4 « * QtA. * * ■ ON THE SCIENCE OF PROPORTIONS. EDINBURGH : JOHNSTONE, BALLANTYNE, AND CO 104 HIGH STREET ON THE SCIENCE OF THOSE PROPORTIONS BY WHICH THE HUMAN HEAD AND COUNTENANCE AS REPRESENTED IN WORKS OF ANCIENT GREEK ART ARE DISTINGUISHED FROM THOSE OF ORDINARY NATURE. DY D. R. HAY, F.R.S.E. AUTHOR OF “FIRST PRINCIPLES OF SYMMETRICAL BEAUTY,” ETC. ETC. ETC. WILLIAM BLACKWOOD AND SONS, EDINBURGH AND LONDON. M.DCCC.XLIX. Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2016 https://archive.org/details/onscienceofthoseOOhayd TO THE HONOURABLE LORI) MURRAY, ONE OF THE JUDGES OF THE COURT OF SESSION OF SCOTLAND, F.R.S.E., ETC. ETC. ETC. THIS WORK IS DEDICATED, AS A TESTIMONY OF THE GRATITUDE, ESTEEM, AND RESPECT, OF THE AUTHOR. CONTENTS. PAGt-: PART I. DEFINITION OF .ESTHETICS, ....... 1 ... II. ON ESTHETIC CULTURE, ....... 7 ... III. ON THE HARMONY OF NUMBERS, AND THE METHOD OF APPLYING IT TO FORM, ......... 21 ... IV. ON THE GENERAL FORM AND BEAUTY OF THE HUMAN HEAD AND COUNTENANCE, ........ 31 ... V. THE SCIENCE OF PROPORTION IN RELATION TO REPRESENTATIONS OF THE HUMAN HEAD AND COUNTENANCE. .... 41 NOTES, ........... 65 INDEX, 79 PREFACE. The recommendation of Sir Joshua Reynolds, that “ every opportunity should be taken to discountenance the false and vulgar opinion, that rules are the fetters of genius,” ought never to be lost sight of by those who treat of the arts of design. Such an idea is scarcely less prevalent in our own day than it was when our great English painter wrote, notwithstanding the practical refutation it receives in the obedience yielded by genius to the rules of rhythmi- cal measure, even in the highest flights of poetic inspira- tion, or in the delicate creations of the musical composer, in subjection to the strictly defined laws of harmony. By an implicit obedience to the application of these definite rules, genius has clothed the creations of fancy in b X PREFACE. poetic numbers, or given form and expression to the most exquisite combinations of musical sound, thereby charm- ing the ear, and entrancing the soul, of the most intelligent and critical student of art, through that inherent principle in the human mind that responds in unison to every species of harmony. Bat while the poet and the musician are thus acknow- ledged as the willing subjects of well-defined harmonic laws, it has been hastily and most inconsistently assumed, that, when genius seeks to give expression to its conceptions in the formative arts, it is folly to imagine that any well- defined laws can be demonstrated, whose bounds shall guide their development, or supply safe canons for the critic’s guidance. It will be shown in the following pages, however, that the laws of proportion, in their relation to the arts of design, constitute the harmony of geometry as definitely as those that are applicable to poetry and music produce the har- mony of acoustics ; and that, consequently, the former ought to hold the same relative position in those arts which PREFACE. XI are addressed to the eye that is accorded to the latter in those which are addressed to the ear. Until so much science he brought to bear upon the formative arts, the student must continue to copy from individual and imper- fect nature, or from the few existing remains of ancient Greek art, while he remains altogether ignorant of the laws by which their proportions are produced ; and, what is equally detrimental to art, the accuracy of all criticism must continue to rest upon the indefinite and variable basis of mere opinion. It cannot be denied that men of great genius in the formative arts are generally possessed of an intuitive feel- ing of appreciation for what is beautiful in form, by means of which they impart to their works the most pleasing pro- portions, independently of any knowledge of the definite laws which govern that species of beauty ; yet even they often do so at the expense of much labour, making many trials before they can satisfy themselves in imparting to them true proportions, along with those other qualities of expression, action, &c., that belong more exclusively to the PREFACE. xii province of genius. To such, an application of the rules which constitute the science of proportion, instead of fetter- ing their genius, would doubtless promote the more free exercise of its powers, and give such confidence and preci- sion to their exercise as no mere mental perception of the harmony and beauty of form can produce. It is also true that the operations of the conceptive faculty of the mind are uncontrolled by definite laws, and that, therefore, there cannot exist any rules, by the inculca- tion of which an ordinary mind can he imbued with genius sufficient to produce works of high art. Nevertheless, such a mind may be improved in its perceptive faculty by instruction in the science of proportion, so as to he enabled to exercise as correct and just an appreciation of the con- ceptions of others, in works of formative art, as that mani- fested by the educated portion of mankind in respect to poetry and music. In short, it appears that, in those arts that are addressed to the ear, men of genius communicate the original conceptions of their minds under the control of certain scientific laws, by means of which the educated PREFACE. xiii easily distinguish the true from the false, and by which the works of the poet and musician may he placed above mere imitations of nature, or of the works of others ; while, in those arts that are addressed to the eye, such as sculpture, architecture, painting, and ornamental design, no such laws are as yet acknowledged. In the following pages, the author endeavours to demonstrate such definite laws of proportion. In making this attempt, he has liere confined himself to their illus- tration in relation to artistic representations of the human head and countenance, having already, in other works, shown their application in architecture, not only to general proportions, but to the minutest details, and in ornamental design to the production of an endless variety of beautiful forms of ornamental vases, and of every species of utensil pertaining to the arts of the ornamental sculptor, the silver- smith, and the potter. Some apology may appear requisite for the unartistic execution of the heads which are added to the geometrical illustrations of this treatise. The author is well aware that XIV PREFACE. they would have been greatly enhanced in effect by artistic assistance in drawing them ; but he conceived that, as these illustrations are added to the diagrams and skulls merely to show how far the science of proportion is productive of beauty in representations of the human head and coun- tenance, independently of those qualities which genius only can impart, this object would he sufficiently attained by drawing them with his own hand, confining himself simply to what in architecture would he termed geometrical eleva- tions in outline. He also trusts that the anatomist will look with no critical eye upon his unprofessional attempts to delineate the bones of the head, in accommodating them to his geometrical figures. JORDAN BANK, EDINBURGH, December, 1848. ON THE SCIENCE OF PROPORTIONS. ON THE SCIENCE OF PROPORTIONS. PART I. DEFINITION OF ESTHETICS. Before entering upon the subject which it is the chief design of this treatise to elucidate, it may be desirable to give some definition of the science of ^Esthetics, of which proportion is the principal element. Dealing, as this science does, alike with the sources and the resulting principles of beauty, it does not belong exclusively either to the physical or metaphysical sciences. It is scarcely less dependent on the accuracy of the senses than on the power of the understanding, inasmuch as the effect which it produces is as essential a property of objects, as are its laws inherent in the human mind. It comprehends a knowledge of those first principles in the arts of design, by which certain combinations of forms and colours B o DEFINITION OF ^ESTHETICS. produce an effect upon tlie mind, connected, in the first instance, with sensation, and, in the second, with the reasoning faculty. It is, there- fore, not only the basis of all true practice in art, but of all sound judgment on questions of artistic criticism, and necessarily includes those laws whereon a correct taste must be based. Many eloquent and ingenious treatises have been written upon taste, but in nearly every case, with no other effect than that of involving the subject in still greater uncertainty. Even when restricted to the arts of design, they have failed to exhibit any definite principles whereby the true may be distinguished from the false, and some recognised laws of beauty reduced to demonstration. This may be attributed, in a great degree, to the neglect of a just discrimination between what is merely agreeable, or capable of exciting pleasurable sensations, and what is essentially beautiful; but still more to the confounding of the operations of the understanding with those of the imagination. Very slight reflection must suffice to show how essentially distinct these two faculties of the mind are ; the former being regulated, in matters of taste, by irrefragable principles existing in nature, and responded to by an inherent quality of the human mind ; while the latter operates in the production of ideal combinations of its own creation, in the region of fancy, altogether independent of any immediate impression from external nature. The beauty of a flower, for example, or of a dew-drop, depends on certain combinations of form and colour, manifestly referrible to DEFINITION OF AESTHETICS. 3 definite and systematic, though it may he as yet unrecognised, laws ; but when Oberon exclaims, in “ Midsummer Night’s Dream,” — “ And that same dew, which sometime on the buds Was wont to swell, like round and orient pearls. Stood now within the pretty flow’ret’s eyes, Like tears that did their own disgrace bewail," — here the poet introduces a new element of beauty, equally legitimate, yet altogether distinct from that which constitutes the science of AEsthetics, as here defined. It is the element of fancy, reducible to no rule, yet adding fresh combinations of beauty, and a distinct source of pleasure to the mind. Our physical and mental powers may be classed under three heads, in their relation to the arts of design, viz., the perceptive, the receptive, and the conceptive. The human eye, from the exquisite beauty of its structure, and the intelligence displayed in its adaptation, is receptive of correct impres- sions from the action of light, according to the innumerable degrees and modes in which the optical phenomena operate upon it. These impressions are conveyed to the sensorium by the optic nerve, and of such the mind is perceptive. This perception induces an operation of the understanding, or is itself an act of the mind, whereby it appre- ciates the nature and quality of the impression originally made on the receptive organ. The mode of this operation is intuitive, and its 4 DEFINITION OF ^ESTHETICS. degree, in regard to accuracy, is regulated by the intellectual vigour of the individual. The intuitive power of the understanding thus enables us to decide correctly as to proportion or deformity; but when it is improved by cultivating and extending our knowledge, we can investigate the causes of beauty, and assign reasons for our judgment in matters of taste. These causes and effects constitute the laws of ./Esthetics. The conceptive power of the mind is that faculty by which original ideas are formed with the assistance of memory, in combining what has already been operated on by the intermediate powers of perception. This constitutes genius. These various powers, which form the chain between the material and intellectual worlds, are so beautifully inter- woven, that it is difficult to assign to them their respective limits, and the examination of each varied link of this chain adds to the difficulty, from the closeness of their affinities and relations. Reception thus appears to be simply the physical effect produced upon the mind by direct, transmitted, or reflected light, through the eye; perception, the operation of the mind by which this impression is appreciated or understood, whether as to its power, in being more or less strong upon the organ — its kind, in being simple or mixed — its nature, in being gay or sombre — or its quality, in being harmonious or discordant; but conception is the power of constructing original ideas from these materials. The understanding operates, in the first instance, in establishing facts, and then the judgment is formed upon DEFINITION OF AESTHETICS. these operations by the reasoning powers, which lead, in their turn, to the creations of the imagination. When an impression is received and perceived, in the fullest sense of the word, the understanding of such an impression, or the manner in which the mind comprehends its nature and qualities, depends upon the mental powers and education of the individual, of the modifica- tions of the former of which there are as many varieties as there are of countenances amongst mankind. But when we conceive an impression, it is by reasoning upon others previously perceived ; for we cannot conceive anything unless it resemble, or, at all events, bear some analogy to an impression already perceived. Memory supplies the materials for conceptions of the mind, and, probably, the only materials ; but memory has received its stores from the perceptive faculty, which contributes to it the result of the first impressions on the organs of sense, as felt, understood, and comprehended by the faculty of perception. In the science of Aesthetics, therefore, the human mind is the sub- ject, and external nature the object. Each individual mind may be considered as a monad in creation — a world within itself. These two separate existences — the individual mind and so much of creation as lies within the scope of its powers — have a distinct relation to each other : the subject is affected by the object, and the media of com- munication are the sensorium and its iidets, the organs of sense — the former being in direct contact with the subject, and the latter with the 6 DEFINITION OF AESTHETICS. object. The organs of sense are thus acted upon in various ways, agreeably to the numerous modifications of the elements of the external world, but aesthetically the mind is affected in two ways only. These affections are either pleasing or displeasing, in so far as they may be in harmony with, or discordant to, a mathematical principle which, in various degrees, exists in the human mind, and by which the truly beautiful is distinguished from the merely agreeable. Note a. The receptive and perceptive powers may be improved by tuition and practice ; and this is called AEsthetic culture. But the conce'ptive or creative power is intuitive, and when developed in a high degree constitutes true genius. The exercise of this power may be assisted by ^Esthetic culture, but the power itself cannot be improved by any mode of tuition. Having thus briefly endeavoured to define AEsthetic science, and to show that it ought to form the basis of all instruction in art, I shall now proceed to inquire into the mode in which it is cultivated at the present period, with a view to improve the practice of art and the appreciation of its productions, as compared with what we know of the mode in which it was inculcated in Greece at the period when art had arrived at its highest excellence, and was most correctly appreciated by the people. ON ESTHETIC CULTURE. PART II. ON AESTHETIC CULTURE. Truth in the sciences has of late been sought, by tracing nature to her most simple elements and first principles of action and combina- tion. By this means natural philosophy has attained its present advanced state ; and by the application of this knowledge, in the use- ful arts, the happiest results have been produced. But in our search for truth in ^Esthetic science, a course has been followed not differing widely from that by which the alchymists of the middle ages con- ducted their investigations ; for our ideas of visible beauty are still undefined, and our attempts to produce it in the various branches of art are left dependent in a great measure upon chance. Our schools instituted for instruction in the arts of design, are conducted without reference to any first principles, or definite laws of beauty; and, from the drawing of a simple architectural moulding to the intricate com- binations of form in the human figure, the pupils have to depend 8 ON .ESTHETIC CULTURE. upon their hands and eyes alone, servilely and mechanically copying the works of the ancients, instead of being instructed in the principles upon which the beauty of those works depends. The instruction given in these schools is addressed almost exclusively to the senses, without reference to the judgment or understanding of the pupils ; and they are thus made to study and imitate effects without investigating causes. Doubtless, men of great genius sometimes arrive at excellence in the arts of design without a knowledge of the principles upon which beauty of form is based ; but it should be kept in mind, that true genius generally includes an intuitive perception of those principles along with its creative power. It is, therefore, to the generality of mankind that instruction in the definable laws of beauty will be of most service, not only in improving the practice of those who follow the arts professionally, but in enabling all to distinguish the true from the false, and to exercise a sound and discriminating taste in judging of artistical productions. .Esthetic culture should, therefore, super- sede servile copying as the basis of instruction in our schools of art. But it has been asserted that, by copying the great works of the ancients, the mind of the pupil will become imbued with ideas similar to theirs — that he will imbibe their feeling for the beautiful, and that, consequently, he will become inspired with their genius, and think as they thought. We, however, see very few satisfactory works of art resulting from this imaginary process in the minds of the pupils; and, indeed, it would be as unreasonable to suppose that the poetry of art ON AESTHETIC CULTURE. 9 is to be acquired by such means, as it would be to imagine that poetic inspiration could be created by setting boys to transcribe the works of the ancient poets. Sir Joshua Reynolds considers copying as a delusive kind of industry, and observes that “ Nature herself is not to be too closely copied. There are excellencies in the art of painting beyond what is commonly called the imitation of nature. * * * A mere copier of nature can never produce anything great.” And in support of these views he quotes Proclus (Lib. II., in Timceum Platonis, as cited by Junius, De Pictura Veterum), who says — “ He who takes for his model such forms as nature produces, and confines himself to an exact imitation of these, will never attain to what is perfectly beautiful. For the works of nature are full of disproportion, and fall very short of the true standard of beauty.” It is remarked by Mr J. C. Daniel, in the Introduction to his translation of M. Victor Cousin’s Pliiiosophy of the Beautiful , that “ the English writers have advocated no theory which allows the beau- tiful to be universal and absolute ; nor have they professedly founded their views on original and ultimate principles. Thus, the doctrine of the English school has for the most part been, that beauty is mutable and special, and the inference that has been drawn from this teaching is, that all tastes are equally just, provided that each man speaks of what he feels.” He then observes, that the German and some of the French writers have thought far differently ; for with them the beautiful is “ simple, immutable, absolute, though its forms c 10 ON AESTHETIC CULTURE. are manifold.” These observations are quite true as regards the works of Hume, Burke, and Alison ; but these authors, although the most popular, were not our only writers on taste. So far back as the year 1725, the same truths advanced by the modern German and French writers, and so eloquently illustrated by M. Cousin, were given to the world in an anonymous publication, entitled, “ An Note B. Inquiry into the Original of our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue.” This author says — “ We, by absolute beauty, understand only that beauty which we perceive in objects, without comparison to any thing exter- nal, of which the object is supposed an imitation or picture, such as the beauty perceived from the works of nature, artificial forms, figures, theorems. Comparative or relative beauty is that which we perceive in objects commonly considered as imitations or resemblances of something else.” Dr Reid also, in his Intellectual Powers of Man,* says, “That taste which we may call rational, is that part of our constitution by which we are made to receive pleasure from the contemplation of what we conceive to be excellent in its kind, the pleasure being annexed to this judgment, and regulated by it. This taste may be true or false, according as it is founded on a true or false judgment. And if it may be true or false, it must have first principles.” M. Victor Cousin’s opinion upon this subject is, however, still more * Chap, vi., p. 442. ON AESTHETIC CULTURE. 11 conclusive. He observes — “ If the idea of the beautiful is not abso- lute, like the idea of the true — if it is nothing more than the expression of individual sentiment, the rebound of a changing sen- sation, or the result of each person’s fancy — then the discussions on the fine arts waver without support, and will never end. For a theory of the tine arts to be possible, there must be something abso- lute in beauty, just as there must be something absolute in the idea of goodness, to render morals a possible science.” * That there are fixed principles which form the basis of ./Esthetic science, is now very generally admitted ; and when these principles are evolved with the same care which has characterized the labours of investigators in natural science, and are applied in the fine arts as the natural sciences have been in the useful arts, a solid foundation will then be laid not only for correct practice, but also for a just appreciation of productions in every branch of the arts of design. In reference to the application of scientific truth as the basis of artistic canons in art, Sir David Brewster justly says — “ It is in the fine arts principally, and in the speculations with which they are associated, that the controlling power of scientific truth has not exer- cised its legitimate influence. In discussing the principles of painting, sculpture, architecture, and landscape gardening, philosophers have renounced science as a guide, and even as an auxiliary ; and a school * Philosophy of the Beautiful , See. London : TV. Pickering. 12 ON AESTHETIC CULTURE. lias arisen whose speculations will brook no restraint, and whose deci- sions stand in opposition to the strongest convictions of our senses. That the external world, in its gay colours and lovely forms, is exhi- bited to the mind only as a tinted mass, neither within nor without the eye, neither touching it nor distant from it — an ubiquitous chaos which experience only can analyze, and touch transform into the realities which compose it ; that the beautiful and sublime in nature and in art derive their power over the mind from association alone — are among the philosophical doctrines of the present day, which, if it be safe, it is scarcely prudent to question. Nor are these opinions the emanations of poetical or ill-trained minds, which ingenuity has elaborated and which fashion sustains. They have been given to the world with all the authority of demonstrated truth ; and in proportion to the hold which they have taken of the public mind, have they operated as a check upon the progress of knowledge.”* I shall now revert to that remote period when the arts of design had attained a height which succeeding ages have in vain attempted to reach, and by this means endeavour to ascertain the nature of the doctrines then inculcated in connection with art. That the principles of art, as well as of science, were taught in the early schools of Greek philosophy, is admitted by almost all writers on the subject ; and it is recorded of Pythagoras, that, on his return from his travels in search * Edinburgh Revieic , vol. lxxviii., pp. 300, 301. OF AESTHETIC CULTURE. 13 of knowledge amongst the Phoenicians, Egyptians, and Chaldeans, about 520 years before the Christian era, he exhibited to his disciples and pupils, amongst other discoveries and improvements, a system of analogy, or key, for finding all harmonious proportions in painting, sculpture, architecture, and music ; and that it was by the help of this analogical principle that the Grecians excelled all other nations in the arts of architecture, sculpture, and painting ; and that, after the con- quest of Greece by the Romans, the Grecian artists employed at Rome kept this principle a profound secret amongst themselves. This I find quoted by Hogarth, in the Preface to his “ Analysis of Beauty,” upon the authority of a writer of the period called Christo- pher Le Blon ; and although I have not been able to discover so defi- nite a statement of a system of harmonious proportion borne out by other writers upon the Pythagorean doctrines, yet I find sufficient to render it highly probable that the principles included in this analogy, which the Greeks certainly employed in the arts, emanated from the school of Pythagoras. These principles, in addition to the uncertainty of their origin, seem for many centuries to have been buried in oblivion. It be- comes, therefore, requisite to endeavour to arrive at some knowledge of their nature, in order that we may see in what respects they were connected with the known doctrines of Pythagoras. It is well known, that in the time of that great philosopher the treasures of science were veiled in mystery to all but the properly 14 ON AESTHETIC CULTURE. initiated, and the results of its various branches only given to the world in works of art by those who had acquired this knowledge. So strictly was this secrecy maintained amongst the disciples and pupils of Pythagoras, that any one divulging the sacred doctrines to the pro- fane was expelled the community, and none of his former associates allowed to hold further intercourse with him : it is even said, that one of his pupils incurred the displeasure of the philosopher for having published the solution of a problem in geometry.* The difficulty, therefore, which is expressed by writers, shortly after the period in which Pythagoras lived, regarding a precise knowledge of his theories, is not to be wondered at, more especially when it is considered that he never committed them to writing. It would appear, however, that he proceeded upon the principle, that the order and beauty so apparent throughout the whole universe must compel men to believe in, and to refer them to, an intelligent cause. To this Supreme Intel- ligence, or active principle, the name of monad, or unity, was given, because it must be always the same ; to matter, or the passive prin- ciple, was given that of dyad, or multiplicity, because it is subject to every kind of change ; f and to the world itself was given that of triad, since it was the result of intelligence and matter. Pythagoras and his disciples sought for properties in the science of numbers, by the know- ledge of which they might attain to that of nature ; and they conceived * Abbe Barthelemie’s Travels of Anacharsis in Greece , vol. iv., pj>. 193, 195. + Or, more probably, because it was subject to two states only, viz., those of chaos and order. ON AESTHETIC CULTURE. 15 those properties to be indicated in the phenomena of sonorous bodies Observing that Nature herself had thus irrevocably fixed the numerical value of the intervals of musical tones, they justly concluded that, as she is always uniform in her works, the same laws must regulate the general system of the universe.* Pythagoras, therefore, considered numerical proportion as the great principle inherent in all things, and traced the various forms and phenomena of the world to numbers as their basis and essence. How the principles of numbers were applied in the arts is not recorded, farther than what transpires in the works of Plato, whose doctrines were from the school of Pythagoras. Li explaining the principle of beauty, as developed in the elements of the material world, he commences in the following words : — “ But when the Artificer began to adorn the universe, he first of all figured with forms and numbers, fire and earth, water and air ; which possessed, indeed, cer- tain traces of the true elements, but were in every respect so consti- tuted, as it becomes anything to he from which Deity is absent. But we should always persevere in asserting that Divinity rendered them as much as possible the most beautiful and the best, when they were in a state of existence opposite to such a condition.” Plato goes on farther to say, that these elementary bodies must have forms ; and as * Abbe Barthelemie (vol. ii., pp. 168, 169), who cites as his authorities, Cicer. Do Nat. Door ., Lib. I., cap. ii., t. 2, p. 405; Justin Mart., Omt. ad Gent., p. 10; Aristot. Metaph., Lib. I., cap. v., t. 2, p. 845. 16 ON AESTHETIC CULTURE. it is necessary that every depth should comprehend the nature of a plane, and as of plane figures the triangle is the most elementary, he adopts two triangles as the originals or representatives of the isosceles and the scalene kinds. The first triangle of Plato is that which forms the half of the square, which is regulated by the number 2 ; and the second that which forms the half of the equilateral triangle, which is regulated by the number 3 : from various combinations of these he formed the bodies of which he considered the elements to be com- posed. To these elementary figures I shall have again to refer. Vitruvius, who studied architecture many ages after the arts of Greece had been buried in the oblivion which succeeded her conquest, gives the measurements of various details of monuments of Greek art then existing. But he seems to have had but a vague traditionary knowledge of the principle of harmony and proportion from which these measurements resulted. He says — “ The several parts which constitute a temple ought to be subject to the laws of symmetry; the principles of which should be familiar to all who profess the science of architecture. Symmetry results from proportion, which, in the Greek language, is termed analogy. Proportion is the commensura- tion of the various constituent parts with the whole; in the existence of which symmetry is found to consist. For no building can possess the attributes of composition in which symmetry and proportion are disregarded; nor unless there exist that perfect conformation of parts which may be observed in a Avell formed human being.” After going ON AESTHETIC CULTURE. 17 at some length into details, he adds — “Since, therefore, the human figure appears to have been formed with such propriety, and that the several members are commensurate with the whole, the artists of anti- quity” (meaning those of Greece at the period of her highest refine- ment) “ must be allowed to have followed the dictates of a judgment the most rational, when, transferring to the works of art principles derived from nature, every part was so regulated as to bear a just proportion to the whole. Now, although these principles were univer- sally acted upon , yet they were more particularly attended to in the construction of temples and sacred edifices, the beauties or defects of which were destined to remain as a perpetual testimony of their skill or of their inability.” Vitruvius, however, gives no explanation of this ancient principle of proportion, as derived from the human form ; but plainly shows his uncertainty upon the subject, by concluding this part of his essay in the following words : — “ If it be true, therefore, that the decenary notation was suggested by the members of man, and that the laws of proportion arose from the relative measures existing between certain parts of each member and the whole body, it will follow, that those are entitled to our commendation who, in building temples to their deities, proportioned the edifices, so that the several parts of them might be commensurate with the whole.” It thus appears certain, that the Grecians at the period of their highest excellence had arrived at a knowledge of some definite D 18 ON AESTHETIC CULTURE. mathematical law of proportion, which formed a standard of perfectly symmetrical beauty, not only in the representation of the human figure in sculpture and painting, but in all other works of art in which beauty of form constituted an excellence. That this law was not deduced from the proportions of the human figure, as supposed by Vitruvius, but had its origin in mathematical science, seems equally certain ; for in no other way can we satisfactorily account for the beau ideal head of ancient Greek art, or the inimitable pro- portions of the Parthenon at Athens, far less for the general beauty of form that pervades all other works of art of the period with which we are acquainted. This system of geometrical harmony, founded upon numerical relations, must, consequently, have formed part of the Greek philo- sophy of the period, by means of which the arts began to progress towards that great excellence which they soon after attained. A little farther investigation will show, that immediately after this period a theory connected with art was acknowledged and taught, and, also, that there existed a Science of Proportion. Pamphilus, the celebrated painter, who flourished about four hundred years before the Christian era, from whom Apelles received the rudiments of his art, and whose school was distinguished for scientific cultivation, artistic knowledge, and the greatest accuracy in drawing, would admit no pupil unacquainted with geometry.* The * Miiller’s Ancient Art and its Remains. ON ^ESTHETIC CULTURE, 19 terms upon which he engaged with his students were, that each should pay him one talent (£225 sterling) previous to receiving his instructions : for this he engaged “ to give them, for ten years, LESSONS FOUNDED ON AN EXCELLENT THEORY.”* It was by the advice of Pamphilus that the magistrates of Sicyon ordained that the study of drawing should constitute part of the education of the citizens — “ a law,” says the Abbe Barth elemie, “ which rescued the fine arts from servile hands.” It is stated of Parrhasius, the rival of Zeuxis, who flourished about the same period as Pamphilus, that he accelerated the pro- gress of art by purity and correctness of design ; “ for he was acquainted with the Science of Proportions. Those he gave his Gods and Heroes were so happy, that artists did not hesitate to adopt them.” Parrhasius, it is also stated, was the first who gave “ expressive airs of heads, mouths embellished by the graces, and hair pourtrayed with delicacy.” He was so admired by his contem- poraries, that they decreed him the name of Legislator. f The whole history of the arts in Egypt and Greece concurs to prove that they were based on geometric precision, and were perfected by a continued application of the same science ; while in all other countries we find them originating in rude and misshapen imitations of nature. * Annchnrsis Travels in Greece. By the Abbe Barthelemie. Yol. ii., p. 325. t Ibid, vi., p. 225. The authorities the Abbe quotes are — Quintil., Lib. XII , cap. x., p. 744; Plin., Lib. XXXV., cap. ix., p. 691. 20 OH AESTHETIC CULTURE. In the earliest stages of Greek art, the gods — then the only statues — were represented in a tranquil and fixed posture, with the features exhibiting a stiff, inflexible earnestness, their only claim to excellence being symmetrical proportion ; and this attention to geo- metric precision continued as art advanced towards its culminating point, and was thereafter still exhibited in the neatly and regularly folded drapery, and in the curiously braided and symmetrically arranged hair.* These examples, few and imperfect as they are, cannot fail to exhibit the great contrast that exists between the system of elemen- tary education in art practised in ancient Greece, and that adopted Note c. in this country at the present period. But it would be of very little service to point out this contrast, were it not followed up by some attempt to develop the principles which seem to have formed the excellence of the Grecian system. This attempt, therefore, consti- tutes the chief object in what follows; while along with it I shall also endeavour to apply those principles practically in the reconstruc- tion of the artistic head of ancient Grecian art. * Miiller’s Archceoloc/y of A rt, c^-c. cm THE HARMONY OF NUMBERS. 21 PART III. ON THE HARMONY OF NUMBERS, AND THE METHOD OF APPLYING IT TO FORM. In several former works I have given an outline of the harmony of numbers, and have shown that, by the proper application of this law to various branches of the arts of design connected with the practice of the architect, the painter, the sculptor, the silversmith, the potter, &c., their productions might be brought to a degree of perfection equalling what we find in the finest works of the ancients. As, however, I am now to treat of that harmony in con- nection with the highest object of art, it becomes requisite to give an outline of it here, in order to make what follows more easily understood. A writer in the British and Foreign Medical Review remarks, with equal comprehensiveness and truth, that “ there is harmony of numbers in all nature — in the force of gravity — in the planetary 99 ON THE HARMONY OF NUMBERS, AND movements — in the laws of heat, light, electricity, and chemical affinity — in the forms of animals and plants — in the perceptions of the mind. The direction, indeed, of modern natural and physical science is towards a generalization which shall express the funda- mental laws of all by one simple numerical ratio. We think modern science will soon show that the mysticism of Pythagoras was mystical only to the unlettered, and that it was a system of philosophy founded on the then existing mathematics ; which latter seems to have com- prised more of the philosophy of numbers than our present.”* Harmony has been philosophically defined as “ the union of con- trary principles having a ratio to each other ; ” which contrary prin- ciples are those of uniformity and variety, and they are produced in the abstract from the various modes in which units may be combined. This numerical harmony is the root of every other species of har- mony, whether addressed to the ear or the eye, and arises as follows : — The first mode of combination is that of one unit with another, by which the number 2 is produced, which number is a submultiple of 4, b, 8, progressively, as 2, 3, 4. It is the first even number ; that is, it consists of two equal and similar portions, and these are its only aliquot parts. It, therefore, may be termed the first prin- ciple of uniformity. The second combination of the unit is 3, which is the first odd number, and is a submultiple of the numbers 6, 9, 12, * No. xxxv, P . 171. THE METHOD OF APPLYING IT TO FORM. these being progressive multiples of 3, by 2, 3, 4. This number being also the combination of 1 and 2, may be called the first principle of inequality, or variety. The third mode of union is the combination of the two contrary principles of 2 and 3, in the number 5. This number is the third simple multiple of the unit, because it has no other aliquot parts, and combines the binary and ternary principles of union amongst units. It is a submultiple of the numbers 10, 15, 20, progressively, as 2, 3, 4. The numbers 2, 3, and 5, are, there- fore, the first three multiples of the unit that have no other aliquot parts ; and it will be shown, in the sequel, that by the union, in proper proportions, of the contrary principles which they exhibit, the proportion and symmetrical beauty of the human head and coun- tenance may be abstractedly produced. In form, generally, these principles may be applied through the medium of the circle, because by the division of its arc into parts called degrees, minutes, &c., the units are adopted by which the harmonic ratios of numerical quantity may be applied to that primary species of plane figure upon which the beauty of form especially depends, namely, the triangle. The division of the circle into 360 parts, seems to me to prove clearly the application of the laws of harmony to form by the earliest geometers ; for no other number embodies, in the same harmonious relations, the numbers to which I have just alluded as the source of all harmony, namely, 2, 3, and 5. The division of the circle by its diameter into equal parts, gives 24 ON THE HARMONY OF NUMBERS, AND the base line from which all angles are calculated, by the degrees contained in the arc which stands upon it, and these are in number 180, divisible into minutes, &c., as just stated. The division of the semicircle by two gives the perpendicular line to the base which divides the arc into quadrants, each of which contains 90°, and the angle thus formed with the base line is called the right angle, be- cause it is the most perfect of its kind, all angles having more degrees being obtuse, and those having fewer being acute. This angle may, therefore, be taken as the fundamental angle, to which all others, in the first instance, should relate, as to a natural key ; and it is by this means that the principle of harmonic ratio may be applied to every species of form. A rectilineal triangle is the simplest component figure of any other rectilineal plane figure, because it has the smallest number of sides and angles. It must, therefore, be to this figure that we are to look for the most simple operation of those first principles which give symmetry to forms. The proportions of all triangles are regulated by the relative numbers of degrees which their angles contain. The primary rectilineal plane figure is the square, which is per- fectly uniform, having four angles of 90°, making in all 360°, the full number contained in the circle. When a square is bisected through two of its angles, it is reduced to its most elementary com- ponent figure, which is an isosceles triangle, having two angles of 45° THE METHOD OF APPLYING IT TO FORM. each, and one of 90°. This peculiar triangle, when bisected through its greatest angle, always produces two triangles with angles similar to itself. (Plate I., fig. 1.) The relative numbers of degrees in the Plate i. angles of this triangle, therefore, exhibit the primary harmonic ratios of 1 to 1, and 1 to 2, in 45° to 45°, and 45° to 90°. The secondary rectilineal plane figure is the equilateral triangle, which, like the square, is perfectly uniform, having three angles of 60°, making in all 180, the number contained in the arc of the semicircle. When this triangle is bisected through one of its angles, it exhibits its primary component figure, which is a scalene triangle, having one angle of 30°, one of 60°, and one of 90°. This peculiar right-angled scalene triangle is, therefore, the elementary figure of which the equilateral triangle is composed ; but it cannot, like the primary isosceles triangle, be divided into two of its own kind, the smallest number that this or any other right-angled scalene triangle can be divided into being four. (Plate I., fig. 2.) The numbers of degrees in this scalene triangle exhibit relatively to each other the harmonic ratios of 1 to 2, 1 to 3, and 2 to 3, in 30° to 60°, 30° to 90°, and (10° to 90°. The pentagon may be termed the tertiary rectilineal plane figure, having five angles of 108° each, making in all 540° — the number contained in three semicircles, or the amount of degrees in the angles of the two preceding figures, the square and triangle. When a pentagon is bisected through one of its angles and one of its sides, E 26 ON THE HARMONY OF NUMBERS, AND the right-angled scalene triangle formed by the bisecting line and the half of its side will he found to be its most elementary component figure, and will contain at its three angles respectively 18°, 72°, and 90°. (Plate I., fig. 3.) The numbers of degrees in the three angles of this triangle, therefore, exhibit in their relative quantities the har- monic ratios of 1 to 4, 1 to 5, and 4 to 5, in 18° to 72°, 18° to 90°, and 72° to 90°. The degrees at the angles of those triangles, and their ratios to the right angle, may be thus represented : — II. 90° I. I. I. 45° 45° 30' III. V. 90° 90° II. I. IY. o O CD 18° 72° Each of these harmonic ratios is compounded of others of a less simple kind. Thus, the simple ratio of 1 to 2, between 45° and 90°, is compounded of the two less simple ratios of 2 to 3, and 3 to 4, in 45° to 07° 30', and 07° 30' to 90°; and these two ratios being multiplied together, the lesser term of the one by the lesser term of the other, and the greater term of the one by the greater term of the other, produce 0 and 12, which have the same ratio to each other as 1 to 2. Again, the ratio of 2 to 3, between (10° and 90°, may be divided into the less simple ratios of 4 to 5, and 5 to 6, THE METHOD OF APPLYING IT TO FORM. 27 in 60° to 75°, and 75° to 90°; and these ratios being multiplied as before will produce 20 and 30, which numbers have the same ratio to each other as 2 to 3. Lastly, the ratio of 4 to 5, between 72° and 90°, is divisible into the two less simple ratios of 8 to 9, and 9 to 10, in 72° to 81°, and 81° to 90° ; and these ratios being multiplied as before, give 72 and 90, which numbers are to each other in the ratio of 4 to 5. The following are, therefore, the numerical ratios found in the angles of those three triangles : — 1 to 2 in 45° to OD O o 2 — 3 — o O — 00 O o 3 — 4 — 45° — CO o o 3 — 5 — 18° — o o CO 4 — 5 — 72° — oc o o 5 — 6 — 60° — 72° 5 — 8 — 45° — 72° 1 — 3 — o O CO — o O CO 1 — 4 — ■ 18° — 72° 1 — 5 18° 00 O o And these ratios correspond exactly to those of the rapidity in the pulsations of the atmosphere, which, according to the well estab- lished laws of the science of acoustics, produce the most perfect consonances of sound upon the ear. This analogy, I may add, is in 28 ON THE HARMONY OF NUMBERS, AND no way forced ; but arises naturally and necessarily from these simple elements of plane geometry. The two first of these triangles have been called the two sym- metrical triangles of Plato, who refers to them in the following words : — “ Of the two triangles, the isosceles is allotted one nature, but the oblong, or scalene, is characterized by infinity. We ought, therefore, to choose the most beautiful among infinities, if we wish to commence our investigations in a becoming; manner.”* These three triangles are the primary elements of the five regular solids, or Platonic bodies, which are, the tetrahedron — bounded by four equilateral triangles ; the octahedron — bounded by eight equilateral triangles ; the icosahedron — bounded by twenty equilateral triangles ; the hexahedron, or cube — bounded by six squares; and the dodeca- hedron — bounded by twelve pentagons. Besides these five, there can be no other solids bounded by like, equal, and regular plane figures, and the solid angles of which are all equal. In describing these, Plato confines himself to the four first, and merely hints at the Dodecahedron in these words : — “ There is also a certain fifth composition which Divinity employed in the fabrica- te D. tion of the universe.” This body may, therefore, have been dis- covered by some other geometer. Be that as it may, these triangles are not only the elements of the most beautiful rectilineal plane figures, but of the most beautiful rectilineal solid bodies. * The Works of Plato, translated by Taylor, vol ii., p. 526 . THE METHOD OF APPLYING IT TO FORM. 29 Every regular rectilineal plane figure has a curvilineal figure which exclusively belongs to it. For instance, if we take one of the equal sides of the primary isosceles triangle, which is half of the square, as a radius of a curvilineal figure, of which the right angle of the triangle is the centre, a circle will be described whose cir- cumference will necessarily pass through both its other angles. (Plate I., fig. 4.) The circle is, therefore, the curvilineal figure that exclusively belongs to the primary isosceles triangle. If, in like manner, we take the two unequal sides of the primary scalene triangle, which is half of the equilateral triangle, as the semi- diameters of a curvilineal figure, of which the right angle of the triangle is the centre, an ellipse will be described, the circumference of which will necessarily pass through each of the other two angles. (Plate I., fig. 5.) This ellipse, which has many peculiar properties, fully described elsewhere,* is, therefore, the curvilineal figure that exclusively belongs to the primary scalene triangle. As the revo- lution of the circle upon its diameter will produce a sphere, so the revolution of the ellipse upon its transverse diameter null pro- duce a prolate spheroid ; and these two bodies are, consequent! y, the curvilineal solids arising from the elementary figures in which tiie principles of geometric harmony have been found to exist. It will therefore be seen, that the figures I have adopted as the elements of beauty, namely, the square, the equilateral triangle, * Essay on Ornamental Design , p. 24. 30 ON the harmony of numbers. the pentagon, the circle, and the ellipse whose proportions are derived from the elementary figure of the equilateral triangle, have not been chosen empirically, but are what have been in every age acknow- ledged to be the most beautiful of all forms. Before applying these elements in illustration of the science of those proportions which distinguish the ideal head of ancient Greek art, it will be requisite to say something of the general form and proportions of the human head and countenance. O N THE GENERAL FORM, &c. 31 PART IV. ON THE GENERAL FORM AND BEAUTY OF THE HUMAN HEAD AND COUNTENANCE. The most remarkable characteristics in the structure of the human head are, its globular form (or rather such union of the globular and spheroidal forms as results, both in the external figure and in its sections, in the ovoid), and the approximation of the plane of the face to a vertical line ; for in none of the lower animals does' the skull present so near an approach to this form, nor the plane of the face to this direction. These peculiar characteristics are variously modified among the numerous races of mankind ; but one law appears to influence the whole. They are invariably found most prominently developed in the highly refined and most intellectual races of men, while the most barbarous tribes present the greatest departure from them, their heads being distinguished by compression of the anterior portion of the skull, and the consequent prominence of the mouth. 32 ON THE GENERAL FORM AND BEAUTY OF generally accompanied with flatness of the nose. The highest and most cultivated races, however, present only an approximation to the perfect development of those distinguishing marks of humanity. Mankind is thus characterized by the partial development of a principle of beauty, in the form and position of the head and face, deducible from mathematical laws. A little further investigation will show, that the arrangement of the organs of sense upon the facial surface approximates to the development of another modification of the same principle, constituting its primary element of beauty. In art, upon the other hand, we find that the development of this principle has, at a very early period, been carried to a higher degree of perfection than has been found in any single example in nature, and that the works of that period present to us a degree of mathe- matical beauty nowhere else discoverable. This species of beauty has been called the ideal, in contradistinction to that of ordinary nature, from which it differs in being free from the deformities and peculiarities constituting the individuality by which men are distin- guished from each other. Some writers upon beauty have asserted that there is no original, or positive beauty in the human countenance, and that our sense of the beautiful, as relative to it, arises from the association of ideas alone ; while others affirm that this depends entirely upon expression. Sir Charles Bell, in his excellent essay upon the subject,* has shown * The A natomy and Philosophy of Expression, S,c. Fourth Edition. London : J ohn Murray, ] 847. THE HUMAN HEAD AND COUNTENANCE. 33 most clearly that such doctrines are erroneous, and that there exists in the permanent form of the human head and face an innate beauty, altogether independent of the enhancement of expression, or of any association of ideas in the mind of the beholder. He observes, that those who have hitherto written on the sources of beauty have not attained to the right principle, because they have not only lost sight of nature, but of what may justly he called the philosophy of the subject. In respect to the permanent form and beauty of the human head and face, in contradistinction to expression, Sir Charles says — “ Beauty of countenance may be defined in words, as well as demon- strated in art. A face may be beautiful in sleep, and a statue with- out expression may he highly beautiful.” “ But it will he said, there is expression in the sleeping figure, or in the statue. Is it not rather that we see in these the capacity for expression ? — that our minds are active in imagining what may be the motions of those features when awake or animated ? Thus, we speak of an expressive face before we have seen a movement, grave or cheerful, or any indication in the features of what prevails in the heart. Avoiding a mere distinction in words, let us consider, first, why a certain proportion and form of face is considered beautiful, and conveys the notion of capacity of expression ; and, secondly, the movements, or the actual expression of emotion. I believe that it is the confusion between the capacity of expression and the actual indication of thought, that is the cause of the extraordinary difficulty in which the subject is involved.” F 34 ON THE GENERAL FORM AND BEAUTY OF This capacity for expression certainly enhances onr admiration of the human countenance, but it is more a concomitant of the primary cause of its beauty than the cause itself. This cause, I believe, will be found to rest on a more simple and secure basis, namely, on geome- tric harmony ; for the nearer the countenance approximates to a har- monious combination of the most perfect figures in geometry, or, rather, the more its general form and individual parts, with their rela- tive proportions, are regulated by such figures, the higher will be its degree of beauty, while unaffected by expression, and the greater will be its capacity for the expression of the passions. The Greeks were the first to impart this species of beauty to representations of the human head and countenance in the statues of their deities ; but the means by which they thus excelled ordinary nature has been long buried in oblivion, and has, consequently, for many ages, formed a subject of discussion to all who have treated of the arts of design. Some of the earliest writers upon the subject, in the enthusiasm of their admiration, asserted that either the gods must have descended to the earth, or that the artists must have ascended to heaven, in order to enable the latter to impart this qua- lity to their works. Modern writers have attempted to account for it more rationally, but the point is still far from being finally deter- mined. Perhaps the most plausible opinion is that which attributes the attainment of this excellence by the ancient Greek artists, to their having long studied what the human countenance possessed in THE HUMAN HEAD AND COUNTENANCE. 35 common, and having thereby acquired the faculty of observing in what individuals were deficient, they thus arrived at a perfect idea of beauty. To embody this idea and refine upon nature, they composed a species of collective beauty, by selecting various parts from the most perfect models they could find in nature, which they combined together in one figure, thus producing ideal beauty. It is, therefore, the characteristic of this school, that the ideal beauty of ancient Greek art can only be arrived at by means of imitation. There have not been wanting those, however, who have affirmed, that it was not by the study of natural forms that the Greeks gave ideal Note E. beauty to their works, but by some creative and abstract principle. M. Victor Cousin, in his Philosophy of the Beautiful , draws the dis- tinction between what are termed real beauty and ideal beauty, more clearly than any other author with whose works I am acquainted. He says — “ If the object that I wish to copy after nature present some beauty, the imitation is beautiful ; but, after all, I only achieve real beauty. If I am not satisfied with one object, and I bring together a great number of models, and, in painting a human figure, take the forehead from one, the eyes from another, the smile from a third, I shall obtain beauty real and collective, but not ideal ; for my work wall not contain a single trait that cannot be found in one or other of the originals. In the same manner that we have distinguished absolute from collective ideas, we shall now separate ideal beauty from real beauty. But those who advocate the real exclusively, deny 36 ON THE GENERAL FORM AND BEAUTY OF the existence of the ideal, or say that it consists only in union, or in choice ; which is equivalent to the negation of the ideal. The school opposed to them allows, on the contrary, only the ideal, and makes a complete abstraction of the models of nature ; they are artists who work de tete — this is their expression. The first school, which desires to see nothing in art but an imitation of the real, forgets that all it meets in nature is but imperfect beauty — that the beau- tiful is concealed beneath the real. The second school, which takes notice of the ideal alone, falls into the opposite error, and produces works that are unapproachable by our senses. The ideal alone is cold and lifeless. We need not neglect the real in the school of art, any more than the collective idea in the school of metaphysics ; but we ought not to pause at the merely collective, or at the merely real. * * * The ideal without the real is lifeless ; but the real without the ideal is destitute of pure beauty. Both ought to be united. The two schools ought to give each other the hand, and be allied: the noblest works of art are the result of such a union. Thus, beauty is an absolute idea, and not a copy of finite, accidental, and imperfect nature. The idea can make itself visible in the bosom of nature, but it is always veiled and imperfect. It shines more brightly in the works of man, because the arm guided by intelli- gence approaches nearer to the model the mind has conceived ; but still the idea can never be entirely unfolded.” This I conceive to be a just definition of what is meant by ideal beauty. THE HUMAN HEAD AND COUNTENANCE. 37 Various attempts have been made to detine geometrically the difference between the ordinary and the ideal beauty of the human head and countenance, the most prominent of which is that of Cam- per. He traced, upon a profile of the skull, a line in a horizontal direction, passing through the foramen of the ear and the exterior margin of the sockets of the front teeth of the upper jaw, upon which he raised an oblique line, tangential to the margin of these sockets, and to the most prominent part of the forehead. Agreeably to the obliquity of this line, he determined the relative proportion of the areas occupied by the brain and by the face, and hence inferred the degree of intellect. When he applied this measurement to the heads of the antique statues, he found the angle much greater than in ordinary nature ; hut that this simple fact afforded no rule for the reproduction of the ideal beauty of ancient Greek art, is very evident from the heads and countenances by which his treatise is illustrated. Sir Charles Bell justly remarks, that although, by Camper’s method, the forehead may be thrown forward, yet, while the features of com- mon nature are preserved, we refuse to acknowledge a similarity to the beautiful forms of the antique marbles. 44 It is true,” he says, 44 that by advancing the forehead it is raised, the face is shortened, and the eye brought to the centre of the head. But with all this, there is much wanting — that which measurement, or a mere line, will not show “us.” — 44 The truth is, that we are more moved by the features than by the form of the whole head. Unless there be a 38 ON THE GENERAL FORM AND BEAUTY OF conformity in every feature to the general shape of the head, throw- ing the forehead forward on the face produces deformity; and the question returns with full force — How is it that we are led to con- cede that the antique head of the Apollo, or of the Jupiter, is beau- tiful when the facial line makes a hundred degrees with the horizontal line ? In other words — How do we admit that to be beautiful which is not natural? Simply for the same reason that, if we discover a broken portion of an antique, a nose, or a chin of marble, we can say, without deliberation, This must have belonged to a work of anti- quity ; which proves that the character is distinguishable in every part — in each feature, as well as in the whole head.” Dr Oken says upon this subject:* — “ The face is beautiful whose nose is parallel to the spine. No human face lias grown into this estate, but every nose makes an acute angle with the spine.” “ The facial angle is, as is well known, 80°. ” “ What, as yet, no man has remarked, and what is not to be remarked, either, without our view of the cranial signification, the old masters have felt through inspira- tion. They have not only made the facial angle a right angle, but have even stepped beyond this — the Homans going up to 96°, the Greeks even to 100°. Whence comes it that this unnatural face of the Grecian works of art is still more beautiful than that of the Homan, when the latter comes nearer unto nature? The reason * Phisio-philosophi/. By Dr Oken. London : 184S. Translated by Talk, and published by the Ray Society. THE HUMAN HEAD AND COUNTENANCE. 39 thereof resides in the fact of the Grecian artistic face representing nature’s design more than that of the Roman; for in the former, the nose is placed quite perpendicular, or parallel to the spinal cord, and thus returns whither it has been derived.” Other various and conflicting opinions upon this subject have been given to the world ; but we find that the principle from which the ideal beauty arose in the head and countenance, as represented in works of ancient Greek art, is still a matter of dispute. When, how- ever, we examine carefully a fine specimen, we find its beauty and grandeur to depend more upon the degree of harmony amongst its parts, as to their relative proportions and mode of arrangement, than upon their excellence taken individually. It is, therefore, clear that those who attribute the beauty of ancient Greek sculpture merely to a selection of parts from various models must be in error. No assem- blage of parts from ordinary nature could have produced its principal characteristic, the excess in the angle of the facial line, much less could it have led to that exquisite harmony of parts by which it is so eminently distinguished; neither can we reasonably agree with Dr Oken and others, who assert that it was produced by an exclusive degree of the inspiration of genius bestowed upon the ancient Greek artists. That the inspiration of genius, combined with a careful study of nature, were essential elements in the production of the great works which have been handed down to us, no one will deny ; but these Note F. 40 ON THE GENERAL FORM AND BEAUTY, &c. elements have existed in all ages, whilst the ideal head belongs exclusively to the Greeks of the periods of Pythagoras and Plato. Is it not, therefore, reasonable to suppose, that, besides genius and the study of nature, another element was employed in the production of this excellence, and that this element arose from the precise mathe- matical doctrines taught in the schools of these philosophers ? Muller has said — “ The principles which the ancients followed in regard to proportions (»AA, symmetria numeris ) — and we know that this was a main object of artistic study — are naturally difficult to discover and determine, on account of the manifold modifications introduced by the application of them to different ages, sexes, and characters.” * In what follows, I shall attempt to determine those principles of Note G. proportion, and thereby to remove the difficulty referred to by so many writers upon art, and to which Miiller here alludes. * Ancient Art and its Remains. By C. O. Muller. Translated from the German, by John Leitch. London : A. Fullarton & Co. THE SCIENCE OF PROPORTION. 41 PART V. THE SCIENCE OF PROPORTION IN RELATION TO REPRE- SENTATIONS OF THE HUMAN HEAD AND COUNTE- NANCE. In Part III. I have endeavoured to explain the ./Esthetic nature of numerical harmonic ratio, and the method by which it may be employed in applying the science of proportion to forms generally. Part IY. is designed to point out the distinguishing peculiarities of form in the human head and countenance, and wherein the ideal representations of ancient Greek art differ from ordinary nature. In the present Part it is sought to show that, by the application of these principles of numerical harmonic ratio, in accordance with a system of descriptive geometry, artistic representations of the human head and countenance may be produced, possessing all the characteristic beauties of form and proportion which distinguish those of ancient Greek art ; and, at the same time, to point out G 42 THE SCIENCE OF Plate L %■ 6 . one of the deviations from this system by which ordinary nature is distinguished. Camper’s system of comparison between the beauty of the ideal head of ancient Greek art and that of ordinary nature, in its various degrees of intellectual capacity, as already explained in Part IV., was confined to the relative prominence upon the facial surface of the frontal bone of the cranium and the lower bones of the face, and was, consequently, very limited in its application. Blu- menbach, finding this to be the case, and that, even within its limited range, it did not accurately apply in some cases, adopted what he termed the vertical rule. He drew his comparisons by arranging the crania, with the cheek bones in a horizontal line, so as to view them from behind the vertex, and thus he deter- mined their degrees of approximation to the highest scale of intel- lect by the projection of the facial bones beyond those of the cranium ; while Professor Owen recommends viewing the skull from its base, the lower jaw being removed. In the descriptive geometry adopted in this treatise, all these aspects are given, with the addition, in every case, of a front view of the skull, so that the peculiarities of each aspect are derived from the same relative proportions, and the harmonious or inharmonious arrangement of the parts. My process is as follows: — Having determined the size , of the head to be represented, construct the right-angled isosceles triangle, A B C (the first of Plato, and half of the square), making PROPORTION. 43 its side, A C, one-third of the determined length ; and from the point C, with a radius, C A or C B, describe the circle A B D E. Construct within this circle the scalene triangle A F G (the second of Plato, and half of the equilateral triangle), and taking its sides as semi-diameters, describe the ellipse A F H I, of which A H is the major axis, and F I the minor axis. These two triangles are symmetrically proportioned to each other in relative size, the second being formed within the curvilineal figure belonging to the first, and, consequently, being in vertical length to it in the ratio of 3 to 2. These curvilineal figures, as explained in Part III,, are those that belong exclusively to the triangles from the sides of which they have received their propor- tions ; and they are, like the triangles themselves, necessarily in the same symmetrical proportion to each other. Let it now be supposed that these two curvilineal plane figures represent the solid bodies which a revolution upon their vertical axes would produce, namely, a sphere and a prolate spheroid, and that these bodies are united and partially amalgamated, so that the cir- cumference of the sphere passes through the centre of the prolate spheroid, as exhibited in the next diagram. Construct the triangle Plate i., A B C, describe the circle ABLE, and construct the triangle A F G, as in fig. 6. Through F draw F FI, equal and parallel to G A ; pro- duce G F, making F I equal to F G ; join I H, forming the triangle I H F ; describe the ellipse HI R G, of which II K is the major axis, 44 THE SCIENCE OF and I G the minor axis. This diagram, therefore, represents a vertical section, through A H, or side view, of fig. 6. Fig. 8 represents a horizontal section, or vertical aspect, of these Plate I., united bodies. Construct the isosceles triangle ABC, and describe tig. S. the circle A B D E, as in figure 6 ; make C F equal to the minor axis of the ellipse A F H I, figure 6 ; bisect this line in G, and with a radius, G C, describe the circle F H C I. These two bodies, thus proportioned and united, represent the typical form of the human head and face, as it arises from this combination of the elements of geometrical beauty. From what follows, it will he seen that the organs of sense may he proportioned and arranged, agreeably to the same laws, upon the facial surface, the reader bearing in view that the surfaces of these curvilineal bodies, in whatever aspect they may be represented, are understood to be referred to a plane — the only way in which any form can be depicted on the retina of the eye. Construct a diagram as in fig. 6, Plate I. ; bisect G H in L, Plate II., F G in M, and G I in N ; join M L and L N ; bisect M G in 0, fig. i. and from the centre M, with the radius M 0, describe the circle 0 ; make L V and N Z equal to M 0, and from the centres L and N, with the radii L V and N Z, describe the circles Y and Z. Con- struct the right-angled isosceles triangle L Q R, with its right angle at L, and its base tangential to the circle whose centre is L, and draw the line K P through L, parallel to F I ; draw A K, making PROPORTION. 45 the angle at A 18°, and complete the isosceles triangles ABE, A F I, and A K P. This diagram is composed of the elements of the five regular geometrical solids, and depends upon these ele- ments for its proportions. A side view of these united bodies, with a diagram of the situa- tion and proportions of the organs of sense which thus present themselves, is the result of the following process: — Construct a diagram the same as fig. 7, Plate I. ; bisect F Iv in M ; draw the line M L at right angles with II K. From L draw the line L N at an angle of 60° with the line L M ; draw the line N 0 parallel to H K ; draw the line L P parallel to M K, and through Iv draw P K parallel to L M. From each of the points L and N describe a circle with a radius equal to M O, fig. 1. Construct the right- angled isosceles triangle, L Q R, with its right angle at Q ; draw c d parallel to II Iv, and d S tangential to the circle around L. Thus, the two triangles which determine the proportions of the features are, as in fig. 1, the first and second of Plato. To show the position of the figures represented in the two pre- ceding diagrams upon a horizontal section, or vertical aspect, of the two united bodies, construct a diagram the same as fig. 8, Plate I. ; make a b, figs. 3 and 4, equal to a b, fig. 2 ; through a, with a radius M 0, fig. 1, describe the circle of which L is the centre. Construct the right-angled isosceles triangle L M N, and describe circles around M, N, and C, whose radii are equal to L a. Plate II., fig. 2. Plate II., figs. 3 and 4. o 46 THE SCIENCE OF Plate II., %• 1 - The harmonic relations of the angles of the three triangles employed in the construction of these diagrams have already been explained; and if we add to these triangles other two, A X D and A S Y, fig. 1, we have the following series: — First, a triangle whose angles are 45° 45° 90' Second, o O CO o O CO 90' Third, 22° 30' 67° 30' 90' Fourth, 18° to o 90' Fifth, 15° 75° 90 These exhibit the following: harmonic ratios to the right angle : — © © © Smallest Angles i at A. Middle Angles at B F X K S. 45° to 90° ratio 1 to 2 45° to 90° ratio 1 to 2 30° — 90° - - 1 — 3 60° — 90° — 2 — 3 22° 30' _ 90° - - 1 — 4 07° 30' — 90° — 3 — 4 18° — 90° - - 1 — 5 72° — 90° — 4 — 5 15° — 90° - - 1 — 6 75° — 90° — 5 — 6 The consecutive relations of these angles are as follow : — Smallest Angles. Middle Angles. 30° to 45° ratio 2 to 3 45° to 60° ratio 3 to 4 22° 30' — 30° — 3 — 4 o O CO — 67° 30' — 8 — 9 18° _ 22° 30' — 4 — 5 67° 30' _ 72 0 _ 15 — 16 15° — 18° ' — 5 — 6 72° _ 750 _ 24 — 25 PROPORTION. 47 If we now accommodate tlie anatomical structure of the bones Plate in. figs. 1, 2, of the head to this systematic arrangement of geometrical harmony, 3 > 4 we have the skull exhibited in its various aspects on Plate III., figs. 1, 2, 3, 4. In the ideal heads and countenances of ancient Greek art which still exist, there is necessarily considerable variety as to general forms and relative proportions of parts, and, as already observed, this has led many who have treated of the subject to assume that it must be difficult, if not altogether impossible, to determine any definite rules for the regulation of these proportions. This difficulty I shall now attempt to remove — begging of the reader, at the same time, to keep in mind that I confine myself to such variety as belongs to the permanent form of the anatomical structure, knowing that to impart the variety which results from the action of the muscles, and gives sentiment and expression to the countenance in obedience to mental impulses, requires the highest efforts of genius, and, con- sequently, belongs to a branch of art beyond the scope of a trea- tise, the sole object of which is to point out the primary laws of geometric harmony from which the countenance derives the beauty of its proportions. The principal varieties in the permanent form of the human head and countenance, as represented in works of ancient Greek art, are those which give, on the one hand, feminine delicacy, and, on the other, masculine power ; and these are not only sometimes 48 THE SCIENCE OF blended, but exchanged, in the Greek ideal heads, as they often are in those of ordinary nature. Of this, the heads of Minerva, Venus, Juno, Apollo, Hercules, Bacchus, &c., afford ample evidence. But in thus referring to these examples, it is scarcely necessary to remark, that as the laws of harmonic proportion which I now seek to illustrate leave untouched what belongs to the wider field of creative genius, they can in no way interfere with the higher themes Note H. of /Esthetic criticism in relation to ancient Greek art. I shall, there- fore, proceed with the legitimate object of this treatise, and endea- vour to show, geometrically and systematically, in what these cha- racteristic varieties in form and proportion consist, without reference to any existing examples. The proportions resulting from the numerical ratios in the angles of the triangles employed in constructing the diagrams in Plate II., will, I believe, on referring to Plate III., be generally acknowledged to have produced a purely feminine character of head in its anato- mical structure, although, as compared with ordinary nature, of a severely geometrical cast. The change in these ratios by which a masculine character of anatomical structure may be arrived at is of an equally specific kind. Instead of the series of triangles employed in constructing the diagrams in Plates I. and II., the fol- lowing are adopted — the first, second, and fourth being the principal, and the third and fifth the two additional ones which necessarily result from these : — PKOPORTIOX. 49 First, a triangle whose angles are 45° 45° 90 ! Second, 33° 45' 56° 15' 90' Third, 27° 63° 90' Fourth, 22° 30' 67° 30' 90‘ Fifth, 18° 72° 90' Exhibiting the following ratios to the right angle : — Smallest Angles at j i. Middle An gles at B F X K S. 45° to 90° ratio 1 to 2 45° to 90° ratio 1 to 2 33° 45' — 90° — 3 — 8 56° 15' — 90° — 5 — 8 27° — 90° — 3 — 10 63° — 90° — 7 — 10 22° 30' — 90° — 1 — 4 67° 30' — 90° — 3 — 4 18° — 90° — 1 — 5 72° — 90° 4 — 5 The angles of these triangles have the following relations to each other consecutively : — Smallest Angles. 33° 45' to 45° ratio 3 to 4 27° — 33° 45' — 4 — 5 22° 30' — 27° —5 — 6 18° _ 22° 30' — 4 — 5 45° Middle Angles. to 56° 15' ratio 4 to 5 56° 15' — 63° —8—9 63° — 67° 30' — 14—15 67° 30' 72° — 15 16 The principal change, and that which governs the other triangles, it will he observed, is made upon the second triangle, which gives Plate VI., fig. 1. H 50 THE SCIENCE OE its proportions to the prolate spheroid. Its smallest angle being 33° 45', is to the smallest angle of the first triangle in the ratio of 3 to 4, instead of 2 to 3, which was the ratio between these angles in the first diagram. The change from 30° to 33° 45' gives a ratio of 8 to 9. Between these two specific kinds of proportion there lie numerous intermedia, one of which, namely, that which lies midway between Plate iv., the two, I here give as a connecting link. Construct the right- angled isosceles triangle ABC, and describe the circle A B E, as in Plate II., fig. 1; within this construct the scalene triangle A F G, making its angle at A 31° 52' 30". Taking the sides of this tri- angle as semi-diameters, describe the ellipse A F H I ; within this ellipse construct the scalene triangle A K L, making its angle at A 21° 15' ; bisect G F in M, G I in N, and M G in O ; and with a radius, M O, describe the circles of which M N and L are the centres. Construct the right-angled isosceles triangle, Q L It, and the diagram Plate iv., of the intermediate form of head is complete. Figs. 2, 3, and 4, figs. 2, 3, and 4. as in Plate II., give the various aspects of these combined figures, Plate v., as referred to a plane; and Plate V., figs. 1, 2, 3, and 4, the ana- igs. 1, 2, .3, and 4. toiuical structure agreeably to these proportions. A diagram of the purely masculine proportions, the triangles of which have already been described, is formed in the following man- Piate vi., ner : — Construct the right-angled isosceles triangle A B C, propor- fig- i • tioning the length of its sides to the full length of the intended head O o O PROPORTION. 51 in the ratio of 4 to 11, instead of 4 to 12, as in the first diagram, and describe the circle A B L E, as in fig. 1, Plate II. ; within this circle construct the scalene triangle A F G, making its angle at A 33° 45'. Taking the sides of this triangle as semi-diameters, describe the ellipse A F FI I ; within this ellipse construct the scalene triangle A K L, making its angle at A 22° 30' ; bisect G F in M, G I in N, and M G in 0 ; and with a radius, M O, describe the circles around M, N, and L. Construct the right-angled isosceles triangle Q L R, and the two additional scalene triangles, A X Z and A S V, making the first 27° at A, and the second 18° at A. Repeat all the scalene triangles on the opposite side, and the diagram is complete. Figs. 2, 3, and 4 receive their proportions from fig. 1, as in Plates II. and IV. In Plate VII., the anatomical structure of the bones of the head is accommodated, in the four principal aspects, to this specific change in the geometrical harmony. On comparing this structure of skull with that given in Plate III., the characteristic difference in the general form, and in the relative proportions of parts (the whole being more square and massive), seems characterized by such a change in form and proportion as usually distinguishes the male from the female skeleton. The effects of this process of geometrical construction of the human head upon its external appearance, are exhibited in Plate VIII., figs. 1 and 2 of which are a front and a side view of the Plate VI., figs. 2, 3, and 4. Plate VII., figs. 1, 2, 3, and 4. Plate VIII. figs. 1 and 2 52 THE SCIENCE OF head and countenance, resulting from the first species of geometrical harmony. The predominating figure of this is the scalene triangle of 30°, 60°, and 90°, and will, I believe, he acknowledged as decid- edly feminine in character. The head of which figs. 3 and 4 are a front and side view, is Plate vm , the result of the medial combination — the predominating or ruling figs. 3 and 4. figure of which is the scalene triangle of 31° 52' 30", 58° 7' 30", and 90°. This head is neither decidedly masculine nor decidedly feminine in its general form and proportions. The decidedly masculine character of head and countenance which results from that species of geometrical harmony governed by Plate vm , the triangle of 33° 45', 56° 15', and 90°, is given in front and pro- figs. 5 and 6. file, in figs. 5 and 6. This operation of the numerical harmonic ratios in the con- struction of the ideal head of ancient Greek art, proves that the science of those proportions which distinguish it is identical with the well-established science of acoustics, and while it is as mathematically precise in its fundamental principles, it equally admits of an endless variety in the production of those works which are governed by its laws. It is a fact remarked by Dr Oken in his Pliysio-philosophy, that “ there are only two art senses, the eye and the ear ; and thus but two departments of art, the plastic and the sonant, or that of form and motion.” The result of this investigation, therefore, is the most satisfactory that could have been rationally looked for, PROPORTION. namely, that these senses, in their receptive powers, and the mind, in its perceptive faculty as to what these senses convey to it, are governed by one law of nature. The establishment of this law, however, induces me to differ from Dr Oken and others, when they say that the ideal head of ancient Greek art is unnatural, because there has not been found any individual in nature with a head fully exemplifying the pro- portions by which it is characterized. If I have succeeded in proving that the science of these proportions is identical with the science of acoustics, the ideal head of ancient Greek art is not only the most beautifid, but also the most natural — its form and proportions being the full development of a law which is only partially developed in ordinary nature. It will be shown in the sequel that, imperfect as this development is in general, it is sufficiently decided in all cases to give to the human head that characteristic form which so dis- tinctly marks the difference between it and those of the lower animals. It certainly has not been recorded by any who have hitherto investigated the subject, that an individual has been found with a head and countenance in every respect possessed of equal beauty of form with those represented in ancient Greek art ; yet it remains to be proved that examples of such could not have existed in nature, or may not exist. No countenance can be pronounced unnatural unless it be deformed ; and although such an inclination of the 54 THE SCIENCE OF major axis of the spheroid as will throw its vertex towards that of the sphere, changes the relative proportions, and lowers the head and countenance in the scale of humanity, this does not produce defor- mity, unless carried beyond certain well-defined limits, presently to be pointed out. But to give, in any degree, such a direction to the major axis of the spheroid as would throw its vertex outwards from that of the sphere, will produce deformity of a species too often to he found in works of art, where the effect of superior intel- lect is attempted to be imparted by an exaggerated imitation of the peculiarities of the antique. The human head, like every other object in nature, must have uniformity, combined with variety, to render it symmetrically beau- tiful ; but these qualities must be confined within certain bounds in their relations to each other. The uniformity consists in the correspondence between the lateral halves, and the variety in the relative proportions and situations of the features. There are, con- sequently, even in the ideal head, various modes in which the fea- tures may be arranged, without departing from ideal beauty, but only producing a change in its character. One of these changes is Plate ix., exemplified in Plate IX. Figs. 1 and 2 of this Plate are a front tigs. 1 and 2. and side view of the head, resulting from the first process, with the triangles G M L, and G N L, Plate II., fig. 1, altered from 30°, (10°, and 90° each, to 31° 52' 30", 58° 7' 30", and 90°, being the propor- tions of tl ie triangle upon which the ellipse of the intermediate head PROPORTION. oo is described. Figs. 3 and 4 are a front and side aspect of the same Plate ix , figs. 3 and 4. bead, with these triangles altered to 33° 45', 56° 15', and 90° — the same proportions as the triangle upon which the ellipse of the mas- culine head is described. Figs. 5 and 6 are a front and side view of Plate ix., figs. 5 and 6. the intermediate head, with this change, that the point L, fig. 1, Plate IV., is placed upon the circumference of the circle, by which the centre triangles have angles of 37° 30', 52° 30', and 90°. These changes give a more sensual cast to the features, without, however, reducing their intellectual capacity, because they do not affect the form of the cranium, or its relative proportion to the bones of the face, but simply the relative proportions between the length of the upper and of the under jaw. But the variety of ordinary nature is of a different description, and most frequently manifests itself in the development of these laws in an infinity of degrees of imperfection. In regard to this original perfection in the form and proportions of the human head and countenance — for such I conceive it to be — innumerable causes have operated, and do still continue to operate, on the one hand, in degrading it, and, on the other, in counteracting this degradation ; and to these operations may be attributed that endless variety of countenance by which nations, classes, and indi- viduals, are distinguished. Amongst such causes the effect of climate, and, still more, the degree of civilization under which a people is trained, seem to be the most effective. There can be no doubt that all the features are affected, to a great extent, by continual exposure • 5(3 THE SCIENCE OF to excesses of heat or cold ; but their character is more permanently formed by the degrees of moral restraint, as well as by the priva- tions and toil induced by the state of society. In savage life, on the one hand, the want of mental cultivation, and the consequent dor- mancy of the reasoning powers, must ultimately rob the countenance of its inherent capacity for intellectual expression. The modes, also, by which the means of existence are procured, along with continual exposure to the inclemency of the seasons, must produce a permanent expression of mere animal desire, and even, in some cases, of brutal ferocity. In civilized life, on the other hand, the employment of the higher faculties of the mind, agreeable occupations and amusements, refined modes of supplying the wants of nature, and the protection afforded from the inclemency of the weather, must all conduce towards regularity of the features, and impart to the countenance a permanent composure and serenity. As the passions by which the mind is thus moved, and the modes in which the wants of nature are supplied, act upon the muscles of the face, in giving them an enduring character, so must these muscles, in course of time, act upon the hones to which they are attached, producing a permanent effect upon the structure of the skull, which ultimately becomes hereditary in nations and classes. Hence the protruding jaws and high cheek-bones of savage tribes, as compared with those of the more civilized races of mankind. I shall now endeavour to illustrate the process by which the PROPORTION. 57 anatomical structure of the head geometrically changes from the most perfect development of the science of proportion, as exemplified in works of ancient Greek art, down to the most imperfect of ordinary nature. It has been observed in Part IV., that the structural characteristic of the human head was such a mixture of the globular, or spherical, and spheroidal forms, as resulted in an ovoidal figure, either in a front or vertical aspect, and that the natural position of the profile tended towards a vertical direction ; also, that the nearer to the per- fectly vertical, the more intellectual and beautiful is the cast of the countenance, and consequently, the more it inclines towards the hori- zontal, it becomes the less marked by these characteristics of humanity. In the combination of the sphere with the prolate spheroid, which forms the basis of the geometrical process by which the ideal heads explained in this part, and shown in Plates VIII. and IX., are pro- duced, the axis of the spheroid is made parallel to a vertical line passing through the centre of the sphere; to which parallelism, agree- ably to the principles adopted in this treatise, the principal distinc- tion between the artistic head of ancient Greek art and that of ordinary nature is to be attributed. According to the same principles, I shall now proceed to show how a departure from this parallelism affects the general structure of the head, and relative position of the features upon the facial surface, and that it does so without any change being made on the proportions farther than what the degree i 58 THE SCIENCE OF of this inclination produces. The farthest limit to which I shall carry this inclination of the axis is 27°, which gives the general form and characteristic proportions of the head of the African negro, or those of a European of the lowest grade. According to many writers on the natural history of man, there have existed abnormal races of a lower class than this change in the geometrical structure indicates ; but the discussion of such questions does not influence my subject, as the existence or non-existence of such races leaves the principles I am attempting to demonstrate unaffected. Between the vertical position of the axis and an inclination of 27°, there are an ample number of gradations to embrace every species of characteristic form ; but in order to give a sufficiently marked dis- tinction, I shall take, as a connecting link, an inclination of 18°. The parallelism of the axis of the spheroid to the vertical axis of the sphere, in the examples already given, enabled me to commence with the diagram of a front view of the head and countenance ; but, as in such an aspect the inclination about to be given could not be per- ceived, unless in its effects, I shall now commence with the diagram of a profile, which, accordingly, is fig. 1, in the following examples, instead of fig. 2, as in those already given. The change from the ideal, exhibited in this connecting link, may be described as follows : — Construct a diagram of the circle and first ellipse, with their prin- cipal divisions, as in fig. 2, Plate II., but, instead of making the major axis of the ellipse II K parallel to the vertical diameter A I) Plate X., % 1- PROPORTION. 59 of the circle A E D B, give its vertex, H, an inclination of 18°, keeping its centre, F, on the circumference of the circle A E D B, and its own circumference tangential to a line, Y Z, drawn through A, at right angles with A D. Upon this diagram draw the line a b through F, parallel to A D. At right angles with a b, draw the lines E t, through C ; c d, through X ; e S, through L ; and g h, through f. Plate X., figs. 2, 3, The other three diagrams, figs. 2, 3, and 4, of this example, take their and 4. proportions from the vertical and horizontal lines of fig. 1. Plate XI. exhibits the change upon the anatomical structure of Plate XI., figs. 1, 2, 3, the bones of the head and face, produced by this inclination of the aiul 4 - axis of the first ellipse, and, consequently, of the axis of the pro- late spheroid which it represents. Plate XII. exhibits the change upon the anatomical structure, Plate xii., figs. I, 2, 3, agreeably to the second, or intermediate, proportions. and 4 - Plate XIII. exhibits the change upon the anatomical structure, Plate xm., figs. 1, 2, 3, agreeably to the third, or most masculine, proportions. and 4 - Figs, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, and 6, of Plate XIV., exemplify the external Plate xiv., figs. ], 2, 3, appearance of the heads and countenances formed upon the anato- 4 - aml <>• mical structure, agreeably to the three kinds of proportions, as modified by the inclination of 18° of the prolate spheroid. The diagram in Plate XV., except in one point, being the same Plate xv., % 4 - as that given in Plate X., farther description is unnecessary, than merely to state that the inclination of the axis of the spheroid is here carried to 27°, which I conceive to be its natural limit. This 60 THE SCIENCE OF Figs. 2, 3, 4. Plates XVI., XVII., and XVIII. Plate XIX. Plate XX., figs. 1. 2, 3, 4, 5, and 6. Plate XXI. farther inclination, it will he observed, materially affects the other figures, and gives to the three anatomical structures which follow, in Plates XVI., XVII, and XVIII., the peculiar characteristics of form which belong to the skull of the negro. These, like the three fore- going skulls, are drawn upon diagrams of the first, second, and third class, or of the feminine, medial, and masculine proportions ; and the following example gives the heads and countenances formed upon them, with the characteristic thick lips and woolly hair of the African negro. Although thick lips and woolly hair (unless in rare and apparently accidental exceptions) compose part of the clothing of this structure of skull in the African negro, they do not seem to assist in lower- ing the intellectual character of the countenance resulting from it. These peculiarities in the clothing of the structure appear rather to modify the effects of its departure from the mathematical beauty with which the Creator originally endowed it. This I have endeavoured to make apparent, by clothing the same skulls with such European features as are suitable to their structure. A species of countenance is thus produced not unfrequently to he met with amongst ourselves, and evidently the result of a degraded state of society. When we compare the heads on Plate XIV. with the antique or ideal heads on Plate VIII., there seems a very considerable hiatus. In order, therefore, to give a connecting link, I have exemplified the effects of an inclination of 9°, the exact intermediate between PROPORTION. 61 a vertical position and an inclination of 18°. The head and features resulting from this diagram, and given in Plate XXII., although Plate xxii. figs. 3 and 4- exhibiting such an approximation to a full development of the science of proportion as we seldom meet with in ordinary nature, is still evidently devoid of the peculiar grandeur produced by the perfect parallelism of the axis of the prolate spheroid to the vertical axis of the sphere. To the Plates given in illustration of the nature of the science of proportion, and the mode of its application, I have added other three, in order to show the effect of some of those geometric heads when freed from the lines of the diagrams, and decorated in the Greek style. Figs. 1 and 2, of Plate XXIII., are a front view and profile of a Plate xxm. female head, drawn agreeably to the geometric diagram and anato- mical structure in Plates II. and III. Figs. 3 and 4, are a front and side aspect of a male head, drawn agreeably to the diagram and ana- tomical structure in Plates VI. and VII. These heads are given, with the lines upon them, in Plate VIII., figs. 1 and 2, 5 and 6. Figs. 1, 2, 3, and 4, of Plate XXIV., are front views and profiles Plate xxiv. of two female heads, drawn agreeably to the geometric diagram and anatomical structure in Plates II. and IIP, and modified, as shown in Plate IX., figs 1, 2, 3, and 4. Figs. 1 and 2, of Plate XXV., are a front view and profile of a Plate xxv female head, drawn agreeably to the geometric diagram and ana- (32 THE SCIENCE OF PROPORTION. tomical structure in Plates IV. and V. This head is given, with the geometrical lines upon it, in Plate VIII., figs. 3 and 4. Figs. 3 and 4, are a front view and profile of the same head, with the geometrical construction modified, as shown by the male head, figs. 5 and 6, Plate IX. Thus have I endeavoured to trace to its primary elements the beauty of proportion which distinguishes the artistic head of ancient Greek art from that of ordinary nature. I have shown that these elements are of the most simple kind, and that the peculiarity of their nature consists in an embodiment of the fundamental principles of numerical ratio ; which, thus applied, are as much the cause of that harmony of form by which all the parts unite in one pleasing whole, as they are, by a well understood law of nature, the source of harmony amongst various sounds when simultaneously addressed to the ear. These ratios are, therefore, the first principles of formative beauty, and constitute a science of proportion sufficiently definite to admit of universal application in the arts of design. NOTES. NOTES. NOTE A, (P. 6.) The distinction between the truly beautiful and the merely agreeable is clearly defined by Cousin. He observes — “ When we cast our eyes over existing nature, whether it be over the life that is called human, or that more extensive organic life, or even over inanimate nature, subject only to mechanical laws, we meet with objects that make us feel pleasing or painful sensations. A form is present to your eyes, and at the moment that you know it is, you feel an agreeable or a disagreeable sensation. If you are asked why it pleases you, you cannot give a reason ; if you ai’e told that it displeases others, you are not surprised, because you know that sensibility is not constant, and that it is not necessary to dispute about sensations. Up to this point we have not slipped into the domain of art ; its object is beauty, and we are but at the agreeable. Now, does it not sometimes happen that a form is not only agreeable to us, but, beyond this, that it appears beautiful to us ? When we were asked why it was agreeable to us, we could only have answered, according to our individual right, ‘ I am the sole judge of what pleases or displeases me; 1 but when we are asked why we call this form beautiful, we appeal to an authority which is not our own, which is imposed on all men — the authority of reason. ...... “To the question, AVhat are the characteristics of the agreeable and of the beautiful l we reply, that it will be shown presently that unity, proportion, simplicity, regularity, K 66 NOTES. grandeur, and generality, appear more or less in objects that we call beautiful ; and that variety, motion, pliantness, energy, and individuality, are marks of the agreeable.”* The want of a more extensive dissemination of such correct and comprehensive views upon this subject, has led to the erroneous notion that every one has a right to hold his own opinions as to the beauty of proportion in works of formative art. The author, therefore, feels that he cannot recommend too strongly to his readers the study of Cousin’s excellent work, from which the above extract is taken. NOTE B, (P. 10.) The full title of the work here referred to is — An Inquiry into the Original of our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue : in two Treatises , in which the Principles of the late Earl of Sha/ts- bury are Explained and Defended against the Author of the Fable of the Bees ; and the Ideas of Moral Good and Evil are established , according to the Sentiments of the Ancient Moralists. With an Attempt to introduce a Mathematical Calculation in subjects of Morality. London: 1725. The author of this work makes many excellent observations upon the nature of beauty with reference to art, from which I shall select the following. He observes (p. 6) — “ The only pleasure of sense that our philosophers seem to consider, is that which accompanies the simple ideas of sensation ; but there are vastly greater pleasures in those complex ideas of objects, which obtain the names of beautiful, regular, harmo- nious.” At p. 7 he says, “It is of no consequence whether we call these ideas of beauty and harmony, perceptions of the external senses of seeing and hearing, or not. I should rather choose to call our power of perceiving these ideas an internal sense , were it only for the convenience of distinguishing them from other sensations of seeing and hearing which men may have without perception of beauty and harmony.” ' The Philosophy of the Beautiful. From the French of Victor Cousin. Translated, with Notes and an Introduction, by Jesse Cato Daniel, Cheshunt College. London : William Pickering. 1848. NOTES. 67 This is exactly the difference between what we are enabled to pronounce as beautiful, or, simply, as pleasing to our senses. At p. 33 are the following observations : — “ As to the works of art, were we to run through the various artificial contrivances or structures, we should find the foundation of the beauty which appears in them to be constantly some kind of uniformity , or unity of proportion among the parts, and of each part to the whole. As there is a vast diver- sity of proportions possible, and different kinds of uniformity , so there is room enough for that diversity of fancies observable in architecture , gardening , and such like arts, in dif- ferent nations: they all may have uniformity , though the parts in one may differ from those in another. The Chinese or Persian buildings are not like the Grecian and Roman , and yet the former has its uniformity of the various parts to each other, and to the whole, as well as the latter. In that kind of architecture which the Europeans call regular , the uniformity of parts is very obvious, the several parts are regular figures , and either equal or similar at least in the same range ; the pedestals are parallelopipedons , or square prisms ; the pillars, cylinders nearly ; the arches circular, and all those of the same row equal ; there is the same proportion everywhere observed in the same range between the diameters of pillars, and their heights — their capitals, and the diameters of arches— the heights of the pedestals, the projections of the cornice, and all ornaments in each of our five orders. And though other countries do not follow the Grecian or Roman proportions, yet there is even among them a proportion retained, a uniformity , and resemblance of cor- responding figures ; and every deviation in one part from that proportion which is observed in the rest of the building, is displeasing to every eye, and destroys or diminishes at least the beauty of the whole. “ The same might be observed through all other works of art , even to the meanest utensil, the beauty of every one of which we shall always find to have the same foundation of uniformity amidst variety, without which they shall appear mean, irregular, and deformed.” The soundness of these doctrines is not surpassed, and has been seldom equalled, by writers upon art of the present day. 68 NOTES. NOTE C, (P. 20.) I think it requisite to lay the following facts before the reader, connected as they are with the mode of aesthetic culture adopted in this country. So far back as March 1836, a select committee of the House of Commons was appointed “ to inquire into the best means of extending a knowledge of the Arts and of the Principles of Design among the people (especially the manufacturing popula- tion) of the country ; also, to inquire into the constitution, management, and effects of institutions connected with the arts. 1,1 Amongst many others, I had the honour to be examined before this committee, and on that occasion stated my firm conviction that the best mode of extending a knowledge of art and of the principles of design among the people (especially the manufacturing population) of the country, would be to disseminate such printed instructions as would enable the rising generation to commence a system of self-tuition, by first practising the drawing of geometrical figures by the free hand, and then to study from the large well- developed leaves of such plants as were to be found on the road-sides and hedge-rows throughout the country ; observing, that as great elegance of form is to be found in the common dock, the thistle, the fern, and even in a stalk of oats or barley, those who thus formed their taste, when they came to study the ornamental remains of Athens and Rome, would find themselves familiar with the source from which the beauty of those works was in a great measure derived ; for the ancients adopted the most common pro- ductions of nature for the leading features of their ornamental designs. I also observed, that this kind of study could not be commenced too early, or made too general, as, independently of its usefulness, it would prove a continual source of pleasure to all who might adopt it — and being a means of drawing out the latent talent of the country, would thereby form a test by which teachers could select their pupils ; concluding, that schools established upon such a basis would conduce more to originality of orna- mental design amongst our manufacturing population than any other means that could be employed. NOTES. 69 When asked by the chairman, if I did not consider that free access to a collection of casts from the antique would be of service, I replied, “Undoubtedly it would; but such examples would be of tenfold benefit to those who had brought themselves to a degree of proficiency by the mode I have already recommended. It is at this stage that the works of the ancients ought to be studied, in order to derive benefit from their beau- tiful combinations, but not servilely copied : I consider servile copying of the works of others very injurious to the ornamental designer, as it retards originality of conception.” — {Report, 568 — Arts and Manufactures — 1 6th August 1836. Pp. 37 to 43.) Such was the general tenor of the suggestions I made on that occasion ; but they do not seem to have had any weight with the committee, as the result of its labours was the establishment, early in the following year (1837), of a Government School of Design at Somerset House, in which the means employed for “ extending a knowledge of the Arts and of the Principles of Design amongst the manufacturing population of the country” have been lately brought to light, in the following manner : — In 1847, ten years after the establishment of this school, a committee of the Board of Trade was appointed to investigate the mode in which it forwarded the objects for which it was instituted. One of the leading witnesses examined before this committee says — “ At present, copying is the plan laid down, and thus the pupil is led to no higher exertion of his faculties than the desire to imitate.” Another witness says — “ Instead of any attempt being made to teach the principles of any style of ornament, the only principle acted upon is that of continual copying. And this system is not merely suf- fered, but encouraged ; indeed, I may say that it is the only system taught.” The result of this investigation has necessarily been an alteration in the constitution of the school, by which it is hoped better means may be used for extending a knowledge of art amongst the people. One of the resolutions, in the Report of the second special committee, augurs well, being a step towards a system of self-tuition, namely — “ That the Committee of Instruc- tion should take into immediate consideration the question of establishing elementary schools, and the practicability of relieving the head school of a large number of young students who have not attained a certain degree of knowledge of the principles and prac- tice of drawing.” 70 NOTES. The facts to which I have alluded, however, fully warrant the statements I have made in the text regarding our mode of aesthetic culture. NOTE D, (P. 28.) In order that the reader may judge for himself as to the accuracy of what I have stated in the text regarding the Platonic theory, as translations of the works of that phi- losopher are not very widely circulated, I shall here (as in a former work) give the whole passage referring to these triangles : — “ But when the Artificer began to adorn the universe, he first of all figured with forms and numbers fire and earth, water and air, which possessed, indeed, certain traces of the true elements, but were in every respect so constituted as it becomes anything to be from which Deity is absent. But we should always persevere in asserting that Divinity ren- dered them as much as possible the most beautiful and the best, when they were in a state of existence opposite to such a condition. I shall now, therefore, endeavour to unfold to you the distribution and generation of these by a discourse, unusual indeed, but to you who have trod in all the paths of erudition through which demonstration is necessarily obtained, perspicuous and plain. In the first place, then, that fire and earth, water and air, are bodies, is perspicuous to every one. But every species of body pos- sesses profundity ; and it is necessary that every depth should comprehend the nature of a plane. Again, the rectitude of the base of a plane is composed from triangles. But all triangles originate from two species, one of which possesses one right angle, and the other two acute angles, and one of these contains one right angle distributed with equal sides ; but, in the other, unequal angles are distributed with unequal sides. Hence, pro- ceeding according to assimilative reasons, conjoined with necessity, we shall establish a principle of this kind as the origin of fire and all other bodies. The supernal principles of these, indeed, are known to Divinity, and to the man who is in friendship with I )i vinity. “ But it is necessary to relate by what means four most beautiful bodies were pro- duced, dissimilar, indeed, to each other, but which are able, from certain dissolutions NOTES. 71 into each other, to become the sources of each other’s generation ; for if we are able to accomplish this, we shall obtain the truth concerning the generation of earth and fire, and of those elements which are situated according to analogy between these ; and then we shall not assent to any one who should assert that there are visible bodies more beau- tiful than these, each of which subsists according to one kind. W e must endeavour, therefore, to harmonize the four sorts of bodies excelling in beauty, and to evince by this means that we sufficiently comprehend the nature of these. Of the two triangles, indeed, the isosceles is allotted one nature, but the oblong or scalene is characterized by infinity. We ought, therefore, to choose the most beautiful among infinities, if we wish to com- mence our investigation in a becoming manner. And if any one shall assert that he has chosen something more beautiful for the composition of these, we shall suffer his opinion to prevail, considering him not as an enemy, but as a friend. Of many triangles, there- fore, we shall establish one as most beautiful (neglecting the rest) — I mean the equila- teral, which is composed from three parts of a scalene triangle. To assign the reason of this would, indeed, require a prolix dissertation ; but a pleasant reward will remain for him who, by a diligent investigation, finds this to be the case. We have, therefore, selected two triangles out of many, from which the body of fire and of the other elements is fabricated, one of which is isosceles, but the other is that which always has its longer side triply greater in power than the shorter. “ But that which we formerly asserted without sufficient security, it is now necessary more accurately to define ; for it appeared to us, though improperly, that all these four natures were mutually generated from each other ; but they are in reality generated from the triangles which we have just described — three of them, indeed, from one triangle con- taining unequal sides ; but the fourth alone is aptly composed from the isosceles triangle. All of them, therefore, are not able, by a dissolution into each other, to produce from many small things a mighty few, or the contrary. This, indeed, can be effected by three of them ; for, as all the three are naturally generated from one triangle, when the greater parts are dissolved, many small parts are composed from them, receiving figures accom- modated to their natures. And, again, when the many small parts, being scattered according to triangles, produce a number of one bulk, they complete one mighty species of a different kind. And thus much may suffice concerning their mutual generation. NOTES. 72 “ It now remains that we should speak concerning the quality of each of their kinds, and relate from what concurring numbers they were collected together. The first species, indeed, is that which was composed from the fewest triangles, and is the element of that which has its longer side twice the length of the shorter side, which it subtends. But two of these being mutually placed according to the diameter, and this happening thrice, the diameters and the shorter sides passing into the same as into a centre, hence one equilateral triangle is produced from six triangles ; but four equilateral triangles, being composed according to three plane angles, fonn one solid angle, and this the most obtuse of all the plane angles from which it is composed. Hence, from four triangles of this kind receiving their completion, the first solid species was constituted, distributive of the whole circumference into equal and similar parts. But the second was formed from the same triangles, but at the same time constituted according to eight equilateral triangles, which produced one solid angle from four planes, so that the second body received its completion from the composition of six triangles of this kind. And the third arose from the conjunction of twice sixty elements, and twelve solid angles, each of which having twenty equilateral bases, is contained by five plane equilateral triangles. In this manner, then, the other elements generated these. But the isosceles triangle, being constituted according to four triangles, and collecting the right angles at the centre, and forming one equilateral quadrangle, generated the nature of the fourth element. But six such as these being conjoined, produced eight solid angles, eacli of which is harmonized together, according to three plane right angles. Hence the figure of the body thus composed is cubical, obtaining six plane quadrangular equilateral bases. There is also a certain fifth composition, which Divinity employed in the fabrication of the universe, and when he delineated those forms, the contemplation of which may justly lead some one to doubt whether it is proper to assert that the number of worlds is infinite or finite.” — The Works of Plato, translated by Taylor, Vol. II., p. 52G. NOTES. 73 NOTE E, (P. 35.) In the year 1807, the Academie des Inscriptions et Belles Li tires offered a prize on the following question : “ What were the chief causes which produced the great schools of sculpture and painting among the Greeks; and by what means can they be reproduced?” On the competition for this prize, M. Victor Cousin makes the following remarks : — “ The successful writer, M. Emerie David, maintained that it was by the contempla- tion and constant study of real forms, by the exact reproduction of natural objects, that the ancients had raised the arts to the highest degree of perfection ; and that, therefore, imitation alone could help us to reach the Grecian beauty, the true expression of life. M. Quatremere de Quincy contested this opinion, and affirmed that it was not by the study of natural forms, but by realizing ideal beauty, that the Greeks brought those works to light which are not found in nature. He showed that there are two great prin- ciples in the arts, the one individual and imitative — the other general, abstract, absolute, and creative. The first can produce nothing but portraits — the second arrives at the purely beautiful. M. Emerie David maintained that ideal beauty is the model, and the model is in nature. M. Quatremere proved that the model, however beautiful it may be, is always nothing but one of the less imperfect of the human species. Art, according to M. de Quincy, expresses the general and the absolute ; according to M. Emerie David, it- expresses the individual. These two theories can be reconciled, if, in the arts, we are not ruled entirely by the individual, or entirely by the absolute. Shall we resign ourselves to the exclusive contemplation of the individual, or shall we view the model as a perfect ideal, of which there is not a vestige in living nature? The question again returns to that of the mathematical circle. My opinion is, that we begin at once, at the same moment, with the individual and the absolute. At the sight of a natural figure which possesses some rude proportion, the mind gifted with power to conceive of the absolute and general, when this figure is presented to it, constructs it into a perfect circle. But man can never realize in matter a geometrical circle : he can only produce a natural one, and therefore an imperfect one. It is thus that, in the idea of the true, the beautiful, and the good, there are always two elements blended — the one concrete and particular, L 74 NOTES. the other abstract and absolute. As we have already said, there are two kinds of abstrac- tion : First , We examine several individuals; we overlook their differences, that we may attend to their resemblances ; thence we form a kind of collective unity : this operation of the mind may be called comparative abstraction ; Secondly, By an abstraction of another kind, one object being given, without having recourse to any comparison, we disengage from that one object a general and absolute view-point. I call this operation of the mind, immediate abstraction. This is true not only of pure geometry, but of the concep- tion of the beautiful in the fine arts, and of the good in morals Ideal beauty, then, is evolved from real beauty, by an immediate abstraction which perceives the one in the other. The operation is twofold ; if it were not, we should obtain the individual by itself, or the absolute by itself — that is to say, life without the ideal, or the ideal without life. Art must devote itself to the production of the ideal and of nature equally. 11 — Philosophy of the Beautiful , p. 32. NOTE F, (P. 39.) In the article on the Fine Arts, in the seventh edition of the Encyclopaedia Britannica, the author (Hazlitt) attributes the ideal beauty of the Greek statues to the immediate imitation of nature, and remarks — “ What has given rise to the common notion of the •ideal as something quite distinct from actucd nature , is probably the perfection of the Greek statues. Not seeing among ourselves anything to correspond in beauty and gran- deur, either with the features or form of the limbs in these exquisite remains of antiquity, it was an obvious, but a superficial conclusion, that they must have been created from the idea existing in the artist’s mind, and could not have been copied from anything existing in nature;” and continues to argue that “the general form both of the face and figure which we observe in the old statues is not an ideal abstraction — is not a fanciful inven- tion of the sculptor, but is as completely local and national (though it happens to bo more beautiful) as the figures on a Chinese screen, or the copperplate engraving of a negro chieftain in a book of travels. 11 He farther remarks, that “ the Greek form appears to 1n t 0TES. < o have been naturally beautiful, and had, besides, every advantage of climate, of dress, of exercise, and inodes of life to improve it and supposes from these causes, operating in conjunction with that of the artist having every opportunity afforded him for studying the human form, ideal beauty was produced. In the article on Painting, in the same publication, the author (Hayden) attributes the perfection of Greek art to a very different cause, and observes — “ The whole history of ancient art shows the estimation in which the unsophisticated judgment of the public was held. Aristotle says — ‘ The multitude is the surest judge of the productions of art.’ ‘ If you do not get the applause of the public,’ says some one else, ‘ what cele- brity can you attain ?’ and Cicero makes the public the supreme judge. Thus, then, no one ought to wonder at the perfection of Greek genius in everything, stimulated as it was by these secondary causes, and the one acting upon the other in a climate adapted in every way for comfort, health, and for convenience. The Greeks were men like ourselves; not larger, as their arms prove, and not handsomer, for there exist as fine forms, in either sex, in Great Britain, as ever graced the atelier of Zeuxis ; indeed, Cicero complains of the plainness of the Athenians. When genius and secondary causes unite, as they some- times do, then such men as Pericles and Alexander, and Polygnotus, Zeuxis, and Apelles, are the result.” These very opposite opinions, advanced in the same publication by two such popular writers on the fine arts, prove how very unsettled the question still remains. As to the particular proportions of the human countenance, generally given in those lectures upon the principles and practice of the arts, upon which the public has so much reliance, Haydon’s directions are a fair specimen. He says — “The head is four noses from top to chin, and from ending of hair in front, three to chin ; make the forehead broad, not ‘ villanous low,’ as Shakspeare says ; the eyes, an eye separate ; the face, from the root of the hair to the chin, three noses ; the upper lip, a fourth of the nose ; the ear, two noses sideways from the nostrils,” &c . — Lectures on Fainting , p. 7 1 . 7 6 NOTES. NOTE G, (P. 40.) Jn farther illustration of this part of my subject, I shall here give some quotations from Mengs, Winckelmann, Leonardo da Vinci, and J3ossi, which I have selected (along with some accompanying observations of the author) from one of the best works upon the beauty of the human form with which I am acquainted.* Mengs, in treating of the remains of ancient Etruscan and Greek statues, says — “ In these figures we find a proportion, impossible to be known and practised without an art which furnishes sure rides. These rules could not be founded otherwise than in propor- tion, which was invented and practised by the Greeks.” That the Greeks,” says Bossi, “ wrote much on this subject (their doctrine respect- ing symmetry) we have ample evidence in Pliny, Vitruvius himself, Philostratus the younger, and others. “ Polycletus did not confine himself to giving a commentary upon this fundamental point, but, in illustration of his treatise, according to Galen, made an admirable statue, that confirmed the precepts laid down in the work; and The Rule of Polycletus, the name given to this statue, became so famous for its beauty, that it passed into a proverb to express a perfect body, as we may find in Lucian. But of so many treatises not a frag- ment remains (except the few lines of Vitruvius), nor is there now any hope that a ves- tige will be found, unless something may remain for posterity amongst the papyri of Heroul aneum.” Upon this Mr Walker justly remarks — “ Now, to approach to the ancients in excel- lence is quite impossible, until some one shall explain the great principles upon which they acted, Assuredly they are, in some of the most important respects, unknown at present. Servile imitation will never answer the purpose ; and to learn as the ancients did, and reach perfection, perhaps in as many ages, is not very rational, when we can avail ourselves of their practice to discover their principles.” “ It is probable,” says Winckelmann, “ that the Grecian artists, in imitation of the Egyptians, had fixed, by well-determined rules, not only the largest, but even the very smallest proportions, and Beauty, illustrated chiefly by an Analysis and Classification ?a? mm ? §S tiaiSP IV. yoxrcst Scalp? ] III ? D.ILEajrDel^ 17. l^oTrest Sculp 1 D.Ii.Hky-IDel!' If. Tone st Scxlp? D.EHkjrDel' t W Forrest Sculpt 1 WORKS BY D. R. HAY, F.R.S.E. i. FIRST PRINCIPLES OF SYMMETRICAL BEAUTY. Octavo. 100 Plates. Price 6s. THE PRINCIPLES OF BEAUTY IN COLOURING SYSTEMATIZED. Octavo, with 14 Coloured Diagrams. Second Edition. Price 15s. III. A NOMENCLATURE OE COLOURS, HUES, TINTS, AND SHADES, APPLICABLE TO THE ARTS AND NATURAL SCIENCES , TO MANUFACTURES, Ac. With 228 Examples. Price 35s. IV. AN ESSAY ON ORNAMENTAL DESIGN, IN WHICH ITS TRUE PRINCIPLES ARE DEVELOPED AND ELUCIDATED, Ac. Oblong Folio. 57 Plates and numerous Woodcuts. Price £2, 2s. PROPORTION, OR THE GEOMETRIC PRINCIPLE OF BEAUTY ANALYZED. Quarto. 17 Plates and 38 Woodcuts. Price 25s. THE NATURAL PRINCIPLES AND ANALOGY OF THE HARMONY OF FORM. Quarto. 18 Plates and numerous Woodcuts. Price 15s. VII. THE LAWS OF HARMONIOUS COLOURING ADAPTED TO INTERIOR DECORATIONS, Ac. Sixth Edition. With Coloured Diagram. Price 7s. 6d. W. BLACKWOOD & SONS, EDINBURGH AND LONDON. OPINIONS OF THE PRESS. I NOTICES OF THE THREE WORKS ON “PROPORTION,” “ FORM,” AND “ COLOUR,” IN The Edinburgh Review, Oct. 184 3. “ These works are highly honourable to Mr Hay as a practical man. He has been long known | as an extensively employed and elegant artist in the department of decorative painting; and he has found leisure, notwithstanding the pres- sure of his professional avocations, to appear before the public as an author, with strong claims to its attention and respect. He is one of the few artists who have drawn the resources of their profession from the recognised fountains of knowledge; and who, in offering the lessons of their experience at the shrine of science, have been anxious to listen, in return, to her infallible counsels. The disposition to this species of ex- change, and to introduce into the intellectual community the principles of free intercourse, is by no means general ; but we are confident that art will not sufficiently develop her powers, nor science attain her most commanding position, till the practical knowledge of the one is taken in return for the sound deductions of the other. “ Many causes have concurred to place art and science at variance: but these causes have been gradually diminishing, and in the present ad- vanced state of the mechanical and useful arts, they have almost wholly disappeared. It is in the fine arts, principally, and in the speculations with which they are associated, that the con- trolling power of scientific truth has not exer- cised its legitimate influence. In discussing the principles of painting, sculpture, architecture, and landscape gardening, philosophers have re- nounced science as a guide, and even as an auxi- liary; and a school has arisen whose speculations will brook no restraint, and whose decisions stand in opposition to the strongest convictions of our senses. That the external world, in its gay colours and lovely forms, is exhibited to the mind only as a tinted mass, neither within nor without the eye, neither touching it nor distant from it — an ubiquitous chaos which experience only can analyze, and touch transform into the realities which compose it — that the beautiful and sublime in nature and in art derive their power over the mind from association alone — are among the philosophical doctrines of the present day, which, if it be safe, it is scarcely prudent to question. Nor are these opinions the emanations of poetical or ill-trained minds, which ingenuity has elaborated, and which fashion sustains. They are conclusions at which most of our most dis- tinguished philosophers have arrived. They have been given to the world with all the au- thority of demonstrated truth; and in propor- tion to the hold which they have taken of the public mind, have they operated as a check upon the progress of knowledge. “ While opinions like these were con- sidered as sound and well established, philoso- phers never thought of studying the laws of visible direction in single and double vision, by which all the difficulties of the subject have been subsequently removed; and, in like man- ner, while the present theories of taste prevail, there can be no inducement to discover the rules of harmonious colouring, or to investigate the origin of beautiful forms, or to develop the laws of regular and irregular symmetry. When speculation, however, is thus in the ascendant, ; and theorists least apprehensive of danger, truth is often securing auxiliaries from localities the least likely to supply them. The sovereignty of association in matters of taste had never been recognised by practical men, who study nature principally through the eye; and the painter, the sculptor, the architect, and the landscape gardener, had been striving in their respective spheres to discover those ‘ laws of harmony,’ both in colour and form, which ought to regu- late the taste, and direct the hand of the artist. In so far as we know, Mr Hay is the first and the only modern artist who has entered upon the study of these subjects without the tram- mels of prejudice and authority. Setting aside the ordinances of fashion, as well as the dicta of speculation, he has sought the foundation of his profession in the properties of light, and in the laws of visual sensation, by which these proper- ties are recognised and modified. The truths to which he has appealed are fundamental and irrefragable; and the conclusions which he has deduced from them will admit of no modifica- tion either from taste or fashion. In the adap- tation of his principles, indeed, to the various circumstances in which they are to be applied, taste and judgment are undoubtedly required; and even in the decoration of the boudoir and the drawing-room harmony of colour and sym- metry of form may be made to co-exist with, and even to control, the caprices of fashion, and the glitter of meretricious ornament. “ Notwithstanding some trivial points of dif- ference between Mr Hay’s views and our own, we have derived the greatest pleasure from the perusal of these works. They are all composed with accuracy, and even elegance. His opinions and views are distinctly brought before the reader, and stated with that modesty which characterizes genius, and that firmness which indicates truth.” — 0 — The British and Foreign Medical Review. No. XXXV. P.171. “ There is harmony of numbers in all nature — in the force of gravity — in the planetary move- ments— in the laws of heat, light, electricity, and chemical affinity — in the forms of animals and plants — in the perceptions of the mind. The direction, indeed, of modern natural and phy- sical science is towards a generalization, which shall express the fundamental laws of all by one simple numerical ratio. We would refer to Professor Whewell's ‘ Philosophy of the Induc- tive Sciences,’ but more particularly to Mr Hay’s ‘Researches into the Laws of Harmonious Co- louring and Form.’ From these it appears that the number seven is distinguished in the laws regulating the harmonious perception of forms, colours, and sounds, and probably of taste also, if we could analyze our sensations of this kind with mathematical accuracy. We think modern science will soon show that the mysticism of Pythagoras was mystical only to the unlettered, and that it was a system of philosophy founded on the then existing mathematics, which latter seem to have comprised more of the philosophy of numbers than our present.” Fraser’s Magazine. “ We have now gone over all Mr Hay's works, but, we confess, not in a manner calculated to OPINIONS OF THE PRESS. 3 do them the justice they deserve. This, indeed, could be done only in the pages of a work de- voted to scientific pursuits, and whose particular class of readers may be supposed to possess that peculiar turn of mind which delights in philoso- phical inquiry, and in the abstruse investigations of science. In a periodical like ours, such in- quiries would be out of place. “Yet, enough has been said, it is presumed, to show that the author of the works we have just been noticing is a remarkable man. He un- doubtedly is. He is a leader in his vocation; one of those men who stand prominently out in the front of his fellows, and who, by the force of original genius, have acquired a certain ascen • deney over the public mind. “ Looking to the philosophical spirit and cha- racter of Mr Hay's treatises, we cannot but con- sider them valuable acquisitions, their purpose being to improve the general taste, and by con- sequence — for it is a consequence thereof — to contribute to the advancement of civilization. NOTICES OF THE “FIRST PRINCIPLES OF SYMMETRICAL BEAUTY,” IN The Spectator, Oct. 31, 1846. “ This is a grammar of pure form, in which the elements of symmetrical, as distinguished from picturesque beauty, are demonstrated, by reduc- ing the outlines or planes of curvilinear and rectilinear forms to their origin in the principles of geometrical proportion. In thus analyzing symmetry of outline in natural and artificial ob- jects, Mr Hay determines the fixed principles of beauty in positive shape, and shows how beau- tiful forms may be reproduced and infinitely varied with mathematical precision. Hitherto the originating and copying of beautiful colours have been alike empirical; the production of a new design for a vase or a jug has been a matter of chance between the eye and the hand ; and the copying of a Greek moulding or ornament, a merely mechanical process. By a series of pro- blems, Mr Hay places both the invention and imitation of beautiful forms on a sure basis of science, giving to the fancy of original minds a clue to the evolving of new and elegant shapes, in which the infinite resources of nature are made subservient to the uses of art. “ The volume is illustrated by one hundred diagrams, beautifully executed, that serve to ex- plain the text, and suggest new ideas of beauty of contour in common objects. To designers of pottery, hardware, and architectural ornaments, this work is particularly valuable : but artists of every kind, and workmen of intelligence, will find it of great utility.” — o — The Athenaeum, Jan. 2, 134 7. “ The volume before us is the seventh of Mr Hay’s works. It is the most practical and sys- tematic, and likely to be one of the most useful. It is, in short, a grammar of form, or a spelling- book of beauty. This is beginning at the right end of the matter; and the necessity for this kind of knowledge will inevitably, though gradually, be felt. The work will, therefore, be ultimately appreciated and adopted as an intro- duction to the study of beautiful forms. “ The third part of the work treats of the Greek oval or composite ellipse, as Mr Hay calls it. It is an ellipsis of three foci, and gives practical forms or vases and architectural mouldings, which are curious to the architect, and will be very useful both to the potter, the moulder, and the pattern-drawer. A fourth part contains applications of this to practice. Of the details worked out with so much judgment and ingenuity by Mr Hay, we should in vain at- tempt to communicate just notions without the engravings of which his book is full. We must, therefore, refer to the work itself. The forms there given are full of beauty, and so far tend to prove the system.” — o — The Glasgow Courier, Nov. lO, 1846 . “ This is a work which could not fail, under any circumstances, to be highly appreciated by those professionally engaged in the pursuits of art, as well as by that numerous class amongst general society who are now happily accustomed to feel an intelligent interest in connection with the productions of artistic genius; whilst it seems to possess at the present time more particularly, a very high degree of value in relation to the efforts now made under legislative encourage- ment for advancing amongst the producing classes a knowledge of the principles of sym- metrical beauty by the instrumentality of schools of design. In conclusion, we may state that, valuable as all Mr Hay’s preceding works on painting and design are acknowledged to be, we question whether there is any one of them which can claim to rank superior, if even equal, to the present, in point of practical value. And we feel much pleasure in recommending it to general notice as a work fitted to convey both instruc- tion and pleasure to the artist as well as the general reader.” NOTICES OF “THE PRINCIPLES OF BEAUTY IN COLOURING” IN The Spectator. “ In this new analysis of the harmonies of colour, Mr Hay has performed the useful ser- vice of tracing to the operation of certain fixed principles the sources of beauty in particular combinations of hues and tints; so that artists may, by the aid of this book, produce with mathematical certainty the richest effects, hither- to attainable by genius alone. Mr Hay has re- duced this branch of art to a perfect system, and proved that an offence against good taste in respect to combinations of colour is in effect a violation of natural laws. “ The volume is of beautiful exterior, fit for the drawing-room table; and the diagrams of colours are bound up in a separate volume con- nected with the text, yet distinct from it, like two books under one cover, so that the reader can refer to the illustrations without inter- ruption.” — o — The Britannia. “ From Mr Hay’s theory, scientifically stated and ably reasoned, it results that the mind has in its very constitution certain instincts directing it to the perception of beauty in colour as in 4 OPINIONS OF THE PRESS sound, and that the greatest artist in colour, at least, is he who follows those instincts most un- erringly. Mr Hay is well skilled in the practice of colour, and in its harmonious combinations ; and more confidence, therefore, will be felt in his conclusions when it is known that his own suc- cess sprung from the application of his own prin- ciples. “ Mr Hay has illustrated his theory by ex- amples in colour, disposed, not on the artistic, but on the mathematical principles, and has spared no labour to render his Essay acceptable to the scientific inquirer.” — o — The Athenaeum. “ Mr Hay is already well known to our readers by a long series of books on beauty. We had first, ‘The Natural Principles and Analogy of the Harmony of Form’ developed; then, not long after, his Treatise on ‘ Proportion, or the Geometric Principle of Beauty ; ’ and next, his ‘ Essay on Ornamental Design,’ with its fifty- seven plates. Thus much on beauty of form ; but we have also had a similar series on beauty of colour — first, in ‘ The Laws of Harmonious Co- louring;’ then in ‘ The Nomenclature of Colours, Hues, and Tints ; ’ and, finally, the conclusion of this matter, in ‘ The Principles of Beauty in Co- louring,’ now before us. We have enumerated these six steps of this series, because we have re- garded, and do still continue to regard, the pro- duction of Mr Hay’s works as a remarkable psychological phenomenon — one which it is in- structive both for the philosopher and the critic to study with care and interest, not unmingled with respect. In these books we behold a strong, manly, honest mind, endowed with considerable sensibility, and working its way slowly, labori- ously, almost even groping it, among the chaotic masses of beautiful and unbeautiful things in the material world, in the endeavour to extricate from this heterogeneous mass a few of those beautiful, deep-seated, elusive truths, in virtue of which inert matter becomes endowed with that living soul which we love, which we call beauty, and which Plato denominated ro xa.Xov x,ai ayccdov, the soul of the world. In this long series of Mr Hay’s works, we are enabled to trace his progress from year to year in this arduous pursuit of the beautiful and true. We see how his mind has been gradually guided by Nature herself out of one track, and into another, and ever and anon leading him to some vein of the beautiful and true, hitherto unworked.” NOTICES OF “THE NOMENCLATURE OF COLOURS,” &c. IN The Daily Mews. “ A nomenclature of colours, in which their enumerable hues and tints should be divided from their primary elements, has long been a desideratum It is so, however, no longer, thanks to the talent and industry of Mr D. R Hay. “In this work Mr Hay has brought a larger amount of practical knowledge to bear on the subject of colour than any other writer with whom we are acquainted, and in proportion to this practical knowledge, is, as might be ex- pected, the excellence of his treatise. There is much in this volume which we would most ear- nestly recommend to the notice of artists, house decorators, and, indeed, to all whose business or profession requires a knowledge of the manage- ment of colour. The work is replete with hints which they might turn to profitable account, and which they will find nowhere else.” “ An anxiety to be useful, to render his know- ledge and acquirements subservient to practical purposes, is evident in every page of Mr Hay’s work, a quality which cannot fail to be duly appreciated by all who take an interest in the advancement of art.” — o — The Athenaeum. “ We have formerly stated the high opinion we entertain of Mr Hay’s previous exertions for the improvement of decorative art in this country. We have already awarded him the merit of invention and creation of the new and beautiful in form. In his former treatises he furnished a theory of definite proportions for the creation of the beautiful in form. In the present work he proposes to supply a scale of definite proportions, for chromatic beauty. For this purpose he sets out very properly with a precise nomenclature of colour. In this he has constructed a vocabulary for the artist — an alphabet for the artisan. He has gone farther — he constructs words of three syllables. From this time it will be possible to write a letter in Edinburgh about a coloured composition, which shall be read off in London, Paris, Petersburgh, or Pekin, and shall so express its nature that it can be reproduced in perfect identity. This Mr Hay has done, or at least so nearly, as to deserve our thanks on behalf of art, and artists of all grades, even to the decorative artisan — not one of whom, be he house painter, china pattern drawer, or calico printer, should be without this simple manual of ‘ words for colours.’ ” The Scotsman. “ Here is another professional work by Mr Hay, and one distinguished by all the charac- teristics by which his other works recommend themselves to public notice and favour — vigour, originality, and an entire and thorough mastery of his subject, “ Taking the work altogether, there can be no doubt of its being one of the very best of its kind that has yet been presented to the public. The amount of practical knowledge it contains, and the masterly way in which that knowledge is placed before the reader, cannot fail to impress him with sentiments of the highest respect for the talents and acquirements of the author. Nor will these sentiments be weakened by noting the philosophical spirit in which, when opportunity offers, he treats his subject — affording in this, evidence of an order of intellect equal to much greater things than the demands of his pro- fession.” — o — The Courant, “ The whole tenor of the work evinces, on the part of the author, a sincere desire to advance art, a spirit of genuine philosophy, and a lively appreciation of the beautiful. Never before has been exhibited so systematic, so complete, so satisfactory an arrangement of colours. The whole of the chromatic scale, through all its gradations and modulations, is shown. Its melo- dies, harmonies, and contrasts, are all clearly ON MR D. R. HAYS WORKS. O defined. All the individual colours, tints, and hues, are placed in their proper position, ex- tending- through a series of two hundred and forty. The arrangement is so skilful, that the eye wanders delighted over them all, from the fiery and exciting colour of red, down to the most gentle and retiring of the neutral tones.” — o — The Glasgow Constitutional. “This, perhaps, will be found to be the most generally useful of the many valuable and very ingenious works with which its indefatigable author has, within these few years, enriched our literature. It so far surpasses all previous at- tempts of the kind as to preclude any comparison with them. “ The book addresses itself more immediately to those engaged in the study of the arts, sci- ences, and manufactures; and of its value and importance to this class of persons we need say nothing. But w r e would strongly recommend it also to the attention of all who take an interest in objects of taste, as containing an amount of in- formation which they will find nowhere else, and from which even those whose eye has been most carefully cultivated in the perception aud dis- crimination of colour, will find that they have much to learn.” Edinburgh Weekly Journal. “ Mr Hay may in his works, both as an artist and an author, be almost considered as the founder of a new department of design. That he was thoroughly master of his subject, the warm approbation which has greeted his works on Harmonious Colouring, Form, Proportion, &c., sufficiently evinces ; and the present work may be considered as the practical application ot some of the theories jjropounded, as, after teaching his disciples how to use their tools to produce the best effects, he here gives the tools themselves, viz., colours, mapped out, arranged, classified, and described, not only as to the es- sential composition, qualities, and effects of each, but also its relations to its neighbour and its antagonist tints, and the exact influences over all by the interference, more or less, of the two great opposites, black and white, darkness and light.” — o — The Glasgow Argus. “ Mr Hay is not alone a patron of the arts, but, as an instructor of the followers of art, he is a benefactor to the public. All his works, whether he writes upon ornamental design, or the har- mony of form, the laws of harmonious colour- ing, or brings his comprehensive mind to bear analytically upon the geometric principles of beauty, while they improve and delight the reader, render him the more capable of being of use, by extending his sphere of action, and placing him nearer that perfection it must be the constant aim of every artist to arrive at. “ The primary colours are taken by Mr Hay in their natural order ; and not only will the artist and the connoisseur find ample material for thought, but the naturalist, the mineralogist, and the botanist, will discover new lights opened out to them of the most valuable tendency. NOTICES OF THE ESSAY ON The A then scum, April 12, 1845. “ In conclusion, Mr Hay’s book goes forth with our best wishes. It must do good. It must be prolific of thought — stimulant of invention. It is to be acknowledged as a benefit of an unusual character conferred on the arts of ornamental design.” — o — The Spectator, January 4, 1845. “ Mr Hay has studied the subject deeply and scientifically. In this treatise on ornamental de- sign, the student will find a clue to the discovery of the source of an endless variety of beautiful forms and combinations of lines, in the applica- tion of certain fixed laws of harmonious propor- tion to the purposes of art. Mr Hay also ex- emplifies the application of his theory of linear harmony to the production of beautiful forms generally, testing its soundness by applying it to the human figure, and the purest creations of Greek art.” Fraser’s Magazine, Jan. 1845. “ We come now to Mr Hay’s last, and, we are almost tempted to say, his best work, be- cause of the more popular nature of its interest. Each part is enriched by diagrams of great “ORNAMENTAL DESIGN” IN beauty, direct emanations of principle, and, con- sequently, presenting entirely new combinations of form. Had our space permitted, we should have made some extracts from this ‘ Essay on Ornamental Design;’ and we would have done so, because of the discriminating taste by which it is pervaded, and the forcible observations which it contains ; but we cannot venture on the indulgence.” — o — Civil Engineer and Architect’s Journal, May, 184 5 “ Mr Hay has paid particular attention to this branch of design, which is of extensive applica- tion, and as to which few accessible examples exist. It will, from its intrinsic interest, prove an attractive work for the study and the draw- ing-room.” — o — Renfrewshire Advertiser, Feb. 1845. “ So broad are the principles, and so pervad- ing the illustrations, which Mr Hay has laid down in this work, that it cannot be said to in- clude no other students than those connected with the industrial arts, to whom he has ad- dressed his able and important Essay. It in- volves the whole range of ornamental design.” NOTICES OF THE WORK ON “FORM” IN The Athenaeum. “ The study of the true , the goods and the beau- tifuls has formed an important occupation of life in all highly civilized nations, and has been in- culcated by the truest patriots and the highest philanthropists. Science, virtue, and beauty, form the noblest elements of creation, and of the human soul — they form the first objects of 6 OPINIONS OF THE PRESS uur national institutions, the highest elements of a national character, and the best themes of a i national literature. 44 It would be a great step in the advancement of our national civilization, were the love of the beautiful, and the power of appreciating the value of its manifestations, more intimately | mixed up with the associations and habits of our j countrymen. That we have artists of high powers — architects of consummate skill — that we have, or have had, Barrys and Cockerells, Wilkies and Etty^, Landseers and Mulreadys, Flaxmans and Chantreys and Westmacotts, is matter of national congratulation, but does little j to prove the existence of a high standard of | national taste. The habit of enjoying the beau- ! tiful, and the power of appreciating it, should pervade the national character, should determine its national institutions, and be diffused among the peasantry of our streets and hamlets. 4 The farmer and the mechanic (we quote Clianning) should cultivate the perception of beauty .'' — 4 Every man should aim to impart this perfec- tion to his labours.’ Were every man a judge and appreciator of beauty, then, indeed, might we expect forms of loveliness and grace to per- vade the regions of domestic and every-day life — to replace, in our streets, the expensive ugli- ness of our street decoration — in our homes, the | vulgarities of ornamental deformity — and in our churches, the distortions and anomalies of mere- tricious decoration. “We hail, therefore, with delight, the appear- ance among us of any evidence of progress to- wards the diffusion of correct principles in taste, of accurate knowledge in art — and we receive the work before us as a harbinger of better times — as an index of the wider diffusion of knowledge in art. “ Hay on 4 Harmonious Colouring ’ formed the precursor to Hay on the 4 Harmony of Form.’ The former work was chiefly designed to correct and direct the public taste in the decorations of domestic life : the present has a higher aim — the determination of the forms and proportions which give to objects and structures a maximum of beauty. “ The fact that Mr Hay, by an independent process of his own mind, versant about propor- tion and beauty, has arrived exactly at some of the identical proportions of the Platonic theory, as we understand and apply it, is to be reckoned as an important psychological phenomenon, de- monstrating the inherence of certain fixed and essential principles of proportion and beauty in the human soul. “All Mr Hay’s proportions are, therefore, good. They exist in the best specimens of per- fect architecture; they are necessary elements in judicious decoration. They give rise to sym- metry and simple numerical proportions in an- gular compositions They pervade the works of the Greek artists, and were the identical prin- ciples taught by the philosophers who gave wis- dom to the times of Pericles and Phidias.” — o — The Court Gazette. “ This is a work of great talent and value. It has the peculiar merit of being new and original, in the midst of the sickly spirit of repetition, which seems to shed its drowsy influence over the largest department of modern publication. It is devoted to Form. The author is one of the individuals peculiarly endowed with that rich gift which constitutes the sculptor, the archi-l tect, and the painter ; and hence the ingenious theory developed in this work, which logically associates sight with sound, geometry with acoustics. It is the developed theory of Plato, who eloquently commented on the music of beautiful forms— a theory which Darwin, the Platonic poet, in a note to his 4 Temple of Na- ture,’ practically carries out, by suggesting the construction of a machine which, while pro- ducing the varied notes of the gamut to the ear, should, at the same time, present to the eye the 4 various modulations ’ of the prismatic co- lours. Mr Hay’s theory is somewhat like this, but practically developed for the painter, the sculptor, and the architect. The illustrated architectural examples deserve especial notice. The geometrical production of the fa§ade of a Doric temple, from the projected combination of the vescica piscis, or double circle — (the free- masons’ secret of Ancient Egypt, and the monas- tic architects’ of the middle ages) — is most curi- ous. We cordially recommend to our readers this ingenious work, which is profoundly philo- sophical in its geometrical analysis of abstract form, and replete with the exciting spirit of poetry and music in its tasteful associations.” — o — The Sun. 44 The object of this treatise is to show that the impressions made upon the eye by forms are really founded on natural principles; and that the proportions and peculiarities of form which produce the most pleasing impressions, are in reality, as well as appearance, dictated by nature, being a response to those principles in the hu- man mind. The treatise is singularly well writ- ten, both as respects manner and matter, exhibit- ing a force and closeness of reasoning which lead to the inference that the author has a decided penchant for mathematical pursuits, and is ex- tensively acquainted with that difficult and com- plicated science. He gives several curious and interesting plates, illustrative of certain theories advanced in the course of his treatise. These plates are finished off 1 with the utmost nicety, and artists and men of science will derive many a useful suggestion from them.” — o — The Glasgow Herald. “It is, of course, impossible, in a cursory notice like this, to do more than indicate the general character of the very profound, as well as extremely interesting theory which Mr Hay has propounded The volume, we may remark in conclusion, contains numerous most beautiful diagrams, illustrative of the author’s theory ; and the reader may feel himself amused, as well as instructed, by studying 4 the melody of the portico of the Parthenon,’ expressed in musical notes, as well as by the intervals of Mr Hay’s scale of harmony of form.” — 0—— The Glasgow Citizen* 44 This is decidedly an able, as well as original, publication, in some degree in the subject, but more so in the author’s manner of treating it. 44 To persons of taste and knowledge in art, Mr Hay’s work will be peculiarly acceptable, and we are confident that such will consider it as no slight contribution to the cause of art and sci- ence.” The Caledonian Mercury, 44 This treatise on the principles of linear liar- ON MR D. R. HAY'S WORKS. i mony, will eminently conduce, we think, to one main object, which its ingenious author seems to have had in view, namely, the improvement and guidance of the public taste in judging of works of art that owe their excellence to beauty of form. Mr Hay has here undertaken to demon- strate, and, so far as we are able to judge, he has done so clearly and convincingly, that the im- pressions made upon the eye by forms are really founded on natural principles — that the propor- tions and peculiarities of form which produce the most pleasing impressions are dictated by nature, being a response to these principles in the human mind — and that forms are, in all respects, analogous to sounds ; so that a system of linear harmony may be established similar to i that which regulates the arrangement of musical notes.” NOTICES OF THE WORK ON “HARMONIOUS COLOURING ADAPTED TO DECORATION,” IN The Critic, May 1, 184 3. “ The volume before us is an evidence of the great progress which has been made of late years in the taste for decorative .art To Mr Hay belongs the merit of having been among the first to invite the attention of his country- men to decoration as an art. He first reduced to rule and reason the paints and papers to be used in the various rooms of a dwelling. The choice of colours was little more than a freak of fancy, until he showed why one should be pre- ferred to another.” — o — Fraser’s Magazine. “ In the absence, in the general case, of all in- dications of taste in the internal decorations of our dwellings, or which is, perhaps, yet more to be lamented, in the presence of the evidences of a bad one, our understandings have been hither- to wrapped in a kind of Cimmerian darkness, as regards the employment of decorative painting for domestic purposes, for the embellishment of our dwellings. A ray of light, however, and a brilliant one, has been let into this dark pro- found by Mr Hay, who not only points to a bet- ter state of things, but leads the way. Urged by the irrepressible energies of an active, vigor- ous, and original mind, Mr Hay has stepped from the ranks of a profession, hitherto of the hum- blest pretension — a profession whose practice was thought to require little judgment, and still less taste — and has rendered himself remarkable by the ability with which he exposes this fallacy. Mr Hay has, in truth, elevated house-painting to the dignity of an art — an achievement which he has accomplished simply by recognising princi- ples, the power of which in producing the most beautiful , in both form and colour, his own practice has long illustrated. In his ‘Laws of Harmonious Colouring,’ Mr Hay blends the sci- entific with the practical, which, in popular lan- guage, means two things: first, that he begins at the beginning of his subjects; and, second, that he gives reasons for all he advances. “ The art of house-painting has hitherto been considered a very humble one ; but it would be no difficult task to show, that it is far from being so inherently, and that its degradation was wholly the result of combined negligence and incapacity. The proof of this may be found in the elevation to which it has been raised by the genius and talent of Mr Hay.” The Spectator. ‘ Mr D R. Hay of Edinburgh affords another and a striking proof of the advantage, as well as the pleasure, derivable by a craftsman in intel- lectualizing his labour by scientific study. He thoroughly understands his subject — a merit that does not belong to all writers — and he lays down the principles of Harmony in Colour, as applicable to decorative purposes, explicitly and fully and in a practical manner.” — o — The Morning Chronicle. “ In the early part of his work, Mr Hay throws a most important light on the theory of colours, by the agency of which he has been enabled to go much further towards the elucidation of this subject than any previous writer. He then, in a lucid manner, explains the relations which colours, in their various tints, hues, and shades, should have to each other to produce an har- monious result. “ After the extracts we have made, it is hardly necessary to observe, that this is a work of great originality; and we have not the least hesitation in adding, that we believe that a diffusion of the knowledge of the principles laid down in it would prove of material use to our manufac- turers. In addition also to the utility of the study of those laws which regulate harmonious colouring to those engaged in productive in- dustry, there can be little doubt that a know- ledge of them would greatly enhance the plea- sure derived from pictorial art.” — o — The Atlas. “ This is a new and improved edition of Mr Hay’s work on the ‘ Laws of Harmonious Colour- ing, and is adapted to every art and science in which colours form an accessory. Every line of this useful book shows that the author under- stands his business ; and he has contrived to in- tellectualize his subject in a very interesting manner. The principles of harmony in colour, as applied to decorative purposes, are explained and enforced in a lucid and practical style, and the relations of the various tints and shades to each other, so as to produce an harmonious re- sult, are descanted upon most satisfactorily and originally. The applications of the laws of colour- ing to house-painting is an era in science; and the precepts given cannot fail to dignify the calling, by converting it into an imaginative as well as an agreeable and useful pursuit.” — o — The Ulster Times, “We are happy to see that the good taste of the public has called for a third edition of Mr Hay’s ingenious treatise on this interesting sub- ject. While we hail Mr Hay’s work as likely to popularize the delightful study of which it treats, we can assure the scientific and the re- fined, that they will find in it many observations worth their attention.” 8 OPINIONS OF THE PRESS. The Architectural Magazine. “ It is impossible to peruse the work before us without being convinced that the author is tho- roughly acquainted with the science of his art. We have given as distinct an idea as we can of Mr Hay’s treatise without the aid of his coloured plates; and we have done so with a view of showing every young architect, or other person connected with houses or furniture, how much they may gain from Mr Hay’s book In short, there is no other such work on the subject of which it treats, and none of which it may be so truly said, that it ought to be in the hands of every one at all connected, however remotely, with building or furnishing. We repeat, that we cannot too strongly recommend Mr Hay’s work to our readers.” The Edinburgh Chronicle. “ This work, written by an eminent citizen of Edinburgh, has been long before the public, and has been so highly appreciated, that it has now undergone three impressions. It is well worthy of this great success, for it is a production of uncommon originality and genius ; and, while it is honourable to the taste and talents of its author, it cannot fail to prove extremely useful, not merely to the young aspirant, but to the most experienced and eminent artist, particu- larly to the house-painter. House-painting has hitherto been considered as scarcely connected with art at all, and has consequently, in practice, been characterized by no exhibition of taste or ‘ harmonious colouring but Mr Hay has struck out new lights as to his profession, and has shown in this publication that the business of a house-painter should be founded on science, and regulated by laws, as well as the higher depart- ments of art. And, what is more, he is the great sublime he draws. In his own extensive busi- ness, he has carried most successfully into effect those great principles which he has so well de- veloped in the work before us ; indeed, his own bright example has done for the art of ‘ harmo- nious colouring,’ in this city and neighbourhood, more than has been effected by his predecessors in the same profession for centuries. — o — Chambers 7 Journal. “ An exceedingly instructive little volume has fallen under the notice of the editor, entitled, * The Laws of Harmonious Colouring, adapted to House-Painting,” by D. R. Hay, house painter in Edinburgh, and a perusal of which would be | sure to refine the taste of the artisan engaged in this ingenious profession, and be particularly serviceable to gentlemen in the embellishment of their residences. It will have been often re- marked, that the colouring of the walls in our houses is in many cases unpleasing to the eye, and quite out of character with the furniture, the carpets, the degree of light, or the nature of the chambers. One room is painted green, be- cause green is a pretty bright colour; while another, for some reason equally frivolous, is daubed over with a pink salmon tint. To cor- rect these, and many other absurdities in house- painting, Mr Hay has presented us with a variety of comprehensive rules.” — o — The Literary Journal. “We are glad that Mr Hay’s book has gone to a second edition; and we doubt not that the, ability and excellent knowledge of his profession which it displays, will meet with the reward to which they are well entitled.” — o — The Patriot. “ It is impossible to read Mr Hay’s clear, lucid remarks, without being at once convinced that he is completely master of his subject. Indeed, we have never perused a work which, in a less obtrusive manner, contained more useful and well arranged information.” — o — The Civil Engineer and Architect’s Journal. “ Mr Hay’s book is the fourth edition of a work decidedly esteemed for its practicability, cheapness, and the soundness of its principles; and to it is added, in this edition, an excellent treatise on house-painting. It is, indeed, the cheapest and best book on the subject, and one to which our readers, of aH classes, may refer with advantage and delight.” — o — Loudon’s Encyclopaedia of Archi- tecture. “ After consulting all the works that are con- sidered the most valuable on the subject of house and ornamental painting, we think that by far the best, and indeed the only one that embraces principles, is a work entitled, ‘ The Laws of Har- monious Colouring,* &c., by Mr D. R. Hay, house- painter, Edinburgh. We strongly recommend Mr Hay’s work to every painter who aims at ex- cellence in his profession, and to every amateur who wishes to judge for himself.” Ancient and Modern Art, Historical and Critical. By George Cleghorn, Esq. “ But of all the treatises on the harmonic theory, those of Mr Hay of Edinburgh — already well known to the public for his excellent work on the ‘ Laws of Harmonious Colouring’— are the most J satisfactory. He has illustrated his subject by a series of publications, embracing ‘ The Harmony of Form;’ ‘Proportion, or the Geometrical Principle of Beauty Analysed;’ ‘ The True Principles of Ornamental Design as applied to Decorative Arts,’ &c. In the opinion of the best judges, he has j all but arrived at the solution of the Platonic theory — a discovery which involves an important psychological phenomenon, demonstrating the existence of certain fixed principles of proportion and beauty in the human mind. The development of such principles may be of essential service in their application to architecture, and that description of decorative art connected with geometrical figures. It is impossible to read these treatises without being convinced that the author is well versed in geometry, music, and acoustics. His style is clear, graceful, and philosophical. His works are not only highly interesting, but quite original, and well worth the attention both of the artist and the philosopher. EDINBURGH: JOHNSTONE, PALLANTYNE, AND CO. GETTY CENTER LIBRARY 3 3125 00113 4366 , _