eee St OOOO eae willie nnse ouvanscnsmcewscowsemnanca TS TT See ae aaa aaa eee ee aaa a eee Tea SS ag eee se rae pf poraas naman eens pascanar rene ar ee ew anne ee Sena REST NN NANT EAa NY ERLE TET ST AO ES PO TE aE SL A RENEE S NESSES IST ANN RL SET TE Sie CPE Se a Seraoecevereremmns Soc ne See ae ee ea oem —— a a a a a — ya f ie SEL 6 ga Division. a Aerie i ¢ Py Cie | hia witli Section fel tite { An i Yas iy I vt uth * se pay niga Be ow Pan’, A ee Aree! CARTESIANISM CARTESIANISM BY MICHAEL J. MAHONY, S.J., Pw.D. PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY FORDHAM UNIVERSITY Author of “Formal Logic” and “Epistemology” FORDHAM UNIVERSITY PRESS NEW YORK Imprimi Potest Lavurentius J. Ketty, S. J. Preap. Prov. Provincie Marylandie Eboracensis HRibil @bstat Artuur J. Scanian, S. T. D. Censor Librorum Imprimatur MK Patrick, Carpinat Hayes Archbishop of New York New York, July 4, 1925 Copyright, 1925, by ForpHam Unrversiry Press. PRINTED IN U. 8. TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION Chap. I, René Descartes Chap. II. Exposition of His Philosophical System Chap. III. Its Constructive Aspect Chap. IV. Critical Examination Chap. V. Criticism (Continued) . Chap. VI. Occasionalism . Chap. VII. Ontologism . Chap. VIII. The Pre-Established Harmony of Leibnitz and the Pantheism of Spinoza Chap. IX. Some Practical Lessons to be Learned from Cartesianism 103 119 129 141 INTRODUCTION HE subject that is to claim our attention and study in this class during the coming year is the “History and Criticism of the Various’ Philosophical: Systems of Modern Thought.” ‘That we may have a sufficiently clear concept of what this subject means, it will be well, by way of intro- duction, to stake off its territory and define its limits, so that the other branches of philosophical studies which may engage your attention may not encroach upon the property rights of our subject, or our rights upon theirs. 1. What, then, in the first place, are we to under- stand by a philosophical system of thought? 2. Secondly, what philosophical systems are unani- mously set down as modern? 3. Lastly, what method shall we pursue in setting forth the history of the latter systems, and what standard shall we adopt in passing a crit- ical judgment on their merits? - Let us try, in the first place, to understand what is a “philosophy” or a philosophical system of thought, and how is it differentiated from all other kinds of thought. In other words, what does the mind endeavor to solve when it philosophizes? Now, thought may be described as the exercise of our reasoning faculty upon any subject. In this sense thought is a swbjective process or activity. Thought is also taken in an objective sense to signify the results of thought; that is, the truths which it dis- 6 CARTESIANISM covers. Now, among the truths that rational thought brings within the sweep of our knowledge, there are some that are beyond and impervious to the ken of sense. We grasp, for instance, by thought or reason- ing alone, the truths of mathematics, the laws of chemistry, physics, and of the natural sciences; we may reason out the solution of great political prob- lems, for example, the question of the payment or reduction of the Allies’ war debts. But the rational thought that is exercised on sub- jects such as those and the conclusions at which it arrives, are not, strictly speaking, philosophy or philosophical thought. Philosophy or philosophical thought is differentiated from all other rational thought by two characteristics. In the first place, philosophical thought or philoso- phy exercises itself in not setting forth the immediate causes that explain facts or phenomena. When a scientist, for instance, explains that water is a combi- nation of H and QO, he is not philosophising. Philoso- phy probes deeper, and professes to set forth the ulti- mate or last causes of all the things that exist around us. All other sciences achieve their purpose when they assign the cause that is next to hand for any happening or fact. The chemist is satisfied when he discovers the simple material elements that compose a compound body, or the kind of material substance a combination of certain elements will form. Chem- istry does not ask, what ultimately is matter itself? What cause has brought this material universe into existence? These deeper questions philosophy asks and professes to answer. If a chemist discusses those questions, he is no longer playing the réle of chemist, but of a philosopher. The science of political econ- omy will investigate the causes of the production and distribution of the wealth possessed by men. But it INTRODUCTION 7 will not ask, what is man? What is the first cause of his existence? Philosophy alone professes to answer those deeper questions. Its field of inquiry begins where the other sciences leave off. It ceases not to ask its inquisitive “whys” until its last “why” is answered. The first characteristic, then, that differentiates the science of philosophy or philosophical thought from all the other natural sciences is this, that philosophy moves thoughtfully along the successive links of a series of causes that account for any fact, until it dis- covers by its reasoning the wlttmate, or, if you wish, the first cause, in the series. Hence, sound philoso- phy must reasonably discover that the last link in any chain of causes, however long, rests in the hand of God. You may often hear a child of six or seven exercising this instinct of a philosopher. The child may begin by asking, for example, — “Mother, what makes the kettle boil? Mother—“The fire, of course.” Child — “What makes the fire?’ Mother — ‘The coal in the range.” Child — “Where did the coal come from?” Mother — ‘From the mines under ground.” Child— “Who put the coal in the mines?” The mother, astonished at the growing reasoning of her inquisitive child, is ultimately forced to answer — “God, darling.” Beyond God there is no other cause. He is the last or ultimate cause of all things. That is philosophy. It professes to lead the mind on and on until it points out the ultimate source, or last cause, of all things around us. All other special sciences are satisfied to remain and rest at some inn on the sides of the mountain of thought. Philosophy climbs to the top. Hence phil- osophy is marked off from all other natural sciences in this, that it is not satisfied with the discovery of any cause for things around us. It demands always the very last or ultimate cause or explanation of all 8 CARTESIANISM things. So that philosophy begins where the special sciences leave off. Philosophy is marked by a second characteristic. It relies in its investigations and questionings wpon the light of natural reason. Hence, strictly speaking, philosophy is not sectarian. It accepts the facts re- vealed to us by our senses and the investigations of the other sciences, and then consults its natural reason to interpret it all. Philosophy is, therefore, limited to what unaided reason can discover about the origin of matter, the origin of man and his destiny, the origin of the soul, and so forth. It has to do with origins. Because feeble reason can discover only a very few truths that have been also revealed by God, the great bulk of divinely revealed dogmas are outside the field of philosophy’s vision. To be outside the field of rea- son does not imply, however, any contradiction to reason. Philosophy, therefore, does not include within its province the discovery of truths that are, as such, divinely revealed. ‘They are beyond its territory. Since it is the business of philosophy to exercise the powers of natural reason to discover the ultimate causes of naturally acquired facts, while it is reserved for Sacred Theology to exercise human reason on facts that are divinely revealed, hence philosophy is differentiated from Sacred Theology in this, that though natural reason is exercised in both, still in philosophy the matter upon which reason works is naturally acquired, whereas in the case of Sacred Theology the matter upon which reason works is supernaturally acquired, because it is supplied by divine Revelation. Having now understood what philosophy is, namely, the ultimate explanation which the natural light of reason gives of all things that exist, it is not to be INTRODUCTION 9 expected, when one considers how feeble is the light of reason, and how prone to error, that every leader of thought, who thinks for himself, will agree in the account they give of the final explanation of the facts of all existence. It is as difficult for reason to keep its poise, so as not to swerve from the straight line of truth in an intricate and long process of reasoning, as it is for a man to keep his balance while walking upon a narrow plank over a deep chasm. Hence it is with the ultimate explanations which reason has given for the things around us, as itis with our watches — no two go just alike, yet each person believes his own. If we look back, then, over the history of the ultimate ex- planations or philosophies of all things around us, we shall find these philosophies as different and numer- ous as were the great leaders of thought that pro- pounded them. Plato has one kind of explanation or philosophy, Aristotle another, St. Thomas and the Scholastics another. We may illustrate the origin of the bewildering number and variety of philosophical systems in the pages of history in this way: Let a number of men, each furnished by the light of a dim lantern, attempt to trace their way through a vast and dark forest to a certain destination, without guide or compass, without the help of the sun, moon, or stars. Though each could, absolutely speaking, find his way out, yet the likelihood is that they would all go astray in such a trackless forest. It is as diffi- cult for an individual mind to track its way by the light of feeble reason through the labyrinth of evi- dence and argument, with the view of arriving at a correct and ultimate explanation of the universe and all that it contains, as it is for a man without a guide to make his way through a vast and unknown forest. Hence the bewildering varieties of the systems of philosophy. 10 CARTESIANISM All those historical systems of Western Civilization (we are not for the present interested in Eastern philosophy) may be conveniently divided into three periods: 1. The systems of the ancient Greek and Roman world, the chief of which were those of Plato and Aristotle. 2. The philosophical system of Scholasticism, which is nothing else but the system of Aristotle cor- rected and developed, so as to bring it into harmony with sound reason and the truths of Christianity by such profound thinkers as Albertus Magnus, St. Thomas of Aquin,-and Duns Scotus. 3. The many systems that have sprung up in oppo- sition to Scholasticism from the time of Descartes (1596-1650) to the present day. It is those latter systems that are known in history as “Modern Phil- osophy” or “Modern Thought.” It is with the expo- sition, therefore, and criticism of these latter systems we are concerned in our present course. They, and not the ancient or medieval systems, will form the subject matter of our present lectures. In order that we may not be beating the air, but know what we are to study in, and how to study, each of those modern systems of philosophical thought, what method shall we pursue? (a) The first topic that will engage our attention in the study of any school or system is the life, times, and personal character of its founder. It is a com- monplace to say that, that which is most intimate in a man, namely, his character, which is nothing else but a habitual inclination of his will, gives to his thoughts and judgments a certain bias. It is most difficult for feeble human nature to preserve that equipoise of judgment, which, like a perfect balance, will unerringly weigh evidence and tilt only on the INTRODUCTION 11 side of truth. Hence a knowledge of the moral and religious character of each founder of a system, of his national and racial tendencies and prejudices, will be an invaluable guide to us, in forming a just esti- mate of his philosophical thought. It is not enough to know the personal character of each founder of a system. We should also endeavor to know his environment, because a great leader or writer wins thousands to his views, not so much be- cause he forms their opinions, but because he gives clear and systematic expression to the half-uncon- sciously formed opinions of the age in which he lives. To judge, then, of the value of a thought-system that gives form and expression to what is called the Zeit- geist, or spirit of the age, we should be acquainted with the intellectual, social, political, economic, and religious movements which dominate the times and country in which the founder of a system of thought lives. Thus did the philosophers of the Hebrew race at the time of Christ, biased by the prejudices of their times, call Christianity a “scandal,” as the philoso- phers of Greece called it “foolishness.” (6) Having gleaned an insight into the character and the environment of the founder of the system of thought which we set ourselves to study, we are ex- pected, in the second place, to become familiar with the fundamental principles of that system. The prin- ciples, of course, of each system will form the main topic of study. This knowledge can be acquired only by a frank and honest exposition of each system according to the mind of its founder. You are ex- pected, then, to be as familiar with the successive steps in the up-building of each system, as you are with the rooms of your home. Now, assuming that you have mastered the main outlines of each system as a whole, you are, in the 12 CARTESIANISM third place, expected to observe the links of thought or logical connection that usually binds together a preceding system with the system that succeeds it. For, despite the diversity in the teachings of each philosophical system, we shall discover that a certain inner connection exists between the different schools of thought that succeed each other in time. The re- sults attained by the earlier philosophers were not lost upon those who succeeded them. On the con- trary, each founder of a new system makes the theo- ries of his predecessors, should those theories be to his mind satisfactorily established, the starting points of the new system. On the other hand, should the suc- ceeding philosopher consider the findings of his pred- ecessor insufficiently established or wholly false, the new system will set up, in opposition to the old, new principles and new foundations. In a word, one of ' the most interesting aspects of this study of systems will be to detect, in the lineaments of the newly-born baby system, a resemblance to its parents. We have now, in the last place, arrived at what we, Catholics, deem of the highest importance in the study of any system of thought that may engage our atten- tion — namely, its criticism. That is, how far may we approve or disapprove of its teachings? Is the sys- tem consistent with, or contradictory of, itself? What are the reasons that justify our judgment of it? Now, profitable criticism has a double purpose. It duly acknowledges and appreciates what is true and noble in a philosophical work, while at the same time it will censure what is false. It will distinguish the laudable purpose of an author, from the means he may take to achieve that purpose. Criticism will point out the influence of a philosopher for good or evil upon his contemporaries and future generations. Now, praise or censure of a philosophical system INTRODUCTION 13 implies in its critic a standard of judgment. What shall that standard be? At first sight it seems a very simple matter to set up such a standard of judgment, and say that such a standard, of course, shall be the philosophy of life, which is unanimously held to be true. But, unfortu- nately, all people, even the so-called educated, are, by no means, unanimous in their adherence to any one philosophy of life, any more than they are unanimous in professing one religious belief. Suppose it were my good or evil fortune, as a philosopher, to have to lecture to a class, some of whom were professed Mate- rialists, others Idealists, another group Atheists, still another Agnostics. My conclusions would be silently or vociferously contradicted by each group of my audience. If I established the existence of a soul or spirit in man, the Materialists would deny it; if I set forth the arguments for the existence of God, the Atheists and Agnostics would not accept them. If I asserted the independent existence of matter, the Idealists would be up in arms. Each group, then, would criticise any conclusion I may arrive at by the light, or may be the darkness, of their preconceived philosophy of life. Thoughtless people are fond of asserting that it is the Irish only that fight among themselves, whereas the truth is, that the smug, sleek philosophers, outside the Catholic Church, are contin- ually cudgelling one another’s conclusions with a pas- sion and vigor that ‘“out-Donnybrook”’ Donnybrook Fair. Where, then, shall you look for a standard whereby to pass a critical judgment on the different antagonistic systems that will come, in the course of your study of “Modern Thought”, before the bar of your Reason? Of course, it is usually admitted that the ultimate standard that is to decide the truth or falsehood of a 14 CARTESIANISM system of philosophy is the evidence that is presented for or against such a system before the judgment seat of reason, somewhat in the same way as a prisoner is declared guilty or not guilty by the evidence pre- sented in a court of law. Our natural reason has no other test whereby we are able to distinguish truth from falsehood except the objective evidence that may be available to guide our judgment. For objective evidence is accepted as the ultimate criterion of truth. If philosophers, then, would sift the evidence for a philosophy of life, free from the sway of preconceived bias or prejudice, in accord with the laws of reason- ing, they would all arrive at the same solution of the vital problems of life, and all say the same thing, ac- cording to the Apostle. But history shows that, as a fact, philosophers have not done so, and if we may judge the future by the past, we are obliged to con- clude that philosophers will never agree. Is there any sun in the heavens, any star in the fir- mament to tell the philosophical mariner when his ship of reason strays from the course of truth and evidence? Is there given to men at least a negative standard of truth, when the positive standard of evi- dence becomes obscure either through carelessness in its examination, or because of some bias of mind? I mean by a negative standard of truth simply this —a standard of truth that will warn you that a philo- sophical system must be false, though it will not tell you the solution that is alone true. Let me illustrate the nature of a negative standard of truth by a familiar example: Suppose you are a teacher. A pupil brings up to you his sum in addition wrongly cast up. You tell him his answer is wrong; you rub out that answer, and send him back to his seat to try again. Herein you are not interfering in the least with the rights of your pupil’s reason, but, on INTRODUCTION 15 the contrary, requiring him to exercise reason right- fully. Now, the teacher, in the case, is for the pupil a negative standard of truth. Negative, because the teacher simply tells the pupil his answer is not true. Should the teacher tell the pupil the true answer, then that teacher would be a positive standard of truth for the pupil. Now, is there given to philosophers a negative guide or negative standard, at least, to warn them when such conclusions of theirs as have a vital bearing on human - life and conduct are wrong, and which will send them back to their studies, as the teacher did the child, to review more carefully their reasoning processes, with the view of arriving at the true solution? Of course, a child is naturally humble, and will not feel any risings of revolt when he is told his answer is wrong. But the philosophers are often haughty, and may stubbornly refuse to obey their negative guide and remain in error. Now, I don’t know any more important principle to take to heart at the very threshold of the study of the “History of Modern Systems of Thought’, that may be fraught with danger for some, than this, namely, that all men are providentially furnished with at least a negative standard of truth to guide them to discern what is false, not in a sum of arithmetic, but in conclusions of philosophy. No greater calamity can befall anyone, than to be educated in a false philoso- phy. It shatters the very foundations of his intellec- tual, moral, and religious life. And this negative standard, which is to thought and science what the polar star is to the mariner, is the divinely revealed truths of faith. We frankly state, therefore, that the negative standard of criticism in passing judgment upon systems of philosophy is the infallible and au- thoritative teaching of the Catholic faith. Hence, any 16 CARTESIANISM conclusions of philosophers, or any professed scientific teaching that openly and clearly contradicts an infal- lible truth of our Catholic faith is forthwith to be rejected as false, and such philosophers or scientists who propose such conclusions are to be sent back to their seats, like school-children, to ponder over their evidence and scrutinize their reasoning processes, un- til they bring their conclusions into harmony with truths that are hedged round by the infallible author- ity of Christ and His Church, which is “‘the same yes- terday, to-day, and forever.” Scholastic philosophy, the “genwina philosophia perenms’’, has always recognized as eminently reason- able the moderating influence of divine revelation as a negative standard or test of truth, in benignantly preserving from error the wayward human reason. But “freedom of thought and science” vehemently protests that the recognition of the authority of re- vealed faith and of the Catholic Church shackles the liberty of philosophy. We answer that philosophy, scholastic or otherwise, even when it recognizes the authority of divine reve- lation as a negative mentor, enjoys all the liberty that is rightly its dwe, and therefore all the freedom which it can reasonably claim. Reason, as exercised by human beings, is clothed in all the features of crea- turehood. It is not, and cannot be, in the nature of things, absolutely independent. Hence, if its Creator speaks and graciously reveals to reason certain truths, it is only reasonable that it should accord to those . truths its submissive and unqualified assent. And since truth cannot contradict truth, it devolves on human reason to subject its native conclusions to di- vinely and infallibly revealed truth, rather than sub- ject God-given truths to the proverbially fallible con- clusions of reason. The latter attitude is not the exer- INTRODUCTION 17 cise of legitimate intellectual freedom. It is intellec- tual sedition. Hence the claim of the absolute indepen- dence of human reason, which is known as Rational- ism, is in itself irrational and therefore self-destruc- tive. This fundamental principle of scholastic philoso- phy, namely, that it would be unreasonable to expect that a truth of divine revelation should yield to that professed to be a product of human reason has been advocated by even John Locke, who was neither a Catholic nor a Scholastic philosopher. He says: — “Whatever is divine revelation ought to overrule all our opinions, prejudices, and interests, and hath a right to be received with full assent. Such a submis- sion as this, of our reason to faith, takes not away the landmarks of knowledge: this shakes not the founda- tion of reason, but leaves us that use of our faculties for which they were given us.” (B. IV., C. XVIIL, 10.) Again Locke says:—“ ... . “there is one sort of propositions that challenge the highest degree of our assent upon bare testimony, whether the thing pro- posed agree or disagree with common experience, and the ordinary course of things, or no. The reason whereof is, because the testimony is of such an one as cannot deceive or be deceived; and that is of God Himself. This carries with it an assurance beyond doubt, evidence beyond exception. This is called by a peculiar name, Revelation, and our assent to it, faith, which as absolutely determines our minds, and as per- fectly excludes all wavering as our knowledge itself ; and we may as well doubt of our own being as we can whether any revelation from God be true.” (B.IV., C. XVI, 14.) The principle enunciated above only emphasizes the law that truth has an indefeasible right to reign over 18 CARTESIANISM the intellect of man, and consequently the human in- tellect is in duty bound to submit to truth. And if the truth of divine revelation, once granted it as given, is not truth, what is? A declaration of independence by human reason against divine revelation would be arro- gant because irrational, and an abuse of free-will. By submitting to duly accredited truth, the intellect is not enslaved, but liberated. On the contrary, human intellects that revolt against the truths of revelation are often already enslaved, because they usually work under the bidding of an illegitimate and disorderly passion—the passion which is dignified by many modern thinkers into an intellectual virtue —irre- sponsible free-thought. a RENE DESCARTES Cuapter I. CHAPTER I. RENE DESCARTES (1596-1650) N the last lecture we have explained, by way of introduction to the “Philosophical Systems of Modern Thought”, what is meant by (1) “phil- osophy”’, (2) by a “System” of philosophy, (3) and what systems in the history of philosophy are unani- mously acknowledged as “modern”. We have likewise set forth the plan or method which we intend to follow in the study of each of those modern systems. We shall indicate (1) the chief events of the life, and of the life-time, as well as the character of the founder of each system. For the char- acter of a man, as well as the stirring events which constitute the environment in which he lived, usually exert a powerful influence in moulding his views and opinions. We shall then (2) give an exposition of his philosophical principles as set forth in his writings. Then we shall (3) point out the logical connection between the different successive systems of thought, and lastly we shall (4) offer a critical estimate of each system. As philosophers, we shall make use of the light of evidence as the standard or test of our critical judgments and as Catholics we shall frankly reject any principle or opinion that openly contradicts the teaching of our faith, no matter how distinguished may be the reputation of the philosopher or scientist who may present that principle or opinion for our acceptance. Because, as we explained in the introduc- 22 CARTESIANISM tion, in a supposed conflict between the conclusions of philosophy or science, and a settled truth of reve- lation, it would be unreasonable to expect that the revealed truth should yield to what professed to be the product of reason. | Having completed the preliminary explanations, which were necessary for the better understanding of the subject that is to occupy our attention, we shall now enter into the study of that system of philosophy which first broke away from the tradition of Scholas- ticism, and inaugurated the period that is known in the history of philosophy as the rise of “Modern Thought.” That system of philosophy, which is uni- versally acknowledged as the herald of “Modern Thought’, is known as Cartesianism. It was founded by René Descartes Duperron, who is popularly known as Descartes. (1596-1650.) Our interest in, as well as the advantages to be derived from, a study of Descartes’ philosophy do not arise from any intrinsic value of its principles, or of the body of doctrines embodied therein, but because his system places in our hands the key that will unlock, at their primal source, the understanding of the many false principles that have moulded the thought and guided the purposes of those men of intellect, whom the non-Catholic world has lauded as its great teach- ers for the last three hundred years. The best means of acquiring a knowledge of the fallacious principles that lie at the basis of the fantastic theories of so many modern thinkers is to examine the sources from which these erroneous principles originally sprang. “He who considers things in their growth and origin”, says Aristotle, “will obtain the clearest view of them.” And, strange to say, though Descartes was himself a pious Catholic, yet he has given to the world a system of philosophy that is, in a large measure, the original RENE DESCARTES 23 source of those diseased germs of thought that have infected the philosophical systems of a large section of the intellectual world for the last three hundred years. It is this diseased thought of Descartes, ac- cepted in whole or in part by so many modern phil- osophers in France, Germany, Italy, England, and America that has bred, as we shall see in the course of our study, the Materialism, the Atheism, Pantheism, and consequently the immorality of international, national, and domestic relations which is at the back of the restless confusion of the world to-day. Itis true that philosophy alone, even were it solid and whole- some, could never and will never regenerate the world. But it is equally true that false philosophies will aggravate the tendency in human nature towards degeneracy. Before entering, however, into the exposition and criticism of Descartes’ philosophy, it will be helpful to know something of his life and character, that we may better evaluate the philosophical child of his brain. Towards the close of the Sixteenth Century, 1596, twenty-four years before the Mayflower landed on Plymouth Rock, René Descartes (Duperron) was born at La Haye, in the Province of Lorraine, France. For the better understanding of Descartes’ mentality and loyalty through life to the Catholic Church, it is not without significance to note that his parents were natives of celtic Brittany. Everybody knows that the Bretons, who gave so many distin- guished men to France, are one of the most ancient, bravest and staunchest Catholic peoples in the conti- nent of Europe. A few days after his birth his mother died of some disease of the lungs. Inheriting, no doubt, her deli- cate health, he grew up a sickly boy, yet his mind was 24 CARTESIANISM so brilliant and inquisitive that at the age of eight he was called by his companions the “young philoso- pher”. Up to the age of sixteen he was a pupil of the Jesuits in the famous college of La Fleche. Speaking in after years of his college days, he says, “I was studying in one of the most celebrated schools of Europe, in which I thought there must be learned men, if such were anywhere to be found. I had been taught all that others learned there; and, not con- tented with the sciences actually taught us, I had, in addition, read all the books that had fallen into my hands. I knew the judgments that others had formed of me; and I did find that I was not considered in- ferior to my fellows, although there were among them some who were already marked out to fill the places of our instructors’. (Method 1). He retained through life a deep attachment to his former Jesuit teachers; his only regret was their refusal to accept his philoso- phy. Though his natural bent was towards Mathematics and Science (he wrote several works on Mathematics and Science), he was also an ardent student of litera- ture. On leaving college at the age of sixteen (1612), he went to Paris, and for a time gave up all study. Of this period of his life he says: “As soon as my age permitted me to pass from under the control of my instructors, I entirely abandoned the study of letters and resolved no longer to seek any other science than the knowledge of myself and the great book of the world”. While yet in Paris and towards the end of his teens, with a view of devoting his time to the study of self and his own thoughts, he formulated the great motto of his life, — “Bene vivit qui bene latuit” (“To live in close seclusion is the way to live well”), and having retired into seclusion in a lonely part of Paris, he again resumed his studies. During this time of in- RENE DESCARTES 25 trospective brooding, even before his twenty- -first year, like many another ambitious youth of inquisi- tive mind, he was obsessed by a passion for truth, but failed to discover what, for him, was a satisfactory ground for certainty either in the sciences or in the philosophy which he was taught in school. Hear his reflections on the philosophy of his time. He says, “Of Philosophy I will say nothing, except that I saw that it had been cultivated for many ages by the most distinguished men, and yet there is not a single matter within its sphere which is not still in dispute, and noth- ing therefore which is above doubt.” (Method I.) His inquisitive and sensitive mind became, so to speak, the heir of all the confused ideas that had their origin in the so-called “Illumination” of the human- ists of the Renaissance and of the Protestant Refor- mation. (Hist. of Phil., Klimke, Vol. I., p. 303.) This confusion caused a wave of utter Scepticism to sweep over his soul. Harassed by his intellectual scru- ples, he resolved, at the age of twenty-one (1617), to obtain relief in travel and in the distractions of an active life. “I spent,” he says, “the remainder of my youth in travelling, in visiting courts and armies, in holding intercourse with men of different dispositions and ranks, in collecting varied experience.” (Method I.) For this purpose he became a soldier. He served in the army of Prince Maurice in Holland and Ger- many and later under the Elector of Bavaria. It was at this period he visited Loretto to pray for light and deliverance from his painful doubts, at the famous Shrine of the Blessed Virgin. While he was living in winter quarters at Neuberg on the Danube, in his twenty-fourth year (1619-1620), the mental crisis of his life occurred. It was then he discovered what he thought would unlock all the mysteries of nature, and 26 CARTESIANISM lay a solid foundation for philosophical thought — his famous “Universal Methodic Doubt.” We find an exact statement of this “Universal Me- thodic Doubt” in his own words. He says, “Not that in my doubt I imitated the Sceptics who doubt only that they may doubt, and seek nothing beyond uncer- tainty itself; for, on the contrary, my design was simply to find ground of assurance, and cast aside the loose earth and sand that I may reach the rock or clay.” (Method III.) Hence he intimates that the older Sceptics doubted for the sake of a doubt; Des- cartes doubted that he might ultimately reach cer- tainty. The precise difference, then, between Descartes and the real Sceptics is, that the end or goal of all thinking for the real Sceptics was dowbt; whereas the end or goal of Descartes’ method was certainty. Des- cartes professed to make of his universal doubt a means or road to ultimate certainty. Hence did he call his doubt methodic. In order to establish beyond all cavil, that Descartes really doubted all and every truth -—— the testimony of the senses, of memory, con- sciousness, self-evident first principles or geometrical axioms and even the principle of contradiction, I shall quote his own words: “T will suppose, then, not that Deity, who is sovereignly good and the fountain of truth, but that some malignant demon, who is at once ex- ceedingly potent and deceitful, has employed all his artifice to deceive me; I will suppose the sky, the air, the earth, colors, figures, sounds, and all external things are nothing better than illusions of dreams, by means of which this being has laid snares for my credulity. I will consider myself without hands, eyes, flesh, blood, or any of the senses, and as falsely believing that I am pos- RENE DESCARTES AM f sessed of these; I will continue resolutely fixed in this belief and, if, indeed, by this means, it be not in my power to arrive at the knowledge of truth, I shall at least do what is in my power, namely, guard with settled purpose against giv- ing my assent to what is false, and of being im- posed upon by this deceiver, whatever be his power and artifice.” (Method I.) Descartes brooded over this methodic doubt from the time he left college (1612), when he was only six- teen, for the period of eight or nine years, partly spent in retirement in Paris, partly in the active ser- vice of a soldier’s life, but so far, he had not as yet published to the world the results of his long investi- gations. It was only in 1629, when he was thirty-three years of age, that he retired to Holland, and there published for the first time his philosophical works — the famous Discourse on Method (1687), his Prin- ciples of Philosophy (1641), and his Meditations (1644). These works attracted the attention of the philosophical world, and made of Descartes a storm center of controversy during the rest of his life. His name became European. At the invitation of Queen Christina of Sweden, who admiringly read his works, he went to Stockholm in 1649. The Queen was so pleased with him that she earnestly begged him to remain at her court and give his assistance towards the establishment of an Acad- emy of Sciences. But the delicate frame of Descartes was ill-fitted for the severity of the climate, and a cold, caught in one of his morning visits to Christina, devel- oped into pneumonia, which caused his death in the beginning of the year 1650, at the comparatively early age of fifty-four. Christina wept for him, had him in- terred in the cemetery for foreigners and placed a 28 CARTESIANISM long eulogium upon his tomb. His remains were sub- sequently (1666) carried from Sweden to France and buried with great ceremony in St. Genevieve in Paris. Such, briefly, is the life of Descartes, truly the doubt- ing Thomas of Modern Philosophy. CHAPTER II. DESCARTES EXPOSITION OF HIS PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM 1. Its Destructive Aspect: In an age when the Catholic Church was involved in a life and death struggle with the Protestant Ref- ormation in Europe, it was natural that the intellec- tual leaders of the insurgent religious sects should have hailed with delight and acclamation the brilliant young student of the Jesuits as the “deliverer’’, the “emancipator” and the new “Luther of Philosophy’’, because he deliberately abandoned scholasticism — the traditional philosophy of the Catholic Church, and founded a new philosophical system, which the innovators deemed more in harmony with the princi- ples which they advocated, and which thus inaugu- rated a new era in the history of human thought. What, then, was this new philosophy which Des- cartes gave to the world? In its exposition we shall adhere as faithfully as we possibly can to the mind of Descartes by quotations from his own works, and then offer an estimate and criticism of his system. The philosophical system of Descartes falls natu- rally into two parts, its (1) destructive, and (2) con- structive aspect. THE DESTRUCTIVE PORTION OF DESCARTES’ Sys- TEM. Descartes, with the best of intentions undoubt- edly, set on foot a new method in philosophy which 30 CARTESIANISM would, as he hoped, restore certainty and intellectual peace regarding God, the soul, religion and morality, to the sceptical and restless world of his time, which was thrown into confusion by the radical philosophy of the Renaissance, and by the more recent turmoil of the Reformation. Having “read”, as he himself tells us, “everything that fell into his hands” during the youthful years of his college career, when he was not yet mature enough to discriminate between what was genuine and what was spurious, his mind natur- ally became a prey to doubt and confusion. To get rid of doubt and rebuild on new foundations the entire edifice of philosophy, he imagined that he should break completely with that system of philosophy that swayed the learned world during “the ages of faith’. He despaired of scholasticism. “I saw’’, he says, “that philosophy has been cultivated for many ages by the most distinguished men, and that yet there is not a single matter within its sphere which is not still in dispute, and nothing therefore which is above doubt’’. (Meth. 1.) As a preparatory attitude of mind, then, to the erection of the new edifice of philosophy which he ulti- mately ambitioned to build, he deliberately adopted (“I shall be my own deceiver”) a mental state of posi- tive doubt, not only towards all previous philosoph- ical systems, but also towards all the knowledge which he himself had naturally and spontaneously acquired during his life-time. He swept from his mind every item of knowledge by the merciless broom of doubt. “As for the opinions”, he says, “which up to that time I had embraced, I thought that I could not do better than resolve at once to sweep them wholly away, that I might afterwards be in a position to admit either others more correct, or even perhaps the ITS DESTRUCTIVE ASPECT 31 same, when they had undergone the scrutiny of rea- son. (Meth. II.) All his previous knowledge, he, therefore, doubted, not merely by a negative, but by areal, positive doubt; that is, he supported his doubt by positive reasons. His purpose or aim in knowledge was not, however, that he might remain irrevocably in a state of doubt, but the aim of his universal doubt was ultimately to arrive at incontestable certainty. Hence his mental state of doubt, as he himself asserts, was not “‘scepti- cal’, that is, in order to remain forever in doubt, but “methodic’’, namely, with the view of making doubt a road or pathway along which his mind was to travel to truth and certainty. “Not”, says he, “in this (doubt) I imitated the Sceptics, who doubt only that they may doubt, and seek nothing beyond uncertainty itself; for, on the contrary, my design was simply to find ground of assurance, and cast aside the loose earth and sand, that I may reach the rock or clay”. (Meth. III.) Now, that we understand more in detail the full sweep of Descartes’ doubt, we will briefly enumerate the different spheres of true and certain knowledge, which the ordinary normal person, in mature life, usu- ally accepts, for the most part at least, as reliable, and then examine whether Descartes really and posi- tively doubted his already acquired knowledge in each of these spheres. 7 The ordinary departments of certain knowledge, which the natural workings of the mind spontane- ously deliver to the intelligent man in the street, are as follows: (1) All men have an unconquerable conviction of the truth of immediate judgments based on the re- ports of the external and internal senses. (2) Of first principles or axioms. 32 CARTESIANISM (3) Of conclusions or correct reasonings derived from previously known and certain premises. (4) Of laws which govern phenomena or facts, arrived at by the process of inductive reasoning. (5) Knowledge derived from the testimony of wit- nesses. (6) Of internal, mental facts revealed by con- sciousness. ] (1) That Descartes positively doubted, in the first place, all judgments that are based on the reports of the external senses is manifest from the passage which has been already quoted in Chapter I., p. 26. The fol- lowing passage, likewise, supplies additional reasons for positively doubting the reports both of his internal and external senses: “I observed that the senses sometimes misled us; and it is a part of prudence not to place absolute con- fidence in that by which we have even once been deceived”. (Medit. I.) “But it may be said, perhaps, that although the senses occasionally mislead us, respecting minute ob- jects, and such as are so far removed from us as to be beyond the reach of close observation, there are yet many other of their informations of the truth of which it is manifestly impossible to doubt; as, for example, that I am in this place, seated by the fire, clothed in a winter dressing gown, that I hold in my hand this piece of paper. But how could I deny that I pos- sess these hands and this body, and withal escape be- ing classed with persons in a state of insanity, whose brains are so disordered and clouded by dark, bilious vapors as to cause them pertinaciously to assert that they are monarchs when they are in greatest poverty, or clothed in gold and purple when destitute of any covering; or that their head is made of clay, their ITS DESTRUCTIVE ASPECT 33 body of glass, or that they are gourds? I should cer- tainly be not less insane than they, were I to regulate my procedure according to examples so extravagant’. He forthwith makes answer to this objection, thus :— “Though this be true’, he continues, “I must never- theless here consider that I am a man, and that, con- sequently, I am in the habit of sleeping and repre- senting to myself in dreams those same things, or even sometimes others less probable, which the insane thing are presented to them in their waking moments. How often have a dreamt that I was in these familiar circumstances, that I was dressed and occupied this place by the fire, when I was lying in bed. At the present moment I certainly look upon this paper with eyes open; this head which I now move is not asleep; I extend consciously this hand, and I perceive it; the occurrences of sleep are not so distinct as all this. But I cannot forget that, at other times, I have been deceived in sleep by similar illusions, and atten- tively considering these cases, I perceive so clearly that there exist no certain marks by which the state of waking can ever be distinguished from sleep, that I feel greatly astonished, and in amazement I almost persuade myself that I am now dreaming! Let us suppose then that we are dreaming, and that all those particulars, namely, the opening of the eyes, the mo- tion of the head, the putting forth of the hands, are merely illusions, and that we really possess neither an entire body nor hands such as we see”. (Medit. I.) His argument for really doubting the testimony of his senses is, then, simply this: We are just as certain the objects of our dreams really exist outside of us, though they are illusions, as we are of the existence of sense-objects in our waking moments. Why, then, may not our life be a continuous dream, since, as he says, there are no certain marks to distinguish dream- y 4 Ww If H ; | 34 CARTESIANISM ing from waking? Descartes, furthermore, confirms his doubt of the testimony of his senses by this addi- tional reflection, which anticipates Berkeley, “The belief”, he says, ‘that there is a God Who is all-pow- erful, and Who created me such as I am, has for a long time obtained steady possession of my mind. How, then, do I know that He has not arranged that there should be neither earth, nor sky, nor any ex- tended thing, nor magnitude, nor place, providing at the same time, however, for the rise in me of percep- tions of all these objects and the persuasion that these do not eaist otherwise than as I perceive them?” (Medit. I.) Thus did Descartes bring himself to a real positive doubt of all objects of the senses, and destroy one of the foundations of certain knowledge. (2) In the second place, he now proceeds to bring into positive doubt the first principles or axioms of the ideal order: “Whether I am awake or dreaming, it remains true that two and three make five, and that a square has but four sides; nor does it seem possible that truths so apparent can ever fall under suspicion of falsity or uncertainty’. “Nevertheless, as I sometimes think that others are in error regarding matters of which they believe themselves to possess a perfect knowledge, how do I know that I am not also deceived each time I add together two and three, or number the sides of a square, or form some judgment still more simple, if more simple, indeed, can be imagined?” (Medit. I.) Descartes reached the final climax of positive doubt when he supposed that he might be under the influ- ence of some “malignant demon” who was ever enm- ploying all his artifices to deceive him. He says, “I ITS DESTRUCTIVE ASPECT 35 will suppose, then, not that Deity, who is sovereignly good and the fountain of truth, but some malignant demon, who is at once exceedingly potent and deceit- ful, has employed all his artifice to deceive me; I will suppose the sky, the air, the earth, colors, figures, sounds, and all external things are nothing better than illusions of dreams, by means of which this being has laid snares for my credulity. I will consider myself without hands, eyes, flesh, blood, or any of the senses and as falsely believing that I am possessed of these; I will continue resolutely fixed in this belief, and, if, indeed, by this means, it be not in my power to arrive at the knowledge of truth, I shall at least do what is in my power, namely, guard with settled purpose against giving my assent to what is false, and of being imposed upon by this deceiver, whatever be his power and artifice”. (Method I.) This supposition of a “malignant demon”, which Descartes seemed to have seriously entertained, would relegate to positive doubt the deliverances of all his cognitive faculties. It is difficult to understand, in the face of this suppo- sition, how he could ever trust the two great sources of knowledge, his senses and reason, yea, his con- sciousness. Because it is at least conceivable that all his cognitive faculties are of such a nature that even their right use leads to doubt. Thus did Descartes pluck from his mind every shred of certain knowledge he ever possessed, whether through the exercise of his senses, which seemed to put him in touch with the external world of matter, or through the exercise of his intellect, in cognising first principles, and deliberately plunged himself into the murky darkness of wniversal doubt, and para- lyzed all his faculties. (5) What was Descartes’ attitude towards knowl- 36 CARTESIANISM edge which well-balanced people acknowledge may be acquired through the testimony of witnesses, or through the authority of historical evidence? In answer to this question we may legitimately argue, without appealing at all to Descartes’ writings, that since the testimony of witnesses depends upon the reports of what is perceived by the senses, and since Descartes rejected, or at least doubted the re- ports of his senses, any testimony which witnesses may give is discredited by him, for the simple reason that untrustworthy senses can yield only untrust- worthy testimony. | Let us, however, consult the views of Descartes himself, on what he thought of the reliability of human testimony. On this question he writes: “Even the most faithful histories”, he says, “if they do not wholly misrepresent matters or exaggerate their importance to render the account of them more worthy of perusal, omit, at least, almost always, the meanest and least striking of the attendant circum- stances; hence it happens that the remainder does not represent the truth, and that such as regulate their conduct by examples drawn from this source, are apt to fall into the extravagance of the knight-errants of romance, and to entertain projects that exceed their powers”. (Meth. I.) In this passage Descartes rele- gates history to the region of positive doubt. (3) (4) What of the third and fourth departments of knowledge? Did Descartes really doubt of con- clusions arrived at by his faculty of reason, whether by deduction or induction? In answer to this question there are two phases of the problem which must be kept apart. First, did Descartes positively doubt about all the actual output of all the knowledge about God, man, and the mate- ITS DESTRUCTIVE ASPECT 37 rial world, which had been delivered to mankind by the exercise of reason, up to his time? Secondly, did he positively doubt of the capacity of reason itself to ever deliver to him or anybody else any reliable knowledge? In other words, did he doubt of the very possibility of ever attaining to true and certain knowl- edge? Regarding the first phase of the problem, Descar- tes did positively doubt all the knowledge which both his own and other men’s reasoning had previously delivered to the world. “I am constrained”, he says, “at last to avow that there is nothing of all that I formerly believed to be true, of which it is impossible to doubt, and that not through thoughtlessness or levity, but from cogent and maturely considered rea- sons’. (Meth. I.) With regard to the second phase of the problem, it is obvious that the above expression of wniversal posi- tive doubt implicitly contains, of course, a positive doubt regarding any and every particular item of knowledge; and since the capacity of reason to ac- quire truth and certainty is an item of knowledge, it follows that Descartes’ expressed universal doubt in- volves even this item. Hence, he doubted the capacity of reason to acquire any certain knowledge. On the other hand, there are numerous passages in his writings which express the utmost confidence in the trustworthiness of his reason. Indeed, Descartes so exaggerated the power of reason that he made of it a fetish. For instance, he says: “As for the opinions which up to that time I had embraced, I thought that I could not do better than resolve at once to sweep them wholly away, that I might afterwards be in a position to admit either others more correct, or even perhaps the same, when they had undergone the scrutiny of reason”. (Meth. II.) 38 CARTESIANISM There is in this passage an implied trust in the ability of his reason. How could he admit back again, by a process of scrutinizing them by his reason, opin- ions which he rejected as doubtful, if he did not trust the capacity of his reason to judge infallibly of their truth? Again he writes: “I further concluded that it is almost impossible that our judgments can be so cor- rect or solid as they would have been, had our reason been mature from the moment of our birth, and had we been guided by it alone’. (Meth. II.) Here he certainly implies that judgments arrived at by ma- ture reason are more correct and solid than those that satisfy immature reason. Does not this carry with it an implication of trust in mature reason? In another passage he says: “I could, however, select from the crowd no one whose opinions seemed worthy of preference, and thus I found myself con- strained, as it were, to use my own reason in the con- duct of my life’. (Medit. I1.) He distrusts, in this passage, opinions based on the reason of all other people, but pins his trust to his own individual reason. Therefore, we must conclude that Descartes trusted his own individual reason to attain truth. Now, if we compare Descartes’ profession of posi- tive doubt with regard to all the knowledge he and other men previously acquired with the above quota- tions, wherein Descartes seems to have the utmost confidence in the capacity of his reason, we arrive at this peculiar position of Descartes regarding the trustworthiness of his reason. His all inclusive wni- versal doubt (cf. Med. I. above) about all previous knowledge would lead to the conclusion that his rea- son never previously in his life functioned correctly, while his own assertions, in the quotations we have presented, would lead one to believe that he still had ITS DESTRUCTIVE ASPECT 39 confidence, that, though reason heretofore in his ex- perience delivered only doubtful conclusions, yet it still has the power in the future to deliver true and certain conclusions. In a word, he doubted all con- . clusions of his own and other men’s reason in the world up to this time; but still trusted the inherent power of his own faculty of reason to function aright under more favorable circumstances. What Descar- tes really and explicitly doubted of, then, was the re- sults of reasoning, not the capability of reason to at- tain certainty and truth. But if this was Descartes’ mind concerning reason, his position was illogical and false. In the first place, if the functioning of his own and other men’s reasoning had brought forth, during the past, doubtful conclusions alone, such a strange result would argue inherent vitiation of the faculty of reason itself. A tree is known by its fruit. If rea- son throughout all time before Descartes bore only doubt, we must conclude that it was a faculty whose intrinsic nature it is to doubt. If reason, then, is in- trinsically a faculty of doubt, Descartes contradicts what seems to be his trust in the capacity of reason to bring forth certainty under any circumstances. Furthermore, unless Descartes admitted the truth and certainty of axiomatic principles, such as the principle of contradiction, he could never reason at all. For the truth and certainty of the principle of contradiction must be supposed in every act of rea- soning. If this principle is doubted, reason cannot function aright; and a faculty or power that cannot function is not a power at all. It is nullified, annihi- lated as a power. When, therefore, Descartes really doubted the principle of contradiction, and thus seri- ously thought that the same identical judgment could be true and not true at the same time and under the same respect, he should have ceased from, and stopped 40 CARTESIANISM short of ever exercising his reason. For any exercise of reason is an impossibility until the principle of con- tradiction is implicitly at least admitted. In really doubting, then, the principle of contradiction, Des- cartes paralyzed his reasoning function, and were he logical, he should have suspended all exercise of rea- soning. That Descartes really doubted the principle of contradiction is manifest from the quotation cited on page 26. Our judgment of Descartes, then, with regard to his position on reasoning is, that though he did not in practice doubt the ability of his reason to arrive at truth and certainty, he should have logically doubted it, folded his arms, if he had any, and stare forever, through the sightless eyes of his reason, into the per- petual darkness of nescience. So far our examination of Descartes’ doubt has brought forth these results: he really doubted the reports of his senses, testifying to the existence of his own body and the external world; secondly, he doubted of the first self-evident principles of knowl- edge, and ought to have doubted, were he logical, the capacity of his reason to reach truth and certainty. Thus has Descartes blotted out from all the find- ings of sense, from all the findings of reason, both deductive and inductive, from all the testimony of witnesses, every mark of certainty. Every beam of truth and certainty that emanates for ordinary peo- ple, from the powers of sense, reason and witnesses, is shorn clear away. (6) One lone department yet remains intact out of the wreck of Descartes’ previously acquired edifice of knowledge. This department is his own conscious- ness. By consciousness is meant that immediate knowledge which we have of our own thoughts and ITS DESTRUCTIVE ASPECT Al states of mind; in general, of all present operations of the mind. We not only feel, but we know that we feel; we not only act, but we know that we act; we not only think, but we know that we think, and that the feeling, knowing, thinking and acting are my own. One characteristic of consciousness must be empha- sized. Inthe first place, it is not the thought or the feel- ing or the act or the purpose itself that is conscious of itself, but it is I, the Ego, that is conscious of my thought or feeling or act or purpose, or of any other present subjective experience. It is “I”, therefore, who is conscious of the present mental states that are murmuring through me. It is not “the stream of con- sciousness” that is conscious of itself. Hence, to talk of a stream of consciousness wherein the stream is the conscious agent, and not I myself, as William James did, is an absurdity because an impossibility. Much less is it true to say, as the same author taught, that a subsequent thought or state of mind could be conscious of a thought or mental state that just pre- ceded it. This latter doctrine was also invented by William James, in order to destroy the ever-abiding existence, in the midst of change, of our own substan- tial personality, and thus pave the way for the fash- ionable doctrines of Phenomenal Idealism, which is expressed by the charming phrase of a “stream of consciousness’. Phenomenal Idealism would have us believe that nothing exists but states of consciousness without any permanently existing person or “Ego” who is conscious of them, and who brings into unity all our disparate internal experience. Without this uni- fying, substantial “Ego”, our conscious experiences would be like “so many beads without a string”’. Now we have at last arrived at the interesting and critical point of Descartes’ methodic doubt. The 42 CARTESIANISM forces of doubt, of real positive doubt, have, like an invading army, swarmed across the frontiers of knowledge. Those ruthless hosts have so far captured and laid waste the fairest provinces of human knowl- edge. Fortresses of truth and certainty that were for centuries deemed impregnable — the senses, first prin- ciples, reason and the testimony of witnesses — have been shattered, and the flag of doubt flung above them. One, and one only, strategic position yet blocks the way of the onward sweep of the triumphant hordes of doubt. That one strong position are the objects of consciousness. Will the retreating armies of knowledge and truth rally in their might around the stronghold of consciousness and hurl back the doubting invaders, and repeat for consciousness the story of a Marathon or a Salamis, a Fontenoy or a Marne? The critical moment has arrived. The ad- vanced armies of doubt are already opening their attack upon the outer fortresses of consciousness. Should doubt be victorious over consciousness — the last hope of knowledge, so far as Descartes is con- cerned, truth and certainty will be no more. It was once said that “Freedom shrieked as Kosioski fell’’. Truly would knowledge shriek should consciousness fail. Confusion and despair would ever more domi- nate the human mind. On the other hand, if the for- tress of consciousness can repel doubt, and the truth and certainty of what it reveals be victoriously de- fended, then is it Descartes’ hope to make of his con- sciousness the basis of his operations, roll back, step by step, the doubting invaders, and set up once more the benign sovereignty of the queen of truth and certainty, over all those fair provinces which had yielded to doubt only a temporary sway. This was to be Descartes’ plan of campaign as set forth in his ““Methodic Doubt”. We do not now say whether that ITS DESTRUCTIVE ASPECT 43 plan was justifiable or not. But it was Descartes’ plan. It was a curious application of “She Stoops to Conquer”. Yes, truth stooped to doubt that she might finally vanquish doubt upon the ramparts of Con- sciousness. Let us describe the conflict in Descartes’ own words: “But how do I know that there is not something different altogether from the objects I have enumerated, of which it is impossible to enter- tain the slightest doubt? Is there not a God, or some being, by whatever name I may designate Him, who causes those thoughts to arise in my mind? But why suppose such a being, for it may be I myself am capa- ble of producing them? (Here he includes in his doubt the very existence of bodies and of God.) Am I, then, at least, not something? But I before denied that I possess senses or a body; I hesitate, however, for what follows from that. Am I so dependent upon the body and the senses, that without these I cannot exist? But I had the persuasion that there was abso- lutely nothing in the world, that there was no sky and no earth, neither minds nor bodies. Was I not, there- fore, at the same time, persuaded I did not exist? Far from it; I assuredly existed, since I was persuaded. But there is, I know not what being, who is possessed at once of the highest power and the deepest cunning (the malignant demon) who is constantly employing all his ingenuity in deceiving me. (Notice how fiercely he is fighting the battle of consciousness against doubt.) Doubtless, then, I exist, since I am deceived, and let him deceive me as he may, he can never bring it about that I am nothing. So that it must, in fine, be maintained, all things being maturely and care- fully considered, that this proposition, ‘I am, I exist’, is necessarily true each time it is expressed by me, or conceived in my mind”. (Method II.) We shall afterwards examine whether Descartes was logical in 44, CARTESIANISM thus absolutely trusting the testimony of conscious- ness. That is, was Descartes consistent, in the face of other principles, in trusting his consciousness, while he persistently distrusted all his other cognitive fac- ulties? It is hard to understand why it is reasonable to reject the normal testimony of all other natural faculties of knowledge, and accord to consciousness, which is on the same plain of nature as the other facul- ties, an absolute trust. If there “is a repugnance in conceiving that what thinks does not exist at the very time when it thinks”, a “repugnance’’, indeed, which is admitted by all, so also is there a repugnance in thinking that it is doubtful “whether two and three make five’, and yet Descartes positively doubted of the latter. Does it not seem that he should, were he consistent, also have doubted the former? We fear that Descartes sacrificed consistency upon the altar of his universal positive doubt. Here is another account of the conflict in Descartes’ words: , “While we thus reject all of which we can enter- tain the smallest doubt, and even imagine that it is false, we easily, indeed, suppose that there is: neither God, nor sky, nor bodies, and that we ourselves have neither hands nor feet, nor, finally, a body, but we can- not in the same way suppose that we are not, while-we doubt of the truth of those things; for there is a re- pugnance in conceiving that what thinks does not exist at the very time when it thinks. Accordingly, the knowledge, “I think, therefore, I exist” (Cogito, ergo sum), is the first and most important certain princi- ple that occurs to me, who philosophizes orderly”. (Princip. VII.) Descartes has, to his own satisfaction, at least, fought and won. The long career of dreary doubt is at an end. One truth certainly is established, which ITS DESTRUCTIVE ASPECT 45 no doubt can shake, no scepticism can shatter, “I doubt (I think), therefore, I exist’. This truth, which he confidently thought that consciousness had revealed to him, Descartes has rescued from the slough of doubt; he has placed it as the foundation- stone of his philosophy. It is a truth revealed to him by his own consciousness. Descartes was not the first to discover and recog- nize, that the incontestable truth of the great fact, “I exist’’, is established by my consciousness that I think. Aristotle and St. Augustine, centuries before, recognized the truth of the same fact. But to Des- cartes belongs the undying merit of emphasizing and expressing admirably and tersely this great principle and fact, “Cogito, ergo sum’. Cuapter ITI. EXPOSITION OF HIS PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM II. Its Constructive Aspect: We now understand how it came to pass that Des- cartes professed to have emerged from the dark night of doubt into the light of certainty. He doubted posi- tively, or thought he could so doubt, all objective realities in the existing order of things which ordinary men accept as certainties. The testimony of his own inner consciousness, how- ever, to the incontestible fact that he doubted, defied every effort of his to doubt. He could not, even if he would, doubt that he doubted. But to doubt, he ar- gued, is to think. Now, “I think” that is, “I doubt” necessarily involves that the “doubter”, that is, the “thinker”, exists. Because a mere nothing could not doubt or think. Therefore, am I something outside of nothing? This single item of knowledge, “cogito, ergo sum’, “I think, therefore, I exist’, and this alone, Descartes saved from the wreck of doubt. The dawn-light of this famous principle dispelled the darkness of his universal doubt. Descartes thus de- scribes the coming of light: “Whilst I wished that all was false, it was abso- lutely necessary that I who thus thought, should be somewhat, and I observed the truth, ‘I think, hence I exist’ was so certain and of such evidence that no ground of doubt, however extravagant, could be al- leged by the sceptics capable of shaking it.” (Meth. 48 CARTESIANISM IV.) That we know for certain the truth of our own existence, as the first fact in knowledge is incontesta- ble. All sane philosophers admit it. It may be a subject of wonder for minds not accus- tomed to philosophical problems to think that it took Descartes twenty years to establish his own existence. But philosophy has always to do with that which is ultimate and fundamental both in reality (metaphys- ics) and knowledge (epistemology). Having at last, then, dug down through “earth and sand’, as he expressed it, to what he deemed to be the foundation principle of all philosophy, Descartes con- fidently proceeds to evolve from this principle, step by step, the whole edifice of his system. Descartes, so characteristically French, was obsessed by a pas- sion for logical system and mathematical precision. This tendency was heightened by his mathematical bent of mind. He was a profound mathematician. Just, then, as a geometrician gradually builds up, by the aid of a few axiomatic principles, all the propo- sitions implicit in the nature of the ordinary figures of quantity, so it was Descartes’ hope to find his whole system of philosophy implicitly contained in his first principle. It was, then, his ambition, after the man- ner of the mathematicians, to draw out logically those implications of that principle by processes of a priori reasoning, and thus evolve a complete system of phil- osophy from a single principle, as nature evolves a. massive tree from a single, tiny seed. Such an achieve- ment is in itself an impossibility. Because sciences, philosophy included, are based upon independent facts of experience revealed to us by different cognitive fac- ulties, facts which cannot be derived one from the other by a process of @ priori reasoning. Still Des- cartes regarded the method of mathematics as the type of the method of philosophy. ITS CONSTRUCTIVE ASPECT 49 We shall, however, give an exposition of Descartes’ attempt to accomplish this feat, and subject each section, as well as the whole of his system, to rational criticism, with the view of rejecting what is opposed to sound reason, and mayhap recommending for your instruction what may be worthy of approval. Of course, Descartes, in the elaboration of his sys- tem, endeavored to reconstruct, on a new plan, every department of philosophical science. He inaugurated, therefore, a new departure in Epistemology, in Psy- chology, in Ontology, in Cosmology, and in Natural Theology. Descartes, in his philosophical writings, did not, how- ever, divide the expositions of his system into each of those departments into which the science of philoso- phy is set forth in modern treatises. We shall, there- fore, set forth before your intellectual vision the main outlines of his philosophical edifice, and viewing it as a whole, we can then study how radically he has de- parted from the traditional Epistemology, Psychol- ogy, Ontology, Cosmology and Natural Theology that has come down to us embodied in the philosophy of the great medieval thinkers. The following, then, is a summary of his complete system: Descartes, as you may have observed, pro- fessed to have discovered his first true and certain item of knowledge by looking within himself. He ob= served that his own conscious state of doubt could not by an effort be doubted. And because he was abso- lutely certain that he doubted, he immediately arrived at the certain truth of his own existence, because doubt necessarily implies the existence of a doubter. Thus it was, that by knowing himself, he came for the first time in touch with objective reality. This first truth, “I think, therefore, I exist’, he set down as the foundation-stone of his system. 50 CARTESIANISM On the other hand, when he looked out of himself through his senses, his intellect, or his reason, or when he consulted the testimony of witnesses, he despair- ingly confessed and professed that he could not know with certainty any objective reality outside and inde- pendent of himself. He positively doubted the ex- istence of all reality outside of himself. Real objects outside of himself seemed, he confessed, to exist. Of their seeming existence he was certain. But his cer- tainty stopped short with the mere “seeming”. “At all events, it is certain’, he says, “that I seem to see light, (I seem to) hear noise, and (I seem to) feel heat; this cannot be false, and this is what in me is properly called perceiving (sentire)”. . . . The best he can be certain of, then, is the seeming existence of objects outside of him, not the real existence of ob- jects in themselves. Descartes himself, at this stage in the construction of his system, stood alone in the universe as the only reality of which he was certain. Descartes, studying the character of the judgment, “T think, therefore, I exist”, asked himself, why is it that this truth is to me most certain? Because, he asserted, it is so clear and distinct. This characteristic of his own existence he then generalized and set up as the criterion, standard or test of all truth. There- fore, he argued, whatever idea is clear and distinct to me is true and certain. By the aid of this criterion he proceeded to advance his knowledge beyond that of his own existence, to- wards the acquisition of other truths which he called eternal, such as (a) “from nothing, nothing can come”, (b) “it is impossible for the same thing to be and not to be, at the same time, (c) “a cause ought at least to contain as much perfection as is contained in its ef- fect”, etc. Then, by the aid of the same criterion, he ITS CONSTRUCTIVE ASPECT 51 advanced to the knowledge of God’s existence, and lastly to the existence of external, material world. He proceeds thus: (1) Amongst the various ideas which I find within myself, there is the idea of God, as a Being of infinite perfection. Such an idea, he argues, could not come from myself, since I am an imperfect being and therefore finite. The cause, then, of this idea of an infinitely perfect God that is within me cannot come from myself. It must come from a being of infinite perfection, namely, God Himeelf, therefore God exists. (2) Furthermore, Descartes maintained that, the idea of God, being infinite, con- tains all perfections. But “existence” is a perfection. Therefore God exists. Having now arrived to his own satisfaction, at least, at the knowledge of God’s existence, who is a Being that is all-truthful and wise because perfect, he then argues from the truth of an all-true and wise God, to the certainty of the existence of the external, material world. Because, he says, we clearly and distinctly perceive matter distinct from our Ego and from God extended in three dimensions— length, breadth and depth. God, then, would be our deceiver, if notwith- standing our clear and distinct ideas of material things, if the external, material world did not really exist. But God, who is infinitely true and wise, could not deceive me. Therefore, the external world exists. Thus did Descartes win back from his original doubt the certainty, not only the certainty of his own exis- tence, and of the eternal truths mentioned above, but also of the existence of the material world. But our knowledge must not rest here. He has es- tablished his own existence, the existence of God, and that of the material world, but he does not yet know either his own essence or that of bodies outside of him. This question Descartes was obliged to answer, be- 52 CARTESIANISM cause it is the part of philosophy to know the essences of things. Now, if we are to understand Descartes, we must carefully bear in mind, in the first place, that, in his system, the direct and immediate objects, which his cognitive faculties, his senses as well as his intellect become directly and immediately aware of in cogni- tion, are not objects that exist outside of himself, but his ideas within himself, something, therefore, subjec- tive and not objective. In other words, our ideas are the direct objects that immediately terminate all our first cognitions. And in the second place, that it is only when those ideas are clear and distinct, do the objects, which they seem to represent, truly and cer- tainly exist outside of us. Because, as he said, God placed in us an irresistible conviction that objects out- side of us, of which we have clear and distinct ideas, exist, and an all-truthful and wise God could not deceive us. Descartes then distinguishes three kinds of clear and distinct ideas within him, namely, the idea of swb- stance, the idea of attribute and the idea of mode or accident. The idea of “substance” he defines as the idea of “‘that which so exists that it is in need of noth- ing else for its existence”. An idea of a “mode or accident” he defines as “that which does not exist in itself, but in a substance, but which can be present or absent without destroying the idea of the substance’. An “attribute” he defines as “that without which the idea of substance, itself, would cease to exist’’. Hence a “mode or accident” may cease to exist without the idea of substance, in which it adheres, ceasing to exist. But if an “attribute” ceased to exist, then, the idea of the substance, of which it is an attribute, could not exist at all. The idea of “attribute” to the mind of Descartes enters into the very essence of the idea of ITS CONSTRUCTIVE ASPECT 53 “substance”, the idea of a “mode or accident” does not. Furnished, then, with those three clear and distinct ideas, he proceeds to establish the essence of body and of own Ego or “TIT”. Descartes now declares that bodies manifest them- selves to us by the qualities of figure, shape,. size, mo- tion, color, etc. But all those qualities may change and any special figure, shape, size, motion or color, etc., may cease to exist without destroying the idea of a body. They are merely “modes or accidents” of body. They come and go. But without extension, I cannot conceive body at all. Therefore, extension is a necessary and essential quality or “attribute” of corporeal substance. And because such an attribute manifests the essence of body, therefore Descartes maintained that the essence of a body consists in ea- tension alone. Since, then, a body is extension and only extension, a vacuum cannot exist, because a vacuum would be extension without a body. But extension is identical with a body, hence wherever extension is conceived, there is body. Consequently, since he con- ceived extension to be indefinite, if not infinite, so is matter indefinite, if not infinite, and can be infinitely divided. All changes in matter are only the result of local motion. Whence comes this motion? Motion cannot originate in matter, since matter is not extension and extension does not imply motion. In fact, he taught that matter was entirely inert and void of all activity. Therefore motion must have its origin from a source distinct from matter. Descartes, therefore, accounts for motion by saying that God endowed matter in the beginning with a certain quantity of motion. This original quantity of motion, imparted to matter in the beginning by God, is immutable. All bodies, 54 CARTESIANISM. therefore, are merely extension; that is, length, breadth and depth in motion, like a machine. Hence comes the famous theory of Descartes regarding matter, which is known as Mechanism. All inorganic bodies, as well as plants, animals and the body of man are only machines (automatons) just like our clocks and watches,— merely matter endowed with motion. All the motions of the animals, which we are wont to interpret as the signs of life, even their cries and bellowings, their digestion and apparent sensations do not spring from any vital principle, but are merely automatic motions of their bodily machines. ‘““Give me matter and the laws of motion”, says Descartes, “and I build a universe exactly like the one that we behold, with skies, stars, sun, and earth, and on the earth minerals, plants and ani- _ mals, in short, everything that experience introduces to us, except the rational soul of man”. Descartes does not admit any vital principles or soul in animals, because, as we shall afterwards see, the essence of soul, according to him, consists of thought, and hence every soul is a “thinking thing’, immaterial and immortal, and endowed with free-will. But Descartes could not admit that animals are immortal, which he would be obliged to admit, did he admit they possessed a living principle, called soul. Let us now examine what Descartes considered the essence of his own “Ego” or I, which he established as existing, and placed as the basic truth and certainty of his philosophy. en Descartes, to his own satisfaction, had estab- lished, beyond any shadow of doubt, his own existence and called himself as we call ourselves, “I” or “Ego”, his next step was to investigate what this “I’’, this “Ego” is, what constitutes it, what is its nature, in a word, “What am I?” When I say “I”, do I mean ITS CONSTRUCTIVE ASPECT 55 my soul alone, or my body alone, or a composite being made up of the intimate union of both body and soul”? This question Descartes presumes to answer by the following course of reasoning: “In the next place”, he says, “I certainly exam- ined what I was and as I observed that I could sup- pose I had no body (he had not at this stage of his system established the existence of matter or body) and that there was no material world or any place that I might be; but that I could not, therefore, sup- ~ pose that I was not; and that, on the contrary, from the very circumstance that I thought to doubt of the truth of other things, it most clearly and certainly fol- lowed that I was; while, on the other hand, if I had only ceased to think, although other objects which I had ever imagined, had been in reality existent, I would have not reason to believe that I eaisted; I thence concluded that I was a substance whose whole essence or nature consists only in thinking, and which, that it may exist, has need of no place, nor is depen- dent on any material thing, so that ‘I’, that is to say the mind by which I am what I am, is plainly distinct from the body”. (Meth. IV.) This is a remarkable passage. It contains the ker- nel of Descartes’ psychology. It professes to answer the question, “What am I?”. That you may vividly grasp this Cartesian answer to the formidable ques- tion, “What am I?”, permit me to cull from this pas- sage its salient phrases: He says: “I, that is to say, the mind”. In this phrase he identifies “I”, “Ego”, with the mind, that is, with my soul or spirit. Hence it is by my soul alone I am what I am. The soul, then, the soul alone, is the man. The body is only an appendage of the real man, something distinct and extrinsic to the real “me” 56 CARTESIANISM or “I” or “Ego”. To repeat once more Descartes’ own words: “I, that is to say the mind by which I am what I am, is plainly distinct from the body”. (Ibid.) The body, therefore, does not enter at all as a constituent factor into my being as a person, which each one gives expression to by the pronoun “I” or “Ego”. Were we all, then, devoted followers of the Cartesian doctrine, the meaning of the personal pro- noun “I” or “Ego” would be strictly limited and con- fined to each one’s soul or spirit or mind alone, to the complete exclusion of the body. Even if I had no body I would still be “I’’, because I would still be a soul. Hence, the disembodied souls of the dead are still, according to Descartes, complete substances. They could still give expression to their consciousness and say, in their own way, “I am I’. This account of what I am, is false, but why it is false, future criti- cism will show. Yet it may be justly said of Des- cartes, that he had nobly vindicated, in his own way, the existence of the soul as more certain than the ex- istence of the body, though in doing so, he irreparably destroyed the true and obvious nature of man or “Ego” by excluding the body as an essentially con- stituent element of a human being. Man is not a spirit or soul alone (the Spiritualistic theory) nor a body alone (the Materialistic theory) nor is man a combination of two complete substances, body and soul extrinsically accompanying each other (the ex- aggerated dualism of Descartes), but man, “Ego”, is composed of two incomplete substances, body and soul, intrinsically united so as to form a single com- posite substance (the Aristotelian and Scholastic doctrine). “What am I?” is one of the most vital questions for humanity. Men and women of all ages have been asking it. They are asking it wistfully to-day. ITS CONSTRUCTIVE ASPECT 57 Reviewing, at a glance, the history of modern thought, six chief answers have been given by differ- ent schools of philosophy to this fearful question: (1) In the first place, the most degraded answer is: “I am a body, matter alone”. I am one and the same stuff as the rugged mountain, the dust I tread upon, the flowers that bloom and fade. All my thoughts, my high ideals and aspirations, are at best only secretions of matter like honey distilled in the body of the bee. This is the answer of Materialists. They are with us to-day. They walk our streets; their materialism is at the basis of their moral, social, polit- ical and economic creeds. They are terribly in earnest to propagate their doctrine; they teach it to their chil- dren. The Socialism of Marx and Engels of Ger- many, now familiar throughout Europe, as well as in our own country, and the Bolshevism of Bakunin of Russia, are the nefarious growth of the materialistic answer which these new political and economic sys- tems give to the question, “What am I?” These mate- rialists are frankly atheistic, haters of God, immor- tality and all religion. Hear the words of Bakunin, the high-priest of Russian Bolshevism: ‘God is a corrosive poison which destroys and decomposes life, falsifies and kills it. Christianity is the impoverish- ment and the annihilation of humanity for the benefit of divinity”. (Cath. World, Dec. 1919.) Radical Evolutionists, as displayed in the exhibitions in our Museum of Natural History in this city, teach Mate- rialism. Descartes was not such as these. 2) The next answer to the question, “What am I?”, though not explicitly, is yet implicitly just as de- grading. It is the answer of English Agnosticism and the disciples of Huxley, Herbert Spencer, etc. The Agnostic asks, “What am I?’, and with an air of supercilious scepticism, answers, ‘““We do not know”, 58 CARTESIANISM This answer signifies, not merely temporary ignor- ance, which they may hope to surmount, but a know- nothingness which involves the positive and arrogant assertion, that it is beyond the power of the human mind to know “what I am”. And just because the ponderous intelligence of Protestant England has been groaning now for three hundred years, and has at last brought forth the mouse of Agnosticism, by proclaiming that it cannot know what man is or what God is, a number of would-be intellectuals, who have already lost their knowledge of, and faith in, God, worship, in order to find some philosophical ground for their irresponsibility, the tiny, dark mouse of Agnosticism, and proclaim to the world that they have concluded that God and man are unknowable, because whatever is supersensible is unknowable. We, over whom the Agnostics of course assume a lofty air of superiority, must adopt, forsooth, the same degrading fashion of know-nothingism. Hence, Ag- nosticism would, if it could, dragoon us all into utter ignorance, not only of what God is, but of what we ourselves are. No wonder, then, that the addicts of this philosophy have opened up a wide gap in the minds of men, through which every fantastic theory of morality, politics, and economics may rush in with impunity. Agnosticism is only a polite expression of stark atheism. Woe to the world if Atheistic or Ag- nostic governments dominate the nations: To know God and Him Whom He has sent — Christ, that is, Catholic Christianity, is the soul of a nation, and when that soul departs from it, then is the death of that nation at hand. Descartes, then, as we have seen, was not a material- ist; neither was he an agnostic. Indeed, his philoso- phy helped to stem the tide of materialism that swept ITS CONSTRUCTIVE ASPECT 59 over the world in the eighteenth and beginning of the nineteenth centuries. (3) The third answer to the vital question, ““What am I?’ has been given by the Spiritualistic Idealists. Their answer is the extreme opposite of the Material- ists. While the Materialists assert, “I am a body, matter alone’, the Idealists, or pure Spiritualists, advance the theory that “I am a soul, a pure spirit alone, plus its own conscious states or subjective mod- ifications. Since Idealists deny outright, or pretend, at least, that we cannot know matter, that is the only answer they give, and can give, to the question ““What am I?’ Whether Idealists, numerous as they profess to be, are sincere in giving this answer, we know not. There seemed to be only one sincere Idealist or Spir- itualist in the history of modern thought, the famous Irishman, Bishop Berkeley, Protestant Bishop of Cloyne, County Cork, who lived in the eighteenth century, about whose interesting character and career we shall have something to say later on. Descartes was not a pure Spiritualist. Though he taught “the Ego was soul or spirit alone”, he yet admitted the existence of our body as a companion at least insep- arable from the soul in this life. The curative practices and beliefs of the well-known devotees of Christian Science, or Eddyism, are based upon the theory of Spiritualistic Idealism. They answer “What am I?’ by affirming we are all pure spirits and ideas. Diseases are only zdeas of human spirits. Hence, if they can rid you of the idea that you are sick, by the force of natural suggestion or persuasion, they consequently rid you of the disease. Perhaps if many of the silly creatures who are de- ceived by Christian Science knew the foundation upon which it rests, the remnant left them of their 60 CARTESIANISM common sense might deter them from embracing this modern superstition. (4) There is a fourth answer to the riddle, “What am I?” It is the solution of the Pantheists, who, as is obvious, may be either Idealistic or Materialistic. All Pantheists agree in this, that they teach, there is only one substance in all eaistence, and this single sub- stance they call God. To Pantheism, then, “I” or “vou” can have no individual, separate existence out- side this divine substance. It answers the question, “What am I?’, by asserting that we are all only phases or aspects of the Pantheistic divinity. “You” and “I” are but so many tiny wavelets on the great ocean of substance; we roll our little course, and sink to rise no more. Pantheism was taught in Harvard during the last generation by the late Professor Royce. Emerson was professedly Pantheistic. Many of the professors of our large universities to-day sub- scribe to this system. It is one of the last develop- ments of the Reformation. Professor Haldane of England has lately published a book in defense of Pantheism. Pantheism, under the name of Theosophy, which is of Eastern origin, has immigrated into San Fran- cisco, and into our other large cities, and is there prev- alent at present among some of the would-be intellec- tuals. Any system of philosophy that does not neces- sitate the existence of a personal God outside and in- dependent of the world as the supreme Author and Creator of all things, will inevitably lead to Panthe- ism. Descartes was not a Pantheist, though, as we shall see later on, his principles, in the philosophy of Spinoza, led to that withering doctrine. (5) The fifth curious answer to the question, “What am I?’, is that given by the Phenomenal Idealists. Since Phenomenal Idealists assert that the only ob- ITS CONSTRUCTIVE ASPECT 61 jects of knowledge that we can become aware of are subjective experiences alone, namely, subjective sen- sations, feelings, emotions, thoughts, mental states, of all sorts; that the substantial subject of those men- tal phenomena are unknowable, and that all objects outside and independent of subjective states are im- _ pervious to knowledge, they deny, therefore, the real- ity of all substances, both material and spiritual. The sphere of knowledge is thus strictly confined to a series of conscious phenomena. If, then, Phenomenal Idealists are asked, “What am I?”, they will prompt- ly answer: “a stream of consciousness and nothing more’. Subjective states follow one another like “so many beads without a string”. Man or “Ego” is a stream of sensations or feelings without anybody to feel them, a stream of thoughts without a thinker to think them. Man—“Ego’,, is a kind of unsubstan- tial, evanescent mist of ghostly conscious states apart from anybody who is conscious of them, “a phantas- magoria”’, as Huxley says, “on the back-ground of nothingness”. Descartes was nota Phenomenal Ideal- ist. He admitted a substantial soul or spirit. (6) The Scholastic doctrine, which we have stated above, is simply this: The soul is the form of the body. Man, therefore, is not a dual combination of two complete and companion substances, body and soul, as Descartes taught, but man consists of the sub- stantial union of two incomplete substances, body and soul, so as to form a single compound substance. We shall now resume the account of Descartes’ system. Descartes employed all his ingenuity to explain the union of soul and body, but his explanation is unsat- isfactory. He taught that the soul is united to the body in the “pineal gland”, where very refined par- ticles of blood, which he called “animal spirits”, act upon the soul, and the soul in turn reacts upon the 62 CARTESIANISM animal spirits, and the motion thus caused in the “ani- mal spirits” moves the nerves and muscles. In this theory a union is set up not between substances, but between the actions of substances after the manner of two wheels of a machine. A striking peculiarity of Descartes’ psychology is that sensations and passion are experiences resident in the soul alone. Nevertheless, Descartes maintains they exist in the soul only so long as it is united to the body. He admitted, of course, the spirituality and immortality of the soul, and its endowment of free-will. Finally, the following are the salient features of Descartes’ theory of knowledge: He distinguished three classes of ideas: (1) innate, (2) adventitious and (8) factitious. All universal and necessary ideas, as being, substance, cause, axioms, God, etc., in fact, all ideas, through which we exercise our intelligent life, are innate. At first, Descartes taught that those innate ideas were “certain realities” impressed upon our souls by God. Later on, under the stress of controversy, he was driven to admit that those ideas were only poten- tially innate, that is, the soul had the power of form- ing them by its own native activity. It is through the medium of those innate ideas we know all things in- tellectually, because God, Who is the author of all things, both bodies and souls, endowed “‘us with those ideas to which realities correspond”. This undue em- phasis upon purely intellectual knowledge to the neglect of knowledge derived from sense-experiences, which is, according to Descartes, in no way a deter- mining cause in the formation of our intellectual ideas, is the reason why, in history, Descartes’ theory of knowledge is called “ewaggerated intellectualism”’. The only part which, according to Descartes, sense- ITS CONSTRUCTIVE ASPECT 63 experience plays in arousing in the mind intellectual ideas is the part of an occasional cause. Knowledge becomes perfect in judgment, by which we predicate ideas of objects. But in order that we may predicate an idea of an object, an assent of the mind is required. Assent, however, Descartes makes an act of the will, not of the intellect. Hence, judgment is not an act of intellect, but of will. All error, therefore, proceeds from the will alone. Though man’s will ought to fol- low his intellect in order that his assents may be true, yet in God, Descartes strangely taught, that divine will decided what is true. Hence, if God should will the contrary or contradictory of what is now true, that contrary or contradictory would be true. Adventitious ideas are those which the mind gath- ers from sense-experience. They reveal to us only singular facts and the relations of bodies to ourselves, while factitious ideas, or ideas which are constructed by ourselves, are combinations formed either from in- nate, adventitious ideas or from both by our own vol- untary fancy. It cannot be too often emphasized that, in the theory of knowledge set forth by Descartes, the direct and immediate object both of intellect and sense is not reality as it is in itself apart from, and indepen- dent of, the idea of it, but rather ideas themselves. This theory, in the course of time, developed into Idealism, CuaAprtTer IV. DESCARTES CRITICAL EXAMINATION OTH the destructive and constructive exposi- . tion of Descartes’ system, as you may have noticed, have set forth and popularized a cer- tain number of fundamental principles that have pro- foundly influenced and even revolutionized philoso- phy in every department from Descartes’ time to the present day. This revolution was, of course, directed immediately against that philosophy which the intel- lectual leaders of the Catholic Church had built up during the Middle Ages. If the principles of Des- cartes are philosophically sound and true, then Scho- lasticism as a system is false. It will be interesting, then, to submit the fundamental principles of Des- cartes’ philosophy to a critical examination of reason, and arrive at a just estimate of their validity. The philosophical world has yet to prove, no matter how they may despise it, that the “philosophia perennis” of Scholasticism is substantially either antiquated or false. By bringing Descartes’ principles into conflict with the corresponding principles of Scholasticism, we hope to make manifest the unreasonableness of the former and the sound rationality of the latter. If we wish to deepen our knowledge of our own philoso- phy, no more virile and profitable intellectual exer- cise than this could be imagined. We shall never know the soundness of our own system until we see it struggle in successful conflict with other systems. 66 CARTESIANISM Two methods are available to obtain a judicial esti- mate of Descartes’ philosophy, which the so-called intellectual world has universally heralded as the glo- rious dawn-light of modern thought. In the first place, we may form a just estimate of Descartes’ thought by studying the different systems that eventually developed in history as the outcome of his principles. By the fruit of his system you shall know it. This evolution of Cartesian principles into the Occasionalism of Geulincex, the Ontologism of Malebranche, the Pantheism of Spinoza and the sys- tem of Pre-Established Harmony of Leibnitz, will form the subjects of our future study. As the logical offspring of Cartesianism, the character of those fan- tastic systems would be sufficient, as we shall see, to justify the rejection of the parent-philosophy from which they sprang. A more direct method of arriving at a just estimate of Descartes’ system would be to submit his basic principles to direct criticism. And then, not only to show destructively, on grounds of rational evidence, that they are either inconsistent, or contradictory, and therefore illogical, but also to set forth constructively the true principle in each case that is consonant with reason. This is the method we shall at first adopt in the Criticism of Descartes’ principles. I. Now, at the very threshold of Descartes’ system, the first topic that challenges our critical investiga- tion is his initial attitude of doubt, not only towards the conclusions of all philosophers up to his time, but also towards all the knowledge which he himself had previously acquired. This doubt was real and posi- tive. “I am constrained”, he says, “at last to avow that there is nothing of all I formerly believed to be true, of which it is impossible to doubt, and that not CRITICAL EXAMINATION 67 through thoughtlessness or levity, but from cogent and maturely considered reasons”. (Medit. I.) Re- call that he even conjured up the fantastic possibility of a “malignant demon” who had the power to deceive all his philosophical predecessors, and of which he himself may have been the victim. This positive doubt was certainly all-embracing and therefore universal. (1) Now, in the first place, it seems obvious that when he made use of his reason to supply arguments to overthrow the trustworthiness of the same reason, he put trust in his reason to discover reliable argu- ments, and as the result of those arguments he aban- doned that trust in his own reason. He consequently trusted and did not trust his own reason at the same time, and consequently contradicted himself. (2) Besides, one of the arguments which he set forth for abandoning all trust in his reason was be- cause this faculty sometimes delivers to us false con- clusions which we take for truth. But how could he distinguish what is false from what is true except by his reason? He trusted his reason, then, because he admitted it could distinguish what is false from what is true, and in the same breath, did not trust his rea- son because it sometimes accepts what is false for what is true. This is the same as saying my reason is not trustworthy because it is trustworthy, which is a manifest contradiction. (3) Furthermore, it was only through the exercise of his reason, which is the same faculty as intellectual consciousness, that he could arrive at the certainty of the fact of his own existence expressed in the famous formula: “I think, therefore, I exist’. But if Des- cartes had already made up his mind to discredit as positively doubtful all the deliverances of his reason or of his intellectual consciousness, which is the same 68 CARTESIANISM faculty, how could he, then, consistently trust his rea- son, that is, his consciousness, when it revealed to him his own existence? No doubt Descartes would say that among all other deliverances of reason, this awareness of his own ex- istence was the one lonely exception that forced itself upon him, in the earlier stages of his investigation, as an undeniable certainty. Why did he not, then, sus- pend his judgment and refrain from forming the the- ory that the deliverances of reason were to be wniver- sally and positively doubted, until he had heard this witness of consciousness (i.é€., reason) bearing incon- testable testimony to reason’s trustworthiness? Descar- tes, as a judge, then, of the trustworthiness of reason, seemed to have condemned this faculty as positively untrustworthy before all the facts of the case were examined and before all the evidence was placed be- fore the court of enquiry. Hence, it seems that Descartes, in setting up the theory that reason is to be wniversally and positively doubted, contradicted himself, because he subse- quently admitted that there was at least one fact, namely, his own existence, to which reason (7. é., con- sciousness) testified, and its testimony, in that case, was not to be doubted. Hence, according to Des- cartes’ own confession, his universal positive doubt regarding all knowledge was not universal at all. When Descartes declared, “I think’, that is, “I am doubting”, what was he thinking of, or about what was he doubting? It is impossible to think or to doubt without thinking of, or doubting about some- thing. When Descartes set forth the grounds for the establishment of the fact of his own existence, he did not explicitly state or explain the object of his think- ing or doubting. Yet, we can infer from another prin- ciple of his system, namely, that the direct and imme- CRITICAL EXAMINATION 69 diate objects of all perception, whether intellectual or otherwise, were ideas, that is, something sub jective or psychical, not something really objective or actual in the sense that this something is outside, and inde- pendent of, the subjective idea. When Descartes, then, said, “I think, z.e., I doubt’, he was thinking of or doubting about an idea, the only direct and im- mediate object of all thought recognized by him. He did not doubt that he perceived a subjective idea, that he was certain of through consciousness. When he asserted, then, “I think, 7.¢., I doubt”, what was he doubting about? He doubted not the idea, but, whether or not that idea had any counterpart in the actual existence of material objects outside and inde- pendently of the idea. He doubted the actual exis- tence of every being outside of the idea of it. And when he said, “therefore, I am, that is, I exist”, what he again knew for certain was his idea of his existence. How, then, could he consistently make the transition from the idea of his existence to his actual existence, in the face of doubting the validity of the like transi- tion from the idea that material things exist outside of him to their actual existence? If he doubtingly balked at the difficulty of “transcending” his idea of the existence of everything outside of him, he should have consistently, doubtingly balked also at “trans- cending” the idea of his own existence and kept on doubting about his actual existence. Why did he ig- nore the difficulty of “transcendence” in the one case, and not in the other? The difficulty, if it is a difficulty, is as valid in the one case as in the other. The idea of the actual existence of all outer objects did indeed involve the idea that he existed. That is all. Des- cartes should, then, consistently conclude not that I actually exist, but that I have an idea that I exist, that is, I exist ideally. In a word, Descartes’ princi- 70 CARTESIANISM ples of knowledge would lead to the conclusion, “I am an idea” and nothing more. It would seem, as we shall examine later on, that Descartes’ method of es- tablishing what he professed to be his own actual exis- tence is open to the same objections as the method he adopted in proving the existence of God. If the latter is an invalid transition from the ideal to the actual order, so is the former. Descartes himself seems to have corroborated the correctness of the above analysis of the method he em- ployed for the establishment of his own existence only as an idea-existence. Because he subsequently, as we shall see, made thought, that is, idea, — for an idea is thought —the essence of soul or spirit, which is the man. If manis, then, only an idea, he has no substantial actual existence, unless he makes an idea substantial. And if man is only an idea or thought, then the only legitimate philosophy is Phenomenal Idealism. (4) Lastly, when Descartes relegated to the region of positive and real doubt all self-evident principles, as we have seen in the destructive exposition of his system, he included in that positive doubt even the objective certainty of the principle of contradic- tion (“it is impossible for anything to be and not to be at the same time and in the same respect”). While in positive doubt, then, regarding this principle, he was illogical in asserting as certain the truth of the fact, “I think, therefore, I exist’. Because, owing: to his real doubt of the principle of contradiction, it be- comes also doubtful whether it is not possible to think and not-think at the same time, or whether it is not possible to be and not-be at the same time.- By ex- plicitly doubting positively the principle of contra- diction he could never know anything. II. The next step in the development of Descartes’ system is the assured establishment of the fact of his CRITICAL EXAMINATION 71 own existence, “I think, therefore, I exist”, a fact which is implicit in every act of knowledge. By teach- ing this fact, Descartes professed to have emerged from the darkness of real doubt and to have at last grasped a reality that is absolutely true and certain. What judgment may we justly form as to the result of a critical examination of Descartes’ effort to estab- lish his own existence? The truth and certainty of this first fact of knowl- edge are admitted by all sound systems of philosophy. Centuries before Descartes’ pronouncement, St. Augustine (De Civit. Dei, XI, 26) insisted upon its certainty and St. Thomas taught it. (“Nullus potest cogitare se non esse cum assensu; in hoc enim quid cogitat percipi se esse.’ De Verit. Q. X., Art. 12.) It is not, therefore, the evident truth and certainty of our own objective existence revealed to us by con- sciousness that we challenge. What we do challenge is, that Descartes, irrespective of the contradictions which we have before pointed out, could not consis- tently and logically admit the truth and certainty of his own existence, and at the same time hold as posi- tively doubtful other propositions quite as evident as this fundamental fact — “I think, therefore, I exist’. “How do I know’, he said, “that I am not also de- ceived each time I add together two and three, or number the sides of a square, or form some judgment still more simple, if more simple, indeed, could be imagined?” (Med. I.) If Descartes admits he may be deceived in forming judgments of the aforesaid truths, then he ought also to confess that he may be deceived in forming the judgment, “I think, there- fore, I exist’. The evidence for the truth and cer- tainty of the above-mentioned judgments is just as cogent and compelling as the evidence for the judg- ment, “I think, therefore, I exist’. 72 CARTESIANISM But a good Cartesian would, no doubt, protest against this line of argument, and say that “even if I should make an effort to cast out the judgment ‘I think (I doubt), therefore, I exist’, by the door of doubt, it would still persist in returning again by the door of truth and certainty”. But this feature of per- sisting to be true and certain is also characteristic of “the principle of contradiction”, as well as many other axiomatic principles, and yet Descartes really doubted them before he professed to have established his own existence. Therefore, logically he ought to have doubted his own existence. But a loyal Cartesian may still advance to the de- fense of his master, and say,— “what Descartes really doubted in the case of the principle of contra- diction, as well as regards other so-called self-evident principles, was not that those principles seemed to be subjectively certain, but rather whether they had an application to objective reality, just as he did not doubt that he ‘seemed’ to see and feel material objects, although he doubted whether mate- rial objects had any objective ‘reality’. Well, then, for the same reason, he ought to have admitted only that ‘he seemed to eaist’, but doubt whether he ex- isted as an objective reality”. The reason why he claimed he was not certain, in the case of sense-knowl- edge, that objects really existed outside and inde- pendent of the subjective act of perception, expressed by the phrase, “I seem to see objects’, though he was quite certain of the mere “seeming to see’’, was, that he could not clearly explain how the mind could transcend itself and grasp an object outside of itself. But that same reason holds good in the case of know- ing with certainty his own existence. Because “I think” is likewise a subjective act or happening, and yet Descartes seems to have no difficulty in admitting CRITICAL EXAMINATION 73 that it transcends itself. In and through this subjec- tive act of thinking, he grasps the reality of his own existence. If, then, Descartes was justified in saying, “TI seem to see objects”, but doubts whether he sees real objects, he ought, in like manner, say —“I seem to exist, but I am not certain that I do”. The diffi- culty of transcendence, if it is a difficulty, holds good in both cases. III. Descartes made consciousness, to the exclusion of all other cognitive faculties, the starting-point of all truth and certainty. Now, since consciousness, by its very nature, is a faculty which can only perceive the acts or states which affect us subjectively, as our own, and cannot directly of itself perceive any objects outside and independent of us, he concluded that the objects which we directly and immediately perceive are our subjective ideas, meaning, as Descartes does by “ideas”, subjective sensations, subjective super- sensible concepts, states of consciousness. Conscious- ness could directly perceive no other objects. This theory afterwards, in the development of philosophy, opened the way to Idealism. Descartes, himself, when he had fully developed his system, was not an ideal- ist. He professed Realism. He based his conviction that material things existed outside and indepen- dently of himself, upon the existence of an all-truth- ful God, Who could not be deceived or deceive us. He was a “reasoned realist”. We shall afterwards examine whether Descartes was logically justified in professing Realism. Idealism of one kind or other, and it has taken a multiplicity of forms, has been, outside of Scholasti- cism, which has always remained a philosophy of Real- ism, the fashionable philosophy with modern thinkers. since Descartes’ time, and continues in vogue at the: 74 CARTESIANISM present day. This prevalence of Idealism in modern thought has been emphasized in the following brief statement by Professor Case of Oxford, who is not a scholastic writer. Professor Case writes: “Psycho- logical idealism began with the supposition of Des- cartes that all the immediate objects of knowledge are ideas. From Descartes, it passed to Locke and Berkeley. But with Hume it changed its terms from ideas to impressions. Kant preferred phenomena; Mill, sensations. The most usual terms of the present day are sensations, feelings, psychical phenomena, and states of consciousness. But the hypothesis has not changed its essence, though the idealists have changed their terms. Verbum, non animwm mutant. They at least agree that all sensible data are psychical objects of some kind or other”. (Physical Realism, p. 15.) This “seeming” or phenomenal, not the real, Ego, is all that Kant and Hume professed to know. That we may understand, then, why it is that the philosophy of Idealism dominates our great non- Catholic universities at the present day, and approves itself to the minds of our modern non-Catholic lead- ers of thought, it will be useful and interesting to trace this prevalence of Idealism to the epistemolog- ical principles set forth by Descartes. Those Carte- sian principles are: That consciousness is the starting point of all knowledge. This is the root principle, and from it are easily inferred the two other principles of Idealism, to wit: (1) That consequently the immediate and direct objects of knowledge are, therefore, not objects out- side and independent of ourselves as is vulgarly thought, but modifications or changes within our- selves, — that is, within our souls, since Descartes in- CRITICAL EXAMINATION 75 terpreted “ourselves” as souls or spirits alone. Those internal or subjective changes the Idealists designate by several different names — ideas, impressions, phe- nomena, sensations, feelings, psychical facts, states of consciousness. The objects which we know directly and immediately, then, and which supply us with the foundation of our knowledge, are of such stuff as ideas are made of. Indeed, if consciousness is the fac- ulty which supplies our first objects of knowledge, those objects could be no other than those above men- tioned. Because it is the very nature of conscious- ness to perceive directly only those experiences which affect us internally, as our own. Consciousness, as such, cannot grasp an object outside of ourselves. Besides, have you ever seriously reflected upon the nature of knowledge? Have you ever realized that knowledge is something unique, something that stands alone, and that cannot be classified under any other category in our experience? Permit me, then, to explain the inherent difficulties of interpreting knowl- edge as the ordinary person interprets it, when he is persuaded that his knowledge grasps external objects, difficulties which have led so many intellectuals to go over to the camp of the Idealists. In the first place, an act of perception, whether of sense or intellect, is an act of the mind, and it is un- deniable that this act, by which, for instance, I grasp the knowledge of yonder City Hall, remains within my mind. It is what is called an immanent act. I know whatever I know by acts of the senses, of sim- ple apprehension, judgment and reasoning. All those mental processes are acts of the soul, and therefore remain within the soul as so many psychical acci- dents, distinct, indeed, from the soul, but still inhering in the soul. The great problem, then, of knowledge is, how can 76 CARTESIANISM an act of the soul, or of a faculty of the soul, grasp an external object which is outside the soul, and is where the soul is not? How can the soul travel, as it were, outside of itself and lay hold of objects by an act that remains within itself? The object that we grasp in knowledge is certainly not physically within the soul. How, then, does it lay hold of it and know - it? This difficulty in reference to knowledge is called the difficulty of transcendence. And overcome by this difficulty, which they say is insurmountable, the Ideal- ists formulate their third principle, which is a logical consequence of making consciousness the starting- point of knowledge, and assert that, (2) The mind or soul cannot transcend itself, and, therefore, cannot know anything except what is inti- mately present within itself. And objects as they ea- ist outside of the soul are not certainly, in their own reality, present within it. But you may say that ideas are images or representations within the mind of ob- jects outside the mind, and when we know the repre- sentations, ideas, or images, by consciousness, then we know objects outside represented by our ideas, just as we see our face in a mirror. Reflect, that if this is the way we know objects outside of us, it fol- lows that we never perceive the objects as they exist in themselves. We only perceive their representa- tions, ideas, or images. And since we cannot know objects directly and immediately in themselves, how could we ever know that our subjective representa- tions, ideas, or images of objects really resemble the objects themselves? The only way we could become certain that our mental representations, or ideas, truly resemble objects outside of us, would be to com- pare the representation with the objects themselves. But that we could never do, because we know only the subjective representations, but not the objects CRITICAL EXAMINATION 77 themselves. Hence, if we make consciousness the starting-point of knowledge, we shall be, like maniacs, ever doomed to stare upon our own subjective ideas. It would be utterly impossible to get outside of our- selves or know anything outside of ourselves. We would be driven to the universally-condemned posi- tion of solipsism. What answer does Scholasticism give to those prin- ciples of Idealism? (1) Descartes asserted that intellectual conscious- ness is the starting-point of all knowledge. Conscious- ness in his system must mean intellectual conscious- ness. Because, for him, the spirit or soul is the man, and the consciousness that is rooted in spirit can only be intellectual. Hence, he would maintain that our intellectual or rational life is developed before our sensitive life, —a doctrine that is opposed to all ex- perience. Hence, it is the teaching of Scholasticism that sense knowledge precedes intellectual knowledge. “Nihil est in intellectu nisi prius fuerit aliquo modo in sensu’, is received as axiomatic by scholasticism. We first look outward, then inward, and lastly upward, whereas, according to the topsy-turvyism of Descar- tes, we first look inward (consciousness) , then wpward (to God), and lastly owtward (to material things). (2) Scholasticism denies outright that the direct and immediate objects of our cognitive faculties, whether of sense or intellect, are psychical or subjec- tive modifications of ourselves, and teaches, on the contrary, that the direct and immediate objects of knowledge are objects that are outside and indepen- dent of the act of perception or thought by means of which they are perceived. The object of perception or thought is not the perception itself or the thought itself considered as a mere modification of ourselves as a subject. 78 CARTESIANISM Ueberweg, who did not profess be a scholastic in philosophy, subscribed to this teaching— He says: “But the complexes of sensation (2. é., the psychical changes within us that accompany the perception of outward objects), though alone immediately in our consciousness, are not therefore necessarily the imme- diate object of sense perception, to wit, if they be at all not the object but the means of it; our attention, in the case of complexes of sensation, is directed en- tirely to the external things manifested to us through them; the external thing is that which I see, handle, perceive. “The complexes of sensation are, as such, late in becoming the object of psychological reflection”. (Annot. to Berkeley, p. 347.) In the language of Scholasticism, the subjective factor of sense or intellect is not that which is directly and immediately known, but the subjective factor, though in itself not directly known, still becomes the means by which the external reality is directly known. An orange, for example, is not a collection of psy- chical or subjective feelings or sensations. This is the primitive and untutored instincts which a child manifests: He stretches out his little hands for the orange. Why should he stretch his hand outward for the orange, if his primitive knowledge told him it was a collection of subjective sensations within him? It is no answer to say, with the Idealists, that the orange is only an outward projection of our inner sensations. The human race possesses an irresistible conviction that the orange is really existing outside of us. The burden of proof to show that this conviction is an illu- sion rests, therefore, with the Idealists. And no Ideal- ist has ever succeeded in proving this conviction delu- sory. CRITICAL EXAMINATION 79 (3) What of the difficulty of “transcendence”, the stumbling block of Idealists? How, they say, can an act of knowledge, which undoubtedly remains within the mind, go outside the mind to reach an external object? An act of a sense faculty or of the intellect cannot, they say, transcend itself, so as to grasp an object outside itself. Scholasticism answers thus: It is certain that what we know is, in some way, in our minds. Our friend, for instance, about whom we are thinking, is in our mind and present to it in some way. But it is equally certain that our friend, as he objectively exists, is not in our minds, any more than the real mountain we know is in our mind. The object we know is in our mind in this way: There is, in our mind, a mental re- production or representation of the real object. It is not this representation or mental reproduction of the real object that is, however, perceived, directly and immediately, but is the means by which the real ob- ject is directly and immediately perceived. This men- tal representation of the object in the mind is called “intentional”, for by means of it the mind tends to- ward the object and grasps it as the term of our knowledge. The mind does, indeed, transcend itself in its acts of knowledge, not, however, physically, but cogmtively. IV. Descartes set up as a criterion, test or meas- ure of truth, “clearness and distinctness of ideas’. But he also felt that he could not put absolute trust in this criterion, until he had proved that it came from God, who could not deceive us. Descartes’ complete criterion or standard of truth was, therefore, not “clear and distinct ideas” alone, but “clearness and distinctness of ideas” backed by the existence of an all-truthful God. “Without a knowledge of these 80 CARTESIANISM two truths”, he says, (1) “that God exists and (2) cannot deceive, I don’t see how I can be certain of anything”. (Med. III.) We shall be obliged to quar- rel critically with this criterion. In the first place, to make “clearness and distinct- ness of ideas’, that is, to locate the mark of logical truth as resident within subjective ideas, and make of this mark a premise from which we may argue from ideas thus characterized by clearness and dis- tinctness to objects beyond and independent of them, would be destructive of what all sane thinkers throughout the ages understand by logical truth or the truth of knowledge. The classical definition of “logical truth” or the truth of thought given by St. Thomas is, “the con- formity of thought with reality” (conformitas intel- lectus cum re), wherein reality is the measure of thought and not thought the measure of reality. Hence, truth necessarily presupposes a subject know- ing and an object known. The mark or criterion of truth must, therefore, be sought for, either in the subject knowing or in the object known. But should we seek for and profess to find it in the subject know- ing or in ideas or thought, which are modifications of the knowing subject, the inevitable consequence would be, that thought or ideas would then become the measure of reality, not reality the measure of thought or ideas. In other words, our thoughts would then be true because we clearly and distinctly think them true. But it is obvious that it does not follow that, just because we think that our thoughts or ideas are true, that they, therefore, measure up to the real- ity. We may have quite clear and distinct ideas to which no reality corresponds. For ages men had a clear and distinct idea that the sun moved around the earth. Yet every school boy knows now, that to that CRITICAL EXAMINATION 81 clear and distinct idea no reality corresponded. That idea or thought, though clearer and more distinct than the thought or idea that the earth actually moves around the sun, was false. We have met people who had very clear and distinct ideas of fairies and ghosts, when the objects of those ideas were mere illusions of their phantasy. Men may justify the most extrava- gant wickedness in morals and the most repulsive errors in religion by saying that they have a clear and distinct idea of the rightness of their actions, or of their religious convictions. To make clear and dis- tinct ideas the measure of truth would be to adopt a relative standard of truth and certainty. Does it not stand to reason, then, that we are to look for the standard, the criterion, the mark of truth, in the objective reality that is known, not in our thoughts or ideas? Because it is the objective reality known, which is the measure and the stamp of our thoughts or ideas, in order that they may conform to reality. We do not look for the measure or mark that is impressed on wax in the wax itself, but in the stamp or signet-ring that imparts its impression to the wax. It is in the object or reality known, then, and not in the subject knowing, that the ultimate criterion of logical truth or the truth of human knowledge is found. That criterion is called objective evidence. _ Now, since objective evidence is the genuine cri- terion of truth, and not clearness and distinctness of ideas, we conclude that the fundamental truth of Des- eartes’ philosophy, to wit, his famous “I think, there- fore, I exist”, though undoubtedly true and certain in every sound system of philosophy, — a truth which St. Augustine has established centuries before Des- cartes, — yet, this principle is not true precisely, be- cause, as Descartes maintained, it conveyed to his mind a clear and distinct idea or thought, but because 82 CARTESIANISM it was objectively evident. And because this funda- mental fact, “I think, therefore, I exist’, is objec- tively evident, it is true, and does convey to our minds a clear and distinct idea. Hence, on the understand- ing that “clearness and distinctness of ideas’ is the effect of objective evidence, then “clearness and dis- tinctness” would be a criterion of truth, but not the ultimate criterion. From the standpoint of this false subjective cri- terion of Descartes, whose spirit has, since its author’s day, capitivated non-Catholic intellectuals, we can judge at their true value many opinions that are prev- alent in our own time. Descartes’ criterion of truth tends to give philosophical respectability to the prin- ciple of private judgment. That principle formulates itself thus—I think clearly and distinctly that my Opinion on this or that question is true, therefore, it is true just because I think so. I bring myself to think, for instance, that divorce is true; to think this or that interpretation of the Bible is true; to think that the state and not parents has the first right to educate children; to think that birth control is true; to think that individuals have no right to private property; to think that state policy as independent of God and of the moral law, etc., is true. Therefore, they are true just because I think them true. No, the true principle is, not that something is true just be- cause I think it true, but rather I think it true because it is in itself really true. And the ultimate reason why a judgment or reasoning is in reality true, is, because it is objectively evident. In other words, if you allow me to coin terms, logical truth is not ideo-centric, but onto-centric. Any man who makes thought or ideas the measure of the test of truth, plays the ostrich. He sticks his head in the sand of his own subjectivity or private judgment, and because he does not conceive CRITICAL EXAMINATION 83 and perceive things as they are, says they do not exist. Private judgment leads to Idealism and ultimately to universal scepticism. It leads to dissensions, bigotry and persecution in society. For bitter conflicts will always arise in society to determine which set of pri- vate judgments is to prevail. In the second place, Descartes himself, as we have already indicated, did not place absolute trust in clearness and distinctness of ideas, to offset the fan- tastic possibility of a “malignant demon who may use all his artifices to deceive him”. He was compelled to establish the existence and veracity of God. Hence, he confesses that “without a knowledge of these two truths, that God exists and cannot deceive, I don’t see how I can be certain of anything”. But how could he arrive at the knowledge of these two truths? Only by demonstration or proof. But demonstration, to be valid, must be based on premises that are already ac- knowledged to be true and certain. Now, true and certain premises were not available for Descartes, because the only test or criterion of their truth and certainty was their clearness and distinctness. But this criterion Descartes distrusted. “Because”, he said, “until I know that God exists, I don’t see how I can ever be certain of anything’. The premises, there- fore, which he could alone make use of to prove God’s existence, were doubtful, and from doubtful premises only doubtful conclusions can be drawn. Hence, the conclusion, ““God exists and cannot deceive me’, de- rived as it was from doubtful premises, was itself doubtful. Consequently, since his method of proving God’s existence failed, Descartes, by his own confes- sion, could never know anything for certain. The out- come of Descartes’ false criterion of truth is, conse- quently, universal scepticism. In closing our examination of Descartes’ Episte- 84 CARTESYANISM mology, it may be well to summarize the main prin- ciples of his theory of knowledge, and contrast them with the principles that appeal to sound reason. DESCARTES Initial attitude of— . To doubt seriously and posi- tively of all that he “‘for- merly believed to be true.” . To make consciousness the starting point of all knowl- edge. . Hence, the direct, immediate and first objects of knowl- edge are ideas. . Unless I know that a good and veracious God exists, I cannot know anything for certain. . The criterion of truth and certainty is clearness and distinctness of ideas plus the knowledge of a good and ve- racious God. . The certain existence of any reality, outside and inde- pendent of the Ego, cannot be known except by a pro- cess of reasoning or demon- stration. SOUND REASON Initial attitude of— . To accept as true and cer- tain whatever your intellect vouches to be immediately evident. . To make the senses the starting point of all knowl- edge. . The direct, immediate and first objects of knowledge are material objects re- vealed by the senses. . I can know many things for certain, antecedently to my knowledge of God’s exis- tence. If I cannot know anything for certain before I know God, then I cannot know God for certain. . The criterion of truth and certainty is objective evi- dence. . The certain existence of many objective realities, out- side and independent of the Ego or self, can be immedi- ately known by judgment based upon the report of the external senses and many objective truths, by the im- mediate avouchments of our intellects, determined by ob- jective evidence. CHAPTER V. DESCARTES criticism (Contd.) We have yet to examine critically the fundamental doctrines of Descartes’ (1) Psychology, (2) Natural Theology, (3) and Cosmology. (1) Having established to his satisfaction his own existence, Descartes asked the significant question, “What am 1?” and answered, “I am a substance whose whole essence or nature consists only in think- ing, —so that I, that is to say, the mind, by which I am what I am, is plainly distinct from the body”. (Method, p. IV.) Descartes, then, teaches that “I” am mind or spirit only; that the essence of mind is thought or thinking; that the body, whose existence at this stage of his system was not yet established, was not an essential part of the “I” or the man; that the body, therefore, was not substantially united to the soul, but merely a companion or extrinsic appen- dage to the soul, and thus a separate and complete substance distinct from the “I”. By thus cleaving the “JT”, that is, man, into two complete and independent substances, and thus destroying man’s substantial unity, Descartes inaugurated what is known in the history of philosophy as “I'he exaggerated dualism of Descartes’, a doctrine which, as a sad heritage, he left to future philosophers to develop; nor did they 86 CARTESIANISM fail to derive from it, some Occasionalism, some On- tologism, some Materialism, some Spiritualism, some Pantheism. Now, we shall endeavor to show that when Des- cartes professed to conclude from the testimony of his consciousness that man is a spirit or soul only, he did not interpret or read aright the complete data of that testimony. What Descartes seemed to have done was, to draw an arbitrary circle around some of the data of consciousness, namely, his intellectual or supersensi- ble operations, and say, “thus far shall the testimony of consciousness go, and no farther”. Of course, if Descartes could establish that the only data which consciousness directly and immediately reveals are our own intellectual operations and their objects, then he would be logical in concluding, at least according to the principles of Scholasticism, that man was spirit or soul alone. It is only spirit or soul alone that could be the subject of intellectual operations. But consciousness obviously reveals to us with equal certainty many other operations and experiences be- sides intellectual operations. Consciousness testifies to each of us also, that we are the subject of sensuous perceptions, of aches and pains, of hunger, thirst, dis- comforts and comforts of body, and some of those at least, a headache or lumbago, for example, reveal that “I”, as subject of those feelings, am spatially ew- tended. Many of the data of consciousness, therefore, carry with them a feeling of bodily eatension, and, con- sequently, that “I’’, as the subject of those data, am a conscious, living, corporeal substance. It would seem to be just as reasonable to judge that “I am a mere animal”, because consciousness reveals to me that I am the subject of various bodily and extended sensa- tions, and feelings, as to judge that “I am a spirit merely, because consciousness reveals to me that I am CRITICISM 87 the subject of intellectual operations. Both of those false judgments would be based on a partial interpre- tation of the complete data of consciousness. Descartes, of course, at the stage of his system wherein he established his own existence, would deny, owing to his positive doubt, that he was certain of the existence of any material being, and, consequently, that our consciousness of our own extended, sensuous operations was a valid basis for judging that we were corporeal substances. For the existence of our own bodies was embraced in the universal doubt of Des- cartes regarding the existence of all material beings. Hence, Descartes could say, as he did say, at this point in the development of his system, “I could sup- pose (i.é., doubt) that I had no body and that there was no world or any place that I might be’. We answer that the the testimony of consciousness is just as peremptory in revealing to us our sensuous, ex- tended experience as our own, as is its testimony in revealing to us our own intellectual operations are our own. And if Descartes doubted consciousness, testi- fying to the existence of our own body as the subject of our sensuous and extended feelings, so he ought likewise to doubt of his substantial spirit, as Hume afterwards did, as the subject of his “thought” or “thinking”. Furthermore, if the clear consciousness of our sen- suous and extended feelings does not reveal to us our own bodies as the subject of those feelings, then, even should Descartes successfully demonstrate, as he afterwards professed to do, the existence of matter or bodies, he could never know that our bodies were our own as distinct from other external bodies. In Descartes’ system, our own bodies would be as alien and external to ourselves as the stones beneath our feet, and his doctrine that “man was spirit alone” 88 CARTESIANISM would anticipate, so far as man is concerned, the spiritualism of Leibnitz and Berkeley. Descartes not only endeavored to establish his posi- tion that “man was spirit or soul alone”, by eliminat- ing from the testimony of consciousness our various sensuous and ewtended feelings, but he also attempted to demonstrate the same doctrine of the purely spirit- ual nature of man from two premises. The first prem- ise was his fundamental and first principle, “I think, therefore, I exist’. The second premise which he used to reinforce the first, was a doubtful supposition, namely, “I could swppose (i.e., doubt) I had no body and that there was no world nor place in which I might be”. The introduction of this principle, which was inspired by his positive doubt of the existence of all corporeal things, and hence of his own body, would leave man denuded of his body, and hence establish him as a spirit alone, if Descartes could prove to a certainty that body does not enter into the composi- tion of man as an essential, substantial element. But Descartes does not say, “I can prove that I have no body”. What he said was, “I could suppose (i.é., doubt) I had no body”. Now any tyro in logic knows that a conclusion, namely, “I am a spirit alone”, derived from one cer- tain premise, “I think, therefore, I exist’, and from another premise which confessedly is a doubtful sup- position, “I could suppose I had no body”, will par- take of the nature of the weaker premise, and, there- fore, the conclusion that “I am soul or spirit alone” is also a dubious supposition, and, therefore, devoid of all truth and certainty. Descartes’. conclusion should have been, “I may or may not be a spirit”, or, whether I am a spirit or not are dubious alternatives. In categorically conclud- ing from the premises employed, that he was a spirit CRITICISM 89 only, he certainly outstepped the logical implications of + premises. (Cf. Coffey, Epistemology, V. ILI., p- 9. It is strange perversion, too, of Logic, to find Des- cartes now making use of his reason and trusting it, though he had never established the trustworthiness of that reason which, antecedently to his examination of his knowledge, he wholly and really distrusted. What value can all his conclusions now have, since they are arrived at by means of his already discredited faculty of reason? But Descartes would undoubtedly contend that he did not distrust reason as such, and he certainly did not distrust his own individual reason. In fact, he had an overweening confidence in his own reason. What he did distrust, he would say, was all the deliv- erances of all other men’s reason throughout the ages up to the day that Descartes’ reason began to func- tion. But it is reasonable to conclude that if the fac- ulty of reason in all men throughout the ages never arrived at a true and certain conclusion in philosoph- ical matters, then human reason must be, in its nature, intrinsically vitiated. We would naturally conclude, for instance, that a pen with which we could never write, or an auto that could never move, were intrinsi- cally vitiated. Because we judge of the intrinsic nature of things by their actions. If human reason never functioned aright throughout so many ages un- til Descartes’ reason appeared as the extraordinary exception, then we would be led to conclude that Des- cartes was not human, but a God-like superman, a claim that would be rather arrogant to make. To return to the question, ‘““What am I?’, we have shown that Descartes’ conclusion that “I” meant soul or spirit only is invalid. 90 CARTESIANISM The true answer to the question, ““What am I?”, is not the spiritualistic answer of Descartes, which in- terprets the “I” as soul or spirit only, nor the mate- rialistic answer that “I”? am body only, nor that “I” am a combination of the two separate, independent substances existing merely in companionship, but that “I” am one single substance made up of two incom- plete substances, body and soul substantially united. Now, that we may understand the peculiar psychol- ogy of Descartes, that is, his account of the nature of the soul, and the origin of all our ideas, we must divide the whole matter into the separate problems which he professed to answer. We can never understand the theories of knowledge that are influencing men’s minds to-day, unless we understand Descartes — the Father of Modern Psychology. What, then, is the essence or nature of the soul, and what is the essence or nature of matter or body according to Descartes, and what are the consequences that logically flow from his teaching? Descartes made actual thought the essence of the soul. This theory, of course, involves the consequence that the soul can- not, for even a moment, cease from exercising actual thought. A cessation of actual thought would imply the cessation of the soul’s existence. Now, can it be successfully defended on psycholog- ical grounds that the soul must always actually think? As long as the soul exists in our present state united to the body, all intellectual thought or thinking de- pends extrinsically upon the activity of the imagina- tion or phantasy. The phantasy, because sensuous, is an organic faculty. It is obvious, then, that the organ of the phantasy may be impaired or paralyzed, and its activity may be thereby interrupted. But any in- terruption of the activity of the phantasy would also bring about cessation of actual, intellectual thought CRITICISM 91 of the soul, and yet the soul may continue in existence. Even were it established that the soul is de facto always actively thinking, it would not follow that active thought is the essence of the human soul. To establish this latter theory, the Cartesians maintain that the essence of the human soul is constituted by the fact that it is always actually conscious of itself. When the Cartesians assert, therefore, that actual thought, which they identify with actual conscious- ness, is the essence of the soul, they mean by “actual thought” or “actual consciousness”, not the “thought” or “consciousness” that has for its immediate and pri- mary object the actually present operations of intel- lect and will, which are so many phenomenal acci- dents issuing from the activity of the soul, and through which or by means of which, because those phenomenal accidents are bound up concretely with the substance of the soul, we come to know the soul itself as something that merely eaists. In other words, the Cartesians contend that they do not attain to the knowledge of the soul’s existence through means of the soul’s phenomenal activities, which mediate or in- tervene between “thought” or “consciousness” and the soul itself. What the Cartesians mean by “thought” or “consciousness” is the “thought” that has for its immediate and primary object the nude soul itself, and by “consciousness,” that substantial consciousness by which the soul directly and immedi- ately attains the knowledge not only to the mere ex- istence of soul itself independently of its operations, but the immediate and direct knowledge of the essence or nature of the nude, substantial soul. Descartes himself, when he formulated his famous first principle, “I think, therefore, I exist’, never pointed out what object he was thinking of. But his successors, the Cartesians, analyzing his doctrine that 92 CARTESIANISM “thought”, that is, “consciousness”, was the essence of the soul, came to the conclusion that the direct object of “thought” in which he placed the essence of the soul must be the very nature or essence of the soul itself and not its operations, which are accidental to the soul. Because they very logically reasoned that if the soul cannot directly exercise its activity of think- ing except upon objects that are not the pure soul, but, as in the case of consciousness, upon objects that are accidental to the soul, to wit, its operations, then it follows that thought or consciousness cannot be the essence of the soul. That “thought” may be the es- sence of soul, then, the nude soul must perpetually exercise its thought. And since thought must have an object, that object must be the pure soul itself. Now, it cannot be reasonably maintained that through “thought”, or consciousness”, we can immediately and directly come to know the bare, nude essence of the human soul. And if it is false to say that we can attain immediately and directly, without the inter- vention of the phenomenal operations of the soul, a knowledge of the pure, nude soul and its nature, as a thinking thing, then it follows that “thought” or consciousness” is not the essence of the human soul. We shall set forth some of the main arguments to prove that the soul is incapable of knowing its own pure, bare self directly and immediately, indepen- dently of our knowledge of every intervening soul- action. In the first place, if we could know our soul im- mediately and directly through its own essence, then it would follow that we should be able to form positive and proper concepts of purely spiritual beings. But experience tells us that we cannot form positive and proper concepts of the essence of any spiritual being. We become aware of the essences of spiritual beings CRITICISM 93 through a process of reasoning, that is, mediately, and the concepts which we form of what is character- istic of them, and which differentiates them from material beings, are all negative and analogical con- cepts. In the second place, the doctrine of the Carte- sians, explained above, would lead logically to the conclusion that the union of the soul and body would be unnecessary because purposeless. Because, then, the soul could essentially and independently of its union with the body know an object, that is, the spiritual soul, which is pre-eminently nobler than all the material objects which we are capable of knowing through the agency of the senses. And if we could know our soul in this manner, then we could also know God and many other supersensible objects in- dependently of all ministrations of the senses, and, therefore, independently of the soul’s union with body. The union of soul and body would, therefore, be useless. Yet, such a union exists, and since we must assume that it was brought about with wisdom, its purpose can only be to contribute to the perfection of the higher faculties in man. | On the other hand, Descartes taught that the es- sence of matter or body consists wholly in “extension”, that is, in length, breadth, and depth. Consequently, matter or body, according to Descartes, is essentially inert, inactive, dormant, incapable of doing anything or being the efficient cause of anything. The only activity it possesses comes to it from the outside, namely, from a certain amount of local motion im- parted to dead matter in the beginning by God, and this amount of motion in the whole universe of matter never changes. Motion, then, is not inherent in mat- ter, but is only an extrinsic push given to matter, just like the motion of a machine. Descartes then looked 94 CARTESIANISM upon vegetables and animals, and even the human body, as matter, pure and simple, without any inher- ent principle of life. He classified the vegetable and animal kingdoms as belonging to the same kind of matter as the mineral world. Hence he explained all the changes that take place in the mineral, vegetable, animal world, and in the human body, by motion ex- trinsically imparted by God to the matter that com- pose them. Hence, you can understand why he called all of them machines or “automatons”, like our watches or children’s toys. Even vegetables, animals, and the body of man are not really living; they are as dormant and dead as minerals are. The circulation of the blood, digestion, breathing, the cries of the ani- mals, their movements, the singing of the birds, all our own bodily activities which we ascribe to the prin- ciple of life are, to Descartes, all the effect of mechan- ical motion. Outside of souls or spirits, all other be- ings, which we imagine live, are so many phono- graphs, whose apparent activities are the result of mechanical motion of the universe. Such a philosophy is known as “the philosophy of mechanism”. In oppo- sition to the doctrine of Descartes, which declares that matter is intrinsically and essentially inert, because extension, which he falsely assumed to be the essence of matter, is by its nature inert, sound philosophy and science proclaim that matter is intrinsically active. In other words, we assert the proposition that — The corporeal substances of this world are true efficient causes and not merely occa- sional causes as the Cartesians maintain. In answer to the question whether corporeal sub- stances are endowed with intrinsic activity or are, in other words, true efficient causes, three theories have been prevalent in the history of philosophy: CRITICISM 95 (a) The Stoics taught that all activity of bodies was not to be ascribed to matter itself, but to an in- visible agency which pervades the visible world, and which they called the “soul of the world’. Akin to this theory is that of the Arabian philosophers who taught that all the changes in this visible world were brought about through the agency of inferior in- telligent and celestial beings. Newman, in his youth, fancied that the angels were the efficient causes of all corporeal changes. (b) The Cartesian theory has already been ex- plained. (c) The prevailing teaching of Scholasticism, which declares that corporeal substances are endowed with real activity, and are, therefore, the proximate efficient causes of all the changes which we observe in this world. We do not enter here the question of miracles. Proofs: (1) The Cartesians admit, of course, with the exception of Spinoza, the existence of the Creator as an infinitely intelligent Being. Now we observe that all living beings are furnished with organs of different kinds and of admirably dif- ferent and delicate structure. If these organs were not so many instruments destined to be exercised by living beings in the performance of different activi- ties, then they would be wseless and created for no purpose. But it would be derogatory to infinite in- telligence to create anything useless and purposeless. Therefore, animals and living beings are not mere “automatons”. (2) Regarding the activity of inorganic matter, all scientists are unanimously agreed that matter is en- dowed with inherent activity. The force of gravita- tion, as set forth by Newton, would discredit the the- ory of the inactivity of matter. 96 CARTESIANISM We can now readily understand the false, though logical, consequence of those Cartesian doctrines in the sphere of psychology. Some of those false conse- quences will be apparent in the answer which Des- cartes gave to the problems — (1) of the union of the soul and body, (2) and of the origin of all our knowledge. Descartes, arguing logically, let us admit, from false principles, opened wide a chasm between the soul and body of man, over which he vainly endeav- ored to build a bridge of union. He saparated out- right the soul and body of man and left that sepa- ration yawning to-day. He attempted an explanation to bring them into unity. He failed and left to future thinkers the famous problem of the “exaggerated dualism of Descartes’, a doctrine which consists both in the utter separation of soul and body, and the im- possibility of any interaction between them. This “exaggerated dualism” was the logical consequence o the following Cartesian principles — (1) that “I” was the soul, as something entirel distinct from the body. (2) that the essence of the soul was thought, and the essence of the body was extension, and since a thinking thing and an extended thing are two heterogeneous substances, they could never be united together to form one sub- stance, nor could one react on the other. An extended thing that is wholly inert could not act upon a purely thinking substance. How, then, did Descartes explain the rise of knowl- edge, that is, both intellectual and sensuous knowl- edge? Whence came his ideas of intellect and his sen- sations? To understand Descartes’ explanation of knowledge, we must divest ourselves, for the time be- CRITICISM 97 ing, of the explanation of knowledge which Aristotle and the Schoolmen had made familiar in Psychology. The Aristotelian and Scholastic explanation main- tains that all our knowledge, even intellectual ideas, begin in sense-knowledge. Hence the principle, “Nihil est in intellectu nist pruis fuerit aliquo modo in sensu’, has been received as axiomatic by the Schoolmen. Descartes repudiated that principle. That principle supposes that bodies or matter, in- cluding our own body, can act upon our senses and make an impression upon them. The Scholastics maintain besides that our senses are faculties that do not emerge from the pure soul or spirit only, but have for their subject a material organ animated by the soul. Sense faculties, then, are not rooted in the body alone, or in the soul alone, but in a single principle made up of body and soul. Now, Descartes, on the contrary, taught that both the intellect as a faculty and the senses as faculties emerged from the soul alone and are faculties of the soul alone. They are both spiritual faculties, or, rather, he did not distinguish the cognitive faculties, whether of a sense or intellect, from the pure soul. Every activity, then, which we call cognitive, are functions of the soul alone — sense perception, imag- ination, pure intellection, as well as our non-cognitive functions — will-action, feelings, emotions, and pas- sions. In the production of all those functions the body did not enter as a factor at all. It was a dead, inert substance that could not act upon soul. Recall that even animals had no sense-knowledge, because they were not, like man, souls or spirits. As a consequence of those principles, Descartes was obliged to teach that all intellectual ideas, and all sensations or sense-knowledge, had their birth within the soul alone, and were completed and perfected 98 CARTESIANISM within the soul, independently of any determination or action upon the soul by matter. Briefly, the soul was mother of all cognition or knowledge without a father, that is, knowledge sprang up in the soul, some- how, without the latter receiving any impression from matter, as a determining cause of knowledge. Hence, Descartes, to account for knowledge, in- vented innate ideas. All our purely intellectual knowl- edge is inborn in the soul alone. Truly, he also added what he called adventitious ideas, which came from the outside or from matter. But those adventitious ideas did not come from matter, in the sense that mat- ter acted in any way as an efficient determining cause upon the soul, but only as an occasion. Descartes’ ex- planation of the origin of those adventitious ideas is one of the most obscure and weakest parts of his psy- chology. He endeavored to explain their rise in the soul thus: He attributed to the body of man what he called “animal spirits”. Those animal spirits were subject to motion. They were not animate, because the body wherein they moved was not animated. Yet other bodies could act upon those animal spirits, and move them, because both the mover and the moved were in both cases matter. When those “animal spir- its” were then moved in the body in a certain way, God took occasion of their movements to arouse within the soul certain corresponding ideas. ‘Those ideas were adventitious, then, in contrast to his al- ready existing innate ideas, but they were not adven- titious, inasmuch as they came from an outside mate- rial cause, but only from an outside material occasion. He also admitted factitious ideas, Those are easily explained, because they are only the combination of either innate or adventitious ideas or of both. You can now easily understand that, on Descartes’ principles, material objects had nothing to do with CRITICISM 99 the making or the origin of our ideas of them in the mind, except as occasional, not as efficient causes. You can also appreciate why it was that the only direct and immediate objects of Descartes’ knowl- edge were the ideas locked within his own soul. The cognitive activity of his soul expressed in thought was completely cut off from external objects. Look- ing at his ideas, he saw that they represented objects, as everybody’s ideas do, but he could not know whether those objects which they represented really existed as they appeared. For aught he could tell, as Huxley says, they may be “an orderly phantasma- goria”’, mere ghosts of objects “in the background of nothingness”. He could contemplate his ideas and thoughts imprisoned in his own soul, but he could not attain to the reality of existing objects outside himself. How, then, did he come to know material objects outside and independent of himself? He ultimately professed to know them, but how? He attempted to reason to their actual existence. For this purpose, he essayed to prove the existence of God. Having arrived at the knowledge of God’s ex- istence, who was all-truthful, he then reasoned that, since he had an unconquerable conviction or persua- sion that bodies did exist, because clear and distinct ideas represented them to him, God, who was all- wise and truthful, could not endow him with this un- conquerable persuasion unless bodies really existed. Otherwise, God would not be an all-truthful being, but a deceiver. Did he succeed in proving the existence of God? This question brings us finally to a critical examina- tion of Descartes’ proof for God’s existence. First proof: He possessed, he said, an idea of God in his soul, an innate idea. The character of this idea was such that it involved all perfections. Now 100 CARTESIANISM amongst other perfections which that idea contained in its comprehension was Existence, because it is a perfection to exist. Therefore, God exists. What are we to think of this argument? There is obviously in this argument the fallacy of the injusti- fiable transition from the ideal order to the real order. Every conclusion of reasoning must be of the same nature as the premises from which it is derived. Grant that Descartes had an idea of God in his soul. It was only an idea. All its perfections were ideas. The idea of existence was, indeed, involved in the idea of God. But that idea of existence was still only an idea. The only conclusion, then, that Descartes could derive from the idea of God is that his idea of God con- tained the idea of His existence. Therefore, he should have concluded that the idea of God’s existence is a fact, but not His actual and real existence. To say that God actually exists because I have an innate idea of God which involves the idea of God’s existence is to confound the ideal order with the actual or real order. Second argument: I have, he said, an idea of God. That idea is infinite. Objects outside of me could not form that idea in my mind, nor could I form it by my own power within me, because this infinite idea of God, as an effect in my soul, could not be produced by any finite cause. But I myself am finite and every other cause is finite. The cause that produces some- thing as an effect-must possess as much perfection as the effect. No other cause is adequate in its perfec- tions to produce this infinite idea in me except God Himself. Therefore, God exists. The fallaciousness of this argument is as obvious as that of the first. Professor Case expresses this argument in syllo- gistic form, thus — CRITICISM 101 More reality cannot be produced by less. But the idea of God has more objective reality than the actual reality of any finite substance. Therefore, the idea of God cannot be produced by any finite substance, but must be received from God Himself. Therefore, God, as the cause of this idea, exists. The major is true. The minor is false, because the objective reality of an idea is always less real and less perfect than the actual reality of the thinker, and, therefore, can be produced by him. God, as He exists, has more reality than an existing man, it is true. The idea of God has more reality than the idea of man. But an actually existing man has more reality than his own idea of God. We can, therefore, retort on Descartes his own argument: The less real can be produced by the more real. The idea of God has less reality than the thinker. Therefore, the idea of God can be produced by the man who thinks it. Descartes’ third argument for the existence of God would be valid in our philosophy. But in Descartes’ — system the argument is invalid because of other false principles involved in that system. The argument is the ordinary “a posteriori” argu- ment for God’s existence. I am an existing being. I know I am imperfect and finite. While I know IL exist, I know also that I may not exist. I am, there- fore, a contingent being. I must be caused, then, not by another contingent being, because that latter be- ing would demand another cause. I must, therefore, be caused by a necessary Being whose essence is His existence and endowed with infinite perfections. This argument is fully elaborated in Natural Theology. 102 CARTESIANISM But for Descartes it would be invalid, if for no other reason than his memorable statement, “I don’t see how I can be certain of anything until I know these two truths, that God exists and cannot deceive’. If he could know nothing for certain until he knew God existed, how could he know, during the process of proving God’s existence, that his argument was true and certain? One more doctrine of Descartes’ system remains for criticism. He teaches that the essence of matter is extension — length, breadth, and depth. Now, we can conceive what is known as a vacuum. We can sup- pose that the intervening space between two bodies may be absolutely emptied by the evacuation of all that exists therein. Still, ewtension would remain in the vacuum. According to Descartes, that mere ex- tension would be a body, because the essence of body is extension. But the conceived supposition is that in a vacuum there is no body, but extension alone. Hence, extension can be conceived as existing with- out a body. But that conception would be impossible if body were extension. Hence, we conclude that body is not extension. Hence, extension cannot be the essence of a body. CuaApter VI. OCCASION ALISM Descartes’ writing made so profound and lasting an impression upon his age that his principles inau- gurated a revolution in philosophical thought parallel to the revolution which the principles of Luther and the Protestant Reformation brought about in relig- ious thought. So fascinating was his influence that his words were accepted by his disciples almost as those of one who was inspired. Descartes was not, however, the complete and adequate cause of the rev- olution in thought of which he is now accredited to be the father and founder. Were the minds of men in his day not prepared by a growing opposition towards Scholasticism, engendered by the false prin- ciples of the Renaissance and the rising Reformation (Luther died 1546), his writings may have fallen still-born upon an uninterested world. Descartes was as much the product of the Scepticism (witness Mon- taigne) of his age as his age was, in its thought and tendencies, the product of Descartes. Just as Spir- itism is popular in our times, not so much on account of the inherent value of the spiritistic revelations, but rather because a considerable part of the Protestant world, owing to its loss of Christian faith, is prepared to accept and cling to any substitute for Christianity, however extravagant. Men and women must have, by an impelling instinct of human nature, a religion of some kind; so must men and women have a phil- osophy of some kind. 104 CARTESIANISM Descartes has been one of those rare geniuses who has cast into the furrows of human thought certain seed- principles, which, enthusiastically cherished and culti- vated as they have been, by his disciples and succes- sors, have deeply influenced the speculation of mod- ern thinkers for the last three hundred years; nor have these Cartesian principles yet spent all their destruc- tive force. It would not be fair, however, to judge Descartes’ character by his principles and teachings. Men are sometimes better than their principles. This was the case with Descartes. He himself was a pious and loyal Catholic, but because he broke faith with Scholasticism in order to set philosophy, as he thought, on a more satisfactory basis, successive thinkers — eagerly wrested his principles to the prejudice and destruction of Catholic doctrine, so that the Catholic Church was obliged to place on the Index his writings, in 1663, sixty-seven years after his death. The teach- ing of Descartes’ doctrines was prohibited in the uni- versities of France by many royal decrees; several of the Dutch universities also prohibited Cartesianism. Descartes’ teachings then met with strong opposition from Rome, France and Holland. Orthodox Protes- tant clergymen, and especially the J esuits, made every effort to suppress it. Opposition, however, seemed to have only increased the devotion of Descartes’ admirers and disciples to his principles. Bossuet and Fenelon and many learned priests of the Oratory, pre-eminently “Pere _ Malbranche, whose system we shall see later on, be- came eager Cartesians. Among the Jansenists who were zealous propagators of Cartesianism were Arnauld, Nicole and Pascal. It was, however, the universities of Utrecht and Leyden in Holland that became the official homes of Cartesianism. Those dis- ciples of Descartes did not, however, merely propa- OCCASIONALISM 105 gate their master’s doctrines as they came from the mind of Descartes. They modified his teachings and gave a new development to his principles. The most famous of those developments of Cartesian principles are now known in the history of thought as — (1) The Occasionalism of Arnold Geulinex (1625- 1669), (2) The Ontologism of Malebranche (1638-1715), (3) The Pantheism of Baruch Spinoza (1632- 1677), (4) The Pre-Established Harmony of Leibnitz (1646-1716). Before entering into the exposition of the first of those systems, Occasionalism, we wish to repel the calumny of calling Descartes “the Luther of Philoso- phy”, which is so frequently repeated in histories of philosophy. Whatever may have been the errors of Descartes, it is a vile calumny, propagated through the ages, to say that Descartes did not respect the authority of the Catholic Church. In repelling the calumny, then, of calling Descartes “the Luther of Philosophy”, his own writings are decisive witnesses. Permit me to give some quotations: Before entering into his philosophical researches, the first rule he lays down for the guidance of his life is, “To obey the laws and customs of my country, ad- hering firmly to the faith in which, by the grace of God, I had been educated from my childhood.” (Meth. III.) In another passage he says: “The truths of faith have ever occupied the first place in my belief.” (Meth. I11.) Again among the two hundred and seven princi- ples which he lays down in his treatise, The Principles of Philosophy, he concludes with this: . 106 CARTESIANISM “However, I submit all my opinions to the author- ity of the Church”, and continues: “Nevertheless, lest I should presume too far, I af- firm nothing, but submit all these opinions to the authority of the Church and the judgment of the more sage.” In the face of these clear expressions of Descartes’ mind no one should be seduced into the belief that, from a religious point of view, there was any sympathy or affinity or shadow of likeness between Descartes and Luther. Such a supposition would be grievously injurious to the memory of Descartes who, as a loyal Catholic, would have shrunk from the thought of openly rebelling against the authority of the Catholic Church. There is no trait in his character which has anything in common with the insubordination and turbulence of Luther. _ Were it true that Descartes had flung out the stan- dard of revolt against the Catholic Church as Luther did, a modern English historian of philosophy,’ George Henry Lewis, the Agnostic husband of the famous “George Elliot”, would never have taunted him with timidity and servility. Just because Des- cartes was professedly a Catholic, Lewis belittles his character by saying: “Descartes was a great thinker; but having said this, we have almost exhausted the praise we can bestow upon him as a man. In disposi- tion he was timid to servility”. To Lewis, then, all intelligent Catholics are cowards because they do not apostacize. On that principle Satan would be Lewis’s greatest hero. This tendency of prejudiced minds to call the virtues of their neighbors vices is as old as Horace, and as new as the present-day bitter invec- tives of one class of Americans against the loyalty and Americanism of another class of their fellow citizens. OCCASIONALISM 107 It is true, however, that the successors of Descartes interpreted his system as favoring “Rationalism”. In a true sense, every reasonable man is a Rationalist, that is, he recognizes reason as one of the means of acquiring truth. Modern Rationalism is something quite different. The usually accepted meaning of Rationalism now is that the human reason is the sole source and final test of all truth. It proclaims the in- dependence or autonomy of reason as the natural and only means to all such knowledge and wisdom as man can achieve. Rationalism, therefore, claims that human reason is competent to discover and define religious truth without supernatural aid or divine revelation. “The complete independence or autonomy of reason is, indeed, the offspring of Protestantism”, says Paulsen, and continues, “to me it is beyond doubt that the fundamental tendency of primitive Protes- tantism has here been carried out in all clearness — Luther, too, found in the heart of the individual the unfailing source of truth”. (Cf. Donat, Freedom of Science, p. 88.) Rationalism, then, leaves no room for faith in the divine word, much less for mystery. It would feign regard doubtful or false what divine revelation proclaims certain and true. Modern Ration- alism is only another name for naturalism, because it rejects all knowledge and belief in the supernatural as mysticism and illusion. Rationalism or Naturalism - would, then, leave no room for divine faith and mys- teries. The following principle of Descartes, namely, “My first rule is never to accept anything as true, unless I evidently know it to be such” (Method II.), gave some color to the accusation that Descartes was a Rationalist in the sense just described. May we not, however, interpret this rule to apply only to naturally acquired knowledge, and the other quotations as wit- 108 CARTESIANISM nesses to the fact that he accepted truths supernatu- rally revealed, and respected unconditionally the authority of the Catholic Church. We shall now address ourselves to the exposition of the first system which developed in history from the principles of Descartes. This system is known in philosophy as “Occasionalism”, and the philosopher most prominently associated with its development was Arnold Geulinex. In the first place, who was Geulincx? Arnold Geulinex was born in Antwerp, Belgium (1625). He was 25 years of age, then, when Des- cartes died. An ardent disciple of Descartes, he was a student and afterwards Professor in the University of Lyon. At this period of his life he was a Catholic priest and member of the Oratory of Jesus. In the University of Lyon he studied philosophy and medi- cine, took his doctor’s degree, and for twelve years lectured in philosophy in his Alma Mater. He was obliged to leave his University, very likely on account of his curious philosophical views. The Jesuits, of course, are blamed for his expulsion from the Uni- versity. If the Jesuits never existed, any Catholic University would force him to quit. Columbia Uni- versity a short time ago forced out some of its pro- fessors for the same reason. But Mrs. Murray But- ler being, I believe, a Catholic, may be a Jesuit in dis- guise. The unfortunate Geulincx then apostatized and became a Calvinist, adopted the religion of Puri- tanism, the most extreme form of Protestantism, which Edmund Burke characterized as “the Protes- tantism of Protestantism; the dissidence of dissent”. He was, then, permitted to give private lectures in the University of Leyden, the city of Holland, which, when Geulinex was five years old, was the refugee home of the English Calvanists or Puritans before OCCASIONALISM . 109 their arrival in New England. In Leyden he was very oor. His contemporaries tell us that, were It not for the kindly assistance of some friends, he would have starved or begged his bread. He wrote several works — Brochures on Disputed Propositions, a Logic, and Ethics, a Physics and a Metaphysics. Geulincx’s contribution to philosophy was a fuller development of Descartes’ principles, which ulti- mately culminated in the system called “Occasional- ism’. What, then, is Occasionalism ? To understand the system we must first clearly grasp what is meant by an “occasion” and how it dif- fers from a “cause”, strictly so-called. ‘We are here concerned with what is termed “effi- cient cause’. That, then, according to Aristotle, is an “efficient cause” which is the source or principle of the activity which produces something, or, if you wish, “the agencies in nature which, by their activity, bring about a change which is called effect”. The sun is the cause of atmospheric heat, sugar is the cause of the sweetening of my coffee. An “occasion” is something very different. An “occasion” is any circumstance or combination of circumstances favorable to the action of a free cause. For instance, a forced sale may be the occasion for buying cheaply; night an occasion of theft; bad com- panionship an occasion of sin. But in these different cases “neither the forced sale” did the cheap buying; “the night” did not perpetrate the theft, nor does a “bad companion” commit the personal sin of his asso- ciate. Hence, an occasion is always spoken of in con- nection with a free cause or agent, and it differs from a cause in having no positive and direct influence on the production of the effect. An occasion has, how- 110 CARTESIANISM ever, a real, though indirect, influence on the produc- tion of the effect by soliciting and suggesting the de- termination of the efficient free cause to act. Having now understood that a “cause” is an agent that directly produces, by its own inherent activity, some happening or effect, as when we say the sun produces the effect of light and heat, and having understood also that as “occasion” is some favorable circumstance which is taken advantage of by some free cause to do or perform some action which it may not otherwise have thought of doing, as when I may take advantage of the occasion of passing an ice- cream parlor to treat myself and my friends to a plate of that palatable delicacy. Geulincx asked the ques- tion, as a good Cartesian, whether there existed in this world real and true created causes and real effects which are truly produced by these causes? Does matter, he asked, by its own activity, really act upon matter? When, for instance, H, S and O come together in certain proportions, do they really produce as active, causal agents the chemical com- pound known as He SO.? Again, Geulinex asked himself, do the beasts of the field, as genuine causes, produce certain effects by their own activity, as for example, should I be kicked by a mule, is it the mule that is the real cause of my wound? To turn to the vegetable kingdom, Geulinex was also curious to know whether real causes acted here, whether, for instance, the acorn is a real cause of the growth of the sturdy oak? Lastly, Geulinex also asked, can matter act upon spirit and spirit upon matter; can this chair, for in- stance, so act upon me as to determine in my mind the idea of a chair, or, again, is it really my will-action OCCASIONALISM 111 that initiates the movement of my arm and really causes me to walk, talk, sing or dance? What answer did Geulincx give to these different questions? Let us first take up the apparent action of matter upon matter. You recall that Descartes thought that the essence of matter was “extension” and extension alone. Now, extension of three dimensions, length, breadth and depth, is absolutely inactive. Extension is in itself stolidly inert. It can do nothing. It cannot even move. It is gagged by its own inherent inertia. If it is of its essence inert, it is absolutely impossible, there- fore, for matter that is void of all activity to produce a change or effect even in other matter. Hence, Geu- linex concluded very logically, from the essential in- ertness of matter as taught by Descartes, that it can never be a real and true efficient cause. But you will ask, what brought about the Hz SOs, if the elements H, S and O by their activities did not? Geulincx will promptly answer that the real, true cause of the H2 SOs: are not the elemental activities of H, S and O, as you imagine. The real invisible cause that is active in each case is God and God alone. God availed Himself, indeed, of the presence of the Hand O, and §S, as an “occasion” merely, but it was His omnipotent power that directly produced the effect H2SOs. Mere matter, on Cartesian princi- ples, could not do so. Hence, according to the Occasionalists, God is the sole cause of all the changes we observe in the king- dom of matter. Material objects which we, in our simplicity, think are causes are only “occasions” for God’s action. That is, God takes advantage of the presence of matter to produce of Himself, directly and immediately, as the one and only acting cause in 112 CARTESIANISM the material kingdom, certain effects. The force of gravitation, then, as Newton understood it, is a myth. It is only a name for God’s direct action. Chemical and physical forces are myths. God and God alone is the Universal Cause in the material world, and mat- ter is only His “occasion”. Hence, Occasionalism. The same is true of the animal and vegetable world. Animals, according to Descartes, and vegetables, too, are mere machines. Descartes calls those “Automa- tons”. They have no vital principle. Hence, they are not really living beings, but inanimate machines. Hence, all their actions are mechanical, and God directly gives them their push as He does to inani- mate matter. Beasts have no sensations proper. Ob- jects outside of the beasts impress them by the impact of mechanical motion of which God is the immediate cause. That motion is imparted to the animal nerves and muscles as to so many wheels in a machine, and they move and walk as a child’s Christmas toy would move, after the manner of an automaton or machine, and God is the only cause of their motion. It is the same for plants. Motion from outside, communicated in the first place by God, explains for Geulinex all the effects of growth and reproduction in the vegetable world. Just as the billiard player im- parts motion to the first ball, and this is communi- cated to the others, so does God impart, immediately as the one and only cause in existence, all the motion to the things of the material, animal and vegetable world, and by that means produces all their effects, of which He is the only cause, their presence being merely “occasions” for His action. We now come to “Occasionalism” as applied to man. You remember that though Descartes did not admit the existence of matter or that of his own body through the direct and immediate testimony of his OCCASIONALISM 113 senses, nor did he demonstrate legitimately, as he at- tempted to do, the existence of matter, yet he admitted finally that matter and his own body really existed, and was not personally an Idealist. Still, by assert- ing that the essence of the soul was “thought” and that the essence of matter was “extension’’, he set up between soul and body such a chasm of separation that he forever precluded the possibility of matter acting upon soul or soul upon matter, even when that matter was his own body. This absolute separation of soul and body in man is what is known in philosophy as the “exaggerated dualism of Descartes’. He left this dualism as a sad heritage to all succeeding gen- erations. It was upon this rock of “exaggerated dual- ism” that the philosophy of Descartes ultimately split. No philosopher of his school has really succeeded, and no philosopher can ever succeed, in bridging this chasm and restoring the union of body and soul in man, simply because Descartes’ dualism is an errone- ous interpretation of human nature, which, in every man is not two natures, but one complete nature, though its constituents are two incomplete substances, body and soul. Attempts have been made to establish unity in man. One school of philosophers restored indeed this unity by the drastic denial of the existence of the soul and became materialists, as Condillac. An- other school denied outright the existence of the body _ and became spiritualistic Idealists, as Berkeley. An- other school asserted the soul and body are only phases or aspects of the same thing, and became Pan- theists, as Spinoza. Geulincx, accepting the theory of Descartes that between the soul and body there can be no interaction, promptly concluded that soul can- not be the true and real cause of any effect wrought upon the body; nor can external matter, or even our own bodies, ever be a true cause of any effect or 114 . CARTESIANISM change wrought upon the soul. In other words, there are no secondary causes acting in the universe. There is only one cause that immediately and directly pro- duces every effect in the mineral, vegetable, animal and human world. That one cause is God. This is, briefly, the doctrine of Occasionalism. Now, there are two questions of paramount impor- tance for the student of the History of. Philosophy to understand: 1. From what principles of Descartes’ philoso- phy did the Occasionalists profess to deduce logically their curious system? 2. What were the serious consequences, for mor- ality and religion, that flowed logically from the system of Occasionalism? 1. In answer to the first question, recall that Des- cartes taught that the body and soul or spirit in man were two wholly distinct, opposite and independent substances; that Descartes confessed that he could form no clear and distinct idea of their wnion or mutual interaction. Yet their union and interaction Descartes seemed to admit. He even made desperate efforts to unite soul and body and explain their inter- action. His explanation was that he ascribed all the motions of the body, which was, like minerals, vege- tables and animals, a mere automaton, to the motions of what he called the “animal spirits”, a kind of subtle fluid that permeated the body, and met the soul in the “pineal gland” in the brain. Those “animal spir- its”, he asserted, somehow acted upon the soul, and the soul, in turn, gave at least direction to the animal spirits as a driver directs the movements of his horse. But the followers of Descartes did not fail to see that this explanation of the union of soul and of body, and of their mutual interaction, contradicts his already OCCASIONALISM 115 established principle that spirit could not unite with body or act upon body. Hence, spirit could not act upon the “animal spirits”, which were material and of a bodily nature. The only way left, then, to Des- cartes’ followers was to call in the direct intervention of God to unite soul and body, and bring about their interaction by a miracle of His omnipotent power. God alone, then, according to the Occasionalists, is the one and only direct cause of the union and inter- action between soul and body. Thus an act of our will (and the extreme Occasionalists, like the Calvin- istic Geulinex, taught that even our will was not free, but was moved necessarily by God) is for God merely an occasion for His effecting a movement in our limbs, like the raising of our arm, walking or talking, etc.; and an impression made mechanically on our senses is an occasion for Him to arouse in our soul a corres- ponding perception or idea of an external object. To the mind of Geulincx, the transition from the prin- ciple of Occasionalism, as applicable to soul and body, to the application of the same principle to the interaction of all other apparent agencies in creation, was very easy. If God is the only cause of the union and interaction of soul and body, He is also the only cause of the union of bodies among themselves. To help out the logical validity of this transition Geu- _linex introduced into Cartesianism his famous, though curious, principle that “nothing acts that does not know how it acts”. Hence, in all creation there is only one cause, the first cause, — God, and there are no secondary or created causes. This conclusion brought philosophy to the verge of Pantheism. The Jew of Amsterdam, Spinoza, a contemporary of Geulincx, promptly deduced, as we shall see, the conclusion of -Pantheism. It is a strange fact in the history of thought that every serious deviation of philosophical 116 CARTESIANISM systems from Scholasticism sooner or later developed into some form of Pantheism. 2. What were the consequences of Occasionalism in the field of Morality and Religion? Those withering consequences have, or ought to have, for Americans a peculiar, because a domestic, interest. Because “Occasionalism” formed a philo- sophical basis on which rested the Calvinistic Puri- tanism of the early days of New England. If God, then, does everything both in me and in all other created things, then I can do absolutely noth- ing. I am incapable of action, for I am not the cause of my actions. I have no will, much less a free will. What, then, is the use of my wishing to be virtuous when I cannot even wish or will to be virtuous or to serve God. If I give up my life for the faith, or sell all my goods to feed the poor, it is not I who do those things. If I shoot a man or commit a burglary, or any crime, it is not I who do those things. God, ac- cording to the Occasionalists, does them all. That is the loathsome doctrine of Occasionalism, as it is the execrable doctrine of Puritanism— God caused men to sin, foreordains or predestines them to sin, that He might punish them. The Puritans believe they were the chosen of God, foreordained and predestined to virtue without the slightest effort of their own. They were, by the nature of things, effortless. The only rea- sonable attitude, therefore, to assume in life is an absolute inactivity, a surrender of oneself to the un- avoidable current of inexorable Fate. “Ubi nihil vales, nihil velis’. (Cf. New England Thought, Cath. Mind, Oct. 22, 1914.) No philosophical system of history has ever attributed to the divine Being a character so loathsome and execrable as did Puritan- ism”. (Moses Coit Tyler, Amer. Lit.) The same may be said of Occasionalism. This doctrine opens OCCASIONALISM LIZ the way to the complete annihilation of all created things, because if creatures cannot do anything, why should they exist? Cuapter VII. ON TOLOGISM The restless mind of man cannot but press a prin- ciple to the utmost limit of its implications even though centuries should intervene between the prem- ises and the conclusion. The embryonic principles implanted in the bosom of any new system of thought rarely reach their maturity during the lifetime of its founder. They usually await the process of mental incubation in the minds of disciples and followers of the original founder before their full significance is fully devel- oped and made manifest. If the original principles of the founder are true, they will bring forth fruit wholesome, sound and beautiful. If these same orig- inal principles are false, by their evil fruits you shall know them. Hence, it is that according to the second method of criticism heretofore indicated, the truth or false- hood of the principles embosomed in Descartes’ phil- osophy must stand or fall by the wholesomeness or poisonous character of the conclusions that have been logically deduced from them by his admirers and dis- ciples. The “Occasionalism” of Geulinex was the first fruit of Occasionalism in the order of time. Its interpre- . tation of nature may be reduced to the simple for- mula— all the created beings in the world, whether matter or spirit, are inert, devoid of all inherent activ- ity of themselves. They are incapable of acting upon one another because they cannot, of themselves, act of 120 CARTESIANISM all. Hence, there are no created causes whatsoever. God is the only cause. What a strange conception of nature such a theory sets before our vision! It sug- gests that all created nature, be it matter or spirit, is, as it were, in cold storage, and frozen into inactivity and inertia. Remark that, as a philosophical system, it suggests the denial of free-will and this denial of free-will was at the basis of the Calvinistic or Puritan religion, the religion of New England in Colonial days, and the religion of Cromwell’s round heads in England. It involves the fearful doctrine of Calvin- istic Predestination. If the multiplicity of material things as well as human souls have no real activity of their own, distinct from the activity of their First Cause— God, on what ground could we sup- pose them to have a real ewistence of their own, distinct from God? Would not the logical inference be. justified that material and spiritual beings have no real existence in themselves, but are all merely phases or aspects of God? Because, as far as we are concerned, we can know objects because their actions come under our observation. But since Geulincx assures us that the only active agent that is at the back of all material objects and souls is God alone, then we ought reasonably conclude that God alone exists, and what we call matter and souls have no existence at all in themselves. There is, therefore, in existence only one substance and that is divine. This is the formula that expresses Pantheism. Within thirty years after the death of Descartes, this conclusion, which was latent in his system, rap- idly matured, through the two-fold stages of “Occa- sionalism” and “Ontologism’’, into the rank and open Pantheism of Baruch Spinoza. No wonder, then, that some Protestants, Jesuits and other Catholic philoso- phers were, from the beginning, keen to perceive the ONTOLOGISM 121 fatal consequences that were implicitly contained in the principles of Descartes. Nor are we surprised that six years after his death the Synod of Dortrecht (1656) forbade theologians to adopt Descartes’ sys- tem, that Rome put his writings on the Index “until _ corrected” (1663), and in 1671 the exposition of Des- cartes’ doctrine was prohibited by royal decree in the University of Paris. Before setting before you, however, the ultimate development of Cartesianism into Pantheism of Spi- noza, we shall be obliged to give a brief exposition of the second development of Descartes’ principles on the onward march toward the precipice of Monism or Pantheism. This second stage is called “Ontologism”, and its father and founder was the famous Nicholas Malbranche. It must be remembered that he, too, like Geulinex, was an Occasionalist. Nicholas Male- branche was born in Paris August 6, 1688. The son of a royal officer, he was, of a family of many chil- dren, the youngest and weakest. Indeed, he was so afflicted in his early manhood by a nausea of the stom- ach that for twenty years every attempt to take food was painful. He was unusually tall and thin, and, un- fortunately, deformed by a curvature of the spine. His head alone was well developed, his eyes fiery, and the expression of his countenance was mild and amiable. He bore his afflictions with great patience, lived temperately, cultivated his mind in peace and quietness, and thereby preserved his life to the age of seventy-seven. Destined for the priesthood, he stud- ied philosophy in the College of De Marche, and took his theological course in the Sorbonne. Like Des- cartes, his studies left him dissatisfied. With these feelings of dissatisfaction, he became, at the age of twenty-one, a priest of the Oratory of Jesus. Not until Malebranche was twenty-six years did he himself 122 CARTESIANISM or anybody else discover his philosophical talents. It was a mere accident that revealed to him his latent abilities. Walking along the Rue St. Jacque, he en- tered a book-store. His attention was called to the latest literary novelty, The Treatise of Man, by Descartes. He took the book home, read it, and his enthusiasm and admiration were aroused. For the first time he felt the charm of philosophy. He had to put the book down more than once, because his throb- bing heart would not let him read further. At last he felt his mind alienated from all other subjects, and for ten.years was completely absorbed in the study of Descartes. At the end of this period he published his famous book, The Investigation of Truth, which rapidly went through six editions. Other books fol- lowed, and so much was he admired that Buffon called him “the divine Malebranche”’. Despite his love of quiet, the rest of his life was occupied in bitter controversies with the Jansenist Arnauld, with the Jesuits, with Fenelon and Bossuet. He lived in his cell in the Oratory in such deep retire- ment for half a century that he was called the silent and meditative man. Many distinguished visitors to Paris paid their respects to him. A story is told that during his last illness he was visited by Berkeley, the Irish philosopher, and the eager conversation that fol- lowed about the existence of matter hastened his death. He died after four months of suffering, Octo- ber 18, 1715. What, then, was the system of Ontologism of which Malebranche was the founder and of whom the first English translator (1694) of his well-known work, The Investigation of Truth (1675), Richard Sault, says: “The very faults of this great man have some- thing in them extremely beautiful, and the jewel is so dazzling that the flaws are scarce discerned”? ONTOLOGISM 123 Unlike “Occasionalism”, Ontologism is not an ex- planation of the causes of the manifold and varied changes observed around us; it is a theory, rather, of knowledge or the origin of our ideas. Malebranche, with remarkable brevity, enumerates all the possible explanations to account for the origin of our ideas in B.III., C.1., of his Investigation of Truth. He writes: “We are assured that it is abso- lutely necessary that the ideas we have of bodies, and of all other objects which we perceive not by them- selves, either proceed (1) from these bodies or these objects (Scholasticism), or else that (2) our souls have the power of producing these ideas (Subjective Idealism) ; or that (8) God created them with our souls (Descartes’ innate ideas) ; or that God (4) pro- duces them every time that we think of any object (Occasionalism) ; or, in fine, that our soul is (5) united with a perfect Being which in general includes all the perfection of created beings’. Now, Malebranche rejects the four first explana- tions and adopts the last, to wit, that the soul is inti- mately united with the perfect Being of God, Who includes all the perfection of Created things; that our minds, therefore, “see all things in God”. He teaches, then, the extraordinary doctrine that our ideas of objects around us, or within us, are not derived in any way from these objects themselves, as we suppose, but that we see God by our intellect directly and im- mediately, by an intuitive vision, and in God we see all things. Farther on in his book he explains more in detail the curious origin of our ideas in the soul. “All beings, he says, “can only be present to our mind because God is present to it, that is, He who includes all things in the simplicity of His being”. (B. IIl., C. VI.) Descartes, you remember, made 124 CARTESIANISM consciousness the discoverer of ideas that were inborn or innate in our own souls. He looked into himself to gaze at ideas already formed and representative, as he thought, of the things outside of us. Scholasticism looks out upon objects and teaches that it is these ob- jects that are, somehow, the determining causes of our ideas. Malebranche neither looks into his soul, nor out upon objects, but looks wp to God, “Who”, he says, “is very strictly united to our souls by His presence, so that we may say that He is the place of spirits, as space is the place of bodies... .” “It is cer- tain, then’, he continues, “that the mind may see what there is in God, which represents created things”. Malebranche rejected Descartes’ innate ideas, be- cause, as he argues, his theory was simpler, and “God”, he says, “never does, by very difficult means, what may be done by a plain, easy way”. (B. IIL., C. VI.) When we know objects, then, Malebranche’s theory is, that we do not know them through our per- ception of ideas within owr soul, representative of outer objects, as Descartes taught, or by perceiving them directly in themselves, as the Scholastics teach, but we know them by contemplating the ideas of them in God, —the Malebranchian mystical theory of On- tologism. As a theory, then, to explain the origin of our ideas, Ontologism professes to be a logical deduction from the same principle of Cartesianism that produced Occasionalism. Hence, the Ontologists taught the doctrine of Occasionalism to explain all the effects produced in material nature, which ordinary com- mon-sense men attribute to the efficiency of natural or secondary causes. But since body and soul, whose essence is “thought” and “extension” respectively, cannot interact on each other, it is impossible for the idea of body or extension ONTOLOGISM 125 to arise in the soul from the determining causality, in any sense, of bodies themselves. The idea of exten- sion of bodies is in the mind of God alone, and we know the ideas of created things only in God. How, then, do we invest material objects with sensuous qualities? Malebranche gives this curious answer. He says: “But though I say that we see in God the things that are material and sensible, it must be observed that I do not say we have a sensation of them in God, but only that it is from God, who acts in us; for God knows sensible things, but He does not fee] them. When we perceive anything that is sensi- ble, sensation and pure idea is in our perception (sub- jective). Sensation is a modification of our soul, and it is God Who causes it in us. And He may cause it, though He has it not, because He sees, in the idea He has of our soul, that it is capable of it. As for the idea that is joined to sensation, it is in God we see it, because it is His pleasure to discover it to us. And God joins sensation to the idea, when objects are present, to the end that we may have such sensations and passions as we ought to have in relation to them’. (B.IIL., C. VI., Investig. of Truth.) Analyzing this novel doctrine of Malebranche, we find that he teaches the following strange doctrines: (1) “We see in God the things that are material’. Hence we do not see or perceive at all material things in themselves. We perceive material things, because our minds, having a direct and _ intuitive vision of God, perceive the ideas of those material things in God. The divine ideas are the prototypes or models or patterns of material things. They repre- sent material things. Hence in perceiving the pat- terns of material things, we perceive those material things in their patterns or models. (2) “When we perceive anything that is sensible, Malebranche says, 126 CARTESIANISM “sensation and pure idea is in our perception”. That, of course, we admit. It is the teaching of our ex- perience. The pure, intellectual idea is according to our author, not, however, our idea, but the idea of God which we contemplate. But whence comes the sensation that accompanies the pure idea? “I do not say’, says Malebranche, “we have a sensation of them in God, but it (7. e., the sensation) is from God, who acts in us”. The sensation, then, that accompanies the pure idea is produced by God in our souls. “Sen- sation”, he says, “is a modification of our soul, and it is God who causes it in us”. Here Malebranche reveals his Occasionalism. If the sensations, then, of color, sound, heat, taste and smell, etce., are merely modi- fications of our souls, known to consciousness alone, how can we ever know that there is anything in ob- jects that correspond to them? Consciousness can never know anything outside of us, but only our own subjective experiences. And the difficulty of knowing whether anything outside of us corresponds to our sensations is aggravated by Malebranche and the Car- tesian Occasionalists, because they teach that bodies or material things are not even the determining cause of our sensations. “For it is God”, Malebranche teaches, “who acts in us and causes our sensations’. Some philosophers, even Catholic philosophers, and many scientists, hold that color, sound, etc., as such, are not objectively in bodies as we imagine them to be, but, at least, all philosophers and scientists, who are not Idealists, admit that those qualities are caus- ally, if not formally, in bodies, that is, bodies cause those sensations in us. But Malebranche would deny even a causal existence of those qualities in bodies, since it is God who causes our sensations. It is only eatension which is identified with bodies, because it is, according to Malebranche and the Car- ONTOLOGISM 127 tesians, the essence of bodies that exist outside of us. Yet we do not perceive, according to Malebranche, extension or bodies in themselves. We contemplate the idea of extension in God, Malebranche teaches, and since the divine idea of extension represents, or is the pattern of created extension or body, we know cre- ated extension or bodies outside of us and of God, because we contemplate its pure idea in God. Yet Malebranche maintains that when we contemplate the divine idea of extension, we do not form in our minds any human idea of the divine idea. The idea of ex- tension or body which we contemplate in God serves all the purposes of our knowing bodies outside of us. But how it is possible to contemplate an idea in God without forming in our souls our own idea of that idea is difficult to understand unless we are ourselves identical with God. But to make ourselves identical with God would, of course, be Pantheism, and there was not wanting future philosophers who drew this Pantheistic conclusion. Finally, all knowledge to Malebranche is a divine revelation, and ultimately rests on revelation. We acquire no knowledge directly and naturally of things around us. “Because”, says Malebranche, “it is His (God’s) pleasure to discover it (2.é., the divine idea of a thing) to us’. But the divine ideas were present in God throughout all eternity. How do we know that God actually created the things of the universe according to the model of His ideas? If we do not know that creation took place, we may contemplate God’s ideas and yet not know that anything actually created corresponds with them. Malebranche and the Ontologists were driven to answer: ‘““We know creation has taken place from the revelation in Genesis’. Thus it is obvious that all our knowledge depends ultimately on revelation, that it is not knowledge strictly so- 128 CARTESIANISM called, but only belief or faith. This doctrine destroys all possibility of naturally acquired knowledge and opens the way to Fideism, which subsequent philoso- phers have advocated. (4) We have in the above quotation a corroboration of this doctrine of Fideism, or that all knowledge is faith. Because Malebranche, in his explanation of why God produces sensations in our souls, says: “and God joins sensation to the idea when objects are present, to the end that we may believe them as they are, and that we may have such sensations and passions as we ought to have in rela- tion to them’. Hence, even if our sensations gave us any insight into the qualities of bodies, we could not know those sensuous qualities of bodies, but only be- lieve or have faith in their existence. Endless are the novel aberrations of the human mind. Descartes’ phil- osophy and its development are for the most part discredited to-day, but the passion for novelties in thought which he inaugurated by breaking with the past quickly developed into unbridled “freedom of thought” that has expressed itself in modern times in a passion for novelty and change, which is called progress, whereas, in reality, the continuous abandon- ment of what we have previously gained to adopt what is entirely new is not progress, but destruction. Cuapter VIII. THE PRE-ESTABLISHED HARMONY OF LEIBNITZ AND THE PANTHEISM OF SPINOZA The restless pendulum of human thought is con- tinually swinging from one extreme to the other. In the history of philosophy, it is a common-place to observe that every novel intellectual movement seems to be followed by a reaction. Critics, in their indigna- tion and zeal for truth, repudiate the exaggerations; the new leaders swing to the opposite extreme. Hence, the Cartesians assure us that we can know truth only by the exercise of pure intellect or reason. The Empiricists, on the other hand, confidently assert that reason is to be discredited and that all knowledge is sense-knowledge. Materialists maintain that noth- ing exists but matter; Spiritual Idealists are just as dogmatic in saying there is nothing but spirit and the modifications of spirit. Thus it was that in the last development of Cartesianism, which we examined, the Ontologists assured us that we have an immediate vision of God, that we see Him face to face, while the modern Agnostics, Spencer, Kant, etc., are just as cock-sure that the human mind is incapable of know- ing anything about God at all. Leibnitz became the champion of a pluralistic universe. He taught that substances were infinitely many. Spinoza, on the con- trary, was frankly Pantheistic, and became for all time the protagonist of the principle that “there is only one substance and that that substance is divine”, 130 CARTESIANISM but in a sense entirely different from that which Christians attribute to the Divine Being. It is our present purpose to give, in the first place, a brief exposition of the system of Leibnitz, which is known in the history of thought as “Pre-Established Harmony,” and, secondly, an explanation of the Pantheism of Spinoza. This Pantheistic system of Spinoza reveals the final development and culmina- tion of the embryonic conclusions that were, from the - first, latent in the principles of Descartes. Who, then, was Leibnitz? Leibnitz (the name is Polish or Bohemian) was, perhaps, the greatest of the Cartesians. He ranks — not merely as a philosopher, but a courtier and a man of affairs, who took a leading part in the political life of his time. He was, besides, one of the greatest mathematical geniuses of the world, sharing the honor of inventing Differential Calculus with Newton. He was the founder of German philosophy. Gottfried Wilhelm Leibnitz (1646-1716) was born at Leipsic, where his father was Professor of Moral Philosophy. He studied there and in Jena and received his doctor’s degree at the age of twenty. He was destined for the legal profession and entered the diplomatic service of the Elector of Mayence. In this capacity he travelled as member of an embassy to Paris and London. He paid a visit to Spinoza at the Hague, and afterwards became court librarian at Hanover. His manifold ac- tivities led him to make frequent visits to Paris, Vienna, Berlin, and Italy. The Pope offered him the headship of the Vatican library, a position which, of course, he declined, as its acceptance would have re- quired him to become a Catholic. At the instance of the Prussian Queen, Sophie Charlotte, a princess of great culture, he wrote his famous work, Theodicy or Natural Theology. His spirit of conciliation to LEIBNITZ AND SPINOZA 131 bring together opposing schools of thought inspired him with an effort to reconcile the Protestant and Catholic churches. He was one of the most learned men of his time, and “in the union of productive and universal knowledge, Aristotle alone’, says Alexan- der, “can be compared to him”. His chief works were his Theodicy (1710), Monadology (1714), Nouveaux Essais sur ?Enten- dement Humane (1765). In this essay his criticism of the Empiricism of Locke embodied in the fol- lowing statement, “Nihil est in intellectu, quod non fuerit in sensu, misi intellectus ipse’”’, is famous. He died in Vienna, in 1716, loaded with honors. The lat- ter part of his life is said to be embittered by his quar- rels with the Newtonians. What, then, was the curious doctrine of “Pre- Established Harmony”? Leibnitz, the last of the great Cartesians, was an original thinker, conversant not only with the philos- ophy of Descartes, but learned in Plato and Aristo- tle, and well acquainted with Scholasticism, of which he spoke in the highest praise. The founder of phil- osophy in Germany, the dream of his life was to bring once more together into unity the different religious bodies. He introduced into Cartesianism many ideas inspired by Plato. It was remarked by Schlegel that every philosopher is in bent of mind either a Platon- ist or Aristotelian. The fundamental difference be- tween their philosophies is that while Aristotle and his followers, the Schoolmen, hold that all our knowl- edge in some way or other begins in sense knowledge, “nihil est in intellectu, nist prius fuerit in sense’, be- ing an axiom of Aristotle and Scholasticism, Plato and the Platonists maintain that the mind contains, as its original endowment, ideas and principles which are not caused by external objects, but which are only 132 CARTESIANISM aroused or awakened by our different sensations. | Hence, Leibnitz, admitting, like Descartes, innate ideas, was a Platonist. Leibnitz likewise accepted the well-known Car- . tesian doctrine of the impossibility of any interaction between soul and body—the famous dualism of the Cartesians. Yet Leibnitz, as his system reveals, was not an Occasionalist. Soul and body seem to interact. How, then, does Leibnitz explain their apparent in- teraction? Already we have reviewed the Occasion- alistic and Ontologistic answer.. What was Leibnitz’ solution of the same problem? It is known in philoso- phy as the theory of “Pre-Established Harmony”. In what did the solution of “Pre-Established Har- mony” consist? It was a most ingenious theory; yet it had little influence on Modern thought. It was too far-fetched to be considered probable, and too intri- cate to be appealing. The ultimate, constituent elements of every being in the whole range of existence are what Leibnitz called “monads’”’. These monads are not like atoms, that is, small masses, whose essence, in the Cartesian system, was extension, indefinitely divisible. The monads are, on the contrary, simple, unextended substances re- plete with energy always active. They are points of force or metaphysical points. Hence, force is sub- stance and substance is force. Leibnitz rejected the mass-atom. Because, Leibnitz argued, there must be simple, indivisible substances since there are com- pounds, “‘for the compound is only a collection or aggregate of simples’. (Monadology.) Each monad, even those that constitute the ulti- mate principles of ordinary matter, are, in the strange teaching of Leibnitz, spirits or souls, or at least anal- ogous to spirits. LEIBNITZ AND SPINOZA 133 There are no soulless bodies, no dead matter. The inorganic does not exist. Every particle of dust is peopled with a multitude of living beings. Every portion of matter is like a pond filled with fish or a garden full of plants. “Whence it appears’, said Leibnitz, “that there is a world of creatures of living things, of animals or souls, in the minutest portion of matter. Every particle of matter may be conceived as a garden of plants or as a pond full of fishes’. (Monad.) Every monad is endowed with perception and ap- petite, but in different degrees of perfection. The monads, which are the ultimate constituents of what we call inorganic matter and vegetables, though en- dowed with perception and appetite, are yet uncon- scious. In animals, at least, one monad, which gives unity to the whole being, becomes to a certain degree conscious. The souls of men as monads become more perfectly self-conscious. Hence, human souls are en- dowed with what Leibnitz calls apperception or con- sciousness in opposition to perception which, as such, is unconscious. All created monads are, according to the degree of their perfection, a likeness or image of the one in- finite, uncreated monad — God the Creator. Hence, all created monads are graded according to their perfection, so that they rise in the scale of perfec- tion from the lowest monads, which constitute mat- ter, to the highest monad. God is the first, uncreated, conscious, infinitely perfect monad. Human souls are next in rank. Material substances, including the body of man, hold the lowest place. Yet even those mate- rial monads are spirits or souls, though devoid of con- sciousness. “All simple substances or created mo- nads”, Leibnitz says, “may be called souls”. 134 CARTESIANISM There are no two monads alike. Their difference arises from the fact that though each monad repre- sents the universe yet each represents it differently. This difference consists in the degree of clearness of the representation. There is no really transient action between the monads. No monad acts upon another. “The monads”, says Leibnitz, “have no windows through which anything can enter or go forth”. Each monad, through its power of perception, whether conscious or unconscious, reflects, as in a mir- ror, more or less perfectly all that is taking place within the other monads of the entire universe. Each monad is a little, independent universe in itself — “a microcosm imaging the macrocosm”’. One of the most extraordinary doctrines of Leib- nitz was the immortality of all things in the universe. Matter, vegetables, animals are, like the souls of men, immortal. Because their ultimate constituents —the soul-monads — are immortal. Nothing begins to be except by creation, nothing can end except by anni- hilation— “There is no way”, Leibnitz said, “in which a simple substance can begin naturally, since it could not be formed by composition. Therefore, we may say that monads can neither begin nor end in any other way than all at once; that is to say, they cannot begin except by creation, nor end except by annihilation”. (Monad.) Hence, according to Leib- nitz, all monads are naturally immortal, like the souls of men. Hence, pre-existence as well as post-exis- tence must be conceded both to animals and to men. The union of soul and body, a problem which nei- ther Descartes nor the Cartesians succeeded in ex- plaining, presented itself to Leibnitz for solution. How did Leibnitz solve this problem? The body, Leibnitz taught, is an aggregate of liv- ing soul-monads, each an active living force. But LEIBNITZ AND SPINOZA 135 since each monad of this aggregate is immaterial and, therefore, simple, it follows that a collection of any number of simple substances could never explain the phenomenon of an extended mass. But the phenom- enon of extended mass appears to exist in bodies. How does Leibnitz explain this phenomenon of ex- tension which our body seems to present? This phe- nomenon of extended mass, Leibnitz taught, was an illusion of sensuous perception. Matter or extended mass was not really objective. Matter is only some- thing present in sensation in a confused representa- tion. Space and time are also nothing real, but only ideal things. Our confused sensuous perception of the collection of monads composing a body is regarding as a continuous unity something, perhaps, like the illusion of perceiving the swiftly moving spokes of a wheel as a continuous unity. The soul is a monad quite independent of the body, yet dominating the collection of monads that constitute the body, because of the superior clearness with which it represents what is taking place in the body monads. The soul and body of each person have been so created and mated by God as to run like two clocks, so excellently con- structed that, without needing to be regulated by each other, they show exactly the same time. The changes, then, whether they be ideas or motions arising in each individual’s soul, are in exact harmony with the same series of changes arising in each individual’s body. Thus did Leibnitz hold that all phenomena of per- ception and volition are adequately accounted for. Such is the ingenious theory of the Pre-Established Harmony of Leibnitz. Leibnitz gives this account of his curious theory: He says, “I cannot help coming to this notion that God created the soul in such a manner at first that it should represent within itself all the simultaneous 136 CARTESIANISM changes in the body; and that he made the body also in such a manner that it must of itself do what the soul wills”. Leibnitz may be said to be an exaggerated opti- mist. Because he taught that this created world is the best world God could create. God, the Creator, he argued, is infinitely intelligent, omnipotent and infi- nitely good. When God created the universe, then, he gave expression to the best possible combination of possible existences, and, therefore, created the best possible world. Not that the world is absolutely per- fect, but it is the most perfect among all possible worlds. It may be well to contrast the outstanding differ- ences between the system of Leibnitz and that of Des- cartes. They are — (1) Leibnitz taught that matter is not, as Descar- tes maintained, an inert, dormant, inactive mass, whose essence is extension or length, breadth and depth. Leibnitz maintained, on the contrary, that the ultimate constituents of matter, namely, monads, were intrinsically active points of force. All changes in them proceeded from an internal principle. Leib- nitz, therefore, rejected the mechanical theory of Des- cartes to explain all the changes in the material uni- verse. Extension, then, which in Descartes’ system held such an important place, was to Leibnitz a mere sensuous illusion, which had no objective reality, be- cause each and all things were spirits or souls. (2) Leibnitz was not an Occasionalist like Geu- lincx and Malebranche. Leibnitz rejected Occasional- ism, because it involved an endless series of miracles. (3) According to Descartes some ideas (pure con- cepts) are innate, according to Leibnitz all ideas are innate. According to Locke, as we shall afterwards see, no ideas are innate. LEIBNITZ AND SPINOZA 137 We shall complete the chief systems that developed from the principles of Descartes by an exposition of the Pantheism of Baruch Spinoza. The developments with Descartes’ own system are known as Cartesian- ism. Baruch or Benedict Spinoza or De Spinoza, the Jew of Amsterdam, was born November 24th in that city, 1632, and died in the Hague, 1677. His parents were Jewish-Portuguese extraction. His teacher in Hebrew was the celebrated Rabbi Marteira, who in- troduced him to the study of the Talmud and the Bible. He studied Latin also under the noted phy- sician, Franz von der Edde. Brought up in the He- brew faith, he was expelled from the Jewish com- munity on account of his “frightful heresies”. Though interested in Christianity and the life and the teach- ing of Christ, he never formally accepted the Chris- tian faith. He lived in great retirement, engaged in his philosophical pursuits, took lodgings with a land- lady of the Calvanistic creed, and supported himself by the polishing of lenses. He lived a frugal life. He was not without friends, but from them he would never accept monetary aid. He was called to the pro- fessor’s chair at Heidelberg, but declined, on the ground that he might be there hindered in the full liberty of thought. Of a delicate constitution, he died of consumption at the age of forty-four. His writings are: The Principles of the Philoso- phy of Descartes; Tractatus Theologico-Politicus ; Tractatus de Intellectus Emandatione; Epistolae; Treatise Concerning God and Man; Ethica— In this latter work is contained his philosophical system. Diverse opinions have been entertained of Spinoza. Dugald Stewart sees in his philosophy black Athe- ism, Novalis, a moral and honest man. “Avoid what is evil”, he says, “because it-is opposite to my nature 138 CARTESIANISM and draws me away from the knowledge of and love of God”. The Pantheistic doctrine of Spinoza took for its starting-point Descartes’ definition of Swhbstance. “By substance”, says Descartes, “we can conceive nothing else than a thing which exists in such a way as to stand in need of nothing beyond itself in order to its existence”. (Prin. of Phil., Pt. I., 51.) Des- cartes distinguished the uncreated (substantia a se) from created substance (substantia ab alio). But Spinoza, casting aside Descartes’ created substance, adopted the first. Thus did Descartes’ peculiar con- cept of substance leave the way wide open for Spinoza to assert that, since the Descartes’ substance “stands in need of nothing beyond itself in order to its exis- tence”, there can exist only one substance — God. Hence, Spinoza, following closely on Descartes, thus defines substance — “I mean”, he says, “by substance that which is in itself, and is conceived through itself ; in other words, that of which a conception can be formed, independently of any other conception”. Spinoza argued that from this definition of substance the following conclusions logically follow: (1) that substance has no cause, otherwise it should be conceived as dependent on its cause, and thus would not be “independent of any other conception”. (2) that substance is infinite, because if it had limitations, those limitations would demand a cause independent of the original sub- stance, and hence this latter could not be conceived as independent. Hence, there can be only one substance, be- cause its infinitude excludes all limitations. (3 —" LEIBNITZ AND SPINOZA 139 The only substance that exists, Spinoza con- cludes, is God, and there is no other sub- stance in existence besides God. Therefore, God is the same as the world and nature. There is only one substance, then, in all ex- istence, and that substance is divine. This is the fundamental statement of Pantheism. There is, therefore, no plurality of substances as we imagine. Every particular substance, which seems to us to exist, whether it be spirit or matter, is only a modification, aspect or attribute of the one uni- versal substance— God. All things, therefore, are identified with God. They are God. “I think that I have shown sufficiently”, writes Spinoza (Prop., XVI.), “that from the supreme power or infinite nature of God, all things have resulted, or do, ever with the same necessity, result, in the same manner in which, from everlasting to everlasting, it results from the nature of a triangle, that its three angles are equal to two right angles”. “Thought”, which consti- tutes, according to Descartes, the spiritual world, and “extension”, which constitutes the material world, are both attributes of the divine substance. Hence, the “exaggerated dualism” of the Cartesians is reduced to unity. This one, all-embracing substance is imper- sonal, because it does not act intelligently for any purpose, nor is it free, except in the Spinozian sense, of not being dependent. It evolves itself from its own inner necessity. All its attributes proceed from it with the same necessity as geometrical properties flow from the nature of a circle or triangle. Hence, there is no freedom of the human will, because human beings are merged in God. The laws of nature are absolutely immutable, hence, miracles are impossible. There is no immortality of the soul, because there is 140 CARTESIANISM no soul existing in itself outside of God. Hence, we ourselves and all things around us, are only like tiny wavelets in the great ocean of substance; we roll our little course and sink to rise no more. There is no God independent of the universe and no creation. Such is the theory of our modern pagans and atheists. Such is the theory towards which Cartesianism logically conducts us, such is the despairing theory to which much of modern thought leads. Not many years ago in New England the school of Transcendentalists, whose leaders were Emerson, Bronson Alcott and Theodore Parker, were Panthe- ists. Bronson Alcott, for instance, once said: “T am God. I am greater than God. God is one of | my ideas. I therefore contain God; greater is the container than the contained. Therefore, am I greater than God.” And again, “Man is a rudiment and embryon God”. Josiah Royce, late Professor of Philosophy in Har- vard, who quotes Spinoza so often with approval, was frankly Pantheistic or Monistic in his teaching. He writes, for instance, “There is one absolute World- Self; who embraces and is all reality, whose conscious- ness includes, and infinitely transcends, our own’. (The Spirit of Modern Philosophy, p. 849.) The extreme Evolutionists who assert that matter alone is, and that it is eternal, ever evolving itself by itself into the multiplicity of forms and beings around us, are, like Haeckel, Materialistic Monists or Pan- theists, as Professor Royce was an Idealistic Monist, like Hegel and Fichte. Truly the errors of Descartes and the Cartesians possess a logical fecundity in pro- ducing other errors. When the foundations of a building are rotten, it is not likely that the upper stories will be stable. CHAPTER IX. SOME PRACTICAL LESSONS TO BE LEARNED FROM CARTESIANISM Many practical people imagine that philosophers are always thinking in the clouds and that the princi- ples they set forth have no bearing on practical life. It is true that philosophers work out their principles in the upper regions of lonely thought, as the rain is formed in the silent clouds. But just as the rain falls to earth and moistens unto growth its hidden seeds, so do the principles of men of thought soon find their way into the minds of the men in the street, mould their convictions and thereby set in motion the springs of human action. Should those principles be sound and wholesome, so will the actions of the masses, which are the natural fruitage of those principles, be likewise sound and wholesome. Should those principles, on the other hand, be unsound and false, they will ex- press themselves in a crop of destructive and evil ac- tions. As a general, who is usually invisible to the great masses of troops, directs the movements of the army, so philosophical principles of some kind, whether true or false, are the invisible inspiring mo- tives of all great movements in history. Now, Cartesianism, which we have just studied, affords a practical and striking example of the appli- cation of the above principles. Descartes, no doubt, was oneof the great minds of alltime. He, during his own lifetime, proposed and popularized certain ger- _ minal principles, the logical implications of which his 142 CARTESIANISM disciples forthwith developed into the further systems of Occasionalism (Geulinex), Ontologism (Male- branche), both of which were gradually shaping and bringing to full maturity that hideous synthesis of all contradictions which finally emerged from the em- bryonic principles of Descartes—the monster of Pantheism. Pantheism is practical Atheism, a word hated of all men, a doctrine that is destructive of a Personal God as the Creator of all things, destructive of all hope of immortality, of free-will, consequently, of religion and morality. Such was the outcome, mark it well, of what the modern non-Catholic world hails as the most brilliant period of French philosophy — the age of Cartesians. With the view of emphasizing the danger of har- boring false principles, allow me to anticipate the final outcome of the philosophy of two other great nations, England and Germany. As Descartes was the father of French philosophy, so John Locke is reputed to be the father of English philosophy. To- wards the end of the seventeenth century, when Cartesianism began to decline, John Locke was en- thusiastically hailed as the opponent of Descartes, and the precursor of the newest fashion in philosoph- ical thought. Locke, too, during the eighteenth cen- tury had many ardent disciples. They quickly devel- oped the logical implications of his principles. And though Locke himself was not a Materialist, any more than Descartes was a Pantheist, yet in half a century Locke’s system developed into rank Materialism. Kant of Germany rejected, in turn, the English philosophy of Materialism, and inaugurated what is known to-day as German philosophy. In the hands of Kant’s disciple, Fichte, and, subsequently, of Shell- ing and Hegel, Kantianism quickly matured into Idealistic Pantheism, which is nothing more than an- SOME PRACTICAL LESSONS 143 other form of advanced Atheism. Hence, that climax of human monstrosities — Nietzsche, could say — “God is dead, long live the transcendental man”. Such, in briefest outline, is the boasted outcome of modern intellectuality. Set before your mind and consider calmly this re- markable fact: What professed to be the best minds of France, England and Germany applied their human reason with prodigious energy and labor to solve the great problems of philosophy —the exis- tence and attributes of God, the origin and destiny of man and the material world, the relations that exist between the Creator and the Creature, the obligations and duties of religion and morality. They all pos- sessed the same faculty of reason. The same data were before their minds. The Frenchman, the Eng- lishman, the German started with high hopes of suc- cess. As conclusion followed conclusion in the mind of each, their paths became widely divergent, and their ultimate answers, to the problems they set out to solve, mutually contradictory. No one, not even the philosophers of their own schools, are satisfied with their solutions. From the days of Descartes to the present day, in all the most cultured and highly civil- ized countries, human reason has exercised itself in a riot of freedom in the solution of “the riddle of the universe” and with what result? Confusion worse confounded, strife among the members of the ration- alistic churches, all kinds of fads and vagaries pranc- ing about their pulpits, Spiritualists vomiting their ec- toplasm, Christian Science trying to ignore bodily dis- ease, and Liberals tearing to pieces the remnants of Catholicity preserved by the Fundamentalists. Such, in brief, is the story of the failure of non-Catholic philosophies since the time of the Reformation. 144 CARTESIANISM Driven by a yearning for truth, which lives in the breast of every man, did a Descartes, a Locke, a Kant, a Hegel—the representative minds of the modern non-Catholic world — embark, like so many mariners with brave determination, unquestioned sin- cerity and singleness of purpose upon the high seas of thought, to discover for the human race the true solution that would be universally accepted as satis- factory and convincing of the ultimate course and final destiny of man and of the visible world around him. With high hopes of success, they, and hundreds of less brilliant minds, loosened their sails of reason to the breeze of their personal genius. Thousands of their non-Catholic brethren cheered them on, and bade them “bon voyage”. Patiently did the latter await on the shore for their philosophers’ triumphant return, to receive, at last, an harmonious message from their lips that would for ever more solve the “riddle of the universe”. Their gallant intellectuals return. They deliver their messages. The Gallic savant, in his ex- cellent French style, declares that the ultimate con- clusion of his rational explorations is Pantheism. The vast majority of his audience turned away in disgust. The English philosopher takes the platform, and with Saxon bluntness declares that the ultimate ex- planation and destiny of all things are dust and mat- ter. An indignant cry of protest is heard from his audience, “Dust thou art, to dust returneth, Was not spoken of the soul.” The brusque German, the great Kant, appears. “T have spent twelve years in my explorations of discov- ery’, he says, “and I have found out that no man can know the existence of God by reason. A thing in it- self exists, but nobody can know anything about it. SOME PRACTICAL LESSONS 145 You cannot know even your own real selves. We live in a dreamland. We know only the phantoms of things — the projections of our own mind — phenom- ena.” As you study the history of non-Catholic modern thought, you will be convinced that the findings of non-Catholic philosophers during the last three hun- dred years are a Babel of contradictions mutually destructive of one another. Are we, then, as witnesses of this tragedy of fail- ure, to despair of the ability of individual human rea- son of itself to discover with certainty that God the Creator of all things exists, and that we owe Him reverence and service? Certainly not. That would be the contention of extremists, who, like Luther and Calvin and all the first Protestant reformers, held the incapacity of reason to know anything about God or morals as a logical sequence from their false con- ceptions of original sin. This impotency of natural reason to know anything of God is the traditional teaching of Protestantism, both liberal and orthodox, even at the present day. Reason, indeed, is finite, is fallible, is limited in its field of vision, still it is not subject in all things about God to delusion. We do not agree with those who would, then, depress reason too much, and reduce man to the level of the irra- tional creation, any more than we agree with those other extremists who would set man above archangels and make his intellect divine. We hold, with the sound philosophy of the ages, that individual reason is perfectly competent of itself to acquire with unerring certainty an indefinite num- ber of natural truths, and that among those truths that thus naturally come within the province of rea- son are to be reckoned the existence of God and the evidences of Christianity. “For the invisible things 146 CARTESIANISM of Him, from the creation of the world, are clearly seen, being understood by the things that are made: His eternal power also and divinity: so that they are inexcusable”. (St. Paul, Rom. C. I., 20. See also Wisd., C. XIII-1: Psalms XVIII-2.) Thus is the teaching of St. Thomas of Aquin. He says: “In the things which we confess about God there are two kinds of truths. For there are some things true concerning God which exceed every fac- ulty of human reason, as that God is Three in One. But there are some things which natural reason can attain, as, for example, that God exists, there is only one God, and other things of this kind. Those things even the philosophers have proved demonstratively, led by the light of natural reason”. (Contra Gen- tiles, C. III.) Having once established the existence of God, rea- son, then, of itself, can tell us that Revelation is pos- sible. Granted the existence of God as the Creator, reason can easily conclude also that miracles are like- wise possible. Even John Stuart Mill frankly as- serted, “If I believed in God, I would have no diffi- culty in admitting miracles.” Not only the possibility of miracles, but their happening as facts can be dem- onstrated by reason alone. Reason, now in possession of the following truths— (1) That God exists; (2) that Revelation is therefore possible; that miracles are likewise possible and have actually taken place can advance another step and show that God has actu- ally spoken to man and revealed certain truths, some of which reason could discover of itself, as God’s ex- istence, many others which are altogether beyond the power of reason ever to attain or dream of, as ree the revealed truths contained in the A postles’ reed. SOME PRACTICAL LESSONS 147 Now that this body of revealed truth has been given by God to man, reason can prove from historical evi- dence independently of the authority of faith or the Church. This body of truth has been placed under the guardianship of an infallible authority in the Catholic Church, whose divinely appointed prerogative is to keep intact, interpret and teach to the world this body of revealed doctrine. That revealed body of doctrine is, therefore, hedged in, and absolutely secure from error, and no cloud of doubt can ever dim its truth and certainty. | Now, grant that there is a divine revelation and an infallible Church, whose mission is to guard, preserve, and teach that revelation, then no man, no scientific research, no exercise of reason can claim the right to contradict this revelation and this Church. Human reason and scientific research are not the activities of a God-like intelligence. No, they are the activities of a human intellect, and the human intellect, because a created intellect, as well as all its activities, are subject to God and truth everywhere. There can be no freedom to oppose the truth. No one has a privi- lege to free himself from the bonds of truth, or claim a right to become an independent creator of truth, any more than he has the right of freedom to change the multiplication table. _ But the champions of independent reason as against revelation and an infallible church may assert that such a revelation and such a church is impossible — well, then, let them prove it. On this the issue rests. If they succeed in proving it, then, at that moment, we shall cease to be Catholics, and Christianity will have been the most stupendous lie in history. The burden of proof clearly rests upon the independent Rationalists. We are in possession. If they cannot 148 CARTESIANISM prove it, then let them give up their vociferous decla- mations of absolute freedom of thought. This, briefly, is how the case stands between recal- citrant reason and the authority of the Catholic Church. The question is a large one. The intellectual world cannot ignore it. It is ever living. We have only offered a few suggestions to stimulate your own reflections and further study. The reason why the question has been introduced in the “History of Mod- ern Thought” is because the independence of individ- ual reason in philosophical speculations form a lead- ing, and, it may be said, the fundamental tenet of Descartes’ system. Throughout the “Ages of Faith” all Catholics held, as they hold to-day with St. Augus- tine, “that philosophy, that is the study of wisdom and religion are not things apart”. The Catholic is convinced that no certain result or conclusion of human research will ever come in conflict with his faith, just as the mathematician is never afraid that his certain conclusions will ever be contradicted by the biologist or chemist. Truth can never contradict truth. An infallible Church in matters wherein it is infallible cannot contradict any certainly demon- strated truth of natural reason, nor can any certainly demonstrated truth of natural reason contradict an infallibly established dogma of the Catholic Church. It is this conviction that enables the Catholic phil- osopher or scientist to devote himself with great free- dom and impartiality to research in every field. It is upon this conviction rests the peace between faith and philosophy or science. Faith and science are not torn apart, are not divorced, but join hands peacefully, like truth with truth, though derived from different sources. It was Descartes’ philosophy that first in its spirit tended towards, and ultimately consummated the com- SOME PRACTICAL LESSONS 149 plete divorce between philosophy and science on the one hand and faith and authority on the other. And by this divorce we mean that individual reason looks upon itself, not only as fully competent to discover all truth, so that which it cannot of itself know, it flatters itself is not truth, but also that individual reason confidently enters into the investigation of the great vital truths—God, His attributes, morality, religion, man’s origin, and last end, without the slight- est regard for what revelation teaches on those awful subjects. Should reason arrive at results, in its spec- ulations, that contradict openly the settled and irre- versible dogmas of revelation it cares not. Reason throws ruthlessly aside authority and revelation as even a negative guide or standard, whereby it may judge of the truth or falsehood of its independent results. (Introd.) Reason, in accord with the spirit of modern thought, goes its own sweet way, just as if revelation was never given to man. The obvious consequences of this attitude is, of course, the frank denial that revelation has been given, and that the whole supernatural order, original sin, grace, mira- cles, sacraments, the supernatural origin and final destiny of man are myths, just because they are above and beyond the reach of reason. No doubt Descartes personally professed to look trustfully to the authority of the Church, as a child to its mother, and again proclaimed his readiness to submit all his conclusions to her decisions. “I affirm nothing”’, he says, “but I submit all my principles to the authority of the Catholic Church”. (Prin. IV., 252.) But the tendency of his speculations were widely different. So that if many to-day venture, as they do, to set forth theories about God, revela- tion and morality, that ignore revelation and the in- fallible authority of the Catholic Church, the divinely 150 CARTESIANISM appointed custodian of that revelation, they allege that it was Descartes who taught them. The captains of reason no longer look to the beacon light of divine revelation and authority to protect, at least nega- tively, fallible reason from the rocks and shallows, when it embarks upon the sea of thought to pursue its investigations of the most obstruse, yet vital, questions for humanity. They rave about “theological fetters’, “ecclesiastical manacles upon freedom of thought” and extol Descartes as “the emancipator who established modern freedom of thought”, “the leader who guided Europe out of the house of bond- age”. . . . But the bondage of truth is freedom. “The truth shall make you free”. Even Pascal bears witness to the reasonableness of the submission of what professes to be the results of reason to the es- tablished truths of Revelation. We say “professes to be the result of reason”, because no really valid con- clusion of reason ever contradicts an article of faith. Pascal says: “If we submit everything to reason our religion will have nothing in it mysterious or supernatural. If we violate the principles of reason, our religion will be absurd and ridic- ulous. There is nothing so in conformity with reason as the disavowal of the suprem- acy of reason”’. John Locke bears similar testimony. (Introd. Lect. end.) | It is fundamental to Catholics that there resides in the Catholic Church an infallible authority to pre- serve and teach to all nations the objective truths of Revelation, because the Holy Spirit is Her guide, guaranteed by the promise of Christ. “And I will be with you all days even to the consummation of the SOME PRACTICAL LESSONS 151 world” (Math. 28-20). Protestants deny this infalli- ble authority and substitute for it the fundamental principle that each person may construct his own re- ligion from the Bible by his own private judgment, and this private judgment is inspired by the Holy Spirit granted personally to each individual. The tendency of Cartesian philosophy favored this latter view, a tendency that gradually developed into full maturity in the system of Kant who gave it, as we shall see, a philosophical basis. Reason, of course, is entirely free in its own sphere of scientific investigation. Even if philosophers and scientists fall into errors, the Church will look upon their errors with indifference, provided those errors, masquerading in the garb of truth, do not contradict its settled dogmas. Otherwise the Church will leave philosophers and scientists to fight out their own bat- tles, and correct their own errors. It is not the direct mission of the Church to teach a philosophy or science. In a word, divinely revealed truths are (1) a negative and (2) hypothetical guide to natural rea- son in its speculations, and all reasonable men ac- knowledge it as such. Date Due eae) 7 = Fi ® nw P r I)