the terms, but at the same time distinguishes one as “‘ac- tive” and the other as “passive’’; and the fact is more fully stated as, “A, active, knows B, passive.”’ This is plainly of the form, (R(Sa) (Qb)), where R is the relation “knowing,” and S and Q, respectively, the qualities “activity” and “passivity.” The relation both relates and “qualifies” its terms; though this must not be construed to mean that the relation is reducible to qualities of its terms. It is always a relation; but each term, through being in the relation, assumes a special character — a character that attaches to it only when it is in the relation. Lan- guage generalizes this distinction of quality which an ordering relation imparts to its terms into the distinction of “‘subject”’ and “‘object.”’ Thus in “‘a before b” or “a in b,” a is the subject and b the object; and in apprehending the fact as ordered, we grasp this distinction of relational quality in the terms. It is ap- prehended as of the form, (before (a, subject) (b, object) ); and this is different from the form, (before (b, subject) (a, object)).! The reason why there is a “direction” from one term to an- other in an ordered fact is, therefore, that these terms are mem- bers of distinct groups; the terms are distinct not merely as terms, but through their places in the whole. If they take differ- ent places, though the constituents of the fact remain the same, the fact will be different. Direction in space or time is a special case of this general structural feature of groups. This description of order applies, moreover, not only to complexes of two terms, 1 It follows from this description of order that a fact such as “A walks and B runs” has order; for the terms are united by a relation, and at the same time distinguished by predicates. The difference between this fact and ‘‘a before b” is not that the former is without order, but that the distinguishing predicates of the terms are independent of the relating relation; they are not relational qualities. 98 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH but to polyadic complexes of any number of terms, in which there is no single direction or “‘sense”’ but a number of interre- lated directions. The relation ‘“‘trusteeship,” for example, dis- tinguishes the ‘“trustor” from the “‘trustee,”’ both from the thing intrusted, and all three from the “beneficiary”’ of the trust.) This tetradic relation gives an order to its terms by mak- ing each a member of a distinctive group; it is of the form, (R (Sa) (Qb) (Lc) (Md)). But not every term in a polyadic com- plex need be distinguished by an order, from the other terms: each between b and c,” makes no distinction of order between 6 and c, though it distinguishes a from both. There are in this complex two objects and one subject; and obviously the objects are not distinct from one another through the relation. Its form can be represented as, (Ra(Sb) (Sc)), which has only three possible variations of order, viz., (Rb(Sa) (Sc)), (Re(Sa) (Sb)), and (Ra (Sb) (Se)). When order is seen to be a matter of grouping alone, it can be represented by symbols whose spatial order is irrelevant to the meaning — whose group relations alone are significant. (Ra(Sb) (Se)), which might mean “a between b and c,” can be written ((Sb)Ra(Sc)), or ((Se) (Sb)Ra), or ((Sb) (Sc)Ra), etc.; and all of these different spatial arrangements will signify the same order of the fact. Language finds in the passive form of expres- sion that order can be indicated by grouping alone. “ Polonius was killed by Hamlet” is equivalent to “Hamlet killed Polo- nius’’; and here the group of the agent (or subject) ? is distin- 1 The other distinctions of case in language, which are additional to the nominative and accusative (subject and object), are generalized forms of these distinctions of order in polyadic complexes. 2 Expressions in the passive form show us, further, that the distinction be- tween subject and object as the active and passive terms, respectively, of a re- lation (or as the referent and relatum) does not always correspond to the dis- tinction between the grammatical subject and predicate of the sentence. Only in the active form is the subject of the relation — or relational subject — also the grammatical subject; e.g., in “Hamlet killed Polonius,” ‘‘ Hamlet” is both the relational and grammatical subject, while in “‘Polonius was killed by Hamlet,” “Polonius” is the relational object but the grammatical subject. UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS 99 guished by the preposition “by.” The expression has the form, (Polonius killed (by Hamlet)), that is, (Ra(Sb)), where R is the relation “killing” and S the preposition “‘ by’ — the mark of the agent. (Rb(Sa)) would be the alternative order. It is clear that in the passive form the spatial order of the words does not affect the significance, so long as the integrity of the groups is pre- served. The sentence might read, “By Hamlet Polonius was killed,” or “Polonius was by Hamlet killed,” or ‘‘By Hamlet was Polonius killed,” or even “Killed was Polonius by Hamlet.’’ In any of these spatial arrangements, the meaning will be the same; and a different order can be signified only by interchanging the terms in the groups. It is therefore only accidental, and not essential — though it is a useful accident — that the spatial or temporal order of sym- bols should be significant. XV If an asymmetrical (or ordered) fact is one in which the terms are distinguished by being members of different subordinate groups within the whole, a symmetrical fact is one in which there is no such distinction of terms through their membership in subordinate groups. Consider “A with B.” The relation “with” imparts no distinctive qualities to its terms; each term is with the other and nothing more. The fact has the form (Rab) and could be symbolized by this group where the spatial and temporal orders of FR, a, and 6 are irrelevant to the meaning. There are no subordinate groups here in which the terms could be differently distributed. We are in the habit, however, of representing symmetrical facts as if they had an order. Since the spatial order of words and mathematical signs is usually significant, we assume that ‘‘ A with B”’ means something other than “B with A” until the contrary is asserted. For this reason, the symmetry of such ex- pressions as “‘ A with B” or “a X b” is commonly described by 100 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH saying that alternative orders of the symbols have the same meaning, that is, that ““A with B”’ is equivalent to ‘‘B with A,” that “a X 6” is equivalent to “b X a.” But this is necessary only because the fact, which is without order, is represented by symbols with an order. If the fact were originally represented by a group such as (Rab), in which the order of the symbols is irrelevant, its symmetry would be apparent. Therefore, the commutative law in algebra and logic — that (aRb) = (bRa)— says nothing more than that the spatial order of the symbols is irrelevant to their meaning. The distinction between subject and object (and between agent and patient) is also carried over to expressions which stand for symmetrical facts; they are represented as if such a distinction were present in them. Thus “‘a is accompanied by b” states a symmetrical fact in asymmetrical form; but it is the same fact as “‘b is accompanied by a,” and to recognize this is to see that no distinction of subject and object (of agent and pa- tient) exists in the fact. The order, which is in this case a certain grouping of the symbols (rather than a spatial order), belongs only to the symbols; the fact is without order. Mr. Bertrand Russell describes all relations as having “sense” or direction; no relation, he says, is without a referent and a re- latum.1 This is certainly true for asymmetrical relations; the re- ferent and relatum are what language recognizes as the subject and object. But the assumption that all relations — symmetri- cal and asymmetrical — differentiate their terms as referent and relatum has no foundation in the data of perception. It rests only on the custom of representing all relational complexes by sym- bols with an order; and it obscures the true nature of symmetri- cal relations, for it makes them a special case of asymmetrical ones. The mere fact that a and b are related does not distin- 1 See B. Russell, The Principles of Mathematics (1903), ch. 9; also, A. N. Whitehead and B. Russell, Principia Mathematica (1910), i, 34. UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS 101 guish 6 from a in any way. Why we should say that a is the rela- tum any more than 6, or b the referent any more than a, is impos- sible to see. A relation is a kind of unity of two terms (or more), and only some relations distinguish, as well as relate, their terms. If it is assumed that all relations have *“sense,”’ it is of course impossible to define a symmetrical relation in any other way than as one which is identical in both of its senses; and this amounts to saying that the distinction of sense (for this sort of relation) is merely symbolic. The more direct way is to represent the fact in the first place by symbols in which there is no distinc- tion of sense, for this makes it clear that symmetrical relations are of a different genus from asymmetrical ones. XVI The representation of order in a fact through the spatial and temporal order of symbols is open to an ambiguity which is not present when the order is reproduced by the grouping of the symbols. ‘There is no mistaking the meaning of “A is preceded by B” or of “Romeo was loved by Juliet.” One knows that the first of these expressions means the order in which B is the re- ferent and A, the relatum; and that the second means the order in which Juliet is the agent and Romeo is the patient. But the expressions, “‘B precedes A” and “Juliet loved Romeo,” lack this explicitness of meaning; and if we could express the order of the fact in no other way than the latter, we should not know which of the alternative orders was meant. The symbols permit two possible spatial arrangements — (aRb) and (bRa) — and the fact, two possible orders; but the question remains, which represents which? The meaning of these groups must therefore be further defined. It is understood that “‘B precedes A” has the same meaning as “A is preceded by B;” that “Juliet loved Romeo” has the same meaning as “Romeo was loved by Juliet.” Thus a unique 102 “SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH correlation is established, so that one spatial order of the sym- bols means one order of the fact, while the other means the al- ternative order. Without this further definition of the meaning, we should know that “Juliet loved Romeo” stands for a fact composed of Juliet, loved, and Romeo, taken in one of two possi- ble orders — taken in the order opposite to that of the fact meant by “‘Romeo loved Juliet.’’ But neither order of the sym- bols could be attached uniquely to either order of the fact. A complete and unambiguous interpretation of the meaning of symbolic expressions requires that the spatial and temporal order of symbols be supplemented, as a means of representing order, by the more accurate and general kind of representation through grouping. (This appears in language as the syntactical rule that the relational subject of a phrase or sentence precedes the relational object, excepting where the subject and object are represented by case endings, or where the sentence is in the passive form.) Order then is not an independent factor of logical form which refuses to be assimilated to group structure. The distribution of terms in distinct major or minor groups which make up a whole is their order. A symmetrical relation is one that groups its terms without distinguishing any of them through their mem- bership in sub-groups; and an asymmetrical relation is one that groups its terms so that some of them are distinct not only as terms, but through their membership in sub-groups. The form, (Rabed), is a symmetrical form (the spatial order of the letters being irrelevant), and can be written indifferently, (abcRd) or (aRbcd), etc. Similarly, the form, ((Sa)R(Sb)) is a symmetrical form, and can be written indifferently ((Sb) (Sa)R), ((Sa) (Sb) R), etc. On the other hand, (R(Sa) (Qb)) is an asymmetrical form, and permits the alternative order, (R(Sb) (Qa)), though it can be written indifferently ((Sa)R(Qb)) or ((Sa) (Qb)R), ete., in the one order, and ((Sb)R(Qa)) or ((Sb) (Qa)R), ete., in the a UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS 103 other order. Only the simpler types of symmetry and asym- metry have been illustrated, that is, those which arise through dyadic and triadic relations; but the same principles for dis- tinctions of order hold in facts of any degree of complexity. XVII The distinction between the terms and elements of unity in groups raises the question as to whether a symbolic group may contain more than one symbol of unity and a fact more than one unifying element. Is every unifying element the center of a single group? In cases where simplicity of statement is desired, each group is viewed as if it were constituted by a single relation, operation, or quality. This group may enter as a term in other groups, or may contain terms which are themselves groups, but each group — whatever its part in the whole may be — will be constituted by one and only one unifying universal. In the arithmetical expression (2+ 3) X ((4+ 5) — 6), for example, there are several different groups, each with a single element of unity. The groups are piled upon one another, and none contains more than a single operation. But it is not necessary that only a single element of unity should appear in a group. A number of qualities, relations, or operations may act to- gether as unifying universals in the same group. Language affords many examples of expressions of this nature. If I say, “he is poor but proud,” I attribute to the subject, not a single quality, but a complex of qualities — “poor but proud.” In the fact, “Boston is near to and north of New York,” the terms are joined, not by a single relation, but by two relations. The elements of unity in these facts are complex. They are themselves groups of universals united by universals; they are elements of unity which themselves contain secondary elements of unity. “Poor but proud” has the réle of a single quality and 104 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH “near to and north of” the réle of a single relation. The facts in which they enter are of the forms, (Q@Ra) and (VMbc), where ® and VY represent the secondary elements of unity. Adverbs and adverbial expressions always modify elements of unity — quali- ties, relations, connectives — and give rise to complex elements of unity. When the forms of symbolic expressions and facts are described, the complexity of the elements of unity cannot be neglected if the description is to be complete; for this is a gen- uine aspect of their form. However, for purposes of simplifica- tion, a complex element of unity can be treated as a single uni- versal; and if this assumption is made, the form (Q®@Ra) is the same as (Na), and the form (7 VMbc) the same as (Kbc). But it must not be forgotten that this is an artificial simplification of the structure, and that a full description of the form would not overlook the complexity of the element of unity. XVIII The present chapter, beginning with the distinction between universals and individuals, has examined the function of univer- sals as elements of unity in facts, and has shown how this func- tion is mirrored by symbols which perform a corresponding function in symbolic groups. The individual and the universal are present in all concrete wholes of knowledge, for there is no presented object which is not at once a unique “this” and a “this” with some characters and relations. For finite knowledge, these characters and rela- 1 The multiplicity of a group, it has been said, is determined by the number of its constituents, that is, the number of its terms plus one; for the element of unity (which, if it is complex, is treated as a single entity) is a constituent though not a term in the group. But in classifying relations as monadic, dyadic, triadic, etc., account is taken only of the number of terms they unite, and thus, according to our definition of multiplicity, a dyadic relation would cou- stitute a triadic group, etc. This is merely a matter of terminology; the multi- plicity of a group could be defined by the number of its major terms rather than its major constituents, so that a triadic relation would constitute a triadic group, etc. UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS 105 tions do not determine the individual; and in this respect spatial and temporal relations are no exception, for the concepts of space and time are built on the perception of the numerical identity and diversity of individuals, and individuals are lo- cated in space and time only by reference to other individuals. Though it is possible to assume, with Leibniz, that an infinity of universals would determine an individual, this assumption is of no aid to finite knowledge. The distinction between the “what” and the “this” continues in its original form. The individual, however, is brought into conception through the use of a varia- ble symbol, to which no value is assigned; but this is the only way in which the individual as such can be thought. Knowledge, in referring to the individual through a symbol of indeterminate meaning, presupposes its own indeterminateness. The universal, on the other hand, is presented as an identity in diverse individuals — in changing and different instances. A changeless universal persists in the background of every change. Therefore the universal can be represented by symbols cf fixed meaning, and knowledge in universal terms, that is, law, is freed from the variability which infects all knowledge of the individual. Universals fill a unique réle in groups. They are elements of unity and themselves members of the group, but not members codrdinate with the others, which are terms. A relation, a quality, or an operation is not related to its terms; it is one with them, and at the same time distinguishable from them. The unity of a group is its “‘ what,” different universals are different kinds of group-unity, and there is no group which is not such a unity; the concept of group-unity is an indefinable but essential part of the concept of a group. Individuals play the part only of terms; without universals they do not enter into wholes; no fact is constituted solely by individuals. But the terms of a fact, as well as its element of 106 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH unity may be universal, in which case the fact will be abstract. Abstract facts are aspects of concrete facts, that is, of facts whose terms are individual; they are separated out from the individ- ualized data of perception. This separation begins in the per- ception of a universal in its instance, and is completed in the realm of conception by the use of symbols which ignore the in- dividual and refer only to the universal apart from any or all in- stances. The problem of abstraction — whether universals can be thought apart from individual instances — is the problem of the objectivity of universals; for if universals are objects, they can be referred to through symbols as single and self-identical things. Nominalism, by attacking the reality of universals, does not disprove their objectivity; if universals are “appearances” or mentally constructed elements in knowledge, they are still ob- jects of knowledge, for such appearances (or mental constructs) are objects of knowledge. A general “grammar” of symbolism rests on the distinction between terms and elements of unity. Symbols of terms alone (substantives), or symbols of unity alone (adjectives), cannot constitute significant expressions; and this fact is recognized in all symbolic systems — in language, in mathematics, in logic. Possibility for knowledge is conceivability in a symbolic system; and any possible object of knowledge must be composed both of terms, which may be individual or universal, and of unifying universals. Special plans of syntax mark the limits of conceiva- bility, of possibility, for special systems, and what is possible in one system may have no counterpart in another. Thus no ex- pression that follows the rules of syntax in a system is nonsense, though its meaning may be fantastic or contradictory, and a possible concept may or may not refer to an actual object. Rules of order are a special class of rules of syntax. The spatial and temporal order of the symbols is significant in most sys- tems; it reflects an order in the fact. But order can be described UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS 107 and represented through group structure alone, since an order- ing relation (or operation) is one that both unites and distin- guishes its terms, this distinction arising through the member- ship of the terms in different sub-groups within the whole. Order must be represented through group structure if all am- biguity of interpretation is to be eliminated. Finally, the elements of unity in groups may themselves be complex; they may be groups composed of universals united by a secondary element of unity. The study of grouping, of the manner in which elements de- termine wholes, both in the fact and in the symbols, is necessary to the understanding of any expression. It is here that nuances of meaning are hidden. Sentences made up of many qualifying adverbs, adjectives, phrases, and clauses are susceptible of subtle shades of interpretation, or misinterpretation, according as they are taken in one or another of several possible groupings. The group structure, the form, is presented in the symbols and is immediately apprehended in its entirety, as is a musical phrase or a visual design. No description of the intellectual processes is better than Plato’s — “the contemplation of forms”’; for forms do not arise without universals, and they are themselves uni- versals, present in thought, through which the mind fastens on its objects. CHAPTER IV DESCRIPTION AND ANALYSIS I Tere are two ways of referring to objects —by single words or symbols and by descriptions. A description is a phrase such as “the bard of Avon,” “‘an enemy of the people,” “some member of Parliament,” “the divine right of kings.”’ The de- scription may be either ambiguously or unambiguously inter- preted, and it may refer either to an individual or a universal. In any case, it signifies an object through some of the predicates (relations or qualities) of the object, and it is a different form of reference from a single symbol, which might mean the same object. Mr. Bertrand Russell, who has thoroughly analyzed the na- ture of descriptions, believes that a description has meaning only in use; that it is an incomplete symbol which, apart from some proposition in which it occurs, is meaningless; ! while on the contrary he believes that single words and proper names are complete symbols; they have significance in their own right, either in or out of a context. Mr. Russell’s theory of descrip- tions rests on a conception of meaning wholly different from the one developed here. It can be shown that descriptions have syn- tactical meaning, whether or not there is an object for which 1 In the Principia Mathematica of Messrs. Whitehead and Russell, how- ever, the term “descriptive phrase” is used to cover only expressions pre- ceded by “‘the’’; it is merely these expressions which are said to be incomplete symbols, 7. e., to have meaning only in use. For the purposes of unifying and simplifying the present discussion, we shall speak of all phrases preceded by the particles “‘the,” “‘a,” “any,” “some,” “‘all,” “‘each,” and “every,” as descriptive phrases. But it must be remembered that what Mr. Russell says of descriptive phrases, in the Principia Mathematica at any rate, applies only to expressions preceded by “the.” DESCRIPTION AND ANALYSIS 109 they stand, and that their significance does not depend on their context. In The Principles of Mathematics, Mr. Russell deals with de- scriptions under the head of denoting phrases. ‘‘The notion of denoting,” he says, “like most notions of logic, has been ob- scured hitherto by an undue admixture of psychology. There is a sense in which we denote, when we point or describe, or employ words as symbols for concepts; this, however, is not the sense that I wish to discuss. But the fact that description is possible — that we are able, by the employment of concepts, to designate a thing which is not a concept — is due to a logical relation be- tween some concepts and some terms, in virtue of which such concepts inherently and logically denote such terms. It is this sense of denoting which is here in question. . . . A concept de- notes when, if it occurs in a proposition, the proposition is not about the concept, but about a term connected in a certain pe- culiar way with the concept. If I say ‘I met a man,’ the propo- sition is not about a man: this is a concept which does not walk the streets but lives in the shadowy limbo of the logic-books. What I met was a thing, not a concept, an actual man with a tailor and a bank account or a public-house and a drunken wife.” } Mr. Russell does not here explicitly take the position that the denoting or descriptive phrase has no meaning apart from a proposition in which it occurs; this is a later addition to his thought. But the problem he puts is the one that must first be faced in examining the nature of descriptions. The object meant by a description is a term and not a con- cept or mediating entity of any sort; it is a term referred to through universals which cluster about it. The concept means 1 B. Russell, The Principles of Mathematics, 1903, ch. 5. In a later state- ment on denoting, Mr. Russell abandons the idea of a relation by which con- cepts inherently and logically denote terms and states his theory of descrip- tions without this presupposition. See, Mind, N. S., 1905, xiv, 479 ff. 110 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH the term indirectly through predicates or relations of the term, and it does not mean simply these predicates or relations. “‘The friend of Caesar” does not mean a concept, nor does it mean “*friendship for Caesar”; “a man”’ does not mean ‘‘manhood”’ or “manliness”; “‘an enemy of the people” does not mean “‘enmity for the people.’’ Each of these phrases means that to which the predicates attach; the term is signified through uni- versals which modify it. lI Now universals always appear in instances; they either mod- ify individual terms directly, or modify universal terms which are themselves attached to individuals; and the “relation” in virtue of which some concepts inherently and logically denote some terms is that they refer to universals which are in unity with these terms, so that the terms are ‘‘an instance of” these universals. The unity of fact is such that any predicates which attach, let us say, to Shakespeare are genuine aspects of this in- dividual, whether or not they completely exhaust his individual- ity. “Bard of Avon” is therefore capable of denoting the term with which it has this unity; “‘man” is capable of denoting any individual of which ‘“‘manhood” is a predicate; every reference to a universal or complex of universals is capable, inherently and logically, of becoming a reference to terms. A descriptive phrase rests on the knowledge of a fact in which the object described appears as a term. An object known to have such and such predicates or relations can be described as “the” object or “an”’ object of these predicates and relations. The unity of terms with their predicates makes this possible. But the description is not tantamount to a statement of the fact in which the term appears: to say that “Shakespeare wrote Romeo and Jultet” is not to describe Shakespeare as “the author of Romeo and Juliet.” The description is based on a knowledge of the fact, DESCRIPTION AND ANALYSIS 111 and includes a reference to the fact, but it is something other than a statement of the fact. “Shakespeare wrote Romeo and Juliet” means that there is a certain relation between certain terms. “The author of Romeo and Juliet” means one of these terms — Shakespeare; though in meaning this person, it also means in some sense that this person wrote Romeo and Jultvet. There seems to be a reason, therefore, for distinguishing be- tween denoting or descriptive phrases and propositions — propo- sitions being references to complex wholes of terms, predicates, and relations, and denoting phrases being references to terms alone, though not without some accompanying subordinate reference to complex wholes in which the terms occur. In the traditional terminology of logic, a description denotes a term and connotes a proposition about this term; “the author of Romeo and Juliet” denotes Shakespeare and connotes Shakespeare’s writing of Romeo and Juliet. But this separation of connotation and denotation throws no light on the problem; it merely dis- tinguishes two sorts of meaning which, once they are admitted as distinct, cannot be brought together under any single concept of meaning. Mr. Russell undoubtedly has in mind some such distinction, > though he does not speak of “‘connoting,”’ when he says: “A concept denotes when, if it occurs in a proposition, the propo- sition is not about the concept, but about a term connected in a certain peculiar way with the concept.” Without doubt the proposition, “I met a man,” is not about the concept “a man” or about ““manhood.” It refers to a person, an individual. Nor is the proposition, “I have seen the portrait of the author of Romeo and Juliet,” a reference to some mediating entity, to some concept, or merely to the authorship of this play; it is about Shakespeare. And yet each of these propositions is about more than a bare term. It is about the term as it is qualified in a certain way, that is, as “‘an”’ instance or “the” instance of a 112 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH predicate. “I met a man” means more than “I met 2x”; it means “I met x and z is human.” “T have seen the portrait of the author of Romeo and Juliet’? means more than “I have seen Shakespeare’s portrait”; it means this, and “that Shake- speare wrote Romeo and Jultet.” If the proposition is not about a predicate taken in abstraction from a term, neither is it about a term taken in abstraction from a predicate. It means the predicate as it is particularized in a term. A descriptive phrase cannot, therefore, be distinguished from a proposition on the ground that a proposition means a complex whole while a descriptive phrase means only a single term. A descriptive phrase means, as any complex of symbols means, through the meanings of its elements, and it means a complex whole. It sets up a complex intention, which is a function of the simple intentions of its elements; and although it does not state the fact on which the description is based, it refers to this fact. It is misleading to say that a descriptive phrase denotes a term, and that this exhausts its meaning. The phrase means (and where connoting is not distinguished from denoting, it denotes) the predicates through which the term is described no less than the term; the term could not be signified through predicates un- less the predicates were also signified. III A descriptive phrase differs from the proposition on which it is based through its form. It is no less a reference to a complex object, to universals as they enter into unity with terms, than the proposition; but its form, unlike that of the proposition, is one in which a term — the term described — takes a central position, so that this term receives an emphasis it would not have in a different structure of the same elements. The term is viewed (is placed in a group) as a subject qualified by certain predicates — predicates which may be simple qualities such as DESCRIPTION AND ANALYSIS 113 “humanity” or a complex set of relations to other terms, such as “‘author of the greatest tragedies in English literature.” The group revolves about the term. At the same time, this term is symbolized by a variable, which in language is presupposed rather than explicitly presented in the symbolism. Thus a de- scription is a variable reference to a particular instance of a uni- versal or of a complex of universals and terms. A particular instance of a universal is a “this of some sort”’ or a “this in certain relations”’; it is an object of the form (xR), where R is the universal (or the complex predicate) and z is a term. The particles which precede descriptions inform us that the expression is to be construed as meaning an object of this general structure. ‘‘ The friend of Caesar” is to be interpreted as standing for z as qualified by friendship-for-Caesar; “the author of Waverley” to mean y as qualified by authorship-of-Waverley; “aman” to mean z as qualified by humanity.! But the particles also tell us more than this; they tell us that a variable is present in the symbolism, and that an interpretation for this variable is to be chosen in a certain way. A descriptive phrase refers then to a fact or complex object, one of the constituents of which (in language) is not explicitly mentioned in the phrase but is understood through the use of the particle, and this constituent is the term — the zg, y, or z — described. The very omission of the term focuses the attention on it. Such a phrase is, in one sense at least, an incomplete sym- 1 The central position of the term described can be indicated by writing it, with different typographical stress, both outside and inside the descriptive expression. Thus “‘the friend of Caesar,’ which means an x as modified by the whole complex “‘friend of Caesar,” could be written “the x ((x friend) of Caesar).”’ This shows that the entire expression, as well as the single predicate “friend,” modifies the term described. In our general schematism, this de- scription is of the form (x ((xJ4)Sa) ); that is, the predicate M attaches im- mediately to x, but at the same time z is modified by the whole complex predi- cate of which M is merely one element. In short, the entire structure pivots about x. If the complex predicate ((xM)Sa) is represented simply by R, the form becomes (aR). 114 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH bol, but not in Mr. Russell’s sense. It is incomplete not because it is meaningless outside a context, but because there is no sym- bolic element in it which corresponds to the term described. This element must be supplied in interpreting the expression; and it is always a variable. The discussion of the form of descriptive phrases leads first to an examination of the nature of a variable, and secondly to a reéxamination of the concept of the analysis of objects; for a descriptive phrase is analytical (and variable) in meaning, and in this respect it is distinguished from a proper name or a single symbol, which is unanalytical in meaning. IV Nothing more is known of the term described than that it is a term modified by certain predicates. The x or y which the par- ticle preceding the description permits us to supply is a symbol of whose meaning we are ignorant. It may stand for anything at all. “In mathematical logic,’ > says the Principia Mathematica- ‘any symbol whose meaning is not determinate is called a vara, able, and the various determinations of which its meaning is susceptible are called values of the variable.’ It is apparent that a variable cannot be without meaning, for if this were the case it would not be a symbol; there is no such thing as a mean- ingless symbol. And yet, if the meaning of a symbol is unde- termined, does this not amount to being without a meaning? Apparently there is an important shade of difference between that which is meaningless and that which is indeterminate in meaning. The difference is this: if I know that a mark or a sound — or any other presented object — is to be interpreted as a symbol, 1 Whitehead and Russell, Principia Mathematica, i, 4. DESCRIPTION AND ANALYSIS 115 but do not know what interpretation is to be put on it, this mark or sound is a variable. The phenomenon is analogous to the sig- nificance present in the words of a foreign language incompletely understood. A sufficient number of the words are grasped to enable us to know vaguely what the ones that are not grasped mean; the latter are treated as symbols, and yet they do not have a determinate meaning. Our attitude toward 2, as it appears in the expression, “xz is human,” is exactly this: if the whole is to be significant, x must have a meaning. We are logi- cally compelled to think of x as a symbol, just as we are logically compelled to think of the words which are not understood in the foreign phrase as symbols; but though z is a symbol its meaning is undetermined. A variable is therefore indeterminate in meaning because it is uninterpreted. It functions as a symbol because we know — not through knowing its meaning, but on other grounds — that it is symbolic; and yet, being symbolic, it means nothing in partic- ular. Variable symbols do not arise in knowledge merely through the accident of ignorance; the analogy of the uninterpreted words in the foreign language is not perfect. Variables are in- troduced for a purpose. We replace the constant “Socrates” in **Socrates is human implies Socrates is mortal’’ by a variable A, and thus achieve generality of reference — “A is human im- plies A is mortal.” Variables are instruments of thought em- ployed for a definite end. But it is essential to this end that no specific reference, no special intention, be attached to the vari- able; it must continue uninterpreted; it must be used with an intended ignorance of its meaning. The circumstance which permits the introduction of variables is that symbolic groups have a structure and a meaning as a whole. A variable presupposes a context — a context of inter- preted symbols or a general schematism of symbolic grouping; 116 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH and thus it is the truly incomplete symbol. In this context, the variable, by virtue of being a part of a whole which is taken to be symbolic, is itself taken to be symbolic. The meaning of the whole tends to lend significance to the parts, which have no specific meanings, that is, which arouse no intentions directed toward objects; and this derived (variable) significance is a new and peculiar kind of meaning, different from syntactical mean- ing or from the direct reference to objects through simple sym- bols. Out of its context a variable is meaningless; it is not a symbol and not a variable. In its context it has meaning, for if any group of marks or sounds is construed as being significant as a whole, the elements must also be construed as being signifi- cant. This is a structural necessity. Take any significant group of symbols — a phrase, a mathe- matical or logical expression — the elements of which have a determinate meaning, and replace these one after another by elements which in themselves mean nothing. The substituted (and intrinsically meaningless) elements will become variables, and the group as a whole will continue to be significant so long as it is construed as a group. If in the sentence, “San Francisco is in California, and California is in the United States, implies San Francisco is in the United States,” I insert the otherwise meaningless marks, 2, y, and 2, for the proper names, the phrase becomes, “‘z is in y and y is in z implies z is in z”; and 2, y, and z are now variables. The phrase does not lose its meaning as a whole, but becomes less determinate; it becomes more general. But since the words “‘in,” “and,” and “implies” still have a fixed meaning, the statement is determinate for these, and inde- terminate only for x, y, and z. When all of the constituents of a symbolic expression are replaced by variables, the limit of inde- terminateness is reached. The only constant element of meaning that remains is the form, but so long as this form is not destroyed the expression continues to be significant as a whole. Its mean- DESCRIPTION AND ANALYSIS 117 ing is highly general, for it is restricted to no special object, but only to objects which exhibit this form. Only the most abstract kinds of thought make use of symbolic groups in which all the constituents are variable and the form alone is constant.! But if a general schematism of grouping — a plan of syntax — is given, so that any group which falls within the plan can be treated as a significant whole, this condition will determine a sufficient framework for the use of variables as instruments of meaning. Thus ((Rab)S(Qdefg)) is a significant complex in which all the constituents are variables, provided the parentheses are taken as signs of grouping, the small letters as symbols of terms, and the capitals as symbols of unity. With these assumptions, this expression is of determinate logical form; but without the minimal context of a symbolic structure, the letters would not be variable symbols, but mere letters. The form of the expression in which a variable occurs there- fore places certain general limitations on the interpretation of the variable. Unless the structure is to be destroyed and the sig- nificance of the whole to disappear, some of the constituents must be interpreted as terms and others as elements of unity. There must be some indications in the symbolism as to which of the variables are to be thus construed. In “a is human implies x is mortal,” x must be taken as a term, or substantive; in “Socrates is R implies Socrates is S,’’ R and S must be con- strued as elements of unity, or adjectives. Universals in their adjectival function are not possible values of variable terms, and substantives (either individual or universal) are not possible values of variable symbols of unity.? Without this restriction, any interpretation would be formless and meaningless. 1 See ch. VII for an example of such a system and for a discussion of “func- tional” variability, which is different from the “interpretational”’ variability here treated. 2 This is the idea which lies behind Messrs. Whitehead and Russell’s theory of types. See Principia Mathematica, vol. i, ch. 2 of the Introduction. 118 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH Aside from this general limitation imposed by the form, the variable can stand for any object, or it can be given a meaning which is a reference to no existent object; it can be defined as equivalent to a symbolic group which stands for nothing. The x in “I saw x yesterday’ may mean “‘the prince of fairies”; the y in “‘y is human implies y is mortal”? may mean “the devil” or “the god Pan.” } However the variable is interpreted, it must be interpreted univocally; otherwise the principle of identity would be violated. The same symbol can have one and only one meaning; and if an undetermined z is construed in one way in one context, and in another way in another context, it is not the same symbol. In “x is human implies z is mortal,” the two 2’s, if they are given values, must be given one value. In the Principia Mathematica, this is stated as the special principle of “the identity of the variable’’; but this principle is not different from the law of identity in its most general form as a principle of symbolism. If x is the same symbol as x, whether its meaning be constant or variable, the two must have a single meaning. For this reason — that a symbol can stand only for a single (self-identical) object — an ambiguous expression such as “a man,” in “I met a man,” can mean one and only one individual if it is interpreted, but, being uninterpreted, it does as a matter of fact mean no indi- vidual. This raises the question of the ambiguity of the variable. 1 The borrowed significance of the variable symbols in knowledge is much like that of the nonsense words in Lewis Carroll’s “‘O frabjous day! Callooh! Callay! He chortled in his joy.” And if one gives way to the inevitable drift of significance which is present in these nonsense verses, he finds himself treating “‘chortled” and “‘frabjous” as variables — as words which must have a mean- ing; he is left free to interpret them as he chooses, provided he remains within the structure of the groups. “‘Frabjous” is evidently an adjective, and “chor- tled”’ a verb; this is fixed by the logical form. But the charm of the verse is that nothing more is fixed; within these limits the words might mean anything whatsoever. : DESCRIPTION AND ANALYSIS 119 V Psychological ambiguity or equivocation is the use of a word in several senses at once, that is, with a number of different intentions; and it is distinguished from the univocal use of words, which is their use in one sense only, that is, with a single intention. Clearly, logical ambiguity is not equivocation. A vari- able does not actually set up an intention; it actually has no reference until it is interpreted. It is ambiguous in the sense that it is susceptible of many interpretations, it can be taken to stand for many different objects or its value can be defined in many different ways, though none of these values is necessarily its interpretation. An equivocal symbol, on the other hand, is susceptible of no interpretations but the ones that already go with it. Each of its interpretations is a constant reference and some one of them must be taken, in any case, as the meaning. An equivocal symbol is never variable. Consider this Shakespearean pun: “Adam was the first that ever bore arms. The Scripture says, he digged: could he dig without arms?” ! “‘Arms” is not a variable, it is not equivalent to an 2; if it had no determinate meanings, there would be no pun. Thus a variable is ambiguous — is open to many interpreta- tions — for the same reason that it is a variable, that is, because it is actually uninterpreted. Its values are “possible interpreta- tions”; they are objects which might be but are not meant, or intentions which might be but are not aroused by it. The psy- chological effect of a variable, e¢.g., in “I saw x yesterday,” is to cause one to run over in his mind a number of meanings which could be attached to # and still allow the sentence to be signifi- cant as a whole; but the mind stops at none of these, for x does not mean some one of them. These meanings are possible inter- pretations of x; x has no actual interpretation. 1 Hamlet, act V, scene 1. 120 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH The variable may be treated, however, as if it had only one possible value, and in this case it will not be a means of generali- zation, as it is when it has many possible values. It will be a variable with a constant (though undetermined) value, an un- ambiguous variable. And this is the difference between the 99 66 meaning of “the” and of “a,” “an,” “any,” and “some.” These particles, which precede descriptive phrases, are signs of interpretation. They do not signify constituents of the fact (if the expression stands for a fact), but they mean that a variable is present and that this variable is to be interpreted in a certain way. Each of the particles indicates a different manner of inter- pretation.1 The particle “the” signifies that there is only one possible value of the variable. The meaning of the description, “the cen- ter of gravity of the solar system,” is x as modified by this com- plex predicate, where it is understood that there is one and only one possible a. But how can a variable have no more than one possible value and remain a variable? Does it not then become a constant? Clearly it does not, for the z is a variable so long as that single value is undetermined. If one says that “‘the center of gravity of the solar system is a constant,” he does not mean that this object is determinately (invariably) referred to; he means that there could be no more than one object which this descrip- tion signifies. (The particle “the” is sometimes used as equiva- lent to “‘a.”’ We say that “Brutus was the (a) friend of Caesar, and Anthony was the (a) friend of Caesar,’ where we do not mean that either was the only friend. This is a loose use of “the”, and it is evident that in the phrase, “the center of gravity of the solar system,” it is not to be construed in the sense of “a.” 99 66 99 66 The particles “a,” “an,” “any,” and “some,” on the other 1 “Every” and “‘each”’ must be treated separately since they involve the idea of “‘all,”’ that is, of reference to a class. DESCRIPTION AND ANALYSIS 121 hand, precede descriptions in which the variable is to be am- biguously construed, that is, as susceptible of many possible meanings; and this is the sole difference between a description such as “‘the bard of Avon” and “a bard of the sixteenth cen- 39 tury.” Both expressions are of the general form (xR), though x is not explicitly given in the symbolism; both refer through an undetermined symbol to a term as it is modified by a complex predicate. But the one specifies in advance that the variable has only one possible value, while the other specifies that it has many possible values. The one is an indeterminate but unambiguous reference, the other, an ambiguous (and therefore indetermi- nate) reference to a term. A description introduced by the particle “a” or “an” can be construed as if it meant either “any” or “‘some”’; but if the particle “any” or “some”’ is present, a further condition of in- terpretation is added to the general condition of ambiguity which is signified by “a” and ‘“‘an.”’ If I say, “‘a woman has the same right to education as a man,” I mean any woman and any man; but if I say, “I saw a woman and a man on the street yesterday,’ I do not mean any woman and any man; I mean some woman and some man. And either of these unexpressed ce 99 meanings can be read into a description prefaced by “‘a”’ or peatits « The particle “any” indicates that a value chosen as the in- terpretation of the variable must be chosen at random from among the possible values; there must be no principle of selec- tion. Thus “any man” means “a man” where there is no rea- son to suppose that one of many possible interpretations is pre- ferred to another. ““Some man,” on the other hand, means ‘‘a man” where the interpretation is not chosen at random, but by some principle of selection not stated. “‘Some” is the antithesis of “any,” though both are ambiguous manners of reference, that is, the phrases in which they occur may have many differ- 122 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH ent values. But “some” differs from “‘any’’ in implying a specific condition according to which the value is to be chosen. “Any” implies that there is no such condition. If I say, “Some man is your friend,” I am speaking ambigu- ously. There are many possible values of “some man’’; and yet I do not mean that “any man is your friend,” for it is assumed that the choice is limited in some way. What I mean is: ““Some man is your friend, and not any man, because you care only for good men,” or “‘because your tastes in friends are not catholic,” etc. There is a presupposed but unexpressed condition of choice. And if I say, ‘“‘Not some man, but any man, is your friend,” the implication is exactly the opposite: that there is no condition of selection.! Whether a descriptive phrase be ambiguously or unambigu- ously interpreted, whether it be preceded by “the,” “a,” “any,” or “some,” it must, if it is assigned a meaning, be given one and only one meaning; it must be univocally interpreted, otherwise the principle of identity would be violated. And this is the para- dox of the variable: that, being capable of many possible deter- minations (excepting when it is preceded by “the”), being an instrument of generality of reference, it must, nevertheless, be given no more than a single meaning, if it is given a determinate meaning. . VI A term described need not be an individual. ‘‘The divine 99 66 right of kings,” “the royal color,” are variable (and unambigu- ous) references to universals; while “‘a talent for music,” “any 33 66 love of beauty,” “some hope of immortality,” are variable (and ambiguous) references to universals. Universals no less than individuals are instances of universals; 1 “Some” carries no reference to existence as a necessary part of its mean- ing; it is not to be distinguished from “any” in this respect. “Some angel’s soul” does not mean that “there exists an angel’s soul.” DESCRIPTION AND ANALYSIS 123 and for this reason, they can be described through their predi- cates and relations. A universal need not be particularized in in- dividuals alone; it can be particularized in other universals, which are in their turn particularized in individuals. The uni- versal described is referred to in abstraction from any or all of its individual instances; it becomes the value of z in the description. This x, being a term however, will mean the universal in its sub- stantive rather than in its predicative or relating form. “The divine right of kings” means (unambiguously) a right of a pe- culiar sort; “any interest of mankind’’ means (ambiguously) an interest of a special sort; but neither means an individual. A described universal is thus signified through a variable ex- pression, as is a described individual; but a universal is no more completely determined for thought through description than is an individual. A description of “friendship” to a man who had not had a friend, or of “color” to a man who had not seen color, would contain a residuum of uninterpreted meaning which could not be eliminated by description alone. And yet univer- sals differ from individuals in that they can be known as spread- _ ing out through many perceptual wholes; they can be identified and re-identified as persisting elements in the process of change; they can be distinguished and redistinguished from other uni- versals. But once an individual has passed from perception, it cannot be again identified as the same individual. This is why universals can be determinately referred to through single words, if not through descriptions. Every universal, since it is self-identical, — itself and nothing else, —has its distinctive per- ceptual flavor; description points the way, but does not take the place of the presentation of these universal objects. Vil There is an apparent line of separation between descriptions and proper names or single symbols, and in Mr. Russell’s theory 124 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH this separation becomes extreme. Mr. Russell believes that proper names (or single symbols) have meaning both in and out of a context, while descriptions have meaning only in a context. “By an ‘incomplete symbol,’” says the Principia Mathe- matica, “we mean a symbol which is not supposed to have any meaning in isolation, but is only defined in certain contexts. . . . This distinguishes such symbols from what (in a generalized sense) we may call proper names. ‘Socrates,’ for example, stands for a certain man, and therefore has meaning by itself, without the need of any context. If we supply a context, as in “Socrates is mortal,’ these words express a fact of which Socrates himself is a constituent. But in other cases this simple analysis fails.” } These are the cases in which a phrase such as “the author of Waverley’’ is employed. Such expressions in themselves are meaningless; they have meaning only in use. This theory is contrary to ordinary interpretations of lan- guage. “The author of Waverley” is capable of standing on its own feet as a significant symbol; one feels no need of a context to give it a meaning. The phrase is used in speech as if it were equivalent to the proper name “Scott,’’ and like the proper name, it is construed as significant both in itself and in a con- text. Mr. Russell’s view is not supported by common sense or usage; it is proved by a number of ingenious arguments which raise fundamental questions as to the nature of meaning. An examination of these arguments discloses a wholly different way of distinguishing between descriptions and proper names (in a generalized sense).“The former are analyzed references or mean- ings; the latter, unanalyzed references. Neither depend on their contexts for significance. At the same time, we discover that a reference to an individual through a proper name is no more determinate than a reference to an individual through a descrip- tion. 1 Whitehead and Russell, Principia Mathematica (1910), i, 69. DESCRIPTION AND ANALYSIS 125 One of Mr. Russell’s most plausible arguments for the view that descriptions have meaning only in use is the following: “Take, for example, the following proposition: ‘Scott is the author of Waverley.’ This proposition expresses an identity; thus if ‘the author of Waverley’ could be taken as a proper name, and supposed to stand for some object c, the proposition would be ‘Scott is c.’ But if c is anyone except Scott, the proposition is false; while if ¢ is Scott, the proposition is ‘Scott is Scott,’ which is trivial, and plainly different from ‘Scott is the author of Waverley.’” * The conclusion is that “‘the author of Waverley’ cannot mean the same as ‘Scott,’ or ‘Scott is the author of Waverley’ would mean the same as ‘Scott is Scott,’ which it plainly does not; nor can ‘the author of Waverley’ mean any- thing other than ‘Scott,’ or ‘Scott is the author of Waverley’ would be false. Hence ‘the author of Waverley’ means nothing.” Such expressions have a meaning in use, but not in isolation. In use, e.g., in the proposition, “Scott is the author of Wav- erley, “the phrase becomes significant when the proposition is understood to mean “‘x wrote Waverley’ is always equivalent to “x is Scott.’” | There is no doubt that propositions in which descriptive phrases occur can be translated into propositions in which these phrases do not occur. A descriptive phrase can always be elim- inated. But this is a symbolic device, and not a proof that the descriptive phrase in itself has no meaning. Usage holds that “Scott”? means the same as “‘the author of Waverley,” that both are significant in isolation from a context, and that “Scott is the author of Waverley” is not, on this account, either a trivial or false proposition. Common usage employs a descriptive phrase interchangeably with a proper name which it takes to stand for the same object, and common usage can be defended. The judgment, “Scott is the author of Waverley,” is analytic 1 Op. cit., p. 70. 126 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH in form. It is of the form, « = (yR), which expresses an identity of meaning between two symbols, or two concepts. But the sym- bol on one side of the identity (if it refers to an object) refers to the object as a single and unanalyzed thing, while the symbol on the other side refers to it as a group of elements — as a complex whole which can be broken up into parts. By substituting x for (yR), which must be possible if these are identical in meaning, the identity x = x can be derived, and this is trivial: it is the law of identity, which is presupposed in the use of x as a symbol. But this does not necessitate the conclusion that either z means something other than (yR) or (yR) is meaningless. The conclu- sion to which it does lead is this: that « (if it means an object) means the same object as (yf), but means it in a different way; that the same object can be meant in two different ways, that is, it can be referred to analytically or unanalytically; and that the exhibition of an analysis — or of different analyses of the same object — is never trivial. If “Scott is the author of Waverley” is either trivial or false, on the usual interpretation of these sym- bols, the equation 2 + 2 = 4 is also trivial or false, for it is an analytic judgment of the same general form. It asserts that what is meant by the complex 2+ 2 is the same as what is meant by the symbol 4; it permits the substitution of 4 for the complex 2 + 2, and yields the identity 4 = 4.7 Vit The judgment is accused of being trivial because it seems not to be synthetic; it seems to add nothing to its subject through its predicate. But a judgment which is analytic in form can be syn- thetic in effect, when one side of the identity expresses an analy- sis of what is represented on the other side without analysis (or through a different analysis). 1 This assumes that the equations of arithmetic represent identities, which is, we believe, the correct view. DESCRIPTION AND ANALYSIS 127 Single words or symbols can mean a great deal more than we are explicitly aware that they mean, and this is because we can refer to an object as a whole without referring to the parts or aspects of the object. To describe an object, which is originally signified by a single word, is to add to our knowledge a knowl- edge of the fact that the object is composed of elements. To signify the same object in these two different ways is expressly to state that the object has certain lines of structure, that a cer- tain analysis of it is possible. Now one can be aware of an object without expressly representing to himself its lines of structure, its possible analyses. Therefore, such a judgment of identity, though it takes the analytic form, x = (yR), is synthetic in effect. It asserts more than x = x. Statements of identity that present an analysis of what is meant without analysis by a single symbol are the only means by which indefinite concepts can be made definite, the only way in which meanings can be defined. But is a description an analysis? If analysis is breaking up an object into its parts, is not the discovery that an object is an in- stance of a universal, or that a certain description fits it, some- thing other than analysis? I can analyze an object into parts, a, b, and c, which are re- lated in a certain way. I can discover that my ink-well is com- posed of a small glass jar with a glass cover, and this seems to be genuine analysis. But if I find that the ink-well is black and that it is on the table, I am discovering relations and qualities which attach to it, and these do not seem to be parts in the same sense. And if I now describe it as “‘a black object on the table,” I do not appear to be analyzing the ink-well. This is a superficial distinction. Whether its blackness and its position on the table are “parts”’ of the ink-well depends on the point of view. These may be, on one definition, external to the object and, on another definition, internal to it. If by “the ink- well”? I intend the bare z, the individual term — what Locke 128 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH would have called its “‘substance”” — then the fact that it has a glass container and a small glass cover is as external to it as the fact that it is black and on the table. But I can mean by “the ink-well”’ either the individual, the z alone, to which certain predicates attach, or I can mean the individual taken with more or fewer of its predicates and relations. And this is possible be- cause the individual, though it may not be completely deter- mined by its predicates and relations, is continuous with them. They enter into the individual. Any predicates or relations of an object are “parts” of the object in a logical sense, for they par- tucipate in the object; and when the object is described, it is analyzed as a complex whole in which these qualities and rela- tions are elements. The bare individual, the x, of which the predicates and relations hold, becomes one element along with others. Description is then analysis, but it may be analysis which leads to an enlargement of concepts — of the meanings of single words or ideas, or of groups — through the discovery of new characters and relations that can be included in the definition. If I make the judgment, “Scott is the author of Waverley,” in ignorance of the fact that Scott wrote Waverley, what this judg- ment tells me is that I can enlarge my concept of Scott to in- clude the authorship of Waverley. I must so enlarge my concept if the judgment is to be true; for if I do not now mean the same thing by “Scott” as by “the author of Waverley,” Iam certainly in error. The meaning of a single symbol can be indefinitely expanded to take in more and more of the predicates and relations of an object, so that judgments of the form, x = (yR), continually widen knowledge by giving new definitions, new analyses, of * This explains the surprise of George IV (mentioned by Mr. Russell) when he learned through a mere statement of identity that Scott was the author of Waverley. DESCRIPTION AND ANALYSIS 129 concepts which have hitherto been used with a restricted or un- analyzed meaning. IX The most restricted possible concept of an individual is that of an x—a mere “this” — devoid of all characters and relations, a concept which is framed only by abstraction from the con- crete, qualified, and related data of perception. Scott, though a single word is used to refer to this person, is a complex object. He has many aspects beyond his bare individuality, he is an in- dividual of this sort or that sort, and this has been shown to be true of all individuals. Every individual is a vortex of characters and relations. When one uses a proper name for an individual, he cannot in the beginning mean an z, shorn of all relations and characters, for no such thing comes into experience to be named. “Scott,” at the very least, originally means an («R), a complex of predicates individualized in a term. Thus, from the outset, a proper name is equivalent in meaning to a minimal description of the object to which it is applied. Though the bare individual is an element in the whole, it is the whole which is named, and not the individual alone. To break up this whole and take the meaning of the proper name to be the z to which the characters and relations attach, and only this, is to reduce the significance of the name to that of an z. “Scott,” if it means merely the indi- vidual, a “‘this” which is distinct from all other individuals and absolutely unique, is a variable; and the fact that the name is treated as if it had one, and only one interpretation, does not eliminate this indeterminateness, for it does not tell us what this interpretation is. No view of knowledge is more inadequate than an extreme nominalism, which holds that individuals can be picked out, apart from their characters and relations, and referred to through determinate concepts, or given distinctive names. And 130 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH yet the opposite extreme is equally inadequate, vzz., that the individual, or any other object, is nothing but its characters and relations. The attempts to reduce terms (whether individual or universal) to their predicates and relations, and the inverse — to reduce predicates and relations to their terms — are destined to failure because they destroy the logical frame-work of fact. The theory of “internal relations” cannot show that terms can be dispensed with in describing the world, without abolishing all distinctions and all description. If all relations and predi- cates completely absorb their terms, everything becomes one and indistinguishable. But it is possible to interpret the “‘inter- nality of relations” in another way. The wholeness of fact is such that the element of unity — the predicate or relation — enters into the terms as well as into the fact. This unity of the terms with the predicate or relation leaves both distinct for knowledge; it is not inconsistent with the externality or dis- tinctness of terms and relations which is necessary to logical structure. But at the same time, the unity of predicates with their terms makes it possible to include in the definition or de- scription of a term a reference to more or fewer of its predicates and relations. Where, it will be asked, does this extension of concepts through the description of objects by new characters and rela- tions end? It would seem that a meaning must eventually be- come coextensive with all the predicates of the object meant, that “Scott” or any other name must finally mean an object taken with an indefinite number of predicates. No characters or relations of the object would then be external to the meaning. This would be the necessary outcome of broadening a concept to its utmost possible limits. The name “Scott” would then signify anything which could be said about the individual, Scott; so that any judgment into which “Scott” entered would be- come analytic and trivial in Mr. Russell’s sense. DESCRIPTION AND ANALYSIS 131 X Just as a judgment may be analytic in form and synthetic in effect, so a judgment may be synthetic in form and analytic in effect. Judgments such as “‘z has the relation R to y,” where R is not identity, or “x has the quality Q,” are, in general, taken to be synthetic, to add something to their subjects through their predicates. But if the meaning of'z already includes the relation R to y or the quality Q, the judgment is synthetic in form only. Its effect is analytic. Thus Kant’s example of an analytic judg- ment, vzz., “body is extended,” is synthetic in form but analytic in effect because the attribute of extension is by definition included in the meaning of the term “body.” If I mean by “Scott,” among other things, “the author of Waverley,” then the seemingly synthetic proposition, “Scott wrote Waverley,” is analytic in effect. Whether the predicate of a judgment adds something to what is meant by the subject depends, therefore, on what one means by the subject. This is why “Scott is the author of Waverley”’ or any similar statement of identity can convey more to the mind than “Scott is Scott,’ and why “body is extended” or “Scott wrote Waverley” can convey no more than “body is body” or “the author of Waverley wrote Waverley.” It is only because we do not know (analytically) what we can mean by a proper name or single word, or because we use them with a deliberately restricted meaning, that any judgments are synthetic in effect. Ignorance is the great restricter of mean- ings, and ignorance renders certain properties external to ob- jects, which on different definitions of these objects, become internal to them. One usually means by a word something less than an object with all its possible predicates and relations, and so the object can be viewed as entering into new relations and acquiring new predicates. “Napoleon conquered Europe” 132 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH shows Napoleon in a new réle, and is a synthetic judgment (both in form and in effect), if one does not include “‘conqueror of Europe” in the meaning of the name “Napoleon.” But this is an arbitrary or accidental restriction of the meaning. What has been said of the analysis of the meaning of proper names is true also of single words which stand for universals. A universal can be described, or it can be represented by a single word. The description means the same thing as the single word, but means this analytically, while the word means it un- analytically. The word is capable of being extended or con- tracted in meaning to take in more or fewer of the predicates and relations of the universal meant. A word which signifies a universal may enter in judgments of synthetic or analytic form, and these judgments will be synthetic or analytic in effect ac- cording to the interpretation put on the word. That single symbols (proper names in a generalized sense) can mean the same objects as descriptions, and that the state- ment of such identities of meaning is highly fruitful for knowl- edge, rather than trivial, are, then, the consequences of this view of description as analysis. It follows, also, that proper names (in the more restricted sense of this term), if they mean bare individuals, are of no more use to thought than 2’s and y’s whose values are not known. And even when their meanings are wider than such references to bare individuals, proper names give us no more determinate, or invariable, knowledge of indi- viduals than do descriptions. Whatever can be referred to through invariable symbols is universal. Aristotle himself, to whom individual substances were the sole realities (God only being excepted), believed that universals alone were the objects of screntzfic knowledge. What can be said of individuals must be said in universal terms, and only when reference to individuals is dropped is knowledge completely freed from variability of meaning. Completely determinate knowledge is of universals DESCRIPTION AND ANALYSIS 133 and their connections. Hence perceptual knowledge is never completely determinate, never wholly compressed into the con- cepts of invariable meaning which function in perception; and yet it is the only concrete knowledge, that is, the only knowledge in which the individual merges with the universal. Complete conceptual determination and concreteness do not go together; what is completely determined for conception is never concrete, and what is concrete is never completely determined in con- cepts. XI Knowledge in universal terms tends to become analytic in form, for here, as elsewhere, concepts enlarge themselves by in- cluding more and more of the predicates and relations of the universal meant. To the layman, water is something wet, color- less, tasteless, and odorless; if he were asked to define it, he would describe it in this way. But if he studies chemistry, he finds that water is made up of hydrogen and oxygen in definite proportions, and his concept must be enlarged by the judgment that “water is H.0,” a judgment of analytic form but synthetic effect. He will discover that water boils at 212° Fahrenheit under atmospheric pressure, and at lower temperatures under lower pressures, etc.; and these facts, together with countless others, must be included in his concept. In the end his concept of water will completely sum up his knowledge of it. The word “water’”’ will mean all that water is known to be and do, and a judgment about water, ¢.g., that water boils at 212° Fahrenheit under at- mospheric pressure, will tell him no more than is included in his concept. It will be an analysis of this concept. Thus the chemist, if he discovers a property or law which is “external to” water as he conceives it, will straightway take this property or law into the meaning of the term. But in addition, there will always remain a perceptual “somewhat” to which the 134 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH name “water” belongs, and this “somewhat” will be spread out in numberless individual instances. But the evasive element of individuality will never be a part of the meaning of the universal term. The concept will include much that can be known only by inference from the perceptual properties of water; these inferred properties, ¢.g., molecular and atomic structure, etc., will also be described in universal and invariable terms. A science becomes analytic in form for this reason: it tends so to broaden its concepts of a subject-matter, originally given in perception, that an analysis of what is meant by these concepts states the laws of the science. The subject-matter is defined as that which follows the laws; anything which does not obey the laws is not included in the scope of the science. Thus matter, originally in perception something solid and extended, becomes anything that conforms to a certain set of principles — physical principles; and mind becomes anything that conforms to an- other set of principles — psychical principles. The drift toward the analytic form is especially evident in the mathematical sciences. Crude perceptions of a spread-out and diversified something called “space” are enlarged by the dis- covery of principles which can be exactly stated in universal terms, and which can be interpreted as referring to these percep- tions. “Space” is finally conceived as that system of objects which obey geometrical axioms and postulates; and, when space is thus defined, to say that space conforms to geometrical laws is to say merely that “space is space.” If different sets of axioms and postulates which can be equally well interpreted by the original experience are discovered, these axioms and postu- lates will define different kinds of space — Euclidean, and the numerous varieties of non-Euclidean space. Thus it becomes a trivial and analytic statement to say, e.g., that the parallel pos- tulate holds for Euclidean space, for Euclidean space is defined through this postulate and others. But to say that this postulate DESCRIPTION AND ANALYSIS 135 holds for space as such is to raise the question as to whether the Euclidean analysis of space is the true analysis, and so to force a choice between this type of geometry and other types. The judgment, “Space as such is Euclidean space,” though analytic in form, is not a trivial statement of identity. It purports to add something to knowledge by showing that what we originally meant by “space” is truly analyzed by the Euclidean axioms and postulates. This judgment is synthetic in effect and can be proved or disproved by experience. A science which assumes the analytic form does not lose its experiential content, and this is no less true of the mathematical sciences than of the physical, biological, or psychological sci- ences. Number and space, though they may be defined through the laws of arithmetic and geometry, are still objects (univer- sals) met with in experience. A “‘science” which had no point of application in presented objects would not be a science, but an uninterpreted or partially interpreted system of symbols (or concepts). The description of the subject-matter given in the laws, the postulates and axioms, must be anchored in experi- ence; the variable terms, the z’s and y’s, described must mean something apart from the descriptions in which they appear. Thus if Euclidean space is simply the x which the postulates of Euclidean geometry describe, one does not know fully what this z is. There may be many different objects, e.g., certain series of numbers, etc., which are possible values of this x. These postu- lates become the laws of space only when they are interpreted by the spread-out and diversified something called “space.” The only reason why one can speak of the postulates of Eu- clidean or non-Euclidean geometry as postulates of geometry is that they are rooted in an original experience of space. An uninterpreted or partially interpreted system of concepts is merely the possibility of a science. It becomes an actual sci- ence only when it is taken to be a description (or an analysis) of 136 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH some field of presented objects. The fact therefore that a science tends to become analytic in form does not free it from the neces- sity of binding itself to experience by a synthetic judgment — a judgment which conveys the information that the subject- matter as perceived is the subject-matter as described. XII A second argument by which Mr. Russell supports his theory that descriptive phrases are without meaning excepting as they occur in a context, brings up the problem of “‘reference to the non-existent,”’ that is, of how symbols can be used significantly when there is no object which they mean. “Suppose we say: ‘The round square does not exist.’ It seems plain,” says Mr. Russell, “that this is a true proposition, yet we cannot regard it as denying the existence of a certain object called ‘the round square.’ For if there were such an object, it would exist: we cannot first assume that there is a certain ob- ject, and then proceed to deny that there is such an object. Whenever the grammatical subject of a proposition can be sup- posed to be meaningless without rendering the proposition meaningless, it is plain that the grammatical subject is not a proper name, that is, not a name directly representing some ob- ject. Thus in all such cases the proposition must be capable of being so analyzed that what was the grammatical subject shall have disappeared.” ! And this argument is carried still further: the Principia Mathematica asserts that a function (a predicate) which is universally true may nevertheless not be true of an object described as “‘the so-and-so.” Though it is true of every object that it is an identity, it is not true of “the round square” that it is an identity. This object is therefore nothing. But if the round square is nothing, does it follow that “the round square” is without meaning? Are not the two phenomena 1 Whitehead and Russell, Principia Mathematica, i, 69. DESCRIPTION AND ANALYSIS 137 of significance, to be without meaning and to mean something non-existent, different phenomena? There is an air of contradiction in the idea of meaning or re- ferring to the non-existent. But this semblance of contradiction disappears if “reference to the non-existent”’ is more accurately described as the significant use of symbols where there is no object for which they stand. It is possible to employ symbols signifi- cantly (with syntactical significance) when there is no object to which the group as a whole refers, and this is what Mr. Russell denies or overlooks. But even if it were true that a phrase which “means a non-entity”’ is without meaning, it would not follow that because some descriptions mean non-entities, all descrip- tions mean non-entities and are therefore without meaning. If “the round square”’ is a meaningless expression because there are no round squares, this fact does not imply that “the Presi- dent of the United States” is meaningless because it is a de- scriptive phrase of the same form as “the round square.” However, the important question is— Can a description, or a symbolic group, be significant and yet not refer to an object? The Principia Mathematica, being concerned with logic rather than epistemology, does not analyze the concept of meaning. But certain assumptions as to the nature of meaning seem to be implicit in its earlier, more strictly philosophical sections. So far as we can disentangle these assumptions, the view of meaning seems to be this: that groups of symbols which state proposi- tions, and proper names (in a generalized sense), are the only symbols which have meaning in themselves. Thus descriptive phrases fall between two stools: they are groups of symbols, but they do not state propositions; they play a part like that of proper names, yet they are not proper names. If this is the as- sumption of the argument which rejects descriptive phrases as meaningless outside a context, the conclusion must be granted. It then becomes necessary to translate descriptive phrases into i PON 5 EE a ———— 138 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH another form, that is, to treat them as significant only when they occur in propositions, and to construe these propositions as statements which make use only of proper names (in the generalized sense). But the possibility that groups of symbols which do not state propositions, and yet are not proper names, might be significant in their own right is not considered. And this is what we have been urging all along: that there is some legitimate sense of the term meaning other than those senses which appear to be assumed in the Principia Mathematica. This type of meaning—syntactical significance—covers both prop- ositions and descriptive phrases; and just as a group of symbols which states a proposition may as a whole refer to no object, so a descriptive phrase may as a whole refer to no object and yet be significant. While proper names and single words, that is, simple symbols, unless they are defined through symbolic groups, arouse inten- tions directed toward objects — intentions which depend on the existence of these objects — a symbolic group, on the contrary, arouses an intention which is a function only of subordinate in- tentions and of the structure of the group. The meaning of a symbolic complex does not depend on the existence of an object for which it stands as a whole. In order that a symbolic group may be significant, it is necessary only that its constituents be significant (or be definable in terms of significant complexes) and that it have a form. It is in this sense of meaning that “France loves Germany” has meaning. There is no object, France loving Germany, but the phrase is significant because its constituents are significant and grouped according to a plan of logical structure. To say that a description “means a non-existent object” is a convenient but inaccurate way of speaking, for a “non-existent object’’ would not be an object and could not be referred to. DESCRIPTION AND ANALYSIS 139 The clearer manner of statement is that a description can be significant apart from any reference, as a whole, to an object. “The round square” means roundness and squareness attaching to a term which is symbolized by a variable; it means “‘z as modified by roundness and squareness.” “‘The king of France”’ means “‘y as modified by the kingship of France.”’ And whether or not any such unities of terms and predicates exist to be re- ferred to is beside the point. Mr. Russell’s argument must be countered by a broader conception of meaning. It is because the existence or non-existence of an object sig- nified does not affect the significance of a symbolic group that “to mean a non-entity” is not to be meaningless. Only simple symbols which refer directly to objects require the existence of an object meant. Such symbols mean “‘categorically,” but syn- tactical or group meaning is “hypothetical,” for it presupposes no object corresponding to the group as a whole. To assert that “the round square does not exist”’ is not, then, to assume that there is an object called ‘“‘the round square” in order to deny its existence. Nor does the truth of this assertion lead to the conclusion that the phrase “‘the round square”’ is in itself meaningless. 1 As for the statement of the Principia Mathematica, i, 87, that the law of identity does not apply to descriptions, 7. e., that one cannot say “the round square is identical with the round square,” this depends on what the as- sertion of identity means. It has been shown above that z = z, as a general principle of symbolism, means that the symbol z is always to be interpreted in the same way, whether or not it stands for an existent object. Thus “the round square = the round square” does not necessarily assert the existence of this object, but it does assert that the significance given to this phrase must be the same in all contexts; that “the round square” can be substituted for “‘the round square”’ in any discourse, without an alteration of the meaning. But if ““the round square is identical with the round square” is interpreted existen- tially, to mean that “‘the round square has identity,” this will not be true un- less the round square exists. However, the symbolic interpretation of the law of identity is separable from the existential interpretation: “x is x”’ need not be construed as predicating identity of an object meant by z. See above, ch. II, see. vii. 140 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH XILIT The particles “all,” “‘every,” and “each”’ introduce a new idea: that of classes. “All men,” “every man,” “each man,” are different ways of referring to the class men. As in the case of the other particles, these particles have no meaning in themselves; they must ap- pear in connection with symbols that refer to universals or com- plex predicates. They do not signify constituents of the fact represented by a phrase in which they occur; they are signs of interpretation. Just as “the” tells us that one and only one in- stance of a universal is meant (though this instance is indeter- minate), and “a” that one among many possible instances is meant, so “all” tells us that the universal is signified in a certain manner of its occurrence — in its occurrence in a class. Classification rests on universals. Though a universal is some- thing distinct from any or all of its instances, though it is an aspect which can be singled out and made an object of reference, nevertheless, a universal occurs in instances, it modifies a num- ber of terms; and a class is the universal taken in conjunction with the terms it modifies. It is a plurality of terms modified by the same universal. Any predicate determines a class — the class of the terms to which this predicate attaches. A relation de- termines a number of classes: “A hates B” is, for example, a case of the class of ‘“‘hatreds’”’; but from this relation the class of ‘‘those who hate B” and the class of “those whom A hates” can also be derived. “‘A is between b and c”’ is a case of the class of “‘relations of betweenness,”’ but it also determines a class of “those objects which are between 6 and c” and “those objects between which a occurs.” In every case a class is a plurality of terms modified by a single quality or relation.’ But a class is at once a plurality and a unity. It derives its 1 A class of one member is the only exception; this is not a plurality of mem- bers: but if it is a class, it is a totality of one. DESCRIPTION AND ANALYSIS 141 unity from the presence of a predicate in a number of distinct terms, and its plurality from the distinctness of the terms. The difficulty of conceiving a class as an object, says the Principia Mathematica, is connected with the “ancient dilemma of the One and the Many.” “If there is any such object as a class, it must be in some sense one object. Yet it is only of classes that many can be predicated. Hence, if we admit classes as objects, we must suppose that the same object can be both one and many, which seems impossible.” 1 But the impossibility is less real than apparent. It is no more present in the conception of a class than in the conception of any object which is analyzed into constituents, broken up into parts which form a whole. Every analyzable object is both one and many, a unity of diverse ele- ments; and if one balks at the problem of the One and Many, he must reject all analysis. The unity of a class, however, is different from the unity of a fact (or a group), and for this reason a class, though it is none the less an object, is not the same kind of object as a fact. It is an object of a different order. “Caesar loving Brutus,” “‘Bos- ton’s being near to but north of New York,” are expressions that stand for factual groups. In these groups the universal unites the terms so that (taken with the universal) they become a single instance of this universal. The predicate which deter- mines a class unites the members in no such way as this. (But if there are classes there will also be factual groups, and if there are factual groups there will also be classes.) The unity of a class is of the peculiar kind called totality, and this is a new prim- itive idea — the defining idea of classes. A class is a universal in the totality of its instances, that is, it is an object like “man” as it appears in this sort of unity with diverse terms. “Man” means a universal apart from its in- stances, that is, in abstraction; but man is not only separable 1 Whitehead and Russell, op. cit., i, 75. 142 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH from its instances, it is also joined to them, spread throughout them. “Men” as distinguished from “‘man” means the universal as it is particularized in a multitude of different terms. This object is one, and can be referred to through a single symbol, because the universal gives it the unity of totality, though this is a “looser” unity than that of a single fact of diverse terms. No part or selection of the terms to which a universal attaches is a class, a totality, through the presence of that universal alone. Every universal determines one and only one totality. Thus a portion of the class men would be a class only through the presence of some other predicate than man, e.g., the predi- cate, brave man, or strong man. A class therefore is nothing short of a universal in its concrete entirety. The universal, in making the instances one, makes them a totality, but at the same time permits them to be distinguished as instances. It follows from this notion that a class is not a sum of objects. The expression, “a and b and ¢, etc.,”’ does not designate a class, for objects which do not belong to the same class can be thus added together. A mere summation of objects will not give us a class predicate which determines them to be a totality. “The table and the chair and the book, etc.,” are not a class through the fact of being conjoined; they become a class only if there is some predicate which gives them the unity of totality. If they are “‘all the objects in this room”’ or “‘all the objects I now see,” they are a class. Nor does the similarity of objects alone make them a class, although objects of the same class are similar. Only if x and y and z, etc., are “all the objects similar to a given object c,” do they form a class, and in such cases this class will be a totality determined by a predicate. Classes are cross-sections of the world of fact. Only very lim- ited classes are presented in their wholeness; most classes can be known only conceptually or symbolically, that is, as the (x) totality determined by such and such a predicate. Though “all DESCRIPTION AND ANALYSIS 143 men” means one object, no one has known all men; and thus classes seem not to be objects, but constructions of the mind. Yet the inability of knowledge to grasp most classes as totalities in perception does not disprove the objectivity of classes. The idea of totality once being given, —as it is in the restricted totalities of presentation, — this idea can be extended to totali- ties that lie beyond presentation, and to infinite totalities. “Each” and “every” as well as “all’’ precede expressions that refer to classes, but the distinctions between ‘“‘each,”’ “every,” and “all” are difficult to draw. The difference seems to be one of emphasis. “All men are sinful’? appears to empha- size the fact that the class of men is a totality. “Every man is sinful”? means the same, that is, that all men are sinful, but em- phasizes the plurality of the class. “‘Each man is sinful” also emphasizes the plurality of the class, but at the same time seems to include a reference to an enumeration of the members. But whatever the shades of difference in the meanings of “each,” “every,” and “all” may be, these three words indicate manners of reference to classes. A reference to a class is clearly a description of the form “the so-and-so” rather than “‘a or some so-and-so.” The totality is meant through an undetermined x which has only one possible value, that is, the totality in question. “All persons”? means “the (x) totality determined by the predicate ‘person’”’; this expression is not susceptible of many interpretations as is “a 299] person. XIV The discussion of description and analysis has brought out the following points: 1 It is plain that a class could have one member or an infinity of members and still be a totality. ‘‘ All the numbers which, when added to a number give that number,” designates a totality of one member — the number zero. “ All the objects which can be put into one-to-one correspondence with the natural numbers”’ designates an infinite totality. { 144 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH The line of cleavage between proper names or single symbols and descriptive phrases is determined by structure alone; the distinction is not that proper names (in a generalized sense) have meaning in themselves, while descriptive phrases have meaning only in a context. Description is analysis, for the predi- cates and relations of a term are logical “parts” of it, and what is represented analytically by a descriptive phrase is represented unanalytically by a proper name or a single symbol. This agrees with common usage, which treats proper names as equivalent in meaning to descriptive phrases. Syntactical significance is present in all symbolic groups, and only when this type of mean- ing is neglected (or confined to groups which state propositions) does the contrary view, that descriptions have no meaning in themselves, become plausible. Symbolic groups are significant apart from the existence or non-existence of objects meant, for their meaning as a whole is a function of the meanings of their parts and their logical form, and nothing else. This wider notion of meaning covers that of descriptions outside a context. If there is no object correspond- ing to a description, this fact does not deprive the description of its syntactical significance. ““To mean a non-entity,” that is, to be significant when there is no object signified, is not to be meaningless. A description signifies a term, together with a predicate or complex of predicates attached to this term; but the term is represented by a variable which, in language, is understood to be present through the sign of interpretation (the particle) pre- ceding the phrase. Descriptions are of the general form (xR): the object has this structure and the symbols themselves take on this structure if the variable, which is understood, is supplied. 99 «66 Thus ‘‘a man” means “a human 2, some friend’? means “some friendly y,” “the president” means “the presiding 2.” The term described becomes the center of a complex of char- 99 66 DESCRIPTION AND ANALYSIS 145 acters and relations, and the variable through which this term is signified is to be interpreted in the sense indicated by the parti- cle. “The” means that the variable has only one possible value. “A” and “an” mean that it has many possible values; “‘any,” that the value is to be chosen at random from among these many possible values; and “some,” that it is to be chosen according to an unspecified condition of selection. Though a description does not state a fact, it always has reference to a fact — to the fact through which the object in question is described. “‘The president of the United States”’ re- fers to the fact that “someone presides over the United States”’; “‘a bard of the sixteenth century,” to the fact that “someone wrote poetry in the sixteenth century”; “a man,” to the fact that ‘someone is human.” And whether the description signifies an existent object, or refers to no object, will depend on the truth _ or falsity of the propositions which assert these facts. ‘This is the basis of Mr. Russell’s reduction of descriptions to the form of | propositions which make assertions about terms. _ But it is not necessary to translate the description into an- _ other form to observe that it refers to a fact as well as to a term. The term is, as it were, viewed through the fact; the fact is viewed as centering about the term, so that the term assumes a pivotal rather than a subordinate place in the fact. (‘This is sym- bolized by writing the x both inside and outside the group through which it is described. Thus (a((xR)Sa)) indicates that the z is described through the whole complex ((xR)Sa).) This centralization of the fact about a single term is the only differ- ence between the fact as it appears in the description and as it might appear in some other (non-descriptive) form of expres- sion. If a description is asserted, — and it follows from this view that descriptions can be asserted, —it will be seen that the de- scription may state a fact, the fact on which the description is based. “The president of the United States is,” affirms the same 146 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH fact as “someone presides over the United States”; “the author of Waverley is,” makes the same assertion as *“Someone wrote Waverley,’ where “someone” is taken to have only one possible value. “A man is”’ affirms no more nor less than “someone is human.”’ ! The difference in these assertions is one of form only, and not of content. Therefore descriptive phrases are not dis- tinguished from “‘propositions”’ through the fact that the latter mean complexes of terms and predicates or relations, while the former mean only terms. Both stand for complex wholes (if they stand for any objects); both mean facts. Variable significance, which is always present in descriptions, is a distinct kind of meaning, different from syntactical meaning or from direct reference to objects through simple symbols. The variable, meaningless in itself, is construed as a symbol because it enters as a constituent in a significant whole; it is a symbol which arouses no specific intention, but which must be treated as symbolic because of its setting. And if it is given a value this can be, by the principle of identity, one and only one value. The variable is no more open to an equivocal interpretation than any other symbol. A variable may, however, have many possible values, and it will then be ambiguous — a means of attaining generality of reference. Both universals and individuals can be described, and both are variably (indeterminately) signified by descriptions. But an individual is still variably signified when it is given a proper name, for the proper name must be defined through a descrip- tion, which contains a variable element; otherwise the name would stand merely for a “this” of presentation and would be even less determinate in meaning than if it were defined through a description. The only data of perception which can be represented by 1 “Ts” as a sign of assertion in these expressions adds or subtracts nothing from the meaning of the phrase. DESCRIPTION AND ANALYSIS 147 invariable symbols are universals, and so the only knowledge which is completely free from variability of meaning is knowl- edge in universal terms, that is, abstract statements, laws, which make no reference to individuals. Definitions are analytic in form. They are statements of iden- tity, such as a = (#R); and they can be reduced to the form a = a. But they are not on this account trivial, since their effect is synthetic; they add to the knowledge of the object meant, a knowledge that it can be analyzed as (rR), or that predicates which were originally external to the meaning of a can be in- cluded in this meaning. Concepts of restricted meaning enlarge themselves through such statements of identity by taking in more and more of the predicates of the object meant, and in this way knowledge tends to become analytic in form. It tends to sum up all that can be said of an object in the very concept (the very name) of the object. But the postulates and axioms of a science do not completely determine the subject-matter of the science, even though an analysis of what is meant by “the sub- ject-matter” may be a statement of the laws of the science. Knowledge of analytic form must be anchored to experience by a judgment which is synthetic in effect — which asserts that the objects within a certain field of experience are the objects thus analyzed. Euclidean or non-Euclidean geometry is geometry because its postulates can be interpreted in terms of the experi- ence called “space.” Lastly, there is a type of object — a class — which is referred to by descriptions prefaced by “all,” “every,” and “each.” Classes are not groups, not wholes of the form (Rab ...), but a class is nevertheless one through the presence of a universal in terms. Its unity is of the undefined sort known as totality. Classes, with the exception of the limited totalities given in per- ception, are known only conceptually, that is, through symbols, as “‘the (x) totality determined by such-and-such a predicate.” 148 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH Descriptions, then, do not stand apart from other symbolic expressions. All symbolic groups have significance in themselves, and this significance is independent of the existence of an object meant. The possibility of using symbols significantly, either in descriptions or in propositions which are not descriptions, when no “real” object is referred to, lies at the basis of the distinction between truth and falsity. Meaning becomes truth when it is joined to existence; it becomes falsity when it is severed from existence; but without meaning there is neither truth nor falsity. CHAPTER V TRUTH AND FALSITY I Trourn and falsity are properties of symbols. A symbol is true if it stands for an object; it is false if it is significant, yet stands for no object; or, in the words of Thomas Hobbes, “True and false are attributes of speech, not of things . . . truth is the right-ordering of names.” ! If the term “speech” is widely enough construed, this definition of the aim of knowledge is a corollary of the theory of meaning that has been presented. The “right-ordering of names” is building symbols into structures that correspond to structures of fact, and this correspondence is truth. Belief and disbelief do not alter the truth or falsity of sym- bolic expressions, for the existence of meaning is a sufficient as well as a necessary condition of the existence of truth. No one can be in error unless what he believes has meaning, and he can- not be convicted of error if his meaning is misunderstood; nor can he believe truly unless that which he believes is significant. Yet truth and falsity are independent of belief; any idea that can be entertained is either true or false. Once a meaning is fixed, its truth or falsity is fixed; and meanings are carried only in symbols. This is the idea behind Hobbes’s definition. Yet it must not be forgotten that a symbol is more than a mark, a sound, a gesture, or an image; it is any of these together with the effect it has in a mind, that is, together with the psychical attitude to which it gives birth. Symbols are concepts, and to say that truth is a property of symbols is to say that it is a prop- erty of concepts. 1 T, Hobbes, Leviathan, Part I, ch. 4. 150 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH Truth, moreover, cannot be defined without some reference to reality or existence; ideas, thoughts, perceptions, are true when they present or represent what 7s. To apprehend a truth is to apprehend the existence of something meant. Thus knowledge from the outset is directed toward reality, and finally toward a metaphysical goal. Epistemological questions project them- selves toward metaphysics through the concept of truth. But one must approach metaphysics humbly. He must begin with a limited concept of the real, which he may alter or abandon in the light of further criticism; for a theory of the relation of knowledge to reality can have no basis except in an analysis of knowledge as a phenomenon, and this analysis leads to a limited notion of reality and of truth. The definition here set forth is of this sort. Truth as reference through symbols to existent objects may be a reference to ob- jects that are, metaphysically speaking, only “appearances”; or if these objects are not appearances, they may be objects that are not separable from knowledge, they may be mind-objects only. And there are many other metaphysical contingencies which the definition ignores — to which it is, in Mr. White- head’s phrase, “closed.” 1 It adopts a restricted concept of exist- ence, and this yields a restricted concept of truth, whose im- mediate claim to acceptance is that it is workable in science, mathematics, and every-day thought, whether or not it is finally able to withstand metaphysical scrutiny. II The examination of this definition — of the notion of exist- ence in terms of which it is stated, together with the tests of truth to which it gives rise — can be better understood if it is prefaced by an inquiry into another view of truth: the view that truth is not a property of symbols, but of entities which are 1 A. N. Whitehead, The Concept of Nature (1920), ch. 1. TRUTH AND FALSITY 151 neither symbols nor existing objects, yet which have a being in themselves. On this theory, it is to “propositions” that truth attaches, and a proposition is not thought of as a symbol or symbolic group coupled with the psychical set or intention it arouses in a mind. A proposition is independent of psychical processes; it is a meaning, but a meaning considered apart from its setting in a mind. It is something distinct from symbols, to which they refer, and yet it is not an object. The proposition thus conceived enters as a tertiwm quid between the symbols, in which it is con- veyed, and the datum or object, of which it is true. It is a wedge which opens the way for a new class of entities — subsistent en- tities — which are to be distinguished from objects. The pe- culiar manner in which these subsistents are apprehended is said to be conception; to conceive is to know something, to refer to something, but not to refer to an object. On this view, the initial reference of conception is to a subsistent proposition, and the proposition in its turn may or may not be directed toward an object. If the proposition is directed toward an object, if the tertium quid meant by the symbols exists as well as subsists, it is true; otherwise it is false. This theory purifies truth of all psychical elements. Truth and falsity are not determined in any sense by the act of thought; they belong only to these independent entities, which can be thought of but are not created by thinking. At the same time, truth and falsity are not taken to be properties of objects, so that the difficulties of one type of view, which says that there are “false objects,” are avoided. The most convincing arguments for the assumption of these subsistent entities are derived from the consideration of false and negative propositions. Mr. G. E. Moore puts the case for them in the following way: “How can a thing ‘appear’ or be ‘thought of’ unless it is there to appear or be thought of? To say 152 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH that it appears or is thought of, and yet that there is no such thing, is plainly self-contradictory. A thing cannot have a prop- erty unless it is there to have it. .. . When I think of a unicorn, what I am thinking of is certainly not nothing; if it were nothing then, when I think of a griffin, I should also be thinking of nothing, and there would be no difference between thinking of a priffin and thinking of a unicorn. But there certainly is a differ- ence; and what can the difference be except that in the one case what I am thinking of is a unicorn, and in the other a griffin? And if the unicorn is what I am thinking of, then there certainly must be a unicorn, in spite of the fact that unicorns are unreal. In other words, though in one sense of the word there certainly are no unicorns — the sense, namely, in which to assert that there are would be equivalent to asserting that unicorns are real — yet there must be some other sense in which there are such things; since, if there were not, we could not think of them.” } The status of propositions, on the view in question, is that of Mr. Moore’s unicorns and griffins; they are entities which are “‘there”’ in some sense, though plainly they are not “there”’ in another. They are objectives, which may be real or unreal; which subsist rather than exist.? Subsistence is a kind of being to which existence may be added, but to which existence is not necessary. In the realm of subsistence, the lion and the unicorn lie down together. To think of a lion or of a unicorn is to think of entities that partake equally of this impartial being, this thinner reality, which in- cludes the possible and the imaginary as well as the real. 1G. E. Moore, “The Conception of Reality,” in Philosophical Studies (1922), p. 215. 2 The terminology is that of A. Meinong’s gegenstandstheorie. Two among Meinong’s important works on this subject are: Untersuchungen zur Gegen- standstheorte und Psychologie (1904, Leipzig) (a collection of studies by several authors including Meinong), and Meinong’s Uber Annahmen (1902, Leipzig). - ee TRUTH AND FALSITY 153 Ii The concept of the “objective” springs from what appears to be a logical necessity in the analysis of meaning. Meaning must have an objective reference, and it is thought therefore that there must be a thing meant wherever there is significance. If meaning is reference to something —a relation in which the mind is only one term — unless this relation is to disappear, it must terminate in a referent. This is the idea behind Mr. Moore’s statement that “to say that (a thing) .. . is thought of, and yet that there is no such thing is plainly self-contradictory.” When the referent is a non-entity, it cannot (if the argument is pursued) cease to be a referent; it must therefore have some status. It is not nothing, for if it were the meaning relation would collapse, being deprived of one of its terms. Furthermore, the reference of symbols is not merely to psychi- cal states, to images, to the content of the mind. The very es- sence of the meaning activity is that through it the mind reaches out toward something other than its own states;1 and yet, if this “something” is to be grasped, it must be somehow given. It must have a being which allows it to be referred to when it is, in some sense, not a presented or existent content of the mind. It must be “‘there” in some way and not “there” in another; otherwise meaning loses its objectivity of reference and becomes intra-psychical in the narrowest meaning of the term. But the dilemma here is not so sharp as it appears. Objectiv- ity of reference does not require the assumption of subsistent (and sometimes unreal) entities as the second term of the mean- ing relation. The reference of a symbol, either simple or com- plex, can be directed beyond the mind’s content when the entity referred to is in no way presented or “‘there’’; and a complex 1 That is, toward something other than its own present states. This does not preclude the metaphysical hypothesis that all objects referred to are ulti- mately ‘“‘mental”’ in a wide sense of the term. 154 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH expression can have an objective reference when there is no ob- ject or objective to which the expression as a whole refers. Consider, first, the meaning of simple symbols which stand directly for objects. The theory of objectives assumes that these symbols, no less than complex expressions, have significance through reference to subsistent entities. It is not sufficient that the meaning relation shall have been grounded in an existent term; it must continue to be grounded in a subsistent one. Now, if to mean something is to intend it, to take an attitude of mind appropriate to it, the continued being in any sense — either as a subsistent or existent entity — of that which is meant is not necessary to the meaning. Indeed, anticipating or intending is just the sort of reference to objects that is compatible with the absence, as well as the presence, of what is referred to. Meaning is not a static relation between the mind and any sort of entity. It is an activity, and this activity has a direction away from the mind’s present content, whether or not there is a given object (or objective) in which it terminates. The direction of a meaning is determined once an object has been the terminus of the activ- ity; the activity continues to intend, to be appropriate to this object thereafter, when the object is absent or non-existent. It is sufficient therefore that the things which simple symbols mean shall have existed; the subsequent use of these symbols does not demand the persistence of their referents, either as subsistent objectives or existent objects. A meaning can be carried by an intention alone, and the reference does not lose its objective direction. A second type of meaning is that of complex expressions. If the mechanism of conception is analyzed (as it has been) into the grouping of symbols, the groups as a whole continue to refer, to mean — and to mean something other than a present psychical content — whether or not there exists or subsists an object or objective to which they refer. The meaning of a sym- TRUTH AND FALSITY 155 bolic group has been shown to be a function of other mean- ings, together with a scheme of logical structure. A number of subordinate meanings enter into a unity to form a new meaning, ‘ which cannot be described as a simple “‘mind-referring-to-ob- ject-or-objective,” as Mr. Moore would describe it; for the situation is made complex by a new factor — a plan of structure by which the symbolic elements are welded into a whole. If _ there is an object referred to, the reference is indirect. The sym- bolic group is a construction which is not taken, in its entirety, to stand for an object as a single word or proper name might be. From the direct references of the elements to things that exist or have existed, the mind fashions a secondary reference — a reference composed of references. Thus I build up the group, “the snow will melt to-morrow’”’; I join the several direct refer- ences of the words, whose meanings are determined by previous use, into a single indirect reference of a certain form; but I can know only to-morrow whether this secondary reference does or does not terminate, as a whole, in an object. If there is an object corresponding to the whole expression, this object will be both a unity and a plurality, a whole of parts; e.g., the unified fact, “the melting of the snow on the morrow.” But if there is no such unified object, the parts will still exist (or will have existed) as a plurality; e.g., there will be a to- morrow, and there have been snow and melting. Therefore the meaning of the group will be grounded in a reference to objects. The significance of the expression will be directed toward some- thing other than the present content of the mind, despite the fact that it corresponds in its entirety to nothing. It is in this sense that the false statement, “Shakespeare wrote The Critique of Pure Reason, has an objective reference. wrote,” “The Critique of Pure Reason,” stand 99 <¢ “Shakespeare, for objects. These references to existent things, or to things that _ have existed, lend objectivity of reference to the whole. They 156 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH give it a foundation in fact, though it corresponds to no fact. And since the symbolic elements of any significant group must stand directly for objects which exist (or have existed), or must be definable in terms of symbols which stand thus for objects, no symbolic group is without an existing locus of reference of the sort that the primary, direct act of meaning demands. The _ meaning of the group cannot collapse into a total absence of re- lation to the objective world, for the objects meant by the ele- ments of the group are in this world and thus determine the mind to have a direction beyond itself. This is not all. The plan of structure is no less objective than the constituents meant by the simple symbols, even if there is no fact which combines these constituents in this structure. The logical form intended is presented, and exists, in the symbolic expression as a universal of which the group is itself an instance. The structure meant is identical with the structure of the con- cept, that is, of the symbols; and it is equally as real, equally as objective, in its conceptual or symbolic instance as it would be in a non-conceptual or non-symbolic instance, for it is the same in both. The fixity of complex concepts arises from their logical form. Given a certain form in certain symbols whose individual mean- ings are determined, and the meaning of the concept is deter- mined. If there is an object whose elements are the ones meant by the simple symbols, and whose structure is identical with the structure devised by the mind for this group, this object will be the thing meant. But there need be no such object; the meaning is still fixed and still turned toward the world of objects. The mind, once it invents a concept, is bound by it. The concept seems to become external to thought, to pass over into a realm beyond the mind’s caprice; for the form of the concept, though it is constructed in thought, is a universal which may appear elsewhere. The constructive activity of the mind is exercised in a TRUTH AND FALSITY 157 medium which is not purely of the mind — in the medium of logical form. Instead, therefore, of saying that thought arbi- trarily assigns meanings to complex concepts, as it does to single words or signs, one can say that these concepts assign meanings to thought. The logical structure of the concept reaches out toward objects and, as it were, selects the one (if there is one) to which the concept corresponds. The structure of the concept means the structure of the fact because it is identical with the latter. And so the verification of a complex expression is a search in the direction of the objects meant by the constituents of the expression for an instance of the same logical form which is present in the expression. Thus the mind invents its concept but discovers their truth or falsity. IV The tertitum quid which, on the theory of subsistence, is as- sumed to intervene between symbols and their objects disap- pears in this analysis of meaning. It is absorbed in the symbols themselves. Meaning is not, as the theory of objectives would have it, what is referred to through symbols; it is the referring itself, that is, the meaning rather than the meant. And this act is always turned in the direction of existing objects, even though _ there may be no single object in which it finds its fulfillment; so that meaning does not become purely a relation of one psychical event to another. It is an act in which psychical events point beyond themselves, and symbols are the perceptible embodi- ments of this act. Not only are symbols the instruments of knowledge, they are of its very stuff. Mediate knowledge and a large part of immedi- ate knowledge are words, images, signs, taken with the effects of these in minds. There is no independent thing called “knowl- edge,’ which words, images, psychical attitudes, signs signify. _ The act of knowing itself, in so far as it is not pure awareness, is 158 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH the use of symbols. To assume that there is some such thing as the “proposition” or “objective,” which is the referent of sym- bols but which is itself neither a symbol nor an object, is to postulate a detached element of “meaning” as the terminus of thought. All attempts to catch this elusive and independent “meaning” end in the capture of images, of words, of attitudes or sets of the mind. The view that propositions are what sym- bols signify, that they are meanings apart from symbols and from the mind in which these symbols have significance, cuts off meaning and hypostatizes it, as if it might have being in itself; but this is as impossible as that a picture might exist without the canvas on which it is painted. The elimination of these subsistent entities subserves the end of economy of assumption. Truth is to be found in the two-term relation between symbols and objects; the proposition as a third entity is not needed. Symbols either signify existent objects or no objects, for the phrase “existent object” is a tautology, and the phrase “non-existent object” is a contradiction. The cate- gory of objectivity is not wider than the category of existence; there are no non-existent entities of any sort. And yet it is possi- ble to speak or think significantly without assuming an object thought or spoken of. It is this notion, that a concept need not have an object, which supports Kant’s refutation of the ontological proof of God and makes ontological arguments in general invalid. No concept implies the existence of an object conceived. But the theory of subsistence restores the ontological argument in a rare- fied form. Though one cannot, on this theory, argue from a con- cept to the existence of an object, he can always argue to the subsistence of an objective. “A thing must be in some sense to be thought of.” This gives every concept a referent with a being — a being which is often non-existence. A strange multiplication of ontological types! One sort of being should suffice. If a thing TRUTH AND FALSITY 159 does not exist it has no being; to speak of it as subsisting is merely to attempt to smuggle it back into reality, from which it has been once dismissed. An expression which “means a non-entity”’ stands, then, for no sort of entity; but it is still an expression which has signifi- cance and an objective reference, apart from the existence or subsistence of any corresponding referent. V. Under what conditions is reality or existence predicated of objects? What are the criteria of objectivity? The first criterion of existence, as the term is used in the present definition of truth, is perception. In perception, some- thing is given to the mind, there is a datum; and it is to this datum that existence belongs. And yet an uncriticized percep- tion does not guarantee the reality of its object. Dreams, illu- sions, hallucinations, are no less vivid and convincing than waking or normal presentations; they are no less perceptions in which something is given. But one cannot say that a dream object or an illusory object is really what it appears to be. Perception is complex; the datum is only one element in it. - What seems to be given as a datum may be largely the creation of concepts, of signs with their attendant mental attitudes, at work in the perception. For an object perceived is always an ) object meant, referred to, intended by, a concept. Concept and datum blend to form a presented whole, and what is merely in- tended or meant cannot easily be separated from what is given. Perceptions must be criticized, and only some of them can be accepted as presenting objects which are really what they seem to be. I am walking in a forest, let us say, and I see at some distance the body of a man across my path, which proves on closer in- spection to be the trunk of a fallen tree. What I first saw had the 160 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH appearance of being given; yet it could not have been wholly given or it would have resisted further examination. The percep- tion was an elaboration of data. Images, and perhaps unspoken words, together with their meanings, fused with the data; the mind automatically organized these elements into a whole, so that the data were presented under a concept — they were per- ceived through a meaning. Not only was this the case with the perception of the recumbent body; there is every reason to sup- pose that the perception of the tree-trunk was also an elabora- tion of data. Here, too, concepts were added to what was given, the data were viewed through a meaning, the presentation being no less complex; and if I believe the fallen tree-trunk to be a real object, it cannot be on grounds of its givenness alone. Perception is a union of sensation and conception. Sense data are the simplest observable elements in perception; with them the analysis of a presented whole comes to an end, though it is difficult (and often impossible) to disengage these sense data from their settings. The sense data are obviously supplemented by something non-sensory. They are signs which, in the lan- guage of Thomas Reid, “suggest” what is perceived. Take an extreme example: I hear a footstep outside my closed door and perceive that someone is about to enter the room. The sensory elements are plainly much less than the whole perception. The sound may not be a footstep, it merely “‘suggests” a footstep; and certainly it may not be the footstep of someone who is about to enter the room. This is clearly a conceptual addition to the sense data. Now what is true in the extreme case is true also in other cases. One perceives, for example, that it is raining; but the sensory constituents of this perception are not the whole fact, that it ts raining. There are sensations of dampness, of grayness, of cold, of faint vertical motions in the field of vision; and these sensations together with what they mean make up the fact. They awake in the mind, as do the words on a printed TRUTH AND FALSITY 161 page, certain intentions carried by images and half-uttered words; they cause one to take an attitude which is appropriate not only to dampness, to cold, to grayness, but to a whole of which these are parts; and thus they mean that it is raining. The effect of them is as if they caused one to formulate this proposition.! The sense data and the concepts, moreover, come into a pe- culiar unity in perception. They coalesce, and the elements that are sensed infect the conceptual elements, so that a large part of what is conceived seems also to be sensed. An excellent illustra- tion of this is the perception of space; we seem actually to see depth, though there is no doubt that much, if not all, of the per- ception of depth is a conceptual elaboration of sensory elements. The sense data are both signs to which concepts attach and parts of the objects which these concepts signify; and in the perception of a complex object or fact the sensory elements fall into their proper places as constituents of a whole which is both conceived and sensed.” The presented whole, nevertheless, has the appearance of simplicity. The fact that it 1s raining seems to be given in its en- 1 Reid adds that in perception we believe “‘irresistibly”’ in the reality of what is presented, and so perception becomes judgment, being conception joined to belief. But perception need not include belief. One often doubts the evidence of the senses; yet the doubt does not do away with the perception. Further, an illusory perception persists when it is disbelieved; this is indeed the very reason why it is illusory. It is nearer to the fact to say that we tend to believe our perceptions, that the perception tends to become a judgment, rather than that it is a judgment. Belief is a new attitude of mind, and one can withold belief in his perceptions. If perception produces immediate and “‘irre- sistible”’ belief, this is a belief that usually gives way to doubt — a belief that does not persist unless it is substantiated by other evidence than the givenness of the perception in question. See T. Reid, Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man, Essay II, especially ch. 10. 2 A thing, a complex object, is therefore much more than a class of sense data, as Mr. Russell describes it. It is a unity of sense data according to a definite plan of structure. The data enter into a conceptual scheme, they be- come parts of a meaning, and are at once signs and constituents of the object meant. For Mr. Russell’s view, see Our Knowledge of the External World (1914), ch. 4. 162 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH tirety; the tree-trunk appears to be presented as a solid, three- dimensional object; and even though the perception is known to be a fusion of data with concepts, an inspection of the presented object by itself does not readily separate what is conceptual from what is not conceptual. It may well be that the object ex- ists as it is perceived; that the very whole intended is given, as well as the sensory elements. The concepts may aid the mind to grasp what is actually a complex datum, rather than cut it off from a clear knowledge of the real object. And yet if the whole content of every perception is taken to be a datum, it is impos- sible to deny existence to the objects given in illusions, hallu- cinations, and dreams. If I dream that I am in Thibet and awake to find myself in my bed, I have been in Thibet and have been miraculously transported to my bed. The conclusion must be that, in some perceptions at least, only a part of the content is a datum; in illusory perceptions, the interpretation of the data, rather than the data themselves, creates the illusion. There is a compulsion in perception which is not found in con- ception, and this is why we conclude that a part, if not all, of the content of the perception is given to the mind and exists. No analysis of knowledge can ignore this compulsion of perceptions; this is their claim to be presentations of reality. Concepts can be altered at will so long as their references to perceptual objects are disregarded; they are inventions rather than data. But per- ceptions — even illusory and dream perceptions — are not purely invented. There may, to be sure, be some metaphysical sense in which the data of perception are created by mind; nothing may be completely independent of mind in the most in- clusive meaning of the term. The data of perception may be nothing more than lively and compelling psychical states — nothing more than Hume’s impressions; or they may be, as Berkeley would have us believe, thoughts in the Divine Mind. TRUTH AND FALSITY 163 But this dependence on mind in a wider sense would not render them, if they are truly data, any the less independent of thought in a narrower sense, that is, of the mind’s conceptual or sym- bolic activity as it has been described. If conceptual activity created objects, there would be a real object for every thought; ontological proofs could not be invalid; one could not think without thinking of the existent, and even a phenomenal dis- tinction between reality and illusion would disappear. Existing objects in the limited sense now in question are independent of concepts. Yet these objects are cognized in perceptions from which concepts are never absent. The most that can be said of the reality of a datum, apart from the concepts through which it is known, is that it exists as *‘something-or-other”’; and this is self-evident and trivial, for it asserts merely that it is a datum. Such an indefinite predication of existence is not yet the cognition of an object, and is not suffi- cient for organized knowledge. To apprehend the reality of an object is to apprehend more than the existence of “something- or-other,”’ more than reality in general, though this wholly un- specified reality is the only reality that givenness alone can con- firm. The “something”’ which is real must be perceived to be of a definite nature or in definite relations to other things; it must be placed in reality, as well as perceived simply to exist. It will then be brought under a concept; it will be apprehended through a meaning. No presentation can be dismissed as totally unreal, however illusory its content may be. In a dream, the dream places, peo- ple, events, are given to the mind and they exist. But they do not exist as physical realities; they are dream objects only. The fact that I perceive palaces, gardens, and praying fakirs in my dream of Thibet is no illusion; the illusion is that I perceive these as physical rather than dream realities. The deception 164 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH vanishes when the data are differently conceptualized — when the whole is placed in reality as a dream.’ When reality is predicated of what is given in perception, this is always a predication of something other than bare reality; it is a predication of reality of a definitely intended sort. If, on the contrary, the content of a perception is judged to be unreal, this judgment does not mean that it is unreal without qualification. It is unreal only under some concept, ¢.g., as a “physical” or “external” object, etc. Bare existence belongs to every datum, and the question for knowledge is: How can this existence be so conceptualized that it fits in with other existences? If perception were the apprehension of data and nothing more, everything would be what it is perceived to be, and given- ness in perception would be an absolute guarantee of the reality of the object given as it is given. But a presentation from which all conceptual elements were subtracted could be only an im- mediate awareness of a reality that could be named or char- acterized in no way. The datum would not be articulately expe- rienced; it would be intuited rather than perceived. Truth, as a property of symbols that mean existent objects, is not a refer- ence to reality as it might be known in pure immediacy, but a reference to perceived objects; and givenness in perception goes only part way toward assuring reality to such objects. VI Do not sensations guarantee the existence of their objects, if perceptions do not? Are not sense data “hard,” indubitable, and free from conceptual elaboration? 1 “Tife and dreams are leaves of the same book. The systematic reading of this book is real life, but when the reading hours (that is, the day) are over, we often continue idly to turn over the leaves, and read a page here and there without method or connection; often one we have read before, sometimes one that is new to us, but always in the same book. Such an isolated page is indeed out of connection with the systematic study of the book, but it does not seem so very different when we remember that the whole continuous perusal begins TRUTH AND FALSITY 165 Sensationalism and empiricism have been frequently con- fused. It has been taken for granted that what is given in ex- perience is given through the senses alone and that there are no data but sense data. And yet, search as we may for a pure sen- sation, one is never found. “A pure sensation is an abstraction.””? Sensations appear only in the context of perception, as the sim- plest elements of presented wholes. Experience itself is of “a teeming multiplicity of objects and events,” which cannot be reduced to or derived from elements so thin as sense data; and the attempt to do so is well characterized by James as “aban- doning the empirical method of investigation.” ? To recognize a sense datum is to observe that the complex objects of perception can be analyzed into simpler constituents, but this observation does not carry the implication that these complex objects are (or are known as) sense data and nothing else.* The table on which I write is brown, hard, and rectangular; it is cold and smooth to the touch; yet these sensations, by themselves, do not give the table I perceive. The perceived ob- ject is more than sensory elements; it is these “thought” or meant together into a whole. A pure sensation, or collection of pure sensations, if there could be any such thing, would be as near the negation of experience as anything imaginable. Short of a purely intuitive knowledge, which would be an awareness of no specific object or quality — not even of some- thing as definite as a sensory quality — there are no cognitions which do not make use of concepts. The elements in experience which psychologists call “sensations” only approximate toward pure sensations. The concepts through which the content of a and ends just as abruptly, and may therefore be regarded as merely a larger single page.” Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Idea, Bk. I, sec. 5. 1 W. James, The Principles of Psychology, ii, 1. 2 Op. cit., vol. i, ch. 9, p. 224. 3 The view which makes sense data the primary units of cognition speaks of objects, situations, facts, as “constructs” from sense data, but we are urg- ing that sense data are “‘destructs”’ from complex objects, situations, or facts. 166 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH sensation is apprehended may have been thinned down to a minimum; yet it cannot be maintained that concepts are wholly absent so long as sense data are known as specific qualities, so long even as they are definitely attributed to the senses. The very predicate “sensation” conceptualizes them. The cognition of objects, qualities, events, no matter how simple, is never any- thing less than recognition; the mind intends, takes an attitude appropriate to, the things it senses, and thus recognizes them as things meant. A bare sensation, ¢.g., of red, does not spring into my mind without a concept to meet it. My mind is prepared for knowing red, and the sense datum stands forth from the back- ground of purely immediate knowledge because “red” is what I mean as well as what I sense. And if I mean “red,” a sign of some sort is present. There is an image or an incipient vocal ut- terance, etc., which carries what is in effect the proposition, “this is red.” Through the concept, the sense datum becomes a part of my articulated knowledge. Sensation then “differs from perception only in the extreme simplicity of its object or con- tent’’; ! and the outer limit of knowledge is not sensation but the pure awareness, or intuition, which surrounds the whole act of concrete knowing.” Since conception is present everywhere in knowledge within this outer limit, the richer experience of objects, events, situa- tions, facts, has no less a claim to be taken as a datum, which exists as experienced, than have sensations. The true empiri- cism is not sensationalism. The true empiricism accepts the con- tent of presentations in their wholeness and makes what it can of them, rather than analyzing out the sensory aspects and de- nying reality to all that remains. Sensationalism does violence to experience and is the shortest road to scepticism, for, if only the impermanent and insubstantial data of the senses exist, reality speedily dissolves into a flight of subjective shadows. 1 W. James, loc. cit. 2 See below, ch. VIII, sec. xii. TRUTH AND FALSITY 167 The fact that experience in the full meaning of the term ap- pears only when concepts, that is, thoughts and their references, enter in cognition, does not make it necessary to hold that these conceptual factors cut us off from reality. Concepts may facili- tate as well as hinder the apprehension of data, for it is only by means of concepts that the passing sensation is arrested and experienced as an aspect of an object. When a landscape is be- fore me, I know through the concepts that I am experiencing trees, mountains, and a river, rather than a mere flow of sensa- tions. The concepts may cause me to come into a closer cogni- tive relation to the real, instead of causing me to misinterpret and misconceive the real. Thought is not a veil separating the mind from what exists. Kant shattered Locke’s conception of the mind as a tabula rasa; he made it evident that mind is active not passive in per- ception. Even Locke faltered in his “‘blank-sheet”’ sensational- ism. The mind, which, like a dark room with a single window high in the wall, has at the beginning of Locke’s Essay only one aperture of light, sensation, is discovered in the end to gain most of its “complex ideas” from comparing, relating, and abstract- ing the “ideas” which enter through the senses. The mind is found to be active. Knowledge will not submit to the tabula rasa description. At every point in experience, thought — organization in a conceptual scheme — is at work. Concepts, symbols and their intentions, bridge the gaps between this experience and that, between disorganized sensory presentations and integrated per- ceptions; and empirical reality — reality in the sense in which we are now speaking of it —comes into knowledge through what might be called “presentational thinking.” The view that thought isolates the mind from reality and leaves a thing-in-itself shivering in the empty noumenal spaces ‘beyond experience, might possibly be true for an ultimate real- 168 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH ity. But Kant himself insists that the objects of experience, if they are “transcendentally ideal,” are “empirically real.” They are given in presentational thought, and this is their empirical reality. Whether or not reality is, in the last resort, inaccessible to thought, there must be some sense of the term “reality” which makes the real accessible to thought; otherwise there would be no objects of perception. Objects are capable of exist- ing, in this meaning of the term, as they are perceived through concepts — as presented wholes of definite characters or in definite relations; and truth is reference to these objects. Thought, therefore, may cause knowledge to approach the real, or it may remove it from the real. Truth in perception is possible for the same reason that illusion (or falsity) is possible; because thought is a constituent of perception. And for this rea- son, likewise, no perception in itself attests the existence of its object as it is perceived. Vil The second criterion of existence, which is a necessary supple- ment to givenness in perception, is consistency — consistency with the whole of our organized knowledge. By means of this criterion, the data of any single perception are fitted in with other data and given a place in reality, as well as judged barely to exist. At the same time, this criterion permits us to infer with more or less certainty, depending on the strictness of the inference, the existence of objects not given in perception.’ (That this criterion of existence — consistency with the whole of knowledge — does not render our definition of truth circular will be presently shown.) 1 This metaphysical hypothesis, however, is extremely unstable, since the thing-in-itself can be positively characterized in no way. It is an x, of which one can say nothing more than that it does not appear in any experience; it is something other than any possible object of experience. See below, ch. VIII, sec. iii. t The whole problem of the validity of induction is involved here. But if any inductions are true, the objects they refer to exist. TRUTH AND FALSITY 169 The axiom that there can be no inconsistency in the real is open to several interpretations, each of which turns on a differ- ent notion of reality. Consistency and inconsistency are relations between propo- sitions or concepts — that is, between symbols. By definition, p and q are inconsistent if, when one of them is true, the other is never true. No two true propositions are inconsistent. Now, on the assumption that an existent object is not a proposition or a concept, it follows that the real cannot be truly said to be eithor consistent or inconsistent, though the concepts through which it is viewed give it the appearance of consistency or inconsistency, The thorough-going rationalist, if he grants that reality is not conceptual or propositional, will still believe that a complete knowledge of the real through propositions would be a consistent knowledge. He will postulate that reality is consistent in the sense that it can be consistently conceptualized, even though it is other than concepts. The anti-rationalist, on the contrary, will assert that no consistent or inconsistent body of proposi- tions is adequate to reality; that the real is wholly beyond con- ceptual knowledge and is known no less truly through incon- sistent propositions than through consistent ones — for, to the anti-rationalist, neither could represent reality. Thus the thesis of any one of the Kantian antinomies tells us as much, or as little, about the Kantian reality as the antithesis; and M. Berg- son joyfully embraces contradictions as a means of leading the mind to intuitions, not because reality is contradictory but be- cause it is beyond the grasp of concepts and propositions. “In attempting to describe what we know in the abstract logical terms which are the only means of intercommunication that human beings possess, Bergson is driven into perpetual self- contradiction, indeed, paradoxical though it may sound, unless he contradicted himself his description could not be true.” ! 1 K. Stephen, The Misuse of Mind (1922), p. 12. 170 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH Each of these interpretations of the axiom of the consistency of the real — the rationalistic and the anti-rationalistic — refers to an unlimited, an ultimate, reality. But the reality we have been considering is limited, and the very principle of its limita- tion is that it must be capable of being consistently presented and represented. If there are realities which cannot be consist- ently conceptualized, these are real in some more extended sense. One cannot deny Kantianism or Bergsonianism unless it be on metaphysical grounds; nor can he affirm the complete con- sistency, the rationality, of the real. It may be that empirical- rational knowledge floats on the surface of a world whose depths are reached neither in perception nor in thought. Yet it is possi- ble to go some distance with a less extended notion of the real, which makes reality rational but does not preclude a final “ir- rationalism.” We mean then by a real object one which can be given in (or inferred from) an experience which is consistent with the whole of knowledge. Such real objects can be known through concepts, as these concepts enter in perception; and if an object given in perception is really what it appears to be, its characters and re- lations will not have been created by the act of conception. A real object is independent of concepts, though it may not be in- dependent of mind on a much wider interpretation of this term. Moreover, these real objects must have a structure; otherwise, they could not be known through concepts, nor could they be consistently assimilated to the whole of knowledge. These are all necessary conditions of the reality of an object, in the present limited sense, but it must be observed that they are not sufficient conditions. The whole of knowledge might conceivably be false, and then none of the objects presented in such a consistent experience would be really what they are per- ceived to be. The most we could truly say of them would be that they had a bare existence, that they were not non-entities. And TRUTH AND FALSITY 171 so we have not completely defined even this limited reality; we have merely laid down certain conditions which it must fulfil, we have confined it within certain boundaries. It remains still a basic and undefined term, necessary to the analysis of truth. VIII For Kant the limits of experience were marked by the cate- gories, which were necessary principles of thought, implicit in the act of judgment itself. But Kant’s categories are empty of content. The consistency of empirical-rational knowledge is more than a purely formal consistency, more than fidelity to the laws of logic — even of “transcendental logic.” Everything that can be thought or experienced will, it is true, obey these formal laws, but obedience to the laws of logic alone is no criterion of existence. The touchstones of the reality of what is presented to us are general truths which cannot be derived from the princi- ples of logic. They are categories, but not categories which are implicit in the nature of thought; no a priori deduction of them is possible; they are always subject to revision. First among these “empirical categories” can be placed the generalizations of common sense that is, prescientific generali- zations: nothing is ever both crooked and straight, round and square, black and white; nothing is ever before something else and at the same time after this same thing; nothing is ever out- side something and at the same time within it; everything has a cause; water does not flow up-hill — and countless other princi- ples which do not follow from the postulates of logic but which operate in determining the reality of objects. When I awake from a dream of the other ends of the earth, though the experi- ence has been sufficiently vivid to convince me of its physical reality, I conclude that I was dreaming; for I could not have been in two such distant places as the remote regions of the earth and my own bed at so nearly the same time. The dream is 172 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH inconsistent with common-sense physical categories. So long as I conceive these events as physically real I am unable to place them in experience without contradiction. All well-established scientific principles operate in the same way as the generalizations of common sense in determining the reality of given objects. It is assumed that if an object is really spatial or numerical in its nature it will not violate the principles of geometry or arithmetic; that no material reality would trans- gress the laws of mechanics, and no chemical reality the laws of chemistry. Every new generalization, every new theory, adds a further category under which reality is predicated of presented objects; so that experience both tests and is tested by scientific and prescientific generalizations. Laws, theories, and the facts on which laws and theories are built mutually correct one an- other. A generalization is verified by the existence of an object which conforms to it in a special instance, or by the empirical reality of something which can be deduced from it. At the same time, presented objects are accepted as real because they are perceived as special instances or consequences of general princi- ples. The criterion of the truth of theories is empirical reality, and the criterion of empirical reality, the truth of theories. We may be mistaken in our perceptions themselves, or in the assumptions, the body of theory, by which we estimate the real- ity of what is given in perception, or in both. It is always possi- ble that a new set of categories may completely overturn all previous estimations of reality. Yet the fact that all perceptions and all judgments are subject to error does not make it neces- sary to believe that no perceptions, no judgments, give us real- ity. When a presentation is consistent with the whole body of knowledge, the presumption is overwhelmingly in favor of the presented object being really what it is perceived to be. We can 1 “Theory” is here taken to mean any principle or body of principles that exceeds the given. TRUTH AND FALSITY 173 attain no more certainty than this. There is no self-evident, un- deniable badge of reality — unless it be of bare existence. The categories that operate in fixing the places of presented objects in reality are not a priorz and unalterable principles of reason, blank forms of perception and judgment. They are accepted universal truths which are themselves subject to error. The mediaeval philosopher who, when he was asked to view the spots on the sun through a telescope, replied — “‘I have read Aristotle many times and I assure you that there is nothing of the kind mentioned by him; be certain therefore that the spots which you have seen are in your eyes and not in the sun” — was cor- rect in method though not in fact. His categories were anti- quated, but within these categories his reality was consistent. A nice balance of theory and fact is for science the very prin- ciple of its life. And if the “delicate, contentious, and fantasti- cal”’ learning of the Middle Ages bore no fruit but the delight in speculation for its own sake, the worship of fact alone cannot bring forth even this fruit. Knowledge is a growing whole of fact and theory. IX If truth is the correspondence of concepts or symbolic expres- sions with existent objects, and an existent object is one given in a perception that is consistent with the whole of knowledge, is not the definition of truth completely circular? It would be circular if consistency with the whole of knowl- edge were identical with existence, that is, if concepts created their own objects. But this is not the case. The existent is in- dependent of the concepts through which it is known. Truth as a property of symbolic expressions, and existence as a property of objects, are not the same. Though existence can be definitely predicated of objects only if certain general truths are consist- ently applied in experience, the objects to which these truths 174 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH refer stubbornly resist being reduced to thought-creations. They are data given to thought but not invented by it, and truth is reference to reality, not reality itself. Consistency with the whole of knowledge is therefore a test of existence and of truth, but it constitutes neither truth nor ex- istence. Clearly, if truth is the correspondence of concepts with existing objects, no true generalization could be inconsistent with a perception of existing objects. True generalizations would necessarily become tests of existence. But the existence of objects would not thereby become a function of the truth of these generalizations; nor would the truth of these generaliza- tions be merely their consistency with perceptions of existing objects. The tests of truth follow from the definition; they are not equivalent to the definition. Moreover, the consistency which is a function of the truth of propositions ! could not define truth, for 2és definition presup- poses the idea of truth. And if consistency means, as it other- wise would, “conceivability” apart from truth or falsity, this is equally far from being truth. One can invent an infinity of con- sistent systems of concepts, if consistency is a matter of con- ceivability, of definition, alone. Such systems remain non-con- tradictory so long as the ideas in them are used with the original definitions, and so long as the general principles of the construc- tion of concepts are observed. But there is no compulsion, no reason other than caprice, for defining an idea in one way rather than another. The consistency of such a system gives it no refer- ence to reality; it places it merely as one among an infinity of “possibilities for thought.” If I find perceptual objects that can be consistently conceptualized in the propositions of such a sys- tem, the system has passed one test of truth; and if I further discover that it is consistent with the whole of accepted knowl- 1 p and q are consistent if there is a case in which both are true, and incon- sistent if, when the one is true, the other is never true. — nl ——- —~- -~+ TRUTH AND FALSITY 175 edge, it has passed another. Its truth is as nearly established as possible. But the proof of truth and truth itself are different things. The truth of the system is its correspondence to reality. D4 The pursuit of “conceivability”” as a definition of truth leads to the “coherence” theory, in which conceivability finally tran- scends the limits of all ordinary thought. The essence of the cor- respondence theory is that it holds thought and reality apart, and the essence of the coherence theory, that it identifies them — that truth, reality, and conceivability become one. Coher- ence, as the term is used in this theory, is more than the con- sistency of a single science or of all sciences. It is an ideal of knowledge beside which all else is fragmentary and “mutilated,” and to which no finite knowledge attains. This is made plain by Mr. H. H. Joachim, who carefully dis- tinguishes coherence from consistency: “The ‘systematic co- herence,’ therefore, in which we are looking for the nature of truth, must not be confused with the ‘consistency’ of formal logic. A piece of thinking might be free from self-contradiction, might be ‘consistent’ and ‘valid’ as the formal logician under- stands those terms, and yet it might fail to exhibit that syste- matic coherence which is truth.” ! For Mr. Joachim, to be “con- ceivable” and “coherent” means to be “a significant whole”; and ultimately there is only one significant whole — the Ideal Experience, which is Reality. Nothing short of knowledge of this Whole, this Absolute, is Truth. There are no separable truths. A single isolated proposition is partly true and partly false; it is incomplete, and no more than a faltering step toward the perfection of knowledge — the one Truth. Mr. Russell, in criticising Mr. Joachim, pointedly asks : Is the theory itself, being not the whole of knowledge, wholly true? 2 1 H. H. Joachim, The Nature of Truth (1906), p. 76. ? B. Russell, Philosophical Essays (1910), p. 150. 176 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH Mr. Joachim’s examination of truth proves one thing cer- tainly: that truth, as it appears in empirical knowledge, in sci- ence and every-day thought, and in the despised reasoning of the formal logician, is not the truth he is speaking of; that a metaphysical criticism of knowledge passes beyond — and it may be reverses — a descriptive epistemology. The objections that Mr. Joachim levels against correspond- ence are instructive; they illuminate the nature of this relation.’ He points out that any correspondence must be a correspond- ence of the structure of wholes as well as of their elements. Each element must play the same part, fulfil the same functions, as the corresponding element in the other whole; and thus the two must be identical in structure. But he concludes that it is im- possible to make out any such correspondence between per- ceived wholes and conceptual or propositional wholes, giving as his reason for this that: “‘On the one side, we have a whole of experience at the level of feeling; and, on the other side, a whole of experience at the level of reflective thought. To say that there is (or may be) identity of structure is to maintain that these ex- periences are different matters subsumed under an identical form ... the idea of an identical structure in different materials is quite inadequate when applied to the wholes in question, wz., felt- and thought-wholes.” ? The conclusion which Mr. Joachim rejects is exactly the one that the analysis of logical form has led us to accept. Concepts, symbolic expressions, and presented objects are indeed “differ- ent matters subsumed under an identical form.” A perceived 1 There is no doubt, as Mr. Joachim shows, that unless reality — or a kind of reality — were present in knowledge, the notion of truth as correspondence to existent objects would be an unworkable hypothesis. Locke, for instance, seems to be beating thin air when he describes truth as the reference of ideas to unknowable objects beyond ideas. Yet even this theory cannot be shown to be false. The most serious accusation that can be brought against it is that it is quixotic; that it is impossible to apply the definition as a test of truth. 2 Op. cit., pp. 26, 29. TRUTH AND FALSITY 177 whole is not merely “felt”’; perception is not on the level of pure awareness in which nothing articulate is given. Objects are per- ceived as having a certain structure, their elements are given as grouped in a definite order, they are composed of major and minor groups of distinct and recognizable forms. Reality, in the present sense, is rationally presented in that it is analyzable, in that its form is presented with it. And what Mr. Joachim calls the structure of “reflective thought” is embodied in the group- ing of the symbols in which the thought is expressed. The iden- tity of form in propositions (symbolic groups) and perceived objects brings about the correspondence of “reflective thought”’ with fact, which is truth. Correspondence it is true implies a distinctness, a separate- ness or externality of the corresponding wholes. Yet in percep- tion there is no separation of the concept, which is a constituent of the presentation, from the datum. Datum and concept cannot be disengaged and compared. Must one say that here the rela- tion is no longer correspondence, that datum and concept be- come one in “presentational thought,” where the margin of dis- tinctness between them is so narrowed that the object is given along with (or through) the proposition which is true of it? This is undoubtedly Mr. Joachim’s view; a perception, he believes, is already at the level of “reflective thought”; there is nothing ex- ternal to the perception to which it can correspond. A pure concept, that is, a proposition whose object is not given in perception along with it (or through it), is, on the other hand, clearly distinct from its object and can be said to corre- spond to the object; e.g., ““Napoleon escaped from Elba”’ is purely conceptual, its object does not accompany it, and hence there is no difficulty in describing its truth as correspondence to fact. Scientific theories, generalizations, historical statements, memories, predictions — the larger part of knowledge — are purely conceptual; such propositions are distinct from the ob- 178 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH jects of which they are true and can be said to correspond to these objects. But, as Mr. Joachim points out, this is an unim- portant type of correspondence, and it cannot be truly said to be correspondence — but is rather coherence — unless the truths of perception can be likewise shown to be genuine cases of corre- spondence. There is no doubt that in perception the proposition and the object cannot be torn apart, the concept fits the object as the die fits its cast, the two coincide as superimposed figures in ge- ometry might; and the only evidence of a discrepancy is the in- consistency of the perception with other experiences. Yet the relation however close must still be correspondence when the concept is true, for so long as the concept and the object are not identical they are distinct. One would be justified in giving up the notion of correspondence only on the hypothesis that the proposition and the datum are the same. And this is the funda- mental reason beneath the objections of the coherence theory to correspondence as a definition of truth: the coherence theory wishes to eliminate the distinction between thought, or concep- tion, and reality. Certainly if an existent object is identical with a coherently thought object, it is absurd to speak of truth as the correspondence of concepts with existent objects. But existence must be independent of concepts, where conception is anything short of the coherent — and unattainable — thought which is, for Mr. Joachim, Reality; especially, where conception is the significant use of symbols. For if existence were identical with conception, every thought would refer to a real object. We could not escape thinking of the existent; there would be no falsity. Since the existent and the conceptual are distinct, their relation is correspondence, however narrow the margin of separation for knowledge between them; nor does identity of structure make the proposition and its object one. The notion that the structure of thought is found in the sym- TRUTH AND FALSITY 179 bols it uses to express itself and that this same structure perme- ates the world of real objects, at least the real objects which can be presented in a consistent experience; the further notion that these real objects are not identical with concepts and yet can be apprehended only by the use of concepts, though they may in this way — even in perception — be apprehended falsely; these ideas give a complete and simple meaning to the definition of truth as the correspondence of concepts to reality. At the same time, the notion of syntactical significance, of meaning which is directed toward the world of objects yet need not terminate in a single object or fact, permits propositions to be false without robbing them of their significance. Truth becomes in a literal sense a property of symbols, for propositions and concepts are symbols or symbolic groups as they function in minds. All this is implicit in Hobbes’s statement that “‘true and false are attri- butes of speech, not of things . . . truth is the right-ordering of names.” XI Since meaning alone is all that is necessary to truth and fal- sity, belief and disbelief, assertion and denial —in short judg- ment — fall outside the discussion of truth and falsity proper. Yet from one point of view, judgment is closely connected with truth, for no truth is genuinely known until it is judged or be- lieved. To know truth is to judge, but to be in doubt, to enter- tain ideas without assertion, to perceive without believing, is not to know truth. Assertion and denial, belief and disbelief, are secondary atti- tudes toward propositions. They supervene on the primary atti- tude of understanding, which is that of holding the proposition, the symbol or group of symbols, before the mind with a con- sciousness of their reference but without regard to whether or not there is an object to which they refer. To understand is to frame a hypothesis, to put one’s self in a state of inward prepa- 180 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH ration for an object when the mind is still in doubt as to the ex- istence of such an object; and here the attitude of understanding ends, or else passes by a gradual transition into that of belief. To believe an idea was, for Hume, to have it vividly present in consciousness; but the vividness of ideas is a cause of belief rather than belief itself. It is certainly true that a lively percep- tion of an object or an especially clear understanding of a propo- sition tends to become a belief. Entertain an idea for a suffi- ciently long time and you will believe it; 1 for belief is of the same mental genus as understanding. Both are preparations for objects, both are intentions of the mind with a direction beyond the mind’s present content. Belief differs only in being a more complete preparation, a more earnest intention. Belief is readi- ness to act as if the proposition which is understood meant an existent object. It is willingness to use the proposition as if it were true. As against Hume’s notion that belief is the vividness, insist- ence, or compulsion of ideas, it is only necessary to observe that one may suffer from a vivid illusion without believing that the illusory content is what it appears to be. Though one tends to believe anything he understands (or its negative, which is sug- gested by it), and particularly to believe what is given in percep- tion, still there is a point of transition between entertaining an idea or being presented with a content, and believing in the truth of this idea or the existence of this content. This transition cannot be described as a passage to clear understanding or vivid presentation, for the understanding may be already clear, the presentation already vivid. It is a transition to a new state of mind, to a state of mind which has something in common with the apprehension of meanings or of presented contents, but is nevertheless distinct. The existence or non-existence of the things our thoughts 1 Or believe its negative, which is suggested by it. TRUTH AND FALSITY 181 mean, the truth or falsity of concepts, adapts these concepts to uses which would not otherwise be possible. A true proposition can be employed as a premise in an inference in a way in which a proposition merely entertained cannot be employed. The truth and falsity of ideas makes possible a calculable and suc- cessful commerce with the world of fact; so that the value of truth is, in the first place, practical. Yet if truth is good as a means toward other ends, it is also good in itself — as an end toward which a certain intellectual interest is directed. But there is an intellectual interest which is wider than the interest in truth: this is the interest in possibilities, in fancies or fictions for their own sake. The apprehension of significance, that is, of possibilities for thought (constructive imagination) is the primary function of the intellect, and if the truth of these possibilities added to them no qualities of use or attraction, thought would end in hypothesis. There would be no judgment; the existence or non-existence of objects meant would be of no moment. To the dreamer, the truth of his dream is irrelevant; to the believer, the truth of his belief is indispensable, for the mo- tive of belief is the interest in truth. Thus beyond judgment lies pure speculation; add the interest in truth, which is the widest — the most impractical — of practical interests, and you add belief. XII Belief is more than the thought of existence coupled to a con- cept, and this is another reason why it must be regarded as a new attitude of mind, distinct from (though continuous with) conceiving and perceiving, however vivid and clear. To assert and believe that “Shakespeare wrote Hamlet” is not to entertain the thought of “the existence of Shakespeare’s authorship of Hamlet,” for this is itself a concept and not a belief. Belief and assertion take a step that carries the mind beyond conception; 182 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH they leap the gap between conception and existence by trans- forming the hypothetical into the categorical. This is strikingly put by Hume in a passage in which he also shows that a single concept (that is, on our view, a single word or symbol) can be true or false and can be affirmed or denied. He comments on the accepted definitions of conception, judgment, and reasoning as follows: “‘ Conception is defined to be the simple survey of one or more ideas: judgment to be the separating or | uniting of different ideas: reason to be the separating or uniting of different ideas by the interposition of others, which show the relation they bear to each other. But these distinctions are faulty in very considerable articles. For, first, it is far from being true, that, in every judgment which we form, we unite two different ideas; since in that proposition, God is, or indeed any other which regards existence, the idea of existence is no distinct idea, which we unite with that of the object, and which is capable of forming a compound idea by the union. Secondly, as we can thus form a proposition which contains only one idea, so we can exert our reason without employing more than two ideas... . Whether we consider a single object or several; whether we dwell on these objects, or run from them to others; and in whatever form or order we survey them, the act of the mind exceeds not a simple conception; and the only remarkable difference which occurs on this occasion is when we join belief to conception, and are per- suaded of the truth of what we conceive.” ! As for Hume’s first point, judgment is undoubtedly more than a union of the idea of existence with a concept. The onto- logical proof of God fails to produce belief because it is apparent that the addition of the idea of existence to that of God does not make the latter any the less a concept. But Hume, who is con- firmed by Kant on this point, is not wholly correct in saying that ‘*the idea of existence is no distinct idea, which we unite with 1D. Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, vol. i, part iii, sec. 7, note. TRUTH AND FALSITY 183 that of an object.” It is possible to conceive of the existence, or for that matter of the non-existence, of something meant; e.g., “the non-existence of the round-square”’ is an intelligible ex- pression. Existence can be a predicate, even if it is the most gen- eral possible predicate. The important fact is that, although ez- astence is a predicate which can be added to concepts, belief goes further than the addition of predicates to concepts. It com- pletely removes the concept from the area of the hypothetical. The second point made by Hume in this passage is of special interest in connection with the present definition of truth. Hume declares that a single idea or concept can be judged and can be true or false, though truth is usually thought to belong only to propositions and it is not customary to give the name “propo- sition”’ to anything less than what is expressed in a complete sentence. “God,” “evil,” “the king of England,” and similar fragmentary expressions are not commonly said to exhibit truth or falsity. But the difference between a word or a phrase and a full sentence is not that the one is capable of being true or false, while the other is not; the difference is that the one (usually) embodies an assertion or a denial, while the other embodies something merely understood, assumed, held before the mind without assertion or denial. “‘God is,’”’ “‘evil is,” are assertions of what is meant by “God” and by “evil.”’ The single words (unasserted) are therefore as much entitled to be taken as propo- sitions (unasserted) as are any completed sentences.! 1 Whether we are to name single words and incomplete phrases “propo- sitions,”’ is a verbal question. The term “proposition,” if one so wishes, can be reserved for complex expressions which have the completeness of full sen- tences. But this will not alter the fact that the less complex expressions are either true or false. Propositions — even if they are held always to be complex, a union of subject, predicate, and copula — are unities which are affirmed and denied as wholes, and which are true and false as wholes. The subject-predi- cate logic, which asserts that the predicate is affirmed or denied of the subject, that it is true or false of the subject, breaks un the unity of the proposition and is at a loss to restore it. Yet this unity must be restored if there is to be truth. A proposition composed of a subject, predicate, and copula is true only if both 184 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH For some symbols, then, — for those which refer directly to objects and are not merely defined through symbolic groups, — truth and significance are the same thing. Knowledge, being built on elementary simple symbols which refer thus to objects, takes its rise from true concepts or “true symbols,” and falsity, which appears later, rests on truth. Only when a kind of signifi- cance which is other than a direct reference to objects is devised does falsity become possible. But any symbol, either simple or complex, is either true or false, and a full sentence differs from a fragmentary phrase or a single word only in that the former is asserted or judged, while the latter is (usually) simply considered or understood. XIII Just as the primary attitude of understanding is carried by symbols, so also is the secondary attitude of belief. Beliefs do not hang in mid-air cut off from expression. One believes when he expresses this attitude by some sign to himself or to others, and since belief is readiness to act, a natural and common sign of belief is action. I know that I believe most of my perceptions because I act as if what appears in them were really what it seems to be; moreover, I am often unaware of what I believe un- til I assert it, which shows that belief is inseparably bound to its expressions. the subject and predicate mean something existent, and — what is more im- portant still — only if there is an existent whole in which the predicate is united by the relation of predication to the subject. The fact that the propo- sition can be broken up into a subject, predicate, and copula is not therefore the reason for its being true or false. This necessary unity of meaning in a proposition suggests that the term “‘proposition” can be used for any whole which has a unified meaning, and this would not exclude single words or in- complete phrases. We might speak of a single word as an “‘unanalyzed propo- sition” in contrast to all symbolic groups, which would be “‘analyzed propo- sitions.”” Among analyzed propositions we should need to distinguish descrip- tive phrases as a special class. On this more extended interpretation of the term, a proposition would be any unified meaning; and since on our view meanings are carried only by symbols, it would be any symbol or group of symbols taken in its function as an instrument of significance. TRUTH AND FALSITY 185 Assertion is so closely related to belief that it is impossible sharply to distinguish them. If there is any difference it is this: that assertion is the inward or outward expression of belief by a sign, while belief itself is the attitude expressed. A full sentence always contains a sign of belief: ““money is the root of all evil” stands for two things, for the fact and the belief in the propo- sition; while “money’s being the root of all evil” signifies the same fact without the belief. (The passage from consideration to belief is often marked in thought by the insertion of the verb “is,” or its equivalent, in the train of inward speech which passes and repasses in the mind.) If one openly asserts some- thing he does not believe, the presence of the sign of assertion is nevertheless calculated to produce belief in others. The copula or any symbolic element equivalent to the copula has a triple réle in judgment. Its primary function is to call at- tention to the truth of the proposition in which it appears, to signify that this proposition is believed or ought to be believed. Secondly, it indicates the unity of the whole, though it is not necessary that the copula be present in order that the propo- sition be taken as a whole; the syntactical signs give the sym- bolic group its unity of meaning. Thirdly, the copula adds the predicate existence to the concept. But of these three functions, the first — as a sign of assertion — is the essential one.! XIV Belief and disbelief appear, on first thought, to be direct opposites which are related to one another as desire is to aver- sion, approach to withdrawal, or acceptance to rejection. Yet disbelief cannot be the witholding of belief, for this is under- standing or consideration without belief or disbelief, without affirmation or denial. Nor can it be the dismissal of the propo- 1 There is still a fourth meaning of the copula: its use to signify identity, e.g., “Scott zs the author of Waverley.” 186 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH sition disbelieved as meaningless, for an idea must be enter- tained if it is disbelieved. Disbelief if more than the suspension of judgment, the refusal to commit oneself. It is as affirmative as belief. “The true opposites of belief, psychologically considered, are,” in the opinion of William James, “‘doubt and inquiry, not disbelief”; 1 and this suggests that disbelief is really a species of belief. Disbelief is a belief in the falsity of a proposition, that is, that there is no existing object corresponding to it; and thus dis- belief is a belief in the truth of the proposition “‘p is false.”’ By the principle of the excluded middle, either p or not-p is true, so that “‘p is false” is equivalent to “not-p is true,” and “‘p is true” is equivalent to “not-p is false.’’ Hence to disbelieve a propo- sition, to believe that “‘p is false,”’ is in effect to believe its nega- tive. (And the converse is also true; to believe a proposition is in effect to disbelieve its negative.) Disbelief, instead of being the negation of a belief, is the belief of a negation. But if belief is an attitude of preparation, completer prepara- tion than understanding, for an object intended by a proposi- tion, how can one believe a negative? Are there negative ob- jects? Can one act as if something negative were in existence? For this is what belief in a negative would require. If I assert that “I have not been in China” and expect this proposition to be believed, the assertion must refer to some objective content to which the belief can be fastened. Negatives must have a point of attachment to existing objects. This being the case, denials will take a place beside assertions as positive judgments which are equally useful in inference and equally necessary in bringing about successful adjustments to the world of fact. Full-blown disbelief differs from belief only in the nature of the content toward which it is directed; it is not a different attitude of mind. Every proposition tends to suggest its negative. To under- 1 W. James, Psychology, vol. ii, ch. 21, p. 284. TRUTH AND FALSITY 187 stand the meaning of a proposition is also to understand the meaning of its negative, and hence the intention which carries the significance may as readily pass over into disbelief as belief. To entertain the idea of p is also to entertain the idea of not-p: it is to be in readiness for two mutually exclusive contingencies. The added psychical pressure of belief may be in the direction of one or the other, but in either case this new attitude of mind will be continuous with, not opposed to, the attitude in which the idea is merely understood or considered as a possibility. When it is said that any idea which is understood tends natu- rally to be believed, this means that either its positive or nega- tive tends to be believed; in other words, that the tendency to belief is always present in understanding but forks toward the two alternatives, one of which is disbelief. There is, on the other hand, a frame of mind in which one ex- periences an intellectual aversion toward accepting either the truth or falsity of ideas, in which he says “no” without affirm- ing or denying the proposition thus met; an attitude of simple incredulity, appropriate to strange phenomena or extraordinary concepts. It is this attitude which is directly opposed to belief. I may, like Aladdin before the hidden jewels, rub my eyes in the very presence of an unfamiliar sight, and be unwilling to act either as if it were real or unreal. This attitude, which is familiar to all men, completely replaces belief (and disbelief) in the mind of the sceptic, who knows no truth and is not even sure that he knows no truth. Incredulity supervenes on and is provoked by the survey of possibilities for thought, but like its opposite, belief, it is a de- parture from the attitude of merely considering possibilities. The sceptic does more than understand or entertain the ideas of which he is sceptical; he sets his mind against them, he inhibits the natural tendency to affirm or deny the propositions he holds before his understanding. Incredulity is a definite shrinking 188 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH from belief or disbelief, and not simply the survey of possibili- ties for thought; and this is why it is the genuine opposite of belief. Thus in a mood of pure speculation or fancy, scepticism has no more place than belief or disbelief. It is quite as inappro- priate to be incredulous of a myth or a romantic tale as to in- quire whether it is true or false; to be sceptical as to whether the Ancient Mariner shot the albatross is no less irrelevant than to believe or disbelieve it. Yet to the thoroughly incredulous per- son, the true sceptic, a world of fancy — whether it be of roman- tic, scientific, or metaphysical fancy —is still open. Thought can range where it will among possibilities, for if possibilities for thought were not left to the sceptic, there would be nothing to be incredulous of. Scepticism is a sophisticated philosophy because only by dint of much thinking, much turning over of possibilities, do ideas so completely nullify one another that none seems worthy of ac- ceptance. The unsophisticated man on the contrary is credu- lous, for concepts, ideas merely entertained, project themselves toward action and belief. Incredulity, when it is not erected into a philosophy, is unstable; it can play no positive part in knowl- edge. It can prevent us from falling into error and nothing more» but it can be of no use in shaping a course of action, in arriving at conclusions either in theory or practice, as positive denial can be. The “no” of the sceptic is the “no” of indecision. To be incredulous is to attain no end, but positively to deny a proposition is to believe something which may be of use. XV Belief and disbelief, denial and assertion, are the only avenues of approach to truth. Though truth is not manufactured by 1 Aristotle denies even the consideration of possibilities to the sceptic, for he believes that one must accept the truth of the principle of contradiction if he thinks in any sense of the term. See Aristotle, Metaphysics, bk. iii, ch. 4. TRUTH AND FALSITY 189 judgments, it does not stand out for knowledge in isolation from the judgments through which it is known. The cognition of truth, like that of beauty or good, is colored by an interest, which is the motive of judgment — the interest in truth. And just as it is possible to lose sight of the objects toward which the moral and aesthetic interests are directed, and to confuse beauty and good with the feelings they arouse, so it is possible to mis- take truth for the feeling of certainty that accompanies satis- factory belief. Truth is then reduced to a psychological state; it becomes a matter of intellectual taste, as beauty and good, on the parallel theory, are matters of aesthetic and moral taste. The contradiction in this psychological relativism appears in the answer to the question which Plato put to the Sophists: If belief is the measure of truth, and I believe that this is not so, do I not believe truly? ! There is no reply but an affirmative one on the Sophists’ own hypothesis, and only if the relativist is willing to give up the law of contradiction, does his view sustain itself. Scepticism, like relativism, often arises from the fact that truth can be known only through belief; but this philosophy, extending as it does no further than incredulity — incredulity reiterated and reinforced by incredulity — is born of too great rather than too little love of truth. The sceptic disdains to find truth in the feeling of certainty. He withholds judgment to the very last and does not deny truth, for he is aware that a single judgment — even the judgment that there is no truth, or that he doubts that there is truth — is like a stone cast in still water: the circles widen outward, embracing a more and more extended region, so that if one affirmation or denial is ventured on there is no stopping short of a theory of truth and reality. He therefore finds all things, perceived and unperceived, to be unacceptable to the intellect, indifferent to knowledge. Hume’s scepticism goes only part way. He is incredulous of all 1 Plato, Theaetetus, Jowett’s translation, marginal p. 161. 190 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH metaphysical theories, but not of the psychological processes by which ideas are joined together and brought into relation to the “‘impressions’’ of the senses. Yet he is acutely conscious that knowledge is belief — and, it may be, nothing but belief. If we could attain truth, he argues, we could not be certain that we had, for we should still be believing. The mind, like a moth at- tracted by a light, trusts its impressions because it cannot help doing so; but that these impressions are true of a reality given in them or beyond them remains forever no more worthy of belief than disbelief. Hume sees knowledge only from the psychologi- cal angle, and leaves it hopelessly tossed between this “‘irresist- ible” idea or impression and that, but with no anchor for any be- lief. And Hume, too, touches the profounder scepticism that doubts even itself; there are revulsions from philosophy, sudden returns to common sense, when the most ordinary beliefs seem to him no better or worse than the finest-spun philosophy. Scepticism of this sort can be escaped but not refuted. One can easily imagine Hume undermining the whole structure of Kant’s “refutation” by merely pointing to the fact that it is built on belief. Scepticism, in its subtler forms, is an over-cau- tious, not a self-contradictory, philosophy. It refuses to take the leap of belief — to undergo the risk of error that is never absent from knowledge. The one final criterion of truth is our capacity to believe prop- ositions; though a belief may be arrived at by circuitous routes, the ultimate evidence of truth is the compulsion of a belief. If one asks for what reasons he holds a conviction, it is either on the strength of some other conviction, or on the inherent strength of the conviction itself. Try as he may, he cannot break the circle of his beliefs. To test truth we must assume truth; we must believe that there is some valid principle by which truth can be tested, and that there is a truth to test. It is not difficult for the sceptic to show the risk of defining or Ht TRUTH AND FALSITY 191 attempting to test truth. Consider the test that has been pro- posed, consistency with the whole of knowledge. How complete must this knowledge be? Clearly, no experience is ever complete; there are always additions and corrections; in the light of fur- ther experience what now appears to be consistent may prove to be inconsistent. Yet if the test of truth is consistency with’an in- complete experience, this is too narrow; no allowance is made for the reversals to which any growing body of knowledge is sub- ject. But what could be meant by a “‘complete experience’’? Is this something more than a personal knowledge—is it all know]- edge, past, future, possible, including that of other minds, as it might be brought together in a single mind? If so, much as one might like to appeal to this complete experience, he cannot do so; for he can see through no other eyes than his own, and know through no other mind than his own; and he can know only in the present. The test he actually can apply is that of consistency in his experience at the present moment — the present including memories of the past; and this is only a small measure, a feeble approximation, to complete consistency. Furthermore, it may be that reality is not self-consistent, that consistency is read into it by the mind, that reality slips between the eager fingers of the intellect, leaving only a shell of empty appearances. But the very imperfections of this test show how the circles of belief strive to push outward beyond the phenomenal to that which can in no sense be called an “‘appearance.”’ The concept of truth links itself inevitably to that of reality. A truth grounded in anything less than a complete, a metaphysically conceived, reality will still be open to question in the mind that conceives this truth. A theory of knowledge without a metaphysics is at best only a partial repudiation of scepticism. If one embarks on an examination of truth, the security of his position will ulti- mately depend, not only on a faithful description of knowledge as a phenomenon, but on the scope of the concept of reality to 192 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH which he finally comes. He will need to complete the picture by a metaphysics of knowledge. XVI What has been said of truth, existence, and judgment can be summarized as follows: The correspondence of propositions or concepts with existing objects is truth, but a proposition (or concept) is not a subsist- ing tertium quid interposed between symbols and objects; it is the symbols themselves, taken with the intention or psychical set they arouse in a mind. This does not deprive the proposition (or symbolic expression) of an objective reference, a direction toward the world of objects, even though there exists or subsists no referent for it as a whole. For its meaning is a function of simpler meanings united in a scheme of logical structure; and these simpler meanings, being direct references to objects that exist or have existed (or being definable in terms of such direct references), give the complex meaning a direction beyond the mind’s present content. Moreover, the structure of the expres- sion codperates in determining the whole to have an objective reference, since the object meant (if there is an object meant by the whole) must be identical in this respect with the expression; and if the whole stands for no object, the structure, being a uni- versal which could occur in a factual as well as a symbolic in- stance, will still refer beyond itself. The assumption of subsist- ent entities as the termini of meanings is therefore unnecessary ; especially since meaning is not a static relation between the mind and some second term, but an activity — an activity of preparation or anticipation, which presupposes the presence in no sense of the object anticipated or prepared for. It is necessary only that some objects — those which are directly referred to by the constituents of the symbolic group — shall have been pre- sented, in order that complex expressions should have a mean- TRUTH AND FALSITY 193 ing; these expressions in their entirety do not need to refer to any entity, subsistent or existent. Thus a false proposition is one which is significant, yet stands as a whole for no existing object or subsisting objective. The category of objectivity is no wider than that of existence. The term “existence” or “reality” is used in a limited sense, though it is not defined; and the criterion of existence, which is also the criterion of truth, is the presentation of an object in an experience consistent with the whole of knowledge. Inferences based on such perceptions (if these inferences are valid) permit us to reach objects not given in perception. Every perception has a datum, but the datum is always perceived under a con- cept. Concept and datum coalesce to form a whole of presenta- tion, so that what is given and exists independent of the percep- tion cannot be disentangled from what might be added through concepts, by the mind’s invention. Sense data are the simplest elements of presented wholes, but even these data are not purely immediate; the mind in recognizing them brings them under concepts. Therefore sensationalism, which grants existence only to the data of the senses and fails to observe that a sense datum is never known in complete isolation from presented wholes, is not the true empiricism; the complex perceptions of objects, situations, and facts have an equal claim to be taken as presen- tations of reality. Indeed, the concepts in perception may bring us into a closer cognitive relation to the real, rather than sepa- rate us from the real, for the mind is more than a blank sheet on which objects write impressions. No presentation in itself guarantees to its datum anything other than bare existence, reality of an indefinite sort; but it does guarantee this thin reality even to the data of dreams, illu- sions, and hallucinations. When the data are apprehended as objects of this or that sort, or in this or that relation (as they must be apprehended if they are to enter into organized knowl- 194 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH edge), a further criterion of existence than givenness is needed. The data must be placed in reality under a concept which makes the presentation consistent with the whole of knowledge. This consistency with the whole of knowledge is a criterion of existence for this reason, that the existence which gives truth, in the present meaning of the term, to symbolic expressions is re- stricted to objects which can be consistently conceptualized, which can be fitted into rational knowledge without contradic- tion. This does not assumé that reality is finally self-consistent, or that it can be completely known through consistent concepts. Nor does it assume the contrary, that neither consistent nor in- consistent concepts are adequate to the real. That the existent is capable of being consistently presented and represented is the limiting condition of the notion of reality on which this defini- tion of truth rests, but it need not be a condition of a more ex- tended reality. Consistency is determined not by the laws of logic alone, or by formal “categories,” but by general truths, empirical cate- gories, which are subject to revision and reversal. All well-estab- lished scientific principles and a host of prescientific generaliza- tions operate as tests of the reality of perceived objects. The criterion of the existence of objects is the truth of theories, and the criterion of the truth of theories is the existence of objects. Theory and perception mutually support and correct one an- other. This fact does not make the definition of truth circular. Truth is correspondence to reality, and so it follows that per- ceptions of existing objects will be consistent with general truths, but it does not follow that existence is a function of these truths, nor that truth and consistency are the same. Con- sistency is a test of truth but is not equivalent to truth. The “coherence theory” rejects correspondence as a defini- tion of truth because this relation implies the distinctness of the corresponding wholes and hence the separateness of knowledge TRUTH AND FALSITY 195 and reality. The “‘systematic coherence” which is, on this view, at once Truth and Reality transcends the consistency of formal logic and ordinary thought. Thus there can be no separable truths, for such truths would not be the whole Truth. Though reality as thus conceived may be identical with thought as thus conceived, the limited reality of perceptual objects cannot be identified with the thought which is embodied in propositions or symbolic expressions, for if this were so there would be no fal- sity; every concept would refer toa real object. Since concepts and objects, in this less extended sense, are not identical but are distinct, the relation of concepts to objects, even when they come together in perception so that the meaning of the concept cannot be distinguished from the object, must be cor- respondence. This correspondence is a correlation such that the elements of the corresponding wholes fulfil the same structural functions in each; the relation of correspondence rests on an identity of logical form in real objects and in propositions or concepts. Truths are known only through belief or judgment, which is a secondary attitude toward propositions. This attitude is like understanding in that it is a preparation for an object intended, but it differs from understanding in being a completer prepara- tion — a willingness to act as if the object intended were in ex- istence. Belief is more than the thought of the existence of the object meant, and more than vividness of presentation or clear- ness of understanding. Belief, like meaning, is carried in sym- bols, it is inseparable from its expressions; and if there is any difference between belief and assertion, it is that the latter is an outward or inward signification of belief, while the belief itself is the attitude of mind signified. A full sentence differs from a single word or phrase in that it contains a sign of belief; the es- sential office of the copula is to serve as such a sign. But a word or phrase is no less capable of being true or false, and of being 196 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH asserted or denied, than a full sentence; a single word is a propo- sition. Disbelief reduces to belief, to a belief in the negative of the proposition disbelieved, while the true opposite of belief is in- credulity, the attitude of the sceptic. Disbelief is therefore posi- tive and takes a place beside belief as a means of reaching con- clusions through inference or through action; incredulity serves only the negative end of preventing error. Finally, the indecision of scepticism, which springs from the fact that truth is reached in no other way than through belief, can be escaped only by taking the risk of error which judg- ment necessarily involves; and belief, once it is set in motion, is carried on by its own momentum toward a theory of truth and reality — and in the end to “first philosophy.” For nowhere else are to be found the principles that justify all others. CHAPTER VI NEGATION AND CONTRADICTION I T xx notion of a negative truth — or a true negative — has an intrinsic appearance of paradox and even of self-contradiction, especially when truth is defined as the correspondence of propo- sitions, or symbolic expressions, with objects. What sort of object can a true negative mean? Does it stand for a “negative object”’? Clearly it must stand for some object. The significance of a negative cannot be, like that of a false prop- osition, a meaning determined by other meanings and yet corre- sponding to no object, for all negatives would then be false. Nor can it be a direct reference to objects given in perception. There are no negative data; perception is always the perception of something that is, never of something that 2s not. A direct refer- ence to objects cannot be anything but positive. The analysis of negation, therefore, falls between the horns of a dilemma: either negatives refer to no objects and are false, or they refer to ob- jects and are not negatives. There are many ways of escaping this dilemma, the simplest of which is to embrace one of its alternatives; and this is what Mr. Bertrand Russell does. He finds that negative propositions mean “negative facts,” which are unanalyzed and necessary elements in the world of fact." A negative fact, if there is such a thing, is plainly not of the same order as a positive fact. To observe that “the sun is not shining” is very different from observing the contrary. In the 1 See B. Russell, “The Philosophy of Logical Atomism,” in The Monist, vol. xxviii (1918), and vol. xxix (1919). 198 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH latter case, a complex object, the shining of the sun, is immedi- ately given; in the former, what is immediately given is some- thing other than what is referred to. To “perceive” that the sun is not shining is to notice clouds in the sky and, perhaps, rain; or it may be, to observe that night has fallen — and these data are not negative facts. If negative facts are “given,” they are not given through perception, as are positive ones; they are in- ferred or constructed from perceptions; their reality, like that of classes, extends far beyond any immediate presentation; they are facts of a highly complex type, and the propriety of using the term “fact” for them is questionable, as it is for classes, which cannot properly be called “facts.” ? The assumption of negative facts as the referents of true nega- tive propositions does not analyze negation. It cuts the knot but leaves the threads of the difficulty tangled. Negative significance remains an anomaly unassimilated to the rest of knowledge, un- less it can be shown to have a positive basis in some other sort of meaning. | A particularly interesting attack on the problem is that of Mr. Raphael Demos, who, though he does not carry the analysis to its completion, suggests that a negative proposition is like a de- scriptive phrase; it is an ambiguous reference to what is meant by a number of positive propositions, the meaning of some one of which is the meaning of the negation.? Thus the sign of nega- tion, “not” or its equivalent, plays a part similar to that of the signs “‘a,” “any,” “some,” and “the.” It is a sign of interpre- tation. It does not signify a constituent of the fact to which the expression as a whole might refer, but indicates that the propo- sition is to be interpreted in a special way, that is, negatively ; 1 See above, ch. IV, sec. xiii. 2 See R. Demos, “A Discussion of a Certain Type of Negative Proposi- tion,” Mind, N.S., vol. xxvi (1917), p. 188. Despite obvious disagreements, the central idea of the theory of negation here presented, that of the ambiguity of the negative, is taken from Dr. Demos’ article. NEGATION AND CONTRADICTION 199 which is to interpret it as a variable with an ambiguous refer- ence to certain positive propositions. II The ambiguity of negative propositions is their most striking characteristic. They are variables, and they continue as nega- tions only so long as their significance is not fully determined. If I assert that “the sun is not shining,”’ I do not assert that “it is raining,” or that “it is night,” or “that the sky is clouded.” None of these propositions expresses the meaning of the nega- tion. Nor do I assert all of these propositions. The meaning is like that of the statement, “I met a man.” If a value for the variable a man is chosen, so that the statement becomes, “‘I met Mr. X,”’ this is not what I assert; it is more specific than my actual assertion. And though I must have met Mr. X or Mr. Y or Mr. Z, etc., if the statement is true, still it remains undeter- mined which one of these men I did meet, and this indetermi- nateness is an essential element in the meaning. Similarly, what I mean by “‘the sun is not shining” might be either that “‘it is raining,” or that “‘it is night,” or that “the sun is in eclipse,” etc., but it is actually none of these. The negation is essentially unspecific in reference and to make it specific is to rob it of its negativity. The observation that negatives are ambiguous is the first step toward freeing us from the error that a negative is merely what zs meant. The manner of significance is no less constitutive of the meaning of a negation than are the things it might signify; and since propositions alone are ambiguous, negation belongs to the realm of propositions or concepts, and not to things. Things do not have negatives, for things are not ambiguous; and without ambiguity there is no negation. Toward what objects or facts is this ambiguous reference of the negative directed? 200 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH Every negation has its ground; it rests on a perception or af- firmation of fact. But the ground of a negation is not coexten- sive with the meaning, since the ground is a single fact or com- plex of facts, while the meaning covers a multitude of facts, some undetermined one of which is the value of the negative. I may affirm that “Chaucer’s Canterbury Tales are not good reading” on the ground that they are immoral, but this fact will not be the only possible interpretation of the statement. This negation might mean that the language of these tales is difficult, or that they are dull. If I advise you that “carbolic acid should not be drunk,”’ the ground of my advice may be that it is poison- ous; yet this is not what I assert, and you may construe my statement to mean that “suicide is criminal”’ or that “life is worth living.” To identify the ground of a negation with the meaning is to abolish the negation, for it is to choose one among the possible values; hence the negation is no longer a variable and no longer a negation. If a negative proposition were equiva- lent in meaning to the single positive proposition that is its ground, there would be no reason for employing negatives; they would disappear. Though negatives are often used where posi- tive propositions would serve as well, their function in knowl- edge is the same as that of other ambiguous expressions; namely, to avoid a definite reference or to refer to that which is not determinately known. Negation is notoriously the language of diplomacy and guile. In addition to the actual ground of any negation, there are many possible grounds. These possible grounds are all the prop- ositions with which the proposition negated is incompatible; 1 and Mr. Demos limits the possible values of a negative to its possible grounds. On his view, then, a negative proposition means (ambiguously) the same as some one of the propositions 1 Incompatibility is the relation of inconsistency between propositions, dis- cussed in chapter v. p and gq are incompatible if, when the one is true, the other is never true. This does not preclude both being false. NEGATION AND CONTRADICTION 201 whose truth excludes the truth of the proposition negated. To say that “‘life is not short, nasty, mean, and brutish” is to refer to the fact that “it is long or happy,” or that “‘it is romantic,” or that “‘it is capable of perfection,” etc., none of these possi- bilities, however, being chosen as the value of the negative. Mr. Demos’s analysis does not go far enough. The relation of incompatibility or logical opposition, in terms of which it is stated, is complex; it rests on truth and falsity and is an extrin- sic rather than an intrinsic relation between concepts. It cannot be apprehended through direct inspection of propositions or con- cepts; one must know more than the meaning of a proposition to know that it is incompatible with another; he must know that it is never true when the other is true. Nor can incompatibility be apprehended as a relation between the data of perception. Logical opposition is not perceived, for what is meant by the logical opposites cannot be in the same universe; and if percep- tions seem to be inconsistent with one another, the inconsistency is in the concepts through which the data are presented, and not in the data themselves. The proposition “‘a is black”’ is incom- patible with the proposition “‘a is white,” “‘ Juliet loved Romeo”’ is incompatible with “Juliet hated Romeo’’; but white is not logically opposed to black, and love is not logically opposed to hate, since all of these qualities or relations exist in the same universe. Propositions alone can be logically opposed, and their logical opposition is a function of their truth and falsity. From the point of view of formal logic, there could be no ob- jection to defining “‘incompatibility ” in terms of truth and fal- sity and to deriving negation from this propositional relation. Nor could there be any objection to assuming incompatibility itself, without definition, as the foundation of a theory of nega- tion and truth. It is also possible to construct a logical system in which negation and incompatibility are both defined in terms of another function of propositions. Mr. H. M. Sheffer’s rejec- 202 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH tion is a primitive idea which makes these latter definitions possible." But what is primitive in a set of postulates for logic may be complex as an element in knowledge. The data of epistemology and the primitive ideas of logical systems are not simple in the same sense. For formal logic, the simplest primitive ideas for any system are those which are the smallest in number and which yield by deduction all the propositions belonging to the system; thus a number of different concepts might be chosen as primitive for different sets of postulates which apply, neverthe- less, to the same subject-matter. The facts to which these prim- itive ideas refer might have the appearance of extreme complex- ity, but this would not make the ideas any the less primitive and simple, so far as the logical part they play in the system is con- cerned. This is not the sense in which the basic ideas of a theory of knowledge are simple; these ideas are not arbitrarily chosen because of their economy and fruitfullness in deduction. Their simplicity must correspond to a certain simplicity in the subject- matter; what they mean must present the appearance of sim- plicity, it must appeal to the mind as being capable of no fur- ther analysis. It is this sort of simplicity which is lacking both in the concept of negative facts and in that of incompatibility as the basis of negation. It is possible to dissociate negation from truth and falsity, and thus to gain in completeness of analysis. The incompatibility or logical opposition of a negative and its positive is not the most fundamental idea involved in negation; this notion of incompat- ibility arises from a combination of the idea of truth with that of negation in a highly general sense. In order to understand a posi- tive proposition or symbolic expression, it is not necessary to consider whether it is true or false. (The only symbols whose 1 H. M. Sheffer, A Set of Independent Postulates for Boolean Algebras, Transc. Amer. Math. Soc., vol. xiv, no. 4, pp. 481-488. NEGATION AND CONTRADICTION 203 significance involves their truth are the elementary simple sym- bols from which complex expressions are constructed.) It is suf- ficient to know the form of the proposition and the meanings of its elements. The understanding of a negative, similarly, ought not to require a knowledge of its truth or falsity, or — what amounts to the same thing — of its incompatibility with an- other proposition. A negative must be such that it can be enter- tained as a possibility for thought without any consideration whatsoever of any object that it might mean, or that any other proposition might mean. Some relation which can be directly apprehended in apprehending the significance of propositions must be sought to mark the limits of the possible values of nega- tive expressions. This will yield the more general negation which does not depend on truth and falsity. Il This relation is that of distinctness of meaning; and it is the symbolic counterpart of the diversity or otherness of objects. A negative proposition means “something distinct from that which is meant by the positive’’; and this, coupled with the am- biguity of the reference, is the whole of negation when the ques- tion of the truth or falsity of the negative does not enter — that is, when the negative is purely a possibility for thought. This definition of the possible values of a negative proposition seems to remove all limitations and to lead to startling conclu- sions. Among the possible values of “‘the sun is not shining”’ are thus included, not only propositions that might be the ground of this negation, such as “it is night”’ and “‘the sky is overcast,”’ but also propositions that could by no stretch of the imagination be its ground — propositions such as “Chicago is in Illinois,” > ‘‘man is a rational creature, ” etc. In short, any proposition which is distinct in meaning from “‘the sun is shining”’ is a pos- sible interpretation of “‘the sun is not shining.” 204 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH The appearance of paradox is partly removed if it is remem- bered that the negative proposition does not actually mean one of its possible values. It is a negative only while it is ambiguous; and, though some propositions are relevant to it as grounds from which its truth or falsity might be inferred, it no more signifies a particular one of these than it does a particular one of the count- less propositions irrelevant to it as grounds. The statement SiLite sun is not shining” does not actually mean “Chicago is in Tlli- nois,” nor does it mean ‘“‘the sky is overcast.’ It means “‘some- thing other than that the sun is shining.” If a pessimist were asked whether life is good, he might reply, “anything but”; and this inelegant, yet emphatic denial correctly indicates the range of possible values of a negative. It must be observed that the limit of the possible values of a negative is marked, not by the diversity of objects signified, but by diversity of significance, irrespective of objects. On this widest interpretation of the principle of negation, false propo- sitions (which correspond to no objects) may be values of the negatives of false propositions. “New York is not in Brazil” need not signify merely what is meant by some true proposition; it might mean (though being ambiguous it does not actually mean) that “New York is in Turkey.” And if I say that “Cin- derella did not love her stepmother,” which is false because there was no Cinderella, still I might mean that “Cinderella hated her stepmother,” which is also false. The question whether or not the truth of a negative precludes the truth of its positive is irrelevant to this purely conceptual negation. Any use of symbols presupposes distinctness as well as iden- tity of meaning. Thought is not a repeated series of tautologies, and no symbolic system could be constructed from symbols whose meanings were all equivalent. Just as every symbol, if it is to retain its identity (to be the same symbol) in its recurrent instances, must be interpreted in one and only one way, so a NEGATION AND CONTRADICTION 205 symbol, if it is to have anything other than a reference so vague that it could not be called a meaning, must be distinct in sig- nificance from some other symbol; and where distinctness of meaning is present, negation is also present. The dictum that “determination is negation” is no less true for thought than for reality. Without negation, that is, without distinctness of mean- ing, there is no meaning; and without diversity there are no ob- jects. Everything that zs 1 is diverse from something else, and every significant idea is distinct in meaning from some other idea. Just as the same symbol or concept, when it is applied to the world of objects, will (by the very definition of the same symbol) mean one and only one object, so a symbol that is dis- tinct from it will (by the very definition of a distinct symbol) mean a different object or no object. And the negative, since it has the same significance as any symbol distinct from the positive, will therefore always be distinct in meaning from the positive. IV This general condition of the use of symbols — that a nega- tive is always distinct in meaning from its positive — which fol- lows from the purely conceptual definition of the meaning of a negative, is the principle of contradiction in its most abstract form. It is like the principle of identity in that it is a general rule of symbolism, and therefore a general principle of thought. Now the law of contradiction is often confused with the law of the excluded middle, which states that “either p or not-p is true”’; but this latter principle has no connection with the prin- ciple of contradiction, when truth and falsity are not considered in the definition of negation. As a general rule of symbolism the law of contradiction asserts that to every symbol corresponds another, its negative, whose meaning is distinct from the first. 1 In the sense of ch. V. 206 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH It can be written, “‘a ¥ not-a,” the sign (#) being taken to mean “distinct from.’ Both the laws of identity and contradic- tion, on their purely symbolic interpretations, state general in- tentions in the use of symbols. The law of identity, “a = a,” tells us that any symbol “a” is equivalent, for symbolic pur- poses, to itself; that it can replace itself in any context without altering the meaning, since every symbol can have one and only one meaning. The law of contradiction, on the other hand, tells us that there is at least one symbol that is distinct, for symbolic purposes, from any given symbol “a,” and this is “not-a”’; if it replaces ‘“‘a’’ in any context, the meaning will be completely altered. As statements of general intentions in the use of symbols, the laws of identity and contradiction are a prior? in the sense that they are rules laid down by the mind for its own guidance. They are self-affirming; if they are denied, they are assumed, for no proposition or concept can be framed without them. In knowing what it is to think, we know these laws, and we can escape them only by escaping from the use of propositions or concepts — that is, from the use of symbols. There is another interpretation of these principles, an extsten- tial interpretation, which construes them as general truths about objects, as well as general principles of symbolism. If ‘‘a” stands for an object — for any object — “a = a” asserts that “any object is identical with itself,” or simply that “any object has an identity”; while “a # not-a” asserts that “any object is dis- tinct from anything other than itself,” or simply that “any ob- ject stands in the relation of diversity to-something.”’ Both of these statements are tautologies, but they could not be true un- less there were identity and diversity in the world of fact. They express the minimal conditions of the being of objects — that is, of the objects which are presented or represented in empirical- rational knowledge. NEGATION AND CONTRADICTION 207 The very assertion of these general truths, however, assumes the laws of identity and contradiction as principles of symbo- lism. Only if “a” is the same symbol as ‘“‘a” does “a = a” affirm that “‘any object is identical with itself”; and unless “a” and ‘‘not-a” are always distinct in meaning, “a ¥ not-a”’ might mean “‘a # a.” The predication of diversity in objects presupposes diversity in the meanings of symbols, apart from objects meant, but the statement that “‘a # not-a” in the sym- bolic sense does not imply that a or not-a stands for an object. Though it is false to say that “griffins are not not-griffins,” if this means that griffins exist as distinct things, this is not false as a statement of how the concepts “griffin” and “not-griffin” are to be used. If the law of contradiction were not valid both on its symbolic and existential interpretation — if there were no distinct sym- bols and no diverse objects — thought would find itself in a strange situation. It would be impossible to think of anything without at the same time thinking of everything. In order that a symbol may mean a specific object, not only must the object be self-identical and the symbol be the same symbol in its different instances, but there must be something that is not meant by this symbol and that can be signified only through a different symbol — something for the apprehension of which a new and distinct concept is the only appropriate instrument. Without negation thought would be even less definite than the Parme- nidean tautology, “Being is”; and without diversity in objects, the whole structure of the world of fact, as we know it, would disappear. The limiting condition of the reality that gives truth, as we have defined it, to symbolic expressions or propositions is that it must be capable of being consistently presented and represented; and, so, for this reality, the principles of identity and contradic- tion on their existential as well as their symbolic interpretations 208 ’ SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH must be true a priori. Anything that could be consistently pre- sented or represented would necessarily be self-identical and diverse from other things. The principles of identity and contra- diction are the “formal” categories of this limited being; the test of consistency, which makes use of the “empirical catego- ries”? of science and common sense, can be applied to existent objects only if these more general principles hold of them. These principles are implicit in the condition that marks the limits of this reality. How much further the validity of the laws of identity and contradiction, as truths about reality, can be extended is a matter for speculation; and here again the theory of knowledge finds its completion in metaphysics. If reality were constituted by thought, these most general conditions of thought would certainly be the most general conditions of being. But for a the- ory any less extended than this, it is a wide leap from the most general rules of thought to the most general principles of being. It is possible that reality cannot be trimmed to the neat dimen- sions of thought; there may be nooks and corners of the real hidden from this knowledge which demands the identity and di- versity of its objects. It is even possible that these very require- ments of thought form a barrier between the mind and reality, confining knowledge to a realm of Kantian phenomena. But neither this metaphysical alternative, nor the other — that they are true a priori of reality in the most inclusive sense of the term — can be established on the premises so far laid down. V What of the third “law of thought,” the principle of the ex- cluded middle? To construe the meaning of a negative proposition as “any- thing other than the meaning of the positive” appears to be a direct violation of this law, for this permits a false proposition to NEGATION AND CONTRADICTION 209 be a value of the negative of a false proposition and therefore allows the possibility that when p is false not-p might also be false. “Paris is not the principal city of England” might mean “Paris is the capital of the United States,” and this is clearly not allowable if the principle of the excluded middle is true. Moreover, “‘Paris is not the principal city of England”’ could mean (though on account of its ambiguity it does not actually mean) that “birds have wings” or that “to-day is Friday,” and the truth or falsity of these propositions seems to be totally un- connected with the truth or falsity of ‘‘ Paris is the principal city of England.” The law of the excluded middle, that “either p or not-p (but not both) is true,” connects negation with truth and falsity by adding a further condition than diversity of meaning to deter- mine the possible values of a negative. We thus return to the more complex and special type of negation, which Mr. Demos defined in terms of incompatibility. This law is not a necessity of thought in the same sense as are the principles of identity and contradiction in their most general forms. The latter are needed if concepts or symbolic expressions are employed in any way whatsoever; the former enters only when truth and falsity (as well as the identity and distinctness of concepts) are considered. It is necessary for inference — for the derivation of the truth or falsity of propositions from the truth or falsity of others; but it is not necessary for the very existence of meaning, as are the first two laws of thought. In order that the principle of contradiction may yield the law of the excluded middle, the negative must be interpreted in a special way, which takes account not only of the distinctness of concepts, but of their truth. Now true propositions are distinct through the objects they mean, as well as distinct in significance apart from these objects; but false propositions are not distinguished from one another 210 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH through objects meant, since they mean no objects. Moreover, any true proposition is distinct from any false proposition through an object meant, for the one means an object, while the other does not. This notion of “being distinct through an object meant”? supplies the necessary principle for determining the possible values of a negative, when the law of the excluded mid- dle is added to the laws of identity and contradiction. If not-p means (ambiguously) the same as any proposition that is dis- tinct from p through the distinctness of an object meant, it will follow that when p is true not-p is false, and vice versa, that when p is false not-p is true. To include the idea of an object meant, that is, of truth, in the definition of negation is to remove negation from the realm of the purely conceptual. It is no longer sufficient merely to know the meaning of a proposition — merely to consider it as a possi- bility for thought — in order to know the meaning of its nega- tive. One must also know whether it is true or false. But if this kind of negation is less simple than the other, it is more effective; negatives now become instruments of inference. All false prop- ositions fall together as indistinguishable through an object meant, though they still remain distinct as concepts; and hence the negative of a false proposition can mean only true proposi- tions. It will be true for any value that can be chosen for it, so that the truth of not-p can always be inferred from the falsity of p. “New York is not in Brazil” will not include among its possible interpretations, “New York is in Turkey” or “New York is in Australia,’ since these propositions are not distinct through an object meant from “‘New York is in Brazil.” Any possible value of “New York is not in Brazil’’ will be a true proposition. Among these possible values there will be one that is the most probable ground of this negation, viz., “New York is in the United States”; but it is not necessary to suppose that this value is the sole possible meaning of the negation in order to tml i a sir — NEGATION AND CONTRADICTION 211 establish its truth. Any true proposition will be a possible value of this negative. On the other hand, if p is true — and if there is a single false proposition among all the propositions which can be formulated — then not-p will be false. For among the possible values of not-p will be included, not only all the true propositions that are distinct from p through an object meant, but also some false proposition; and since the negative is ambiguous, it might mean this false proposition. It cannot be true if there is a single possi- bility of falsity.1 Thus, since it is true that “carbolic acid is poisonous,” and since some false proposition can be stated — let us say the proposition that “carbolic acid is good to drink”? — the negative, “carbolic acid is not poisonous,”’ might mean that *“‘carbolic acid is good to drink.” This latter proposition, being false, is a possible value of the negative of the original true prop- osition, for any true proposition is distinguished from any false proposition by an object meant. And though the negative, “car- bolic acid is not poisonous,” might also mean countless other propositions, both true and false, it cannot be true so long as there is any possible interpretation for which it is false. Thus where the possible values of a negative are the meanings of those propositions which are distinct from the positive through an ob- ject meant, the falsity of a negative can always be inferred from the truth of its positive. It is clear that this more restricted type of negation — this inferential negation — eliminates possibilities which the wider and simpler form of negation permits. When the negative is con- strued in this narrower way, “fairies do not live on bread and meat”’ could not possibly mean “fairies live on dew and honey.” Its positive being false (since there are no fairies), this propo- 1 The assumption that some false proposition can be formulated amounts to the assumption that there is falsity; and certainly a negative could not be false unless there were falsity. There must be some false proposition that it could mean. 212 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH sition must mean the same as some true proposition; it must be true. By the very definition of the meaning of the negative, we are no longer permitted to consider it as a mere possibility that ‘fairies do not live on bread and meat”’; we are forced to infer its truth from the falsity of the proposition of which it is the negative. The principle of the excluded middle thus drags us down to earth from the world of pure speculation. VI The conditions of the truth and falsity of negatives have al- ready been mentioned in passing. A negative is false if there is a single false proposition among its possible values, and it is true only if all of its possible values are true propositions. This fol- lows from the ambiguity of the negative. Let us examine this idea more closely. Now the meaning of a proposition determines whether it is true or false, and if this meaning is not fully specified — that is, if the proposition might mean a number of different things, but actually does mean none of these — the truth of the proposition will depend on what it might mean, not on what it actually does mean; for it actually does mean no specified object. Thus an am- biguous proposition (or one which contains ambiguous constitu- ents) is not true in the same sense as an unambiguous proposi- tion. Its truth, like its meaning, is fixed by possible references to objects, rather than by an actual reference. It is “ambiguously true.”’ To be true in this sense is to be susceptible of many differ- ent interpretations, but not to be susceptible of a false interpreta- tion. Just as ambiguous meaning is an unspecified possibility of meaning, so ambiguous truth is an unspecified possibility of truth, rather than truth for a definite object or class of objects. And if among the possible determinations of such an ambiguous expression there is one for which it would be false — if there is a single possibility of falsity — the proposition fails of truth as NEGATION AND CONTRADICTION 213 an ambiguous proposition, even if it might be true for some of its possible values. Though an ambiguous proposition, if it is asserted, need not be asserted for all of the things it might mean, its truth requires that it be capable of being true for all of these. Consider the statement, “‘I saw a friend on the street yester- day.” This is a particular proposition but, since it contains an ambiguous constituent, it does not assert that I saw a particular friend — Brown or Jones; nor does it assert that I saw ali my friends. I might have seen any one of them, and if among them I count, as did the poet Blake, a certain group of friendly spirits, or if some whom I call friends are not friends, the proposition might be false; and the mere possibility of falsity invalidates it as an ambiguous assertion. If the assertion is true — which means that all possibility of interpreting it as false is eliminated — any person that could be meant by the variable “a friend” must be a real person, and must be really a friend. A negative is “ambiguously true.” If it is asserted, it is not asserted for one of its possible values or for all of them; it is am- biguously asserted. And if it is true, it must be true for more than one or several possibilities; there must be no possibility for which it could be false. A true negative embraces the entire uni- verse of true propositions, but not one false proposition; while a false negative embraces a universe of true and false propositions —one true proposition, only, being excepted: the positive of this negative. If these conditions of the truth and falsity of negatives are born in mind, the remaining implications of the principle of the excluded middle are easily seen to be true; v2z., that when not-p is false, p is true; and when not-p is true, p: is false. Suppose that not-p is false. Then some proposition that could be a value of it, some proposition other than p, must be false. 1 This principle, “either p or not-p is true (but not both),” implies that (1) if p is false, not-p is true, (2) if p is true, not-p is false — both of which have been demonstrated in the previous section — (3) if not-p is false, p is true, and (4) if not-p is true, p is false. 214 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH But if p is also false, p would not be distinguished ‘‘through an object meant”’ from this value of not-p; that is, not-p would not be the negative of p. And therefore p must be true. Thus, since it is false that “men do not desire pleasure,” it cannot also be false that ‘‘men do desire pleasure.” For, if this were the case, one of the possible values of the negative, “men do not desire pleasure”’ — let us say the false proposition “‘men desire pain” — would fail to be distinct from the positive, ““men desire pleas- ure,” through an object meant; so that “men do not desire pleasure”? would not be the negative of “‘men desire pleasure.” The very definition of the possible values of this negative de- mands that its positive be true when it is false. On the other hand, when nof-p is true, p must be false. For, not-p being true can mean only true propositions; and, since it is always possible to state some false proposition (since there is al- ways falsity), unless p were false when not-p is true, not-p would include this false proposition among its possible values, for this false proposition would be distinct from p through an object meant, if p were true. Therefore p must be false. It is true, for example, that “fortune is no respecter of persons”; but some false proposition, g, can be stated; and if it were also true that “fortune is a respecter of persons,” this latter proposition would be distinct from the false proposition, g, through an object meant, and q would be a possible value of its negative. The nega- tive might then be false. Thus it must be false that “fortune is a respecter of persons”’ if it is true that “fortune is no respecter of persons.” Where the negative means ambiguously the same as any prop- osition distinct from the positive through an object meant, the law of the excluded middle is therefore valid in all of its implica- tions. From the truth (or falsity) of p, the falsity (or truth) of not-p can always be inferred; and from the truth (or falsity) of not-p, the falsity (or truth) of p can always be inferred. NEGATION AND CONTRADICTION 215 VII The examination of judgment led us to the conclusion that to disbelieve or deny a proposition is to believe or assert its nega- tive — belief, like understanding, being an attitude of prepara- tion for or anticipation of something meant. But if the meaning of a true negative might be that of any one of an entire universe of true propositions, what possible attitude of preparation or an- ticipation could be appropriate to it? To prepare for so many truths would be to prepare for — and to believe — no specific truth; so that the analysis of negation seems to have given nega- tives a basis in fact at the cost of rendering their significance so vague that they cannot be believed. And yet there is a kind of belief which is appropriate to nega- tive propositions in their total ambiguity — a belief that is di- rected toward no specific object or class of objects. Such a belief is an anticipation of anything at all other than what is denied; it is a general readiness to accept something or other — anything excepting the proposition disbelieved — as true. This is the frame of mind in which the atheist denies God; he is prepared to believe anything but that there is a God. And it is the attitude one takes toward propositions which are plainly self-contradic- tory or false. If you tell me that “triangles have four sides” or that “oxen fly in the air,” I shall probably reply that I can ac- cept anything but this. This kind of disbelief, however, though it has a positive content of a formal and indefinite sort, amounts to little more than turning the mind away from the proposition disbelieved. It is a bare (and often groundless) disbelief which hardly escapes scepticism and which, like the sceptical attitude, can never take the place of a positive judgment in knowledge. Negatives are rarely thus asserted or believed in the full ex- tent of their possible meanings. Ordinarily, values which are relevant as grounds to the falsity of the proposition disbelieved 216 : SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH are selected from among the possible values, and on these belief centers. Now the ground of a negative — and of the assertion of the falsity of a proposition — is some proposition which is incom- patible with the proposition negated or with the proposition that is believed to be false. It is a proposition which is never true when the other is true. And this incompatibility is deter- mined by the “empirical categories” of science and common sense. Scientific theories and laws, and prescientific generaliza- tions, are the tests not only of the existence of objects and the truth of propositions, but also of the “non-existence of objects” and the falsity of propositions. A proposition is false — it stands for no object and is conveniently, if inaccurately, said to mean a “non-existent object’ —when it is inconsistent with the whole of knowledge. The mere failure to discover something in exist- ence that the proposition might mean, though it may be ground for denial, is no proof of the falsity of the proposition, and can lead only to the bare disbelief which is directed toward no spe- cific truth. The grounds of negative judgments thus fall into two classes: the failure of verification(which is really privation of ground), and the discovery of true propositions from which the falsity of the proposition denied can be inferred by the aid of the general- izations of science and common sense. In the first case, when I believe a proposition to be false, I can merely deny it by affirm- ing its negative in its full ambiguity. In the second case, my be- lief will be capable of some limitation; I can select as its special objects the truths from which the falsity of the proposition in question follows. I am not therefore always confined to the formal knowledge that ‘“‘anything other than what is denied is true,” in affirming the falsity of propositions, though this is all that the definition of the meaning of the negative can tell me. I can infer, through the laws which I have found to hold in experi- NEGATION AND CONTRADICTION 21%, ence, that certain propositions are true when the other is false, and I can direct my belief toward these propositions. These are the “‘most probable”’ values of the negative. If I assert that “no man defies the laws of society with impunity,” I most probably believe that “‘crime is always punished” or that “criminals are detected” or that “‘the social outcast is miserable,” any one of which could be the ground of this negative judgment. But since there are, in any case, many possible grounds of falsity,— many propositions which are incompatible with the one negated,— to believe a negative, even when a whole universe of truths is not considered, is to prepare for more than a single contingency. And yet it is to prepare for a contingency, to be ready to act as if some definite propositions were true; and thus disbelief be- comes as fully positive as it is capable of becoming. The fact that this more fully positive type of disbelief is di- rected toward specific ones among the possible values of the negative does not restrict the meaning of the negative to these values, that is, to its possible grounds. The negative does not cease to be an “infinite negative” (as the older logicians called it), which might mean the same as any one of an indefinite number of propositions; nor are the formal requisites of its truth — that it cannot be false for any possible interpretation — altered. Thus negative judgments are never wholly equivalent in effect to positive ones, for there is always a margin of possibility which is not covered by belief, even when the “most probable” values of the negative are selected as the objects of belief. The “‘infin- ity” of the negative allows for the totally unforeseen and unfore- seeable — for contingencies which none of the principles of sci- ence and common sense embrace. When one believes a negative, therefore, he can find in his belief a residuum of that general readiness for anything other than what is denied — a margin of “preparation for the wholly unexpected’? — which arises from 218 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH the ambiguity of the negative. Negative judgments, no matter what their grounds, remain evasive to the end; they commit one to much less than positive judgments. They do not completely attain to the solidity and certainty of positive judgments. Vill It must not be forgotten that ideas can be entertained apart from belief and disbelief, as possibilities for thought; that nega- tion can be dissociated from truth and falsity; and that there is a realm of the purely conceptual, where identities and distinc- tions of meaning alone are relevant. The fact that the laws of identity and contradiction (when truth is not a part of the definition of the negative) are general rules of symbolism and therefore of thought, irrespective of ob- jects which are or might be meant, makes it possible to distin- guish conceptual validity from truth, and formal consistency from existential consistency. A system is conceptually valid, whether or not it is true, if it does not violate these two principles of the use of concepts. This means that symbols which are originally taken as distinct — to be values of the negatives of one another — must continue to be treated as distinct, and that symbols originally taken as identical must continue to be treated as iden- tical. These conditions are sufficient to give the system formal consistency. Whether it is existentially consistent and true — that is, whether it contains no incompatible propositions — is another matter, but this will in no sense affect its formal con- sistency. The consistency of the system is a consistency of defi- nition only. This sort of formal consistency and conceptual validity be- longs to uninterpreted deductive systems and to the whole world of romance and fiction. The canons of the constructive imagination are the laws of identity and contradiction, where these laws are rules of symbolism and nothing more. NEGATION AND CONTRADICTION 219 IX The present analysis of negation, beginning with Mr. Demos’s notion that a negative proposition means ambiguously the same as some positive proposition which is incompatible with the proposition negated, has separated the idea of negation from that of truth, thus distinguishing purely conceptual from infer- ential negation. The law of the excluded middle requires that the negative be construed in the latter sense, and the law of con- tradiction in its most general form, that it be construed in the former. The assumption of “‘negative facts”’ as the referents of true negative propositions does not analyze negation; nor does the theory that the negative means ambiguously some proposition incompatible with the positive carry the analysis to its comple- tion, for the notion of incompatibility is complex; and though incompatibility might be taken as simple for purposes of deduc- tive exposition, it is not simple as an element in knowledge. Incompatibility is a function of the truth and falsity of prop- ositions. Negatives are unquestionably ambiguous, but if the possible values of a negative are restricted to its possible grounds, that is, to those propositions whose truth excludes the truth of the positive, the meaning of a negative cannot be dis- sociated from its truth or falsity. A negative proposition, where the negative is interpreted in the simplest way, means (ambiguously) the same as any propo- sition distinct in meaning from the positive, and this distinct- ness of meaning need not be connected with diversity in objects meant, that is, with truth. Distinctness of meaning, apart from objects referred to, is a necessary presupposition of the use of symbols; and the principle of contradiction, “a # noft-a,” as a general rule of symbolism and hence as an a priori condition of thought, asserts that a negative is always distinct in significance 220 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH from its positive. This principle is codrdinate with the law of identity, “a = a,” which asserts that any symbol is equivalent (or identical) in meaning with itself. Both of these principles can be interpreted in another way, that is, as general conditions of the being of objects, and these existential interpretations assume the principles as rules of symbolism. If a means an object — any object — the law of identity states that “any object is identical with itself,’ and the law of contradiction that “any object is distinct from anything other than itself.’ These statements are true only if existing objects have the formal characters of iden- tity and diversity. For the limited reality which can be con- sistently presented and represented — for the existing objects of empirical-rational knowledge — these laws must hold; but whether they hold for all reality can be determined by nothing less than a complete metaphysical theory. The third law of thought, the principle of the excluded middle, joins the idea of truth to that of negation. This principle is not necessary to the very existence of meaning, as are the others, but it is necessary to inference. If the negative means the same as any proposition distinct from the positive through an object meant, it will always be true that “either p or nof-p is true (but not both).” To believe a negative in its full ambiguity is to be ready to accept “anything other than the positive,”’ which is disbelieved. This form of bare denial does not limit itself to the possible grounds of the falsity of the proposition disbelieved. More com- monly, denial and disbelief are directed toward values specially selected from among the possible values of the negative; that is, toward the values which might be grounds of the falsity of the proposition denied. These grounds are determined by the gener- alizations of science and common sense, which are the tests of the “non-existence of objects” and the falsity of propositions, as well as of the existence of objects and the truth of proposi- : NEGATION AND CONTRADICTION 221 tions. But no negative judgment is wholly equivalent in effect to a positive one, since its ambiguity is never eliminated, and it might mean something other than it is believed to mean. The material consistency of the knowledge whose truth and falsity is tested by its compatibility or incompatibility with other portions of knowledge (accepted as true) can be contrasted with the formal consistency of conceptual systems which con- form to the principles of identity and contradiction, as general rules of symbolism, but are not affirmed to be either true or false. Conceptual validity and truth are distinct. It is possible to construct valid deductive systems which are completely unin- terpreted, in which the identity and distinctness of concepts (or symbols) and of logical forms alone are considered. Logical form can be isolated and studied in itself. This is the work of the purely formal deduction which, in Mr. Russell’s phrase, “‘does not know what it is talking about, or whether what it says is true.” CHAPTER VII FORMAL DEDUCTION I Format logic might be defined as “‘the science of pure form,” for it is interested in forms, and their connections, apart from any “‘matter” in which they might be exemplified. Since sym- bols in themselves embody logical forms, formal deductive sys- tems can be presented in uninterpreted symbols, they can be stated as if they referred to no objects; and logical form, thus dissociated from a “‘matter,”’ becomes a subject of study in itself. There are numerous sets of postulates for geometry, — both Euclidean and non-Euclidean, — for arithmetic and algebra, for serial order, and for logic itself, which attain — or nearly attain — this ideal of abstract statement, and it is these systems which best illustrate pure deduction. An examination of them makes it plain that formal deduction is concerned with nothing but forms and their relations. In order that the deductive connections in _ these systems may stand forth clearly, they are separated from the subject-matter and stated in terms of postulates, axioms, and theorems which might equally well apply to other subject- matters. Though these postulates, axioms, and theorems can be interpreted in many different ways, their form remains the same whatever objects they refer to — even if they refer to no ob- jects. Their form is independent of all interpretations. Such systems are hypothetical in the sense that they are purely conceptual and not asserted. They conform to the prin- ciples of the construction of concepts, that is, of the use of sym- bols, and are therefore possibilities for thought; but the question of their truth or falsity does not enter. If complete interpretations FORMAL DEDUCTION 223 for them can be found, they will be ‘‘materially”’ consistent and true for these interpretations; the hypothetical connections be- tween the postulates, axioms, and theorems will become infer- ences; the theorems can be truly asserted as consequences of the postulates and axioms. But if they have no interpretations, or only incomplete interpretations, these systems will still be possi- bilities for thought — conceptually “valid” and “formally” consistent; and, from the point of view of formal logic, this is all that they need be. It is not possible to empty a set of postulates of all meaning, for it would then cease to be a set of postulates. An uninter- preted deductive system is not a collection of meaningless marks. It has its plan of syntax, its groups, its terms and symbols of unity; its meaning is syntactical; within a general framework of significance, the uninterpreted symbols become variables, which, though they do not actually refer to objects, could refer only to objects whose formal characteristics are those given in the symbolic groups of the system. The general scheme of sym- bolic structure determines the possible values of these variables. Some symbolic context is always necessary to a variable. Out- side a context, a variable is not a symbol (and not a variable); and though the context of the variable may include symbols of fixed significance, this context need be only a formal plan of grouping. If every element, excepting the form, of a symbolic expression is a variable, the expression will not lose its meaning. If only one factor in the meaning is determinate, viz., the form, this will be sufficient to give the expression significance as a whole — a significance that has reached the maximum of in- determinateness. It is then the use of variables in a general con- text of logical structure which makes the study of form in itself possible. The meaning of a formal deductive system is syntactical, and so the postulates of the system are a plan of syntax, which de- 224 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH termines what groups have significance in the system and how these groups can be derived from one another. The deductive connections appear as rules of substitution, by which one sym- bol (or group) can replace other symbols (or groups) and yield expressions which still have meaning. To state this plan of syn- tax, it is necessary to assume nothing but the general principles of symbolism and certain possibilities of substitution; these as- sumptions are sufficient to make the system a connected whole which embodies a number of different logical forms related (hy- pothetically) to one another as premises to conclusions. The structure alone is constant; all other elements in the meaning are variable. When the system is asserted for a definite (and complete) interpretation, these hypothetical connections be- come the premises and conclusions of inferences, and the propo- sitions that were assumed in their maximum generality, without interpretation, prove to be a deductive exposition of truths which hold for certain sets of objects. But when there is no interpretation, the system retains its syntactical meaning; through the conditions of significance imposed on it, it contin- ues to be a presentation of logical forms connected in certain ways; and this is all it originally purports to be. It is not strictly true that, in putting forward a formal deduc- tive system, “we do not know what we are talking about,” though there is no doubt, since all the elements of the system with the exception of the form are variable, that we need not know or care “whether what we say is true.” We are talking about logical forms, which are given in the very symbols through which we talk about them. We are mapping possible systems of concepts, as Columbus mapped the continent of which he dis- covered only the shore; but in this case it is not even necessary to know that there is a continent to be mapped; we need know only the principles of map-making to explore the world of possi- bilities. FORMAL DEDUCTION 225 II The general principles of symbolism, that is, the most general conditions of the construction of concepts, have already been stated. They are (1) the principle of group significance, that the meaning of any group is a function of the meanings of its ele- ments and their grouping; (2) the general rule of “‘symbolic grammar,” that every significant group must contain both a symbol of unity and terms (or a term), and this rule demands that the symbols of unity be distinguished from the terms; (3) the principle of identity, that every symbol has one and only one meaning; and (4) the principle of contradiction, that thereis at least one symbol which is always distinct in meaning from any given symbol, that is, its negative, which means (ambiguously) the same as any symbol other than the positive; and this prin- ciple demands that there be distinctness as well as identity of meaning. Every symbolic system must be such that it could be inter- preted, even though it refers specifically to no objects; other- wise, it would not be a possibility for thought. The general prin- ciples of symbolism themselves are the conditions under which systems could be interpreted. From these principles, in the above order, it follows that any purely conceptual system must, first, be composed of groups which are taken to be significant as wholes. If the system contained no such groups, its symbolic elements would not be variables, but mere meaningless marks.! Thus there must be certain signs of syntax to indicate the struc- ture of the groups — their divisions into major and minor wholes, and the group relations between these wholes. Secondly, the symbols of unity must be distinguished from the terms; and when the system is interpreted, the former will stand 1 Or else symbols with a determinate reference to objects, in which case the system would not be uninterpreted. 226 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH for relations, operations, or qualities in their rdéle as elements of unity in facts, while the latter will stand for individuals or for universals in their substantive réle. There are no objects which are not terms related or qualified or operated on in some way; hence, without this distinction between symbols of unity and terms, the system could not be interpreted and would not be a possibility for thought. Thirdly, every symbol must be identical in meaning with it- self, that is, the equation, a = a, must hold throughout the sys- tem; and this principle (the principle of identity) gives a rule of substitution which is valid in all systems, v2z., the rule that any symbol can be substituted for itself without altering the mean- ing of the group in which it is substituted. The concept of iden- tity makes it possible, moreover, to define symbols which are distinct in character as identical in meaning. Indeed, many of the symbolic elements of a conceptual system may enter the system only through being identical in meaning with the origi- nal groups of other elements, that is, many of the variables may gain their variable significance through definition alone. Such equivalent symbols can replace one another in any of the groups; this also is a rule of substitution which is valid in all systems. Fourthly, symbols originally taken as distinct in meaning must be construed as distinct throughout. None of the transfor- mations of the system can result in the use of distinct symbols as the same or equivalent. For this would violate the principle of contradiction, which asserts that any possible value of a nega- tive, that is, any symbol distinct from a given symbol, is always distinct from this symbol. And yet this principle permits the sub- stitution of distinct, as well as identical, symbols for one another, when the special rules of the system so provide. Though such substitutions of distinct symbols for one another will always result in alterations of meaning, this fact does not render such substitutions impossible, for distinct symbols do not become FORMAL DEDUCTION Q227 identical in meaning by being substituted for one another. Iden- tity of meaning is more than a possibility of mutual substitu- tion.’ In fact, the more important transformations in any sys- tem are the ones which come about when the symbols in groups are replaced by other (distinct) symbols. Special rules of substi- tution, which hold only for the special systems in question, pro- vide for transformations of this type. A formal set of postulates will begin by assuming that certain symbolic groups, whose terms and symbols of unity have been distinguished, are significant, that is, that these groups have syn- tactical meaning apart from any objects they might represent. A set of postulates will also assume some special rules of substi- tution, in addition to the general rule that the same symbol or symbols of identical meaning can replace one another. It may further assume certain special identities of meaning, that is, special equivalences or definitions, which (when the system is interpreted) will represent identities in objects. With these as- sumptions, the set of postulates is a complete plan of syntax for a symbolic system. Any group or equation which can be derived from the original groups or equations by the rules of substitu- tion will be significant in the system, and combinations of sym- bols which cannot thus be derived will be nonsensical; they will have no meaning in this context. The plan marks the boundaries of an area of concepts; it separates what is conceivable or sig- nificant in terms of its own symbols from what is inconceivable or nonsensical in these terms; but it does not separate what is true from what is false. All of its propositions are “‘thinkable”’; whether they are true or false is another and an irrelevant ques- tion. Deduction in a system of this type is the manipulation of the symbols according to the rules. 1 Symbols which are identical in meaning must, if they stand for objects, stand for the same object; while symbols which can be substituted for one an- other may stand for diverse objects, and must stand for diverse objects if they are distinct in meaning. 228 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH The process of formal deduction, divorced from a subject- matter and occupied only with logical forms and their connec- tions, is the derivation by substitution of significant symbolic groups of different elements and forms from other symbolic groups; and a formal deductive system is a set of uninterpreted symbolic complexes of many distinct forms and elements built up, by this process of substitution, from a few simple symbols and symbolic complexes. Where possibilities alone are consid- ered, deduction is an engrossing game played with symbols. The rules of the game are the general conditions of the use of sym- bols, together with the possibilities of manipulation opened up by these rules and by any other special rules which may be de- vised for special systems. III The study of a set of postulates — for geometry, algebra, logic, or any other field of knowledge — reveals the importance of the part which substitution plays in formal deduction. Logicians speak of substitution as an essential modus operandi or real operation in uninterpreted systems.! It is in fact the sole means of connecting the theorems with the postulates and axioms when these postulates and axioms are purely hypotheti- cal, that is, when their truth or falsity as premises and conclu- sions is not even considered. Sets of postulates rarely state their rules of substitution ex- plicitly, though they always make use of such rules. One of the simplest methods of providing for the manipulation through substitution of the symbols of a deductive system is that em- ployed by Mr. E. V. Huntington.? As the “base” of a set of postulates, he assumes a class, K, of elements, a, b, c, etc., and 1 See C. I. Lewis, A Survey of Symbolic Logic (1918), pp. 353 ff.; also A. N. Whitehead, A Treatise on Universal Algebra (1898), Bk. I, ch. 1, “On the Nature of a Calculus.” ? See E. V. Huntington, Sets of Independent Postulates for the Algebra of Logic, Transc. Amer. Math. Soe. (1904), v, 288-309. FORMAL DEDUCTION 229 relations or operations, R, S, etc. Since the postulates hold for any element of K, the terms, a, b, c, etc., can be mutually substi- tuted for one another without rendering the postulates invalid. Thus, if (aRb) is postulated in the system, (aRc) and (bRc) will also be in the system, Further, if the group (aRb), is itself an element of the class, K, it can be substituted for a, b, or c (since it might be any element of K), giving the complex ((aRb) Rb), etc. And if the substitutions were carried forward — (aRb) re- placing a or 6 in this latter group, and so on — an infinity of complexes of different forms would be provided for by this sin- gle possibility of substitution. The result of assuming the class, K, as a “‘base”’ is then the same as if it were explicitly stated, in the beginning, that any of the simple symbols of the system can be mutually substituted for one another, and any of the original groups can be substituted for any of the simple symbols. In the Principia Mathematica, Messrs. Whitehead and Rus- sell make use of substitutions in most of their proofs, especially in those of the earlier propositions from which the later ones follow by implication; and they speak of this process as “notic- ing that (these propositions) are instances of general rules,” ! that is, of the primitive propositions given in the first section of their work. These substitutions are possible, in the symbolic system of the Principia Mathematica, because these primitive propositions are principles of logic asserted for any proposition, rather than purely uninterpreted groups of symbols. In Mr. Huntington’s language, the class, K, of the Principia Mathe- matica is the class of all propositions; any proposition can be substituted for any other in the original complexes of the sys- tem. For example, p v p->- p, states that ‘“‘any proposition or the same proposition implies itself.’’ And from this postulate, together with the definition of implication, p > g-=-~pvq, which asserts that “‘an implication between two propositions 1 Whitehead and Russell, Principia Mathematica, i, 102. 230 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH means that either the first is false or the second true,” the princi- ple of reductio ad absurdum, p > ~p:+ >+~>p (“any proposition that implies its negative implies its own falsity”), can be de- rived by substitution as follows: The proposition, ~p, (not-p), is substituted for p in the primitive proposition, pv p:>:?p, giving ~pv op->+ op. Now, if wp is substituted for q in the definition of implication, the resultisp 3 ~p-=: pvp; and if p > ~p (being equivalent to ~pv ~p) is substituted for the latter in ~pv w~p:>5-~p, we have p > ~p->. op, the principle of reductio ad absurdum, which was to be proved. This proof illustrates how the Principia Mathematica derives the ‘“‘immediate consequences of the primitive propositions.” “‘The recognition that a certain proposition is an instance of some gen- eral proposition previously proved or assumed,” say Messrs. Whitehead and Russell, “‘is essential to the process of deduction from general rules”’; ! and this is, in effect, the recognition that certain substitutions are permitted in the system. It must be observed that these deductive substitutions are al- ways carried through completely. If one symbol replaces an- other in a group, it replaces the latter wherever it occurs. Thus, when ~7 is substituted for p in pv p->->=, every instance of the symbol p becomes an instance of ~p, giving ~pV ~p+a- op. That the substitutions must be complete is a general prin- ciple of deductive substitutions, the reason for which is not im- mediately evident. It will be remembered that the distribution of tautologous (or recurrent) elements is a formal feature of symbolic groups. Now, if the rule of completeness of substitution were not followed, groups that include tautologous members could be transformed into groups in which no tautologous members were present. A reflexive group, such as (Raa), could yield a non-reflexive group, such as (Rab). There is no objection to this if the system in ques- 1 Loe. cit. FORMAL DEDUCTION 231 tion contains a non-reflexive group (which is otherwise the same in form) for every reflexive group.’ But if the system contains no non-reflexive groups (or only non-reflexive groups which do not correspond in other formal features with its reflexive groups), the rule of completeness of substitution will be needed; other- wise, complexes which have no significance in the system will be introduced. In the first type of system (one which contains a non-reflexive group corresponding to every reflexive group), it is always possible on the other hand to derive the reflexive from the non-reflexive groups by substituting instances of the same symbol for distinct symbols: (Rabe), for example, gives (Raaa) if a is substituted for both b and ¢, so that the rule of complete- ness of substitution can be imposed on these systems without decreasing their deductive possibilities. The rule is therefore assumed as a general principle, applicable alike to those systems for which it is necessary and to those for which it is redundant. The reason is, in short, that non-reflexive complexes are more general in form than reflexive ones. The rule of completeness of substitution prevents us from deriving the more general forms (the non-reflexive) from the less general (the reflexive), but per- mits us to derive the less general from the more general by sub- stituting instances of the same symbol for distinct symbols. Though this latter type of substitution — of instances of the same symbol for distinct symbols — is permitted by the rule of completeness of substitution, it is not required by this rule, and it cannot be assumed that in all systems instances of the same symbol can replace distinct symbols. If this were erected into a general principle, there would be no systems which did not include reflexive groups, and there are many such — notably, systems of serial order. Indeed, for some systems, it can be laid down as a special rule that distinct symbols must always be re- 2 The term “reflexive group” is here taken in a general sense to mean any group containing tautologous members, however distributed. 232 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH placed by distinct symbols. In these systems it would be impos- sible to derive a complex such as (Raaa) from one such as (Rabe). This special rule prevents the introduction of tautologous ele- ments where tautologous elements were not originally present; it is applicable to systems whose complexes are irreflexive throughout. But if this narrower condition of substitution is not introduced, it is taken for granted that instances of the same symbol (that is, tautologous symbols) can replace distinct symbols; that reflexive groups can be derived from all the non- reflexive groups in the system. In most deductive systems, then, the rules of manipulation permit any of the original terms mutually to replace one an- other, and any of the basic or derived groups to replace any of these terms — the rule of completeness of substitution being al- ways observed, and the rule that distinct symbols must be sub- stituted for distinct symbols being sometimes added. Still other possibilities of manipulation than these highly gen- eral ones are usually provided for in a set of postulates. It may be specified that some of the groups are identical in meaning with others or with some of the original terms, and hence that these symbols of identical meaning can be mutually substituted for one another. In Mr. Huntington’s first set of postulates for the algebra of logic, among other equations, the following ap- pears: a® (b@c) = (a@®b) @ (a@c). When the system is interpreted, this equation means “a or b and ¢ is identical with a or b and aor ec.” ? It represents different structures in an iden- tical object, that is, on the class interpretation of the algebra, the expressions on each side of the sign of equality stand for the same class. But when the system is uninterpreted, the equation merely states an intention to use these groups as identical in 1 There are some systems, however, in which the basic or derived groups cannot be substituted for the original terms, and an example of such a system is given below. See below, sec. vii, note. ? See E. V. Huntington, op. cit. FORMAL DEDUCTION 233 meaning, whether or not they refer to objects. Since such as- sumed identities of meaning equate different logical forms, they are “equations of structure.” In lieu of or in addition to these equations of structure, a sys- tem may include connections of meaning which appear as impli- cations. It may be specifically provided that some of the groups imply others. For instance, in Mr. Huntington’s postulates for serial order, it is stated that (afb) (bRc) “implies” (aRc), and this asserts (where R stands for the relation “‘precedes”’) that “if a precedes b and b precedes c, a precedes c.”’ ! Now, in an unin- terpreted system, these cannot be implications of the usual sort, for ordinarily implications are functions of the truth values of the propositions they unite; p implies g means that “either p is false or q is true,” that is, that when p is true, q is also true. Truth values are not considered in an uninterpreted system, and so these implications cannot be truth-implications. They become truth-implications when the system is interpreted. Otherwise, they are connections of meaning apart from truth and falsity, and as such are nothing but possibilities of substitution. If p im- plies q in an uninterpreted system, this implication means sim- ply that q can replace p as a conclusion in any deduction. Any series of transformations that leads to =: leads also to q. These “implicational substitutions” belong to a special class, and must not be confused with the others. If q is an “implica- tional substitute” for p, this provision does not allow q to take the place of p in any complex in which p appears; but it does allow q to be substituted for p when p appears at the end of a chain of deductions. And this is readily verified by any concrete example of implication: “x is human” implies “x is mortal,” and if “‘x is human” is deduced from the fact that “x walks erect and speaks,” “‘x is mortal”’ can also be deduced from this fact. But “x is mortal” cannot replace “‘x is human” wherever 1 E. V. Huntington, The Continuum (1917), p. 10. 234 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH the latter occurs; for instance, ‘zx is human” implies that “zx thinks’; and yet “x is mortal” does not imply that “x thinks.” An implicational substitute for any expression cannot replace this expression as a premise, or as a constituent in any expres- sion whatsoever, but it can replace it as a conclusion. There is one other important type of manipulation which must be noticed. The process of substitution is transitive, that is, if a can be substituted for b and 6 can be substituted for ¢, a can be substituted for c. If each of a series of propositions can replace one another in order, all of the intermediate steps can be dropped; the first of the series can be replaced by the last. This transitivity of substitutions enables us to bring together the premise and conclusion of a long line of deductions, the interven- ing links being omitted. And this principle applies where the substitutions proceed via identities of meaning, or where a con- clusion is replaced by something that it implies. Such condensa- tions of chains of deduction are employed in all systems; and the general rule that permits them will hereafter be used without specific statement, and will be referred to in proofs as “conden- sation.” The single modus operandi of pure deduction is the “real oper- ation” of substitution. By this operation alone the theorems of a deductive system are developed from the basic groups, equa- tions, and implications; and by this operation, also, the pre- mises and conclusions of the system are brought together or “condensed.”’ The postulates and theorems affirm no truths and no relations between truths. All that is considered is what groups have meaning in the system, and how these groups can replace one another. The manner of formulating a plan of syntax, that is, a set of postulates, for a deductive system, so that the basic groups can be transformed by substitutions into theorems, will be better understood through a more complete illustration, in which there FORMAL DEDUCTION 235 are many different possibilities of symbolic manipulation. The substitutions will always follow (1) the rule of completeness and (2) the rule that the same symbol, or symbols of identical mean- ing, can replace one another; but the special condition, that dis- tinct symbols must be substituted for distinct symbols, will not be imposed. When this system is before us, we can ask what con- nections among facts the deductive manipulations of the sym- bols might represent. IV The system chosen as an illustration is a Boolean Algebra, an algebra of logic; and it will be interpreted as referring to classes and class relationships, though it can be interpreted in several other ways, e.g., in terms of regions in space together with cer- tain relations between these regions.! But no interpretation is necessary to it. Through symbolic complexes of variable ele- ments, which have syntactical meaning apart from objects they might mean, it presents an area of possible logical forms and shows how, from a few of these forms, all the others can be de- rived. Logical forms and their connections are its sole concern. It is complete in itself as a collection of symbolic groups, equa- tions, and rules of manipulation; and if it had no interpretation it would still be an experiment in possibilities for thought. That it happens to be a class algebra is an interesting and useful acci- dent, but not essential to it. (1) The basic groups of this system are (Rab), (Sab), and (Na). R, S, and N are undefined symbols of unity, and a and b are undefined terms. The parentheses are signs of syntax or grouping, to be construed in the way in which such signs are always construed. (Since these groups have a logical structure, they are significant, and the symbols R, S, N, a, and b are vari- 1 See E. V. Huntington, op. cit. 236 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH ables.) A third undefined term, c, will also be assumed. R, S, N, a, b, and c are symbolically distinct.’ (2) The substitutions permitted are: (a) any of the undefined terms can be mutually substituted for one another, and (b) any of the basic symbolic groups, or any groups derived from them, can be substituted for any of the undefined terms. This latter rule permits substitutions in one direction only, that is, the un- defined terms cannot be substituted for any of the groups, un- less they are equivalent to them. (The rule of completeness of substitution, and the principle that the same or equivalent sym- bols can replace one another, are taken for granted.) (3) The following identities of meaning are assumed: A. Ra(Sb(Nb)) = a. C. Ra(Sbc) = S(Rab)(Rac). B. Sa(Rb(Nb)) = a. D. Sa(Rbe) = R(Sab)(Sac). Since the original undefined terms of the system appear on both sides of these identities, these identities are not definitions. When the system is interpreted, these equivalences will repre- sent differences of structure in an identical object. ? They are *“‘equations of structure.” (4) Two symbols which are not among the undefined terms are introduced by definitions: E. z = Sa(Na). F. u = Ra(Na). These are definitions because z and wu are not included in the original terms but enter the system only through being identical in meaning with certain ones of its significant groups. Such definitions are not necessary to the exposition; they are merely symbolic conveniences which condense complex expressions. But it would be uneconomical to take as undefined, and hence to 1 The spatial order of the symbols in the groups is irrelevant; it plays no part in their logical form, which is determined by grouping alone; and there- fore it is not necessary to mention the fact that (Rab), (aRb), and (abR) are the same symbol. 2 See above, ch. II, sec. vi. . 1 ; ’ ‘ { FORMAL DEDUCTION 237 place among the original (primitive) symbols of the system, a symbol whose meaning could be defined through some of the groups. “Occam’s razor”’ must always be applied; entities must not be assumed unless they are necessary. (It is to be noted that the rules of substitution given in (2) hold for the original terms, and not for z and wu. There are special rules for these terms, which can be deduced from the other rules.) The general and special conditions of substitution permit three classes of transformations in this system: (1) The elements of a group can be altered without altering its form. If, for ex- ample, a replaces b, and ¢ replaces a, in Ra(Sb(Nb)) = a, this substitution will give the equation, Re(Sa(Na)) = c, which is of the same form as the first, but of different elements. Such trans- formations are unimportant. (2) Tautologies can be introduced where tautologies did not originally appear, for there is no pro- viso that distinct symbols must be replaced by distinct symbols. Thus from Ra(Sb(Nb)) = a, we can derive Ra(Sa(Na)) = a; from (Rab) or (Sab) we can derive (Raa) or (Saa), etc. The sys- tem therefore contains reflexive forms corresponding to all its non-reflexive forms. (3) Complexes of a higher type can be de- rived from complexes of a lower type, and this process can be carried, theoretically, to infinity. (Rab), for example, yields (Ra(Rab)), and this complex yields (Ra(Ra(Rab))), etc., when (Rab) is substituted for b; so that the system contains an infinity of possible forms. It is apparent that all of the complexes which appear in the equations, A, B, C, and D, and in the definitions, E and F, are significant in the system; they can all be derived from the basic groups by these rules of substitution. The “equations of structure”’ and the definitions, moreover, make possible a fourth class of transformations, those obtained by substituting equivalent symbols or groups in groups. With- out the “equations of structure,” each of the groups in the sys- 238 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH tem might, when the whole is interpreted, stand for a distinct object. The equations impose limitations on these possible dis- tinctions of meaning, as do also all the other equations which can be deduced from them by proper substitutions; and at the same time these equations increase the number of manipula- tions which can be performed in the system. (5) Some of the most important theorems, and their deriva- tions, are the following: 1. Raz = a. 2. Sau = a. The proof of these two theorems requires the definitions, E and F.. These definitions are, like the other equivalences in the system, subject to all the permitted transformations by substi- tution. Therefore, z = Sa(Na) yields z = Sb(Nb) by the sub- stitution of 6 for a; and u = Ra(Na) yields u = Rb(Nb), by a similar substitution. And, since equivalent symbols can be sub- stituted for one another, we can derive Raz = a from the equa- tion Ra(Sb(Nb)) = a by replacing Sb(Nb) by z. Similarly, we can derive Sau = a by replacing Rb(Nb) by u in the equation Sa(Rb(Nb)) = a. This is the deduction of theorems 1 and 2. The rules for the substitution of these two special symbols, z and u, follow from their definitions. Since they are equivalent, respectively, to Sa(Na) and Ra(Na), they can be substituted for any symbol for which these groups can be substituted. There- fore, they can replace any of the terms, a, b, c, ete., of the sys- tem; but these terms cannot replace them, for these terms can- not replace the groups through which z and wu are defined. In other words, so far as concerns the manipulation of the symbols in this system, z and u are values of any of the variable terms, but they are not themselves variables; they are constants.! 1 This introduces a new kind of variability, “functional variability,” which is something other than indeterminateness of significance; z and wu are func- tional constants, rather than functional variables; but their meaning is still undetermined. This is explained below, sec. vi. FORMAL DEDUCTION 239 Other theorems are the following: 8. Raa =a Proof: a = Sau (by theorem 2). Raa = Su(Raa) (Raa replaces a in 2.) Su(Raa) = S(Ra(Na)) (Raa) (By def. F, Ra(Na) replaces u). S(Ra(Na))(Raa) = Ra(Sa(Na)) (where a replaces b, and Na re- places c, in C). Ra(Sa(Na)) = Raz (By def. E, z replaces Sa(Na)). Raz =a (by theorem 1). Therefore: a = Raa (“‘condensation”’). 4. Saa =a. This can be deduced in exactly the same manner as 3, by using theorem 1 for 2 and u for z. Theorems 3 and 4 are the analogues of one another for the symbols of unity R and S respectively. 5. a = N(Na) Proof: 1’. 2 = S(Na)(N(Na)) (by def. E, where Na replaces a). 2’, u = R(Na)(N(Na)) (by def. F, where Na replaces a). a = Raz (by theorem 1). Raz = Ra(S(Na)(N(Na))) (By 1’, S(Na)(N(Na)), replaces z). Ra(S(Na)(N(Na))) = S(Ra(Na))(Ra(N(Na))) (by C, where Na replaces 6 and N(Na) replaces c). S(Ra(Na))(Ra(N(Na) = Su(Ra(N(Na))). (By def. F, u replaces Ra(Na)). Su(Ra(N(Na))) = Ra(N(Na)) (by theorem 2, where Ra(N(Na)) replaces a). Therefore: 3’. Ra(N(Na)) =a (“condensation”’). N(Na) = R(N(Na))z (by theorem 1, where N(Na) re- places a). R(N(Na))z = R(N(Na))(Sa(Na)). (By def. E, Sa(Na) replaces z). R(N(Na))(Sa(Na)) = S(R(N(Na))a)(R(N(Na))(Na)) (by C, where N(Na) replaces a, a replaces b, and Na replaces c). S(R(N(Na))a)(R(N(Na))(Na)) = S(R(N(Na))a)u (By 2’, u replaces the group R(N(Na))(Na)). S(R(N(Na))a)u = R(N(Na))a (by theorem 2, where R(N(Na))a replaces a). Therefore: 4’. N(Na) = R(N(Na))a_ (“condensation”). Therefore: N(Na) =a (by “‘condensation” of 3’ and 4’). 240 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH When the system is interpreted as a Boolean Algebra, this theorem is the principle of double negation. (It is to be noted in the proof that the group Ra(N(Na)) in 3’ is the same as the group R(N(Na))a in 4’, since the spatial order of the symbols is irrelevant.) 6. 2=Nu Proof: z = Sa(Na) (by def. E). z= Su(Nu) (u replaces a in def. E). Su(Nu) = Nu (by theorem 2, where Nu replaces a). Therefore: z = Nu (“‘condensation”’). 7. ui= Nz Proof: u = Ra(Na) (by def. F). u = Rz(Nz) (z replaces a in def. F). Rz(Nz) = Nz (by theorem 1, where Nz replaces a). Therefore: u = Nz (“‘condensation’’). Some of the other theorems which can be derived in the sys- tem, but of which the proofs are not given, are the following: 8. Rau = u 12. Rab = N(S(Na)(Nb)) 9. Saz =z 13. Sab = N(R(Na)(Nb)) 10. Ra(Sab) =a 14. R(Rab)b = Ra(Rab) 11. Sa(Rab) = a 15. S(Sab)b = Sa(Sab) The introduction by definition of the group (b(Za)) simplifies the system; on the class interpretation of the algebra this group means that the class a is included in, or “subsumed under,” the class 6.! This new complex can be defined in several different ways: (b(Ta)) =(Rab = b) (G) (b(Ia)) = (Sab = a) (H) (b(Ia)) = (Rb(Na) = u) (I) (b(Ia)) = (Sa(Nb) = z) (J) 1 The grouping of (6(Ia)) indicates that it has a “‘sense”’ or order; the al- ternative order is (a(Ib)). No specific symbol of unity is inserted to join the sub-group (Ja) or (Ib), as the case may be, to the term a or b; the outer paren- theses show that they form a group, and this is all that is necessary; their group unity is of the most general sort — simply “‘togetherness”’ or “unity.” FORMAL DEDUCTION 241 Some of the postulates and theorems stated above can be translated into the terms of this new group, and this translation will give, among others, the following theorems: 16. (a(Iz)) Proof: (Rbz = b) is in the system (b replaces a in theorem 1). (Rab = b) = (b(Ia)) (by def. G). (Rzb = b) = (b(Iz)) (z replaces a in def. G). Therefore: (b(Iz)) is in the system, since it is equivalent by definition to a group in the system. 17. (u(Ia)) Proof: (Rau = u) is in the system (by theorem 8). (Rab = b) = (b(Ia)) (by def. G). (Rau = u) = (u(Ia)) (u replaces 6 in def. G). Therefore: (u(Za)) is in the system. 18. (u(Iz)) Proof: (Ruz = u) is in the system. (u replaces a in theorem 1). (Ruz = u) = (u(Iz)) (u replaces b, and z replaces a, in def. G). Therefore: (u(Iz)) is in the system. 19. (a(I(Sab))) 20. ((Rab)(Ia)) The proof of theorems 19 and 20 is similar to that of 16, 17, and 18, where theorems 10 and 11 and definitions G and H are employed. 21. (a(Ia)) Proof: (Raa = a) is in the system (by theorem 8). (Raa = a) = (a(Ia)) (a replaces b in def, G). Therefore: (a(Ia)) is in the system. There are many more theorems in terms of the group (b(Ja)) which are not stated. This group is unlike the groups in terms of R, S, and N in that there are no rules which permit the substitution of (b(Ia)), or 242 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH its derivatives, for the original terms, a, b, and c, of the system. The group is defined as identical in meaning with the equiva- lence (Rab = b), or with the other equivalences given as H, I, and J. It can, therefore, be substituted for these equivalences; and when the latter, or their derivatives, are members of the system, some J-groups will also be, by definition, members of the system. But (Rab = 6), or the other equivalences, H, I, and J, cannot be substituted for a, b, and c; and hence the J-groups cannot be substituted for these terms.! V In practice, all deductive systems are devised with one eye on the facts, that is, on an interpretation. They are stated as if they referred to no objects, but they prove in the end to be connected expositions of truths which hold in some realm of experience, that is, to be systems of geometry, algebra, logic, etc. And if the plan of a system were constructed without this arriére pensée, it is not likely that an interpretation — or anything more than a trivial one — could be found for it. To explore all possibilities for thought, cut off from moorings in the world of the actual, would be an interesting but an endless experiment, for the num- ber of possible conceptual systems is infinite; and so those sys- tems which embody the structure of actual sets of objects are selected. Pure speculation then gives way to assertion, what seem to be arbitrary manipulations of symbols become infer- ences, and the significance of the whole is bound down to the real. A conceptual system which corresponded to no subject- matter would be an exercise in logical construction, and nothing more. Yet such exercises show that from the point of view of 1 The original rule of manipulation, that any of the basic groups or their derivatives can replace any of the basic terms, does not provide that the “equations of structure”’ or the definitions, taken as wholes, can replace these terms; for these identities of meaning are not derived from the basic groups (though their constituents are), but are postulated on their own account. FORMAL DEDUCTION 243 formal logic all that need. be considered, even in an interpreted system, are logical forms and their connections. The system which has been developed here is adapted to sev- eral different subject-matters. The symbols a, b, and c can stand for propositions, and the groups (Rab), (Sab), and (Na) for cer- tain “truth-functions”’ of propositions; v2z., (Rab) will mean the proposition, “either a or b (not excluding both) is true”; (Sab) will mean the proposition, “‘a and 6 are both true’; and (Na) will mean the negative of a. Another interpretation can be given in terms of regions of a plane surface, together with certain rela- tions between these regions; viz., (Rab) represents the region that includes both regions a and 6; (Sab) represents the region where a and b intersect; and (Na) represents all of the plane that lies outside the region a.1 We shall interpret the system as a logic of classes. A class has previously been described as a totality of distinct objects which have some predicate in common. Every predicate determines such a totality, e.g., the predicate “‘man”’ deter- mines the class ““men.”’ Classes may be related to one another in many ways, and these class relationships can be employed in reasoning. Classes may overlap, they may include or exclude onc another, their members may be added together to form a new class. There is also a null class, one that has no members, the class of “nothing”; and this class is determined by any predi- cates of which there are no instances, e.g., “‘the present King of France”’ determines the null class. Further, there is a universal class of which everything, excepting this class itself, is a mem- ber.? Every postulate and theorem of the system can be inter- 1 See E. V. Huntington, Sets of Independent Postulates for the Algebra of Logic, cited above. 2 This exception is necessary to avoid the difficulties involved in the notion of “the class of all classes.” See Whitehead and Russell, Principia Mathe- matica, ch. 2. Though the universal class is not a member of itself, still it is coextensive with itself; 7.e., the relation of class inclusion or subsumption, represented by the J-groups of the system, holds for it; so that (w(Zu)) is true. 244. SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH preted as a true statement about classes, and every manipula- tion as a true inference, leading from premises to conclusions that concern classes, The original terms of the system, a, b, and ¢ stand for any classes; but since these terms are symbolically distinct, they can not, in any expression, be interpreted as signifying the same class. (Rab) means the class that includes all the members of a and 6, and only these members; this is called the “logical sum” of a and b. (Sab) means the class whose members belong both to a and 0; it is the “logical product” of a and b. (Na) means the class of all objects excluded by the class a. The symbol z stands for the null class, and wu for the universal class, for “nothing” and “everything,” respectively. The expression (b(Ia)) means that the class a is included in the class b. The rules of substitution tell us: (1) That any of the original terms can be mutually substi- tuted for one another, and that any of the basic groups, or groups derived from them, can be substituted for any of the original terms. Now if, on the class interpretation, (Rab), (Sab), (Na) and their derivatives represent anything, they will stand for classes. The logical sums, products, and negatives of classes, together with their derivatives, are themselves classes. Hence they can replace the variables a, b, and c in any expression and the expression will still be true, for a, b, and ¢ are any classes. Moreover, every sum and product might be the sum or product of a class and itself; so that every expression containing distinct symbols can be altered, by substitutions, into one containing tautologous symbols without rendering the expression untrue. (For the reason that groups formed by R, S, and N stand for the same general sort of entities, that is, classes, as those meant by their terms, these symbols of unity represent operations, rather than relations.) } 1 See below, sec. vii. FORMAL DEDUCTION 245 (2) The group (b(Za)), which means that the class a is in- cluded in the class 6, cannot, on the other hand, be substituted for a, b, and ¢, since it does not stand for a class. If a is included in b, the classes a and b are related, but this relation constitutes a new sort of fact, which is not itself a class. (3) The classes z and u can replace any of the original terms, a, b, and c, but these terms cannot replace z and u; for the null and universal classes are special elements, they are unique. What is true of any class is true of them, since they are classes, but the converse does not hold. (4) Equivalent groups or symbols can replace one another, for they represent the same class. Thus the null class is defined by and can be substituted for Sa(Na); it is the logical product of any class and its negative, that is, it is the class that includes all the members both belonging to and excluded by any class a— and these are no members. Obviously, these rules of manipulation make it possible, through the substitution of interpreted symbols or groups in other interpreted groups, to derive true propositions about classes from other true propositions about classes; they yield true inferences. The interpretations of the postulates are not so simple as those of some of the theorems. Theorem 1, Raz = a, is the fa- miliar proposition that “‘the logical sum of any class and the null class is identical with the first class,” that is, ‘the class in- cluding all members of a and of the null class is the same as a.”’ Theorem 2, Sau = a, states that “the class of members common to a and the class of everything is the same as a.” Definition E, z = Sa(Na), is the principle of contradiction for classes, and asserts that “‘a class and its negative have nothing in common.” Definition F, u = Ra(Na), is, on the other hand, the law of the excluded middle for classes; it affirms that “the class including all members of a and all members excluded by a is the class of 246 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH everything,” or simply “that a class and its negative exhaust the universe.’ Theorems 3 and 4, Raa =a and Saa = a, are two forms of the principle of identity for classes. The first states that “the class including all the members of a and of a is the class a”’; and the second, that “‘the class of members common to a and a is the class a.’’ Theorem 5, a = N(Na), that is, ‘‘the class that excludes all that is excluded by any class a is the class a,” is the principle of double negation; “‘not-not-a is identical with a.” Theorems 6 and7,z = Nuandu = Nz, show that the universal and null classes exclude, or are the negatives of, one another, that is, “nothing” excludes “everything” and “everything” excludes “nothing.” ! Theorem 8, Rau = u, states that ‘the uni- versal class added to any class a gives the universal class”; and this theorem differentiates the wu (and the “‘addition’’) of the class algebra from the number 1 (and the “‘addition”’) of ordi- nary algebra; 1 added to any number does not give 1. Theo- rem 9, Saz = z, however, shows an analogy between the null class and the zero of numerical algebra: “the logical product of any class a and the null class is the null class.”” Theorems 10 and 11 are two forms of the principle of “absorption”: Ra(Sab) = a asserts that “any class a absorbs by addition a logical product of itself”’; and Sa(Rab) = a, that “‘any class a absorbs the sum of itself and another class in a logical product of itself and this sum.”’ Theorems 12 and 13 are forms of the principle of “‘trans- position”: Rab = N(S(Na)(Nb)) allows a sum of classes to be transposed into the negative of the product of the negatives of these classes; while Sab = N(R(Na)(Nb)) allows a logical product of classes to be transposed into the negative of the sum of the negatives of these classes. Theorems 14 and 15 are the “‘as- sociative”’ law for class sums and products, respectively. Postu- lates C and D are the “distributive” law; Ra(Sbc) = S(Rab) 1 By theorem 18, “nothing”’ is also subsumed under or included by “every- thing.” The null class has the peculiar property of implying its own negative. FORMAL DEDUCTION 247 (Rac) states that “the sum of aclass and a product of classes is the same as a product of two sums” (loosely put); while Sa(Rbe) = R(Sab) (Sac) states that “the product of a class and a sum of classes is the same as a sum of products” (loosely put). The symbols express this proposition more clearly than a brief form of words can, as is also the case with postulates A and B: Ra(Sb(Nb)) = a asserts that “if the logical product of a class and its negative is added to another class, the whole will be identical with this latter class”; and Sa(Rb(Nb)) = a asserts that “if the logical sum of any class and its negative forms a product with another class, the whole will be identical with this latter class.” The “commutative” law, Rab = Rba and Sab = Sba, does not appear in this system. It is unnecessary to state that “the logical sum or product of a and b is the same as the logical sum or product of 6 and a” for the reason that the spatial order of the symbols in the groups is not relevant to their significance. Rab is the same symbol as Rba, and Sab is the same symbol as Sba; the operations of class addition and class multiplication are symmetrical, and these symbolic groups — which are without order — represent them as such. The group (b(Ia)), however, has an order; “the class a is sub- sumed under the class b” means something different from “the class 6 is subsumed under the class a.’’ The order (6(Ta)) stands for the first of these facts, and the order (a(Ib)), for the second; and these differences of order are represented by the distribu- tion of the terms a and 6 in the two constituent groups of the ex- pression (a(Jb)), not by the spatial arrangement of the symbols. The theorems in terms of J-groups, interpreted as class inclu- sions or subsumptions, state the following propositions: Theo- rem 16, (a(Jz)), affirms that “the null class is included in any class,” that is, any class covers as great a logical area as a class of no members, and, if it is not itself a class of no members, covers 248 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH a wider area. Theorem 17, (u(Ia)), expresses the fact that “any class is included in the class of everything,” which is plainly true. Theorem 18, (w(Zz)), is, like theorem 16, paradoxical; it asserts that “the null class is included in the class of everything,” that is, that the universal class covers everything which is covered by the null class—and much more. Theorem 19, (a(I(Sab))), states that “any class includes the members common to itself and an- other class’’; and theorem 20, ((Rab) (Ia)), that “any class is included in the class formed by itself and another added to- gether.” Theorem 21, (a(Ja)), tells us that “‘any class includes and is included by itself.”” The definitions of class inclusion, G and H, are clearly true: (b(Ja)) = (Rab = b) says that “if a class 6 is identical with the class composed of all the members of a and 6, this is equivalent to the statement that } includes a’’; and definition H, (b([a)) = (Sab = a), says that “if a class a is identical with the class whose members are common to a and b, this is equivalent to the statement that a is included in 6.” All of the original postulates, definitions, rules of substitution, and many of the theorems of this deductive system are thus seen by inspection to be true for classes. But in order to verify the system as a whole for this interpretation, it is necessary to verify only the postulates, definitions, and rules of substitution, for if these original propositions hold for classes, all the propo- sitions derived from them will hold for classes. The reason for this will be apparent from a further consideration of the mean- ing of rules of substitution in general, and of the inferences to which they lead when they are interpreted. VI Symbolic groups built up from other symbolic groups or from simple terms are functions of these groups or terms. (We have observed before that the idea of a group is the same as that of a function.) Every symbol in an uninterpreted deductive system FORMAL DEDUCTION 249 has a functional range, which is simply all the groups into which it can enter as a constituent. A rule of substitution lays down conditions determining the functional ranges of symbols; it tells us either that the functional ranges of two symbols coincide or that the one is wider than the other, that is to say, it prescribes what their functional ranges shall be. If it were possible to spread out on a single page all the groups of a symbolic system, there would be no need for rules of substitution; we could see at a glance what was the functional range of every symbol. But in all except trivial systems the number of possible groups is very great, usually infinite, and so rules of substitution are necessary. If a symbol z can be substituted for a symbol y in an uninter- preted system, the functional range of z is wider than that of Y that is, for every group in the system containing y as a member there is a group (similar in every other respect, both in its con- stituents and in its form) containing x as a member, but not the reverse. And if x and y can be mutually substituted for one an- other, their functional ranges coincide, that is, there are no groups in the system containing x which are not paralleled by groups (similar in every respect except for the presence of 2) containing y, and vice versa. This conception of the functional range of a symbol intro- duces a new kind of variability, functional variability, which is wholly different from the interpretational variability — inde- terminateness of reference — hitherto considered. A functional variable is a variable with respect to the groups in which it can play a part; and objects, no less than symbols, exhibit this type of variability. Just as a symbol composed of other symbols is a symbolic function, so an object composed of other objects, that is, a factual complex, is an objective function. We describe ob- jects through their predicates and relations; any object may have many different predicates and relations, it may enter into 250 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH many different complexes; and its functional range is all the complexes in which it can be a member. With respect to these groups the object is a variable; it may appear now in one group and now in another, and other objects may take its place in groups. Thus a deductive system, when it is interpreted, will describe a certain set of objects through certain selected func- tions of these objects. ¢ Strangely enough, the variables of wider functional range are the values of the variables of narrower range; the former are the more specific in meaning, while the ones of narrower range are the less specific. Thus, in the system now under consideration, the terms z and wu enter in functions in which the terms a, b, and c cannot play a similar part; z and wu are functional variables of wider range than a, b, and c, and hence are special values of the latter. (Theorem 6,2 = (Nu), for example, cannot be translated into z = (Na) ora = (Nu).) But the reason for this is evident. The more we know about an object, the more determinate it be- comes for thought, and the more functions in which a symbol enters, the more completely is its réle in the system fixed. A rule of substitution, then, lays down the conditions of func- tional variability for the interpretational variables of a symbolic system. In doing so it prescribes the form of the system and at the same time, through prescribing the form, imposes limitations on the interpretation. When the symbols are given (interpreta- tional) values, these values must be such that the facts into which they enter are of the same structure as the symbolic groups into which the uninterpreted symbols enter; and even so, a wide range of possible (interpretational) values is permitted to any of the symbols of the system. But the interpretation must always fulfill the conditions imposed by the rules of substitu- tion, and this requires that the objects meant by any symbol or group must have a functional range in the world of fact which corresponds to the functional range of this symbol or group in FORMAL DEDUCTION 251 the uninterpreted system. This being the case, the manipula- tions of the symbols will always yield true propositions. Thus, if the terms a, b, and c, in the Boolean Algebra stand for classes and the symbols of unity R, S, and N signify the opera- tions of class addition, multiplication, and negation, it will be possible to substitute a, b, and c for one another for the reason that any class forms a sum or product with any other class, and also has a negative. The groups (Rab), (Sab), (Na), and their derivatives can be substituted for these terms, for these groups also signify classes (complex classes) and so can have sums, products, and negatives of their own. Every complex class en- ters into the same sort of class operations as every simple class. But the simple terms a, 6, and ¢ cannot replace the symbols for these complex classes for the reason that there are certain functions of complex classes which are not functions of simple classes. In the interpreted system, the rules of substitution cover a multitude of existential or “‘material”’ implications which hold for the objects meant. The rule which permits the substitution of (Rab), (Sab), (Na), for the terms a, b, and c informs us that “if there are classes, there are sums, products, and negatives of these classes’’; the provision that a, 6, and ¢ can be mutually substituted for one another tells us that “‘if there are functions of one class, there are similar functions of other classes.’ But these existential implications must not be confused with spe- cially postulated, and uninterpreted, implications of the sort mentioned before, which permit the substitution of certain sym- bols for others as conclusions in chains of deduction. When the system is interpreted, these specially postulated connections of meaning will be “formal” rather than existential implications. Thus, though (Na) yields by substitution (and hence existen- tially implies) the complex (N(Na)), this could not mean that (Na) “formally” implies (N(Na)), for this would assert that 252 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH “any negative implies its own negative.” The substitution really means that “the negative of a negative is an instance of a nega- tive,” or “if there is a negative of a class, there is also a negative of this negative.” } A symbol whose range of functional variability includes but does not coincide with that of another is a constant with respect to this variable of narrower functional range. The symbols z and u in the Boolean Algebra are constants with respect to the terms a, 6, and ¢, since z and u can be substituted for these terms, but not the reverse. Yet z and u are not completely determined in significance by this fact; there are still as many possible inter- pretations for them as there are for the system. A symbol whose meaning is variable in interpretation may function as a con- stant, when its part in an uninterpreted system alone is consid- ered. Such a symbol is a “functional constant,” and is known in mathematics as a parameter. Moreover, all the groups of our system are, with respect to the terms a, b, and c, functional con- stants; any one of these groups stands for some particular sort of combination of classes. Indeed, if the system is taken merely as an uninterpreted set of symbols, the only elements in it that function as variables are the terms a, b, and c. Every other ele- ment or expression is a value of these variables. Therefore, a, b, and c, which have the narrowest range of functionality in the system, are the “functional variables’’; and each of the substi- tutions of a group or other element (unless it be of the elements 1 The notion that a rule of substitution is to be interpreted as stating a relation between the functional ranges of two variables makes it clear why symbols of indistinct meaning, 7.e., the symbols on either side of the sign of identity, can be mutually substituted for one another. When the system is interpreted, these symbols must always be given an identical value, they must stand for the same object; and obviously every object has the same functional range as itself. Further, it is clear that a coincidence of functional ranges, and hence a possibility of mutual substitution, is not the same as identity of meaning. FORMAL DEDUCTION 253 a, b, or c) for a, b, and ce, puts a functional constant in place of one of these functional variables. VII The symbols of unity R, S, and N stand for operations. That they must stand for operations, and not relations, is determined by the deductive use made of the groups in which they appear. The distinguishing feature of an operational group is that it can be substituted in ctself for one of its terms; and in the Boolean Algebra this is provided for by the rule that (Rab), (Sab), and (Na) can take the place of a in any group, and hence in these very groups. In other words, an operational group is a value of the functional variables that enter into it. The “‘plus,” ‘‘minus,”’ and “‘times”’ of numerical algebra, for instance, are operations because the complexes they form are numbers. If a and b represent numbers, (a — b) will be a num- ber; it may be the number a, where b is zero, or the number (—b), where a is zero. But it will always be some number, and thus it can take the place of a or b in any algebraic expression and still give a number; it can be substituted in the very combi- nation (a — b), giving ((a — b) — b), which is a number. A relational group, on the other hand, is not a value of the variable terms that appear in it. If a and b are points, and (Rab) means “‘a follows b,”’ this fact is not also a point, and it cannot take the place of a or b in any complex of points. For this reason, the I of the Boolean Algebra is a relation rather than an opera- tion. The I-groupscannot be substituted for the terms that enter 1 It is possible to consider these ‘‘constants” as functional variables of dif- ferent orders. What is a functional constant with respect to one symbol might be a functional variable with respect to another. The order of variability of the symbols is shown by the rules of substitution. Thus, in the Boolean Algebra (Rab) is a functional constant with respect to a and a functional variable with respect to (R(Rab)b), which is a special case of it. But for purposes of simplifi- cation, all the groups can be lumped together as constants with respect to the terms a, b, and c. 254 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH into them, for if a class a is included in a class b, this does not form a class, as does the logical sum or product or negative of a and b. Operations give rise to systems of an infinite number of possi- ble forms; an operational group can replace again and again a term which appears in this group itself, yielding each time a group of higher type. For every complex that contains a, in the Boolean Algebra, there is one of higher type that contains (Rab), (Sab), or (Na); so that a “proper part” of the collection of groups in which a is a member can be put into one-to-one corre- spondence with the whole of this collection. And this proves that these groups are infinite in number. 1 For a definition of an infinite collection, see E. V. Huntington, The Con- tinuum, pp. 7 ff. ? A set of postulates for serial order of the simplest sort illustrates the dif- ference between operations and relations, and also shows how a system wholly different from the Boolean Algebra is constructed: (1) Assume that a, 6, and ¢ are distinct symbols for terms; and that the system is built on the basic group (a(0b)) v (b(Oa)). (The symbols (v) and (.), which stand respectively for the logical ideas “or” and “and,” are used in the statement of the plan of this system; and if the system is to be completely un- interpreted, these symbols might be replaced by symbols that do not suggest these logical ideas, e.g., by L and N.) It will be observed that the grouping of the complex (a(0b)) shows that it has an order, irrespective of the spatial ar- rangement of the symbols; and that (b(Qa)) is the alternative order of this asymmetrical form. (2) The symbols a, b, and ¢ can be mutually substituted for one another; but distinct symbols must always be replaced by distinct symbols. (3) The special “formal” implication, (a(0b)). (b(Oc)) ““implies”’ (a(Oc)), holds in the system. It is apparent that (a(Oa)) or any combination in which this group might appear is not in the system; for the provision that distinct symbols must al- ways be substituted for distinct symbols will not permit us to derive (a(Oa)) from (a(0b)) or from any of the other O-groups. These O-groups are therefore wreflexwe. Further, the group (a(0b)) is, by its grouping, distinct from (b(0a)); and this is a distinction of sense, 7.e., of the distribution of the terms in the constituent groups. The O-groups are therefore asymmetrical for distinct terms. (Obviously, if there were an O-group of indistinct terms, e.g., (a(Oa)), this would be symmetrical; but there is no such group.) The implication (a(Ob)) . (b(Oc)) “implies” (a(Oc)), shows that the O-groups are transitive; but transitive only when a, b, and ¢ are distinct, for (a(Qa)). (a(Oa)) “‘implies” (a(Oa)), and (a(0b)) . (b(Oa)) “implies” (a(Oa)) cannot be derived from this implication without violating the rules of substitution. The fact that the O- groups cannot be substituted for the terms a, b, and ¢ shows that they are FORMAL DEDUCTION 255 Vill The apparently arbitrary manipulations of the symbols of an uninterpreted system are “deductions” for this reason: that, when the system is interpreted, that is, when the postulates are asserted for a set of objects, these manipulations become infer- ences. The theorems are then asserted on the strength of their connection with the postulates; the truth of the postulates strictly proves the truth of the theorems. Inference is allied to assertion and belief. There is no such thing as a hypothetical inference, just as there is no such thing as a hypothetical belief. If a proposition is believed, it is re- moved from the realm of the hypothetical; it is no longer an idea merely entertained, but is accepted as true or, it may be, “‘ac- relational, rather than operational, groups; and since (a(Ob)) v (b(Oa)) is sig- nificant in the system, the terms a and 6 (or a and ce, and b and ¢, if these are properly substituted in this expression) are connected in one sense or the other by the relation O. This is the postulate of “connexity.” Now, a relation which is connected, irreflexive, transitive for distinct terms, and asymmetrical for distinct terms, is a “serial relation.” (See E. V. Hunting- ton, op. cit., pp. 11 ff.) If a, b, and ¢ stand for points on a line, and (a(0b)) means that “the point a precedes the point b, in the order left to right,” the postulates can be interpreted as follows: (1) Asserts that “any point precedes any other point, or this latter precedes it.” The condition that the points must be distinct is added by the second half of the rule of substitution under (2). (2) The first half of this rule of substitution asserts that “if there is a point, there are also two other points”; and the second half asserts that “if any point precedes a point, these two are distinct,” since only symbols that refer to distinct points can appear in the complex “a precedes b.”’ (3) Asserts that “if any point precedes a second, and this second precedes a third, the first point precedes the third.” That the proposition (a(0b)) . (b(Oa)), t.e., “a point a precedes point b and this latter point also precedes a,” does not hold in the system is proved by the fact that in order to derive this group from the similar group in the implica- tion, (a(0b)). (b(Oc)) “implies” (a(Oc)), we must assume a contradiction; we must suppose that a is a distinct symbol from a. With this supposition, a can be substituted, according to the latter half of rule (2), for c in this implication, giving (a(O0b)) . (b(Oa)) “implies” (a(Oa)). But if a ¥ a, this is a violation of the principle of contradiction, which is always assumed as a general rule of symbolism. 256 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH cepted as false,’’ which means that its negative is accepted as true. And similarly, a proposition that is inferred from another is accepted as true (or false), not because it is verified in itself, but because it is believed to be connected in a certain way with a proposition previously accepted as true (or false). Inference is the passage from a belief, by way of a belief, to a belief, and is expressed by the assertion of a premise and of a connection be- tween this premise and a conclusion, followed by the assertion of the conclusion. The connections on which inferences rest are im- plications. (There arc, however, certain types of inference — probable or inductive inferences — which do not rest on the strict implications considered here.) It is characteristic of true propositions that they can stand alone as objects of belief. Though most propositions have their “reasons,” that is, their premises, by which they are implied, any truth can be severed from its premises and believed on its own account. Its truth does not consist merely in the “reasons” that can be given for it. If it is true, it is equally true apart from the propositions which imply it, equally true with or without “reasons.”’ If it were necessary to remember all the logical con- nections of a proposition believed, belief and assertion would be difficult undertakings; but fortunately the premises of a belief can be forgotten without destroying the truth of the proposition believed (if it is true). Therefore inference, since it leads from one proposition believed to be true to another believed to be true, is well described as “the dropping of a true premise . . . the dissolution of an implication.” ! But a premise which is not believed cannot be dropped, and for this reason the asscrtion of a chain of implications is not an inference. “‘p implies q” means that whenever p is true, q is true; but it does not assert the truth or falsity of p or of q; it merely excludes the possibility that “‘p is true and q false.” So far as its 1 Whitehead and Russell, Principia Mathematica, p. 9. FORMAL DEDUCTION 257 constituent propositions are concerned, a true implication is still hypothetical; though a connection between p and q is asserted, p and q themselves are still entertained and not believed. And if the supposition that the premise of this implication is true is added, this supposition will not result in an inference to the truth of q; it will yield nothing but the supposition that q is true “if p is true and p implies g.” One might go on forever asserting implications and supposing that their premises are true without performing an inference. The chain of implications is broken only when the premises, as well as the implications themselves, are asserted. Every one of the series of propositions which are believed to be connected by these implications can then be be- lieved, by themselves, to be true. Inference is, in short, a form of judgment and, like all judg- ment, it takes the leap of belief; it introduces a new attitude of mind toward propositions. But it differs from simple judgment in that it must take two leaps of belief; it must accept the truth of an implication (or series of implications) and of the premise of this implication (or series of implications). Thus, from survey- ing propositions and asserting that they are connected in certain ways, it passes to the affirmation of these propositions apart from their connections. That a belief in the truth of a proposition implied by a true premise is justified follows from the nature of implication. Any- thing implied by a true premise is true; for the truth of the im- plication, “‘p implies g,”’ does not admit the possibility of p be- ing true and q false. To believe p, and to believe that Pp implies certain propositions, is inconsistent with believing that these latter propositions are false. And though one is not compelled to believe the consequences of p when he believes p (for he always has the alternative of being sceptical), he cannot consistently believe that these consequences are false. Here as always the goal of his belief is consistency. 258 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH The two principles which underlie inference, then, are: (1) that any true proposition is true apart from its connections with other propositions, and can be asserted on its own account; and (2) that a true implication and a true premise always yield a true conclusion. These principles permit us to move in thought from one assertion or belief to another; to wipe the slate clean and start afresh with each new conclusion. When a formal deductive system is taken to refer to certain objects, it is asserted, and if its postulates and rules of substitu- tion are true for these objects, the conditions necessary for in- ference are satisfied. But it is more important still to observe an- other fact which follows from the complete interpretation of a deductive system. The conditions of truth and of significance in the system become the same. Every proposition which has a mean- ing is true, the system contains no significant propositions which are false. The symbolic manipulations, which are the inferences of the asserted system, arise in the unasserted (purely hypothetical) system from rules of syntax which prescribe how the symbols are to be taken together as significant groups — rules analogous to rules of grammar. General principles of symbolism, a “uni- versal grammar,” necessary in all systems or “languages,” are laid down, and within this framework special conditions of sig- nificance are provided for, so that each deductive system be- comes a special “language.” Its postulates state nothing more than what expressions are to be considered significant, what symbols are identical in meaning, and what symbols can be sub- stituted for one another without rendering the expressions in which they appear meaningless. The system differs from more concrete languages in that its “words” and “phrases” refer to no objects but are variables, grouped about certain fixed ele- ments, v2z., certain logical forms. These logical forms are the sole subject-matter of the uninterpreted language; they are em- FORMAL DEDUCTION 259 bodied in the “words” and “phrases,” the symbols and groups of symbols, but they are not asserted to exist elsewhere. The language asserts no truths but simply surveys logical forms. On the other hand, when the system is completely interpreted, the language that previously asserted no truths becomes a language that asserts nothing but truths; there is no expression in it which is both significant and false. The so-called “false propositions” of a completely inter- preted deductive system are “pseudo-propositions,”’ that is, meaningless collections of the symbols, and not significant groups permitted by the syntactical rules. Such “ pseudo-propo- sitions” can be introduced only by violating the conditions of significance. In the postulates for serial order,! for example, the group (a(Oa)) does not enter; it is nonsense so far as the syntac- tical plan of this “language” is concerned. Interpreted as the system is interpreted, this pseudo-proposition asserts that “any point, a, precedes itself,” but though this idea can be expressed in words, it cannot be significantly stated in the symbols of the system. T’hus it is superfluous (in fact absurd) to say that (a(Oa)) is false, for only a significant expression can be false. Completely interpreted deductive systems are therefore com- pletely inferential. Every transformation which conforms to the “grammar” of the system is an inference; every “grammatical” expression is true. IX Ordinary language, on the contrary (as well as the system of mental images), is incompletely inferential. The conditions of sig- nificance and truth for its expressions are not the same. Clearly if one follows merely its grammatical rules, he will not be led from true premises to true conclusions. Only some of the manip- ulations of its words and phrases will be inferences. But the pro- cess of thought, as it is carried on in language and in images, 1 See above, sec. vii, note. 260 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH presents an interesting analogy to the transformations of formal deductive systems, for thought in these former media is also the manipulation of symbols. Thought has two aspects: it is both dynamic and static; and inference belongs to its dynamic side. Inference is a movement of thought coupled with belief, but strict inference arises in a wider setting of thought-movement — a setting which Hobbes calls “mental discourse” or the “train of imagi- nations.” “Mental discourse,” beginning with presented objects, mir- rors a world of fact in a world of representations; it builds simple symbols which refer to objects into complexes, which may or may not correspond to objects. The drama of “‘ideas”” makes use of symbols as its puppets; the symbols combine and recombine, the puppets move on the stage, and one grouping succeeds an- other to the end of the piece. Words and images are the primary instruments of this “mental discourse.”” They combine, dissolve, and recombine, pass and repass in new and changing unities, and here and there they precipitate a reference to fact. Such discourse is the free play of the imagination, musing or dream- ing, rather than deductive reasoning, but it is akin to deduc- tive reasoning in that it is a process of substitution within a plan of syntax. Images (both simple and complex), words, and phrases, take the places of one another in groups; the group that was now of one form assumes a different form; but throughout all these mutations, the plan of syntax on which the system of images or of words is based is never violated. The “mental dis- course”’ confines itself within the limits of intelligibility which this plan imposes. Yet this discourse is not inference, as it would be in a completely interpreted deductive system, for the plan of syntax within which it is carried forward cannot be so inter- preted that every significant proposition to which it gives rise is true. There is no difficulty in abandoning fact for fancy within FORMAL DEDUCTION 261 the systems of language and images; but ina completely inferen- tial system nothing that is conceivable is false. We cease to dream and begin to infer when our purpose in the manipulation of symbols is to arrive at truth. A completely in- ferential (and interpreted) deductive system is so constructed . that this purpose can be accomplished merely by following its tules of significance, for these rules sum up a multitude of impli- cations which hold for the subject-matter. But the syntactical plans of language and the imagination do not run parallel to logical connections of the subject-matter. In these media, only a limited number of expressions will imply or be implied by others, and so can be inferred from others. These expressions will form a solid island of true inferences in a sea of fancies. Yet there is a marked analogy between free imagination, “mental discourse,” and formal deductive inference. The constructive imagination is a genus of which the process of formal deduction is a species; imagination is necessary to reason. Xx The principal points that have been brought forward in this examination of formal deduction are the following: For formal logic, all that is essential in any subject-matter is its logical structure, and this structure can be isolated and stud- ied in itself through uninterpreted symbols whose forms and their connections alone are considered. Such uninterpreted sys- tems of symbols are not without meaning, however. In the con- text of logical structure, all the elements of these systems, with the exception of their logical forms, are variables, that is, sym- bols of undetermined meaning; and the groups as wholes have significance, though they refer to no objects, for any symbolic group with a structure is significant. The forms to be studied are presented in the very symbols through which they are studied. The postulates of these systems are plans of syntax which de- 262 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH termine what groupings of the symbols are permissible, that is, what the possibilities for thought in the system are; and the whole becomes a special “language” with a “grammar”’ of its own marking the boundary between sense and nonsense for the system. All special plans of syntax assume the general principles of symbolism: (1) the principle of group significance; (2) the dis- tinction between symbols of unity and terms; (3) the law of identity and (4) the law of contradiction. From these principles, it follows that the system must be composed of groups of terms joined by symbols of unity; the same symbols must always be used with the same significance, though symbols of different characters and forms can be taken as identical in meaning; and symbols that are originally distinct in meaning must always be distinct. All the significant complexes of the system are derived from certain basic complexes by substitutions, and this process of transformation by substitution 7s formal deduction; it is the manipulation of symbols within a plan of syntax. Two general rules of substitution are always followed: (1) the same symbol can be substituted for the same symbol, and symbols of identical meaning can be substituted for one another, in any complex; (2) all substitutions must be carried through completely. In addi- tion to these general rules, every system has its special rules of manipulation, and among these may appear certain “equations of structure,”’ definitions, and specially postulated implications. The latter permit the substitution of one group for another only when this other group appears as a conclusion of a series of de- ductions. Deduction in these systems is nothing but the manipu- lation of the symbols according to these rules, as is illustrated by the Boolean Algebra, which, though it can be completely inter- preted in terms of classes and class relations and operations, can be stated as a system of uninterpreted groups and rules of sub- stitution. FORMAL DEDUCTION 263 A rule of substitution, in general, is based on a relation be- tween the functional ranges of the variables. If symbols coincide in their ranges of functional variability, they can be mutually substituted for one another; and if the range of one includes that of another, the former can be substituted for the latter, for it will be a functional value of the latter. With respect to vari- ables of a less inclusive range, those of wider range are “func- tional constants’’; while the variables of narrowest functional range in any system — those for which all other expressions of the system can be substituted, but which can not be substituted for these expressions — are the most general “functional vari- ables” of the system. Both functional constants and functional variables are undetermined in meaning; both are ““interpreta- tional”’ variables. If a group is a possible value of the variable terms which enter in this group itself, this group is operational rather than rela- tional. Operational are distinguished from relational complexes by the use which can be made of them in formal deduction, by the fact that they can be substituted in themselves for their own terms. Thus they give rise to an infinity of distinct possible forms. When a deductive system is interpreted, the arbitrary manip- ulations of the symbols become inferences, for the postulates and rules of substitution then embody implications, and if the postulates are true, the theorems are also true. To perform an inference is to pass from a premise that is believed, by way of an implication that is believed, to a conclusion that is believed on the strength of these other beliefs. Inference cannot be sepa- rated from belief and assertion; it cannot be purely hypothetical and the principles on which it rests are: (1) that any true propo- sition is true, and can be asserted, apart from its premises; and (2) that what is implied by a true proposition is true. Inference is “the dropping of a true premise.” 264 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH In a completely interpreted deductive system, whatever is significant is true; any of the permitted transformations of meaning lead from true premises to true conclusions, so that these systems are completely inferential. They are to be con- trasted with zncompletely inferential systems, such as language and the imagination, in which there is a discrepancy between significance or conceivability and truth. Though these latter systems resemble the former in that thought is carried forward in them by the manipulation of symbols within a plan of syn- tax, they differ from the former in that the pursuit of their rules of significance, alone, gives rise to fancy and free imagination rather than to inference. These formal deductive systems, in which everything but the logical structure of the matter referred to (if there is a matter referred to) is pruned away, show much more clearly than other symbolic systems how symbols copy the forms of facts and why the logical structure, which is present in the symbols as it is in the objects, is the essential bond of meaning between the mind and its objects. The mirror of thought, which reflects in the be- ginning a world of concrete facts, may send back a reflection of forms alone and these forms may belong to no world of fact, they may be merely possibilities for thought embodied in sym- bols. But the structure of these possible concepts will determine what they can stand for; if they represent objects, these objects must correspond to them in logical form. Whether formal de- ductive systems are interpreted or uninterpreted, thought reaches in them its maximum of clarity.! 1 The views of formal deduction and truth here set forth are closely similar to those of Leibniz as interpreted by L. Couturat in La Logique de Leibniz (Paris, 1901). ‘“‘In an unpublished fragment relating to the universal lan- guage,” says Couturat (pp. 88, 89), “‘Leibniz imposes another condition on signs: it must be possible to deduce from their form alone, and from their composition, all the properties of the concepts which they represent. . . . Their combinations must depict for the imagination the logical connections of the corresponding concepts, so that the composition of the signs agrees with the FORMAL DEDUCTION 265 composition of the ideas, following an exact analogy. . . . Moreover, not only does the symbolism translate the thought under an intuitive form, but it serves also to guide, to relieve, and even to supplant or replace thought. Just as the combinations of the ideas are represented by combinations of the corre- sponding signs, so the operations of the mind — that is to say, the reasoning which is carried on with these ideas — is expressed in concrete and sensible operations performed on the symbols. The abstract laws of logic are thus translated into intuitive laws which govern the manipulations of signs.” To the nominalism of Hobbes “Leibniz replies peremptorily,” continues Couturat (pp. 104, 105), “that, if signs are arbitrary, the relations between signs, which express or constitute propositions, are in no sense arbitrary; and that they (signs) are true or false according as they correspond or not with the relations of the things signified. Thus truth consists in the connection of signs so that they agree with a real and necessary connection of ideas or objects, which does not depend on us; or, in other words, it consists in that similarity of the relations of signs and the relations of things which constitutes an analogy in the proper mathematical sense of the term, that is to say, a propor- tion or equality of relationships. . . . The choice of signs and the definitions of words can, then, be arbitrary, but the linkage of the words and signs does not become so; and it is in this linkage alone that truth and falsity reside. We can even change the system of signs at will without changing a truth or making it dependent on our wishes; for, whatever symbols are chosen, there will be an arrangement of these symbols — and only one arrangement — which will be true, that is, which will correspond to the real order of things or facts. There is then an analogy, not only between signs and objects, but between different systems of signs in so far as they express the same reality. “This necessary rather than arbitrary order which exists in things is, though unknown, the objective basis of all truth. Once a certain system of arbitrary signs or a certain set of conventional definitions has been adopted, it no longer depends on us what combinations are true and what false; and this proves that truth, although it resides solely in our minds, rests on a principle outside us and expresses symbolically a reality of some sort.” CHAPTER VIII THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE I A tHEory of knowledge must come at last to metaphysics, for the aim of knowledge is to grasp reality, and without some no- tion of what reality in the broadest sense of the term is, we can- not say whether knowledge succeeds or fails. The limited reality of which we have spoken up to this point — which can be given in or inferred from an experience consistent with the whole of knowledge — is not enough. It is always possible that what can be thus given or inferred is merely an appearance, and that reality is something deeper, inscrutable to perception and perhaps even to reason. And so we must set out without any arti- ficial restriction of our concept of reality to answer, or rather to sketch the barest outlines of answers, to these fundamental questions: Can reality be known? If so, what is reality and how is it known? The first question is prompted by the sceptical impulse of knowledge to self-criticism; it arises from a mood of doubt which is unfamiliar to very few men. Walt Whitman speaks of this mood as “‘the terrible doubt of appearances, Of the uncertainty after all that we may be deluded; May-be the things I perceive — the animals, plants, men, hills, shin- ing and flowing waters, The skies of day and night — colors, densities, forms — May-be these are (as doubtless they are) only apparitions, and the real something has yet to be known.! 1 Walt Whitman, “Of the Terrible Doubt of Appearances,” first published in Leaves of Grass, 1860. THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE 267 Most of us easily shed this “terrible doubt of appearances.” Practical life obscures it, common sense engulfs it, and only poets, mystics, and metaphysicians are left to worry over it. But those whom it haunts find that there is no compromising with it; either all knowledge gives way before it or else thought is driven back and back till it touches first principles — and lays the foundations of a system of metaphysics. The peculiar thing about this question is that it cannot be sig- nificantly answered in the negative. Either we are condemned to perpetual asking without an answer or else we know reality. The sceptical impulse of knowledge to self-criticism defeats itself, at- tains no end, unless there is knowledge, not merely knowledge of appearances but of reality. A criticism of knowledge makes use of the very thing it criticizes, and unless the argument is to become circular or lead back indefinitely from premise to prem- ise, the knowledge on which the criticism is based must itself be exempt from criticism.! If knowledge fails (in some sense) to grasp reality, in knowing this fact it attains an ultimate truth and does not fail completely; and if it succeeds, the knowledge of why it succeeds cannot stand in need of justification, and so on through a series of justifications that has no end. This suggests either that no final criticism of knowledge is possible, that suspension of judgment is the way of sanity (and this means equally that knowledge cannot be vindicated or dis- 1 This idea is clearly put by Aristotle; see W. D. Ross, Aristotle (1924), p. 45. “There are, says Aristotle, two errors (with respect to the ultimate validity of knowledge) which rest on a common basis. There is that of suppos- ing that knowledge implies either an infinite regress from premise to premise in order that nothing may be accepted as unproved, or else the acceptance of unproved and therefore unknown premises, and that knowledge is therefore impossible. And there is the error of supposing that knowledge is possible but proceeds in a circle — truth being thus reduced to the mutual implications of propositions none of which are independently known to be true. The common basis of the two errors is the assumption that proof is the only way of know- ledge, and against them both he affirms his principle that there are first prem- ises which neither need nor admit of proof.” 268 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH credited); or that there are first principles, final insights into the nature of the real, on which all knowledge rests. The former al- ternative is scepticism; the latter, the necessary starting-point of any metaphysics. And yet there have been attempts to compromise with doubt by answering this initial question — can reality be known? — in the negative, attempts to maintain that knowledge is of appear- ances only and that reality is hidden and unknowable. Herbert Spencer makes his bow in the opening chapters of his First Prin- cuples to the eternal mysteries of the universe, leaving this empty but venerated realm of the Unknowable to religion and meta- physics, and choosing for science the full and certain area of the Knowable. A strange, unstable dichotomy! There is to be no poaching of metaphysics and religion on science, and none of science on religion and metaphysics. Each goes its own way, metaphysics to the Unknowable, which is the real, and science to the Knowable, which is the unreal or half-real. Metaphysics becomes an unfulfilled aspiration toward the ultimate, and sci- ence a description of phenomena which, so far as we can tell, are less than shadows flitting before the senses. The agnostic compromise with doubt attains no better suc- cess than this. Clearly it is no compromise. Agnosticism is not a half-way house on the road between scepticism and meta- physics. There is no half-way house. If one accepts any truth, he accepts a standard by which he discriminates the true from the false, and beneath this standard is found his metaphysics. From the beginning of thought a concept of reality is present, making itself clearer as thought goes forward but never abandoned — unless thought thins out into scepticism. Men are for the most part neither self-conscious metaphysi- cians nor self-conscious sceptics; the temper of most minds strangely blends these two tendencies. But if either of these in- compatible strains is brought to light, it must exclude the other. THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE 269 The scepticism which is fully aware of itself witholds all belief, ventures on no single affirmation, — not so much as the affirma- tion that belief is fruitless and unjustified, —and is thus reduced to silence, or at best to a vagrant roaming among possibilities, none of which is affirmed to be actual. But if one asks himself how it is that he can assert any truth, even the most meagre, he begins to uncover a metaphysics, for truth is never anything less than knowledge of the real. To become alive to any truth he must bring to the surface of thought the concept of reality he now discovers to be buried there. The description of knowledge which has occupied us so far takes its departure from the point of view of the plain man and hence is neither self-consciously sceptical nor self-consciously metaphysical. It appeals to experience in a wide meaning of the term, witholds judgment on ultimate questions, but at the same time is aware of its assumptions and does not assert that they are more than assumptions. The upshot of the positive theory of knowledge is this: the truth of ordinary experience is the cor- respondence of concepts through their structure with real ob- jects, and this reality can be given in or inferred from an experi- ence consistent with the whole of knowledge. Whether reality as such has a structure, whether the objects that appear in ex- perience are finally real, whether the mind in knowing is sepa- rated from or joined to an ultimate reality — all these ques- tions remain untouched. And yet, if they are swept aside, the door is left open for scepticism. In the face of these questions the limited truth and reality of the positive theory of knowledge must expand into a final truth and a full reality or contract into a flux of impressions and ideas — leaving only doubt. The positive theory of knowledge, including as it does the two incompatible strains, is unstable; it is a metaphysics tinc- tured with scepticism, a scepticism tinged with metaphysics. The task of speculative philosophy is to bring to complete self- 270 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH consciousness the one or the other of these warring attitudes of mind. It is this aim which distinguishes speculative philosophy from the special sciences. Science tolerates the frame of mind that joins scepticism to the assertion of truths. The scientist does not doubt that he is approaching a completer knowledge of reality, though he could not say why this is so without becoming a meta- physician; and yet he refuses all commerce with ultimates and thinks of his premises as working assumptions which he is not averse to discarding for better ones. Hesitating to affirm that he has reached a final truth, the scientist still believes that his growing knowledge is an indefinite approximation to such a truth. Here the metaphysician makes his point. If one’s stand- ards of truth are not themselves finally true, if one does not in some way already grasp reality when he sets forth on the jour- ney of thought, he cannot even conceive of attaining truth. The method of science is the method of assumption, hypothe- sis, postulation, and this way of thought falls between scepti- cism and metaphysics; it holds the two in an unsteady balance within itself. A full-grown metaphysics cannot rely on postu- lates or assumptions, for if these assumptions are false the whole of knowledge collapses, and assuming them to be true does not make them true. A full-grown scepticism, on the contrary, is equally receptive to all assumptions, not excluding contradic- tory ones. II A tradition of critical philosophy which purports to be neither sceptical nor metaphysical, nor yet to be poised as are the spe- cial sciences between these extremes, appears in the thought of the eighteenth and late seventeenth centuries. Kant is the father and Locke the forerunner of this more carefully reasoned agnosticism. By an examination of the nature of knowledge; this critical philosophy hopes to determine whether or not meta- THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE 271 physics is possible, and it concludes that metaphysics is impossi- ble — that knowledge, being limited not only in extent but in its very essence, cannot penetrate through appearances to reality. The distinction between appearance and reality is as old as thought; indeed philosophy was bred in the suspicion that the real world is not what it appears to be, and the first philoso- phers set out with the confidence of adventure to discover the ultimate beneath the surfaces of things. But a second suspicion followed speedily on the first: that knowledge is without power to reach this ultimate. And so thought turned inward, its confi- dence shaken, to a criticism of its own capacities and aims. Whether knowledge is able impartially, and without begging the question by assuming its own validity, to criticize itself, is a query that does not occur to the agnostic. Pretending with Kant that this self-examination of thought will show whether a final truth can be reached, the agnostic forgets that his own theory is built on a metaphysical first principle, and that he himself claims one final insight — namely, that knowledge is confined to appearances. ‘Though all other truths are in his opinion limited and phenomenal, this truth — that we cannot know the ulti- mate — is absolute. Stated thus in outline, critical agnosticism appears self-con- tradictory. It is as if we were saying that by sight man can dis- cover that he cannot see. Yet both Locke’s Essay Concerning Human Understanding and Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, hav- ing begun with the conviction that knowledge by internal criti- cism can reveal its own frailties, arrive at this conclusion. Kant and Locke have fostered a tradition which gives epistemology a peculiar authority in the field of philosophy, but their episte- mology is in reality a metaphysics. The philosophy that Kant terms critique is speculation of a most insidious sort, disguising itself as it does under another name. Though its aim is to dis- cover “whether such a thing as metaphysics be at all possible,” 272 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH it is itself impossible without the metaphysics whose wings it hopes to clip. The epistemological tradition of Locke and Kant is an unsuccessful attempt to straddle the issue between scepti- cism and metaphysics. Before the Kantian critical philosophy was born, a reply to 1t was framed by one of the metaphysicians whose dogmatism Kant condemned. In Spinoza’s Tractatus de Intellectus Emenda- tione, Kantianism is forestalled by the following argument: “In order to find the best method of investigating what is true, we must not stand in need of another method to investigate this method of investigating, nor in need of a third one to investigate the second, and so on to infinity. For by such a method we can never arrive at a knowledge of what is true, nor at any knowl- edge whatever. For it is the same thing as with artificial instru- ments, of which we might argue in the same manner. For inorder to work iron a hammer is needed, and in order to have a ham- mer it must be made, for which another hammer and other in- struments are needed, and so on to infinity; and in this manner any one might vainly endeavor to prove that men have no power of working iron. But in the same way as men in the be- ginning were able with great labor and imperfection to make the most simple things from instruments already supplied by nature . so also the understanding by its native strength (vis sua nativa) makes for itself its intellectual instruments wherewith it acquires new strength for other intellectual works, and so gradu- ally proceeds until it attains the summit of wisdom.” ! This na- tive strength of the intellect is its power of insight into reality, which is present in thought from the first. The severance of appearance from reality, on which most criticisms of knowledge are based, may be more or less com- plete. It may be sharp and irreparable as in Kant, or it may be partial and reconcilable as in the Absolute Idealists, who be- 1 B. de Spinoza, T'ractatus de Intellectus Emendatione, sec. 6. : . | THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE 273 lieve that “there is no truth but the whole truth,” and yet that no appearance is denied its small grain of reality and truth. The breach between appearance and reality once opened must be healed, and the reason is not far to seek. What appears must have some sort of reality or it could not appear; it would be simply nothing. The important question then is, not how are appearance and reality separated, but how are they united? — how, in Spinoza’s language, does reality manifest itself in attri- butes and modes? To hold that there is a world of absolute ap- pearance cut off from a world of absolute reality, as Plato’s realm of opinion is from his realm of ideas! and Kant’s nou- menal realm from the phenomenal, is to fall into a difficult di- lemma. Either the world of absolute appearance or the world of absolute reality should be dropped; the two refuse to stand side by side unrelated. Just as Aristotle attempted to bring the Pla- tonic ideas into the concrete matter of experience, so the Post- Kantians attempted to raise the Kantian phenomena toward the level of the noumena by making the phenomena finite parts of an infinite and absolute whole. iil Before we consider ways of healing the breach between ap- pearance and reality, let us examine the breach itself in its most extreme form, as it occurs in Locke and Kant. It arises here from a theory of mind-isolation which places appearances in the knowing subject and leaves reality out in the cold beyond the grasp of the knower. Locke’s metaphysics of mind-isolation rests on two premises: that “all our knowledge is conversant only with ideas,” and that ideas are of qualities only, never of substances, which are the substrata of qualities. Locke’s view presupposes the passiv- 1 There is a question as to whether Plato intends completely to sever his two worlds. 274 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH ity rather than the activity of mind; a static screen of ideas im- poses itself from outside between the knower and reality, never to be swept aside. This is the crudest and simplest statement of the mind-isola- tion theory —the theory of epistemological dualism. Since Berkeley, it has had little currency in this form. The crux of Locke’s argument is the second premise, the distinction be- tween substance and its qualities; but just why substance, which Locke sometimes says is known in a confused way and other times not known at all, should be retained — why qual- ities (appearances) do not make up a self-sufficient and com- plete reality — does not become evident. Locke’s substance is nothing more than an arbitrary limit set to knowledge for no other reason than to satisfy the common-sense prejudice that things must have a substratum in which their qualities inhere, and the slender thread that holds together substance and its qualities snaps under the tension of Berkeley’s criticism; qual- ities alone are left, the unknowable xz, substance, being can- celled out. Locke’s first premise, that “knowledge is conversant only with ideas,” supports the theory of mind-isolation if one thinks of ideas as essentially disparate from real objects and (in Locke’s language) real qualities. One can for example suppose that real objects cause ideas different from themselves. How one can know this is another question, for apparently he must go be- yond ideas to do so. Therefore, if knowledge is conversant only with ideas, it is by hypothesis not conversant with objects which cause, bound, or limit ideas; and so the statement that knowl- edge is restricted to ideas has no foundation, unless it affirms merely that “we know what we know.” This is again the typical difficulty of agnosticism: if the mind is isolated, it would need to escape its isolation to know this fact. Though Kant’s formulation of the theory is more profound THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE Q75 than Locke’s, it comes in the end to the same thing — agnosti- cism and mind-isolation. Kant does not argue from the distinc- tion of substance and its qualities, and he supports the notion that knowledge is conversant only with ideal objects by nega- tive if not by positive proofs. Kant insists as against Locke that the mind is active in cognition; this is perhaps his most impor- tant observation on knowledge as a whole. Yet from this prem- ise he draws the amazing conclusion that in the very act of knowing the mind shuts out from itself the reality (the thing- in-itself), and thus becomes ignorant of what it is striving finally to reach. As soon as the work of knowledge begins, the mind like a snail in its shell withdraws within itself. The concepts (cate- gories and forms of perception) which determine the mind’s essential directions of activity, far from causing it to expand outward to a fuller apprehension of the real, which it has some- how touched in “‘the original receptivity of the senses,” turn it away toward ideal objects which correspond in no intelligible way with the ultimate reality. Knowledge is not a passive recep- tion of impressions (Kant argues), but an active assimilation of them under concepts,—the mind is not a blank sheet, but a working organic whole with a structure, — and so knowledge is confined to appearances, which are the products of the under- standing at work with concepts on the materials of the senses. Thus the objects of knowledge form a neat and orderly closed system through which the wind of reality does not blow. The safe and sheltered island mapped out by thought is untroubled by the waves of the ding-an-sich which beat along its shore. Why must this strange introversion go with the notion that the mind is active in knowledge? Granted that thought works with concepts and categories, that the mind is not like a vat of dough, merely receptive to external impressions, but that it does something in cognizing an object. Still, it does not follow that this activity is a contraction of the mind within itself. The con- 276 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH cepts along the grooves of which cognition is directed may lead the mind outward to a more complete knowledge of the real, rather than twist it inward upon itself. The more reasonable corollary to the observation that the mind is active in cognition is the exact opposite of mind-isolation. The activity of thought through concepts, intentions, (that is, symbols with their atten- dant mental attitudes), should bring the mind into more perfect and stable relations with the reality it touches in “the original receptivity of the senses.”’ We cannot conclude that the organ- ized knowledge of perception and experience is not knowledge of realities simply because thought plays a part in the organization. If reality itself is a complex whole, with “a time-less subtlety of complexity,” ! surely it is not strange that reality should be clearly apprehended only by an organized and active mentality. What is needed in place of the Kantian theory of isolation is the notion that mind by its activity joins itself to real things in knowledge, that is, an epistemological monism which takes ac- count of thought-activity in cognition. Mind grows into a cog- nitive unity with the reality it originally knows only in fleeting and momentary glimpses; the mind in knowing is actively con- tinuous with real objects. We shall presently say more of this continuity. Kant’s tidy world of experience, created by the mind at work with concepts and categories, could be peopled only by objects for which these concepts and categories are universally and nec- essarily true; and so necessity is brought into connections of “matters of fact” (as against Hume) at the cost of severing the whole world of fact from a vast and incomprehensible realm be- yond fact. One feels cheated, tricked, by this vindication of a priori knowledge. It is a peace without victory. And what of this theory of mind-creation itself? Is it, too, nothing but a mind- creation? If not, Kant is thrown back on the insight into real- 1 A. N. Whitehead, The Principles of Natural Knowledge (1919), p. 15. THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE Q77 ity of which Aristotle and Spinoza speak. Kantianism is slain by its own hand unless its own first principle — that knowledge cannot go beyond appearances — is apprehended as not itself an appearance, apprehended by a kind of reason not subject to the limiting categories of ordinary thought. But to admit such a rational insight or “intuition” would have been a return to dog- matism of the sort Kant hoped forever, by a dogmatism peculiar to himself, to demolish. Kant’s “dialectical” arguments attempt to show the futility of offering rational answers to metaphysical questions. But the cure is more reason, closer analysis, clearer concepts, and not, as Kant would have us believe, the surrender of rational meta- physics. A growing knowledge is bound to meet contradictions and thus to alter its concepts, and here lies the correction for the Kantian antinomies as well as for the more numerous contradic- tions which Mr. F. H. Bradley — following the scent of the dia- lectical argument even further than Kant — finds, in his Ap- pearance and Reality, to be inherent in discursive thought. This much truth can be distilled from both the Kantian and the Bradleyan dialectic: it is fatal to employ the concepts of the special sciences for unscientific, that is to say, for metaphysical purposes. Metaphysical categories (if there are any such) must be the widest possible categories. Mr. Bradley finds that thought in the effort to complete itself does not attain to wider concepts, but “commits suicide” by transcending its own forms, thus making way for the dim apprehension of an Absolute of which discursive knowledge gives only an imperfect and restless fore- sight. In this way Mr. Bradley escapes agnosticism to fall into something very close to mysticism. Kant’s conclusion from his antinomies is, on the other hand, the most glaring and insoluble antinomy of all. An inherently defective reason becomes able to know its own defects; a mind isolated from reality and confined to a world of phenomena becomes negatively but not positively 278 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH aware of its isolation. Even so the mind craves a positive knowl- edge of this reality and its relation to the world of experience. The noumena do not cause phenomena, for causation is a con- nection between objects of experience only. Indeed, theconclusion ought to be that the noumena are not related to the phenom- ena, for relations hold only between phenomena. The thing-in- itself, the ultimate reality thus severed from its appearances, is an entity which plays the same part in knowledge as zero in arithmetic; the addition or subtraction of it does not alter the value of the other elements. The outcome of the Kantian“ dia- lectic” is that knowledge of that which limits knowledge is negative only; which amounts to saying that knowledge is limited in a way that is not known by something that is not known. And it is a short step to the conclusion that knowledge is not limited, and hence to a rejection of the whole theory of mind-isolation. One other conclusion stands out in the “dialectic.” Reason is always attempting to complete the synthesis of experience, to effect a “complete unity of knowledge . . . by which that know]l- edge becomes not only a mere aggregate, but a system con- nected according to necessary laws.’ Kant sees reason as dy- namic and directed toward a goal, which it approaches but does not reach. Not content with a slow process of growth and cor- rection, it takes disastrous short-cuts, falling thus into self- contradiction. But this incompleteness of knowledge is not a sufficient ground for the agnostic separation of appearance from reality. It is one thing to assert that knowledge at any particu- lar time does not give us the whole of reality. This is a mild con- fession of ignorance and finitude, a gentle and tolerable agnosti- cism, which is the part of intellectual humility in the face of changing concepts, shattered theories, and discredited beliefs. It is quite another thing to assert that knowledge never grasps more than an appearance. A knowledge that is not complete in THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE 279 detail must nevertheless reach through to reality; otherwise, it is not knowledge. IV Four major points emerge from this discussion of agnosti- cism. (1) Any final criticism of the validity of knowledge must rest on metaphysical premises. The epistemological tradition which pretends to determine the limits and extent of human knowledge — especially, whether metaphysical knowledge is possible — appeals itself to metaphysical premises which are true without limitation. Appearance and reality cannot be held _ apart. (2) Though the mind is active in cognition, this fact need not lead to the conclusion that the mind shuts itself out from reality, building a world wholly its own. To the theory of mind- isolation must be opposed that of the continuity of the mind with real objects in the act of knowledge. The activity of the mind in the channels of concepts brings it into more complete touch with the reality of which sensation gives only passing glimpses. Through the use of concepts knowledge expands out- ward to reality, rather than inward to its own ideal world. (3) At every moment knowledge is incomplete, the whole of reality is not known in detail; the truths of to-day may be reversed by those of to-morrow. Yet the very notion that knowledge is in- complete demands that some knowledge be ultimate. Thus (4) a rational insight or intuition is needed to take account of meta- physical truth, for the truths that vindicate (or enable us to repudiate) all others cannot themselves be vindicated or repudi- ated, nor can they be merely postulated. They must be appre- hended as final. These conclusions must be expanded and correlated with the description of knowledge previously given. 280 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH V The essence of the first point is this: if there is any knowledge, there is knowledge of reality. An appearance is never a bare ap- pearance, for if it is true that it is an appearance, then it has some status in reality. It is really an appearance. The opposi- tion between appearance and reality becomes less and less sig- nificant the more one contemplates it. The question is, not whether what appears is a reality, but what sort of reality it is. What is its place in the scheme of reality? An appearance de- ceives when it is misplaced in reality or judged to be all there is, yet even a deceptive appearance is something; it cannot be dis- missed as not being. To hold that appearances have no reality is to deny that they are appearances, and hence to wipe them, and all the problems connected with them, clean off the slate. If the distinction between appearance and reality is to have a mean- ing it must fall within experience, and not between what is known and what is unknown or unknowable. It must fall within an apprehended reality. The very terms “appearance” and “reality” mislead one. We ought not to say that the reality we know differentiates itself into appearances, but into parts, aspects, elements, modes, which never lose their essential real- ity. What we call “appearances” are fragments of reality, and reality is in the fragments no less than in the complex structures, that is, objects, situations, facts, into which these fragments fit to form a world. The task of metaphysics is to describe what is most general (and hence least noticeable) in this apprehended reality, how- ever fragmentary the part apprehended may be. Metaphysics cannot look for the real beyond or behind experience, nor in an ideally complete experience. It must, like any other effort to think clearly, dig into the basic units of knowledge which are presentations or wholes of experience. Metaphysics is the most searching possible analysis of these wholes. THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE 281 This analysis should reveal what part the mind plays in ap- prehending these wholes. Does the mind in some far-reaching sense create their reality? Or do they in some mysterious way enter the mind from outside and mold it to their own forms? VI There has always been a tendency to break up the act of knowledge into sensation and thought, sensation being passive and thought active, and this has led to curious results, some of which have already been observed. In the main, those who have stressed sensation and the passive réle of mind have in- sisted that reality is external and indifferent to mind, and that reality becomes known through impressing itself on the mind; while those who have stressed thought have made the opposite claim — that reality is mental, rational, a thought-creation, and that it is known through the mind’s activity. There is something to be said for both of these views for the reason that the act of knowing is not sensation with thought added, or thought with sensation entering accidentally in it. To know is to be at once active and passive, to receive an impression and reflect upon it. The act is a single whole in which thought and sensation are blended; what is impressed on the mind is assimilated to, and not distinguished from, what is meant, imagined, thought. Con- crete knowing is the active assimilation of reality through sen- sational-thought. We have spoken of this before as presentational- thinking. It is impossible to say where the receptivity of the mind leaves off and its activity begins. Certainly it is highly artificial to draw this line at sensation, for there is no such thing as a pure sensation in abstraction from the cognitive act as a whole. As an element within this whole, sensation or sensing no less than thought is active. Moreover thought, as an element within the cognitive whole, has its passive side; it comes sharply against the thing it means given in experience, and 282 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH this encounter checks and at the same time fulfills its inten- tions. What has been previously said of thought must be recalled: that thought is essentially reference through symbols, an out- ward reach of the mind toward objects. There is a distinction between pure thought, which is reference and nothing more, and perceptual thought — which is reference when what is referred to is also immediately presented. The latter is what we are now speaking of as “concrete knowing.” This is the basic form of knowledge. Pure thought, purely mediate knowledge, is knowing in which the element of presentation (that is, passivity) is re- fined away, so that the thing meant is no longer given but merely intended. I do not know the other side of the moon concretely, but I do know concretely the facade of the house opposite upon which my window looks. Since pure thought is a distillation, an abstraction, from concrete thought, it is to the latter that we must look for the fullest relation of the mind to real objects in knowledge.! The view that objects impress themselves on the mind through the senses is insufficient for many reasons. Sensations are nothing in themselves; they are always parts of larger wholes. It is not correct to say that we “sense” relations, facts, complex structures; yet we experience these things. Cognition is always recognition; memory plays a part in it, and what is given has a reference before and beyond itself. There is an adjustment to experienced objects; they are classed, catalogued, fitted into a scheme of things in the very act of perception. The fact that objects are experienced as “black,” ‘‘white,” “round,” or even as “objects” or “‘sense data,” shows that a concept is actively 1 This distinction between pure and concrete thought corresponds to Aristotle’s distinction between potential and actual knowledge. In actual knowledge we grasp the real; potential knowledge needs something, a fulfill- ment or realization, to become actual knowledge. See W. D. Ross, Aristotle (1924), p. 171; also Aristotle, Metaphysics, Bk. XIII (M), ch. 10. THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE 283 at work in the apprehension of them. Unless objects can be con- sistently assimilated to the knowledge already present to us, they puzzle us; we feel that they are not clearly apprehended, that we have not yet succeeded in perceiving them. Thus not only is a single concept present in the apprehension of objects, but a whole body of theory — certainly the whole body of com- mon sense — presses forward to enter into the act of knowing, and the perception remains unstable until it is reconciled with this body of knowledge. All these and many other arguments point to the inadequacy of the notion that knowledge is a pas- sive reception of impressions. Concrete knowing feeds on the whole of knowledge; what has been experienced, and the use the mind makes of it, determines what is and will be experienced. The direction of one’s thoughts, meanings, intentions, codperate in what he sees and hears, no less than does the external situa- tion in which he happens to find himself. If the mind were a tabula rasa, there is no reason why first impressions should not be as clear, as complete and final, as last impressions. Yet there is a stubbornness, a resistance, an alien character, in the objects of concrete experience which prevents us from taking the opposite point of view, namely that they are thought- creations, things merely meant and in no sense given. We do not invent the things we see about us; they force themselves in upon us, and though the mind goes forth through its intentions to meet reality, still thought comes in the end to something un- yielding. If experience deceives us, we do not get rid of the ex- perience by apprehending it under proper categories and thus doing away with the deception. The data remain, however we conceptualize them. It is impossible to convince one’s self that the world is merely a coherent set of meanings. Whatever the activity of thought does in contributing to concrete knowing, there always remains a matter not its own creation. However thought may elaborate this matter, the matter persists, to con- 284 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH fine and complete concrete thought.! Of the infinity of worlds possible to purely abstract thought, one is realized, and it is this one which experience reveals to us. For abstract thought alone any other world might equally well have been. The idealist, who looks on reality as a rational system of meanings or concepts, still finds it necessary to account for the stubborn givenness of this world; he cannot ignore the specific materials of knowledge; he must make it clear why this rather than that possibility is realized. And quite properly, not wishing to fall into the Kantian predicament, which places reality be- yond the reach of hought and yet maintains that in some strange way this reality limits and molds experience, even though this experience is always of ideal (mental) objects only —not wishing to fall into this difficulty, the idealist distin- guishes between subjective and objective thought, between relative and absolute knowledge. Finite experience is a frag- ment of the absolute experience, finite thought a part of the ab- solute thought. Through entering (partially) into this absolute thought, we know reality, and so the world about us is more than the creation of our own minds. This idea is most simply put by Berkeley, who interpreted the whole of nature as a direct communication from God. In the hills, the trees, the stones, the events of history, we read the thoughts of the Deity; all are signs of what is passing in His mind, The stability of nature, the persistence and externality of perceptual objects, arise from the stability, persistence, and ex- ternality of God’s thought. Illusion and error are man’s dream; truth is the apprehension of what God compels us to know. Berkeley’s idealism has a fresh, naive beauty not found in his more sophisticated brethren, the Post-Kantians; but in essence it is absolutism. Absolute Idealism, then, does not do away with the alien qual- 1 Matter in the Aristotelian sense. THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE 285 ity of the objects of experience, and at the same time it takes complete account of the work of thought in apprehending these objects. It does not ask us to believe that reality stamps itself on the mind from outside, that we are mere receptacles of im- pressions and ideas. Knowing becomes an entering into reality, a sympathetic understanding of a thought-world which is alien to and more inclusive than our own world of thought. The ac- tivity of the human mind is compelled and illuminated by the activity of the Absolute Mind in which it has its being. f VII This is a heady doctrine, and one pauses to ask himself what it comes to. What is the Absolute Mind? Need one call it a “mind” ? What significance remains in speaking of reality as essentially “thought”? The chief argument for idealism, aside from the necessity of accounting for the mind’s activity in knowledge, is one that has been mentioned above; the mind must be continuous with the reality it knows. Thus it is easy to leap to the conclusion that reality is mental, to Berkeley’s esse est percipi. Yet objects re- fuse to be reduced to my mental states or my meanings; they persist, I believe, when my back is turned (and certainly Berke- ley also believed this). The laws of nature, of mathematics and logic, are not my thoughts; I discover and do not invent them. And though Berkeley would have admitted that he “ate, drank, and was clothed with ideas,”’ these were God’s ideas and not his own. Reality must be sufficiently close to the mental to be known through the activity of my mind, but it must not be so completely mental as to be reduced to this activity. The ideal- ist’s argument comes to this: he is forced to distinguish “men- tal,” from “mental ,”, and what remains? Merely lip-service to a word. What he is saying, apart from this word “mental,” is that his mind is so related to reality that it can know reality 286 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH through its activity. Obviously, no mind can be completely foreign to the reality it knows; the mind and its objects must be in the same universe; they must not be so wholly sundered that no relation, no sort of community or continuity, can exist be- tween them. But it profits me nothing to insist that this reality is mental, a thing of thought. I mean that it is “mental ,” and not “‘mental,” and these are very different. “Reality”’ is the most inclusive of all possible terms; if any distinctions of meaning exist, these must arise within reality. There can be no significance in defining reality in one way rather than another, for whatever special term be taken as its defini- tion, this term will have arisen as a distinct “‘somewhat”’ within reality, and it will lose its special meaning if it is made equiva- lent to reality. To speak of reality as mental is to spread mental- ity so thin that, to all intents, it becomes “‘not-mental.’’ We are driven to qualifications — “‘objectively”’ and “‘subjectively”’ mental — to bring back the significance that has departed from the term. One might as well recognize at once that reality is reducible to none of its aspects or modes, and be content with the term “‘reality”’ in its simplicity as undefined. For the logic of the situation will finally force him virtually, if not explicitly, into this position. The realist declares that “reality is independent of the knowing subject and not essentially mental, though it can be known”’; the idealist — what appears to be the same thing — that “‘reality is mental (but not subjectively so) and dependent on mind (but not on the subjective mind).’”’ Both agree on the fundamental point that the mind in knowing is continuous with real objects; both repudiate the Kantian dualism of idea and real object, of phenomenon and thing-in-itself. In this respect the American realists go further than many idealists; they assert not merely that the mind is continuous with the real objects it THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE 287 knows, but that it is identical with them — or at least partly so. The truly significant tendency in modern metaphysics, whether it be idealistic or realistic, is toward breaking through the old fixed categories of the mental and the physical. We are returning to the point of view of the ancients, having suffered for three centuries from the blindness of the Cartesian dualism. If a chasm is opened, as it was by Descartes, between the physi- cal and the mental, there is no way of closing it. We have strug- gled vainly throughout most of modern philosophy to solve a problem which, as it is stated, is insoluble: that of the relation of “thinking substance” to “extended substance.”’ In psy- chology it has appeared as the mind-body problem: How can a physical thing be related to, act upon, control or be controlled by, a non-physical thing? And there is no answer in terms of the Cartesian concepts. The theory of psycho-physical parallelism merely restates the problem in a more vivid way. Psychologists have learned that they must go back to earlier notions and merge “body” and “mind” in larger concepts such as “‘struc- ture” and “‘function.” Mind and body are aspects of, abstrac- tions from, a known reality which is wider and richer than either. In the theory of knowledge, the dualism of the mental and the physical has led to that extraordinary difficulty — how can one know the physical world? — a question which, rightly, did not enter Aristotle’s head. Descartes solved it by a tour de force, but it would not have needed to be solved unless he had assumed that physical objects are so completely disparate from minds, so wholly resident in another universe, that nothing short of a miracle could bring them together. Physical objects are not so 1 See E. B. Holt, The Concept of Consciousness (1914), chs. 8, 9. Mr. Nor- man Kemp Smith’s recent Prolegomena to an Idealist Theory of Knowledge (1924), points out that the idealism, realism, and naturalism of current philos- ophy are indistinguishable on many fundamental issues. 288 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH foreign to minds that they cannot be known, nor are they so akin to minds that they cannot be when they are not known. This is what both idealists and realists recognize, that the knowing relation is an entrance of the mind into external ob- jects, or an entrance of external objects into the mind — which- ever way one chooses to put it. Idealism as it appears in Berkeley is a polemic against ma- terialism rather than against realism.! In his day materialism was showing its head everywhere, and the good Bishop of Cloyne wished to refute a doctrine against which all that has been said above concerning idealism can be equally well main- tained. To speak of reality as “‘matter’’ is to divest the term “material”? (or physical”) of its specific meaning; for within this so-called ‘‘material” reality mind arises, at least as an epi- phenomenon—a shadowof a shadow of matter. And this subtler thinking matter is no less a reality than the cruder unthink- ing matter. We have “matter ,” and “matter,.” Thus “real- ity,” following the inevitable logic of the meaning of this term, widens out and transcends its physical as well as its mental aspect. VIL The capital crime of metaphysics is the attempt to reduce re- ality to one of its aspects or modes, a crime which is equalled only by its converse — the attempt to sever reality from all of its aspects or modes. Reality is fuller than any single set of rela- tions, laws, principles, which can be discovered within it. It is all these, and more. But though it is not possible to define reality — to state exhaustively in conceptual terms exactly what it is to be real — there are perfectly general truths which hold without qualification for reality. Any one who believes that a rational 1 We mean “realism” in the modern rather than the mediaeval sense. Berkeley’s repudiation of abstract ideas can certainly be construed as a polemic against the realism of the schools. THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE 289 metaphysics, or for that matter rational knowledge, is possible must believe that there are such general truths. The terms in which these truths are stated must be sufficiently wide to include both the mental and the physical; they must spring from the observation that reality is neither physical nor mental exclu- sively, but that it can be both. The physical and the mental must be capable of fusion. Further, it must be recognized that the dichotomy of the physical and the mental does not exhaust reality, but that there are other orders of being — perhaps, as Spinoza thought, an infinity of such orders.! No metaphysics can successfully maintain that reality is ~ essentially disparate from mind. Non-mental objects must be capable of coming into the knowing relation, and hence there must be unities which include both the mental and the non- mental. Nor can a metaphysics maintain that reality is essen- tially internal to mind in any significant sense of the term “mind.” “Idealism” and “spiritualism” suggest the latter point of view, while ‘“‘realism,” by a modern perversion of its meaning — by stressing the externality of terms and relations, of mind and its objects, and forgetting that all relations also en- ter into and modify their terms — suggests the former. There should be a name for the metaphysics which consciously repudi- ates both of these points of view and sets out from the notion that reality is an unbroken whole whose parts mutually if not completely determine one another, the mental and the non- mental being phases within this whole. Our answer to the question — how is the mind related to real objects in the act’of knowledge? — rests then on this premise, that reality is neither essentially disparate from or internal to mind. Concrete knowl- 1 Mr. A. N. Whitehead’s recent lectures at Harvard have, for the present writer, thrown a wholly fresh light on metaphysical problems; especially on this question of how, in detail, a set of general concepts can be framed which embrace the physical, the organic, the mental, and at the same time leave room for other orders of being. 290 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH edge is first of all knowledge of the real, and only secondarily knowledge of the mental or the physical. Within this appre- hended reality, two orders can be distinguished, the mental and the physical, but the one is no more essentially real than the other; each is a mode of reality, bearing on itself the stamp of being. Furthermore, the act of knowing has both its passive and ac- tive side; here as in physics the law of action and reaction ap- plies. The mind receives an impression and correlates it with other impressions, fits it under concepts, actively assimilates it to the whole body of knowledge. Objects are perceived through thought and thought through perception, for as Kant’s phrase runs, ‘percepts without concepts are blind, and concepts with- out percepts are empty.” Yet the activity of thought, rather than estranging us from external reality, brings us into contact with a reality other than thought. 1X Let us examine more fully what is meant by the “mental” with a view to showing how the mental can be continuous with the non-mental in cognition, and why thought-activity is needed to put us in touch with objects. Forget as completely as may be the distinction between the physical and the mental; put yourself in the most naive possible frame of mind and gaze on the things about you. What you see before you is a field of objects, probably a changing field; you close your eyes and see other, fainter objects, or perhaps only a dark area illuminated by dim streaks of light; you open your eyes, and perceive objects closely if not indistinguishably like those you first saw; and all the while within your body you ex- perience faint or vivid sensations of movement, perhaps of pain or of a vague well-being. There is no reason for singling out any part of this whole experience as mental. Some parts of it are THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE 291 more closely associated with the body than others; the pain is localized in the body, while the wall of the room is not; but ex- ternality or internality to the organism gives us no criterion of the mental. The distinction is certainly not an early datum of experience; it comes to the surface only after reflection, only after certain sequences and orders of events have been observed. Then it is discovered that some of the things experienced hang together by a different sort of coherence from others. Within the single field of real objects, which is the original cognitum, we find two worlds which differ in structure but easily become a single world, and there can be no question as to how knowledge passes from the one to the other. From the beginning knowledge is synoptic, it covers both. The lineage of this view, which was strikingly put by William James in his essay, Does Consciousness Exist,’ can be traced at least to Spinoza: “‘thinking substance and extended substance are one and the same thing, which is now comprehended through this and now through that attribute.” *? James need only have added to the two types of structure found in the world of “pure experience,” an infinity of types of structure (corresponding to the infinite attributes) to have become a thorough-going Spino- zist. Mr. Bertrand Russell, who has elaborated James’s view, as distinguished from ’ gives the name ‘‘mnemic causation,’ “physical causation,” to the type of law which is characteristic of the mental realm.® Memory is certainly one of the chief principles of order in the mental world, but the term “‘mnemic causation” is too sug- gestive of Hume. Its effect is to turn the attention away from the very essense of mind, activity toward an end — the unity of 1 W. James, Essays in Radical Empiricism, 1912. 2 B. de Spinoza, Ethics, Bk. II, Prop. VII, note. 3 B. Russell, The Analysis of Mind (1921), sect. 4. 292 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH memory and purpose, of backward and forward looking inten- tions, which is a personality or self. If the soul-substance view of mind is dead, so also is that of Hume — that the mind is a stage where ideas pass and repass without a spectator to take account of them. The stuff of “pure experience” does not combine and recombine of its own weight, according to the principles of asso- ciation or of mnemic causation, to form a mind. The laws of mind are laws of purposive activity; memory is itself an activ- ity; will, striving, conation, are at the core of mind; and these strands of activity are always caught together in a unity which is the self of the moment. This self changes, but not without per- sistence of its structure. At any moment a definite past, which can be called up and known again (though not exactly as be- fore), converges toward the present, and a future — purposed, desired, intended, striven for — expands from the present. This is a mind. Moreover, the activity of the mind can become reflexive, it can be turned upon itself or its own products; and this “‘reflec- tion” occurs in two very different ways. (1) In desiring, we know that we are desiring; in knowing, we know that we are knowing. Josiah Royce speaks of this as the “self-representative”” power of knowledge,! that is, knowledge can reflect on its own proc- esses. (2) The activity of the mind tends also to crystallize into a content which is still wholly within the mind. To think of or intend something is to set in motion the whole apparatus of cognition; the thought refuses to continue merely as a pure intention but strives to become concrete, that is, to fulfill itself; and thus an image or “reflexive content” appears. The image is a deposit of the activity. To know the image is therefore not merely to know that we are knowing; it is to be aware of something the mind creates. Images are the products of minds rather than minds themselves; they arise in the process of 1 J. Royce, The World and the Individual (1901), Vol. II, pp. 509 ff. THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE 293 mental activity, but they are not the activity, nor are they of the same stuff as non-mental objects. Though the activity of the mind creates reflexive contents, there is no foundation for the belief that all experience is of reflexive contents only; and if this is the meaning of Locke’s statement that “knowledge is conversant only with ideas,” an essential fact’of knowledge is overlooked, that one knows ideas and the mind that creates them only by distinguishing them in a reality which extends beyond both. Given, then, that the mind from the outset knows something other than itself, and it still remains to be shown how the mind is continuous with this non-mental reality in cognition. This continuity is not identity. The mind is other than the ex- ternal reality it knows; there is always more of the reality to be known, and always the knowing, which is of the mind but not the same as the non-mental object. (The knowing tends also to create a reflexive content which fuses with the non-mental object, but, difficult as these images are to distinguish from the object, they are not identical with this object.) The epis- temological monism which identifies mind with its non-men- tal objects makes the object of knowledge a sponge that ab- sorbs everything — error and illusion, as well as meaning and truth. Mind is cognitively continuous with non-mental objects in the same general sense as other things in this world are continu- ous with one another. And we are not speaking here of the math- ematical theory of continuity, but of something found in experi- ence, which M. Bergson describes as “interpenetration” and Mr. Whitehead as the general ‘“‘togetherness’’ of objects and events. This continuity is not, we believe, a relation. It is rather the unity or wholeness within which both terms and relations arise. Distinct things singled out as self-identical always merge in the wholes within which they are distinguished, and this union 294 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH of the parts in the whole is not due to confusion in the perception that distinguishes them, but to the nature of reality. Though reality at all points takes on distinct structures or forms, these structures are always elements in wider structures, and every whole is continuous with other wholes. Let us recall what was said previously in connection with relations| A is related to B not because the relation R which unites A and B is related to its terms, for if this were so an in- finity of relations would be needed to bring about a unity of the terms. The terms and relation are joined once for all. They form a whole in which the aspects A, B, and R can be distinguished; this is what we mean by saying the relation R holds between A and B. There is no point where the relation ceases to be a rela- tion and becomes a term, or where the terms cease to be terms and become a relation. Motion is an apparent case of such con- tinuity. There is no point at which the moving object ceases to be in one place and passes into another; in fact, the passage is just a continuous process which cannot be completely described in terms of places or points, any more than a relation between terms can be described in terms of elements and a relation. We must have the ultimate concept of the unity of the elements. We must think of the elements as abstracted from this unity, in- stead of thinking of the unity as added to the elements. We must think of the points and instants, in terms of which we describe the motion, as abstracted from the passage, rather than of the passage as superimposed on the points and instants. The mind and its objects fuse as one segment of a motion fuses with another, as a relation merges with its terms, as any part of a whole or any whole, with another. The mind projects itself into the non-mental and the non-mental into the mind. There is an unbroken flow of process, and throughout a stretch of this process—at the segment of “greatest luminosity ’’—the 1 See above, ch. III, sec. vii. —— sO THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE 295 cognition of the object comes into being. Minds are together with external objects in the same general way as objects, events, situations, are together with one another. This continuity of mind and its objects needs, however, to be further specified. Continuity (or unity) is a general background against which any elements of reality — whether they be minds, physical objects, or what not — stand out; and in each distin- guishable whole of experience this continuity is of a specific sort. Thus the whole (ARB) might be a whole of “spatial before- ness”, that is, it might be the fact “A is before B in space.” Motion is obviously a spatio-temporal unity of a specific kind. _ What sort of unity or continuity is this cognition of a non- mental object? Certainly it is not a spatial continuity. Though the object known may be spatial, the cognition is not in space but of space. These two types of whole —the spatial and the non-spatial — come together in the wider whole of cognition. On the other hand, the continuity of mind and its non-mental objects is both zn and of time; the mind as well as the world it cognizes is a changing, temporal unity. In the specious present of knowledge we grasp, in an act which is itself temporal, the im- mediate past and future of the thing known, so that each whole of cognition — being itself in time — is nevertheless a survey of time. And yet the object of knowledge has its non-temporal aspect. It is a “‘what,”’ a universal as well as an individual, and its “what” cuts across time as well as across space and belongs intrinsically to no single time or space. This is indeed the great- est paradox of knowledge, that being in time it takes hold of both the temporal and the non-temporal. The key to this para- dox is memory. In so far as we attain to any knowledge of uni- versals, of timeless objects, we do so through memory; and since concrete knowing is always the seizure of something both universal and individual, of something unique and passing which is nevertheless blended with something that has been and may 296 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH be again — for this reason, concrete knowing is a continuity of a remembered past with a new, yet familiar present. The passage of thought is plainly not motion, though it is activity; and one speaks only metaphorically of the mind as “going forth to meet its object.” Knowing is a fulfillment, a realization, in which the mind attains an end which has been obscurely before it; and whether or not teleological categories are of use in describing nature, they are indispensable in describ- ing mind. Finally, the act of knowledge is inclusive of itself. In knowing objects we know the process by which we know, the mind re- veals itself through its commerce with its non-mental environ- ment. And beyond all this, knowing has its peculiar tang which is no more subject to description than the sound of a tonic triad or achord of the seventh. Analysis discerns in knowing, as in the chord of the seventh, a number of phases, but it still remains simply what it is — a unique union of mind and object. xX It must not be supposed that the external objects which pro- ject themselves into knowledge are those that act on the senses. We perceive colors, shapes, smells, sounds, motions, houses, trees; we observe relations between these objects and laws that hold for them; but we do not perceive light-waves or sound- waves, molecules, electrons or electronic structures, nor do we perceive the bodily processes which light-waves or sound-waves, molecules or electrons, arouse in us. One can construct a theory of how these infra-experiential entities act on the sense-organs, but it is not possible to perceive these entities through their ac- tion on these organs. An immense amount of error has been propagated by the view that the only real physical objects — or, for that matter, the only real objects — are these infra-experiential entities in THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE 297 terms of which physical theory is constructed. The problem of our knowledge of physical reality is totally misconceived if one attempts to solve it by explaining how these entities, which are undoubtedly connected in some way with our sensory reactions and with all our intellectual processes, can be known through this connection. Whatever the relation of these entities to men- tal processes may be, it is certainly not the cognitive relation. This must be sought elsewhere. The physical objects of concrete knowledge must be distin- guished from the physical objects of scientific theory; these two types of physical object together make up the complete physi- cal object. There is no doubt that perception penetrates only a short way into the complete physical object; what is perceived must be pieced out by a theory as to the nature of this whole object. But this lack of concrete knowledge of the whole physi- cal object does not make the objects of perception purely men- tal. They retain their otherness, they still belong to an order dif- ferent from that of mind. The presented physical object is a mediating link between the mind and the physical object of sci- entific theory. It is sufficiently like the mind’s reflexive content (images, dream-perceptions, etc.), to be deceptive when taken out of its setting. (There is no intrinsic difference for perception between an isolated physical sound, for example, and an isolated sound-image.) Yet the presented physical object, in its setting, bears the marks of a structure different from that of the mind or the mind’s reflexive contents; and it is on this observed differ- ence of structure that a theoretical world of physical objects, extending completely beyond concrete knowledge, is built. In the act of cognition, we are aware at once of the distinctness and the unity of our minds with the presented physical object; but we are never concretely aware of how this perceptual object, or the mind, is related to the scientific physical objects. A color is doubtless vastly unlike a light-wave, yet the color is a physical 298 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH phenomenon, a non-mental reality. It comes into being in a cer- tain situation, theoretically represented as a light-wave striking an eye. It is a part of the whole physical situation of which the light-wave is a part; it is that part of the situation which can be in knowledge and at the same time in the external world. The problem of how the objects of physical theory are related through the presented physical objects to the mind, of how these three can be together, is a phase of the problem of mind and body. But the problem of the cognition of the physical world, or for that matter of any order of being beyond our own minds, is wholly another question. If there is to be any physical theory and any problem of mind and body, both the physical and the mental must be known. The mind could not leap mirac- ulously to the notion of an infra-experiential world of atoms and electrons and then ask, ‘“‘What is the relation of this world to the mind?” Whatever the solution to the mind-body problem may be, the mental and the physical are continuous in a specific way in cognition. They must also be continuous in some other specific way through the action of molecules, electrons, light- waves, on the nervous system. Since the presented physical object arises in a situation in which both a mind and other physical objects, not presented, codperate, one can ask — what aspects of the presented object are relative to this situation? — and what aspects extend be- yond it? These questions can be generalized for any situation. Every situation is altered in general complexion if some of its elements are removed. Something more than these elements goes out of existence; the original “‘what”’ of the whole is extinguished and the remaining whole is a new “what,” perhaps of a very differ- ent complexion. Thus there is something in every situation which is relative simply to that situation. Take away the spires of the cathedral at Chartres and the proportions of the building THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE 299 are destroyed; new, probably ugly, proportions come into being. It is not simply that the spires are missing; the personality of the cathedral has vanished, to be replaced by another. And yet the two personalities have something in common; the mutilated whole can be pieced out to give the original; there are hints as to what the old personality might have been. So also in every whole there are suggestions of other wholes of which it might be a part. The presented physical object, issuing as it does from the unity of a mind and other physical objects not presented, must be a distinct “what” relative to this situation. But to call atten- tion to the fact that its general complexion is determined by the psycho-physical situation is not to deprive the presented physi- cal object of its reality; nor does it make the object any more essentially relative to mind than to the physical world beyond. Just as a real object other than the single notes comes into exist- ence when a chord in C-major is sounded, so a real (perceptual) physical object comes into existence in the proper situation.1 What is the nature of the physical object when it is not per- ceived? All one can answer is that it cannot be exactly the same as when it is perceived. The situation has altered. One element, the element that makes the object perceptual, is absent; but just what aspects of the object pass out of existence with the absence of perception we certainly cannot say. Locke describes the un- 1 The question of the relevance of the perceptual object to a psycho-physical situation is not the same as that of the “privacy” of this object for an indi- vidual perceiver. Every real situation is individual, and this individuality is determined by that of its elements; hence, there must be an individuality in the perceptual object which is bound up with (though not reducible to) the in- dividuality of the perceiving mind. But every situation has, also, its universal aspects, so that the “privacy” of the perceptual object is not incompatible with its “‘publicity.” Indeed, as has been shown in the discussion of the indi- vidual (above, ch. III), only the public aspects of the object are clearly and determinately known. The perceptions that men share are those of general natures and relations, 7.e., of red, motion, etc., rather than of natures and re- lations as individualized in particular situations, The question of the “priv- acy”’ of the perceptual object is one phase of the more general metaphysical question — how can a real object be at once individual and universal, abso- lutely unique yet like other real objects? See below, secs. xii and xiii. 300 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH perceived physical object as colorless, tasteless, odorless, sound- less, but insists that it retains its geometrical and mechanical properties. Yet even Locke admits that the colors, smells, tastes, odors, are still in the physical object as ““powers”’, that is, there is something in the unperceived physical situation which be- comes a color, taste, smell, or odor when perception is added. Perhaps an unperceived color differs much more widely from a perceived color than an unperceived motion differs from a per- ceived motion, but this supposition would not warrant us (fol- lowing the distinction between primary and secondary qualities) in placing some of the modes of being of the perceptual object only in the mind and others both in the mind and in the physical field beyond the mind. Certainly the whole object as unper- ceived is continuous with the object as perceived; the latter is a real whole merging with another (unperceived) real whole and giving indications as to its nature. Thus, if there is a ‘‘somewhat”’ in the perceptual object which is peculiar to it, there are also a vast number of properties and relations which are not peculiar to it, but which stretch out into the unperceived reality. For all reality is shot through and through with the general. Though each real whole is unique, it is still an instance of many universals which link it to other wholes. Physical theory seizes on certain relations and proper- ties found in the perceptual physical object,— for example, mo- tion, acceleration, mass, spatial relations, etc., — and by refin- ing and extending these properties and relations, so that they can be used as instruments of exact description, pieces out the picture of the whole physical reality. 1 Along with the tendency of the mind to codperate with the elements of the physical situation in giving birth to the perceptual physical object goes an opposite tendency — the tendency not to codperate. Certain elements of the physical situation are excluded from the perceptual physical object. Thus, not only is there the problem of how the unperceived color or motion is perceived, but there is also the problem of why the light-waves, electrons, molecules, etc., are not perceived. THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE 301 XI What has been said of the relation of the mind to its non- mental objects makes it even more difficult to believe that these objects are known passively by impressing themselves on the mind. Both the mind and a perceptual (external) object are to- gether in the earliest wholes of cognition. The object is in the mind, the mind is in the object, and there is no reason to think that the impulse to a more complete cognition comes — as the blank-sheet view of mind would have it — from the object rather than from the mind. It is most unlikely that the mere repetition of a situation in which a mind and a perceptual ob- ject are together leads to a clearer knowledge of the object. Some other factor must also be at work. The object must catch the attention; it must attract as well as impress the mind, and this means that it must complete the mind’s intention. Cognition is always the fulfillment of an intention, and so there must be native impulses to cognition from which the first knowledge of objects springs. The mind no less than the body must have its initial structure, which grows and is modified by successive acts of knowledge. And the structure of the mind, like that of the body, must be adapted to its environment. This is — if one wishes so to speak of it — a theory of innate ideas; but just as most criticisms of the “instinct psychology” object to the specificity of the instincts assumed rather than to the fact that there are instincts, so one can repudiate innate ideas so special as those of God, of right and wrong, of mathematical truth, without repudiating all innate cognitive tendencies. An original impulse toward analysis, toward selection or sift- ing, is found in knowledge. To cognize anything clearly is to isolate it from its surroundings. This tendency toward analysis is accompanied by another, the tendency to hold together with its surroundings what has been sifted out. Not only is a single 302 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH element more clearly known through selection, but the whole of which it is a part is also more clearly known. And these most general impulses are associated with more special ones, such as jumping at a noise, turning the eyes toward a light, grasping, etc. Indeed, every special instinct is cognitive in that it leads us to analyze and to take account of the unity of our environment. Objects do not of their own accord separate themselves out from experience; they might impress themselves forever on the mind without giving rise to the dissociation of their parts which is analysis. Yet reality is so put together that it permits this dis- memberment and also resists it, thus satisfying both the impulse to analysis and to unification. The mind finds real chinks and crannies in the object, real lines of stratification along which it breaks up for thought, so that we do not create out of whole cloth a mere appearance of analysis. We adjust ourselves through analysis to something real in the world beyond. (The reason why knowledge is for Kant an act of introversion is that the cognitive impulses are totally out of adjustment to reality; there is no trace of agreement between the way in which the mind tends to think and the way in which objects are beyond the mind. It would be strange if, with bodies so nicely adapted to the physical world, our mental impulses were completely askew to reality. The theory of evolution ought to apply to minds no less than to organisms.) Analysis is a cumulative process; what has been analyzed can be further analyzed, one analysis makes possible another. We select from what has been selected, we learn that things are to- gether which have not been previously observed to be together, the channels of cognition become more and more complex, more and more numerous, enabling us in the end to take account of subtleties, distinctions, unities, which were before obscured. Finally, we become aware of the widest intentions of thought, which make analysis possible. These are the intention to direct THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE 303 every intention toward one and only one object (the principle of identity as a rule of symbolism); the intention to direct distinct intentions toward distinct objects (the principle of contradic- tion as a rule of symbolism);! and the intention to apprehend facts, situations, objects, as unified groups of distinct elements. We discover that reality yields to these intentions, that every object is what it is, self-identical and distinct from other ob- jects, yet joined with them in continuous wholes. The mind thus learns to be conscious of its categories, its structure, through the operation of these categories, the functioning of this structure, in concrete knowing. At the same time its contacts with special aspects of its environment multiply and refine its more special concepts. But the activity of the mind in the grooves of concepts would not bring us into touch with reality unless reality were perme- ated by the general. This fact is what adapts the environment to our cognitive impulses. Every concrete object is at once uni- versal and individual, absolutely unique and yet like other ob- jects. It is the universal — which is itself an object — which ful- fills our intentions in knowledge. For, as has been pointed out in another place,’ analysis is first of all the dissection of an object into a “what” and a “‘this,”’ a universal and an individual aspect. If there were nothing in the real which persisted, if every object came once and never again, our concepts could take hold of nothing. Reality would slip by unanalyzed, taken account of only in that pure awareness which lies below the level of clear cognition. No situation is wholly new; hence, it can be assimilated to knowledge held in the memory, the mind can come to rest in the apprehension of something which completes its intentions. In any moment of time (and knowledge is both an and of time) the mind, through the fulfillment of intentions 1 See above, ch. VI, sec. iv. 2 See above, ch. III, sec. i. 304 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH which bridge many times, attains a knowledge of a reality stretching far beyond the moment. With the conceptual tools forged by the aid of cruder tools, the mind digs into the object before it to discover principles which radiate into other objects — and into all reality. Thus the immediate impression is the occasion of true knowledge; yet knowledge in expanding beyond the moment does not turn upon itself to a world of appearances. It grows always in the direction of the real. In all this something which remains to be considered has been anticipated. It has been assumed that reality has a struc- ture. The essence of structure is logical form. Does reality exhibit logical form? Is reality made up of self-identical and distinct objects which coalesce into wholes (groups) with elements of unity and terms? Are universals, that is, elements of unity, real? Do the principles of identity and contradiction, which are the formal conditions of the being of self-identical and distinct objects, apply to reality? If these questions must be answered in the negative, not only does the activity of thought end in a blind-alley, but, from the metaphysical point of view, the truth which we have described as the correspondence of concepts through their structure with real objects becomes error. If reality is structureless, it cannot be adequately known through a thought bound to logical forms. XII Here is a turning-point in any metaphysics of knowledge. How are we to stand off from thought and hold it up beside its objects to discover whether the two are commensurate? If they are commensurate, if there can be a real identity of structure in concepts and the things they refer to, we cannot demonstrate through concepts that such an identity is possible, for this cor- respondence of concepts with objects is itself the condition of rational truth and demonstration. Nor can we know this struc- THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE 305 tured reality in a cognitive act which takes no account of struc- ture. And if thought and its objects are incommensurate, we can not prove them to be so by going back to the negative arguments of agnosticism. We cannot, through the logical forms of thought, show that reality is without logical form; some positive knowl- edge, not through thought, of this formless reality would be needed. Beside agnosticism, which on purely negative grounds denies reason access to reality, stands positive irrationalism — a meta- physics which condemns reason on the strength of an intuition that goes deeper than thought to a mystic union with the real. ‘Agnosticism does not successfully negate rational metaphysics. Does this positive irrationalism meet with better success? To answer this question, we must consider in what sense the act of cognition as a whole escapes from the concepts which at once confine and guide it. Every act of concrete knowing overflows the conceptual. To perceive an object is to capture in experience what one intends, but it is also to capture more than one intends. This is one rea- son why the real is alien to thought. Concepts can be multiplied indefinitely, yet the real object to which they lead is not ex- hausted and is always ready to yield further analyses, to submit to new descriptions. I conceive the object as a unique “some- what” in certain relations to other unique “somewhats’’; but when I grasp the object concretely I know that these concepts direct me only to some of its aspects. The object zs as I conceive it, but is also other than I conceive it; and in knowing that what can be picked out clearly and stated as true of the object is only an aspect, I must apprehend the object as transcending and in- cluding all its aspects. What has been said before of the universal and the individual sharpens this point. For conceptual knowledge, the individual 306 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH is always attempting to become universal by dissolving into a complex infinity of characters and relations, but it succeeds only in being an indeterminate x; while the universal is always seek- ing to become individual by qualifying and requalifying itself in an infinity of ways. If I wish to conceptualize the individuality of a pebble picked up on the beach, I am driven to hundreds of characterizations, of measurements, of minute observations; yet the pebble is still the x of which these relations and qualities can be predicated, and I cannot even be certain (with Leibniz) that an infinity of such predicates would distinguish this pebble. I cannot, in thought alone, bridge the gap between the x, which means indeterminately an individual, and the other concepts, which stand for its predicates and relations. It is in vain that I fill in with more predicates. In concrete knowledge the gap is closed, though not by concepts. I know the pebble, hold it in my hand, as a unique object in which all the predicates I have ob- served are reconciled. It is not merely that concrete knowledge adds sensation to thought; I do not sense the unity of the predi- cates in the individual. The act of knowing has pushed out be- yond sensation and thought to an intuition of the object. This intuition has been spoken of before as pure awareness. Pure awareness issues from thought and sensation; we cannot catch it in itself apart from the other phases of cognition, and yet it is not the same as either of these other phases. What intuition gives us is a residue of knowledge, left over when all that is clearly conceived or sensed in the object has been analyzed away. Consider the knowledge of a personality. Here intuition is especially prominent. Calculation, analysis, will carry one only a short way in adjusting himself to persons; something like talent, skill, tact, is needed — not a talent separated from the power of analysis, but a talent which makes use of every shred of clear knowledge, and yet does not rely wholly on clear knowl- KS eee ee eee ee ee eee ee THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE 307 edge. To know a personality is to enter into that personal- ity, not blindly, but so that analysis plays its part and is left behind. Pure awareness is not sensation for the reason that a sensa- tion is atomic; it is a distinct “‘what,” e.g., this redness, this sourness, distinguished within a perceived whole. Moreover, a “pure sensation” would be a sensation of nothing whatsoever, for sensation cannot be thinned down till every vestige of mean- ing, thought, has been wiped away. When this search for a “pure sensation”’ is pursued, the sensum approaches a vanish- ing point. A “‘pure sensation” is the thinnest of abstractions, an _ imaginary limit which cognition never reaches. When knowledge overflows the conceptual, it does not do so in the direction of sensation. Nor does knowledge pass beyond concepts by going to the other extreme, by sifting out all traces of sensation, leav- ing the materials of experience behind and attaining an esoteric vision of a reality that never was and never could be found in perception. Yet to speak of pure awareness, of non-conceptual knowledge, is to suggest the one or the other of these views — sensationalism, or rationalism become esoteric. An act of concrete knowing is bathed in an atmosphere of the non-conceptual; it has a part of its being in a medium which is neither pure thought nor pure sensation; and no act of concrete knowing is complete until it finds itself surrounded and upheld by the non-conceptual. This ever-present background of pure awareness tends, like other backgrounds, to be forgotten and to emerge only when a foreground has been clearly distinguished. But it is always there, bringing thought and sensation together and completing knowledge as neither thought nor sensation can. It is impossible to isolate thought from sensation, and equally impossible to isolate pure awareness from sensation and thought. Perceptual thought transforms itself into pure awareness and pure awareness passes smoothly into perceptual thought. There 308 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH is no pure awareness dissociated from these other modes of cog- nition. An anti-intellectualistic philosophy such as M. Bergson’s wishes to set pure awareness or intuition on its own feet, to sever rational thought from the non-conceptual medium into which and from which it flows. M. Bergson does violence to the cognitive act; he looks at cognition abstractly in the very effort to fasten on that which is most concrete in it. Instead of seeing it as it is, a fusion of reason, sensation, and intuition, he exalts the irrational component at the expense of the rational. “By intuition,” M. Bergson explains, “is meant the kind of intellectual sympathy by which one places oneself within an ob- ject in order to coincide with what is unique in it and conse- quently inexpressible. Analysis, on the contrary, is the opera- tion which reduces the object to elements already known, that is, to elements common both to itself and to other objects. To analyze, therefore, is to express a thing as a function of some- thing other than itself. All analysis is thus a translation, a de- velopment into symbols, a representation taken from successive points of view from which we note as many resemblances as possible between the new object which we are studying and others which we believe we know already. In its eternally un- satisfied desire to embrace the object around which it is com- pelled to turn, analysis multiplies without end the number of its points of view in order to complete its always incomplete repre- snetation, and ceaselessly varies its symbols that it may perfect the always imperfect translation. It goes on, therefore, to infin- ity. But intuition is a simple act.” ! M. Bergson’s writings, like his snowball rolling down hill and growing as it rolls, bulk together to force it on the mind that concrete knowing is more than analysis. But that analysis is es- 1 H. Bergson, An Introduction to Metaphysics, T. E. Hulme’s translation (1912), p. 8. THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE 309 sentially falsification, that intuition enters into reality to find a changing, formless, flowing durée which eludes all concepts — these are conclusions which follow only from making a part of concrete knowing equal to the whole. M. Bergson is Heracleitus with the logos left out. If reality is change, this fact, as Heraclei- tus observed, does not itself change, and here is an entering wedge for the permanent. An intuition cut off from concepts could not name the reality it knows. Just as the concrete con- tent of pure sensation or of pure thought would approach a zero, so the concrete content of pure intuition tends to be nothing. M. Bergson insists, for example, that to conceive a motion as an infinite series of brief motions taking place at point-instants ar- ranged in order is to fail to know the passage which is the es- sence of the motion. One must identify himself with this passage by intuition. Yet this pure intuition of the wholeness of the mo- tion is, in itself, no less empty than the representation in terms of point-instants. Though there is something real in the passage which is given only in intuition, there is also something real in it which corresponds to the conceptual series of point-instants.’ To know the motion either simply as passage or simply as a re- lated series of motions at point-instants is, in each case, to have an insecure hold on its reality. Irrationalism springs from a desire deeply rooted in human nature — the desire to give oneself up, like a resting swimmer on a bright sea, to the sustaining buoyancy of a limitless and intimate reality. But one knows the buoyancy of the sea only by learning to swim, and one knows reality only by learning to think out his intuitions and to gain new intuitions through his thought. M. Bergson’s feeling that the deliverances of intuition prove 1 See A. N. Whitehead, The Principles of Natural Knowledge (1919), chs. 8, 9, 10, 11 on extensive abstraction for a definition of points and instants which correlates these entities with the perceived reality. 310 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH the inadequacy of thought cannot rest on a contradiction be- tween what is known without concepts and what is known in concepts, for contradiction has meaning only where concepts apply. Intuition could not contradict reason. When the cogni- tive act is taken in its wholeness as the convergence of thought, sensation, and intuition upon an object, this feeling of the inad- equacy of thought to reality melts away. Though one is aware that reality is not completely compressed into the molds of reason, he still finds something in the real which fits these molds. Reality exhibits logical form. XI That reality is logical in form means that the distinction be- tween terms and the universals, that is, the qualities and rela- tions, which modify and unite these terms, is a real distinction. It means that there are basic terms, individuals, about which qualities and relations cluster to form concrete facts. It means that every object, whether individual or universal, is self-identi- cal and distinct from other objects, and finally that these ob- jects unite into wholes, groups, which are themselves real ob- jects. For Kant it is just this logical form which is created by thought and which confines thought to a world of phenomena; and for M. Bergson this logical form is the product of a platoniz- ing intellect. But since the mind from the outset of knowledge is in contact with the real, in knowing objects it must be able to know that logical form is in reality and not merely in a mind compelled to think in this fashion. This is the first and most fundamental metaphysical insight. Let us return to the vis sua nativa of the intellect of which Spinoza speaks. If there is any knowledge, there is a metaphysi- cal insight which upholds knowledge at every stage and which becomes conscious of its own general intentions and, through >? a oe THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE 311 these, of the general structure of reality, when knowledge is faced with the question of its own validity. To know is, from the be- ginning, to have an insight into the real. This power is not at- tained after long meditation. It is not by falling into antinomies and seeking a way out that thought is enabled finally to seize reality; nor is it by dismembering the act of knowledge and at- tempting to know through pure sensation, pure reason, or pure intuition. This power is a crude and original endowment of the mind. It is manifest in the simplest act of concrete knowing, not as one component but as the very life of the act itself. To reflect on knowledge, to ask how we can know and what we can know, is to bring this original metaphysical insight to a consciousness of itself. Instead of being aware of objects as fulfilling specific intentions, as being of this or that sort, we become aware of ob- jects as fulfilling the most general intentions of thought, and thus we discover the logical structure of the reality to which our thought is from the first adapted, and from which it is never cut off. We cannot step outside the act of knowledge to an intuition which renders all knowledge but itself invalid. Knowledge from its inception embraces a reality which is logical in form, without being aware of what constitutes logical form. We do not pause to reflect that in knowing we are distin- guishing terms from their qualities and relations, that we are taking some terms as individual, that we are treating objects as self-identical and distinct, though as united into real wholes. But if we do pause to reflect, we know that only because objects conform to these highly general conditions are they real. To know that the widest intentions of thought are fulfilled by ob- jects is to tighten rather than loosen the native grasp of the mind on reality. In perceiving the logical framework of the real- ity within which it operates, the mind knows its own power with a new clarity. That concrete knowing even of the most elementary sort is 312 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH insight into the real, and that the act of knowing as a whole is the source of this insight, are the basic propositions of a meta- physics which justifies knowledge. These propositions do not assert that all concrete knowledge is true. An object may not be as it is known, it may be misconceived. But even a miscon- ceived object zs, if it is known concretely; it is there to be reck- oned with, to be fitted into the scheme of reality. The act of knowledge, becoming conscious of itself, reveals the essential pat- tern of this scheme, but it does not reach through more readily to the details than it would without this self-consciousness. By discovering that the general principles of knowledge are rooted in the general structure of the real, we learn that a rational truth is possible, but we do not establish specific truths. Spe- cific truths must be hewn out laboriously from the materials of experience by many cumulating acts of knowing. The details must be fitted into the general pattern, and for this the skill which grows with the expansion of knowledge is needed. Thus in one direction knowledge is complete, it can take se- cure hold of the form of the real; while in another direction it is never complete, it is being continually enlarged and fortified by new details. Within the essential scheme of the real, there is room for an infinite variety of detail. The form is in the detail; the variety of detail, in the form. The metaphysical insight which makes use of the complete cognitive act shows us how passing and tem- porary objects embody universal principles and yet are them- selves unique products of an ever-renewed process of becoming. Reality is as changeful and growing as M. Bergson finds it to be, but the change is an affirmation rather than a denial of logical form. Against the newness, the individuality, of the thing of the moment, the universal, which is neither new nor individual, stands out. M. Bergson condemns analysis because it must “ex- press a thing as a function of something other than itself” and THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE 313 so miss what is unique in the thing. One can condemn pure in- tuition because, in refusing to express a thing as a function of something other than itself, it misses what is not unique in the thing — and so fails to know this very uniqueness as sharply as might be if analysis were joined to intuition. To the irrationalist, reality cannot be self-contradictory for this reason, that it resists concepts — and contradiction is a logi- cal relation between concepts; the term has no meaning for him as applied to the real. The reality known through the fuller metaphysical insight of which we are speaking is non-contra- dictory in another sense; the principles of identity and contra- diction can be truly affirmed of it. This reality can be consist- ently presented and represented through concepts. And yet, if we consider these principles themselves, it is plain that they permit an endless mutability of the particular. As statements about the real world they affirm that “any object is identical with itself and distinct from other objects,” but they give us no information as to what objects are self-identical and distinct. They tell us merely that, however tangled the lines of identity and distinctness may be, there must still be such lines. Con- sistency has thus its metaphysical basis as a test of truth which is valid even though no experience includes a reality which is complete, full-grown, in every respect. Judgments can go on correcting themselves by their consistency even though con- sistency does not determine the subject-matter of any truth. This infinite perfectibility of knowledge does not lead to the corollary that there is no truth except through an infinite pro- cess of correction. We know the logical form of reality without such a process; logical form is a perfectly general aspect of the real which can be grasped in finite knowledge. Yet it is only an aspect. And if we can know one perfectly general aspect of real- ity in finite knowledge, we can know others— provided there are such aspects to be known. 314 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH The laws of nature seem to hang midway between these purely formal principles and particular truths. It is possible, as C. S. Peirce, H. Poincare,’ and others have suggested, that whole systems of natural law are superseded by other systems, as one event in history is superseded by another, or old sets of personal habits by new ones. But if the universe, from time to time, gives up one general mode of behavior to adopt another, it does not contradict itself. The particular events of history can be truly known, so long as we do not insist that they are more than particular events; and so a system of natural laws, which might dissolve and pass, could be truly known if we did not be- lieve it to be eternal — if we could see what went before and came after. But just as every set of personal habits embodies the laws of human psychology, so every one of a successive infinity of cosmic habits would embody the psychology of the universe. And even if the laws of this cosmic psychology were more con- crete than the formal principles of structure we have discussed, they could be known in perfect generality. Whatever the whole of reality may be — if there be a whole— we can be certain that we do not know this whole. A complete understanding of any whole rests on a knowledge of its parts, and a complete understanding of the parts on a knowledge of the whole, but it does not follow that there are no truths which are valid for the parts alone. Though the process of the growth, the becoming, of reality may go on infinitely, and though it may be impossible to know all there is (or will be) to be known con- cerning any fragment of the real — unless it be in a mind which spans this infinite process,— still these considerations do not demonstrate the impossibility of attaining truth in a knowledge which is immersed in the process of becoming. 1 C.S. Peirce, Chance, Love, and Logic (1923), ““The Doctrine of Necessity Examined”; also, H. Poincare, La Valeur de la Science (1905), ch. 11, and Derniéres Pensées (1913), ch. 1. THE METAPHYSICS OF KNOWLEDGE 315 XIV No criticism of knowledge, then, can destroy knowledge; no theory of appearances can prove that reality is unknown or un- knowable. For a knowledge of even the most contradictory of appearances is the beginning of an insight into the real. The theory of knowledge clarifies this insight as one clarifies his speech by learning the grammar of the language to which he is born. But without speech we could not learn the rules of speech, and without true knowledge we could not construct a theory of truth. _ At the poles of knowledge, beyond clear statement and ra- tional proof or disproof, are scepticism and mysticism. The sceptic believes nothing he can state; the mystic can state nothing he believes. Rational knowledge shares with scepticism a readiness to revise itself but refuses to join scepticism in re- vising itself into a state of total incredulity. Something stands firm, if it be no more than the good sense which Descartes found “is of all things among men the most equally distributed.” With the irrationalist and the mystic, rational knowledge shares the conviction that reality cannot be completely packed into neat concepts, but rational knowledge cannot believe that there is no neatness in reality, that because something escapes nice formu- lation, everything does. Making use of all the instruments at its command — sensa- tion, thought, intuition — knowledge can reflect on its own pro- cesses and reaffirm, as against scepticism, mysticism, and ag- nosticism, its own ability to take at least partial possession of the real in a rational experience. But in order to know, it is not necessary to inquire how it is possible to know. As the lungs are prepared by nature for breathing, the hands for grasping, the legs for walking, so the mind is prepared for knowing. We may with infinite patience lay bare the anatomy of the mind, but we 316 SYMBOLISM AND TRUTH cannot in doing so discover that the mind’s function is to trick — us or to shut us off from the real. The air the mind breathes, the substance it grasps, the ground it walks on, is reality. The theory of knowledge, like the knife of the surgeon, may be able to sepa- rate the delicately woven tissues of thought, but it cannot give or take away the power to know. SUPPLEMENTARY READINGS Tars list of supplementary readings is not a bibliography; it is in- tended to bring together for the use of the student some of the contem- porary literature — chiefly in English — on the theory of knowledge, and to suggest directions in which the topics treated in the text can be expanded. It will be well for the reader to take up the selections under each heading in the order given here; the readings most closely allied to the text are placed first in each group. References to the classical philosophers are omitted, except in a few instances. INTRODUCTION On the relation of the theory of knowledge to metaphysics: C. D. Broad, Scientific Thought (1923), Introduction. W. T. Marvin, The New Realism (1912), “The Emancipation of Metaphysics from Epistemology.” S. Alexander, Space, Time, and Deity (1920), Introduction. Cuapter I, Meaninea On the psychology of meaning: E. B. Titchener, The Experimental Psychology of the Thought Process (1909), Lect. 2, “‘Reference to Object as the Criterion of Mind,” Lect. 5, “The Experimental Psychology of the Thought Process.” E. Rignano, The Psychology of Reasoning (1923), ch. 4, “What is Reasoning?” K. Koffka, The Growth of Mind (1924), ch. 5, sec. 10, “The First Use of Language.” J. B. Watson, Psychology from the Standpoint of a Behaviorist (1919) ch. 9, secs. A, B, “Explicit and Implicit Language Habits.” G. F. Stout, Analytic Psychology (1896), bk. ii, ch. 10, “Thought and Language.” On the philosophy of meaning: F. C. S. Schiller, B. Russell, H. H. Joachim, Mind, N. S. vol. 29 (1920), pp. 385 ff., “The Meaning of Meaning, a Symposium.” R. F. A. Hoernlé, Mind, N. S. vol. 16 (1907), pp. 70 ff., “Image, Idea, and Meaning.” C. K. Ogden and I. A. Richards, The Meaning of Meaning (1923), ch. 2, part 2, “Towards a Science of Symbolism,” ch. 9, “The Meaning of Meaning,” ch. 10, “Symbol Situations.” On mediate and immediate knowledge: W. James, The Principles of Psychology (1890), vol. 1, ch. 8, “The Relations of Minds to Other Things,” ch. 9, “The Stream of Thought.” 317 318 SUPPLEMENTARY READINGS G. F. Stout, Analytic Psychology (1896), bk. i, ch. 2, ““The Analysis of Presentations,” ch. 3, “The Apprehension of Form,” bk. ii, ch. 5, ““Noetic Synthesis.” J. Ward, Psychological Principles (1918), ch. 4, secs. 1, 2, “‘The Presentational Continuum,” ch. 6, secs. 1, 2, 6, 7, “‘Perception,” ch. 12, “Thought and Language.” Cuapter II, Logica Form On the structure of complexes: B. Russell, Monist, vol. 28 (1918), pp. 509 ff., “The Philosophy of Logical Atomism,” lect. 2. L. Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (1922), Introduction (by B. Russell), Preface, and Text through prop. 4.04. On identity and diversity: G. E. Moore, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol. 1 (1900- 1901), pp. 103 ff., “Identity.” Cuapter III, Universats AND INDIVIDUALS: ORDER On universals and individuals: J. Laird, A Study in Realism (1920), ch. 6, “‘ Principles.” S. Alexander, Space, Time, and Deity (1920), vol. 1, bk. i, ch. 3, “Universal, Particular, Individual,” ch. 4, “‘ Relation.” B. Russell, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol. 12 (1911-1912), pp. 1 ff., “On the Relations of Universals and Particulars.” G. F. Stout, Proceedings of the British Academy (1921), “The Nature of Universals and Propositions.” W. E. Johnson, Logic (1921), Part I, ch. 11, ‘“‘The Determinable,” ch. 12, ““The Relation of Identity,” ch. 13, “Relations or Transi- tive Adjectives.” On space, time, and objects: C. D. Broad, Scientific Thought (1923), ch. 1, ‘The Traditional Con- ception of Space and the Principle of Extensive Abstraction,” ch. 2, “Time and Change.” A. N. Whitehead, The Concept of Nature (1920), ch. 3, “Time,” ch. 5, “Space and Motion,” ch. 7, “Objects”; also, The Principles of Natural Knowledge (1919), Part II, ch. 6, “Events,” ch. .7, “Objects.” On abstraction: G. Berkeley, The Principles of Human Knowledge (1710), Introduc- tion. A. N. Whitehead, The Principles of Natural Knowledge (1919), Part II, chs. 8, 9, ‘Extensive Abstraction.” On order: B. Russell, The Principles of Mathematics (1903), ch. 9, “Relations.” S. Alexander, Space, Time, and Deity (1920), vol. i, bk. i, ch. 5, “Order.” SS) eS a eel SUPPLEMENTARY READINGS 319 CuHapteR IV, Description AND ANALYSIS On naming, description, and the variable: B. Russell, The Problems of Philosophy, ch. 5, ‘Knowledge by Ac- quaintance and Knowledge by Description,” ch. 9, “The World of Universals”; also, The Principles of Mathematics (1903), ch. 5, “On Denoting,” ch. 8, “The Variable’; and Mind, N. S., vol. 15 (1905), pp. 479 ff., “On Denoting.” B. Bosanquet, Logic (1888), vol. 1, Introduction. A. N. Whitehead, An Introduction to Mathematics (1911), ch. 2, “Variables,” ch. 5, “The Symbolism of Mathematics.” On internal and external relations: F. H. Bradley, Appearance and Reality (1893), ch. 2, “Substantive and Adjective,” ch. 3, “Relation and Quality.” G. E. Moore, Philosophical Studies (1922), ch. 9, ‘‘External and In- ternal Relations.” Cuapter V, TrutH anv Fatsity On truth and falsity: L. A. Reid, Knowledge and Truth (1923), omitting ch. 9 (for a gen- eral survey of contemporary theories of truth). S. Alexander, Space, Time, and Deity (1920), vol. 2, bk. iti, ch. 8, “Tllusion and Ideas,” ch. 9, sec. B, “Truth and Error.” F. H. Bradley, Essays on Truth and Reality (1914), ch. 5, “On Truth and Copying,” ch. 9, “On Appearance, Error, and Contradic- tion.” H. H. Joachim, The Nature of Truth (1906), ch. 1, ““Truth as Corre- spondence,”’ ch. 3, Part I, ‘““The Coherence Notion of Truth.” On sensation and perception: Plato, Theaetetus, Jowett’s translation. J. Laird, A Study in Realism (1920), ch. 2, “The Things We Per- ceive.” R. F. A. Hoernlé, Studies in Contemporary Metaphysics (1920), ch. 4, “On ‘Doubting the Reality of the World of Sense’,”’ ch. 5, ***Saving the Appearances’ in the Physical World.” W. James, The Principles of Psychology (1890), vol. 2, ch. 21, ‘The Perception of Reality.” B. Russell, Our Knowledge of the External World (1914), Lect. 3, ‘The External World.” C. D. Broad, Scientific Thought (1923), ch. 7, “‘Matter and its Ap- pearances,”’ ch. 8, ““The Theory of Sensa.” On the theory of “objectives”: G. D. Hicks, Mind, N.5S., vol. 31 (1922), pp. 1 ff., “‘The Philosophical Researches of Meinong.”’ B. Russell, Mind, N. §., vol. 13 (1904), pp. 204 ff., 336 ff., 509 ff., *Meinong’s Theory of Complexes and Assumptions.” 320 SUPPLEMENTARY READINGS On belief: D. Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature (1738), bk. i, Part ITI, secs. 7, 8, 10. F. C.S. Schiller, Problems of Belief (1924), chs. 1, 3, 9, 10, 11, 12. C. S. Peirce, Chance, Love, and Logic (1923), First Paper, “The Fixation of Belief.” CuapterR VI, NEGATION AND CONTRADICTION Se . On negation: R. Demos, Mind, N. S., vol. 24 (1917), pp. 188 ff., “A Discussion of a Certain Type of Negative Proposition.” F. H. Bradley, The Principles of Logic (2d ed. 1922), vol. 1, bk. i, ch. 3, “The Negative Judgment,” and Terminal Essay 6. B. Bosanquet, Logic (1888), vol. 1, ch. 7, secs. 1, 2, 3, 5. W. E. Johnson, Logic (1921), Part I, ch. 5, “Negation.” H. Bergson, Creative Evolution (1911, transl. by A. Mitchell), ch. 4, “The Idea of Nothing.” On contradiction and the “‘laws of thought”: F. C.S. Schiller, Formal Logic (1912), ch. 10, “The Laws of Thought.” C. Sigwart, Logic (2d ed. 1895, transl.), vol. 1, ch. 4, “The Negation.” ee a ee ee ee ee Cuapter VII, Format DepuctTIion On formal deduction in general: J. W. Young, Fundamental Concepts of Algebra and Geometry (1911), lects. 1, 4, 5, 19, 21. A. N. Whitehead, A Treatise on Universal Algebra (1898), ch. 1, “On the Nature of a Calculus.” C. I. Lewis, A Survey of Symbolic Logic (1918), ch. 6, secs. 1, 3. L. Couturat, La Logique de Leibniz (Paris, 1901), ch. 4, sec. 4 ff., “La Caractéristique Universelle.”’ On the Boolean Algebra: E. V. Huntington, Transactions of the American Mathematical So- ciety, vol. 5, no. 3 (1904), pp. 288 ff., “Sets of Independent Pos- tulates for the Algebra of Logic.” H. M. Sheffer, Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 14, no. 4 (1913), pp. 481 ff., “A Set of Five Independent Postulates for Boolean Algebra.” > sis CuHapter VIII, Toe Merapnysics or KNowLEDGE On appearance and reality: F. H. Bradley, Appearance and Reality (1893), bk. xi, chs. 13, 14, “The General Nature of Reality,” ch. 15, “‘Thought and Real- ity,” ch. 27, “Ultimate Doubts.” J. Ward, Naturalism and Agnosticism (1899), vol. i, Introduction, vol. 2, Part IV, lects. 14, 15. A. J. Balfour, A Defence of Philosophic Doubt (1879), ch. 1, “On the Idea of a Philosophy,” ch. 6, “Transcendentalism,” ch. 13, “Evolution of Belief.’ Sg ee SR ee ee a ee a ee Se SUPPLEMENTARY READINGS 321 On the relation of mind and its objects: W. James, Essays in Radical Empiricism (1912), Essay 1, ‘Does Consciousness Exist?” S. Alexander, Space, Time, and Deity (1920), vol. 2, bk. iii, ch. 4, “Mind and Knowing.” R. B. Perry, Present Philosophical Tendencies (1912), Part V, ch. 13, ““A Realistic Theory of Knowledge.” On idealism and its critics: R. F. A. Hoernlé, Idealism (1924), especially chs. 4, 5, “Idealism as the Theory of the Absolute.” J. Royce, The World and the Individual (1900), vol. 1, lects. 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 10 (an examination of realism, mysticism, Kantianism, and absolute idealism). T. H. Greene, Prolegomena to Ethics (1883), bk. i, ch. 1, “The Spirit- ual Principle in Knowledge and in Nature,” ch. 2, “The Relation of Man as Intelligence to the Spiritual Principle in Nature.” R. B. Perry, Present Philosophical Tendencies (1912), Part III, ch. 6, “The Cardinal Principle of Idealism,” ch. 7, “Objective or Transcendental Idealism.” On intuitionism: H. Bergson, Creative Evolution (1911, transl. by A. Mitchell), In- troduction, ch. 4, pp. 298 ff., “‘Form and Becoming’’; also An Introduction to Metaphysics (1912, trans. by E. Hulme). General reference: C. D. Macintosh, The Problem of Knowledge (1915). INDEX “A,”? 120, 121, 145. Absolute, The, 175, 277, 285. Absolute Idealism, 272, 273. Abstract facts, 82, 106. Abstract ideas, 85. Abstract thought, 117. Abstraction, 83-85, 88, 106. Absurdity, 94, 95. Acquaintance, 13, 38. Action, versus thought, 28. Active form, grammatical, 98. Adjectives, 89 ff., 117. Agnosticism, 268 ff., 278, 279. Algebra, Boolean, 335 ff. “All,” 140. Ambiguity, 56; logical, 119 ff.; psy- chological, 119, 120; of the nega- tive, 198 ff., 219. Ambiguous truth and falsity, 212 ff. An,” 120, 121. Analysis, 31, 47,54, 64, ch. iv (108 ff.), 126; original impulse to, 301, 302. Analytic form, in scientific knowl- edge, 133 ff. Analytic judgments, 126 ff., 131, 147. Analytical representation, 31. Antinomies, Kantian, 169, 277. Antirationalism, 169, 305 ff. “Any,” 121, 122, 145. Appearance, 150; and reality, 272 ff., 280. A priori, The, 208, 219. Aristotle, 44, 66, 84, 132, 173, 188, 267, 282 (note), 287. Assertion, of descriptions, 145, 146. Assertion, 179 ff., 184, 185; sign of, 185. Association, 22. Asymmetry, 96 ff. Aufgabe, 17, 22. Awareness, pure, 18, 20, 39, 43, 66, 157, 305 ff. Bacon, F., 5, 7. Behaviorism, theory of meaning, 25 ff. Belief, 16, 24, 25, 29, 37, 149, 179 ff., 195; and inference 255 ff. Bergson, H., 18, 89, 169, 289, 312, 313; theory of intuition, 308 ff. Berkeley, 7, 21, 85, 162, 274, 284, 285, 288. Boolean Algebra, 235 ff. Bradley, F. H., 67, 89, 277. Broad, C. D., 8. Carroll, Lewis, 94, 118. Case, grammatical distinctions of, 98. Categories, 194; Kantian, 171; em- pirical, 171; principles of identity and contradiction as formal cate- gories, 208. Change, 69 ff., 77, 78, 105. Classes, 140 ff.; infinite, 143; of one member, 143; logic of, 243 ff. Coherence theory of truth, 175 ff, 194. Commutative law, 100, 247. Comparison, 87. Completely inferential systems, 259, 264. Complexes, 30, 42 ff.; order of poly- adic complexes, 98; meaning of, 154, 155. Complex elements of unity, 103 ff., 107. Complex objects, 35. Complex symbols, 35 ff. Conception, 17, 38. Conceptual validity, distinguished from truth, 218, 219. Concrete facts, 82, 106. Concrete thought, 282, 283. Condensation of substitutions, 234. Connoting, 111. 325 326 Consistency, 168 ff., 194; as truth, 174; formal, 218, 223; as a real category, 313. Constants, functional, 252. Construction of concepts, 156; con- structs, 165. Continuity, of mind and objects, 276, 293-295. Contradiction, principle of, ch. vi (205 ff.), 219, 226; as a formal category, 208. Copula, 185. Correspondence, 42; of form, 52; of symbols and objects, 60. Correspondence theory of truth, 173 ff., 176 ff., 192. Critical philosophy, 270 ff. Data, 34; sense data, 14ff., 19, 160 ff.; reality of, 159 ff., 193. Deduction, ch. vii (222 ff.), 261 ff. Deductive systems, 92; conditions of significance and truth in, 258 ff. Definition, 32, 34, 58, 118, 146, 226, 236, 231%. Demos, R., theory of negation, 198 ff., 219. Denial, 185 ff.; bare, 215; privation of ground, 216; positive denial, 216 ff. Denoting, 109 ff. Descartes, 70, 287, 315. Description, 35, 74, ch. iv (108 ff.); of universals, 122; form of, 112, 113, 145; assertion of, 145, 146. Determinism, 68, 72. ‘Determination is negation,”’ 205. Dialectic, Kantian, 277, 278. Disbelief, 185 ff., 196, 215. Distinctness of meaning, as basis of negation, 203 ff. Diversity, numerical, 46, 59, 60; per- ception of, 68; as a real category, 313 Dreams, 162 ff. Dualism, epistemological, 274; Car- tesian, 287, 288. “*Each,” 143. Empiricism, 165 ff. INDEX Equations of structure, 233, 236. Equivalence, 58. Equivocation, 56, 57, 64, 119. Error, 16, 149, 163 ff., 172, 173, 191. Essence, 66. Euclidean space, 134 ff., 147. “Every,” 143. Excluded middle, 186, 208 ff., 219. Existence, criteria of, 159 ff.; as a predicate, 183; limited meaning of, 193. External relations, 130. Fact, 44 ff., 65; unity of, 78 ff.; con- crete, 82; abstract, 82; syntax of, 91; negative, 197 ff., 219. Falsity, 148, ch. v (149 ff.), 193, 197; ambiguous falsity, 212 ff. Fancy, 188. First philosophy, 195. Form, 37; of objects, 43; logical form, ch. ii (41 ff.), 78 ff.; general schematism of, 52; correspondence of, 53; presentation of, 107; of descriptions, 112, 113, 145; objec- tivity of symbolic form, 156; iden- tity of form in fact and symbol, 178; science of pure form, 222. Function, 45. Functional constants, 252. Functional range, 249 ff. Functional variability, 249 ff., 263. Generalization, 116 ff. Geometry, 134 ff.; Euclidean, 147, 222; non-Euclidean, 134f., 147,222. Grammar, 37, 40; of symbolism,. 89 ff., 106. Ground, of negation, 200, 204, 216 ff.; privation of, 216. Groups, symbolic, 35 ff., 40; defini- tion of a group, 45 ff., 64; type of, 47, 48, 63; multiplicity of, 48, 63; major members of, 48, 49; reflex- ive, 61, 62; unity of, 78 ff. Group meaning, 31 ff. Habits, of meaning, 26; of language, 27. Heracleitus, 309. INDEX Hobbes, 22, 149, 179, 260. Holt, E. B., 287 (note). Hume, 7, 8, 59, 60, 162; theory of belief, 180 ff.; scepticism, 189 ff.; 276, 291, 292. Huntington, E. V., 228, 232, 233, 243. Husserl, E., 8. Idealism, 272, 273, 284 ff., 289. Ideas, 9 ff., 38; abstract, 85; innate, 301. Identity, 44, 46; statements of, 54; principle of, 56-58, 64, 139, 206, 207, 226; of objects, 56, 59; of indiscernibles, 71, 74; of univer- sals, 76 ff.; of the variable, 118; of meaning, 126 ff.; as a formal cate- gory, 208; as a real category, 313. Tllusion, 163, 164. Images, 10 ff., 38, 94, 95, 153, 292. Imagination, 35, 36, 73; syntax of, 93 ff.; constructive, 181; and rea- son, 260, 261. Immediate knowledge, 13 ff., 19, 38, 305 ff. Implications, in formal systems, 233, 234, 251, 252. Incompatibility, 200, 219. Incomplete symbols, 108 ff., 124. Incompletely inferential systems, 259, 260, 264. Incredulity, 187 ff. Indiscernibles, identity of, '71, 74. Individuality, reality of, 306. Individuals, ch. iii (66 ff.); determi- nation of, by universals, 67 ff.; principle of individuation, 70; representation of, 71, 72; bare in- dividuals, 129. Induction, 168. Anference, 223; general nature of, 255 ff., 263. Inferential negation, 211. Infinite classes, 143. Infinite negative, 217. Innate ideas, 301. Insight, metaphysical, 272, 277, 279, . 810 fi. Intention, 29, 38, 39. Internal relations, 130. 327 Interpretation, signs of, 120ff.; of formal systems, 224 ff., 242 ff. Intuition, 18 ff., 20, 43, 165, 279, 301, 305 fi. Irrationalism, 305 ff. V8 7185. James, W., 15, 16, 22, 24, 165, 186; theory of consciousness, 291. Joachim, H. H., 175 ff. Judgment, 179 ff.; synthetic, 126 ff.; analytic, 126 ff.; inference as a form of, 257. Kant, 7, 81, 88, 131, 158, 167, 168, 169, 171, 182, 190, 208; agnosti- cism, 270 ff., 290, 302, 310. Knowing relation, 295, 296. Kiilpe, O., 17 (note). Language, 51, 81, 90; habits of, 27; origin of, 33; syntax of, 93 ff., 102; inference in, 259, 260. Laws, 89, 147; of thought, 205 ff. Leibniz, 71, 72, 74, 105; theory of truth and deduction, 264, 265 (note), 306. Locke, 7, 9, 10, 22, 30, 85, 127, 167, 176; agnosticism, 270ff., 293, 299, 300. Logic, 5; formal logic, 201, 202, 222; algebra of, 235 ff.; of classes, 248 ff. Logical ambiguity, 119 ff. Logical form, ch. ii (41 ff.); general schematism of, 52; reality of, 304 ff. Logical opposition, 201. Major members, of symbolic groups, 48, 49. Materialism, 288. Matter, 66, 84. Meaning, ch. i (9ff.), 21 ff.; psy- chology of, 23 ff., 28, 29; be- havioristic theory of, 25 ff.; habits of, 26; syntactical, 31, 35 ff., 39, 40; the non-existent, 35, 36; of complexes, 154, 155; hypostatiza- tion of, 158; in perception, 166... 328 INDEX Mediate knowledge, 13 ff., 38. Meinong, A., 8, 152. Memory, 291, 292, 295. Metaphysical insight, 272, 277, 279, 310 ff. Metaphysics, 5 ff., 150, 170, 191, 208; of knowledge, ch. viii (266 ff.). Mind-body, problem of, 287, 298. Mind-isolation, in Locke and Kant, Q73 ff. Monism, epistemological, 276, 293. Moore, G. E., 8, 76, 151-153. Multiplicity, of groups, 48, 63. Mysticism, 315. Negation, ch. vi (197 ff.); negative facts, 197 ff., 219; ambiguity of negative, 198 ff., 219; as variable, 199; meaning of, 200; ground of, 200, 204, 216 ff.; defined through truth, 209 ff.; negation and infer- ence, 210 ff.; truth and falsity of negatives, 212; purely conceptual negation, 219; inferential nega- tion, 219; double negation, 239, 240. Negatives, 186. Nominalism, 67, 86 ff., 106, 129. Non-deductive systems, 91. Non-Euclidean geometry, 134, 147. Non-existent objects, 35, 36, 158; reference to, 136 ff., 144, 159. Nonsense, 93 ff., 106. Null class, 243. Number, 46. Objectives, 152 ff. Objective reference, 153 ff., 192. Objectivity, of symbolic forms, 156; criteria of, 159. Objects, complex, 35; formal char- acters of, 43 ff.; identity of, 59; relational object, 97; non-existent, objects, 35, 36, 158; perceptual object, 161, 162, 164, 296 ff. Occam’s razor, 237. One and Many, The, 141. Ontological argument, 158, 159, 182, 183. Operations, 52, 79, 80; perception of, 88; criterion of, 244, 253 ff.; dis- tinguished from relations, 263. Opposition, logical, 201. Order, 62, 95 ff., 106, 107; of poly- adic complexes, 98; postulates for serial order, 254, 255 (note). Otherness, 203. Parameters, 252. Parmenides, 207. Particularity, 83. Passive form, grammatical, 98. Peirce, C. S., 314. Perception, 32, 34, 66, 133, 159 ff.; of numerical diversity, 68; of uni- versals, 75 ff.; of operations, 88; of relations, 88. Perceptual object, 161, 162, 296 ff.; reality of, 164. Physical objects, 296-298. Plato, 36, 66, 81, 107, 189, 273. Poincaré, H., 314. Positive theory of knowledge, 6 ff., 86, 269. Possibility, for knowledge, 92, 93, 106. Post-Kantians, 273. Postulate-sets, 227 ff. Presentation, 13, 32, 33; of logical forms, 107. Presentational thought, 167, 168, 193. Primary and secondary qualities, 299, 300. Principia Mathematica, 51, 108, 114, 117, 118, 124, 136-141, 229, 230, 243, 256. : Privacy, of objects, 229 (note). Proper names, 47, 74, 108, 114, 123 ff., 129, 144, 146. Proposition, 35, 111, 112, 146, 151; definition of, 183, 184; asa tertium quid, 151 ff.; simple symbols as propositions, 183, 184. Psychological ambiguity, 119, 120. Psychology, of meaning, 23 ff., 28, 29. Punctuation, 51. Pure awareness, 18, 20, 39, 43, 66, 157, 305 ff. Pythagoreans, 46. 2 a ee a ee SO ee ee ee oe a INDEX Qualities, 52,79; distinguished from relations, 80 (note); primary and secondary, 299, 300. Rationalism, 169, 315. Realism, 67, 286, 288, 289. Reality, 150; of perceptual objects, 164 ff.; limited concept of, 170, 193; definition of, 286, 287. Recurrence, of symbols, 55 ff. Referent, of relations, 98 ff. Reflexive expressions, 61, 62, 230, wale Reflexive relations, 80. Reid, T., 16, 161. Relations, 45, 52, 79, 80, 100 ff.; reflexive, 80; perception of, 88; triadic, dyadic, monadic, 104; ex- ternality of, 130; internality of, 130; distinguished from operations, 245, 253 ff. Relativism, 189. Relatum, 98 ff. Representation, analytical, 31; scale of, 47. Round-square, The, 136 ff. Royce, J., 292. Russell, B., 8, 51, 100; theory of descriptions, 108 ff., 124 ff., 136, 145, 161, 175; theory of negation, 197 ff., 221, 291. Scepticism, 166, 187 ff., 268-270. Schopenhauer, 164, 165 (note). Scientific knowledge, 133 ff. Scientific method, as hypothetical, 270. Sensation, 281-283, 307. Sensationalism, 164 ff. Sense data, 14 ff., 19, 160 ff. Serial order, postulates for, 254, 255 (note). Sheffer, H. M., 201, 202. Signs, of syntax, 51, 65, 225; of in- terpretation, 120 ff. Simple symbols, 31 ff., 39, 64, 154; form of, 47; as propositions, 183, 184. Simplicity, 202. *““Some,”’ 121, 122, 145. 329 Sophists, The, 189. Space, 69 ff., 105; Euclidean, 134 ff. Speech, 149. Spencer, H., 268. Spinoza, 273, 277, 289, 291, 310; on agnosticism, 272. Spiritualism, 289. Structure, symbolic, 41 ff.; of real- ity, 304 ff. Subject, of relations, 97. Subsistent entities, 151 ff. Substance, 44, 128; and quality, in Locke, 274. Substantives, 89 ff., 117. Substitution, 27; deductive, 224, 226, 227, 228 ff.; completeness of, 230, 231; interpretation of rules of, 250 ff. Subsumption, of classes, 240 ff., 247. Sufficient reason, 72, 74. Symbol, general nature of, 21. Symbolic groups, 35 ff., 40. Symbolism, general principles of, 225. Symmetry, 99 ff. Syntactical meaning, 31, 35 ff., 37, 39, 40. Syntax, 40, 41, 106; rules of, 41; plans of, 91; of fact, 91; of the imagination, 93 ff.; of language, 93 ff., 102; signs of, 51, 65, 225; in formal systems, 224 ff. Synthetic judgments, 126 ff., 147. Tabula rasa, 34, 38, 167, 283. Tautologous symbols, 48, 55 ff., 62, 63. Terms, 82 ff., 105. Tests of truth, 174ff., 190, 191, 194. “The,” 120, 145. Theory, 172, 173. Thing-in-itself, 167, 168, 275, 278. Thought, 29, 30, 281-283; and action, 28; abstract, 117; presen- tational, 167, 168, 193; laws of, 205 ff.; as symbolic manipulation, 260, 261. Time, 69 ff., 105. Totality, as defining concept of classes, 141 ff. 330 Truth, 91, 92, 148, ch. v (149 ff.); as » conceivability, 174 ff.; as con- sistency, 174; as correspondence, 173, 176 ff., 192; coherence theory of, 175 ff.; tests of, 174 ff., 190, 191; value of, 181; ambiguous truth, 212 ff. Type, of symbolic groups, 47, 48, 63. Understanding, 25, 29. Unity, of groups, 78 ff.; of facts, 78 ff., 88; elements of, 52, 53, 65, 104; complex elements of, 103 ff.; symbols of, 89ff.; of mind and objects, 294 ff. Universals, ch. iii (66 ff.); percep- tion of, 75 ff.; identity of, 76 ff.; INDEX reality of, 85 ff.; descriptions of, 122; as object of thought-activity, 303. Universal class, 243. Validity, conceptual, 223. Variables, 73, 114 ff., 146, 223; iden- tity of, 118; negative as a variable, 119 ff.; functional variables dis- tinguished from interpretational, 249 ff.; functional, 263. Watson, J. B., 27. Whitehead, A.N., 8, 20, 52, 150, 289 (note), 293. Whitman, Walt, 226. Willis, G., 33. DATE DUE d : =t ot Xu 2 HIGHSMITH #45230 ue ¥ 5 1 j ' rr fens i : ‘ ‘ a ri | | | | | | | | Printed in USA } Sy ne * at Des War tains Ob et 4 7, h ae Ke,