Cl Q ^.A Bk. Trinity College Library Diirham, N. C. • ■ - - - -- I Rec’d i..i5?_br | THE POSITIVE THEOEY OF CAPITAL BY EUGEN V. BOHM-BAWERK COTOSELLOE IN THE AUSTRIAN MINISTRY OF FINANCE, AND HONORARY MMFESSOR OF POLITICAL ECONOMY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF VIENNA TRANSLATED WITH A PREFACE AND ANALYSIS BY WILLIAM SMART, MA. LECTURER ON POLITICAL ECONOMY IN QUEEN MARGARET COLLEGE, GLASGOW REPRINT i9‘J8 G. E. STECHERT A CO. NFAV-YOHK Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2017 with funding from Duke University Libraries https://archive.org/details/positivetheoryof01bohm 3 5 TRANSLATOR’S PREFACE In his Geschichte und Krilik der Kapitalzins-Theorieen (1884), -which I translated in 1890 under the title oi Capital and Interest, Professor Bohm-Bawerk, after passing in critical review the various opinions, nractical and theoretical, held from the earliest times on the sub- ject of interest, ended with the words : “ On the foundation thus laid, I shall try to find for the vexed problem a solution which invents nothing and assumes nothing, but simply and truly attempts to deduce the phenomena of the formation of interest from the simplest natural and psychological principles of our science.” The Positive Theory of Capital, published in Innsbruck in 1888, and here rendered into English, is the fulfilment of that promise. The criticisms directed against the various theories of Interest in the former work may be briefly summarised as follows. The Productivity theories — those which, more or less explicitly, attribute the existence of interest to the productive power of capital — are dismissed as confusing quantity of product with value of pro- duct, either in the way of tacitly assuming the identity oi-ihejwo, or of fading to show any necessary connection between them. The problem of capit al is a pr^ lem of surplus value, and value does not come from the side of producliott-btrt-from the side of consumption. Capital is productive, but interest is not its product. The Use theories, which are a more or less scientific expan- sion of the familiar formula, “ Interest is the price paid for the use of capital,” are shown to base interest, which is notoriously an income obtained from all kinds of capital, on an analogy drawn from one special kind of capital, -viz. durable goods. The idea that the use of capital is something distinct from the using-np of capital, and interest something different from the price of the principal, becomes untenable when the true economic nature of the “ good ” is understood as the sum of its material uses or services. If con- sumption is only a single exhaustive use, and use only a prolonged consumption, the payment for “ use ” of Capital must be included in the price of capitd. In the Abstinence theory, which makes interest a compensation. VI TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE made to the owner of capital, for his renunciation of immediate con- sumption, Bohm-Bawerk sees a confusion of the origin and accumu- lation of capital with the source and cause of interest. Abstinence will account for the owner having a sum to lend, but it will not account for that sum growing 3% larger in a year’s time. Lastly, the Socialist or Exploitation theory, which makes interest simply a gain from exploited labour, is shown to be a theory which could only arise on the negative basis of the unsatisfactory accounts hitherto given, and on the positive basis of a mistaken value theory. When an income obtained without work and without risk was claimed as the reward of abstinence, and when all value was ascribed to the action of material labourers, it was inevitable that there should rise a reactionary theory proving that interest was robbery. Thus the board was swept clean for the Positive Theory A translator who does his duty must pass the work he renders through his own mind. The necessity this imposes on him of understanding his author, and getting at his point of view, should make him peculiarly sensitive to certain diflBculties which are not removed by simple translation. Modes of thought, arrangement, manner of working, may remain foreign. A translator’s preface, then, is not without justification if it anticipates some of the ques- tions that are sure to arise in the minds of readers more accus- tomed, perhaps, to English economics. Now as the main difficulty of the present work is that alluded to by Professor Bohm-Bawerk in his own Preface, that_the strikingly simple outlines of his theory are o bscured by the very elaboration and completeness with which it_js_ w:prked__ouL perhaps the best service I can do is to give a short direct summary of the main argument, expanding on one or two points which seem to me to require commentary. Economic science being based on an analysis of the industrial life, the first question in a theory of capital is one of terminology : What do es tjm practical world mean, and what has it hitherto meant, by the word Capital ? Here we find in common acceptance not one but two conceptions, both based more or less on Adam Smith’s old distinction between National Capital and Individual Capital. It is quite necessary for scientific progress that the exact distinction between these two conceptions should be fully recognised, but it would be useless to refuse the name to either of them : the practical world would not follow us. On looking closer at the two, however, we can see that one of the conceptions really includes the other, and that the difficulty may be avoided by adding an appropriate predicate to each. Taking as basis the old root idea of “an interest-bearing sum of money,” we may define capital in its widest sense (or Acquisitive Capital), as the complex of products destined to the Acquisition of goods. Under this, as narrower category, we put the conception that came later in time, TRANSLATOR’S PREFACE vii but perhaps better deserves the name without predicate, that of Social or Productive C^ita], comprising all products destined for the production of fresl^wealthj briefly, the complex of Intermediate Products. Thus we happily preserve in both conceptions the popular idea of “ income bearing ” : society as a whole can only obtain an income by “producing” new wealth, while the individual may “ acquire ” it as well by the transfer of old wealth. By these definitions Land a nd Labour are excluded from capital. They have certain analogies, even close analogies, with it, but scientific accuracy is not gained by making definitions so wide as to conceal really discrepant elements. The definition of Social Capital also excludes the Maintenance of Labourers ; for, obviously, to include the direct and most obvious means of living would be to take away all possibility of distinguishing between capital and con- sumption wealth. The subject, then, naturally divides itself into two parts; — Capital in the narrower, but more widely important, meaning of the Instru- ment of Production, and CapitaLas^the Source of Income. First, of the I nstrument, of Production. In the economical Avorld man finds himself a being of infinite want, confronted with a universe full of potential wealth but with no tools except hands and brains to give him possession of it. Incapabl e of creat ing any- thing. he yet finds himself endowed with a powe r of moving things, which, as he masters the secrets of nature’s working, gradually enables him to imprison, impress, or suspend the action of her powers, and so make her his servant. In various concrete ways he adapts or rearranges nature — never, of course, changing her laws or acting contrary to them, but varying the causal connection of natural processes in such a way that, to a large extent, he remakes the natural world to suit his purposes. Thus, between man and his natural environment there gradually grows up a third term, a machinery for the fuller satisfaction of man’s life, and to this, in general terms, we give the name Capital. But, however the growth of wealth and industry disuse the fact, in all production of wealth there are only two original forces at work, nature’s powers and man’s powers. Human powers, as always limited, and as always put forth “ at the cost of ” brain or tissue, are all “ economic ” ; but in the great treasury of natural forces there are some powers so universal in their scope and working that they do not enter into calculations of cost. As we say, using two phrases whose full significance we do not always realise, we do not “ economise ” the free gifts of nature — they “ cost ” us nothing ; although they enter into the operations of all production, they do not enter into “ economic ” consideration. The original factors of production, then, are man and nature : the strictly economic factors of production are labour and those natural forces (called by metonymy Laud) viii TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE which are limited and capable of being monopolised. But Capital, however much credit it gets and deserves for its work in present- day production, is no independent factor alongside of these. In one aspect it may be called “ stored-up labour,” in another — and more truly — “ natrff.al.force^stored_uix--by-4abour ” but in capital itself, , alike in its origin and in its working, there is nothing that is not accounted for by the other two factors. We say, in its origin and its working, and it is advisable to emphasise that these are distinct things. The origin of capital is due to two factors, Indus try^ and Saving, both being indis- pensable. It should be noted, however, that what is saved is not capital but productive power. The primitive labourer works overtime, produces a surplus subsistence, and spends it in making tools : his saving is saving of strength to make tools. The modern worker produces a surplus over his subsistence : gives that over to banks and other agencies to be spent in building factories, erecting machinery, etc.: what is saved is the natural forces thus put in position to turn out consumption goods. But when we know the origin of capital, we have stiU to ask : What is the nature , and character of the production carried on by means of capital I The answer may be put in the follovong way. The aim of production is essentially the making or procuring of a living. The animal finds a certain provision spontaneously offered it in nature ; goes straight toward that provision ; and never gets beyond it. Man, on the other hand, even in the simplest state, takes an indirect course. He allies natural with his own (still natural) forces; and he gets behind these natural forces, setting them against each other, or co-operating with each other in carry- ing out his instructions. He steals fire from heaven, and turns I it against the gods. The end is always the consumption good — ! the good which exhausts itself in ministering to man’s life in ' its higher and lower forms; the factors are always labour and nature ; but the way in which the end is reached is here indirect, lengthy, and roundabout. From the rude spade, which the savage first uses as a medium between his bare hai^jls and the fruits or roots he lives on, down to the many years’ production process stretching between the sinking of the shaft for coal or iron and the flying shuttles turning out the cloth which finds its goal in covering bare backs, is simply an evolution of the roundabout method. The course of economic progress puts increasing inter- vals between preparatory and finishing labour, decreasing the stock by increasing the tools ; and at every new stage labour embodies itself in further intermediate products or capital. The character- istic result is twofold. As we should expect from the accumula- tion and concentration of natural forces, this capitalist method is immensely productive as compared with direct or unassisted labour. TRANSLATOR’S PREFACE IX On the other side, however, is to be put the sac:^cis_of Tinae necessarily involved in the indirect process. The relation of these two sides must be carefully noted. As time plays a greater part in production — as the average period is extended — the absolute productiveness of the capitalist process increases, but the relative productiveness decreases. That is to say ; when the process has reached a certain point, it becomes subject to a law of diminishing returns. ^ The fu nction, thei:^,_of capital in production may be said to be; that of allowin g labour-and .natural powers to work out their(, economic effects in p rocesses that take, time, or the utilisation of/ natural forces in roundabout methods. Or, if we adopt the peculiarly modern view that man is the economic Zidpunkt, we may say that capital gives time to labour to avail itself of those powers of nature which become available only at a considerable sacrifice of time. So mu ch for the function of capital, and one is apt to jump to the conclusion that, having shown how capitalist industry produces a great quantity of products as compared with unassisted labour, the sole and sufficient origin of interest has been indicated. A little consideration will show that we are yet on the threshold of that inquiry. The concrete result — the raison d’etre — of a factory is the mass of products it sends to market. These are the transformed shapes of raw and auxiliary materials, machinery generally, and labour ; and the price realised for them repays the outlay on materials, keeps up the machinery, and pays the wages — including all the wages of intellect. But beyond the repaying of all these costs it is a familiar fact that, in normal production, the prices realised leave a surplus. This surplus is not accounted for by pro- fits, although often confused with them. Profit is either employer’s wage (and is thus already included), or it is the chance of a happy conjuncture that allows a higher price to be obtained than is normal — which chance is continually being levelled down by com- petition. But this surplus is recognised as something due to the owner of capital without claim of personal work from him, and it is a surplus of value which competition cannot wipe out. In Bohm-Bawerk’s former book. Capital and Interest, it was exhaustively proved that no theory had yet shown what capital does, or forbears from doing, that it should get this surplus under the name of interest. It is not a payment for the labour embodied in concrete capital, for that labour is presumably fully paid for — say, by the machine maker to his men and to himself — and does not warrant a further continuous payment. It is not a payment for the working of natural forces embodied in the machine, for the value of the machine consists in nothing else than in the working of these forces, and in the price is already paid all the forces that the machine will put forth and h X TRANSLA TOR’S PREFA CE mediate. And it is not wear and tear, nor is it insurance against risk, for in all normal undertakings these are provided for by separate replacement and insurance funds. For proof of these statements I must refer the reader to that book, or the brief summary of it in the preface. What must be emphasised here is that the explanation of capital as the Instrument of Production y is exhausted when it is shown that it allows nature and labour to \ work out their effects in lengthy processes. The source of interest ^ will Q ot be found simply within the sphere of production, for the reason that interest is a problem of surplus value, and value takes us into the sphere of distribution. Thus we come to the next division of the present work. Capital as it appears in the sphere of Distribution, or Capital as the source of the income called Interest. If we begin, as usual, by asking what business people under- stand by interest, we shall be told practically that a sum of money paid down now — say £100 — will buy a greater sum — say £103 or £105 — this day twelve months. Or if I owe £100 now for goods received, and do not pay the debt for a year, I have to add a certain amount under the title of interest. The most obvious fact here is that the payment of interest has some very definite connection with the time when payment is made. This suggests the general question : What is the place and influence of time on the value of goods. And the answer is : It f^is an empirical fact of undoubted universality that pres ent goods / are valued more highly than future goods _of like kind and amount. For this three causes may be given. . First, is the difference between the circumstances of want and the provision for want in present and in future. In any case, if want is pressing and pro- vision is scarce, value is high. But the pressure of want in the present is always with us, while as regards provision in the future it is generally true mine ignotwn gno mirijico. Thus present goods obtain a permanent importance from^ielt^jre^en^wants, and future goods a permanent unimportance from anticipated future provision. Most men, accordingly, — people in immediate distress and beginners of all sorts being types — are willino-_j;o__pledge their future for a really inadequate present sum. (^cond, is the general under- estimate of the future, common to humanity, and traceable to want of imagination, defect of will, or feeling of life’s uncertainty. Children and savages are typical of the improvidence which is more or less striking in all classes. It may be that this cause is not on the same level with the first, and tends to less importance with social progress. But, in the world as it is, it is certain that the things of the ^iire are of less value to us simply because they are future. A^f^ird, is the technical superiority of present goods. As we have already seen, in the hands of labour wealth increases enormously with the extension in time of the production process. TRAJVSLATOJ^’S PREFACE Goods available now have accordingly the promise and potency of being greatly multiplied in the future, while goods coming into our disposal only in the future must undergo another period of pro- duction before the same abundance is reaped. Of these three causes the firs t two^ arei cumulative, the alternative. TheiJ first group alone would account for a difference in value betweenf jmesent and future goods : the appearance of the latter makes the* difiference not only apparent but measurable. If, then, from so many sides and classes — from the young who expect to be better off, from the rich and improvident who wish to enjoy the present, from the industrious who wish to add to their wealth ; that is to say, from probably the majority of mankind — there come s an underestimate of the future compared with the present, it is easily explained why, as a rule, present goods have a grea ter value than future goods of like kind atid amount. I In this empirical and psychological fact, for the full treatment j of which the reader is referred to Book V., our author finds the I source of interest in its three principal forms. q. The simplest case of interest is that in which it appears in the loan for consumpt ion. Here we have a real and true exchange of a smaller amount of present money, or present goods, for a larger amount of future money or goods. The sum returned, “ principal ” plus interest, is the market valuation and equivalent of the “ prin- cii)al ” lent. The apparent difference in value is simply due to our forgetting that £100 in our hands now is not the same thing as £100 a year hence. This Agio on present goods is interest. In other words, interest is a complementary part of the price ; part equivalent of the “principal” lent. In this simple case interest is more evidently the result of the first two causes just mentioned. Apart altogether from an organ- ised system of production this agio would emerge, and has emerged, as something claimed by the saving from the unthrifty. But so long as there was no organic production, the circumstances of borrowers and lenders wei’e too diverse and arbitrary to allow of a measured rate of interest. But when the third factor comes into play, time becomes a condition of surplus product, and interest becomes measurable in terms of time. ^ The second and principal form assumed, then, by interest is that in. whicFltappears as part of the so-called “profit of undertaking.” A capitalist employer hires land, buys raw and auxiliary materials, machinery, power, and labour. He sets these to co-operate in the making of a product. The product is the new shape taken on by all these productive goods, and we should naturally expect that the price obtained for it would exactly cover and reimburse the value of all the goods consumed in making it. But, as we know, after all ordinary costs arc accounted for, the price obtained in normal economic circum- / TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE xii stances shows a surplus of value. The explanation oi the surplus is that productive goods, while materially and physically present, are, to economical consideration, future goods : that is to say, they are products in the making. The wants to which they minister, and from which alone they get their value, are future wants. On the admitted ground of equivalence between costs and products, then, the value of the means of production must be the same as the value of the goods into which they pass. But these goods being in the meantime future goods, and suffering from the discount which, as we have seen, is made on all future goods, the value of means of production must suffer the same discount. The undertaker inten- tionally turns his wealth into productive goods : that is to say, he exchanges his money for raw materials, workshops, machinery, '^labour. In the production process these ripen into present goods, with the full value of present goods. The price he receives for these recoups all his expenditure plus interest. Interest thus V' proves itself, as before, the difference between the formerly future and now present goods. There is a third case of interest which has some features so puzz- ling as to demand separate consideration : this is the case of income obtained from Durable Goods, usually called Hire or Lease, and, in one case. Rent. The distinction, between a perishable and a durable good is that, while both are the sums of their respective uses or services, the durable good is a sum extending over a period of time. But on our theory the later services of such a good must have a less value than the proximate services, and the total value of the good will be a sum of diminishing amounts. The “ capital value ” of such a good, then, will be to all appearance much less than the sum of the values really obtained during its lifetime. Here, as in the former cases, the services originally undervalued ripen to full present value in the hands of the owner, and the difference between the past and the present values, after providing for replacement of the good, is Interest. Thus if the owner of capital throws his parent wealth into the form of stone and lime, he possesses, in the durable shape of a house, a sum of future uses discounted according to their futurity. As each year passes one annual service is realised, and its value is thrown off, while each service still to be realised is one year nearer the present, and is thus one year more valuable. The house, as now containing one rent less, is less valuable, and this loss falls to , be deducted from the gross return as wear and tear. But what is J lost, be it noted, is not one annual service estimated at present value ; it is the last future service of which the good is still capable, — for if all the s rvices have moved up one step in value it is the value of the last service that drops off. The difference between the present service realised (gross rent) and the last service now deducted (economic wear and tear) is the net return of interest. Thus, TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE xiii again, we find that interest is the difference between the formerly future and now present goods. This somewhat difficult point is made clear from the concrete figures on pj). 342-345. It will be seen that in this we have a theory, not only of durable consumption goods such as houses, and of durable productive goods such as machinery, factories, and fixed capital generally, but a theory which carries us beyond our formal definition of Capital into the k sphere of L and . In land we have a durable good whose services will i\ be rendered to generations unborn : the “ last ” service is, therefore, to the calculations of the present, nil : there is no economic wear and tear— no need of any fund for replacement — and the gross return suffers no deduction but is all interest. To put it concretely. A man buys land as he buys fixed capital ; — to get an interest from it. He buys its annual services or rents for a sum which represents the future services diminished in perspective. In other words the ‘‘ capitalised value ” is not an infinite number of years’ rents but so many years’ purchase. In his hands the future uses ripen into present : ^e gets the present value of what he bought as future value j as there is no wear and tear, nothing of this need be set aside for replacement : the whole gross rent is net interest. Ricardo, in pointing to the “ original and indestructible powers of the soil ” /as the cause of rent, was right so far as his explanation indicated / why the gross return was also the net, but wrong so far as it indicated / that rent was due to the productiveness of this peculiar kind of / durable good. The interest on a mine and the rent from land are j essentially the same, although the one should wear out in thirty ' years while the other is “ indestructible.” These are the simple outlines of the Positive Theory. By it all three kinds of interest are traced to the one identical source, the increasing value of what are, either naturally or economicallj^/^ future goods, as they ripen into present goods. But when dealing with the principal fonn of interest, that in which it appears as part of the profit of undertaking, Dr. Bohm-Bawerk makes along excursus into the relation of wealth to labour, which is not the least suggestive and valuable part of the work. As it suffers somewhat, however, from its position in the text, I shall take the liberty of putting it in my own way. There are three markets in which the particular kind of “ future goods” known as means of production are exchanged against finished present goods — practically against money ; these are the Labour market, the Land market, and the market for Concrete Capital. Taking the Labour market as the most typical and the most difficult, its prominent features are these. On the one side are the Capitalist Undertakers. These are men presumably possessed of a surplus of wealth which they cannot advantageously use in their own consumption ; to them personally, therefore, the XIV TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE present goods which constitute their surplus have per se no advantage over future goods. But in this surplus they have the means of waiting over lengthy processes of production As their wealth increases the average period of production is ex- tended, and with every extension the absolute productiveness of the process increases. On the other side is the majority of the population, the Wage-Earners. Their circumstances, as a class, are such that they cannot engage in any independent production that takes time. Even if they could, their production period would necessarily be short, and in competition with the long process the handicap would be too heavy. It may be assumed, therefore, that they will rather take service as “ hands ” than risk independent production. Evidently the big battalions are on the side of the capitalist, and in regard to this particular kind of present good. Labour, it seems to need no further demonstration that the price of it, namely Wage, Avill always be less than tliat of product, and thus allow the employer an interest. This is, in general terms and in a more dis- passionate way, the Socialist answer. But, while admitting, as we very well may, that there is enough and to spare of exploitation in profit generally, the question is by no means so simple as Socialist theory would have it. If there is force on the one side there are certain forces which work steadily on the other. The Trade Unions give the labourers a certain power of waiting, and tend to force employers, as a class, to give up at least that portion of profit which is pure exploitation. Yet wage would not be explained if it were shown to be, in many cases, the exploitation of profit ! The inter- competition of capitalists, again, has surely been effective enough of late decades to force the remuneration of capital towards an economic — as distinguished from an exploitation — level. If there is no economic level of interest, why has it not been wiped out of existence altogether ? The argument is one that Socialism itself often uses ; that, in some respects, the dependence of capital is as absolute as that of labour. It is necessary even for the siaius quo of wealth that the capitalist should bury his surplus in the fertile womb of earth, or in the living powers of man. But in the present state of economic development there is no question of mere preservation of wealth — Jiere can scarcely be, so long as the seed sown returns some thirty, some fifty, some a hundred fold. The motive of the capitalist undertaker is certainly not preservation but increase. He changes his wealth into means of production in order that the value of the products should be more than the value of the costs. He is warranted by experience in assuming that, at the worst, the price realised will contain a certain minimum rate of inte rest ; will, most probably, contain also a good wage for himself as master workman ; and that. TRANSLATOR’S PREFACE XV possibly, a happy conjuncture may give him a “ profit ” besides. (Of course I am speaking of the enlightened employer who knows that “ wage,” tech^cally, is remuneration for work done, and does not claim as wage more than, say, the remuneration of a Prime Minister.) Where the employer and the capitalist are separate entities — as they always are to economic consideration — the motives also are distinct : the motive of the employer is wage and “ profit ” — using that ambiguous word in the loose meaning of gain beyond wage of superintendence and pure interest — while that of the capitalist is interest — with perhaps a chance of “profit.” Now, as thus separated, the competition of capitals with each other becomes more intense; for capital becomes a suppliant, not only to the labourer who demands the minimum wage, but to the class of employers who expect a perhaps extravagant “ wage of superintend- ence,” and a “profit” besides. In this state of sharpened competi- tion the insufficiency of the exploitation theory becomes manifest to experience. We are forced to see that there is a le vel of interest which no a mount of competition normally levels away, and we conclude that this is the economic level. Where the inter-competi- tion of capitals is the fiercest, the owner of wealth has not to content himself with the mere preservation and re-creation of his wealth — much less pay a premium to labour for keeping it — but gets his minimum 2f% or 3% of interest. This explanation will be found if we turn from the question as between labourers and employers^ and consider the larger question as between owners of present goods on the one side, and labourers and employers alike on the other. And here we come to Bbhm- Bawerk’s enunciation of a proposition which seems to me one of the most important in modern economics. It is that t he s upply of _preseut .goods, available in any community either as means of production to labourers or as subsistence to mere borrowers for consumption, i s the sum of that comm unity’s existing wealth exclusive of lan d. No one nowadays hoards wealth, drawing on it as needed. Thanks to banking systems and facilities for invest- ment, nearly all wealth that is not actually being consumed by the owners is made available to supply this double demand. Disre- garding as before the demand for consumption, the effect of which is merely to lessen the amount of wealth available for productive borrowers — and remembering in passing that the agio on present goods is the joint result of these two collateral demands, we find this wealth confronting the demand of labour, transmitted through the employer^ for the means of subsistence during the production period. Now, thanks to well-known motives, wealth in normal circumstances increases faster than population. As it accumulates it becomes possible for the labourers to extejid^ their processes. Seed-time and harvest become separated, not by months but by XVI TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE years, aud the amount of wealth in a community, as enabling labour to bridge over the long time of growth, becomes visibly^ the con- dition of its average production period, and so o f its average pro- ductiveness. Thus to him that hath much muclT is given : the fich nation is the heir of the economic promises. From this it is not diflScult to see that the value of m eans of production must alwa ys lag behind that .of finished products. There is always a demand for ampler means of living, and the condition of obtaining ampler means is — time to extend the production pro- cess. So long, then, as the wants of spiritual beings call for fuller and finer satisfactions, and so long as the working life rises to higher levels, so long .wilLdhere hn a premium put on the present wealth which ma kes more ample wealth possible. Thus we are justified in saying that t ^e demand for means of production will a lwa ys be greater than the supply, and interest, a s th e agio on such, will appear, in the price of products. The superficial resemblance of this ^i ^sistence F und to the generally discredited Wage Fund of the classical economists will not mislead any one who enters into the heart of Bohm-Bawerk’s theory. The difference between the two will be found in the few pregnant sentences on pp. 419, 420. In case of misunderstand- ing, however, two cautions may be given here. One is that by “ means of . subsistence ” must be understood, not simply food, nor even the common necessaries and comforts of life, but alljtha.h goes to t he main tenance of th e worker s, whatever their various levels of comfort It is not a certain wage fund, provided arbitrarily by capitalist employers, that is available for the simple “ subsistence ” of the working classes : it is the entire wealth of the community that is available for the maintenance of all classes of workers. The caution is much needed quite outside of this connection. I am persuaded that many people think they have determined the “ cost ” and due reward of labour when they have found how many weekly wages of 20s. are contained in the community’s stock of wealth. The mischief that this idea does, in making people think that a rise of wages is a social calamity, is, to my mind, very great. To economic consideration, however, the line is a vanishing one which divides Hodge’s beer and bacon from Plugson’s venison and champagne. Rightly considered, the prices of books, the stipends of clergymen and teachers, the seats at theatres and concerts are “expenses of subsistence,” just as much as the labourers’ bread and cheese — unless we are to limit the category of “workers” to the 20s. a week class. The oth^r caution is that this wealth available for subsistence does not consist exclusively of goods already in the finished state. To put all wealth into this form, indeed, would be the greatest possible waste. What is required is, that the various means of TRANSLATOR’S PREFACE xvu subsistence should be ready when wanted, and this involves that, at any given time, the wealth of a country consists of products at all stages of maturity. To put it concretely : — At this moment the wdieat'is'beln^own that will feed human beings after next harvest, while the sapling is being planted that will not come to its full growth for a century to come : at the same moment, perhaps, the oak is being felled that began its growth a hundred years ago, and to-morrow the wood of it will enter into the framework of a thresh- ing-machine which will extend its life-work over a score of harvests : sapling and tree, machine and wheat, are alike parts of that wealth Avhich is available for the labourers’ demand in its continuity. Eemembering these cautions we can see the full import of, this conception . It defines the true relation of wealth to labour in the following terms : The func tion of existing wealth is to subsist t he \ yorkers during the interval between the beginning and the end of the soc ial production period. This strikes us as strange mainly because oE fhe'bourgedis idea that wealth is the end and goal of labour, and the more vicious idea that labour is a tax on life. For certain purposes of economic study we may think of labour as the means, and consumption wealth as the end of pro- duction, but the economist falls into error whenever he forgets that economic life is an endless circle, where wealth, as subsistence, passes into muscle and brain, and muscle and brain pass into wealth again. Even when we rise — as the economist may do — to wider conceptions, and point to man's full free life as the goal of economic effort, we ought to recognise that the working life which, we lead, and sho uld lead, is at once an, end, and a. mean. In working we live, and in working we produce wealth : this wealth, again, permits of freer work and fuller life. In correspondence with this, the type of labourer is not the man who produces on one day to consume on the next, but the man who consumes during his work day — who consumes while he produces — and, moreover, whose consumption increases with his production. The function of Avealth, then, we say, is to support this Avorking life, with its increasing claims, during its Avork. Thus instead of making Avealth the final cause of industry — as the economist in virtue of his professional bias is apt to do — or making it the beginning and limit of industry — as the Wage Fund theory tended to do — t his c onception places Avealth in the centre as the maintenance of the working world during its rise_to higher and higher levels of j vorking life. In other words, it puts the economic conception into line Avith the moral by making Avealth simply the mean to the Avorking life. If, then, interest is so purely a natural phenomenon, Avhy has it met with so much covert dislike, and so much scientific opposition? There are at least three reasons. First, the element on Avhich all interest is based, namely ti me, has come to be a peculiarly important Kviii TRANSLA TOR'S PREFA CE fa^lQr in modern production. All things come to him who waits, and, in economic life, this describes the capitalist. But this fact involves that the labouring classes who cannot wait, and cannot compete ^vith the productiveness of lengthy processes, are put in a position of peculiar dependence : hence the possibility of exploitation of wage, of usurious rates of interest, of unjust rents. Second, from a moral point of view, there is much that is objectionable in the fact that interest allows certain classes to live without working and to make^Eis possibility hereditary in their families. JThird, in this in- come there is no ratio between gain and desert. Those who have little must accept Savings Bank interest for their hard-earned shillings ; those who have much have all the chances of bonds, mortgages, joint-stock investments and the like. All the same, so long as men do put a different valuation on present and future .goods, interest cannot be prevented. Even a Socialist state could not prevent it : if b^'^rc^ible means it were stopped between individuals, it would still obtain between commune and labourer. The state in this case would replace the capitalist, and “ exploit ” the worker in the same way — although, it may be hoped, with a clearer view to the wellbeing of the exploited — but no organisation could make interest into wage. In Book VII. Dr. Bohm-Bawerk passes to the most difficult part of the subject, the Bate of Interest. Here, however, we shall find him using terms which are* scarcely intelligible without some knowledge of the theory of value enunciated by Jevons and Menger, and now held practically as the fundamental doctrine of the Austrian school. The formulation of this theory, so far as was necessary to the theory of capital, occupies Books III. and IV. of the present work. It is not possible, unfortunately, in the short space at my disposal, to give anything like an easy account of this theory. I have already found difficulty enough in putting it into the compass of my own Introduction to the Theory of Value, and all I can hope to do here is, perhaps, to assist the reader who finds any difficulty in the text. The essential points are as follows. Value is altogether based on utility, and the amount of value is determined, not by average, but by final or marginal utility. The subjective value of a good, as distinguished from its utility, lies in its being the indispensable condition of some satisfaction of want : the ammnt of value it obtains is determined by the last use to which it, or a similar good of the stock, is put in the then circumstances of want and provi- sion for want. Thus the utility of a bushel of corn is given it by its power of supporting life : its value comes from the fact that it is so limited that some human want depends on it for satis- faction : the amount of its value is determined by the least use to which the bushel is economically put in the circumstances of the consumers on the one hand and the amount of the harvest on TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE XIX the other. Thus value has no absolute level ; it is neither intrinsic nor relative to any personal or material average : it is always found in the relation of these two determinants of Want and Provision. P rice, or Ex change Yalue, again, is a superstructure on this subjective value, determined by Jhe competition of buyers and sellers with each othermid among themselves. Under a simple barter system each party in a market would put a subjective value on the goods changing hands, as having a direct bearing on his ovti wellbeing, and would base the amounts offered and asked on this valiiation. With organised industry comes the money valuation, where the comparative use value of goods to people generally becomes reflected on a money scale, and it becomes more definite and intelligible to say a thing is worth so many shillings than to say it is worth so many other things which admit of direct valua- tion in terms of satisfaction of want. Buyers and sellers, then, come together in markets with a definite valuation in their minds of what the goods or the money is Avorth to them. Thanks to the differences in subjective scales, it is the interest of both parties, and it is possible for both parties, to get an advantage by t he excha nge, although their interests diverge in regard to the amount of advantage that each may get. In this competition the goods pass from the “most capable” sellers to the “most capable” buyers, and the price is fixed between the valuations of the two “marginal pairs,” viz. the last buyer and seller and the first un- successful buyer and^ s elle r. The level, again, of these marginal pairs is determined by the relation of the wants of both parties to their economical provision. It must be added that, in an organised economy, “utility” becomes a more complex conception. In the case of a manufacturer the utility of raw material is not the personal uses to which he can put his own products, but the uses to Avhich he, as a manufacturer, can put the raw material, and these, again, are determined by the wants of his customers. The direct use of a good is here replaced by the employment of the good, and the “ most useful ” is translated into the “ best paying,” or “ most remunerative.” And this emergence of the professional producer, who makes for the market and to whom his produce has really no subjective value, simplifies the calculation of the marginal pairs by eliminating the subjective valuations of the sellers, and determines the price at the valuation of the last buyer. This law_ jioes not, as one would suppose, come into collision with the old law that value is determined by costs of production. The Law of Costs is one amply confirmed by experience as regards the great mass of articles produced under free competition. But this empirical law was never thought to determine the value of goods produced under any other conditions. The point on which it requires amending is that it should be expressed as a law XX TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE of equality between costs and products. The old theory not only said that the value of goods tended to an equality with that of the means of production, but went on to put the causal relation exactly the wrong way about. As we have said, it is human want gives value to goods ; and that value is thrown back upon the means of production without which the goods cannot come into existence, and which are really the goods in a previous state of existence. In developed economy it is true that there comes a reflex influence from costs to products. If a group of means of production is capable of making goods which for the moment have different marginal utilities, the value that is transferred to the costs is the value of the last or marginal product made from these costs. In time, no doubt, competition forces this value again on to the other products, thus giving the impression that the value comes from the costs : but the fact is that the very value which these costs have, came from their product — not, however, from this or that particular product, but from the marginal one. Now the immediate point of connection between the theory of value qnd the theory of interest is that the problem of interest, in all its manifestations, is nothing more than a problem of price, the commodity bought and sold being — Present Goods. When, then, we go on to the final question, the Amount or Rate of Interest, what we have to remember is that here, as in price transactions generally, we have a resultant of subjective valuations, and that the determining elements we have to deal with are the extent and intensity of the subjective valuations of buyers and sellers. We have already seen what is the extent of this supply, and we know the motives which weigh with the owners and determine its intensity. The demand, again, comes from those who borrow to consume, and those who borrow to produce. Of these two co-ordinate demands we shall, as before, confine ourselves to the more important and more difficult, and to its most important section, the Wage-Earners, refer- ring the reader to Bohm-Bawerk’s last two chapters for the other sections. One way of looking at this demand would be to consider it, not as a direct demand from the wage-earners, but as interpreted and in certain definite ways modified by the undertakers. But it is perhaps better to consider the undertaker as the owner of capital, and take the question simply as one between Wage -Earners and Capitalists. In the following argument, then, we assume that the demand comes exclusively from labour, that the entire supply and demand meet in one single market embracing the whole community, and that all branches of production show the same scale of surplus returns. If wage were a fixed point — say determined at the subsistence level, as the Iron Law assumes — the calculation of the rate of in- terest would be comparatively easy. Say that every added ^100 TRAN SLA TOR'S FREE A CE XXI of capital permitted simply a further extension of process. Every extension of pro cess assures an extra product. But where capitalist industry is well developed, the increments of product at each exten- sion diminish relatively to those preceding, and there comes a point where the increase of product does not balance the expense of extension. To put it in familiar terms : an employer making 10% on his own capital, and offered loans at 4%, may profitably extend his business by borrowing although at every extension he makes a smaller profit. But when the extensio n made possible by the last loan r eturns him only 4 %^ there is no inducement to extend further. In this case the rate of interest would be determined by the “ last dose of capital ” economically applied, to use Thiinen’s phrase. But the great difficulty is that wage is not a fixe d amou nt. The value of labour to the employer depends upon anticipated pro- duct, and that product depends on productiveness, and productive- ness depends on length of process, and thus we have no fixed point from which to start. Bohm-Bawerk’s solution is the following. The fixed point which we cannot get in wage is got in another way. As _in the the ory of money it is well known_ that any quantity of currency, sma ll or gre^ will efifect the necessary exchanges, so here the av ailable quantity of present goods offered for sale will buy up t he whole of the a v ailab le labour. This is due to the circumstances alriady spoken of — the need of the labourers to hire themselves out, and of the capitalists to hire out their wealth. The few cases of unemployed labour and capital may be left out of account, as, obviously, it is only because of bad organisation that there are such. When the proportion of wealth and of labourers changes, all that is required is to contract or extend the production period. Granted this assumption, then, — that at any moment labour buys up the available “ wage fund,” — the rate of interest is determined on the ordinary lines of the formation of price. The period will be extended till such time as the marginal employment of the unit of capital is reached ; that is, till the extra product gained by extension of process i s outweighe d bv tFe .diiuinishing productiveness of the process. To put this difficult argument in a way perhaps more easy to grasp. Say that at any given moment there is a certain amount of wealth divided out among the wage-earners as subsistence. In any case there will be some agio on this wealth, and there will be an average production period. If now wealth increases faster than population — in Great Britain it increases more than twice as fast — there must be some disturbance of the equilibrium at present estab- lished. The new wealth will seek for employment, and find it — not, of course, in offering higher wages, for there is still nothing in increased wealth to increase product — but in extending processes. But as, presumably, we have now entered the stage of progress where extension of period gives decreasing surpluses, the return to a XXll TRANSLATOR’S PREFACE this last employment of wealth will be less than before. This marginal employment will bring down interest generally: the rate will be determined by the last extension of the production period : wage will rise relatively to interest : and the equilibrium be found at a new level. If population increase, wealth and productiveness remaining constant, the converse will be the case : wag e will fall and interest rise because the community is brought back to a pro- duction period where the absolute product is less, but the relative surplus, due to extension of process, is greater. If, lastly, product- iveness increase, wealth and population remaining constant, the same phenomenon will take place, owing to the decreasing progres- sion of surplus returns being for the moment checked, y Thus we can see that the three concrete factors which determine / t^ marginal. extension of process, and thereby the rate of interest, are the amount of the national Subsistence Fund, the numbers of the working Population provided for, and the degree of Productive- ness reached in the industrial development. To quote our author’s words, “ interest will be high in proportion as the national subsist- ence fund is low, as the number of labourers employed by the same is great, and as the surplus returns connected with any further extension of the production period continue high, and vice versA.” All this is in perfect harmony with the known facts of interest. It explains how as a country grows wealthy the rate of interest falls while wages rise ; how an increase of population without a corre- sponding increase of wealth has a tendency to raise the rate of interest and depress wages •, and, finally, how inventions which increase productiveness tend to raise the rate. It is not within the scope of my task here to follow Bohm- Bawerk in gradually adding on the other elements required to make the picture true to the actualities of life, and to show that they make no material change in the principles laid down. Enough has been said to give the outlines of a theory which challenges attention, both by the originality of its ideas, and the thoroughness of its treatment. My thanks are due, first of all, to Dr. Bohm Bawerk, who has materially added to the value of this rendering of his work by giving it the stamp of his revision ; to Professor Edward Caird, of Glasgow, and Professor M'Cormick, of Dundee, for many valuable suggestions and corrections : to Miss Christian Brown, of Paisley, who has again put me under heavy obligation by most carefully revising my proof-sheets : and to two other of my students who have spared me many weeks of thankless work by deciphering and rewriting my crabbed MS. Glasgow, June 1891 . AUTHOE’S PREFACE It has taken me longer than I expected to foUow up the publication of my Geschichte und Kritik der Kapitalzins-Theorieen by the present work. The heavy part of The Positive Theory \ of Capital hes in the theory of Interest . In the other portions ! of the subject I was able, at least on the whole, to follow in the footsteps of previous theorists, but for the phenomena of interest I had to put forward an explanation which breaks entirely new ground. I make this latter statement with some confidence. It is ' quite true that mv explanation of interest rests on certain i mportant idens previously put forward by Jevons. But Jevons did not give them that special application which might have made them serviceable towards the explanation of interest — if they had been taken in connection with certain other lines of thought not then familiar to Jevons. Thus it is that, in his interest theory, Jevons remained under the spell of the old classical opinions-, notwithstanding these new lights which came to him from another quarter and were applied to other ends. And, moreover, as the ideas common to both of us were not borrowed by me from Jevo ns. but discovered in entire independence — indeed long before I became acquainted with Jevons’s writings — I feel bound to take on myself, for good or ill as events may prove, the entire and imdivided responsibility for the interest theory now put forward. As regards the way in which I have treated the subject, I may be allowed to make two remarks. T he method of statement adopted for the most part throug hout this book is that wh ich ^^pnople— generally — not without a suspicion of passing judgment on it — -caU. “ abstrac t.” XXIV AUTHOR’S PREFACE All the same I contend that my theory does not contain one single feature which is not based on true empirical principle s. There are various wavs of being empirica l. We may obtain the facts of experience which serve us as foundations from economic history , or we maj'’ gather them from s tatistics^ or we may try to get them directly in our common daily life by simple informal o bservation . No one of these three methods has any monopoly : each of them has its separate and peculiar sphere. In the nature of things the historical and the statis- tical method treat the matter of experience in much ampler fashion, and gather it from wider fields of observation ; but for that very reason they fail, oir the whole, to seize any but tbn, larger and more apparent fa cts : they put economic events, as it were, through a large sieve, where a great many dehcate and unobtrusive, but, perhaps, more essential features of economic life, escape unnoticed. If, then, we would rescue these and make them objects of economic investigation — and for very many scientific problems we simply cannot do without taking cognisance of tmem — there is nothing for it but to have recourse to the ci^rrriparatively narrow but alwa^ impressive personal observation of life. Now I have endeavoui'ed to make full use of all three methods of investigation . What help economic history and statistics could’affbrd me in my task I have thankfully accepted and conscientiously made the most of, even where I have not explicitly mentioned the original materials with which I worked. But the matter thus obtained was not by a long way sufficient for my purposes. The theory of capital has to reckon with a number of facts which history and statistics have not recorded, partly because in their nature they could not, partly because attention has not hitherto been drawn to the importance of these facts. T\"hat, for instance, could history and statistics say about the question which is so important in the explanation of interest, as., to whether there is in perishable. ’ ■ " T . 1 r-ing nsp. ? How much, again, could actual grounds on which are based the different subjective estimates of present and future goods ? Or what have we learned — up till the present at least — as to the relation between the amount of the national subsistence . fund arirj tVip av prage production period in a commm iitY ? In AUTHOR'S PREFACE XXV matters like these one is obliged, for good or ill, to turn to other sources of information, and other paths of knowledge than those of history and statistics. And if proof be needed that I was ri^ht in doing so, and that indeed it was impossible for me to do otherwise, I may appeal to witnesses whose authority, as regards this question, is beyond dispute, nameiy, the leaders and adherents of the “ historical school ” itself. For full thirty years the historical and statistical tendency has been the prevailing one in German economics. During the whole of this long period there has not been even an attempt to solve the great problem of interest by the tools of the historical method, although this problem has always occupied a front place in economical discussion. Perhaps the nearest attempt to a really historical treatment was that of Eodbertus, with his famous statement of the different forms imder which, in various ages, the ruling econ - oTnie elaggeg have always drawn the better pa.rt of the product of the nation’s labour to themselves, But, accurately speaking, Eodbertus, in these historic flights, aimed only at winning assent to his exploitation theory, while the characteristic feature of that theory is that it makes use from end to end of the abstract- deductive machinery of the classical school, the labour theory of Eicardo. Or to mention only the recognised leaders of the - historical school \ — Eoscher has put together his interest theory out of elements taken partly from J. B. Say, partly from Senior — -that is to say, altogether from “ pre-historic ” theory ; while Knies, following Hermann, invents a theory of the “ use ” of goods, which not only has nothing in the world in common with history and statistics, but, as I at least believe, dispenses with any inductive foundation whatever, and is the result of simple speculation — and not even happy speculation. If, then, the historical economists themselveS j when brought face to face with the problem of capital, have not trusted to their peculiar method, and have taken to a kind of investigation generally foreign to them, J cannot he reproached if I take the same course as they do. I am free — at least I try to be free — from any onesidedness of method. In my opinion there is no one royal road of investigation : to my mind that way is good which leads to the goal of knowledge in the individual case. And sometimes that will be the one, sometimes the c XXVI AUTHOR'S PREFACE other method, according to the different nature of the individual problems that present themselves. In the present case I imagine that I have employed the method of research which was most suitable to the special nature of the theoretical problems ~'~~X)f~-ca pital — abstract in form, but empirical in essence : and indeed, as seems to me, empirical in a truer sense than can be assigned to the investigations which the historical school has directed towards the same end. The second remark I should like to make is this. The fundamental ideas of my interest theory-are. I believe, unusually simple and natural Had I been content to arrange these ideas in a more concise form, avoiding all casuistical matters of detail, I should have put forward a theory which, in small compass, would have produced the impression of being exceedingly simple, even verging on being self-evident. So far as power of carrying conviction goes, this would certainly have been an advantage, and, if I have forborne to seize that advantage, it was only after full consideration. The fac; have been so man found fake, that I must expect to find the public very critically disposed, and indeed must presume that my best and most careful readers will be the most critical. In these circum- stances it appeared to me morp. importaTit t n make the structure of my theory secure than to make it easy and pleasant reading. Thus I decided to encumber my work with numerous demon- strations, details, exact figures, and so on, rather than leave room at critical points for doubts and misunderstandings. In this direction one circumstance gave me particular trouble. In a theory of any range and any difficulty f.ViprP arp ppintf which, by reason of some casuistical pecuharities or other, are not always qnihp pasily pxp lainpd. even when the general principle which will give their solution is already known ; and, so long as those points are not distinctly traced back to the general principle, they stand like so many living objections to its correctness. As it happens, t here are a good many such poin ts in th p <'wf> r.bpnri ps so cinselv connected ; — that of valufe-a nd t hat of capital. Now in the theory of value I had experienced how unexplained questions of this sort may stand seriously in the way and hinder the acceptance of the best grounded general theories, — for I am convinced that people have been so long AUTHOR'S PREFACE xxvii prevented from getting right views on the nature and laws of value only because they stnmhled at certain s t riking facts, which, to hasty consideration, seemed to contradict these views, while in truth they were only complicated cases requiring casuistical treatment. To save my theor y q, like fate T tried tmt.i'mpa fp, nhjp.ctions of this sort , and remove them by suitable digressions. Naturally I did not deal with all conceivable objections, but only with those which seemed to me likely to crop up in the minds of critical readers, and which, at the same time, seemed difficult enough to warrant a special explanation : all the same it gave me occasion to go into more detail than was favourable to the fluent statement of mv theory. Thanks to all this I have arrived at a result as paradoxical as it is natural ; that the very trouble wtn Vh T took to clear difficulties out of the wav has given my theory a certain appearance of difficulty. . Unsuspicious of these hidden and dangerous rocks, many of my readers, I doubt not, would have sailed safely over them, wliile I, knowing them so well, and trying to steer a safe but laboured course, have made the journey long, difficult, and troublesome. I trust, however, that somethmg may be put to my credit in this regard ; for, after all, no one could very well expect to arrive at the solution of a problem of such recognised difficulty except through earnest and laborious thinking. I may at any rate take this oppor- tunity of asking one favour of my readers ; — that, if they have once read my theory with all its ca.suistical detail, t hey w ould go over it a second time omitting the deta il. If in this way the leading ideas are put directly together again, and cleared of aU superfluous elaboration, I venture to think that the theory will again produce that impression of simplicity and naturalness which is warranted by the simplicity of its con- stituent ideas ; an impression which I may have sacrificed to a critical precaution that was perhaps exaggerated, but was not altogether without justification. This book was already well through the press when Carl Menger’s Contriimtion to the Theory of Capital appeared in Conrad’s Jahrhiicher (vol. xvii. part ii.) I very much regret that it was then too late for me to make full use of that most interesting and suggestive work, and, in particular, that I could AUTHOR'S PREFACE not (do more justice to its author in my critical notice of the historical development of the conception of capital. Unfortun- \ ^ at^ by the time it appeared the first part of my book, — that ^ j^nich deals with the conception and nature of capital, and touches most closely on this work of Menger, — was already printed off. For the same reason I could not notice the important work of Wieser on Natxiral Value, which only came to my hands during the printing of my last chapter. E. Bohm-Baweek. Innsbruck, November 1888. ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS Introduction. The different sense attached to the word Capital in the spheres of Production and Distribution. Division of the subject into Capital the instrument of production, and Capital the source of interest pp. 1 — 3 BOOK I THE NATURE AND CONCEPTION OE CAPITAL Chapter I. Man and Nature. The unity of all science demands that economics builds on certain fundamental truths pertaining rather to the natural sciences. Connection of Happiness, Wants, Satisfaction, Goods, Use, Production. Man’s contribution to production — the “moving of things ” — as deciding where and when natural forces shall act. Limitations of our mastery over nature : our allies — knowledge, and the division of nature against herself. ....... pp. 7 — 16 Chapter n. The Nature of Capital. The roundabout method of pro- duction. Illustrations. Its great results as regards product are an admitted fact of experience. The explanation ; — that by getting control of one power we can bring it to bear on other powers, and through many members obtain a cumulative result. This enlisting of natural forces is capitalist production, and capital is nothing but the complex of inter- mediate products which emerge at the various stages on the roundabout journey of production ....... pp. 17 — 23 Chapter IIL Historical Development of the Conception. Originally it appeared as an interest-bearing sum of money. Turgot expanded this into money or goods. Adam Smith divided goods into consumption goods, and income - bearing goods or capital, noticing a distinction in the latter which was developed by his followers into the categories of National and Indi- vidual capital. It escaped notice, however, that these were two entirely independent conceptions, and hence the confused idea that capital bore interest because it was productive. Definitions of Hermann, Menger, XXX ANAL YTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS Klciuwacliter, Jevons, Marx, Kiiies, Walras, M'Leod, Kiihnast. Various interpretations of tlie terms “goods ” and “means of production ” in these definitions ......... pp. 24 — 35 Chapter IV. The True Conception of Capital. The principles of a good definition. Capital in general .(Acquisitive or Private capital) is a group of products which serve as means to the acquisition of goods. Under this we put the narrower, hut perhaps more important, conception of Social or Productive capital, the complex of intermediate products, or products destined for further production ...... pp. 36 — 41 Chapter V. The Competing Conceptions of Capital, (i) Those includ- ing Consumption goods as well as acquisitive instruments — the “national subsistence fund,” Koscher’s ““ products saved for further production,” Knies’s “goods applicable to the satisfaction of want in the future.” (2) Those including Labour : the strong objections to this. (3) Those includ- ing Land as well as products of labour — a classification which, indeed, has some advantages. (4) Those making still stricter limitations — Klein- wiichter, Marx, Jevons. (6) Metaphysical conceptions — M'Leod and Kiihnast .......... pp. 42 — 60 Chapter VI. Social and Private Capital. This division is not coin- cident with that made by Rodbertus and Wagner into purely economic capital and legal property in capital. The groups of goods embraced in each of our categories. Should “warehoused consumption goods” and “money” be included in social capital? Should the maintenance of labourei-s ? Emphatically this latter is not capital, but consumption wealth pp. 61 — 72 BOOK II CAPITAL AS INSTRUMENT OF PRODUCTION Chapter I. Introductory. The two questions answered in the present book : How does capital originate, and what is the natui’e of its work in production ? The un.satisfactory answers up till now are principally due to the neglect of describing facts before explaining them . . pp. 75 — 77 Chapter II. Capitalist Production. Recapitulation. The sole technical factoi-s in production are nature and labour, but, as we economise only where we have not superfluity, the limited natural agents — briefly, uses of land — and labour are the sole economic factors. In capitalist production the roundabout way, while securing increased products, is attended by the sacrifice of Time. This is at the root of the dependence of labour on capital. Every lengthening of process involves some increase of product, but not in equal progression. The “production period”: — the average time between the expenditure of uses of land and labour and the turning out of the finished consumption good ..... pp. 78 — 91 ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS XXXI Chapter HL The Function of Capital in Production, (i) It is symptomatic of the adoption of the roundabout method. (2) As storing up natural power it is a tool to further production. (3) It is an indirect cause of new processes, as giving off, in consumption goods, the main- tenance of labourers, and leaving them free to invest their labour and natural agents in lengthy processes. Thus capital is not an independent productive ^wer, but an intermediate product oi' nature ana labour— a^ medium through which they both work.] The claim of independence would never have been made but for the assumed parallelism between factors of production and branches of income . . . pp. 92 — 99 Chapter IV. The Theory of the Formation of Capital Capital, both in its origin and its growth, is the result of production and saving — not necessarily a direct saving of capital, but of consumption goods wMch leave labour and land free to produce capital .... pp. 100 — 105 Chapter V. Formation of Capital in a Community. At any given moment the capital of a community consists of a mass of intermediate products, some at different stages of the same length of roundabout journey, others at the same stage of processes of different lengths. Eepresentation of this by concentric circles, the outer — that nearest consumption — being . the largest, both in kinds of products and amount of capital invested. Detailed proof of the proposition of last chapter, and demonstration that, alike in socialism and in individualism, saving is necessary pp. 106—118 Chapter VI. Possible Objections, (i) That most capital is not fitted for immediate consumption, and that there is thus no abstinence in not con- suming it — which does not affect the fact that, for the formation of capital, productive powers must be withdrawn from the service of the present, although it is a resisonable argument against those who confuse saving with moral desert. (2) That saving must be a saving of surplus, and surplus is due to industriousness — all the same, the product of industry must not be consumed but saved. The true place of saving as directing nature and labour towards the production of capital, not of consumption goods. (3) That non-consumption is a pure negative — which has force only against those who elevate saving into an independent factor of production. This brings us, then, to the further question : Why do people save capital, and we must before going further find a basis for our interest theory in the theory of value ....... pp. 119 — 125 BOOK III VALUE / Chapter L The Two Conceptions of Value. The old division into Use value and Exchange value we shall replace by Subj ective value (imp ortance to hu man wellbeing) a nd Objective Exchange value (purchasing power) pp. 129—132 xxxii ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS Chapter II. Nature and Origin of Subjective Value While all goods by definition have a certain relation to hunian wellbeing, there is a difference between usefulness, the general capacity to subserve wellbeing; and value, the indispensable condition of wellbeing. For the emergence of value there must be scarcity relative to demand, else we should not economise ......... pp. 133 — 137 Chapter III. The Amount of Value. From the foregoing the amount of a good’s value would seem defined by the amount of wellbeing actually dependent on it. But this is confronted by the old paradox that bread has little value and diamonds much. The solution will be found in accurate examination of what really is the amount of wellbeing dependent on any goods, and to get at this we have to put two questions. First ; when we speak of satisfaction of want (economic wellbeing) do we mean kinds of want or concrete feelings of want ? The older theory made the mistake of saying the former, and so considered that which satisfied the most vital needs the most valuable. Whereas the slightest casuistic consideration shows that we measure the importance of a good by its relation to the concrete want as it arises, and not to the totality which constitutes the kind. Representing kinds of wants and concrete wants in a typical scheme, we can see how little the kind tells us of the urgency of the con- crete want ......... pp. 138 — 145 Chapter IV. The Marginal Utility. Second : where a good is capable of satisfying wants of different importance, which is the dependent want the satisfaction of which determines value ? The answer is ■ — the one which would fail of its satisfaction without the good ; that is, the least important among those actually satisfied. Thus vahie is detennined by Marginal Utility. Illustration of the sacks of corn. In industrial life the familiar fact that quantity is in inverse ratio to value is an empirical statement of this law : the more goods there are of a kind the less urgent is the last want satisfied, and twice "oers&. Thus we have the natural explanation why bread has little value and diamonds much pp. 146—153 Chapter V. Complications. We must be careful to determine in each case what is the marginal utility. For instance, (1) in assessing the value of a durable good, or a collective good (like a harvest), we have to sum up the importance of many concrete wants ; (2) the value of most goods is not determined by their own, but by a foreign utility, that of goods substituted for them, either by purchase or production — a principle of wide application in present economic life ....... pp. 154 — 158 Chapter VI. What determines Marginal Utility. It is the relation between wants and their provision. If wants are many and intense and provision is scant, there are many unsatisfied layers of want, and the marginal utility is high, and vice versd. Thus a good has many subjective values, and goods generally have different values to different classes of society .......... pp. 159 — 161 Chapter VII. Alternative Uses. When a commodity admits of different kinds of use, it is the highest marginal utility — the marginal utility of the ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS xxxiii most useful employment — that decides its value : the other (excluded) employments usually halve no influence on practical calculations pp. 162 — 165 Chapter VIII. Subjective Exchange Value. Organised exchange gives almost every good a second value — the indhect importance which it has for human wellbeing through its capacity of being bartered for goods which directly affect human wellbeing'. Where this and subjective use value compete, value is decided by the higher (alternative) employment of the two. Illustration of how subjective and objective exchange value may move in different directions ....... pp. 166 — 169 Chapter IX. The Value of Complementary Goods. Where several goods co-operate towards -one utility the value of the complete group is the , value of the group’s marginal utility, except where all the members ai’e replaceable. If each member is irreplaceable, and has no use outside the gro.up, then one member has the value of the whole group. But where the members are capable of other (though less remunerative) employments, each member has one value as complement and another as isolated. Lastly, where some members are replaceable, these members never have any greater value than that given them in isolation outside, while the irreplaceable member gets the remainder of the gi’oup value. The far-reaching bearing of this on the distribution problem .... pp. 170 — 178 Chapter X. The Value of Productive Goods. Value and Costs. It has generally been held that the value of goods is regulated by the costs of their production. But, adopting Monger’s division of goods into ranks, it becomes evident that productive groups only get their value (if value is importance for human wellbeing) from the last link in the chain, the final consumption good. Thus the value of the productive groups and of the final product must be substantially the same, and costs of production are reflated by the marginal utility of final products, although each group has its immediate measure in its particular intermediate product. Appeal- ing to experience, the well-known law of costs, affirming the identity of costs and products although putting the causal connection the wrong way about, confirms this. The identity, however, is disturbed by two causes— (1) irregular fluctuations, (2) the normal divergence in which interest emerges. Looking now tg the fact that one group of productive goods may pass into products with different marginal utilities, we find that it is the marginal utility of the least remunerative employment that determines value. ■ But once value is thus given to costs, it in turn, where goods are freely produced, transmits itself to the other products. Thus the law of costs, w'hen understood as a particular law of value, is quite correct, and is not in contradiction with the universal law of- marginal utility pp. 179—189 XXXIV ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS BOOK IV PRICE Chapter L The Fundamental Law. The motive of exchange in general is the striving after economical advantage : postulates of this motive. The condition of exchange — that the exchangers put different values upon the commodity and the equivalent price. The most capable exchanger — the one who attaches most value to the good and least to the equivalent pp. 193—197 Chapter II. Isolated Exchange. Here price is determined somewhere between the subjective valuation of the buyer as maximum and that of the seller as minimum ....... pp. 198 — 199 Chapter III. One-sided Competition. Where there are several buyers and one seller, price is detennined between the subjective valuation of the actual and that of the most capable unsuccessful purchaser ; where there are several sellers, between that of the actual and that of the most capable excluded seller ........ pp. 200 — 202 Chapter IV. Two-sided Competition. The course of competition between several buyers and several sellers shown by an illustrative scheme, proving (1) that transactions are closed between the most capable competitors, (2) that price is determined by the valuations of the marginal pairs, (3) that there is an exhaustive analogy between the formation of price and that of subjective value, and (4) that price is, from end to end, the resultant of subjective valuations. The effect which the various groups of valuations have on price ........ pp. 203 — 213 Chapter V. The Law of Supply and Demand. The price zone determined by the marginal pairs may also be characterised as that within which Supply and Demand are in equilibrium. In two caises, the price of money and the price of labour, this latter formula is even more exact pp. 214—217 Chapter VI. The Individual Determinants of Price. The level (high or low) of the valuation of the marginal pairs is a resultant of the number and intensity of the desires on both sides. Analysing this into factors we find (1) extent of demand, (2) intensity of demand — the latter further analysed into the buyers’ subjective valuations of the commodity and of the equivalent price, (3) extent of supply, (4) intensity of supply — the latter further analysed into the sellers’ subjective valuations of the commodity and of the equivalent price. But where commodities are made for sale the sellers’ subjective valuations fall out altogether, and price is determined by the valuation of the last buyer .... pp. 218 — 222 ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS’ XXXV Chapter VII. The Law of Costs. The law that price tends to equality - with costs of production seems at first sight to contradict our law. But ; the concatenation is really the following. The consumers’ subjective valuations for each class of commodity determine the consumers’ demand. Against this stands supply of the particular commodity. The valuations of the marginal pairs determine its price. This price again determines the extent and intensity of the manufacturers’ demand for raw material, and this material passes to the most capable buyers at the valuation of the last buyer. Thus it is the least remunerative employment (the market/] equivalent of the subjective marginal utility) that determines the value of j the cost goods. What gives colour to the law of costs is the subsequent 1 phenomenon, that the value thus given to cost goods by marginal product is then transmitted from these costs to products of originally higher marginal utility. Explanation of cases where the movement of price seems to be • from costs to products, as in improvement of processes : increased supply changing the level of subjective valuations, and lowering the marginal utility. The symmetry between costs and products is disturbed by two causes — (1) general friction, (2) the lapse of time. This leads us to the consideration of the effect of differences of time on the valuation of goods pp. 223 — 234 BOOK V PEESENT AND FUTUEE Chapter I. Present and Future in Economic Life. Our general economic conduct has more reference to the future than we are always conscious of. Not feeling future sensations we yet anticipate and compare them, and the greater part of our wealth in the present consists of goods getting ready for the future. As future feelings are commensurable so are future goods, our basis of valuation being the marginal utility which they win bring us in the future. It should be noted, however, that the element of objective uncertainty m future goods has nothing to do with the pheno- menon of interest ; it is simply a premium against risk. Our fundamental principle, then, is, that present goods have a higher subjective value, and thus a higher price, than future goods of like kind and number. This is the resultant of the causes mentioned in the three following chapters pp. 237 — 248 Chapter DL Differences in Want and Provision for Want. Here two cases are typical — (1) that of immediate distress, (2) where economical pro- spects for the future are hopeful. In these cases present goods are obviously valued more highly than future. Even where the future does not promise better provision than the present, the shilling in my pocket, as a durable good, avails for the present, for the future, and for any chance that may turn up meantime. The exceptions to this — as in some perishable goods — are insignificant ....... pp. 249 — 252 xxxvi ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS Chapter III. Underestimate of the Future. Men, civilised as well as savage, generally underestimate the future simply because it is futme. Ihree reasons for this : (1) want of imagination, (2) defect in will, (3) Whe uncertainty of life. The latter obtains directly only as regards long periods, but by a species of arbitrage this underestimate is put into a definite percentage which obtains for all periods. This second factor com- bines with that of last chapter to increase the agio on present goods pp. 253—269 Chaptjer IV. The Technical Superiority of Present Qoods- As we ^^^^ow, methods of production which take time are more productive — not only as regards units of product, hut as regards value. Tables to prove this is so, even independent of the influence of the other two factors. The same superiority attaches to present goods simply as consumption goods, in so far as command over such goods leaves our means of production free for investment in lengthy processes. This is the source of Jevons’s mistake in considering subsistence as the only capital . . . pp. 260 — 272 Chapter V. Co-operation of the Three Factors. Tire action of the first two is cumulative, that of the third alternative, but the three really co- operate towards the same end, the preference for present goods. For the reasons already given, all classes — needy, careless, rich, saving — find some- thing in present goods superior to future. These subjective valuations meeting in a market determine a price which contains an agio : this agio, once established, has a reflex influence on subjective estimates, and a developed exchange system gradually levels arbitrary Valuations into a normal Tate ......... pp. 273 — 281 BOOK VI THE SOUECE OF INTEREST Chapter I. The Loan and Loan Interest. Here we have the simplest case : the exchange of two goods, one present, the other future, with the agio necessarily on the former. Misunderstandings of this in the past. Knies’s answer to the criticism of the Use theory in Capital and Interest. Principal plus interest is the equivalent in future goods of the principal lent in present goods. A loan without interest is a sale below market price .......... pp. 285 — 298 Chapter n. The Profit of Capitalist Undertaking. Principles of Explanation. The business of the capitalist is to buy goods of remoter rank, and transform them into consumption goods, his gain being called “profit.” One point must be made clear before going further ; these pro- ductive goods are economically future goods, and subject to the same dis- count as the future consumption goods into which they are ultimately ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS xxxvii changed. This is the ex23lanation of the so-called cheap buying. The capitalist gets his profit simply from the ripening of the future goods in his hand into present goods ...... pp. 299—303 Chapter III. The Profit of Capitalist Undertaking. Complications. (1) Our estimate of future goods is graduated according to the intervening time : corresponding with this the value of productive goods rises steadily as the process goes on, and the increased value is transferred from branch to branch of production. (2) Dmable productive goods contribute differ- ent parts of their contents to products maturing at various points of time, and so unite the characteristics of durable and of productive goods — of which later. (3) Productive goods admit of various employments turn- ing Out different products at different periods ; how then can they be valued in present goods ? — In the marginal utility of such goods the future as well'as the present uses have already been taken into consideration, the possible futm’e uses being reduced to present value. It remains for us now to confirm these theoretical conclusions by appeal to the actual markets where means of production are exchanged for present goods pp. 304 — 312 Chapter IV. The Profits of Capitalist Undertaking. The Labour Market. Assuming that, over the community, an average two year.s’. process is tm-ning out a product w'orth x ner week, supply here will b e- represented by a gi-eat number of labourers ready to accept much less than X rather than work in short unproductive processes. The demand comes from the undertakers, who must find it their interest to sell their goods to labour. What wage can they pay ? In simple circumstances they could employ their capital in extending their own processes, and so increase their return. If, instead, they use it to pay labourers, they must gain more in the buying of labour than they lose by dispensing with the extension of their process. In modern comjdex circumstances the ca^iitalists, who are not, as a rule, workers, lend their capital, through the channels of organ- ised credit, to those who wish to make their labour more productive, and find an agio already in the market. But Loan and Labour markets alike are parts of the great Subsistence market we have now to examine pp. 313—318 Chapter V. The Profit of Capitalist Undertaking. The General Subsistence Market. A fundamental proposition : The fund available for advances of subsistence consists of the entire wealth of a community exclusive of land. With the exceirtion of the small amount consumed wdth- out retmn or wasted, and that consumed by independent producers, all wealth comes to this gi’eat market, and is, directly or indirectly, advanced to labour. It may be objected that wealth in many forms, such as tools, is not subsistence. But all that is required is that wealth should be changed gradually into subsistence as the workers of the successive stages require it. The subsistence fund, then, includes not only finished goods, but goods at all stages of progress, and goods going through all lengths of process. Thus the average production period possible in a countiy depends on the amount of its wealth. Proof that the amount of subsistence required ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS xxxviii before entering on any process must be sufficient for a little over half the production period ........ pp. 319 — 328 Chapter VI. The Profit of Capitalist Undertaking. The General Subsistence Market {contini^el). To find the price at which finished present goods exchange against future on the subsistence market, we must examine more carefully the extent and intensity of supply and demand. The demand consists of (1) wage-earners, (2) independent producers wish- ing to extend their processes, (3) borrowers for consumption. Thus it is easy to see that the demand must always be in excess of the supply ; that an agio must appear : and that, as putting the drag on undue extensions of process, this agio is as healthy as it is inevitable. Finally what is true of labour is true of uses of land and of intermediate products. Error of Socialist theory in not seeing that so-called “cheap buying” is true of these as well as of labour ...... pp. 329 — 338 Chapter VII. Interest from Durable Goods. The value of a dmable good being a sum made up of all the material services inhering in it, the single service may obtain an independent value and price. Where a good lasts for years the remote services suffer the same discount of value as future goods in general. But as each service is given off, the remaining services, by one year's approximation to the present, grow one year more valuable, and each year the parent good loses the value of the most remote service still inhering in the good. Thus what the owner gains is the gross present value of the annual service thrown off : what he loses (wear and tear) is the value of the most remote service : the difference between these two is the net return of interest. Thus our theory gives a simple answer where Productivity, Exploitation, and Use theories found only a stone of stumbling. Obviously also it gives the natural explanation of Capitalisa- tion .......... pp. 339 — 349 Chapter VIII. Interest from Durable Goods {corvtinued). In durable goods that are also productive goods we find a double phenomenon : although the good has perished in giving off its successive services, the services thus incorporated in the process remain bound up in it till its completion : thus it bears interest after it has ceased to exist, but the interest is now ascribed to the circulating capital in which' the services have been incorporated, and not to the “outlay.” An important application If a good is infinitely durable, the capitalised value is infinitely small compared with the sum of successive services ; the last service is infinitely small, and wear and tear vanishes : the gross return and the net return are one. Here then we get the explanation of land rent, as simply a special case of interest obtained from durable goods. The bearing of this on the Eicardian theory pp. 350 — 357 Chapter IX. Results. Owners of capital, then, are merchants in present goods, and such goods being more valuable than the “future goods,” Labour, Uses of land, and Capital, the agio or interest included in the price is only reasonable. Circumstances may often produce exploitation ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS XXXIX and usury, but in the essence of interest, there is nothing unjust ; as in all human institutions, we have to balance advantages with drawbacks, and the balance swings in favour of interest .... pp. 358 — 364 Chapter X. Interest under Socialism. Even here, as time does not stand still, the causes of interest would still be active. Suppose all other sources stopped, if dm'able goods were exchanged for less capitalised value than the full sum of all their futui'e services the agio of interest would emerge. Indeed under Socialism the state would ‘ ‘ exploit ” the labourers — perhaps to divide out the amount more equitably, but still to divide it as interest, not as wage ....... pp. 365 — 371 BOOK VII THE BATE OF INTEEEST Chapter I. The Bate in Isolated Exchange. Our present task is to point out the concrete circumstances that influence the valuations on both sides. Fu’st, of isolated exchange. In the production loan what deter- mines the subjective valuation of the suitor is the amount he will gain by extending his process. But as, beyond a certain point, the sui’plus retiu'ns decrease as processes extend, a present loan has less value in proportion to the length of process already provided for . . . pp. 375 — 380 Chapter IL The Bate in Market Transactions. First assuming that the demand comes froni the wage-earners alone, how high will rise the agio ? Here we meet a special diflBculty. The price of labour is the resultant of subjective valuations of buyer and seller, but what value can the capitalist put upon the labour he wishes to buy wheu it will bring a dift'erent product and value according to the length of process in which it is invested, and when, again, the process he will adopt depends upon the wage he must pay 1 The “fixed point” is found in the fact that the existing stock of wealth can always buy aU the wage labour offered. This gives a certain definiteness to the average length of process, and so the product on which the capitalist bases his valuation. But again it may be a long process at a low wage or a short process at a high Wage. The final answer is, that the wage offei'ed must bring subsistence and number of workers to • equilibrium in such a way that neither party can disturb it by under-bidding or over-bidding. Or, to put it positively ; The rate is determined by the productiveness of the last economic extension of process, in such a way that the amount of capital making the extension possible must bear a less interest than the surplus return obtained by means of it which is pretty much identical with Thiinen’s “last dose of capital ” pp. 381 — 394 Chapter IIL The Bate- in Market Transactions {continued). But what are the concrete determinants which decide the degi-ee xl ANAL YTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS of productiveness of the last extension ? If, ceteris paribus, subsist- ence increases, the same calculations as before show that equilibrium cannot be maintained without an extension of process, an increase of wage, and a fall of interest — the latter accounted for by the fact that men can only keep the increased wealth employed by extensions of process which involve decreased surpluses. If, on the other hand, subsistence falls, equilibrium demands contraction of processes, fall in wage, and rise in interest. If, again, population rise or fall we have the converse results. Lastly, if productiveness increase, ceteris paribus, interest will rise along with the surplus now yielded by the last extension. Thus we conclude that there are three decisive factors which affect the rate of interest, and this is confirmed by history and experience pp. 395 — 402 Chapter IV. The Market for Capital in its Full Development. And now to give the features of actual life to our abstract scheme. It makes no difference to om- aa'gument that product and wage vary from employ- ment to employment : the essential matter for interest is the relation between the two. Nor does it matter that in actual life the annual increment due to extensions of process varies from employment to employ- ment : capital follows an isohypse of surplus returns, not of periods of production, but this does not alter the essential circumstances on which our law rests. Again, there are other demands besides that of the wage- earners — (A) that for consumption credit, completely co-ordinate with the other, (B) that of landowners who require subsistence proportioned to the length of their production processes, (C) that of capitalists themselves, although their claim on subsistence is effect and not cause of the agio. Lastly, we may enumerate the seven concrete factors in the interest rate pp. 403—412 Chapter V. The Market for Capital in its Full Development {con- tinued). To look now at the struggle between immediate consumption and accumulation. In good economical management present and future will be alike considered, and provision made that the present consumption shall not reduce the level of future enjoyment. Thus parent wealth should be saved, and even some portion of income. The two great deviations from economic conduct are due (1) to the perspective undervaluation of the futme and (2) to the neglect of exact calculation of the future’s claims. Differences between our theory and that of the Wage Fund. Finally, the actual market for capital is not one gi'eat undivided market, hut a great number of part markets all communicating and arbitrating each other’s prices. Conclusion ....... pp. 413 — 424 Appendix to page 327 Index of Authors mentioned . . pp. 425-:-426 . pp. 427 — 428 INTKODUCTION In systems of Political Economy the word Capital and the theory of Capital are regularly met with in two distinct spheres ; first, under Production , and, second, under . Distribu.- ' tion. I n the former case capital is represented as a factor or tool of production : as an instrument which men use to extort from nature the various forms of wealth unattainable by simple labour. In the latter case capital appears as a source of income or a rent fund ; and we are shown how, in the division among the various members of society of that wealth which has been produced in common, capital acts like a magnet, drawing a portion of the national product to itself, and deliver- ing it over to its owner : it appears, in a word, as the source of Interest., When we are told that capital assists in the production of wealth, and then again that it assists in the obtaining of wealth for its owner, we are apt to jump to the conclusion that the two phenomena are intimately and essentially con- nected, and that the one is the immediate result of the other — that capital can bring wealth to its owner because capital assists in the production of wealth. .As a fact. Political Economy has taken up this idea only too readily and too completely. Captivated by the deceptive symmetry that exists between the three great factors of production — Nature, Labour, Capital — and the three great branches of income — Eent, Wage, and Interest — the science, from Say’s day till the present, has taught that these three branches of income are nothing else than the payment for the three factors of production , and that 2 INTRODUCTION 1 Interest in particular is nothing else than the compensation which capital receives for its productive services when the product is divided out among society. Propounded by various interest theories in various forms this idea has found its mos t conciRR and, at the same time, its most naive expression, in the well-known “ Productivity theories,” — those theories which explain interest directly as the natural fruit of a productive power peculiar to and resident in capital.' In beginning the study of the theory of Capital, it cannot be too emphatically stated that this idea,, simple and natural as it may appear, contains a, prejudgment calculated to pre- clridft nnhia.R.Rcd chn sideration of the problems of capi tal If there were no other objection, the fact that the word capital is never used exactly in the same sense in the two spheres of phenomena must give us pause. True, all capital which .serves as a tool of production is also capable of hearing interest, but the converse is not the case . \/K dwelling-house, a hired horse, a circulating library bear interest to their respective owners without having anything to do with the production of new wealth. If, in the sphere of distribution, the conception of capital thus embraces objects which are not capital in the sphere of production^, this alone is sufficient to show that the , bearing of interest cannot bv itself be an _indi cation oljths productive power of capital We have not to deal with one motive power transmitting Itself to two different spheres ; not even with two groups of phenomena which have grown up so intimately connected that the explanation of the one is got fully and entirely through the explanation of the other ; but with two di stin ct classes of p henomena, yhus we have two. distinct subj eats, which give' us material for two distinct scientific problems ; and finally, w e have to seek for th e solution of these problems by two distinct and separate roads. It so happens, however, that these reaUy distinct problems are accidentaUv linked together by one name : they are problems of Capital. It may be that, besides identity of name, we shall find many inner relations, between the two series of pheno- mena and the two problems ; — our investigation shall decide that later. But such relations are yet to be discovered ; they must not be assumed ; and unless we would give up all idea 1 See my Capital and Interest, 1890, p. 111. INTRODUCTION 3 of being unprejudiced in our quest and in our conclusions, ipust begin the iiiquir^^ free from any preconceived opinion of a necessary identity, or even of -a n pya pt parallfthRm . between the productive efficiency of cnpital and its power of bearing interest. Our division of the subject will correspond to this real independence of the two problems. In one part of the present work we shall take up the .theory of Capital as a Tool of Productio n, and in another the theory nf Tirte.rest. But we shall first devote a separate book to the attempt to obtain some insight into what Capital itself is, in conception and nature. I BOOK I THE NATURE AND CONCEPTION OF CAPITAL r- •A V- • , y , ■ . -K-'y \.'' ■<;, •. Vi)! i^. I . ■'"'"It- ■,. ■ j ^4 :. ' ■ '♦••. . ' ■ .j ' / V CHAPTER I MAN AND NATURE There is scarcely a system or a text-book of -PoliticRl p,conomy which does not, at some point or other, hring in (lisc^ issicin . s . .o f matters helong-ing to the physical sciences . Usually these are introduced in the chapter on Production. There we are taught that ro create new goods does not mean to create new material, since matter is constant and cannot be increased. We learn what nature contributes to the woiiv of production in the shape of materials and powers ; what is done by the mechanical, what by the chemical, and what by the organic powers of nature ; what importance climate, heat, moisture have on the development of production ; on what physical and technical foundations the working of machinery rests ; and many things of this sort. To the principle of this custom no sensible person will object. It is the form in which, consciously or unconsciously, we pay boTna.o'p. to one of the weight, lAst-, principles of our knowledge, the unity of all science. Ever since Bacon we have recognised that no single branch of inquiry explains to the very end the facts with which it deals, but breaks off at some point or other, and passes on its facts to some sister science for further treatment, so that the total explanation is only given by the totahty of all the sciences. Thus it is that if one would not set before his readers simply a collection of barren fragments, he must add to what is distinctively depart- mental at least so nmch as will connect it wi th the related sciences in, the organic whole of human knowledge, and thus indicate the way in which the explanations begun by him may be concluded. 8 MAN AND NATURE BOOK 1 It would, however, be rather impertinent if we theorists were to think that such terminal truths — as we may appro- priately caU them — -are added only for purposes of statement and for the good of our readers. Eightly employed they are of much greater use to ourselves as scientific inquirers. They may be an effectual means of p reventing us Jrnnn lightly b uilding our whole sy stem, or parts of it, on_air^ and uninten- tionally maintaining in the name of Political Economy some- thing which, in its assumptions or conclusions, is, physically or psychologically speaking, nonsense. I must not be mis- understood however. It is not in the least my meaning that Political Economy should assume a nature foreign to it, and become natural science or psychology ; w hat T do mean is that it must never be in contradiction with these s ciences. What is false in natural science or psychology is false in all and every science. And to prevent us unwittingly running counter to certain fundamental truths, perhaps the best way is to put these truths explicitly in black and white before our eyes. Now the subject with which we have to deal in this work is of such a nature that it very snecially requires to be baset l on sound natural principles, and a very great deal may be lost by neglect of this. I have therefore strong reasons for following the good old custom, and prefacing my theory by ^^some fundamental truths that stretch over into the neighbouring sphere of the natural sciences. I shall endeavour not to abuse the opportunity by inflicting a mass of learned scientific detail on the reader. The few truths I mean to start with would indeed, in a professional classification, be put within the sphere of the natural sciences, but they are of so general a character that, practically, f.hpy are outside departmental l imits, ami belong to the commonwealth of knowledg e. They are known and recognised by everybody, and, in one form or other, they have been expressed all along in our economic literature. There is really only one thing that, I skould like to think, will distinguish my use of them : I shall try so to put t biemJTiai; the y will not be mere paragraphs introducing^ the t heory, but . wi ll remain present and living i mthc-Spirit ofJL Usually these excursuses into the domains of physics are placed in some corner of economical books rather for ornament than use. In one chapter they are made much of ; in the next they are forgotten CHAP. I GOODS 9 and contradicted. In what follows I shall try to avoid this error, and wherever anything depends upon these fundamental truths — which will very often be the case in a discussion on capital — to keep unobtrusively but firmly in touch with them. In this way, while there is no fear of our economical theory obtaining the character of a theory of natural science, it wilL not be one that runs counter to physical facts. _ Men stri vp. happiness. This is perhaps the most general and, certainly, the most vague expression for a complex of strivings, all of wliich have for object the bringing about of such occurrences and conditions as we know and feel to be pleasant, and the averting of those we know to be unpleasant. Instead of “ striving after happiness we may use the expres- sion “ striving after self-preservation and self-development,” or “ stri\dng after the greatest possible furtherance of life ” ; or we may, with equal propriety, use the words, “ striving after the most complete possible satisfaction of wants ” . for the expressions we are'" so famihaf 'wrfK’’ uT economic terminology, “ want ” and “ satisfaction of want,” mean, in the last resort, nothing else than, respectively, the unsatisfied craving of man to be put under conditions he thinks desirable or more desirable than those he has, and the successful obtaining of such conditions. The_ whole world, as we know it. is subject to the law of cause and effee.t; no effect can take place without sufficient cause. From this law man and his conditions have no exemp- tion ; none of those beneficent changes of condition, which we call “ satisfactions of want,” can come about otherwise than as the effect of a sufficient cause ; eA^ery satisfaction presupposes an adequate instrument of safisfaction . The adequate instru - ments for the satisfaction of himian wants, or — what is the same thing — the causes of beneficent changes in human condi- tions, we call goods.^ The man-wJfo*“ wants ” finds goods in different spheres of the world in which he lives ; he finds them in the world o f. persons as well as in the world of thing s. For obvious reasons, which need not be discussed here, we use the word “ good ” in somewhat different ways in these two spheres. On the one See Menger, Grundsii/jze der Volkswirthscho/ftslehre, p. 1. Vienna, 1871. 10 MAN AND NA TV RE BOOK hand, we designate bv the name of goods not t he persons. \Kho- are of use to us. but only the acts, the services, thr ough which. they are of nse ; on the other hand, we give the name to the impersonal material shapes themselves, and call them Material as opposed to Personal goods. In what follows we have to do with m aterial goo ds only_ Material goods are part of the external world : they are natural things. As such they are, in constitution and action, wholly and entirely natural products, and su bject to natural laws. The fact that men’s goods are instruments towards the personal ends of the “ lord of creation ” gives these goods no kind of immunity from complete subordination to the natural order, any more than man himself is able to emancipate the natural side of his being from similar control Material goods. ^ therefore, come mto existence only as natural la ws allow and demand that a material shape, thus and not otherwise consti- tuted, should come into existence. They pass out of existence if a new combination of natural powers, working according to natural laws, results of necessity in the dissolution of their ' former material shape. They cannot exert the smallest effect, be it useful, hurtful, or indifferent to men, unless the given coincidence of materials and powers under natural laws pro- duce this very effect and no other. These seem peculiarly trifling propositions. They are trifling enough to require no formal proof; indeed, no one will seriously dispute them. But, simple and trifling as they are, on certain tempting occasions these fundamental 0/ truths have been lost sight of. and theories have been put in circxilation which implicitly contradict them. The theorist, therefore, has good cause to emphasise them, and even foUow out their logical conclusions to a certain extent into those departments where they have to do duty as, peculiarly, the fundamental truths of economic theory. These depart- ments are the function of goods and the origin of goods ; in other words, tbp tViPri yy of the Use of goods, and the theory of the Production of goods. The theory of the use of goods I have already gone into at length in Capital and Interest} I there showed that material * P. 219 (German edition, p. 266). See also my Bechte und VerMllnisse, p. 61. Innsbrack, 1881. CHAP. I THE USE OF GOODS 11 goods are nothing else than such distinct forms of matter as admit of the natural powers residing in them being directed to human advantage. I showed how the “ use ” they afford is realised through concrete activities of these iia.tural powers; , and, therefore, by real forth putting of power. I showed how a use {Gebrauch or Nutzung) cannot be made of them other- wise than by taking the peculiar forms of the energy of the good at the proper moment, supplying the conditions necessary to render them available where they previously existed in an unavailable form, and t hen bringing these forms of energ; ^^ into proper connection with that object in which the useful effect is to take place. On these considerations I based the conception of the “ Material Services ” {Nutzleistungen) which I believe to be the only one that corresponds with facts, and rejected certain shadowy ideas which connected the old theory of interest with the word “ Uses ” of goods. ^Vdiat remains for us here is, on the same lines, to lay down certain fundamental ideas as to the origin of material goods. We have already said that the origin of natural goods lies entirely mider the control of natural laws. No material good can come into existence except when a previous coincidence of materials and powers has made it necessary in physical law that exactly this form of matter should emerge. Looked at from the point of view of nature, the formation of goods is a purelA^ natural process . Not so, however, from the point of view of man_ Man has cause to lay emphasis on a distinction which is not visible from the purely physical standpoint. One. great class of useful forms of m a, tier comes into existence without interference from man, as the product of favour- able coincidences of matter and force — a product which, from the teleological human standpoint, we should call accidental Thus originate fruitful islands in the courses of streams ; thus the grass on natural pastures and prairies ; thus berries and trees of the wood ; thus deposits of useful minerals. But . thnngb in this way accident does much for man it does not, do nearly enough. In nature left to herself we have on a large scale what we should have on a small one if we wished to make a definite picture out. of coloured bits of stone, and, instead of piecing the picture together deliberately, were to put the bits of stone into a kaleidoscope and wait till accident 12 MAN AND NA DURE BOOK I shook the planless stones into the wislied-for picture. Among the infinite number of ways in which the worlcing materials and powers might combine there are, in the one case as in the other, a countless number of possible effects, but only a few favourable ones ; and in the natural undisturbed course of things these few turn up too seldom for man, with all his wants, to rest content with them, ^^ccordingly he inte^pose^s another factor in the natural -process, his own cons ciousl y \ ^ directed energies — he begins to produce the goods he requires. To “ produce ” : what does this mean ? I t has been s o often said by_econojnists that the creation of goods is not the bringing into existence of materials that hitherto have not existed — is not “ creation ” in the true sense of the word, — but only a fashioning of imperishable, matter . ,int o more a dvantageous shapes , that it is quite unnecessary to say it again. More accurate, but still exposed to misinterpretatibh, is the expression that in production natural powers are the ^ servants of man, and are directed by him to his own advantage. If this proposition be taken to mean that man in any case can im pose his sovereign will in place of na tural laws^ can at wiU “ bully ” natural law into making a single exception at his bidding, it is entirely eiToneous. Whether the lord of creation will it or no, not an atom of matter can, for a single moment or by a hair’s breadth, work otherwise than the unchangeable laws of nature demand. Man’s role in production is much more modest. It consists simply in this — that he, himself a part of the natui’al world, combines his personal powers with ‘ the impersonal powers of nature, and combines them in such a way that under natural law the co-operation results in a definite, desired, material form. Thus— potwik bs tanding th a j i nterference of man, the origin of go ods remains purely.- a natural process. The natural process is not disturbed by man ) but completed, inasmuch as, by apt intervention of his own natural powers, he supphes a condition which has hitherto been wanting to the origination of a material good. If we look more closely at the way in which man assists natural processes, we find that his snip but ample contribution consists in the moving of things. “ Ihitting objects in motion ” is the idea which gives the key to all human production CHAP. I PRODUCTION 13 and its results ; — to all man’s mastery over nature add its powers.^ And this is so simply because the powers reside ill the objects. T^ow. when man bv his physical powers — the power of moving thinp ; s — is able in dip.ta.tP! 'inhp.rp, the objec t shall be, he obtains a control over the place at which a natural power may become effective ; and this means broadly a control over the wav and over the time_ in which it may become effectiye. I sav a control over the wav in wbicb a. natural powey may become effective. Of course a pound weight acts as a pound weight and never in any other way ; whether it be a paper weight on a writing-table, or a counterpoise on a scale- beam, or whether it keep down the valve of a steam-engine, it never ceases to exert the force of gravitation with which its mass is endowed. But just because the expression of one and the same natural power always remains the same, results that n.rp, extraordinarily different mav be obtained by getting it to work in different combinations- — just as by adding like to unlike a different sum may be got every time. And so our pound weight, while in itself constantly acting with perfect uniformity, will, according to the different surroundings in which we place it, sometimes hold together a heap of papers on a writing-table, sometimes indicate the weight of another object, sometimes regulate the pressure of steam in the boiler. A gain T say a control over the, time in which a nat u ral power may become effective . This proposition, also, must not be taken too literally. It must not be imagined that natural powers work intermittently ; that man can sometimes bring them to a standstill, sometimes set them working agaim On thfer contrary^ natural powers are always at work; a natural power not active would be a contradiction in terms. But it is possible that several powers mav be so combined that tbe.ir activities. may for a time mutuaUv balance each o ther, and the resultant be rest- — if not complete rest, still some movement so slight that, as regards human purposes, it may be neglected. i^Tien this is the case, before any new resultant can emerge that is of interest to man, there must be an entirely different .comb ina tion of materials and powers. This suggests hoAv man may get control of the point of time at which a definite resultant ^ See Mill’s Principles, i. 1. 2. 14 MAN AND NATURE BOOK I emerges. It is only necessary for him, by skilful use of his power to ^ove objects, to provide the causes of the desired effect, all hut one. So long as this one is not present the conditions are unfulfilled, and there cannot be the desired result. But when at the proper moment he adds the last c.rmdi±,inT), the Tp ovement hitherto held in leash, as it were, ia suddenly set free, and the desired effect is obtained at the opportune time. Thus the sportsman moves powder and lead into the barrel of the gun ; he shuts the breech ; he raises the cock. Each of these things has for long possessed and expressed its peculiar powers. In the powder are pre- sent the molecular powers whose energy later on is to expel the shot from the barrel. The barrel now, as formerly, exerts ^ts forces of cohesion and resistance. The trigger which is to let the cock smash down, strains and presses against the spring. Still the arrangement, the disposition of the collective powers, is such that the resultant of their mutual energies is rest. But the sportsman covers the wild fowl with the barrel: there is a slight pressure on the tongue, a Little dislocation of the arrangements, and the f^^but flics ^ ^ If we were to carry our analysis of what man does in production a step further, we might approuriatelv distinguish three fundamental wavs in whiej^ the prodiicinp- man “moves things. ” The fi.r.gjt is^ hat, for want of a better name, we may call simple movements or changes of plag e — where men transport _jntire-®bjects from one locality to another. Thus the miner brings the ore from the depths of the shaft to the upper air ; the merchant takes his goods from the place where they are produced to the place where they are demanded and used. The secQftd—embraees- those movements of parts of one a nd t he sa me object whereby it experiences a change of forna , as when nails are made from iron, statues from marble, pipes from clay, dials from ivory, combs from caoutchouc, tumblers from glass, furniture from wood. The third, and much the most common way, i.s where difl’erent objects are brougkvdw^her-ifi-space to form combinations of matter . These combinations may be merely temporary , or they may be lasting . Instances of the one are where the stamp falls on the coin, the chisel chips at the marble, the carving tool is applied to the wood, the ore put into the furnace, the yarn into the loom, the paper under the printing press, the stuff under the shears, the plough through the clods. Instances of the other are where we build a house out of wood, stone, lime, iron, etc. ; where we put together a watch out of wheels, springs, pendula, weignts, stop-action and many other things ; in fact in manufacture generally. I must warn the reader that this division into three fundamental forms neither has, nor is meant to have, the character of strict scientific classification. Indeed, these forms merge in many instances into one another. Temporary combinations, for instance, are very often half-way to changes of form, and what I have called a simple change CHAP, 1 MAN’S ALLIES IN PRODUCTION 15 The same considerations which show us the kind of mastery man has over nature show us at the s amp, timp. the measure and the narrow limits of his mastery . As we have seen, man has a certain power to make natural forces act where, when, and how he will ; but this power he possesses only in so far as he can control the matter in which these forces reside. Now the masses of matter, and therefore the masses of inert resistance, which have to be overcome before our purposes are served, are often immense, while the physical force which is at our command is very modest and comparatively trifling. Often, on the other hand, the matter is too fine to be manipulated by our rude hand. Our interests often call for infinitely delicate rearrangements of infinitely small pieces, and how un suited are our clumsy fingers to deal with molecules and atoms ! How entirely incapable is the human hand of im- itating even one of those wonderfully dehcate cellular tissues which nature flings out in thousandfold, every day, in every plant and leaf! Thus human pow ^pg at-p. fimibly defieient : they are too s light as against the mass, too rude as against the structure of the matter which they have to subdue. In those circumsta nces we should be very badly off for the wherewithal of production if we had not' some real allies bebiml these doubly insuflScient powers. One of these aUief} is the human mind. In investigating the causal rela5idn"6T" things wvu come "tCT'kilow the natural conditions under which the desired goods come into existence : we thus come to learn where human force can be applied with advantage and where not; and thus we are taught to avoid exertions which are barren and choose .those which are profitable. Human power so directed is like a small but well-officered army, which makes up in mobility, cohesion, and energetic use of opportunity, of place is at the same time, in a certain point of view, a material combination, a bringing together of the thing moved and the object (personal or impersonal) to which it is moved. This division, however, will make it easier to find our reckoning, and will prove too, if necessary, the correctness of the general char- acteristics which I have ascribed in the text to productive processes. I mean to say that it is easy to see that every productive activity which one can thin k _Qf ranges itself under some one of these three fundamental forms, and to that extent it is proved that such an activity must; a fortiori, range itself also under the general formula given in the text, where ve have described the nature and method of the production of material goods as the mastery of natural powers by means of putting objects in motion. 16 MAN AND NATURE BOOK I what it wauts in ntimbers. ^ni^ther powerful ally in tho struprple against nature is nature herself. All tliat we are able to do in production would be wretchedly small were it not that, in the storehouse of nature, we find the means of dividjug nature a. p pjjrstdtersel-f and setting force .again st Jbice. But here we touch on a subject which is, in itself, too important, par- ticularly as regards our inquiry, to admit of merely a passing mention CHAPTER II THE NATURE OF CAPITAL The end and aim of all production is the making of things with which to satisfy our wants : that is to say, the making of goods for immediate consmnption, or Consmnption Goodsd The method of their production we have already looked at m a general way. We combine our own natural powers and natural powers of the external world in such a way that, under natural law', the desired material good must come into existence. But this is a very general description indeed o'f the matter, and looking at it closer there comes in sight an important distinc - tion which we have not as yet considered. It^has reference to the distance which lies between the expenditure of human l ^nnr in the comhiued production and the appearan ce of the desired good. We either put forth our labour just before^ the goal is reached, or we, intentionally, take a roundabout I way. That is to say, we may put forth our labour in such su way that it at once completes the circle of conditions neces- sary for the emergence of the desired good, and thus the existence of the good immediatdy follnwa the expenditure of the labour ; or we may associate "ourTahour first with the more remote causes of the good, with the object of obtaining, not the desired good itself, but a proximate cause of the good ; which cause, again, must be associated with other suitable ^ Menger has suggestively called these Good.s of the First lianh, classing all goods which go to their production as Goods of Higher Rank. It is unfortunate that we cannot use the literal English equivalent of the “ Genussguter,” but, as next to it in convenience, I propose to use the expression Consumption Goods for what otherwise we should have to translate as Goods for Immediate Consumption. See Monger’s Gruvdsdtze, p. 8, and Bohra- Bawerk’s Rcchte uvd Verhdltnisse, p, 101. — W. S. C 18 THE NATURE OE CAPITAL BOOK I materials and powers, till, finally, — perhaps through a consider- able number of intermediate members, — the finished good, the instrument of human satisfaction, is obtained. The nature and importance of this distinction will be best seen from a few examples ; and, as these will, to a considerable extent, form a demonstration of what is really one of the most fundamental propositions in our theory. I must risk being tedious. A peasant requires drinking water. The spring is some distance from his house. There are various ways in which he may supply his daily wants. First, he mav go to the .spring each time he is thirsty , and drink out of his hollowed hand. This is the most direct way ; satisfaction follows hnmediately on exertion. But it is an inconvenient way, for our peasant has to take his way to the well as often as he is thirsty. And it is an insufficient way, for he can never collect and store any great quantity such as he requires for various other purposes. Second , he may take a log of wood, hollow it out into a kind of pail, and pprry hi.^ da,v’R .'^ upplv from the sp ring to his cottage. The advantage is obvious, but it necessitates a roundabout way of considerable length. The man must spend, perhaps, a day in cutting out the pail ; before doing so he must have felled a tree in the forest ; to do this, again, he must have made an axe, and so on. But there is still a third ' way ; instead of felling one tree he fells a number of ti’ees, sphts and hollows them, lays them end for end, and so constructs a runnel or rhone which brings a full head of water to his co ttage . Here, obviously, between the expenditure of the labour and the obtaining of the water we have a very round- about way, but, then, the result is ever so much greater. Our peasant needs no longer take his weary way from house to well with the heavy pail on his shoulder, and yet he has a constant and full supply of the freshest water at his very door. Another example. I reqtrire stone for building a house. There is a rich vein of excellent sandstone in a neighbouring hill. How is it to be got out ? First, I may work the lon.qp. ^ stones back and forward with my bare fingers, and break off what can be broken off. This is the most direct, but also the least productive way. S econd. L mgay-Aake a piece of ' iror r ma.ke a hammer and chise l out of. it, and use them on the hard stone — a roundabout way, which, of course, leads to CHAP. II THE ROUNDABOUT METHOD 19 a very much better result than the former. Third method — - Having a hammer and chisel I use them to drill a hole in the~ rock ; next I turn my attention to procuring charcoal, sulphui’, and nitre, and mixing them in a, powder, then I pour the powder into the hole, and the explosion that follows spht.^ the Rtnnp. into convenient pieces — still more of a roundabout way, but one which, as experience shows, is as much superior to the second way in result as the second was to the first. Yet another example. I am short-sighted, and wish to have a pair of spectacles. For this I require ground and pohshed glasses, and a steel framework. But all that nature offers towards that end is silicious earth and iron ore. How am I to transform these into spectacles ? Work as I may, it is as impossible for me ^to make spectacles directly out of sihcious earth as it would be to make the steel frames out of iron ore. Here there is no immediate or direct method of production . There is nothing for it but to take the round- about way, and, indeed, a very roundabout way. I must take sihcious earth and fuel, and build furnaces for smelting the glass from the sihcious earth ; the glass thus obtained has to be carefuhy purified, worked, and cooled by a series of pro- cesses ; finally, the glass thus prepared — again by means of ingenious instruments carefuhy constructed beforehand — is ground and pohshed into the lens fit for short-sighted eyes. Simharly, I must smelt the ore in the blast furnace, change the raw iron into steel, and make the frame therefrom — processes which cannot be carried through without a long series of tools and buildings that, on their part again, require great amounts of ’ previous labour. Thus, by an exceedingly ^ r oundabout wav, the end is attained. The lesson to be drawn from all these examples alike is obvious. It is — that a greater result is obtained by producing goods in r oun dabout ways than by producing them directly . AYhere a good can be produced in either way, we have the I fact that, by the indirect way, a greater product can be gotj with equal labour, or the same product with less labour. But! beyond this, the superiority of the indirect way manifests itselif in being the only way in which certain goods can be obtained'. if I might say so, it is so much the better that it is often the •only way ! 20 THE NA TURE OF CAPITAL BOOK I J That roundaljDiit methods lead to g reater..ji:esu lts than direct methods is one of the most important and fundamental / propositions in the whole theory of production It must be emphatically stated that the only basis of this proposition is the experi ence of pract ical life. Economic theory does not and cannot show a 'priori that it must be so ; but the unanimous experience of all the technique of production says that it is so. And this is sufficient ; aU the more that the facts of experience which tell us this are commonplace and familiar to everybody. But whv is it so ? The economi.st j might quite well decline to answer this q uestion. For the / fact that a greater product is obtained by methods of produc- tion that begin far back is essentially a purely technical fact, and to explain questions of technique does not fall within the economist’s sphere. For instance, that tropical lands are more fruitful than the polar zone ; that the alloy of which coins is made stands more wear and tear than pure metal ; that a rail- road is better for transport than an ordinary turnpike road ; — all these are matters of fact with which the economist reckons, but which his science does not call on him to explain. But this is exactly one of those cases where, in the economist’s own interest — the interest he has in limiting and defining his own task — it is exceedingly desirable to go bevon d_ the specific economic sphere. If the sober physical truth is once made clear, political economy cannot indulge in any fancies or fictions about it ; and, in such questions, political economy has never been behind in the desire and the attempt to substitute its own imaginings .! Although, then, this law is already suffi- ciently accredited by experience. I attach particu lar value to,. explaining its causj ^ and, after what has been said as to the nature of production, this should not be very difficult. In the last resort all our productive efforts amount to shiftings and combinations of matter. We must know how to bring together the right forms of matter at the right moment, in order that from those associated forces the- desired result, the product wanted, may follow. But, as w p s^rW, the na.f.nral forms of niatter are often so infinitely la r ge., often so infinitely fine, that h\iman hands are too weak or too coarse to control them. W'e are as powerless to overcome the cohesion of the wall of rock when we want building scone as we are, from CHAP. II THE ROUNDABOUT METHOD 21 carbon, nitrogen, hydrogen, oxygen, phosphor, potash, etc., to put together a single grain of wheat. But there are other powers which can easily do what is denied to us. and the se are the powers of nature. There are natural powers which far exceed the possibilities of human power in greatness, and there are other natural powers in the microscopic world which can make combinations that put our clumsy fingers to shame. 1£ we can succeed in making those forces our allies in the work of production- the limits of human possibility will be infinitely extended. And this we have done. The, condition of our success is, that we are able to , non ,- 1 trol the materials on wliich the power that helps us dep ends. I more ea.sily than the materials which_ar fi_tQJh e transformed iut oj the desired good. Happily tliis, condition can be very often complied with. Our weak yielding hand cannot overcome the cohesion of the rock, but the hard wedge of iron can ; the wedge and the hammer to drive it we can happily master with little trouble. We cannot gather the atoms of phosphorus and / potash out of the ground, and the atoms of carbon and oxygen/ out of the atmospheric air, and put them together in the shape/ of the corn of wheat ; but the organic chemical powers of thei seed can put this magical process in motion, while we on our partj can very easily bury the seed in the place of its secret working; the bosom of the earth. Often, of course, we are not able directly to master the form of matter on which the friendly power depends, but in the same way as we would like it to help us, do we help ourselves against it ; we trv to secure the alliance of a second natural power which brings the form of matter that'jbears' the first power under our control . We wish to~Bnng the well water into the house, p Wooden rhones would force it to obey our will, and take the path we prescribe, but our hands have not the power to make the forest trees into rhones. We have not far to look, however, for an expedient. r^e ask the help of a second ally in the axe and the gouge ; their assistance gives us the rhones the rhones bring us the water. And what in this illustration is done through the mediation of two or three members may be done, with equal or greater result, through five, ten, or twenty members. Just as we control and guide the immediate matter of which the good is composed by one friendly power^ and that power by a 22 THE NATURE OF CAPITAL BOOK I second, so can we control and guide the second bv a third, t-.he third ly a fourth, this, again, by a fifth, and so on. — always going back to more remote causes of the final result — till in the series we come at last to one cause which we can control c-onveniently by our own natural powers. This is the true importance which attaches to our entering on roundabout ways of production, and this is the reason of the result associated with them ; every roundabout wav means the enlisting in our service of a power which is stronger or more cunning than the human hand ; every extension of the roundabout way means an addition to the powers which enter into the service of man, and the shifting of some portion of the burden of production from the scarce and costly labour of human be ings to the prodigal powers of nature And now we may put into words an idea which has long waited for expression, and must certainly have occurred to the reader ; the kind of production whic lL works in thes e wise circuitous methods is nothing else than what ec onomistS-Call Ca,pita.b'f^|; Production, as opposed to that production which goes directly at its object, as the Germans say, “■'init (hr nackten Famt.”'^ And Capital is nothing but the complex of interm^iate products wfeeh appear on the several stages of the roundabout journey. It is in this way I interpret the most important funda- mental conception in the theory of capital, and I should be very glad to stop here. But, like so many another conception in the theory of capital, this conception of capital itself ba§ become a veritable apple of discord to the theorists. A per- fectly amazing number of divergent interpretations here con- front each other, and block the approach to the theory of capital with one of the most vexatious controversies in which o\m science could be involved. This uncertainty as t o the conception of capital, bad enough in itself, becomes worse in proportion as Capital gives modern science new questions to consider and discuss. It is certainly very unfortunate when a ^ The expression Capitalist Production is generally used in one of two senses. 1 1 desig n ates either a production whieh avails itself of the assistance o f CQUcrele ca pital (raw materials, tools, machinery, etc.), or a production carried on for the behoof and under the control of private capitalist undertakers. The one is not by any means coincident with the other. I always use the ex pression in theJjormer of these two meanings. CHAP. II CAPITALIST PRODUCTION 23 science already earnestly, even acrimoniously engaged on the solution of questions which affect society to its depths, — questions which all the world knows, ponders, and discusses as the great “ problems of capital,” — is struck, as it were, by a second confusion of tongues, and becomes involved in an eurj - less wrangle as to what kind of thing it is that properly is called Capital ! Such a controversy at such a point is more than embarrassing ; it is a calamity ; and has been foimd so in the history of Political Economy. Almost every year there appears some new attempt to Settle the disputed conception, but, unfortunately, no authoritative result has as yet followed these attempts.^ On the contrary, many of them have only served to put more combatants in the field and furnish more matter to the dispute. I confess that, to me, the settlement of the real nroblems connected with the name of capital seems more important. and certainly is more attractive, than the cataloguing of con- troversies as to the proper usp.._Q£ JJre-wor(l All the same the fact remains that the confusion about the name has brought a great amount of confusion. into the matter ; and, again, it might be open to misconstruction — and not without reason, — if the author of a somewhat comprehensive work on capital were to pass over the discussion of what is certainly the most noisy, if not the most weighty controversy about capital. On these two accounts I feel obliged again to trend tbe h eated path of controversy , in the hope that impartial and sober inquiry into the matter hi dispute may succeed in ending it. ^ Looking back over the last few years only, I can recall, as coming in quick succession, the researches of Knies {Bos Geld, Berlin, 1873, pp. 1-56) ; of Cossa {La Nozione del Capitale, 1874, published in the Saggi di Econom/ia Politica, Milan, 1878) ; of Eicca-Salerno {Sulla Teoria del Capitale, Milan, 1877) ; of Umpfenbach {Bas Kapital in seiner Kulturhedeutung, Wiirzburg, 1879) ; of Kiihnast ( Ueher den rechtlichen Begriff des Kapitales in Beitrdge zur Erlduterung des BeiUschen Bechtes, 1884) ; of Supino {II Capitale nell’ Organismo Economico e nell' Econmnia Politica, Milan, 1886). Meanwhile we have the well-known works of Rodbertus and Marx, both bearing the title Bas Capital, and again the elaborate statements in the more comprehensive systems, particularly those of Wagner {Grundlegung, second edition, 1879, p. 36); of Eleinwachter (Schbnberg’s first edition, p. 170 ; second edition, p. 206); and of Cohn {Grundlegung der Nationalokonomie, Stuttgart, 1885, § 145-147). CHAPTEE III HISTORICAL DEVELOPMENT OF THE CONCEPTION It will be most convenient to open the discussion by a his- torical survey of the development of the conception.^ Ori^nallv the word Capital ( Capitale from Cayut) was used to sigpiify the Principal of a money loan {Capitalis pars cleliti) in opposition' to the Interest:' This usage, already fore- shadowed in the Greek formation Ket^aXatov, became firmly established in mediaeval^ Latin, and appears to have remained the prevailing one- for a -jvery long time, even pretty far down in the new era.^ Here, therefore, Capital meant the .same t hing a.a “ an interest-bearing sum of mon ey.” I In the meantime the disputes which had arisen over the I legitimacy or illegitimacy of loan interest brought about an I essential deepening and widening of the conception.®— Jt bad become apparent that, thp. intore.Ht- bpAring power of “ b arren ” money wn.s at bottom a borrowed one — borrowed from the productive power of things that the money could buy. Money only gave the exchange form — to a certain extent the out- ward garb — in which the interest-bearing things passed from hand to hand. The true “ stock ” or parent stem which bora interest was not money but the goods that were got fo r it. _ In these circumstances th e obvious course was so to ch ange the conception that, besides embracing the rep rese ntative 1 See on this subject Knies, Das Geld, Berlin, 1873, p. 6 (second edition, p. 24) ; Ricca-Salerno, Sulla Teoria del Capitale, 1877, chap. ii. ; and Schonberg’s Handbuch, second edition, vol. i. p. 206. “ The English word “Cattle,” as Knies (p. 7) has rightly remarked, has nothing in common derivatively with our conception. ^ Capital and Interest, book i. chaps, ii. and iii. CHAP, in TURGOT 25 thing, money, it would emlirace the represented thing goods. And, indeed, popular language seems to have made this change before science did. At least, as early as the year 1678, in a glossary of that year, besides the meaning of a sum of money there appears this further interpretation of the word capital, “ Capitale dicitur bomim orwne quod yossi detur.” ^ But science was not long behind in sanctioning the adoption of the con- ce ption . We find it substantially in Hume in his essay onl Interest, when he shows that the rate of interest altogether depends, not on the amount of money, but on the amount of riches or stocks available ; the only thing wanting is that he should have formally callecT these riches or stocks “ real _ capitals.’* This formal chan.o~e was finally made by Turgot : “ Whoever,” he says in his Reflexions sur la Formation et la Distribution dcs Richesses, “ gets possession of more goods in aJ year than he requires to use, can lay past the surplus, and accumulate it. These accumulated goods are what people call Capital. . . . It is absolutely the same whether this sum of goods, or this Capital, consists of a mass of metal, or of othe r t hings , since money represents every kind of goods, just as, on the other side, all other kinds of goods represent money.” Thus Turgot gave the second reading m historical succession to the conception of capital It was very soon superseded by a third . Bor when Turgot designated all saved goods mdiscrimihately as Capital, he seemed to have gone too far in broadening the conception. To replace the word “ money ” in the definition by the word “ goods ” only reflected, indeed, the more thorough grasp which was now taken of the subject. But to give the name of Capital, without any further discriminatiorL to stocks of goods, was to give up . without sufficient reason, the second feature in the old conception,^ — the reference that napital i had to a cap&,bihty of yielding interest, to an acquisition or goods. To that extent Turgot’s conception of capital was only in part a development born of the time : in part it was an entirely new reading of the term ; a reading which, at the same time, exposed him to the charge that, without due cause, he had neglected the very suggestive ^ Glossarium of Dufresne du Cange, quoted by Umpfenbach, Das Kapital in seiner Kulturhedeutv/ng, Wlirzburg, 1879, p. 32. 26 DEVELOPMENT OF THE CONCEPTION BOOK I ditfereiices there are between goods and goods. It was no * less a man than Adam Smith who changed and rectified /lurgot’s definition. The “ saved ” stocks, he sa id, mu st be. / distinguished as containing two parts. ^ One portion is { destined for i mmediate consumption, and gives off no kind of income ; the other portion is destined to hriiig in a.n in come to its owner, and this part alone rightly bears the name of Capital. With this distinction, however, Adam Smith connected another consideration, which was destined to have very serious consequences on the development of the conception. He I remarked that his use of the term was applicable. - as__well ‘ to the case of individuals as to th at of a whole community^; I only, with this shifting of the standpoint, the group of things embraced by the conception was also somewhat changed, Tndi\dduals, that is to say, can make a gain, not only by the production of goods, but also by lending to other individuals for a consideration goods which are destined in themselves to immediate consumption, such as houses, masquerade dresses, furniture, etc. But the community, as a whole, cannot enrich itself otherwise than bv the product ion of new goods. Bor I tlie community, then, the conception of “ means of acquisi- tion ” coincides with the otherwise narrower conception of means of production .” In harmony with this the conception oi' capital, from the point of view of the cornmnnity, must Ije limited to a cmnplex of the means of production. It is worth our while to put more exactly before us the bearing of this insignificant remark — which, by the way, in Adam Smith is put more unpretentiously, and much less sharply, than in the abstract which I have given of his meaning. First of all, this- was the beginning of the uivision of t auital into two independent conce ptions — the conceptions afterwards distinguished as hTp.ti'nna.l fia pital and Individual Capital Or, to indicate the relation still more exactly, the ]jaren't'~cdnception of capital as a stock of goods yielding- income lived on under the designation of “ private capital,” l)ut, nnder the name of “national capital.” it sent outran (jffshoot which quickly grew t( independent importance. ; soon, i^eed, to greater importance than the parent conception ^ Wealth of Nations, book ii. chap. i. CHAP. Ill NATIONAI AND PRIVATE CAPITAL 27 itself. It was immediately recognised that a very notable i mportance as regards nroduction attached to that class of goods which people now began to call capital par e^celhnce : and this became the occasion of a great many profitable applications of the new conception to the theory of production. Thus we find the national conception in a short time taking its place as one of the chief fundamental conceptions of that theory, and enga^d in those very important problems that are now associated with its name. In the triad. Land. Labour, and Capital, we find the n ew nnnppptinn gi ving its name to one of the three great sources of wealth , or, as it was put later, to one of the three factors of production. But all the time, in virtue of the old parent conception — that known later as Private Capital — the term capital remained. I connected with the phenomenon- o f intere st, which belonged to I the theory of distribution or income. Thus, from that time onward appeared the peculiar phenomenon which was to be the source of so many errors and complications, that two series of fundamentally different phenomena and fundament- ally different problems were treated imder the same name. Capital, as National Capital, became the central figure of the weightiest'problems of Production : Pnvate riapit-al^ of fhc fuitdamregtaTly -dfstinct pro blem of Interest. In view of this it becomes of consequence to state clearly that Adam Smith’s two varieties of the coimeption of capital are, properly, two "~^tirel^' independent conceptions, resting substantially on quite different foundations, and only connected externally by a very loose bond. As chance, however, would have it, it was just this secondary and external relation that caused the name to be given to the younger conception, and brought about the. identity of name between the two. The centre of gravity of the conception of private capital, as has been poin ted out, lies in the acquisition of interest , in the chafacteristic of being a source of inGom~e~:' the'''cent're~6r gfavdtv of the~ conception of national capital, on the~7ifTierliajid. lies in nroduction. in the characteristic of "being a tool of produc- tion ; sttld the loose bond" that c/mnects th'em. 'is'^'the acci- dental circumstance that the goods of which men make use i q production are the same goods as are the source of profit and interest to a people considered as a whole, and are, therefore. 28 DEVELOPMENT OF THE CONCEPTION book i capital in the original sense. Now this latter reference to income gave the national conception of capital its-Jiame, b ut it was very far from giving it its living substansc This was fmmd so exclusively in the relation to prodnctimi that, in a short time, the formal definition of capital was based upon that relation alone. It was defined as a^omple.v 4)f “ produced means of production.” and such like, and in the / end it scarcely caused any misgiving when, on closer considera- tion, the produced means of production seemed never to be quite identical with those stocks which constitute the income- be aring capital of a people . For there can be no question that 'communities obtain income from consumption goods loaned to other countries against interest. When this ingongruity was expressly noted, and yet, notwithstanding, national capital was quietly defined as a complex of means of production, it (' amounted to a practical and emphatic recognition of the fact that people were interested in capital solely on account of its relations to production, and not at all on account of its accidental characteristic of being the source of interest to the community. To put it shortly : in National Capital the char - acteristic of being tlie national scairce of interest came to t^ front only for a moment, but this moment was long eno ugh-tn attach the name of “ capital ” to it. Scarcely was this done when the eentre of gravity was shifted, and placed in its relation to production, and since then National Capital has been looked on as an independent conception, substantially quite foreign to its namesake. Private Capital. Clearly as the historian of economic theory may now distinguish between these conceptions as developed, the dis- tinction was not seen at the time, nor for long afterwards^ With Adam Smith himself the whole matter lies, I might say, in embryo. Hi s ideas were so far from being fixed that he could occasionally ascribe to them meanings which were quite distinct from and did not at aU fit in with the fundamental conception. An instance of this i s-Jiis extension._Df_ .tlia national conception to aU sorts of personal proper ties , tabenta. etc., — which seem a little out of place as elements of a “ stock,” and which, like spirits rashly conjured, banished peace for many a long day from the theory of capital This, how- ever, is an episode of only secondary importanca The prin- CHAP. Ill NATIONAL AND PRIVATE CAPITAL 29 cipal point is that the followers of Adam Smith not only failed to get rid of the confusion in which he had left the conception of capital, but, on the contrary, positively put their seal to one of its worst mistakes. They did not notice that, in what Adam Smith and they themselves called “ capital.” there were two fundamentally distinct conceptions ; they considered the capital of which they spoke in the theory of production as iden tical with the capit al which bears interest. As we know, Adam Smith had already noticed' that there was a certain difference in the meanings usually given to the word capital, and that, for instance, rented houses, hired furniture, or masquerade dresses were capital in one sense and not in another, and his followers had not failed to loyally transmit the remark. But ob\dously they attached no importance to it, — what was the use of making a fuss about a distinction which referred only to a few hired fancy dinsses and such like ? — and held fast by their conceptmn of capital, tbp. far, tor of production being canital. the source of interest. And now one confusion resulted in another. Before, it was the conceptions that were mixed ; now, it was the phenomena and the problems. Capital produces, and it bears interest. Wha.f more natural than t o gay shortly ; — it bears int'^st' It produces . And thus, introduced’ and made possible "Sy the confusion in the concep- tion of capital, originated that naive and one-sided theor}' of the Productivity of capital which, from Say’s days to our own, has held, and still, in some measure, holds economic science iinder its baneful influences. The Socialist or semi- socialist writers of our time were the first to face in earnest the con- fusion of conceptions by distinguishing capital into “ pure economic capital,” and capital as a “ historico-legal category.” ^ This distinction, as we shall see, did not indeed hit the nail on the head ; but it was at least a distinction which, of necessity, finally distinguished between the obiect of the pro- duction problem and the object of the interest problem , and thus paved the way for an advance in the treatment of the stni viciously confused problems. But this is to anticipate the course of development : to resume the methodical narrative we must go back to Adam Smith. It maY be said that Adam Smith’s fundamental conception ’ Kodbertus, ; Wagner, Grundlegung, second edition, p. 39. 30 DEVELOPMENT OF THE CONCEPTION BOOK r wa s never afterwards quite neglected ; the relation n £-ca.pital to acquisition and to p roductioiL which iu opposition to Turgot he had again imported into the conception, has, in some form or other, been retained by all later writers . Qn the other liand, it very soon became manifest that, within the common funda- mental conception, there was a surprismg amount of latitude for different readings of it, and, as it chanced, there were certain circumstances which very much favoured the taking advantage of this latitude. First of all, economists fell heir not only to the fundamental conception, but to the seed of ambiguity which Adam Smith had planted in it. This seed now burst into full life. Almost everybody, entangled in the conf usian we liave pist described, thought that “ Capital ” mu st be defined by one, uniting conception . But the one party, and indeed theAhajority, thought more about the instruments of prdduc- tion, while the other thought more about the source of income ; and thus they attached to capital the characte ristics of two. ditferent conceptions. This was one fruitful cause of divergent definitions, but there was another still more fruitful Whether the theoretical conception of capital was made to include pro- ductive instruments only, or whether, more liberally, it was made to embrace acquisitive instruments as well, iu any case there are many different kinds b oth of proAup.tivp a.Tid of acq uisiti ve_ instruments . NoW, in proportion as economists discovered more similarities or more contrasts between the various groups / of goods which serve for production and for acquisition, ' they considered it appropriate to group together, under the conception which they called capital, sometimes aU. acquisitive or all productive instruments without exception, sometimes only a certain circle of the same. And this circle again, according to the tendencies of the writer, might be larger or smaller ; sometimes of moderate dimensions, and sometimes, again, very closely limited. It may be said, indeed, that of a.II, combina - tions and permutations which were logically and ma t hematicall y p.nnp.p.iva.blp., pcn nomirfl.] sh'pupp in thisi_r. ase was not spared one . Without attempting either to give a complete tale of these, or to keep to the chronological order, I shall shortly coUocate the more important of them. bTumerous writers define cap i tal as a group of “products. CHAP, in HERMANN, MENGER, KLEINWACHTER tha,t serve towards production.” or as ^rmips of “ p roduced means~~^‘~pro3u ctioi i.” This conception, which is expressly based on the relation of capital to production, excludes, on the one hand, land (as not produced) and, on the other hand, all goods that serve for immediate satisfaction of wants. This conception I have, followed in defining capital as a group of Intermediate Products . In so far as it is not so much an alteration as a more distinct formulation of Adam Smith’s (national) conception, I do not reckon it an independent variation. The variation which Tifrinnuri, however, has given must be considered an independent one, and is the fourth reiidiug in ar ithmetical or der gh-nn. to the. conception. He goes back to capital as the source of income, and makes this the object of his definition : Capital, he says, is “ every durable foundation of a utility iNutzund\ which has exchange value. ” ^ In opposi- fion to the”^IasF definition this one includes under the concep- tion of Capital all land, and besides embraces such consump- tion goods as are durable, like furniture, houses, etc., even if they are personally used by the owners. A fifth variation is given by Mcnger. He defines capital as ^. round two questions : How does capital originate ? and what ^ is the nature of its productive work ? The first question has to do with the theory of the formation or accumulation of capital ; the second, with the productive function of capital The reader who has waded with us through the dozen theories and dozen definitions of capital will scarcely be sur- prised at meeting a similar divergence of opinion on the ques- tion we have now to consider . Of course there is no dispute about the fact that capital is, in the highest degree, useful tc^ production. But I am much afraid that this is the only proposition on which our economists are quite agreed. So soon as the further question is asked : In what does this Y usefuhiess consist , or what character does the co-operation of capital in itself bear ? — agreement is at an end. One finds the utility of capital in putting labour in motion ; another,^ in saving or supplanting labour ; ^ a third, in performing! labour ; ® a fourth praises it as gi^dng man the mastery over the powers of nature ; ^ and a fifth, as enabling the labourer, to “ put an interval 1 letween the beginning and the end of an-i ^ Adam Smith, book ii. chap v. ^ Lauderdale, Enquiry, p. 161, passim. ® Lauderdale, ihid. So also J. B. Say, “11 faut, pour ainsi dire, que les capitaux travaillent de concert avec I’industrie” {TraiU, i. 3). ^ Strasburger, Hildebrand’s Jahrhiicher, vol. xvii. (1871), p. 325 ; and Carey. 76 INTRODUCTORY BOOK II enterprise.” ^ Some, like Lauderdale, see in it an independ- ent, original factor of production along with land and labour ; others, like Gide, call it an independent but still merely derivative factor. Kleinwachter looks on it simply as a “ condition ” ; Carey, again, as an “ instrument ” or “ tool ” of production. Indeed, our theorists cannot even agree as to the wav in which that useful auxiliary of p roduction comes into existence. If we ask the question concretely : How is a plane, or a plough, or a steam-engine made ? — they would probably be able, with perfect certainty, to give minute information as to how those concrete portions of capital come into existence. But whenever they have to generalise what they have observed, they divide into hostile camps. Capital originates in savings says one ; no. says another, it must be produced ; while a third proclaims that it originates in the two together. It is a much greater cause for wonder that economists came to no agreement m these and similar questions than that they remained apart in their theories of interest. The task here was quite different, and essentially easier. Tu the iutpresf, theory the difficulty is to give the proper explanation of facts which are really much entangled, while here there is almost nothing to do but to describe the facts correctly ; and facts, moreover, with which everybody is quite familiar. As we have said, every one knows how a plane or a steam-engine comes into existence. Similarly every one has a sufficiently exact idea what and how a plane, a machine, a plough, a raw material, does in production. It was only necessary to leave out everything pecuhar in those cases, and to describe in appro priate words everything universal and typical in them. and the theory of the formation and function of capital would mhnost have been written. 'C The reason why economists failed in this simple task was that they did not allow the facts to speak fo r th emselves.^ Instead of simply describing them as they were, explanations were read into them and added to them ; one feature was pushed into the foreground, another kept in the background, a third was quite overlooked, while perhaps a fourth was entirely absent, but was read into them. When every man had thus imported his own particular views bodily into the 1 Jevous, Theory of Political Economy, second edition, 1879, p. 243. CHAP. I INTRODUCTORY 77 facts, it was, of course, no wonder that everybody got some- thing different out of them. To my mind the most important duty of the theorist in such a case is to avoid the faults we have just condemned. To make certain of this we shall make a clear distinction, even in outward form, between the statement of the facts and the. interpretation of them . The next chapter, therefore, will delineate and describe the process of capitalist production . When a solid basis of fact has thus been obtained, the inter- pretation and construction will follow in the chapters on the productive fimction of capital, and- on the theory of the forma- tion of capital.^ ^ Tn fipoTinniic literature the cleare.st views as to the nature of ca]ntalist pro- duction are, in my opinion, to be found in Kodbertus. Jevoiis. and Q aT-l Monjjgr The works of Rodbertus, where they are not directly disfigured by the influences of his one-sided Socialist standpoint, are of quite classical accuracy and clearness. Unfortunately there are certain features which very sensibly mar what he has said. This is true in particular of his omission to notice the share which the valuable natural powers take in production, and the influence of time — two things which, obviously, could not easily be fitted into the “exploitation” theory he maintained so vigorously, and so were suppressed. We shall see this more fully later on. Carl Monger, again, by his arrangement of goods according to “rank” {Orundsatze, p. 7), and his statement of the laws which connect together goods of various ranks, has given at once a brilliant proof of his clear insight into the developed phenomena of production, and an invaluable tool to the hands of succeeding investigators. CHAPTER II CAPITALIST PRODUCTION We have already sketched, in its most general outlines, the process of capitalist production^ There are certain features of it which now require more exact treatment. I shall briefly recapitulate, interpolating what remains to be said as we go I along. ^ All human production aims at the obtaininp of goods for consumption. These consumption goods are dependent for their existence on physical conditions, and are subject to natural laws. To obtain them, as we have seen, we must seek to bring about such combinations of active forces as will result in the desired object. Thus we get a product which has come into existence under natural law and continues to exist under natural law. Now look a httle more closely at t he nature of the power which man can employ towards these I productive combinations . It is made up of two componen ts very dissimilar in amount — ^rst. an enormous -mass of powers which the natural world exerts sp ontaneously year out year in ; and second, the much more limited natural pow ers which reside in the hu man organism. The natural world, in midst of which man lives, is endowed with a vast number of forces which are never for a moment idle. Gra^’itation holds this ball of earth together ; keeps all things fast to its surface ; makes the rain fall to earth, and rolls streams and rivers to the sea ; governs the ebb and flood of the tides ; works unceasingly at every point of the earth’s crust as stress, weight, pressure. The -sun sends our earth light and heat, and thereby develops an ^ Book i, chap. ii. CHAP, II THE SOLE TECHNICAL FACTORS 79 infinity of mechanical and chemical procfesses, of which vegeta»- tion particularly attracts our a,ttcntinTi. both by its mysterious magic and by its enormous importance for the human race. Uncounted and countless again are the molecular, electric, and chemical effects and counter -effects which every atom of matter exerts without intermission on its neighbours. The, total of those energies which nature pours forth in ceaseless strenm . without help from man, we may look upon as one branch of the productive endowment of humanity ; and this extremely valuable branch we shall c all man’ s natural. endow - ment . It is an infinite treasure-house from which the pro- dueiug man may draw as much as he wiU and can. As yet ^/ it is only the very smallest part of thi.s treasure that has been touched . As yet by far the greater portion, of the energies of nature pass away in combinations which, from the human teleological standpoint, seem useless or even haraiful. The resistless rise and fall of the tide, the rush of rivers and waterfalls, the atmospheric movements, the giant forces of electricity, magnetism, and gravitation slumbering iu our earth, are powers turned to human account only to a very small extent. Others again, such as the vegetative powers of land, have been utihsed to a greater, but .still very far from complete extent . The steady advancement in agricultural science not only leads us to expect a constantly increasing amoimt of utility from the land, but makes us suspect that the possibihty of such advance is stiU far from being exhausted. Now, as we have seen, the way in which we get command of these natural treasures is through the other branch of oru productive endowment, our own personal powers. We put forth our labour in ail kinds of wise combinations with natural processes. Thus all that we get in production is the reault of two, and only two, elementary productive powers — Nature and Labour. This is one of the most certain ideas in the theory of production. Man finds ready to hand an abundance of natural processes, and allies his own powers with them. MTiat nature by herself does, and what man does along with her — these form the double source from which all our goods come, and the only source from which they can come. There is no place for any third primary source. ^ These two elements, then, jechnically do everything in the 80 CAPITALIST PRODUCTION BOOK II work of production. But, economically, a further and very suggestive limitation must be drawn. Of the vast natural endowment which serves as foundation for man’s productive combinations, one portion particularly claims the interest of economics, and that is, those useful things offered by nature only in limited amoun t. In nature, indeed, there is no lack either of materials or powers ; carbon and nitrogen, oxygen and hydrogen — generally speaking, most of the “elements” — are per se not more scarce than are electrical, magnetic, chemical, and gravitation forces. But certain spontaneous combina- tions of these elements that are peculiarly well adapted to human want may be, relatively, scarce ; such, for example, as useful plants and minerals, water for driving power, fertile land, etc. These limited gifts and energies of the natural world. obtain for us a peculiar economic importance . It would be foob'.sh not to economise them. Technical elements of produc- tion which we may have in any quantity, like atmospheric air or water or sunlight, we may employ or waste as we please without suffering loss in our productive returns. But the limited technical elements must be treated with consideration, must be saved, must be fully utilised. In a word, within the technical natural endowment, as a wider circle, they form the specifically economic natural endowment of man. Since aU, or at least almost all, limited gifts and energies of nature are con- nected with land, we may, without much danger, take Land. with its activities or uses, as the representative of this eco nomic natural endowment. ^ To the uses of land the exertions of labeur form the counterpart. Labour has ahnost entirely an economical char- acter. This is due partly to the fact that physical strength is given us in such scanty measure, as compared with the very extensive claims put forward by human needs, that even the most assiduous exertions of labour power cannot fully satisfy our desire for goods, not to sj^eak of supplying them in super- fluity ; partly to the fact that the exercise of our powers is usually attended by the painful feeling of distress and fatig pn^ 1 Wliere population is scanty, of course, it is possible that land, or at least certain of the uses of land, such as the growing of timber, may be free goods, as obtainable in any quantity. But in modern communities, to which naturally I refer by preference in this statement, the uses of land — with the exception of waste land or desert — are entirely economie goods. CHAP. II THE ECONOMIC FACTORS 81 — at least when carried beyond a certain point/ — and the feeling warns us to economise our labour. Nature and Labour are, then, the technical elements of production ; JTses of T.and and Labour are the economic elements . Tliese latter are the talents which the producing man puts out at usury with nature, with her great fruitful soil and infinite store of force. They are the enj y powers that re.ipuire ecnnnmic, treatment, inasmuch as the co-operation of the free natural powers, which, technically, is also indispensable, is given without question and without cost. It is only the man who has command over the, requisite, uses of land and services of labour who receives the desired economic nroduct : the man who has not these must do without the product ; the man who owns a double allowance or a half allowance of them will — if the technique of production remain the same — receive double or half the product. In production, therefore, they are the only powers with which the economic community has any concern, and with which it has to reckon. In short, land and labour — or, more accurately, uses of land and services of labour — are the primary economic productive powers.^ Now in what way does man use thes e original productive powers, ? In answering this question we turn back for a little into familiar paths. To construct goods for human consumption out of these productive elements man may take one of two ways. He may combine the economical productive powers with one another, — or with activities of free natural powers, — in such a way that the desired good immediately emerges as result nf thp romhinatinn ; ^ On the common experience that “ a3 labour is prolonged the effort becomes. as a gen eral rule, more and more T)aiDfnl, ” see Jevons, Theory of Political Economy, second edition, p. 185 ; and Gossen, EntwicMung der Gesetze des mensch- lichen Verkehrs, 1854. ^ This is the state of the. case, as I believe, expressed with perfect clearness in the facts, and this i.s what Rodbertus profoundly misunderstood when bn maintained, and repeated with emphasis, that labour is the sole original power. with which human economy has anything to do. and drew from that the conclu- sion that all goods, economically, are to be conceived of as products of labour alone {Zur Erkemvlniss unserer stoats, Zvstdnde, theorem i. ; Zur Erkldrung, second edition, p. 160 ; Zur Beleuchtung, p. 69). If to-day we allow a fruitful field to lie fallow, or a mine or water power to remain unexploited if, in short , we do not act economically -with valuable uses of land, we act as directly against cur economic wellbeing as when we throw away labour uneconomicallv,. G 82 CAPITALIST PRODUCTION BOOK. II as when he gathers shellfish on the shore. Or he may take a. roiindahout way, and, with the element at his command, mar make, first, another good, and then, with its assistance, the good he wishes ; as, for instance, when he makes a boat and net and takes to fishing systematically. We already know that the former method is identical with what the Germans call Tcapitallos production, the latter with capitalist production ; and that the intermediate products, which come into existence in the course of the indirect methods, represent economic social capital. The adoption of capitalist methods of production is followed by two consequences, erpially cha,racteristic and significant. One is an advantage, the other a disadvantage . The advan- tage we have already looked at ; it consists in the greater Jechnical productiveness o f those methods. With an equal expenditure of p'rimary productive powers ^ (that is to say, labour and valuable natural powers) more or better goods can be produced by a wisely chosen capitalist process than could be by direct unassisted production. This proposition, which is quite convincingly accredited by daily experience, we illus- trated and tried to explain in the second chapter of Book I. by a number of examples. We found the explanation to be that, when roundabout methods are skilfully chosen, new allies are obtained from the immense stores of natural powers, and their activity is enlisted in the_ JWQrk jrf-^roduetion. It is this well-known fact that is usually indicated by the term “ productivity of capital.” This name, however, imports into the facts a particular interpretation, the correctness of which has yet to be examined in the next chapter. j The disad vp.nta.gp. coimpp.tp.rl with the, ca.pita.b'st Tnethod of •production is its sacrifice of time, The roundabout ways of capital are fruitful but long ; they procure us more or better consumption goods, but only at a later period of time. This proposition, no less than the former, is one of the ground pillars of the theory of capital. We shall see later on that the very function of ca pita l., as a means of appropriatiorL-oc,. so urce of interest, to a great extent rests upon it . . I must, 1 “ Primary productive powers” is the move corrset expression, which we mn.st BOW p.mpiny instead of ths partial expr fl.‘^sinn “ ia'hniir-” used by me in the second chapter of Book I. in order to avoid tedious explanations. CHAP. 11 THE SACRIFICE OF TIME 83 therefore, s^uard it against any- iiiisnndprstanrlitig by the .hwa following remarks. In the first place, it maY very well happen.in an exceptional case, that an indirect method of production is not only better bnt speedier . A man wishing to gather apples from a high tree will evidently attain his purpose sooner by first cutting a stick from another tree, and nsmg it to knock dov/n the apples, than by climbing the tree and trying to break off the apples one by one with his hand. But this is not the rule. In the overwhelming majority of cases we must tread the roundabout ways of capitalist production under technical conditions of such a nature that we have to wait, and often for a very long time, before we get the ripe final product. Instead of giving examples which must occur of themselves to every reader, I would rather draw attention to the fact that, in the loss of time which is, as a rule, bound up with the capitalist process, lies the sole gimmtLaf that much-talked-of and much-deplored dependence of labourer on capitahst . If capitalist production led as quickly from the hand to the mouth as unskilled direct production does, there would be nothing to hinder the workers carrying on sucli roundabout methods from beginning to end on their own account. They would still be dependent on the landowners, who could prevent them from access to the land which at the outset they require, bnt they would not be dependeot on the capitahsts. It is only because the labourers cannot wait tih the roundabout process — which begins with the obtaining of raw materials and making of tools — delivers up its products ready for consumption, that, t hey become economically dp.pp.nd pnt on thp. rapitalists who already hold in their possession what we have called “ inter- mediate products.” ^ ^ It is very characteristic that Eodbertus, when describing the economical effects of adopting roundabout ways of production, chooses his illustration pst ou t-of that minority of cases where the rounda bout wav i s the quicke r {Das Kapital, p. 236). The consequence is that, on this and other occasions, he leaves in the shade all the economical elements which form the basis of the phenomenon of interest — and of these the most notable is the loss of time connected with the canying through of productive methods — and, taking a very one-sided view, lays the origin of rent at the door of the existing circumstances of private right (e.g. p. 310). But private rights in capital would not , by t hemselves, do any harm to the labourers, and it would be very easy for them to avoid the toll-bars which the capitalists have erected, if the fatal lapse of time between beginning and end of the lengthy capitalist process did not make it impossible for labourers to adopt similar processes on their own account. 84 CAPITALIST PRODUCTION BOOK II Again — though this scarcely needs pointing out — when we speak of capitalist production taking time, it is not relevant to raise the objection that, with a piece o_f „ viade, say a tool, a definite than it could be without the assistance of capital ; that, for instance, a tailor takes three days to sew a coat by hand, and one day to do it with a sewing-machine. For it is clear that the machine sewing forms only one part, and indeed the smaller part, of the capitalist process ; the principal part falls to the making of the sewing-machine, and the total process lasts considerably longer than three days. Thus far we have considered capitalist production as an undivided whole, and have contrasted it with production carried on entirely without capital But here we are reminded of a fact that has to be reckoned with, viz. that in capitalist production th^ rp. arp stag es and degrees ; to speak accurately, there are innumerable degrees of “ Capitalism.” In the making of a consumption good the possible roundabout methods are of very varying length. We may make intermediate products from which the final good will be obtained in a month, or a year, or ten years, or a hundred years. The question now is. what influence such differences of degree havft on product . On the whole it may be said that not only are the first steps more productive, but that every lengthening of the roundabout process is accompanied by a further increase in the technical result ; as the process, however, is lengthened the amount of product, as a rule, increases in a smaller proportion. This proposition also is based on experi ence.- and on ly_Qii experience . What it says must be simply taken as a fact of the technique of production. The reader, moreover, will easily be able to check its accuracy if he follows in thought the steps which lead to the production of any consumption good. For instance, firewood can be got quite directly so long as we limit ourselves to the gathering of dry branches or breaking off of weak twigs. We take a short roundabout path in making and using a stone axe. A longer process involves digging ore out of the ground, getting the fuel and necessary tools, and smelting iron out of the ore, working up the iron into steel. CHAP. II INCREASE OF PRODUCT 85 and finally turning out a finished steel axe. Beginning farther back, we may construct cunning machinery for mining and raising the ore, elaborate blast furnaces for smelting it, special machines for making and sharpening the axe. Going farther back still, we may put up engineering shops and machinery for constructing each kind of appliance, and so on. It will scarcely be doubted that every additional step increases the productiveness of the total process ; that is, results in the obtainmg of the unit, say the cubic foot of wood, at a smaller total expenditure of labour (mediate and immediate). But just as little will it be doubted that the first two pro- ductive methods, the use of the stone axe and then of the steel axe, must have caused a much greater revolution in the productiveness of woodcutting than the later improvements, although, absolutely, these may be by no means inconsiderable. If necessary, this may easily be proved to demonstra - tion by a little calculation . Assume, for example, that a labourer working with his hands can cut in one day 2 cubic feet of wood, and working with a stone axe, which has taken three days to make, can cut 1 0 cubic feet : the three days’ capitalist process is rewarded by a surplus return of 8 cubic feet per labour day. Now possibly the doubling of the process — say that the more careful fashioning of the stone axe takes six days — may also double the surplus return, and give 16 cubic feet. But it is scarcely likely that trebling the roundabout process can treble the surplus return. And it is quite certain that extending the roundabout process a thou- sandfold — say by sinking of pits, from which the ore for the axe may be got after years have elapsed — will not be able tg increase the surplus return a thousandfold- Otherwise we should have the all but inconceivable possibility that a worker in one day could cut 8000 feet of wood! From some one point — probably a point not far off^ — the sirrplus, though still increasing, will increase in a less ratio than the production period. Of course in such cases no definite figure can be named, either for the point from which the productiveness of further extensions of the process begins to decrease, or, speaking generally, for the amount of surplus result connected with any definite length of process. These data vary according to the 86 CAPITALIST PRODUCTION BOOK II technical circumstances of each branch of production, and at each stage of productive skill. Every new invention alters. thenL. The discovery of gunpowder, for example, opened up at a flash the possibility, which did not exist the moment before, of increasing the productiveness of the chase by perhaps one half, and the productiveness of stone-quarrying by perhaps a hundredfold.^ We may, however, with sufficient confidence repeat the proposition already formulated, that every exten - sion of the -production proces s (so far as it is wisely chosen, of course) leads, generaUy speaking, to some surplus result. It may be confidently maintained that there is not one branch of production the returns of which may not be considerably increased in this way, as against the method of production prevailing at the time ; and that without any new invention, but simply by the intercalation of intermediate members long familiar to capitalist production, — whether it be by the adoption of a steam motor, or an apt transmitter, or some ingenious gearing, blast, lever, regulator, or the like. How far behind, indeed, in capitalist equipment are the tnost of our agricultural and industrial businesses compared with the most advanced typical businesses ! And certainly these latter are no less far behind an ideally perfect equipment.^ The fact that the prolongation of production processes leads to surplus results, and the fact that these surplus results ' Inventions, so-called, generally mean the rlisnoverv of a new and moiR productive method of production. Frequently — probably in most cases — the new way is longer than the old, and in this case to utilise the invention requires the making of a great number of intermediate products, or, as it is usually expressed, a large investment of capital : e.g. in machinery, building of railways, and the like. But often a happy invention may lead to a better, and at the same time shorter, way of production, s uch as the manufacture of certain dye- stuffs from chemical instead of plant bodies. ' However elaborate the former may be, it is stUl certainly far more direct and speedy than a manufacture which has to wait on tedious processes of growth. ^ It may be asked here, by way of objection, why man does not fu ll y utilii^ the chances o ffe red him of increasing the technical res ult bv the tcclmical know- ledge heJhas at the tnoment . The common explanation runs — from want 0/ capital With the limited amount of capital at his disposal man can only utilise those chances of employment, among the infinite number of remunerative ones, wliich are most remunerative, and a great number of less, but still remunerative, employments must be passed over. This explanation is not quite exact , but it is at least right in the main contention. We may therefore be content with it until, in another connection, we can examine the matter with perfect accuracy. CHAP. II THUNEN'S LA IV 87 usually decrease from a certain point or)wa.rd.a, have long Lftp.n iiotipprl anH .q.pl-nnwIp.Hgp.rl in our science ; mostly, I must say, in another form, and one borrowed from the jargon of the Productivity Theory. It is many years smce Thiinen put them in the most impartial manner, and showed that, in the case of progressive increase of capital, the capital that comes last does lead to an increase in the product of labour. but in a constantly decreasing proportion. ^ On this founda- tion of fact he himself framed the well-known doctrine that the rate of interest adjusts itself to the productiveness of the last dose of capital applied in the least productive employment. and, in the wake of this doctrine, the facts were recognised and received in the widest circles.^ In harmony, however, - with the fashion of the time, these facts were forced into the special forms of presentation and terminology of the Pioductivity Theor}^, whereby the most vexatious mistakes and confusions shpped in along with them.® Lefore going further it seemed to me advisable here to try to restate the facts in their naked simplicity. It scarcely, perhaps, requires to be proved that the capital- ist production of consmnption goods, although carried out in roundabout ways and by many stages, does not , on that account, cease to exhibit an intimately connected and imitpr) work of production . The laliopr which produces the mter- mediate products — -the mediate laboig- . as we shall call it with Eodbertus ^ — ^ajid the labour which, out of and with the inter- mediate products, produces the desired good — the immerbate labour — both form- a part of the production of the consumution good. The production of timber is more than the labour of 1 Der isolirte Stoat, third edition, part ii. div. i. p. 97. See particularly the table on p. 101. * For instance by Soscher , Grundlagen, § 183 ; by Mangoldt, VolJcswirth- schaftslehre, 1868, p. 432 ; by Mithoff in Schonberg’s Handhich, second edition, p. 663, and by many others. Jevons independently adopted quite similar views. Theory of Political Economy, second edition, p. 277. ® In particular the “ physical” or “technical productivity^.” which is founded on these facts (that is, the circumstance that by the assistance of capital more products can be produced than without it), was confused with a “value pro- ductivity ” (that is, a pretended power of capital to produce more value than it itself posses.ses). See my CapiUd and Interm, pp. 112, 131. * Bos Kapital, p. 236. 88 CAPITALIST PRODUCTION BOOK II felling wood in the forest ; it embraces the labour of the smith who makes the axe, of the carpenter who cuts the haft, of the miner who raises the ore, of the iron workers and steel workers who prepare it, and so on. True, our modern divisinn of employment to outward appearance b reaks up the u nity of the process into a number of independent parts, but it is the theorist’s business to understand economic processes in their living connection, and he dare not, of course, let himself be deceived by appearances, but must reproduce in his own mind the real unity of the work of production thus obscured. The masterly manner in which Eodbertus has done this is one of his best services to economics. But this very consideration, essentially economic as it is, raises a doubt we must fairly meet. According to what has been said, the production period of a consumption good is, strictly speaking, to he reckoned from thp. moment nn whip.h tt ip firgf-, banri wq p laid to the making of its first inter - mediate right down to the completion of the good itselh In our times, when unassisted production has almost entirely disappeared, and one generation builds on the inter- mediate products laid down by earlier generations, the produc- tion period of almost any consumption good could, in any strict calculation, trace its beginning back to early centuries. The boy who cuts a stick with his knife is, strictly speak- ing, only continuing the work of the miner who, centuries ago, thrust the first spade into the ground to sink the shaft from which the ore was brought to make the blade. Of course the finished product of to-day owes a quite infinitesimal fraction — not worth calculation even if that were possible — to the firstlings of labour in these far-off centuries, and it would therefore give a, very false view of the degree of capitalism expended in the eiitting pt tbp if wp were to estimate it hv the absolute period of time intervening between the atom of labour first put forth and the completion of the work. It is more important and more correct to look at the period of time which elapses on the ^eraqe between the expenditure of the original productive powers, labour and uses of land, as successively emp oyed in any work, and the turning out of the finished consumption goods. Brnriiip.tion i.s ^ more or less capitalisti c according to the average remoteness o£ ^ CHAP. 11 THE AVERAGE PERIOD 89 the period at which the original productive powers exerted diu'ing the process are paid . Say, for example, that the pro- duction of a commodity costs in all a .hundred days of labour — for the sake of simplification we shall leave out the co-oper- ating uses of land — and that, of these hundred, one day was expended ten years before the completion of the work, another nine years, others respectively eight, seven, six, five, four, three, two, and one year, while the remaining ninety days were expended immediately before the completion. Then the first day of labour is paid ten years later, the second nine years later, the third eight years later, and so on, while the last ninety days are paid immediately. The calculation is as follows : — 10 + 9 + 8 + 74-6 + 5 + 44-3 + 2+1 55 loo ^ lOO' That is to say, on the average the hundred da, vs of l abour a.ra paid in about half a vea.r. Say that the prodiiction of another good were also to demand in all a hundred days of labour, likewise spent in the course of a tEn years’ period, but spread over it in such a way that twenty days’ work was expended ten years before, other twenty days’ work nine years before, five days’ work in each year from the eighth to the first successively, wliile the last twenty days were spent immediately before the completion of the work, t he average would cnme out quite differently and much higher : — 200 + 180 + 40 + 35 + 30 + 25 + 20 + 15 + 10 + 5 560 100 ~ 100 ’ or more than five and a h alf year_s^ It is highly probable, moreover, that in both cases some fraction of a day’s work will have been spent centuries before, but such a small element will scarcely influence the average, and may in most cases be simply neglected.^ 1 The first of the above schemes corresponds to the case of a production where one single tool is employed, and where the total process extends over ten years — for instance, the making and using of an axe of Bessemer steel. The second scheme, again, corresponds to a production where, besides the axe, a number of other capitalistic tools, auxiliary mechanism, and materials, are employed, the existence of which, however, does not date from farther back than ten years. This compari.son clearly shows how, without incieasing the absolute length of the nroduction period, the degree of capitalism may be very considerably. 90 CAPITALIST PRODUCTION BCOK 11 Where I have spoken above of extension or prolongation of the roundabout process of production, and of degrees of capitalism, I must be understood in the sense just explained. ;^ The length or the shortness of the process, its extension or its. curtailment, is not to be measured by the absolute duration of tJip. p eriod that lies between the expenditure of the first atom of labour and the last — otherwise the cracking of nuts with a liammer which might chance to be made of iron brought from a mine opened by the Eomans would perhaps be the most “ capitalistic ” kind of production. Nor is it to be measured the number of independent intermediat e me mbers which the production process embraces — otherwise when, by means of the three intermediate products, twig, hme, and bird-lime, a boy catches birds on the same day as he commences making these three forms of capital, his bird-catching would be more capitalistic than the far-back labour of the miner who devotes years to the sinking of a shaft. KBut it is to be measured bv the average period which lies between the successive expendi- ture in labour and uses of land and the obtaining of the final good. It is only in methods' of production where the expendi- ture in original powers is distributed equally over the whole production period that the absolute length of the process affords at the same time the proper measure for the degree of capitalism.^ Let us now apply what has been said of siugle acts of pro- duction to the circumstances of an entire commmiity . Every year a community comes anew into possession, and gets the disposal of a certain quantum of original productive powers, the powers represented by its labour and land. The farther away its production is from capitalist production — there is no production, of course, absolutely without capital — the greater increased ; all that is necessary is to alter the proportion between the number of early workers and that of the finishing ones. Whether it is ten workers employed in the final stage against one worker employed ten years before, or one worker in the final stage against ten workers ten years before, in either case the, total produ ction process extends over a period of ten years . But in tlie former case the finishing workers would be very sparingly provided with tools, machines, etc. ; in the latter case they would be very amply provided. The latter. -o.C ^ourse, would be far and away the more capitalistic of the two, 1 See the interesting calculation and graphic statement of the amount of investment of capital in Jevons’s Theory of PoUtical Economy, second edition, p. 249. CHAP. II SUMMARY 91 will be the -propo riinTi nf t.hp ypar’s prnfliip. tive powers that is changed into consumption goods during the same year . The more capitalistic the production is, the smaller will be the proportion of the year’s productive powers consumed within the year, and the greater the proportion invested in inter- mediate products that will come to maturity as finished goods only in future years, ^nd again, the higher the degree of capitalism is. the more remote will he thp . pprind at. wliirh these intermediate products mature. Thus a community pro- ducing from hand to mouth consumes in each year the fruits of the productive powers of that same year. A capitalist community consumes only to a small extent the fruits of productive powers of the present year, and to a great extent the fruits of the productive powers of past years, while it again is making intermediate products for the service of future years. And the higher the degree of capitalism , the foiiher — h ack in the past, on the average, are the years whose productive powp.r.ci it, c.nn.cimnes^ and the farther on in the future are the periods for which it provides And now, I trust, the following proposition, which puts together the chief features of the capitalist production process, will be understood beyond possibility of mistake. All consumption goods which man produces come into j existence through a co-operation of human power with natural (, powers, which latter are partly economic, partly free. ^ means of these primary productive powers man may make the - consumption goods he desirps , piT.hp.r inimpdiately, or through. the medium of intermediate products c alled Capita l.^ The latter method demands a sacrifice of time, but it has an advantage in s the quantity of product, and this advantage, although perhaps ' in decreasing ratio, is associated with every prolongation of the roundabout way of production. CHAPTEE III THE FUNCTION OF CAPITAL IN PRODUCTION After what has been said in the preceding chapter it should not be difficult accurately to indicate the role which capital plays in economic production. Capital has, first, a symptomatic importance. Its presence is always the symptom of a profitable roundabout production . I say, deliberately, “symptom” and not “ cause ” or “ condition ” of profitable methods of production ; for, as a fact, its presence is rather the result than the cause. If men to-day are fishing with boats and nets instead of picking the fish out of pools on the shore with their hands, it cannot be said that they have adopted those more fruitful methods because they possess boats and nets. Obviously they possess bo ata mnd nets because they ha ve adopted these meth ods. They must have already chosen the roundabout way of production before these goods, speaking generally, come into existence.’^ This, however, does not exhaust the importance of capital. At is. secondly . — and herein lies the chief point of its productive efficiency, — an effective intermediate cause of the consummation of th is profi table roundab out, process. ^ Every piece of capital is, to a certain 'extent, a store of useful natural powers, the working of which helps to bring to a successful issue the roundabout process in the course of which the piece of capital has come into existence. I say “ intermediate cause,” not ^ It would be somewhat different if we were to adopt the other conception of capital, and understand by it, not intermediate products only, but the entire national siibsistence fund, which would therefore include the labourers’ subsist- ence. In that case, but only in that case, nna tnip'ht sav that, rapiffll wns cause of these profitable ro undabout ways of production being adopted . CHAP, ni AS TOOL AND CA USE 93 “ cause.” Capital gives no independent impulse ; it_ only transmits an impul.se given hy the nrigiual p roducti ve powers. just as one billiard baU. transmits motion to another. The function of capital, indeed, has been called the “ prianninp- of natural powers.” The expression is quite appropriate, and very happy. Only it must never be forgotten that this attribute belongs to the entire capitahst process, not only to the “descending branch,” generally called the use of the capital, but also to the “ascending branch,” in which the capital itself is first made. Man does not first prison natural powers by means of capi tol : capital itself originates as the_ result— of-a previous imprisonment — by the original productive powers that are at man’s own bidding — of certain comphant natural powers. Taken all in all, among the many predicates which economists have given to capital, the one that best fits this aspect of the case is that of “ Tool of Production.” But, thirdly, capital is also the indirect cause of other profitahlft rnn rid about ways of production being e ntered oa — other, that is, than those in the course of which it itself has come into existence. When a people possesses much capital not only can it successfully complete those processes in the course of which the capital presently existing has come into beiug, but it can also adopt other and new methods. For the stock of capital in hand (which, essentially, is nothing else than an aggregate of consumption goods in a transition state throws off every year a certain quantity of its constituents , which have just completed their transition state and becoma finished good^ and places them at the disposal of the current economic period for purposes of immediate consumption. In this way t he greater the stock of capital, the larger is the share taken bv the productive powers of the past in providing- means of consumption for the present, and the less are the new productive powers of the present drawn on for the present. Thus a larger proportion of these current powers is free for the service of the future, that is, for investment in more or less far-reaching processes of production. If a community is so poor that the consumption goods ^ Schaffle very finely speaks of capital a-s “Consumption wealth as it were in, the stalk, when it is still only swelling bud and ripening fruit (Schbnberg’s Handhijch-, second edition, vol, i. p. 208). 94 FUNCTION OF CAPITAL IN PRODUCTION BOOK II maturing out of capitalist intermediate products in any year, say in 1888, scarcely cover ^ of that year’s wants, then the remaining must be provided out of the labour and uses of land of 1888, and only a fractional part of the productive powers of that year remains over to initiate methods of pro- duction that will turn out consumption goods in the years following. If. on the other hand, the past has accumu- lated a treasure of intermediate produ cts — raw materials, tools, machines, factories, workshops, etc.^ — so great that their successive maturing covers the consumption demand of the year 1888 to the extent of that of 1889 to the extent of 3 ^^, that of 1890 to the extent of and so on, then only one half of the productive powers of 1888 wi ll _be clai med to make up the current wants, w hile the entire other half may be spent unhesitatingly in producing intermediate products which will come to maturity, as consumption goods, only in later years — all the later in proportion as the next year’s wants are already covered by accumulations of capital in the past. V In this sense, but only in this sense, is it correct to say tha t man must already have capital before h e can enter on roundabout wavs of prod uct ion ; that want of capital prevents man taking advantage of far-reaching and profitable methods of production, such as the laying of railways, building of canals, irrigation schemes, altering of river-beds, and so on. It would be quite incorrect to understand this proposition as meaning that a community must have, finished and ready to hand, that kind of concrete capital with which the methods of production in question are carried out, or even the concrete capital (raw materials, tools, etc.) out of which are made the forms of capital first needed. All that is required is, that the com- munity possess so much capital, whatever its shape, as will cover — while it is being gradually changed into consumption goods — the demand of the present and near future for such goods sufficiently to leave the current production powers free for investment in intermediate products- of the kind required. It would be essent ially m ore cor rect to sa x that_we- re quire consurnftion goods before we can en ter upoiLrpundabimt_ways_ o f production, whether these be in the form of finished stocks of goods ready for consumption, or in the transition form of intermediate products. CHAP, in NOT AN INDEPENDENT FACTOR 95 Lastly, we can now answer, easily and categorically, the much-disputed (T[up,stinn. w hpf.hpT- any indepeudent productive power is inherent in capital : or, to put the question in its usual form, whether capital is a third and independent “ factor in production ” alongside of labour and nature ? The answer must be a most distinci negative. This seeing to me the only conclusion any one can come to, provided he makes clear to himself the sense in which this question is put, and must be put if it is worth the trouble of putting at all. And this sense is a very emphatic one. The following analogy will make it perfectly clear. A man throws a stone at another man and kills him . Has the stone killed the ma n ? . If the question is put without laying any special emphasis it may be answered without hesitation in the affirmative. But how if the murderer, on his trial, were to defend himself by saying that it was not he but the stone that had killed the man ? Taking the words in this sense should we still say that the stone had killed the man, and acquit the murderer ? How it is with an emphasis like this that economists inquire as to the independent productivity of capital. The question comes up in the course of the inquiry concerning the elements which constitute our material goods. A similar interest to that which the chemist has in the analysis of com- pound bodies leads the economist to analyse the multiform transition stages of material goods, to trace them ban k. -to their source , and to resolve the thousandfold instruments and auxiliaries of production, to which, directly or indirectly, they owe their existence, into the simple fundamental powers from the co-operation of which everythiug proceeds. In this con- nection the doubt arises whether capital is an independent productive power or not. The whole spirit of the inquiry allows only one meaning to be given to the question, and the emphasis is very marked. AVe are not asking about dependent intermediate causes, but about ultim ate in depeudeut elemeuts.' The question is not whether capital plays a part in the bring- ing about of a productive result — such as the stone does in the killing of the man — but whether, granted the productive result, some part of it is due to capital so entirely and pecu- liarly that it simply cannot be put to the credit of the two 96 FUNCTION OF CAPITAL IN PRODUCTION book ii other recognised elementary factors, nature and labour. Now can this question be answered in the affirmative ? Emphatically it can not. Capital is an intermediate ^product of nature and labour, nothing more . Its own origin, its existence, its subsequent action, are nothing but stages in the continuous working of the true elements, nature and labour. They and they alone do everything from beginning to end in bringing consumption goods into existence. The only distinction is that sometimes they do it all at once, sometimes by several stages. In the latter case the completion of each stage is marked outwardly by the appearance of a fore-product or intermediate product, and capital has emerged. But, let me ask, is a thing any the less the work of its author- that it is not prod uced- -all, at once, but in instalments? If to-day, by allying my labour with natural powers, I make bricks out of clay, and to-morrow, by allying my labour with natural gifts, I obtain lime, and the day after that make mortar and so construct a wall, can it be said of any part of the wall that I and the natural powers have not made it ? Again, before a lengthy piece of work, such as the building of a house, is quite finished, it naturally must be at one time a fourth finished, then a half finished, then three-quarters finished. What now would be said if one were to describe these inevitable stages of the work as independent requisites of house-building, and maintain that, for t h e building of a house, we require, besides building materials and labour, a quartPT--fini.cthftd house , a half-finished house, a three-quarters- finished house ? In form perhaps it is less striking, but in effect it is not a whit more correct, to elevate those inter- mediate steps in the progress of the work, which outwardly take the shape of capital, into an independent agent of production by the side of nature and labour. This would never have been called in question had it not been that the introduction of division of vocations and labour had split up the united work of producing consumption goods into a number of apparently independent acts of production. It was this that made economists forget to look at it as a whole, and made them, with singular modesty, bow before the dependent intermediate creations of previous human activity as if they represented an independent power. But CHAP. Ill NOT AN INDEPENDENT FACTOR 97 even as it was, it was scarcely possible for any acute theorist to make this confusion if another circumstance had not conspired to assist it. That was th e aenepted parallelism between factors of production and branches of income, and the awkwardness economists feared to encounter in the explanation and justification of interest if they had to refuse recognition to capital as an independent factor of production. All natural income, it was taught, is based on participation in the production of goods. The various branches of income are nothing else than the forms in which the different contributories to production are paid. Kent of land, is the payment for the factor of nature, wage the payment for the factor of labour, and interest — well, interest appeared to have no substantial foundation if it also could not be inter- preted as a payment for a third independent factor of produc- tioiu It did not seem to be explained theoretically, nor — what indeed might be more serious to the theorists in question — to be justified practically. Thus it was that many a learned thinker was driven into a corner, and preferred rather to shut an eye to clear facts than to sacrifice the independent pro- ductivity of capital, and with it the welcome basis for the current theory of interest. Facts certainly spoke with perfect distinctness. It was impossible to deny that capital is no element in the proper sense of the word, inasmuch as it itself springs from the co-operation of nature and labour. Not only so, but by a siugular irony of fate this had to be expressly proved — as it had been by Adam Smith before them — by those very theorists who maintained its- independent productivity. In their theor y of price , in having to show how all prices resolve themselves finally into rent, wage, and interest, they were forced . to demonstrate in the most minute wav that concrete capital is noj an elemen t ; that, for instance, copper and steel, which serve as capital in the manufacture of watches, originate in the co-operation of the natural mineral deposits, of the work of miners, and of older capitals, which themselves have originated in similar ways, and so on.^ In the face of this, to maintain the independent productivity of what they had just demor- strated to be a dependent and intermediate product, they were ^ e.g'. Say, Traite, seventh edition, p. 344, H 98 FUNCTION OF CAPITAL IN PRODUCTION BOOK II driven to adopt vft ry singii lar expedients ^' The favourite ones were obscurity and brevity . Instead of making an earnest effort to bridge the yawning contradiction, they either did not suggest the doubt at all, or, if a doubt had already been raised, they dismissed it with some laconic phrase or other. A long series of writers make no scruple about expounding capital on one page as a factor of production “ de rived ” from nature and labour, and on the next as a third ind ependent, Jactoi. of production along with nature and labour.^ Mill has so far yielded to the pressure of facts as to admit that capital is itself the product of labour, and that its instrumentality in production is therefore in reality that of labour in an indirect shape. But with a quick turn he saves its independence. “ Not the less,” he continues, “ does it require to be specified separately. A previous application of labour to produce the capital required for consumption during the work is no less essential than the application of labour to the work, itself.” ^ Th erefore, because labour must be applied twice, in different stages of productio n, something else besides l abour- must be recognised as the independen t condition of prod uctionj Some writers, of course, treat the matter more seriously. They do not evade the difficulty, but try to get a real solution of it. They cannot overlook the fact that capital first comes into existence through combination of simpler factors. Quite correctly, therefore, they do not attempt to claim for capital itself the character of an element ; but they still require an independent support for interest. This they obtain by resolv - ing capital into its elements, and fin ding jthaLJaesldes nature ^nd labour, there is stiU a t h i rd inde pend ent element •. Senior ^alls it A bstinenceT Hermann calls it the Use of Capital. These attempts at solution, which I went into in detail and pronounced upon in my former book. Capital and Interest, were certainly not very happy. Hermann’s, in particular, is singularly unfortunate in being obliged to explain the “ use ” which capital gives as more elementary than capital itself — as if the egg which the hen lays is antecedent to the hen ! ^ Of older writers, e.g. B. Fulda, Grundsdtze der Ode, pol. or Kameralwissen- schaften, second edition, 1820, p. 135 ; Sclidn, Neue Untersuchung der Natimial- Oekonomie, 1835, p. 47. Of later writers Cossa ■ himself, Elementi, eighth edition, p. 34 ; and Gide, Principes d’£c. Pol. 1884, pp. 101, 145. - Book i. chap. vii. § i. CHAP, in NOT AN INDEPENDENT FACTOR 99 Nevertheless as regards our present question these theories are very instructive. They show that several of our most clear- sighted thinkers prefeiTed to take refuge in the most hazardous and artificial constructions rather than agre p in t,hp. c urren t doctrine that capital itaelf. while originating in the co-operation of nature and labour, is. all the same, an " indpppridp.nf'. ” fac.tnr of production along with them ! We mny confidently, then, strike capital out of the list of ^ independent productiv e powers , as a portion of the English school did long ago, and as the Socialists have done more recently. I may say, however, that the manner in which they have done so is not quite appropriate. In the instrumentality of capital they see only the instrumentality of the labour expended in producing it ; they explain it as “ previous stored- up labour.” This is not correct. Capital — to keep the same ^ form of expression — is “ stored-up labour,” but it is something more ; it is also stored-up valuable natural power . It is the medium through whicBTthe two original productive powers exert their instrumentality. To the instrumentality of gold, which is employed as capital in gilding the lightning-rod, the labour of the miner, who finds the ore and refines it, is not the only contributory : nature also has contributed her share in depositing the valuable vein or placer. Although, then, we have traced its instrumentality in pro- duction to nature and labour, is capital itself not productive at aU ? Certainly it is, in more than one sense of that too ambiguous word.^ It is, first, “ productive ” because it finds its destina-'^ tion in the production of goods : it is, further, productive*^ because it is an effectual tool in completing the roimdabout and profitable methods of production once they are entered on ; finally, it is productive indirectly because it makes the adoption ‘s o f new and profitable methods possible . One thing, however, it is not ; jL-ia _not indeyendentlv productive in the sense on which the most important part of the controversy turns. As the old economist Lotz expressed it, briefly and succinctly ; ■“ Of any independent labour in capital there is simply no question.” ^ ' See Capital and Interest, p. 114. - Handhuch der Staatswirthschaftslehre, Erlangen, 1821, i. p. 66, in note. CHAPTEK IV THE THEORY OF THE FORMATION OF CAPITAL In our science there are three views in circulation as to the formation of capital. " ^One finds its origin in Saving, a second in Production, and a third i n both together. Of these the third enjoys the widest acceptance, and it is also the correct oim Put the formulawill have to be amplified to some extent, and presented in a way that is, at once, clearer and more true to life than has Usually been the case.^ The dispute as to the share which Savi ng plays in the fo r mation of capital is almost as old as economic scien ce. The theory which ascribed it the prominent place was the first to appear. Already suggested by the Physiocrats, it was formulated by Adam Smith in the often-quoted proposition, “ Parsimony and not industry is the immediate cause of t he inc rease of capital ” ( Wealth of Nations, book ii. chap, iii.) Supported by his authority it was for a long time almost the only one that held the field, and, although in later times it has suffered many reverses, it still finds some notable apostles : thus, among others, Mill — “ Capital is the re.sult of saving ” (book i. chap. v. § 4) ; Roscher — “Capital is mainly the result of saving ” {Grundlagen, § 45) ; Francis Walker — “ It arises sulely ou t of savin It stands always for self-denial and abstinence” {Political Economy, p. 67). But from a very early period there was sharp opposition to the thenyy.,. first from Lauderd ale- {Inquiry, 1804, chap, iv.) ; then, after some time, from the socialist theorists, Rodbertus {Das Kapital, pp. 240, 267 — “Just as the capital of the isolated individual originates and increases, so does the national capital, — only through labour and not through saving ”) ; Lassalle {Kapital und Arbeit, p. 64) ; Marx {Das Kapital, i. second edition, p. 619). To these opinion^ a great many recent writers of otlier schools more or less incline : thus, very clearly and decidedly, Gide {Principes, p. 167) ; less decidedly, Klein wiichter (in Schbnberg’s Eandbueh, second edition, p. 213), and R. Meyer {Das Wesen des Einkennmens, 1887, p. 213) ; more by way of reconciliation, Wagner {Orundle- gung, second edition, § 298) ; and, a little obscurely and confusedly, Cohn {Grundlegung, 1885, § 257). Although, however, this tendency to ascribe capital to labour is unmistakably rapidly gaining ground, that view which ascribes to. saving a share in the form a tion of capit al is stillAlie view of the majority . But the later representatives of this view are in the habit of rightly limiting it, and CHAP. IV. SA VING AND PRODUCING 101 To put the matter, first of all, in its simplest conceivable terms. Suppose a recluse working a .bsnlntely w ithout capital — say some Eobinson Crusoe thrown on a lonely shore without either tools or weapons. Being without capital he must at first support hfe in the most primitive fashion, as, for instance, by gathering berries which grow wild. Now what must happen before he can get possession of his first capital, say a bow and ^ arrow ? ^ Let us put the first theory to the test. Is saving by" ^. itsp.lf .qnfRcient to call capital into existence ? Certainly not, With the one possession that he has — his wild fruits — our Crusoe may save and stint as much as he please; he will^ . , . accumulate a store of berries — goods for consumption — but that will never give him a single botv or arrow. As we can easily see, these must be positively produced. Ts i>, .<;nffip.ipnt l.bpTi for tbp. nriOTnatinn nf Piipital that it be produced ? Again, certainly not. Of course, once Crusoe has got the length of commencing to produce capital, the formation of capital is as good, as accomplished. But before he gets that length, thpre is something else to be done, and that something is by no means self-evident. Productive- powers are to be set free for the proposed formation of capital^ and this can only be done- as we shall see, through saving_ The amoimt of original productive powers which our Crusoe has daily at his command is equivalent — leaving natural gifts out of account — to one day’s labour, which we shall assume to be ten hours of labour. Suppose, now, that the berries within reach of his hut are so scarce that a ful l da y’.c! Iflbnnr nf tp.n'hours is neces sar y to provide as. jmuGb -food as wEL just support him in bare life, obviously no formation of capital is possible. There is no use advising him to produce a bow and arrows. Producing requires time and strength, and all the time and strength our Crusoe has is fully claimed expressly emphasising the fact that saving alone is not sufficient, and that there Tnii.st also be “labour, ” or “ devotion to productive purposes,” or such like — which, indeed, may very well have been the true meaning of many of the older adherents of the Saving theory, and only not expressed by them because of its assumed obviousness. See, e.y., {Volksicirthschaftslehre, eighth edition, i, § 133), Eicca-Salemo {Sulla Teoria del CapUale, chap. iv. p. 118 — “II capitale deve la sua origine aU’ industria e al risparmio ”), Cossa {ElemcTUi, eighth edition, p. 39), and many others. 102 THEORY OF THE FORMATION OF CAPITAL book ii already to keep him in life. To produce capital, then, may be difficult enough without something else ; and what that is will appear immediately on our varying a little the assumed facts of the illustration. Suppose there is such wealth of berrie s, that the result of nine hours’ gathering is sufficient to support bare life . whUe ten hours’ gathering gives a return such as to guarantee a subsistence amply sufficient to maintain Crusoe in health and strength. Obviously, h.e„has now a choice betwe en two lines of condu ct. Either he may take advantage of the opportunity thus offered to complete his provision, and consume each day the fruits of an entire ten hours’ day of labour — in which case it is perfectly clear that he has now no time and strength left to make a bow and arrows ; or, although the productive power at his disposal would enable him to live better, he may content himself with the barest liv iag. which, as we said, can be provided by the nine hours’ labour of gathering ; then, and then only, has he a tenth hour free in which to make weapons for future use. This amounts to saying, in other words, that, before capital can actu ally be formed, the productive pnwe.rp necessary to its making must be _by enernaebin g nn th e Tn oment’a enjoyment . To anticipate and avoid a mistake very apt to be made, it must be said distinctly that this encroaching on the moment’s enjoyment .need by no means invol v e down right privation. With more productive labour, Crusoe’s choice would not lie, as in the above illustration, between bare Living and comfortable living but, perhaps, between comfortable and ample living. It is not a question of the absolute insignificance of these claims on the moment’s enjoyment, but on their relation to that amount which I may indicate in the shortest and most generally intelligible way by the word “ Income ” — -an expres- sion, unfortunately^ not yet strictly enough defined in scientific usage. 1 On the many divergent and contradictory readings of the conception of Income, see E. Meyer’s Baa Wesen des Einkommens, 1887, particularly pp. 1-27. I purposely avoid going into the controversy as to this conception, which Meyer’s work, notwithstanding its many merits, seems to me to have by no means adequately settled. Where 1 use the word Income in the sequel it i^ to be understood, not in Meyer’s sense, hut in a sense very much in agreement with pop ular nsag e^ CHAP. IV SAVING OF PRODUCTIVE POWERS 103 productive powers should not be entirely claimed for t.ha immediate consumption of the current period, but that a portion of this endowment should be retained for the service of a future period. But such a retention will undoubtedly be called a real saving of productive powers. A saving of nroductive powers, be it noted : for productive^ powers, and not the goods which constitute capital, are the immediate object of saving . This is an important point, which must be strongly emphasised because, in the current view, too little consideration is given to it. Man saves consumption goods, his means of enjoyment ; he thus saven productive powers, and with these finally he cam. capital. ^ It is only exceptionally that capital itself is the immediate object of saving ; it may happen in the case of those goods which, by nature, admit of being used either for con- sumption or for production, such as grain. To the extent that a man withdraws such goods from immediate use in consumption, his saving directly lays the foundation of capital. To build on that foundation, of course, the negative element of saving must have added to it the positive element of devoting the saved goods to production, as intermediate products. It is easy to show that every further increase of the existing stock of capital is limi t ed by the same conditions the first formation. Assume that for a month our Crusoe consumes daily only so much fruit as he can gather in nine hours’ labour, and devotes the tenth hour to making weapons. As result of this thirty hours’ work he now owns a bow and arrows, and jn them hp. has the possibility of making his living much more easi ly and amply than before. Naturally his desires widen. He wishes decent clothes, a house, all sorts of things that minister to comfort. But for these he requires the suitable intermediate products — axes, nails^ braces, etc. Now we ask further what kind of conditions must be fulfilled that Crusoe may obtain this new capital ? This is very easily answered. If he makes use of the improved circumstances, which he owes to the possession of ^ Adam Smith’s celebrated proposition therefore — “Parsimony and not industry is the immediate cause of the increase of capital ” — is, strictly speaking, to be turned just the other way about. The immediate cause of the origi n of. capital is production ; the mediate cause is j. previous saving. 104 THEORY OF THE FORMATION OF CAPITAL book ii the bow and ar rows, simply ^ increa^ his smnpti<2n — that is, if he spends the whole labour time at his disposal in the service of the moment, hunting, gathering fruits, and sleeping, — not only is it impossible for him to acquire new capital, but he will lo s e the o ld. Bows and arrows do not last for ever. In a month’s time, we shall say, his arrows will be spent, and his bow worn out. If, therefore, his capital is to remain in existence, he must, obviously, employ at least one of the ten hours in renewing his weapons, and, at the most, he can employ nine only in gathering and hunting. To put it in propositional form. To retain capital in {/ existence, man must make over, and devote to the service of the future, at least so much of the productive powers of the current period as he has consumed, during the current period, of the produce of forimr productive powers. ^ Or, to put it in other words, the consumption of the current period is limited by the produce of as many productive powers — present and past taken together — as come into existence anew during the current period. Finall y.— i£ -an increase of capital is to become, - possible, obviously a still greater proportion . of tha curre nt productiv e powers must be withdrawn from the consumption of tb^ pr esent, and transferred to the serv ice of Uie fu^re^ of his ten hours of labour our Crusoe must devote one to renewing his weapons, and less than nim& to gathering berries and killing game, if he is to make the new capital he desires in what remains free of his labour time. To put it generally, he must curtail the immediate consumption of the current period to such a point, that it uses up the produce of fewer (past and present) productive powers than come into existence anew in the same period ; he must, in a word, save productive powers. All this is quite clear and simple ; indeed it is even a l ittle too simple for our purpose- Robinsonades and pictures ^ It k only in cases -wlLere, in th e meanwhile, the technignB of the partienlar production has improved , that the transference of a less anionnt_of 4)rQdiicj±Ee powers to the service of the future is sufficient. If, for instance, Crusoe learns how to make in fifteen days those weapons which formerly had taken thirty days, it is, of course, sufficient for the upkeep of the capital if he works only half an hour daily at the repair of his weapons, and nine and a half hours can be spent in directly obtaining a more plentiful maintenance without prejudic to his economical position. CHAP. IV SAVING OF PRODUCTIVE POWERS 105 of primitive circumstances are very good when the object is to present clearly the simplest typical principles — to give a kind of skeleton of economical procedure, — and to that extent, I trust, our Kobinsonade also has done good service. But, naturally, they cannot give us an adequate picture of those peculiar and developed forms in which this skeleton clothes itseU’ in the living actuality of a modern economic community. And it is just at this point that it becomes important to fill out the abstract formula with explanation and illustration taken from Hfe. We shall, therefore, leave the lonely shore of our Crusoe, and come to the industrial conduct of a. great- nation with its millions of people. CHAPTEE V FOEMATION OF CAPITAL IN A COMMUNITY • Let US take the case of a community embracing tp.n Tnillirms o f able -bodied persons. Leaying out of account the current uses of land, so as not to cumber the statement unnecessarily, the annual endowment of such a nation — its original productive powers — thus amounts to ten million years of labour. Its. accumulated stock of cap ital, we shall suppose , re presents, tha fruit of thirty m illion labour -years (and a corresponding amount of uses of land) invested during previous economic years in intermediate products. Now look at the constitution of this stock of capital more closely. Every capital is, by its nature, composed of a mass of inter- mediate products, and the common goal of all these products is to ripen into consumption goods or means of enjoyment. They reach this goal through the continuation of that produc- tion process in the course of which they themselves have come into existence. They are all, as it were.j a iL the way towards the goal of human consumption. But the length of the road which they have had to travel is different. This is partly because the various branches of production adopt round- about ways of various length : mining, for instance, or railway building, takes a much more roundabout and lengthy method than wood-cutting. But it is partly, also, because those goods which constitute the community’s capital at the moment are at various points on their respective roa^. Many an inter- mediate product has just entered on a very lengthy roundabout road, as, for instance, a boring machine, whose life-work it will be to drive a gallery in a mine. Some are midwaY . Others, again, like clothing stuffs ready for making into coats Fig.1. 1 108 FORMATION OF CAPITAL IN A COMMUNITY book n and mantles, are near the end of the journey their particular production process has to take. Now the inventory of capital lays a kind of cross-section through the production -processes. thus unlike in length and unlike in stage of progress, and intersects them, of course, at the most different points, just as a national census lays a section through the paths of life, and encounters and registers the individual members of the nation at the most different stages of life. Considered with reference to the varying distances at which intermediate products lie from the goal of consumption, the total mass of capital divides itself into a nnmhp.r of annual classes or stages of maturity, which may he very appropriately piGtnrp.d hy a. rlia gram of concentric annual circles . The out- most circle (Fig. 1) embraces those goods which will be trans* formed into goods ready for consumption. 'within the coming year ; the second circle represents those goods which will ripen into consumption goods in the year after ; the third circle, those which 'will be ready the year after that, and so on. In a community where production is not yet strongly capital- istic, the inn er circles will rapidly contrn.c t (Fig. 2), because, in such a community, very lengthy roundabout ways of pro- duction, such as turn out their finished goods only after many years, will be rare. In rich and well-developed communities, again, there will be a considerable number of comprehensive circles, and of these the inner ones will have a content that, although relatively smaller, is not inconsiderable. V This representation of the stages of maturity by concentric circles is peculiarly appropriate on this account that it also g vpry hi^ ppy expression to the quantitative relations of these stage s. Exactly as the outmost of the concentric circles possesses the greatest area, while the inner circles possess a gradually decreasing one, does the first of these cla sses — that nearest to the completion of the process — alway.s. by its very nature, embrace the largest q u ota of the total mass of capital. while a decreasingly smaller quota falls to the more remote classes. There are _ two reasons for this. The first is that the various branches of production generally adopt processes of different lengths — lengths varying with the technical cir- cumstances of each branch. Many complete the entire work of production, from the preliminary processes to the turning CHAP. V STAGES OF MATURITY 109 out of the finished product, within a year ; many require two, three, and five years ; only a few have a production period extending over ten, twenty, and thirty years. The result is that in the highest classes — those farthest removed in time from the finished product — only a few branches of produc - tion are found : intermediate products, for instance, in the tenth circle can only be provided by those branches of production which have at least a ten years’ production period. But the lower circles are filled, not only by those last-named branches of production (for the intermediate products of these very long processes must pass circle by circle towards maturity), but also by those branches of production which have shorter periods. Thus the quantity of intermediate products grows larger and larger up to the first class, and to this first class every branch of production, without exception, sends its representativ e. But there is still another circumstance that works in the same direction. The ripening of intermediate products into consumption goods demands a steady addition of current pro- ductive powers. At each stage of the production process new *^ labour is added to the intermediate productS- 3vh.ich h ave been passed on to it from the previous stage, and they pass on to the following stage in a more advanced state. In one stage the intermediate product wool is changed, by the addition of labour, into the intermediate product yarn ; that again in a following stage, by the addition of labour, into the intermediate product cloth, and so on. This has the natural result that, within each branch of production, the amount of invested capital increases with each advancing stage of the production, or, what is the same thing, at every change into a lower circle. Consequently not only are the lower circles, as has been shown, supplied from more branches of production, but they are supplied with relatively larger amounts of capital, and this gives the lower classes a twofold numerical superiority over the higher ones.^ On these lines we may now put our illustration into figures. To facilitate our survey we shall assume that the ^ Durable productive goods, which give off their use gradually in the course of several years, belong naturall y (in various parts of their content as uleful goods, or in various annual circles of their activitvi to several circles simultaneously . no FORMATION OF CAPITAL IN A COMMUNITY book ii total capital of th e communit y is comprised in ten yearly circle. If thirty million labour-years are embodied in this total capital (for simpbcity’s sake I again leave out invested uses of land) we may assume the following division of the circles. The 1st circle contains the intermediate products of 6 million labour-years. 2d 5 ) 55 55 5 55 55 3d 55 55 4 55 55 4 th 15 55 55 3-5 55 55 5 th 11 55 55 3 55 55 6th 5 ) 55 55 2-5 55 55 7 th 51 55 55 2 55 >5 8th 55 55 55 1-7 55 55 9th. 15 55 55 1-3 55 55 IQth 51 55 55 1 55 55 In the normal course of things the outmost circle hecnme.ci divided off from capital each year, and is changed into con - sumption goods , but the succeeding circles press forward, each circle, by the addition of new labour, advanced one stage, both as regards nearness to maturity and amount of capital invested. The first class, therefore, is changed into consump- tion goods, the second class into the first, the third into the second, and so on. Now the following important questions suggest themselves. What use must the community make of the original productive powers which come anew into its possession during the current year — that is to say, the new ten million labour-years if, for simplicity’s sake, we still leave out uses of land — in order to conserve the capital that is in existence ? And how must it act to increase that capital ? I These questions are easily answered. To keep the capital at the present level the community must not spend more than f our milHon labour-years in presen t- time production. ^ With the remaining six miUion labour-years the stock of ^ Under this name {Gegenwartsproduktion) I mean to group, for the sake of shortness, all those acts of production which agree in this, that the original prn - d uctiye powe rs which are put fo rth^jnthes e acts reach their goal, and tunLc mt consumption goods, within the s ame economic period . This applies to two kinds of productive acts-; partly and principally to those of the final stages, the labour required to transform the first circle of capital into consumption goods {e.g. agri- cultural labour, the labour of the miller, baker, shoemaker, tailor, etc.), partly to industries where the production process is short , and can be carried through from beginning to end within a single ecohomic period. CHAP. V INVESTMENT OF PRODUCTIVE POWERS 111 capital, reduced by the separating ofi' of the first year’s circle, must be brought up i n quantity and quality to its former kvel. This demands that the nine other yearly circles be brought each one step nearer maturity by the addition of the requisite labour, and that the tenth class, which is now non- existent, be new created. The amount of labour necessary for this may be exactly determined. The former second class, in which as yet only five million labour-years have been embodied, needs, in order to make it entirely equal in value to the former class ij 3.11 addition of 1 million labour-years. The 3d class needs an addition of 1 55 55 >5 4th 55 55 0-5 55 55 5th 55 55 0-5 55 55 6th 55 55 0-5 55 55 )> 7 th 55 55 0-5 55 55 55 8th 55 55 0-3 55 55 55 9th 55 55 0-4 55 55 55 loth 55 55 0-3 55 55 And the creation of a new 10th class requires the labour of 1 55 55 In all 6 55 55 It should be noted that it is not a matter of indifference at what point, in which partiV.nlar circles, the six: million labour-years are spent . If, for instance, they were to be spent in making intermediate products, but not according to the above distribution — say they were aU spent in making inter- mediate products of the first circle, which would come to maturity in a year’s time — the disadvantage would be two- fold : first, the production processes which had only got the length of intermediate products of the higher classes would be brought to a standstil l ; and second, as we know, the shorter methods would be loss prndnctivp.. With six million labour-years invested in a one year’s process, the present would hand over to the future the same number of productive powers indeed, but — what in the last resort is the important thing — these powers would, in virtue of their one year’s process, be capable of producing only a smaller amount of products than the present has received for consumption from the past. The next .year’s production, therefore, would necessarily be reduced, and the stock of capital would not be maintained at its former level 112 FORMATION OF CAPITAL IN A COMMUNITY book i A^ain. if the present stock of capital is to be increased, it is evidently necessary that the community give up a portion of the consumption which it might, havo enjoyp.tj- — while still I maintaining the stock at its former height ; — that it withdraw V/ a portion of the productive powers at its disposal from the service of the present ; that it save and employ them for additional future production. Productive powers may be saved in various ways. (1) Other dispositions remaining unchanged, a smaller portion of the current productive powers — say three instead of four million labour -years — may be employed in immediate “ present -time production .” Or (2) the arrangements for saving may have been already made, and the total capital organised in such a way that the circle which is now passing over into the stage nf full malnrity cap - tains a less quantity of capita l, say five instead of sLx million labour -years. Inasmuch, then, as only five instead of six million labour -years are now required for the replacement of capital, there remains — if, as before, four out of the ten million labour-years which are the current productive endowment are spent in “present-time production” — one million over, available for the -formation of pew capita l. Or (3) it is conceivable that, at the last moment, the disposition of the capitn.1 - sh ould be so ajtered that less passes into the stage o f _ full maturity than was originally contemplated. It is a familiar fact that there are many goods which admit of being employed in a variety of ways. This often makes it possible to put back goods which have already attained full maturity, or which stand quite near to maturity, by several stages. Gxaic, for instance, instead of being ground for food purposes, may be stored for seed, or used in distilling ; coal may heat the blast furnace instead of the domestic oven ; iron may build machinery instead of park railings ; and so on. If, by thus disposing goods differently, the amount of capital which arrives at maturity becomes reduced from six to five million labour- years, there will, after four million labour -years have been expended in “ present-time production,” be one million labour- years free for the making of new capita l. All three methods, then. — of which, in practical life, the s econd is most common, and the first is least so, — ‘agree in one essential point, that during the current year the produce of CHAP. V IN THE SOCIALIST STATE 113 ■millinn la bour-years only is constimed, while ten million labour- yeaxs come forward ; that accordingly, in other words, one m illion labour-years of the current productive endowment are saved.^ Hitherto we have spoken of the formation of capital by a community as if in such a community there was one single economy, guided by one individual wUl. Of course this is not the case. It remains, therefore, for us to show how, in a community where industry is divided up and managed by many heads, the productive forces that conduce to the forma- tion of capital are actually disposed, and to inquire whether , as we have maintained, these dispositions presuppose “ saving.” And since it is claimed, and not without reason, that universal truths should be proved to hold not only in the present and historical organisation, but in every social organisation, I pro- pose in this inquiry to look both at the actual economic form, wliich is pre-eminently individualistic, and at that form which is at least conceivable, the sociahstic. We may begin with the latter as being the easier from the standpoint of our present problem. In a socialist state from which private capital and private<^ undertaking were banished, and where the entire national production was organised by the state, the — frirmatinn pf capital, and the •previnns saving of productive powers necessary theiat p, would be control! pri nfiRpiflUy The method would ^ If, during the current year, there should be introduced such improvements in the technique of production that the capital, which had taken six million labour-years to produce, could be fully replaced by an expenditure of five million labour-years, there would be a change in the figures of our illustration, but the principle would remain the same It would now be possible to preserve the capital already in existence, even if five million labour-years were spent in present production, and if the produce of eleven million labour-years in aU were spent in immediate consumption (see above, note to p. 104). But in an^ case tlm formatjuu-of new capital would require the renunciation of some portion of that_ immediate consumption which would be possible i f it were only wished to preserve capital at the same level ; in other words, would require that a portion of the “income,” which might be consumed without diminishing the stock of capital, be not consumed but saved. Moreover, if technical improvements did not con- tinue to be made, then, after some years — that is to say, when the capital pro- duced according to the old methods of production was quite used up, — the old figures would come true again ; capital tvould be kept at the same level if in _any period the produce immediately consumed just corresponded to the pin- ductive powers which came forward anew in the same period. I 114 FORMATION OF CAPITAL IN A COMMUNITY book ii simply be to put a considerable proportion of the national workers to very lengthy processes, whereby the -makirig of . capital, in the form of intermediate products, would . be very ^eat. and the aTn oi^^it. nf ma tured profiucts iu the future would l 6e much increased. Many workers, relatively speaking, would be put to mining, railway-building, regulation of rivers, machine- making, and the like, and few to wine-growing, silk-spinning, lace-making, beer-brewing, cloth-making, and the like. The. people would thus be compelled to,, save, by pres sure from above, inasmuch as, of the national production thus conducted by the state, in each year relatively few goods would b e put at__ t.heir disposal for immediate consumpt ioji: — less, that is to say, than might be annually produced and consumed if the existing stock were merely to be maintained. The productive powers left free would be invested in lengthy capitalist pro- cesses of production. Somewhat more complicated, but still easy to grasp in principle, is the procedure in the individualistic organisation of society as we find it in the present day. Here, in the first, instance, it is the undertakers who decide how the productive powers, as they come forward annua lly , shall b e employed, and they thus decide the direction which the national production takes. But they do not decide it at their ple asure ; they '^fo llow impulses given by the pr ice s of products. Where lively demand promises a profitable price they extend their produc- tion, and curtail it in those kinds of goods where failing demand can no longer take off the supply, and the prices fall below a paying level. Extension and contraction of supply continue till such time as production has adapted itself to the desire for the particular commodities. Tp tbc l ast resort. therefore, it is not the undertakers who decide the direction of national production, but the consumers, the “public” All depends on the effective desire they exert by means of their income. The income of a people is, in the long-run, identical with the return of its production. The circle that represents a year’s income coincides, roughly,^ with the circle that re- 1 I have neither time nor desire to go into subtle distinctions here, although there is material enough for them. Interesting investigations into the relation between national product and national income — although I cannot altogether agree with them — may be found in R Meyer’s book, pp. 5, 84. See also the investigations of Lexis (which appeared while the present volume was passing CHAP. V IN THE INDIVIDUALIST STATE 115 presents a year’s return of its productive powers. If every individual in the community were to consume exactly his year’s inoome in the form of consumption goods, there would arise a demand for consumption goods which, through the agency of prices, would induce the undertakers so to regulate production that, in each year, the return of a whole year’s circle of productive powers would take the form of consumption goods. If ten million labour -years (and the corresponding uses of land) form the annual endowment of a people, and this people wishes, to consume, and does consume, the whole of its income in the form of consumption goods, it is a necessity that the produ pp. of t he whole ten million labour -years (together witli the corresponding uses of land) be changed each year into the form of consumption goods . In this case there is no productive power left to dispose of in increasing capital, and capital only remains .a s it was. If, on the other hand, eacit individual consumes, on the average, only three-quarters of his income, and saves the rest, obviously the wish to buy, and the demand for, consumption goods will fall. Only thrc p-fniirtbs of thp. f ormer, consumption goods-wil l find demand and sj le>. If the undertakers, however, were for some time to continue the old dispositions of produc- tion, and bring to market consumption goods to the amount of ten mi llion labour -years, the over -supply would very soon press down the price, business would become unremunerative, and the pressure of loss would compel the undertakers to adapt their production to the changed circumstances of demand. They will now provide that, in one year, only the produce of seven and a half million labour-years is transformed into consumption goods (whether it be by the maturing of the first class, or by adding to “ present-time production ^), and the two and a half millions wliich remain of the current year’s endowment may and will be spent in the increasing of capital. I- say “ will be .s pent.” for an economically advanced people does not hoard.- but puts out what it saves- — in the purchase of^ through the press), entitled Uehcr gewisse Werthgesammtheiten und derm Bezieh- ungen zwm, Geldwerth {Tubinger Zeitschrift, forty-fourth year, part ii. p. 221), where also the yearly “consumption sum.” “production sum.” and “primary income sum’’ are treated as “quantitatively, approximately equal ” amniints. ^ The change of disposition will, as we have seen, be made essentially easier by the adaptability of many forms of capital to various uses. 116 FORMATION OF CAPITAL IN A COMMUNITY book ii valuable paper, in deposits in a bank or savings-bank, in loan securities, etc. In these wavs the amount saved becomes part Qf productive credit : it increases t he purchasing power of pro- d.ucers for prod uctive purp oses ; it is thus the cause of an extra demand for means of production or intermediate products ; and this, in the last resort, induces those who have the regula- tion of undertakings to invest the productive powers at their disposal in these intermediate products. We see, therefore, as a fact, an intimate connection bg,- tween saving and formation of capitah If no individual saves, the people, as a whole, cannot accumulate capital, because the great consumpt of consumption goods forces the producers, by the impulse of prices, so to employ the productive powers that, every year, the produce of a whole year’s endowment is demanded and used up in the shape of consumption goods, _ B.ud no prndnp.t.iv e powers are left free for the increasing of ca pital . But if individuals save, the altered demand, again m ilAAAUlAAi) . X CkVJlJ^ Ccrwr, through the impulse of prices, compels the undertakers to dis- pose of the productive powers differently ; fewer powers are put, each year, at the service of the present, and thereby is increased the amount of those productive powers whose produce will be found in suspense as intermediate products ; in other words, the economical capital will be increased with a view to an increased consumption in the future. JSTow there is stiU a third possibility. Individuals may consunle, on the average, more than their income : instead of saving they may waste their parent sum of wealth . Accord- ing to our theory, this must lead to a diminution of the community’s capital, and, as a fact, it does so. The steps of the process are as follows. By the prevailing extravagance more than a year’s income of the community, and, therefore, more than the produce of one year’s circle of productive powers, is demanded in the shape of consumption goods. Production. compelled by the impulse of pr ices, yields to the deinand. V^or instance, the former disposition was that the first circle, with its six million labour -years, should mature during the current year, and that, of the ten million labour -years that form the current endowment, four millions should be spent in “ present- time production,” and the other six in replacing the capital consumed. Now we shall suppose that, through the 'I /W CHAP. V NO MYSTERY ABOUT IT 117 extravagant manners of the citizens, the year’s demand for consumption goods rises till it requires the produce of twelve million labour-years. The undertakers will act in something like the following manner. Of the current labour endowment they will invest, perhaps, not four but five million labour- years in present production, and, in correspondence with this, the amount devoted to the replacement of capital will shrink from six to five millions. This will cover one million of the extra amount required. At the same time, by differently dis- posing of such goods as allow of more than one employment, they will perhaps divert the produce of another million of labour-years from a more remote class into the first cla^jSj^aud^ thus add it to the consumption of the current year. This will '' ' cover the second million of the extra demand. The com - munity now receives and consumes what it desires,, the pro- T ^ /T ^ duce of twelve million labour-years in the form of consumption t goods hut it does so at the expense of the stock of capital. which is insufficiently replaced, and so diminished by two million labour-years.^ Possibly I have wasted too many words in proving a truth so obvious that no thinking man unskilled in science would ever doubt it. Every child knows that a piece of capital, say a hammer, must be produced if it is to come into existence. And to every simple man it is obvious that no stock of capital can he made, or can increase, if men regularly consume their ^ whole available income ; if, in other words, they do not save. It was reserved for the sharp and subtle wits of learned theorists to suggest the first doubt about it. This, however, it would have been difficult to do if, instead of dogmatising on the formation of capital, they had attempted to give a complete and fai thful repre.senta.tion of the process by which, capital is formed . Here lies the entire, but almost the only, difficulty of these and many other economical doctrines ; and this suggests, I might add, the reason whj^' so many abstract ^ Viz. six million from the original proyision of the first circle, one million diverted and added to that by changed disposition, and five millions from the current labour endowment. ® The stock originally embraced the return of thirty million labour-years ; it now gives seven millions to the consumption of the current year, and it receives only five millions to replace them, whereby it falls from thirty to twenty-eight million labour-years. 118 FORMATION OF CAPITAL IN A COMMUNITY book ii deductions are discredited and fail of result. It is not the deductive method that deserves the distrust, but the persons who misap-ply it. Vulgar errors in thought, indeed, are quite exceptional among capable thinkers; and here the fault lies mostly in this, that the economists in question could not put a sufficiently clear and life-like picture before their minds- of the circumstances and processes which they introduced into their deductive arguments as assumptions, or, at least, did not keep it persistently enough before them through all stages of the deduction. Hence, losing touch with life, they began to make deductions, not from truth of facts, but from words of formulas, and so fell without knowing it into the emptiest dialectic. It is because so many economists, as it seems to me, have made this mistake, that I risk being tedious rather than being sus- pected of sophistry. CHAPTER VI POSSIBLE OBJECTIONS It is perhaps advisable to supplement our positive statement by a brief critical consideration of the most important objections that might be urged. Two of these appear to me particularly worth noticing. TLp. firgf-. is that the majority of goods which constitute t^aoital are, by nature, quite unfit ted tn iTnTnpdifltp. consumption There is, therefore, no sacrifice in withdrawing them from a use which they could never serve. Indeed, it is ridiculous to speak of the “ non-consumption ” of steam-engines and land improvements, of roofing tiles and bars of metal, as an act of saving or abstinence.^ To me this seems a somewhat cheap, but still perfectly goo d, argument against those who formula te the theory of saving superficially or falsely. But, as against the essence of the theory, it proves nothing. If any one is stupid enough to interpret the theory of saving as meaning that finished capital, in its form as concrete capital, must be “saved,” he must submit to the retort that man cannot eat iron machines.^ But this is not at all the meaning of any thoughtful representative of the theory. What is maintaiped is only that, without saving, capital cannot he made or increased : that saving is as ^ indiappusaLIp a npnrlif.ipn nf thp formatinu nf ca pital , And this is literally correct. The machines themselves have ^ This iH v ery strongly pnt by the Socialist writers, as, e.g., Lassalle {Kapital und Arbeit, p. 69) ; Rodbertus (ZJas KapUal, p. 271). In a somewhat diluted form the same doctrine appears in Wagner {Gruvdlegung, second edition, p. 600), who makes a distinction between goods in which the peculiarities of capital are inherent, and those in which they are not. The former are not, at least “ directly .” objects of saving. Similarly Kleinwachter (Schbnberg’s Handbuch, first edition, p. 173). * Lassalle. 120 POSSIBLE OBJECTIONS BOOK II not been saved, but built. B ut in order to build them. men had previously to withdraw the productive powers necessary to building them from the service of the present ; they had, therefore, in the strictest sense of . the term, to save them.^ It may serve towards the settling of this controversy to remark that t he idea of sacrifice, of renunciation, and thus of moral desert, need n ot be associated wit h the conception of saving .^ There may be sacr ifice in saving, and it may be praiseworthy, but not at all necessarily. A man with a small income will, of course, feel it a sensible privation, and it will require strong self-denial in him to lay past anything ; while one who has an income of £100,000, and is content to con- sume one half of it, has little claim to be considered a hero of asceticism because he saves the other half as capital. It is / simply the fact of a saving that is indispensable to tbp. forma- ti on of capital ,: whether there is sacrifice and moral desert in it or not is all the same to the result. And it follows from this that the theoretical truth, that saving ” is necessarY to the formation of capital, cannot and must not be used to justify. '^either morally or socio- politically, all and every taking of 1 In the second edition of Schdnberg’s SarndbucJi (p. 214) Kleinwachter comes a long way nearer our conception in assenting to it, as regards at least one of the chief forms of capital — tools of production. He allows that the making of such tools “ always involve s, to a certain extent, the renunci ation of an immediate enjoyment ,” because the materials which are made use of in making the tools of production might have been employed in making some kind of consumption goods ; and thus there is no reason for objecting to call such a renunciation of enjoyment by the name of Saving. But it is different, he says, with the materials of production. Such thin gs as raw wool, stone, and lime, etc., could not in any way be objects of direct consumption, and so could not be saved ; they must be looked on, therefore, economically as products of labour only, and not as the result of saving. In this Kleinwachter is not logical. As regards the tools of production he, quite correctly, does not consider whether the finished tools them- selves might have been consumed, but whether, by the instruments from which the tools were made, any consumption good might have been made ; and because this is the case he answers the question as to saving in the affirmative. But if he had kept to this line of thought as regards the materials of production, he must have seen that, bv means of the same productive nowera as man uses to quarry stone, to build a house, or obtain lime for mort ar, he might have made h imself goods for immediate consumption.. — e.g. hunted wild animals or caught fish, — and that here, consequently, on exactly the same grounds and in exactly the same way as in the case of tools, saving does come into the question. - See above, p. 102. CHAP. VI SAVING NOT SACRIFICE 121 interest This i.s another instance of tliat, p,nnfuain,cr of the theoretical with the socio-political problem of interest which I adverted to in another place ^ as having done so much harm. One side mixed up the theoretical doctrine that the formation of capital must be preceded by saving, with the moral judgment that interest is justified as the “ reward of abstinence,” and the other side, which saw, quite correctly, that interest could not be justified in such general terms, was misled, by the same confusion of the problems, into denying not only the false socio-political deduction but the true theoretical premiss. If these two problems are kept distinct it will help us to give both parties their due. To Eodbertus and Lassalle we may grant at once that saving need not be moral heroism, and therefore is no sufficient socio-political justification of interest ; but we must stand for the recognition of the theoretical truth that the fact of saving is in any case required to the formation of capital A second objection lavs emphasis on the fact that, for a. man to be able to accumulate capital, he must ac/iuire. mn'ce. than he uses, and draws the conclusion that it is essentially the productmty of labour — industriousness and not abstinence — to which the formation of capital is due. Thus Eodbertus says, in so many words, that if, in the beginnings of economic development, an “ isolated worker has no time to make a tool because he must always live from hand to mouth,” the blame lies simply in the productivity of labour being too small. If, later, this producti%T.ty increases so much that, say, eight hours’ labour is sufficient to produce the day’s maintenance, then “ from the labour time, which up till now he had to devote entirely to make what was absolutely necessary, he has a portion over for other labour, and it is this spare labour which he is now able to devote to the making of a tool.” And from this quite correct consideration Eodbertus draws the conclusiop tha,t it is only the increasing of the productivity of labour, and not saving, which makes the p.xi.stencp. nf snob a prim ary rapital possible .^ And stiU more briefly and strongly does Klein- wachter give expression to* the same idea when he says : “ He who transfers a portion, say a half, of his revenue to the bank is merely industrious. He might, for instance, by a five hours’ * Las KapUal, p. 242. - See Capital and Interest, p. 3. 122 POSSIBLE OBJECTIONS BOOK II day of labour earn his bare maintenance, and devote, say, every afternoon to his recreation or enjoyment ; instead of which the man works ten hours a day, and regularly carries what he earns in the afternoon to the savings-bank.” ^ ■J I think this objection is very easUy met. Tt is simply not correct to say that the man is “ merely industrious. ” He is industrious and saving. If he were simply industrious he would, every day, spend the produce of the afternoon’s labour, along with the produce of the forenoon’s labour, in immediate enjoyment of life. That he does not do so is because he is saving as well. I freely admit that greatei industriousness, causing a return far exceeding necessary require- ments, and, similarly, greater productivity of labour, very much facilitate saving, just as I admit also that, without acquisition, saving, as weU as formation of capital, is absolutely impossible. But I must as emphatically claim recognition of the fact that the greatest acquisition could not lead to the formation of capital if a portion of it were not withdrawn from present use and “ saved.” Production and Saving form two vicqually indispensable conditions of the formation of capitaL and it is only dialectical one-sidedness — which, unfortunately, has already played much too great a part in the doctrine of capital — that could deny the co-operation of either of them.^ ^ But does not this involve me in contxarliV.t.inn with the proposition so ea rnpstly mnl-pnflpd fr»r in lagt. nhpptp.r, that all goods (and consequently all capital! p roce ed from two elements^ of which saving is not one, viz. from nature and labour ? ® Certainly it does not, It is not my intention to do as Senior ^ Kleinwachter, in Schonberg’s Handhuch, second edition, p. 215. * A very striking illustration of these words may be found in the already- mentioned utterances of Rodbertus on the subject. On p. 242, from the fact that, if the productivity of capital is too small, there can be no saving and no forma- tion of capita], he contents himself with drawing the quite correct conclusion that “ necessarily some other element besides saving must intervene.” Thus he ascribes to saving its proper place, as not suffici e nt by itse lf, but.^ all the same, as_ a facUir^ o f the formation of c apital. It is only on p. 243 that the fact of a certain degree of productivity of labour being indispensable is dialectically changed into the statement that only the increase of productivity, and not saving, makes the formation of capital possible. ® A similar objection was urged by the old economist Lauderdale against the Saving theory, Inquiry, pp. 207, 272. CHAP, VI IS SA VING PUREL Y NEGA TIVEf 123 did/ and try to make Saving a third factor in production along with Nature and Labour. Tt does not stand beside these factors, but behind them. It does not share with them in the work of production in such a way that any part of the same is due to it solely and peculiarly ; it only effects that the productive powers, nature and labour, which in any case must do the whole work of production, are directed straight to this and no other goal — the production of capital and not of con- sumption goods. In a word, it has its nlace. not among tl^ means of production, but among the motives of production- — the motives which decide the direction of productiom The proposition, then, that nature and labour are the only true productive powers, can stand perfectly well beside the wider assertion, that, if capital is to come into existence at all, there must, first, hp. certain, intp.llop.tual dispositions through which renunciation is made of a portion of the immediate consump- tion that is otherwise possible ; in other words, there must be “ Saving.” Saving, it is objected again, is a “non -consu mption ” — s omething purely negative : and a pure negation can bring forth nothing.^ To my mind there is more dialectic than truth in tins argument. Is it quite correct to say that saving is some- thing purely negative ? How comes it, then, that, although nothing is easier than a “ pure not-doing,” so many people feel saving an uncommonly difficult and disagreeable thing ? In truth, saving is a mental business ; and often, indeed, though ^ Political Economy, third edition, p. 57, where three great agents or in- struments of production are distinguished — LahfliiL,— J!Iat»iaL_AgentSj_an^ Abstinence. ^ Marx, Bos Kapital, second edition, i. p. 61 9, in note (English translation, p. 608) : “It has never occurred to the vulgar economist to make the simple reflection, that every human action may be viewed as ‘ abstinence from its opposite ^ Eating is abstinence from fasting, walking abstinence from standing stUl, working abstinence from idling, idling abstinence from working, etc. These gentlemen would do well to ponder, once in a way, over Spinoza’s Deter- mxtwiio est Negatio.” Gide, Prindpes d'ie. Pol. p. 168: “Un act purement negatif, une abstention ne saurait produire quoi que ce soit. . . . Sans doute on pent dire que si ces richesses avaient ete consommees au fur, et a mesure qu’elles ont pris naissance, elles n’existeraient pas k cette heure, et qu’en consequence Tepargne les a fait naitre une seconde fois. Mais k ce compte, il faudrait dire qu’on produit une chose toutes les fois qu’on s’ahstient d’y toucher et la non destruction devrait etre classes parmi les causes de la production, ce oui serait une singuliere logique.” 124 POSSIBLE OBJECTIONS BOOK II not always, a veiy troublesome mental business, preceded by long deliberation and conflict between contending motives. This, of course, does not constitute an act of production, and the representatives of the above dialectical objection are, in the end, quite right in raising it as an argument against those theorists who would dignify saving by the name of a third factor in production. But, indeed, simply mental a,s sa,ving may be. it is. sii fRm'p.nt to effect, nally^-filL I.Vip. rnip which wp, have assigned to it in the formation of capital, viz. exerting an influence on the direction of production. For the rest, whether it be a “ pure negation ” or not, we can, in no case, allow dialectical considerations to interfere with establishing important scientific facts. And it is an import- ant scientific fact, which must be reiterated all the more emphatically that it has been disputed, that the progress of capital stands in a causal relation with the extension of the immediate claims put forward by individuals and peoples. Whatever body — be it an individual or a people — extends the claims of the moment so far as to exhaust, during the current period, the entire amount of consumption goods which its income makes possible for the current period, can neither make new nor increase old capital ; and this fact finds accurate and straightforward expression in the proposition that saving is an indispensable condition of the format ion of capital .^ Suppose now that we have succeeded, after considerable trouble, in establishing the proposition that capital comes into existence through saving and devotion to production of what is saved, we have still got but half the answer to our inquiry as to the formation of capital. We have now to face the further question : Dn what does it depend that people can, will, and , ^ actually do save and produce intermediate products ? Strictly speaking, this second question is the more important of the two ; it noints to the impelling and working forces in th , g , formation of capitaL while all that has preceded has merely laid down the external forms of the process. ^ I will not, g 'priori, deny that possibly one miglit contrive to hunt up some subtle examples whars rapital Tpartip-nlarly social capital! comes into existence without saTinpf properly so called. But all the more strongly do I hold by my proposition that, as regards the great mass of the economic formation of capital, saving, in the way I have indicated, has its place. CHAP. VI TRANSITION TO VALUE T25 The most general answer, but still, it must be confessed insufficient for all its generality, runs thus : what people look, to in economic life is the Value of goods. Here we touch a subject which is too important and too difficult to be spoken of merely in passing. To obtain the basis for the principal part of our work — the explanation of interest — we require to go into the theory of value. I shall, therefore, leave the theory of the formation of capital at this stage, returning to it shortly in the last chapter, where we shall give it the logical conclusion that it still lacks, BOOK III VALUE CHAPTEE I THE TWO CONCEPTIONS OE VALUE ^ In the science of Political Economy, as in ordinary speech, two very di.stinot things have usually been p,1a.ssp.d tngethp.r nndor the one name of Yalue . From the first it could scarcely escape notice that there was a difference between them, but the full extent of the difference was certainly underrated. Instead of being recognised as phenomena belonging to entirely distine t categories of thought, they were, quite falsely, represented as members of one and the same group of phenomena, and, under the not very felicitous names of Use Value and Exchange Yalue. they were assumed to be .<^ub-.qpep ies of._nT ie imiver^ ^ My views on the subject of Valae have already been published at lene-tli in another place {Grundziiae der Theorie des WirthschaftlKhen Outerwcrths, in Conrad’s Jahrhucher filr NationalokoTiomie und Statistik, vol. xiii. 1886, pp. 1-86 and 477-541). Since then I have seen no reason to change them. What I have now to say on the same subject can, therefore, offer but few new features. On the whole, what follows is an extract from my former work adapted to the requirements of the theory of capital, and, in the composition of it, I have gone on principles suggested by the nature of my present task. Those fundamental ideas o n which the understanding of the whole depends, and those lines of thought with which the theory of capital is specially connected, I have taken in all their detail from my other book ; and, as a simple change of form would have been as troublesome as it was useless, I have taken them, for the most part, without change. T have omitted, on the other hand, ail those explication s, demonstra- tions, and so on, which were important for the Value theory, but seemed not altogether indispensable for the understanding of the theory of Capital. In place of these I have added a good deal of matter in which I have taken advantage of the newest literature on the subject, and have tried to give a still clearer formula- tion to several ideas, and, particularly, to develop with more exactitude special points where the value theory comes into more intimate connection with the theory of capital. The most important additions occur in chapter vii. of the present book, and at the end of chapter v. and in chapter vii. of the next book. Readers who are interested in the theory of value and price for its own sake, I should ask to consult the statement in Conrad’s Jahrbiieher, which is much more complete, and which I tried to make easier by numerous references. K 130 THE TWO CONCEPTIONS OF VALUE book in conception of Value, and distinguished from each other as such. This distinction once made, however, the so-called Use Value was almost entirely dropped out of sight . Economists took no trouble to inquire any deeper into its nature, nor did they make any use of it in further investigations- They simply catalogued it, as it were, among the conceptions of political economy, and left it lying in a corner of their systems like a stone for which there was no use. It is only of very recent da^ that economical investigation has disco vefed~~in this "stone~re-. iected of the builders ” the basis and support of one of the most important conceptions of economics, and has awaked to tlTe^fact that on it depends a group of most notable laws — laws with consequences reaching far beyond the boundaries of the theory of value, and laws to which almost every branch of economic theory must go back for its root and spring. But, first of all, it is important that we give right names to those things which tradition has handed down to us under the inadequate designations of Use Value and Exchange Value. The two groups of phenomena, to both of which popular usage has given the ambiguous name Value,” we shall distinguish as value in the Subjective and value in the Objective sense.^ / Value in the Subjective sense is the importanop. which r. r^ood. or a complex of goods, possesses ^^th regard to the welL- 1 being of a subject. In this sense I should say of any par- ticular good that it was valuable to me, if I recognised that my wellbeing was so associated with it that the possession of it / .satisfied .some want, secured me a gratification or a feeling )of pleasure which I should not have had without it, or saved /me from a pain which, otherwise, I should have had to endure. In eYTt^teuee of th e good means mv gain, thfi. absence of it mv loss, in wellbeing : to me it is a matter of importance, for me it has value. By Objective value, on the other hand, is meant the Power or Capacity of a go od to pr ocure some one ob jective result. In this sense there are as many kinds of value as there are external results with which man may be connected. There is a nutritive 1 I frankly confess that I would gladly exchange these pedantic and clumsy ex- pressions for terms more euphonious and popular, if they could be got to indicate the opposition referred to with even approximate correctness.* But I have not been able to find such expressions. The words Use Value and Exchange Value are nol ■suitable at all, because, as we sha ll see, there js a Subjectiy fl .ex change value . CHAP. I SUBJECTIVE AND OBJECTIVE 131 value of food, a heating value of wood and coal, a fertilising value of manures, a blasting value of explosives, and so on. In any expressions of this kind all reference to the wellbeing or illbeing of a subject is excluded from the conception of va.hif; . If we affirm that beech has a superior heating value over pine, we only express the purely objective and, as it were, mechanical fact that with a definite weight of beech a greater amount of heat can be raised than with the same weight of pine. In the above connections, then, instpad of thp. word " Val ue ” we use, as entirely synonymous with it, the expressions “Power” nr “ Capacity ” — expressions which themselves suggest a purely objective relation. Instead of “ nutritive value,” “ heat value,” " explosive value,” we use “ nutritive power ” or “ nutritive capacity,” “ heating power,” “ explosive power,” and so on, as meaning exactly the same thing. The varieties of Objp.rtive value iust mentioned bv wav of illustration do not, however, belong to economical but to purely: ^.bnipa.l rph tinns ; and, however frequently they are referred to in economical text-books, they do not properly belong to political economy at all. It does not fall within the province of our science to expound the heating value of wood, nor, in explaining other economical phenomena, has it occasion to lay stress on this heating value any more than it does on any other physical or technical fact. I have given these illustrations purely as illustrations, with the intention of putting in clearer relief the very intimately related nature with the above of that branch of objective values which, of 'course, has the greatest possible importance for political economy, namely, the objective Exchange value of goods. By this expression B’^nean the oi^ective worth of goods in excEahTOT“br. in other words, the pr>ssTbT]ifry' nr nbtaiin'ng jn PYP.bapgp. fnr thprir^ . q . other ecQiioini'car goc^s.Thi s possibility bping looked.- aipon as a power or a property of the former goods. In this sense we say that a horse'ls worth £50, or a house worth £1000, if, in exchange for these, we can obtain, respectively, £50 or £1000. Here, again, it must be noted that, as in the kindred expressions heating value and the like, we say nothing at, all as to the influence which goods mav exert on the, wellbeing of any subject wha^iver ; we simply indicate the objective relation that for a particular good a certain amount of other goods may 132 THE TWO CONCEPTIONS OF VALUE book hi be had in exchange. In this case also the characteristic phenomenon recurs, that thp wor d “ Value ca,n be. gm'tp. adequately, replaced by_the word. “Power” and is, indeed, so replaced in popular speech. Besides the expression “value in exchange” English economists use, quite indifferently, the expression “ purchasing power, ” and we Germans are beginning in the same way to put in general use the term Tauschkraft. The economical theory of value has, then, the double task of interpreting, on the one hand, the laws of Subjective Value, a^nd, on the other, the laws of Objective Exchange Value, as from the economic , point .. of view by far the mpst imp ortant br anch of objective value. The first part of this task we shall take up in the present book, the second in the follow- ing book deaHng with the theory of Price. It is true that the two conceptions, “ Price ” and “ Exchange Value,” are by no means identical. Exchange Value is the capacity of a good to obtain in exchange a quantity of other goods. Price is that other quantity of goods. But the laws of these two coincide. So far as the law of price explains that a good actually obtains such and such a price, and why it obtains it, it affords at the same time the explanation that the good is capable, and why it is capable, of obtaining a definite price. The law of Price, in fact, contains the law of Exchange Value.^ 1 The, foundations of the modern value theory have been laid by three writers whose work is in substantial agreement — Carl Menger. Jevons, anil Walras. Of these, in clearness and completeness, Menger's Ttat’ement takes the first place. Twenty years before his time, several of the most weighty and fundamental ideas had been already propounded by Gossen in his remarkable book, Entwicklung der Gesetze des menschlichen Verkehrs und der daraus Jliessenden Begeln fur menschliches Handeln, Brunswick, 1854. Like the book itself, these ideas sank into complete but undeserved oblivion, and had to be rediscovered by the economists just mentioned. That this was done almost simultanp-oiisly by difF erent men, belonging to three different nations, and quite independently of each other, is a very remarkable coinc idence, and is, at the same time, no small guarantee for the correctness of the principles on which all three were certainly agreed, although in thoroughness their statement of them was unequal. Since then these principles have had a notable development, and received wide acceptance. Not long ago, in the preface to his Theorie de la Mcmnaie (Lausanne, 1886), Walras could give an imposing list of writers as ad herents of the new theory. Since then we may add the name of E. Sax {Grundlegung der fheo- retischcn Staatswirthschgft, Vienna, 1887, p. 250), — with whom, however, I cannot agree in many particulars, particularly in those where he tries to establish original ideas that are not in harmony with those of his predecessors ; and that of R. Meyer {Das Wesen des Einkommens, Berlin, 1887). CHAPTEE II NATURE AND ORIGIN OF SUBJECTIVE VALUE All goods without exception — indeed according to the very conception of them as “ good ” — possess a certain relation to human wellbeing. There are, however. twiL,esseatiaIlw distinct grades of this relation . A goodUbilrags to the lower grade, whenTl^ssesses the general capacity to snhsprvft human wpal The higher grade, on the other hand, demands that a good should be more than merely a sufficient cause ; it mu.st he an indispensable condition of human wellbeing — a condition of such a kind that some gratification stands or falls with the having or wanting of the good. In the expressive vocabulary of everyday Life we find a separate designation for these grades. The lower is called Usefulness, the higher Value . This dis- tinction, already recognised in common speech, we must try to make as clear and well-marked as its fundamental importance for the whole theory of value deserves. A man dwells beside a bubbling spring of water . He has filled his cup,- and the spring goes on pouring out enough to fill a hundred other cups every minute. Another man is travelling in thejieseifi A long day’s journey over glowing sand still divides him from the nearest oasis, and he has come to his last cup of water. What is the relation i n each case between the cup of water and the wellbeing of, its owner. ? A single glance shows us that the relation is very dis- similar ; but wherein lies the difference ? Simply tha,t, in tlie former case, we haA'^e only the lower grade of the relation we call wellheingr that ~ of usefulness ; in the latter case we ha^’e the higher" ~^a'iTe~ a!s well. In the first ca^' “jtist as in the 134 NATURE OF SUBJECTIVE VALUE BOOK in second, the cup of water is. aseful , that is, capable of satisfying a~~Want7 and, moreover, in exactly the sam e degree ; for evidently the refreshing qualities of the water — the qualities on which its capacity to quench thirst is based, such as cool- ness, taste, etc. — are not in the least degree weakened by the fact that other cups of water chance to possess similar properties ; nor, in the second case, are these refreshing qualities in the least augmented by the accidental circum- stance that there is no other water near. On the other hand, the two cases become essentially distinct when con - sidered with reference to the second grade. Looking at the former case we must say that the possession of the cup of water does not provide the man with one single satisfaction more, nor its loss with one satisfaction less, than he could have obtained without it. If he has that particular cup of water he can quench his thirst with it ; if he has not that cup — well, he can quench his thirst quite as well with one of the hundred others which the spring puts freely at his disposal every minute of the day. Tfjie likes, therefore, he may make that one cun the cause, of his s^atisfactidn 'b;^que'nching his thir.st with it: an indispensable condition of his satisfaction it cannot be : for his wellbeing it is dispensable, unimportant, indifferent. It is quite otherwise in the second case. Here we must say that, if our traveller had not that one last cup, he could not quench his thirst ; he must bear its pangs imassuaged, perhaps even succumb to them. In the cup of water then, in this case, we se e not merel y a sufficient cause, but the ind is- pensable condition, the sine, qua non of human wellbein g. Here it is of consequence, even of urgency ; it possesses importance for his wellbeing. Now it is not too much to sav that t he distinction here drawn is one of the most fruitful a nd fundamentaL in the whole range of our science. It does not owe its existence to the microscope nor to any hair-splitting distinctions of the logician. It has its life in the world of men, who know it and use it and take it as guide for their common attitude towards the world of goods, not only as regards the intellectual estimate they apply to these goods, but as regards their actual business transactions. About goods _which are o nly: CHAP. II THE INDISPENSABLE CONDITION 135 useful the practical businR-^ss man i.g carpi hss and indifferent. The academic knowledge that a good may be “ of use ” cannot evoke any efficient interest in the good, in face of the other knowledge that the same use may be obtained without it. Such goods are practically naught as regards our wellbeing. and we treat them as such ; we are not put about when we lose them, and we make no effort to gain them. Who would fret at, or make an effort to prevent, the spilling of a cup of water at the spring, or the escape of a cubic foot of atmo- spheric air ? WTiere^ on the other hand, the sharpened glance of the economic man recognises that some sati.qfaction. well- being. gratification. ^ connected with a particular good, there the effective interest whi ^’k -are tak^ in own -wellbeing is, transfefred to the good which we recognise as its condition : we see and value our own welfare in it ; we recognise its importance for us as value ; and finally, we develop an anxiety, proportioned to the greatness of that importance, to acquire and hold the good. Thus, formally! defined, value is the importance which a good or complex of goods possesses with respect to the wflUbping* of a subject . Any addition to this definition, regarding the kind and reason of the importance, is, strictly speaking, not necessary, since goods can only have an effective importance for human wellbeing in one way, viz ^y the in d ispen .sabl e condition, the sine qua non, of some one utility which sub- serves it. In view of the fact, however, that in other defini- tions of value it is very often translated as an “ importance,” while the importance spoken of rests, erroneously, on a simple capability of utility, or, not less erroneously, on the necessity of expenditure of costs, or the like,^ we shall define it, un- ambiguously and exactly, as : That importance which goods or complexes of gooiks. jicgnire. as the r^ognised "condition of a utility which makes for the wellbeing of a subject, and would, not ~be obtained without them. All gnnd.s bavp. usefulness, but all goods have not value. For the emergence of value there must be ^ scarcity as well as usefulness — not absolute scarcity, but scarcity relative to the demand for the particular class of goods. To put it more ^ See Conrad’s Jahrhiicher, vol. xiii. p. 11. 136 NATURE OF SUBJECTIVE VALUE BOOK III exactly : goods acquire value when the whole available stock of them is not sufficient to cover the wants depending on them for satisfaction, or wlien the stneic would not he silfiReieot ^ without these particular goods. Ou the other hand, those ■ goods remain valueless which are offered in such superfluity that all the wants which they are fitted to satisfy are com- pletely supplied, and when, beyond that, there is a surplus which can find no further employment in the satisfaction of want, and which, at the same time, is large enough to spare the goods or quantities of goods that we are valuing without imperilling the satisfaction of any one want. After what has been said as to the nature of value, it should not be very difficult to prove these propositions. When the supply of goods is not sufficient , and some of the wants which they are adapted to satisfy must remain un.satisfied. it is clear that the loss of even a single good involves the loss of a, possible satisfaction, while the addition of a single good in- volves the acquisition of a satisfaction otherwise impossible ; and it is clear, consequently, that some gratification or form of wellbeing depends on the existence of that good. Conversely, it is quite as clear that, if goods of any class are to be had in superfluity, there is no harm done if one of the goods be lost — since it can be immediately replaced from the superfluous stock ; nor any utilitv got if another such good be added — since it cannot be employed in. fl.n y useful way . Suppose, for instance, that a peasant requires ten gallons of water per day, and no more, for general purposes — say, for his own drinking, for that of his family and servants, for watering his cattle, for cleansing, flushing, etc. — and suppose that the only spring within reach supplies no more than eight gallons a day. It is quite evident that he cannot spare one single gallon from his waters supply without suffering, to a more or less sensible extent, as regards the wants and aims of his economy. Every gallon in this case is the Condition of a definite sphere of usefulness. Even if the spring supplied just ten gallons this would still be true But if the spring supplied twenty gallons per day, it is just as obvious that the loss of one gallon would not do the slightest injury to our peasant He can only employ ten gallons usefully, and he must let the other ten gallons flow away unused. If one gallon is spilled it is replaced from the CHAP. II ONLY ECONOMICAL GOODS HAVE VALUE 137 overflow, and the only effect is that now the unusable surplus is reduced from ten gallons to nine. Now' as it is the insufficient, or the barely sufficient, goods that are the objects of economical care — the goods we “ economise ” or endeavour to acquire and keep, — while such goods as are to be had in superfluity are free to everybody, we may express the above propositions shortly in the following form: AH economical goods have value ; all free goods are valueless. ^ In any case it must steadily be borne in mind that it is only relations of quantity that decide whether a ny particular good is merely capahle nf nsc or is also the con- dition of a utditv for us. ^ 1 Some very interesting phenomena of value may, in certain circnmstances. be exhibited by free ^ooda also . For the explanation of this see my Qrundziige, p. 15. ^ Those numerous writers of whom Scharling is the latest instance (Conrad’s Jdhrhucher, vol. xvi. pp. 417 and 513, and particularly 424, 430, 551), who say that the distinguishing criterion of “economical” and “valuable” goods is difficulty of attainment, the necessity of expending labour, and the like. ar£. giving a secondary ground of definition instead of the really decisive and primary one. It is only when and because we are suffering, or fear to suffer, loss of satisfaction from insufficient supply of goods that we decide, generally speak- ing, to submit to the hardships of acquiring them, to labour, and so on. Ltb^i v and hardship could not by themselves confer an economical character on grinds were it not that, for the most part, another circumstance, and that the really decisive one, is also present ; in other words, that those kinds of goods, which are difficult or troublesome to obtain, are, at the same time, the goods that remain scarce . That, however, it is not the, diffi i^nlty but: tb^ s carcity that decides is vividly shown in those cases — not, I grant, very common — where the technical circumstances are of such a nature that the good can be got only, indeed, by conquering difficulties, but then in superfluous amount. When the peasant obtains good drinking water, e.g., by bringing it along a pipe to a house, it may occasion him a permanent expenditure of labour and costs for construction, upkeep, and management of the water-.supply. But if this brings the water in greater quantity than he requires, it will not occur to the peasant, in spite of the labour, that he must “economise” the water. CHAPTER III THE AMOUNT OF VALUE In asking what is the principle that reflates the amount of value, we pass fco a sphere where lies the chief taaV of a. t.hftnry of value, and where at the same time lie its greatest difficulties. These difficulties are the result of a peculiar coincidence of circumstances. Erom one point of view the true principle almost suggests itself. If the value of a good is its importance to human wellbeing, and if this “ importance ” means that some portion of our wellbeing is dependent on our having the good, it is clear that the amount of the good’.ci value must he determined by th^ am ount of wellbeing which depends on it. l^^^^-^oods will have high value if our wellbeing depends on them to any important extent, low value if it does not. But from another point of view, there are certain facts in the economical world which seem to give the lie to this very simple and natural explanation. Everybody knows that, in practical economic life, precious stones possess a high value, while bread and iron have a moderate value, and air and water usually no value at all. Now everybody knows that without air and water we simply could not exist, and that the uses of bread and iron are extremely important, while precious stones , for the most part, only satisfy the love of ornament, and have, accordingly, a very inferior importance for human wellbeing. It would appear, then, that one who holds fast by the principle that the amount of a good’s value is determined by the importance of the services which it may render to human wellbeing, must expect to find in precious stones a low value, in bread and iron a high value, and in water and light the very highest value. But facts show that exactly the opposite of thi g is the case . CHAP. Ill THE OLD PARADOX 139 This startling phenomenon has been a veritable rock of offence in the theory of value. The highest utility acconi r panied by the sTnallp.cit value is a strange paradox. It is true that, in confusing Usefulness and Use Value , economists did not apprehend and describe the state of the case quite exactly. When they falsely ascribed to the iron a high “ use value ” and to the diamond a low “ use value,” the only reason for surprise was that the “ exchange value ” of these goods went so entirely in the opposite direction. But this was only to change the name of the opposition, not to take away any of its sharpness. There were plenty of attempts to bridge the fatal contradiction by involved explanations, but these were unsuecessful ; and so it happens that, from Adam Smith’.s time, to our own, innumerable theorists- have. -despaired of finding the~Sature andT measure of value in any rft1a.tion to human wellbeing, and have fallen back upon quite foreign and often wonderful lines of explanation, such as labour or labour time, costs oF~ production, resistance of nature to man, and the like. Btrtrunable to get rid of the feeling that the value of goods must have sometliing to do with utility and human wellbeing, they put down the want of harmony between the utility and the value of goods as a rare and perplexing contradiction , a contradiction 4conomiq%ic. In what follows I mean to prove that the older theory had no need to abandon the most natural explanation. The measure of the utility which depends on a good is. actually and p.vprywbp.re. the measure of value for that good. To prove this nothing more is necessary than a dispassionate but keen casuistical investigation into the question. What is the gain to our wellbeing that, in any given circumstances, depends on a good ? I say deliberately “ casuistical ” investigation ; for the entire theory of subjective value is, properly, nothing else than a system of casuistry , determining when, under what circnmstances, and how far our wellbeing is dependent upon any particular good. It is very remarkable that the ordinary man in everyday life is constantly making casuistic distinc- tions of this kind, and making them with great certainty. He seldom makes a mistake, and he never makes a mistake in the principle. He may, of course, ascribe a trifling value to a diamond if he mistakes it for a glass bead. But the theoretical 140 THE AMOUNT OF VALUE BOOK HI consideration — wliicli is quite irrelevant here — that without water tlie human race could not continue in life, would never lead him to the casuistical conclusion that every gallon of water which flows from the village spring is a good of priceless value, or worth thousands of pounds. Our task, then, is to hold the niir r ar up . to those casuistical distinctions which men make in the ordinary affairs of life., and to bring those laws, which the ordinary man instinctively handles with certainty, to clear and conscious presentation. What human wellbeing may gain from a good, and thus the advantage which is dependent on a good, is, in most cases,^ the .satisfaction of a. wanL The casuistical consideration that really determines how far a person’s wellbeing depends upon a particular good is found in the answer to two questions : first, which, among two or more wants, depends on it ? and, second, what is the urgency of the dependent want or of its satisfaction ? For convenience we shall take the second question first, and answer it in the present chapter. Jt is a famil iar faet that our wants vary very greatly in importance . We are accustomed to rank them according to the seriousness of the consequences which their non-satisfaction has on our wellbeing. Thus we attach the greatest weigh t to those wants the non- satisfaction of which would T;)e followed by. deat h. Next to these we place wants the non-satisfaction of which would result in some serious permanent injury to our health,, h^onour, or happiness. Below these again come such wants as expose us to more tem porary injuries , pain, or deprivations. Finally, we put in the very lowest class those wants the non-satis- faction of which costs us nothing more than a very slight unpleasantness , of the deprivation of some qtiite"TnsTgnificant pleasure. Arranging our wants according to these characteristics we, obtain a regularly grad uated scale of wan ts. Of course as differences of bodily and mental disposition, culture, and so on, result in very marked difi’erences of wants, this scale will come out very different for different individuals, and even for ^the same individual at different times. All the same, every practical man whose means are limited must have a scale On certain comparatively rare exceptions see Conrad’s Jahrhiieher, vol. xiii. p. 42. CHAP. Ill KINDS OR CONCRETE WANTS? 141 ■mnrpi nr less clearly before Vn's mind i£ - hp wniilrl tthiVp. a cVinicf among thRSP. wants, and even theorists have often had occasion to sketch such a scale from the “ objective ” standpoint of impartial scientific consideration. So far everything would be simple and certain were it not that there is an ambiguity when we speak of graduation OP ranking of wants. We may mean by these terms either the graduation of wants as kinds of wants, or the graduntinn of degr ees of wants , the concrete individual feelings of want ; and these two are essentially different, even divergent. If w^e compare kinds of wants, looked at as a whole, according to their importance for human wellbeing, there is no doubt whatever that to t he needs of subsistence would lie allotted the first ranb;. to the needs of housing and clothing a rank not much inferior, to the wants satisfied by tobacco, spirituous liquors, music, etc., a very much less important place, while the wants of ornament and the like would have a very in- significant rank indeed. the graduation of coTiCTete feelings of want is esseh- tially different from this. Within one and the same kind of want the feeling of want is not always uniform, not always equally strong. Every feeling of hunger is not equally intense, and every satisfaction of hunger is not equally per- fect. In the class of “ needs of subsistence,” for instance, the concrete want of a man who has not eaten a morsel for eight days is infinitely more urgent than that of another man who has already got through two courses of his ordinary dinner, and is meditating whether he should have a third. In the graduation of concrete wants we have to deal with an entirely different state of affairs, and with a much greater variation. In t he s cale -of- fa^Zs-olvscants-dhe “ne eds of su b- sistence” came far and away befo r e the d esim for tobacco, for liquor, for ornament, etc. In the scale of concrete wAuts , wants~5eIongm^ to the most various kinds cross and intersect each othen It is” true that, everrTefe, the' most important- concrete wants in the most important classes of wants stand at the top of the scale ; but the less important concrete wants of these classes are frequently overpassed by concrete wants of much inferior classes — th e bottom members of the highest class, perhaps, overpassed by the top member of the lowest 142 THE AMOUNT OF VALUE BOOK III class, It is very much the same as if a geographer were one time to arrange the Alps, Pyrenees, and Harz by their height as mountain ranges, and another time were to arrange their single summits. As ranges the Alps would, of course, come before the Pyrenees, and the Pyrenees before the Harz. But, in comparing individual heights, a great many of the Alpine summits would take rank below individual peaks of the Pyrenees, some even below hills in the insignificant Harz. And now the question is. When goods have to be valued. by wbip.b seale shn11 wc measure the importance of the wants . they siihserve — the scale of kinds or the scale of concrete wants,? When the older theory came to this dividing~of~the ways — the very first opportunity offered it of making a mis- take — it chose the wrong wav. It adopte d f.be seale, nf kinds, On this scale the class “ Needs of Subsistence ” occupies one of the most conspicuous places, while the class “Desire of Orna- \/ ment ” has a subordinate place. Thus the older theory decided that bread, universally, has a high “ use value,” and diamonds a low “ use value,” and, naturally, was very much astonished that the value practically put upon those two kinds of goods was exactly the reverse of this. Now their conclusion was quite wrong. What the casuist must say to himself is : If I have a slice of bread I can indeed still this or that concrete feeling of hunger as it arises, but— I can never satisfy the totahtY of such feelings — the actual and p ossible, present and future, feelings of hunger wliich. togeth er- make up the kind “ needs of subsistence.” Obviously, then, it is quite out of place to attempt to measure the service which the piece of bread can render me by the fact that the totality of such feelings possesses much or little importance. To do so would be like the act of a man who, on being asked as to the height of the Kahlenberg, an insignificant off-shoot of the Alps near Vienna, were to ascribe to it the height of the Alpine chain ! As a fact it would never oeoiir to n.s in practical life to value every bit of bread in our posseu - |ion as a treasure of infinite importance . We do not rejoice every time we buy a baker’s roll as if we had saved a life, nor do we blame a man as spendthrift when he carelessly gives away a slice of bread or throws it to a dog. Yet this is the judgment we must pass if we would transfer the import- CHAP. Ill THE SCALE OF SATISFACTION 14:5 ance of the kind “ needs of subsistence,” on the satisfaction of which our very life depends, to the goods which actually minister to that satisfaction. This much is clear, then, that the value we ascribe to goods has nottitrrg Tn~r1n wi't-.h thp graduation of kinris of want, hut only .witimie~^aduation of concrete wants. In order to bring out a]jr~fhat is^ihvdrved in this conclusion, it may be desirable to put more clearly certain points relating to the composition of this graduated scale, and to put the whole argument on a surer basis than has been done in the foregoing analysis. Most of OUT wa.uts arc divisible, in the sense that they are susceptible of piecemeal satisfaction. When hungry I am not compelled to choose between satisfying my hunger completely and going entirely unsatisfied. I may take the edge off my appetite by a moderate meal, intending, perhaps, to dispel the feeling of hunger altogether later on by a full meal, or, perhaps, to make shift with the partial satisfaction I have got. Naturally the partial satisfaction of a concrete want has another and a smaller importance for my wellbeing than a complete satis- faction of the same ; and, to a certain extent, this of itself would suffice to call attention to the above-mentioned phenomenon that, within a kind of wants, there are concrete wants (or degrees of want) of varYing importance . But with this is connected a further notable fact. Tt is an experience, as familiar as it is deep-rooted in human nature, that jthp. .same enjoyment, when constantly repeated, gives us. heyonr l a. certain point, a constantly decreasing gra tification, till, in the end, it changes into its opposite. Any one can prove for himsedn that at a meal when the fourth or fifth course is reached, the! appetite is not nearly so keen as at the first course, and that, f if there are too many courses, a point is reached where enjoy- ment turns into discomfort or disgust. The same occurs in too long a concert, lecture, walk, play, and, generally speak- ing, in the case of most physical as well as intellectual enjoyments. If we put the essence of these weU-known facts into technical language we get the following proposition : The con - crete degrees of want into which our sensations of want may he divided, or the successive degrees of satisfaction obtained from similar amounts of goods, are usually of very dissimilar- 144 THE AMOUNT OF VALUE BOOK III importaace — -indeed, of importance which diminis h es st ep b_v_ step to zero. This will explain a whole series of propositions which were simply asserted above. It explains, firstly, how, in one and t he same kind of wants, there may be concrete wants, or- defp-ees of want, of varying urgency . Indeed in the case of all divisible satisfactions as the term is defined above — that is, in the great majority of cases — this not only may be but must be so, quite normally and, so to speak, organically. It explains, again, that, even in the most important kinds of wants, there are lower and lowest grades of importance . Properly speaking, the more important kind is marked off from the less important only by the fact that, to some extent, its head rises higher than the others, while its base stands on the same level as all the others. And, finally, it explains that, not only may it occasionally happen, as I have just said, that a concrete want belonging to a kind which, on the whole, is more important, may be out - weighed by some individual concrete want of a kind, on th,p. whole, le ss importan t, but that this happens as a perfectly normal, ordiWry, and organic occurrence. There will always, for instance, he innumerable concrete subsistenop. wa.nt. level ind ependently of their concrete complementary employment, and this value they have when we distribute out the total value of the group aniongTS individual members. The distribution, then, will be made~thus : of the total value of the whole group — which is determined by the marginal utility of the joint employment this fixed valup i.'s prpvin nsly assig riPrl tr. rppIgppgVilp members?~an(n^b p rpmaind^r — which varies according to the an idunt o f , t^e marginal utility — -is reckoned tn tbp. non- replaceable Tnembers as their individual value. To use our old~iIIustration again; say that the joint marginal utility amounts to 100, and that the members A and B have a fixed “substitution” value of 10 and 20 respectively, 70 must be reckoned the individual value of the non-replaceable good C ; or, say that the marginal utihty of the group amounts to 120, the individual value of C will be 90.^ Of the three cases we have discussed the last mentioned is by far the most common in practical life, and, accordingly, in the great majority of cases, the value of complementary goods is determined according to the latter formula. The . jnost important application of it is in the distribution of the product among the various productive powers co-operating in producing. it Almost every product is the result of the co-operation of a group of complementary goods consisting of uses of ground, labour, fixed and floating capital. Of the complementary members the great majority are marketable coumnodities . and replaceable at wiU ; as, for instance, the labour of wage-earners, the raw materials, fuel, tools, etc. Onh^ a few of them are non- replaceable, n r not easily replaceable ; as, for instance, the land on which the peasant works, the mine, the railway hnes, the factory walls, the activity of the undertaker himself with his peculiar and high qualifications, and so on. It is easy to see, therefore, that here we have exactly those casuistical cir- cumstances in which the foregoing formula of distribution ^ If C also were replaceable by a substitute of less value the case mentioned on p. 170 would emergej and the marginal utility of the joint use would not determine the value of the complementary group. 176 THE VALUE OF COMPLEMENTARY GOODS book iii obtains, and, as a fact, it is acted upon in practical life in the I most accurate way. In actual business the cna taiL.a TP, firal. deducted from the total return . If we look closer, however, we shall see that what is deducted is .not all the msta. — for, if so, the use of ground, or the undertaker’s activity, as both valuable goods, would come under costs — but only the expendi - / ture for the replaceable means of production with a given \ substitution value, viz. the wage of labour, raw materials, wear I and tear of tools, etc. The remainder , under the name of / “ net return,” ^s ascribed to the non-replaceable membe r or ‘ members : the peasant calculates it to his land, the mine- owner to his mine, the manufacturer to his factory, the merchant to his undertaking activity. If the joint returns increase, it would not occur to anybody to ascribe the surplus to the replaceable members ; it is always the ground or the mine that “ produces more.” And, similarly, if the joint returns decrease, nobody would credit the “ costs ” with the reduced amount ; the deficiency also is conceived as exclusively due to the diminished productiveness of the ground or the mine. And this is entirely logical and correct : on goods replaceable at any moment only the fixed su bstitution value is actually dependent ; the entire remainder of the joint amount of utility obtainable depends on the goods that cannot be replaced. * The theory of the value of complementary goods is the l^ey which will solve one of the most important and difficiflt problems of politica l econoTTiy — the_ ,problem of the _diS-tlib.utiQn of goods as made in the present state of society, where competition is more or less free and prices are determined by free contract. All products come into existence through the co- operation of the three complementary “ factors of production,” labour, land, and capital. Now our theory, in showing, how much of the joint product n^ economically^ be c onsidered as ^ Not physically. It would, in most cases, be absolutely impossible to calculate the physical share — how could one be supposed to distinguish what percentage the material and what percentage the artist had contributed physi- cally to the making of a statue ? — but it is also a matter of no importance. On the other hand it is, in most cases, quite easy to determine what share of the utility, or of the value, would have to be done without if one were not in pos- session of a definite -individual factor, and this quota, conditioned by the possession of one factor, I call its economical share in the total product. CHAP. IX ITS BEARING ON DISTRIBUTION 177 due to each of these, and what shar e of the t otaLvalue may, accordingly, be assigned to each of them, lays down, at the same time, the most decisive basis for determining the amount of remuneration which each of the three factors obtains i ~~Snd thus although, as we know, capital as “ factor of production ” does not exactly coincide with capital as " source of income,” yet this gives us at least a rough indication of the way in which the amount of the^three branches of income — wage, rent, and interest — is determined. It does not indeed do this quite directly. That quota which the workers receive, and that other quota which the owners of the co-operating ground receive, is directly identical with wage and rent. But the quota which falls to the co-operation of capital is not interest — as, in theories of dis- tribution, economists have repeatedly assumed ever since the days of Say with fatal precipitation. It is. first, the gross remun eration for the co-operation of capital ; and, out of this, interest is got, like a' kernel out of a shell, because, and to the extent t'hat.~ something remains over after deducting from the gross rem uner ation the value of the worn-out capital. To explain how this is^ so is a problem in itself. To make it quite clear by an illustration, suppose that a commodity, produced by the co-operation of aU three factors, is worth £100. The law of complementary goods will carry us thus far ; it will enable us to determine that the share of labour (the labour directly employed in the production) amounts to, say, £20, that of ground to £10, that of capital to £7 0. But it does not tell us what, or how much, of tha t ^70 remains over nd, as interest, after deduction of the wear and tear of capital. On the contrary, the law of com- plementary goods in itself would rather lead us to the conclusion that nothing remains over. For, according to it, it would be most natural to assume that the capital, to the co-operation of which the return of £70 is ascribed, and which has been consumed in obtaining that return, had already been valued at the entire £7 0 ; and, if this were the case, the return to capital would naturally be entirely absorbed by the wear and tear of the capital. That this is not the case is, so to speak, an internal mattei u^a matter which plays its part inside, the gross share of capital determined by the law of 178 THE VALUE OF COMPLEMENTARY GOODS book iii complementary goods, and is the object of an independent problem, the peculiar problem of Interest . But before we can discuss interest there is still a great deal to be explained.^ ^ The confusion, so common in economic literature, between the gross share assigned to the co-operation of capital {Jtohzins) and net interest, has been fully discussed in my Capital and Interest (see the criticism of Lauderdale, p; 146 ; of Carey, p. 155 ; of Strasburger, p. 175 ; of Say, p 189, etc.) It will not be expected of me to give a complete theory of distribution in the passing, as it were! I purposely refrain from going deeper into the subject than is necessary for my special task, the development of the Interest theory. And for this it is. sufficient to sketch only in the broadest lines the principles which limit the gross share of capital, as against the shares of labour and uses of land that co-operate with it : our special task will be to lav down what is the state of the c ase as regards the gross share of capital. Moreover I hope that on this question of the shares allotted to the various factors, which I am compelled to treat in a very cursory way, the eagerly expected work of Wieser will very shortly shed a clear light. (Wieser’s Der Naturliche Werth, Vienna, 1889, appeared while this was passing through the press. — W. S. ) CHAPTEE X THE VALUE OF PRODUCTIVE GOODS. VALUE AND COSTS It has been almost a commonplace of economical teaching that the valne of gnnris is rAgnlatprl hy the costs of their prodnctioiL This doctrine has very seldom been questioned on grounds of theory/ but very often IfAvalidity has been closely hmited by the enumeration of exceptions/ and insertion of all sorts of saving clauses. In this contracted sphere, however, it has held almost unquestioned authority down to our own times ; it has a certain amount of support in practical experience, and, what is most serious, it seems to contradict the theory o f va.bip. jn.cq, put forward. For “Costs of Production” are uothiTior p.Irp t han the sum of productive goods which must .■he used up in the making of a good — the concrete capital consumed, the labour expended, and so on. Now to the question as to the ground and amount of value which a good has, our theory answers : it depends on the marginal utihty which a good is capable of render iug : that. is to sav. it depends on \t?^^uture, employment. But the other thedry''ahswef s ; it depends on the value of the productive goods consumed in producing it : that is to say, on the conditions of its origin . Putting aside this contradiction for a moment, and forgetting everything we have been taught as to costs, let us inquire impartially what 1 Among ol der writers it was disputed by Say . Traite, vol. ii. chap. ix. seventb edition, ”p. 404 : “ Ce qui nous ramene i ce principe deja etabli, que les frais de production ne sont pas la cause du prix des choses, mais que cet.t.e. cause est dans les besoins que lea prodnits peuvent satisfaire. ” In more recent litera- ture wbat M'Leod has said {Elemmis of Political Economy, 1858, p. iii) is worth notice. But the mat ter was really first grasped in its entirety bv Menger. Jevons. and Walras, whose books mark an epoch as regards the whole value theory, and of these again the work of Menger was the most profound. 180 THE VALUE OF PRODUCTIVE GOODS book in our theory of maroinal utility, logi call y carried ou t^ has_tO- say as to the valu p of pmrl na tive g-nof1rT^u1a.r fluctuations. But, besides these, we notice ay&i^^ence from complete identity which is constant and ^rmal. It is a matter of observation that the total value of a compip.tp. group of remote rank lags somewhat behind the value of its product, and in a definite ratio : and that, indeed,^ the amount of this difference in value is graduated according to th e time required to change the group of means of produc- tion into its product. If the value of the product, for instance, is £100, experience teUs us that the total value of the labour, uses of land, fixed and floating capital spent in producing it, is CH. X WHERE PRODUCTS ARE OF VARIOUS VALUES 185 something less than £100 — perhaps £95 if the production process lasts a year; perhaps £97 or £98 if it lasts only half that time. This difference of valu e is the crease, as it were . in which Interest is^au^t T explahaSonis^a subject by itself, with which we^^all have enough to do in following chapters. It would be very far from advisable to mix it up with our present inquiry, where we are dealing with the general relation between the value of means of production and that of their products, and for the moment we shall therefore entirely disregard the existence of this particular difference of value. Up to this point we have expounded the law which governs the value of productive goods under the simple hypothesis that each group of productive instruments permits of o nly one quite definite employ ment. But i n actual life th e cases in which this hypothesis correspond s with fac ts are very limited^ It is, indeed, characteristic of productive goo ds that they^^dmit of an infinitel y more various use than co nsumption goods: The" vasU^majority of them are adapted to several productive uses, while many of them, like iron, coal, and, above all, human labour, are adapted to thousands .of different uses. In theoretical research we must, of course, take note of these actual circumstances, and see whether they do not involve some modification of our law, that the value of a group of goods of remote rank is determined by the value of its product. Suppose, then, we vary the assumptions of our tyj illustration. A man possesses a great stock of groups of pro-" ductive instruments of second r an k (Gg)- From one sue group he can, at will, make a finished commodity of the kind^ A, or one of the kind E. or one of the kind C. Naturally h^ will provide for his various wants harmoniously, and w: therefore, by means of different parts of this stock, produce simultaneously finished goods of all three classes according to the measure of his requirements. In a scheme of provision that was really harmonious, the amounts produced would be so regulated that, in each kind, wants of something like the same importance would depend on the last sample of the kind, and the marginal utility of every sample would therefore be approximately equal. ^ Nevertheless there will be differences, ' This is demapded by the prinniplp, of “ftfionoinin r.onHiint .” See Wieser, Ursprung und Hauptgesetze des vyirthschaftlichen Werthes, p. 148. 186 THE VALUE OF PRODUCTIVE GOODS book in and e ven considftTa.h1p. diffp.rpinp.pis. of marginal utility , because, as we a lready know.^Jdie gradation of thft p.n-nnrfttp. wants ip any kind of want is not always uniform and unbroken . One fireplace in a room, for instance, wlU give me a very consider- able utility — which I may represent by the figure 200 — while a second fireplace would not be of any further use to me. Naturally, in providing for my wants, I shall therefore, in any case, stop at fireplaces when I have one fireplace with its marginal utility of 200, even if in other branches of wants the provision goes down, on the average, as low as a marginal utility of 100 or 120. To make our typical illustration true to nature, therefore, we must assume that the marginal utility of one sample is of different amount in the three kinds A, B, and C — say 100 in A, 120 in B, 200 inC. The question now is. In these circumstan p.pa what is tb^ v alue of ? After the practice we have had in drawing distinctions of a similar kind, we can give the answer without hesitation — the value will he equal to 100. For if one of the available groups were lost the o wner would naturally shift the loss to th e least J sensitive part : he would neither limit the produc tion of the k ind B, where he would lose a marginal utility of 120, n or of the ki nd C. where he would lose a marginal utility of 200. He would simply produce one less of the kind A, whereby his loss of weUbeing would be only 100. To put it generally: The value of th p pmrlnprivp. n ni t-adjusts- its elf tO the marginal utility and value of that nroduct which possesses^ the least arginal utihlv amnncr all the products wl^e ~pnjt d.uetioq ^e economically, have been e-mpin^.d jA.ll the ^relations which we found to hold as regards the value of means of production and of theii' products under the simple hypothesis of the single employment, hold, therefore, generally between the value of means of production and their ha^t mhwhle, prodncl, . And how does it stand with the value of the remaining classes of products. B and 0 ? This question brings us to the ^urce of the “ law of costs.” If, under aU circumstances, the marginal utility attainable within the kind itself were to decide, the kinds of goods B and C would possess a value diverging, as well from the value of 1 See above, p. 145. CHAP. X SOURCE OF THE LAW OF COSTS 187 tlie kind A, as from the value of its costs Go. B would have a value of 120, C a value of 200. But this is one of tho se of goods' is 'Shifted to another kind, and consequently the marginal ntilTT^y~7)F~the latter— beemaes the^j^ staadardTfoir'the former. ^ “That is~to say, if one of the kind C gets lost there is no occasion to give up the marginal utility of 200, which it would have directly afforded ; we can and will immediately procure a new C out of a productive unit Gg, and we shall prefer to produce one less of that kind of good in which the marginal utility, and with it the loss of utility, is least. This, m our illustration, is the kind A. In virtue of the opportimity of substitution offered by production a good of the kind C is therefore valued, not at its own marginal utHitv 200. but at 100, the marginal utility of the least valuable cognate product. A The same holds, of course, of the value of kind B, and would hold, generally speaking, of every kind of good which is “ cognate in production ” ^ with A, and has at the same time an immediate marginal utility greater than that of ^e kind A. This leads to several important consequences. ^ First of all .^ in this way the value of goods which have a higher individual Tna.Tgina.1 nt.ibty is put on a level with the va l ue o f the j “ marginal produc t ” — as we shall call that product which has the least marginal utility — and thus with the value of thp | means of production , from which both in common come ; the theoretical r»£..Vgl 2 TP anrl rinat s. therefore, holds in casa-^alsQ. But it is well worthy of notice that here the agreement between y ^ie and costs is brought about in a way essentially diff erent from the agreement between costs and marginal product. In the latter case the identit y was brought about by the value o f means of produc tionadapting" itself to the valuffoT th e product; the value of th e product was the determi ning, that of the means of produ ction the determined. In the present case, on the nontrary^ it, k the value of the product that must adapt itself In the last resort, of course, it adapts itself only to the value of another product, the marginal product of the cognate production ; but, in the first instance, it accommodates itself also to the value of the means of production from which it comes, and which are mediated ^ See above, p. 156. ® "Wieser, p. 146. 188 THE VALUE OF PRODUCTIVE GOODS book in by the substitutionary connection with the marginal product. Here the cond u'^ti'^" of flpsp.rihp s; as it, were^ a broken. Jine, First it goes from the marginal product to the means of production and fixes their value ; then it goes in the opposite direction, from the means of production to the other products which may be made from them. In the end, therefore, products of higher immediate marginal utility get their value from the side of thair mpans of production . To translate this from the abstract formula into practice. If we are considering what a I good B or C (generally speaking, a product of higher immediate I marginal utility) is worth for us, we must say first of all : It / is worth exactly as much as the means of production from \ which we could replace it at any moment. Then if we examine I further how much the means of production themselves are I worth, we come to the marginal utility of the marginal product A. But very often, indeed, we may save ourselves this further inquiry, as we already know the value of the goods that make up the cost without having to begin at the foundation and follow it from case to case ; and in all such cases we measure the value of the products in an abbreviated form, both accurate and convenient — that is to say, simply by their costs. Here, then, we h ave the whole truth about the celeb rated Lawrf Co^ As^aTTact people are right when they say that costs regulate value. Only they must always be conscious of the limits within which this “ law ” holds, and the source from ( which it gets its strength. It is, first, only a particular law. It holds only in so far as it is possible to obtain, at will and af; tlTe right time, substitutes through production. If there is no opportunity of substitution the value of every product has .to be measured by the immediate marginal utility of its own kind, and its agreement with the value of the marginal pro- duct, and with the intermediate means of production, is dis- turbed. Hence the well-known empirical proposition that the law of costs holds only as regards goods “ reproducible at will,” or “ freely produced,” and that it is simply aiT approximate law w Eic!r~does not bind the value of the goods that come un der it with slavish~~exactitu de to the level of co sts, but — according as production for the moment comes short of demand or runs beyond it — permits of fluctuations now on one side, now on the other. CHAP. X THE LA W OF COSTS SECONDARY 189 But it is still more important to emphasise, in the second place, that, even where— tbe-4a^ of cos ts hnlHs . costs are not the final hut only the intermediate cause of A'alue. In the last resort they do not give in il miv products, but receive h , from them. In the case of productive goods whicli have only a single employment this is perfectly clear. That Tokay is not valuable because there are Tokay ^^neyards, but that the Tokay vineyards are valuable because Tokay has a liigh value, no one will be inclined to deny, any more' than that the value of a qu icksilver mine depends on the value of quicksilver, the wheat field on the value of wheat, the brick kdn on that of bricks, and not the other way about. It is only this many- sided character of most cost goods — their capacity of being employed in many different uses — that gives the appearance of the contrary, and a little consideration shows this to be an appearance and nothings more. As theji OQn .- tefle.c ts -tli e suu '^ ravs on to the earth, so the many-sided costs reflect the value. which they receive from their marginal product, on to their ot her produc ts. The principle of value is never in them, but outside them, in the marginal utility of the products. The law of costs is not an independent law of value ; it only forms an incidental case inside the true universal law of marginal utility. It is simply the great counterpart to the law of Com- plementary Goods. As the latter disentangles and explains those relations of value which result from the temporary and causal collocation — the simultaneous co-operation of several goods to a common useful end ; so does the Law of Costs for the value relations of those goods which act in temporary and causal scqiicncc — the w'orking of goods after one another and " through one another to the same final goal. If we think of 'i o • o the value relations of goods that work into one another as a J much -tangled net, we might say that the former law < entangles the meshes in their length and breadth, while latter disentangles them in their depth ; but both fall un the all-embracing law of Ma,rmna1 Utility, and are nothing special applications of that law to special problems. BOOK IV PEICE CHAPTEE I THE FUNDAMENTAL LAW Exchanges are not made simply for amusement. People who take the — not always trifling — trouble to exchange the goods which they possess for other goods, do so for a rational and material end, and, in nine hundred and nuiety-nine cases out of a thousand, this end is to better their economical condition by the exchange.^ Whether this end be attaine d, and in what degree it be attained, de^iends naturally on the current condi - tions of exchange, particularly on the prices which the parties get as equivalent for their goods. It is, therefore, a perfectly natural thing that the motive which gives rise to exchange in general, namely, the striving after economical advantage, should maintain a commanding influence in the fixing of the exchange prices. In what follows I mean to inquire how prices are deter- ' mined under the assumption that all who take part in the exchange act ej-clusively from the motive of pursuing iheir T immediate economical advantage in it . The law which we \ shall arrive at in this way I have already,^ for very good reasons, called the fundamental law of the formation of price. I am perfectly aware that, in practical life, this law does not exactly obtain. For, although the motive of self-advantage is almost never absent, and is almost always the most prominent motive, still, in price transactions, other motives do very often get mixed up ; such motives as humanity, custom, friendship, ^ Menger, Grundsdlze, p. 153. Of course now and tlien exchanges may be made simply to show some person a kindness ; perhaps to conceal a present, or a charity in the guise of an exchange. But such cases form only a quite insignificant minority. ^ Orundzugc, part ii., in Conrad’s Jahrhucher, vol. xiii. p. 4&t). O 194 THE FUNDAMENTAL LA W BOOK IV vanity, or the influence of outside institutions, such as govern- ment taxation, union regulations, boards for fixing wages, and the like, give them another direction than that they would have taken if exclusively dominpited hv self-n.d vantage . Such motives, indeed, scarcely ever get the upper hand of the other to the extent of making us conclude an exchange which would cause us positive economic loss ; but they often make us decide to be content with a less amount of advantage than we should have got in steadily pursuing our interests. I have on the same occasion ^ expressed myseK with all clearness on the theoretical and practical importance of the admixture of these other influences, and I shall only now briefly sum up what I then said. In actual life this admixture of motives causes certain modifications of the fundamental law of the formation of price, and the statement of these modifications cannot be neglected in any accurate and complete theory of it. But if all that is wanted is to grasp the characteristic features of the formation of price, it is enough to put forward the " fundamental law ” above mentioned. For just as, among the motives . that determine price, that of striving after self- advantage in exchange has the lion’s share, s mdop.ci the lion’s share in the theoretic explanation of the pbp.nnTn p.na of priee fall t o the “fundamental law” here stated And it is suf- ficient for us in our present task, as we have not to pursue the theory of price as an end in itself, but only so far as is necessary to establish the theoretical connection between tke elementary phenomena o f su bjective value and the complicated phenomena of interest . In this law we obtain a principle which is not minutely accurate, but is amply sufficient for the further development of the theory of capital. Before going on to state the peculiar laws of price, it may be desirable to preface them by some considerations that may, more accurately, unfold the content of the fundamental motive which forms the assumption and basis of the whole of the following inquiry. In exchange transactions the decisions made always turn on two points : these are — (1) whether, in a given state of things a man should exchange or not ; and (2) i f he decide to ^ Grundziige, p. 480. CH. I MEANING OF EXCHANGE WITH ADVANTAGE 195 ft;cr,ha.ngp,. what form he should trv to crivp in thp. tf.rms of the g^xchange . Now in making these decisions it is obvious that the man who looks to his own immediate advantage and nothing else, will act according to the following rules. First, he will exchange only if the exchange brings him an advantage . Second, he will rath er e xchange~ibr'a~ CTeater~lid^ntage than forj^less. Thi rd, be widl^TatheTexdlangeloif a small ad^htage than not^xchange_at_a,lI It scarcely need be shown that these three rules are dictated by our fundamental motive, and constitute the practical sub- stance of it; what does require elucidation is an expression that recurs in them aU, “ to exchange with advantage.” The meaning of the expression obviously is — to exchange in «np.h a way that ^ bp. p.YP.h anger gains more in wellbeing from the goods, he gets than he loses in the goods-he-^es ; or, since the importance that goods have for life and wellbeing is ex- pressed in their subjective value, to exchange in such a way that the goods received pn.ssp..ss a greater .suh|pptive value than the goods parted with. If A owns a horse and is willing to exchange it for fen casks of wine, it can only be because the ten casks of wine have a greater value for him than his horse has. But, naturally, the other party to the contract thinks exactly in the same way. He, on his part, will not give up the ten casks of wine if he does not get for them a good that has a greater value for him. He will exchange his ten casks for A’s horse only if the wine is worth less to him than the horse is. From this we get an important rule. An exchange is economically possible only between person .s w ho pnt a different value, even an opposite value, upon the commodity and upon the price equivalents^ The buyer must put a higher, the seller a lower, estimate on the commodity than he does on the equivalent. Indeed the interest which the two parties have in the exchange, and the gain they get from it, increases as the difference between their estimates increases; if the difference ^ It will be observed that our author does not confine the word Price to Money price,. but applies it to the equivalePt good or goods obtained in exchange for what is, pre-eminently, the good — the object of demand frqm buyers, and of supply from sellers. The convenient word Prdsgut I render by “price equivalent,” or simply “equivalent.” — W. S. 196 THE FUNDAMENTAL LA W BOOK IV decreases their gain decreases ; and if the difference disappears, and their estimates coincide, no exchange is, economically, possible between them.^ It is easy to see that, under the regime of the division of labour, there must he inmimerahlp. chances of opposing estimates. and therefore innumerable opportunities of exchange. That is to say, as each producer makes only one or two kinds of articles, and these far in excess of his own personal requirements, he has at once a superfluity of his own products and an absence of all others. He will, therefore, ascribe to his own product a low subjective value, and to other products a relatively high subjective value. But, conversely, the other producers will ascribe a high value to all products which they have not, and a low value to their own products of which they have too many, and here we have in the fullest degree that relation of opposite valuations which is most favourable to the effecting of exchange. Another idea that comes out in what has been ^aid we may follow to its logical consequences. To one consulting his own advantage an exchange, as we saw, is economically possible only when he estimates the good to be acquired more highly than tlie good possessed. How, obviously, this will more readily occur the less value he puts on his own commodity, and tlie more vahm hft pu ts nu the equivalent . A man who values his horse, subjectively, at £50, and values a cask of wine at £10, has, economically, a much greater possibility of exchange — or, as we shall say in future for brevity’s sake, is much more “ capable of exchange” — than another who values his horse at £100 and a cask of wine at £5. The former, obviously; can proceed with the exchange if six casks are oflered him for his horse, while the latter must hold back unless something over twenty casks is offered him. If a third party again values his horse at £40 only, and a cask of wine at £15, obviously he would be economically capable of concluding an exchange if even thi’ee ^ Say, e.g., that A values his horse at five casks of wine, while B values it at fifteen, then, if the horse goes for ten casks, each gains an amount of value repre- sented by five casks of wine. If A values the horse at eight and B values it at twelve, each gains only a value of two casks. Finally, if both agree in valuing the horse at twelve casks of wine, B, of course, would be glad to get the horse for ten casks, or for any price under twelve casks, but A, naturally, would not give it him at that price. See Meuger, Grundsdtze der Volkswirthschaftslehre, p. 155. CHAP. I THE MOST CAPABLE EXCHANGER casks were offered him Generally speaking, then, that ex- changer is the most capab le ” wh^ pu^'The- least Tal tte on his own comm odity in companso n with that offered him h r exchange, or, what is the same thing, puts the highe st value on the other commodity In. co mparison with the commo^y wl iich he offers in exchange for it. Now that we are sufficiently acquainted with the meaning and content of our “ fundamental motive,” we may proceed with our proper work, and consider what are the normal effects which this fundamental motive exerts on the formation of price . In this part of our work the method already piprsued by several distinguished economists seems to me by far the most convenient : first, by typical illustrations to show how . \ under certain definite assumptions, jrice, is and m ust hp. I determined , and then to separate the accidental surroundings | of the illustration from what is universal and typical, and I fo rmulate the latter into laws . I shall begin with the simplest typical case, the determination of price in isolated exchange between a single pair of exchangers. CHAPIEE II ISOLATED EXCHANGE A PEASANT, whom we shall call A. requires a horsg. His individual circumstances are such that he attaches the same value to the possession of the horse as he does to the possession of £30. A neighbour, whom we shall call B, has a horse for sale. If B’s circumstances also are such that he considers the possession of the horse worth as much as, or worth more than £30, there can, as we saw, be no exchange between them. Suppose, however, that B values his horse at considerably less, say at £10 . What will happen ? First, it is certain that there will he an exchange ; in the assumed circumstances each of the contracting parties can make a considerable profit by the exchange. If, for instance, the horse changes hands at £20, A, who considers it worth £30, makes a profit of £10, and B, who gets £20 for an article worth only £10 to him, gets the same amount of profit. They will, therefore, in any case, according to the proposition “ rather a small gain than no exchange,” agree on making an exchange at a price advantageous to both of them. The question now is : How high will this price goJ As to this it may be said definitely : The price must at aU events be les^ than £30 . otherwise A would have no economical advantage, and would have no motive for going on with the exchange. And it must at all events be highp. r than £10. or there would be no use in the exchange to B, and perhaps even loss. But the particular point between £10 and £30 at which the price will be fixed cannot be determined beforehand with certainty. Any price between the two is, economically, possible ; a price of £10 : Is. or a price of £29 : 19s Here, then, is room for CHAP. 11 ITS UPPER AND LOWER LIMIT 199 : higgling^’ According as in the conduct of the any amount of transaction the buyer or the seller shows the greater dexterity, cunning, obstinacy, power of persuasion, or such-like, will the price be forced either to its lower or to its upper limi t. If both parties have equal skill in bargaining, the price will be fixed approximately midway: that is to sav. about £20. • There is no difficulty in putting this briefly in the form of j a general proposition. In isolated exchang e — exchange between / one buyer and one seller — the price is determined somewhere ^ between the subjective valuation of the commodity by the J buyer as npper limit , gnV»jQp.t,ivp vabi ation by the seller ' as lower limit. CHAPTER III ONE-SIDED COMPETITION First : of o ne-sided competition of Buyers . Accommodating the conations of our illustrationto the requirements of the new typical case, let us assume that A^ finds a competitor, whom we shall call A 2 , already in the field, and that he also has the intention of purchasing the horse. The circumstances of this competitor are such that he counts the possession of the horse worth as much as £20. What will happen now ? Each of the competitors wisRes to buy the horse, but only one, of course^ can buy him. Each of them wishes to be that one. Each, therefore, will try to persuade B to sell the horse to him, and the means of persuasion will be to bid a higher price. Thus ensues the familiar phenomenon of mutual overbidding. How long will this last ? It will last till the rising bids have reached th e-^^^^alna tion of t he least ^g^aR Ie^m p etitor. wlioT^ this case, is A 2 . So long as the bids are imder £20, A 2 , act- ing on the inbtto “ father a small gain than no exchange,” will try to secure the purchase by raising his offer, which attempt, naturally, A^, acting on the same principle, will counteract by raising his ofiier. But A 2 cannot go beyond the limit of £20 without losing by the exchange. At this point his advantage dictates “ better no exchange than a loss,” and he leaves the field to his competitor. This is not to say that the price A, pays must be just £20^ It is possible that B, knowing A^ to be in urgent want of a horse, will not be content with £20, and wiU try, by holding back and by skilful bargaining, to extort a price of £25, £28, or even £29 : 19s. The one thing certain is that the pr ice cannot exceed £30 (the valuation of Aj who concludes the CHAP. Ill ONE SELLER AND SEVERAL BUYERS 201 purchase) and cannot be under £20 (the valuation of Ag, the excluded competitor). Assume n ow that, in addition to A^ and A^, three other ^uvers T^^. A,. A., compete for the horse, and that their cir- cumstances are such that they count the possession of the horse equivalent to £22, £25, and £28 respectively. It is easy to show, in the same way, that, in the ensuing com- petition, A 3 will bid to the limit of £ 22 , A 4 to £25, and A 5 to £28 ; that the most capable competitor, Aj, will always be the successful one; and that the price will be fixed between £30 as higher limit, and £28 — the valuation of the most capable of the excluded competitors — as lower limit. The results of this investigation may therefore be expressed in the following general proposition : — In one-sided competition of buyer s — where there is one seller and more than one buyer — -the most capable competitor will be ( bp pnrcbagpj ; that is, the one who puts the highest value on the commodity he wishes to buy in comparison with the good he wishes to sell ; and the price will lie somewhere between the valuation of the purchaser as higher limit, and the valuation of the most capable among the unsuccessful com- petitors as lower limit — always understood that the price can in no case be lower than the subsidiary lower limit of the seller’s own valuation. Comparing this proposition with the result arrived at under the former typical case, we see that competition of buyers has the effect of narrowing the sphere within which price is determined, and narrowing it in the upward direction . Between A and B the limits within which price was determined were £10 and £30 ; by the added com- petition the lower limit was moved up to £28. Second : of one-sided competition of Sellers . This forms the exact converse of the foregoing. Entirely analogous ten- dencies lead to entirely analogous results — only in an opposite direction. The statement of this need not detain us long. Suppose that our friend A is the only buyer, and that five jdealers, whom we sh a ll call B,, B„ B,, B^, and Br, are compet - ing to sell him a horse . We assume that all the horses are equally good, but Bj values his horse at £ 10 , B 2 values his at £12, Bj at £15, B 4 at £20, and B 5 at £25. Each of the five 202 ONE-SIDED COMPETITION BOOK IV rivals tries to utilise the present as the sole opportunity of sale, and endeavours to secure a preference over his competitors by underselling, as in the former case by overbidding. But as no one will care to offer his commodity for Ip.s.s than what, it, is worth to himself, will cease offering at £25. B, at £20, B 3 at £15 ; then B^ and Bj will compete for a while till, hnally, at £12 Bg finds himself “economically excluded,”^ and Bi alone keeps the field. The price at which he remains a seller must necessarily be higher than £ 10 — otherwise there would be no use in the exchange, and therefore no motive for it — but neither must it be higher than £ 12 , otherwise Bg will continue his competition. In general terms, then, we have the following proposition. In one-si ded com pp.tition of sellers — where there is one buyer and more than one seller — the most capable competitor will be the actual seller ; that is, the one who puts the lowest value on the good he wishes to sell in comparison with the com- modity he wishes to buy ; and the price wdl lie somewhere between the valuation of the seller as lower limit, and the valu- ation of the most capable among the unsuccessful competitors as higher limit.^ Compared, therefore, with the case of isolated exchange, where, according to the first formula, the price had to lie between £10 and £30, the sphere within which price is determined will be narrowed by the competitions of sellers, and narrowed in the downward direction. ^ Menger, p, 183. Always without prejudice to the second or subsidiary upper limit formed by the valuation of the buyer, which the price can in no case go beyond. Where there is anything like full competition of sellers, however, this is seldom of practical importance. CHAPTER IV TWO-SIDED COMPETITION The p.aRp. of twn- sided competition is the most common in p/^.nnormV, it is t,hp, mo sl. imp or tant in the development of thp. Law of Price. It demands, therefore, our most careful attention. The t}^ical situation which the present case assumes may he represented by the following scheme. It shows us ten buyers and eight sellers, each of them wishing to buy or seU a horse, and it tells us at the same time the degree of the subjective valuation put upon the horse by each of the exchangers. It will be seen that the figures which represent these valuations are very different, and this exactly corresponds with facts. Indeed, the individual relations of want and provision for want, which regulate subjective value, are so very various that it would be difficult to find two persons who had an entirely similar opinion about the value of any one thing. BtrvEKS. Sellers. A, values a horse at £30 El values a horse at £10 (and win buy at any price under) (and will sell at any price over) -^2 35 £28 E2 33 „ £11 As 33 33 £26 E3 33 „ £15 ^4 33 33 £24 E4 33 ^17 As £22. Es 3J ^ „ £20 ^ Ae * 53 £2r.ji 33 „ £21;l0s.;i3 Ar 33 33 £20'/ ^ E, 33 „ £25 As 53 33 £18 Eg 33 „ £26 A9 33 33 £17. Aio 33 33 £15 To complete the scheme, it must be added that all the. competitors appear simultaneously in the one market : that all 204 TWO-SIDED COMPETITION BOOK IV the horses offered for sale are of equal quality ; and, finally, that the buyers and sellers make no mistake about the actual state of the market, such as would prevent them from really pur- suing their own egoistic interests.^ We ask now. What wil l hap pe n in th is situation ? The circumstances of Aj are such that he considers a horse to be worth £3 0 to him ; it would therefore be to his advantage to buy even at £29 ; and it is quite certain that any of the eight sellers would be glad to sell him a horse at a price so advantageous to them. But, evidently, Aj would be a very poor business man if he rashly bought at such a high price. For his self-interest demands from th e excha nge not merely a profit, b ut the ^eatest possible profit. Instead, then, of buying at the highest price — which, all the same, he might do in the worst possible case — he will prefer to begin by offering a price as low as his least capable rivals, and will only raise his offer when, and in the degree that, it is neces- sary to save himself from being shut out of the market. In the same way Bj, who, economically, could quite well sell at a price of £11, and at that price could very easily find buyers, will carefully hold back from offering his horse at the lowest figure which he would accept, and will not reduce his price below what he must take if he is to keep his place in the c om petition, jit mav he assumed, then, that the transac tion w ill begin with th e buyers hold ing back and _ .offering _lp^y prices, and with the s ellers hold ing bac k and asking hig h, priceai. ^ If, e.g., a buyer erroneously imagines the number of horses brought to market to be much less than it really is, U mav very well happen that h e hastily consents to pay a higher price than he would have found .necessary if he had given better attention to his own interests. The influence of errors like this on the formation of price must not, of course, be overlooked in a theory of price, but where we are merely trying to bring out the simplest fundamental law it is not necessary to go into such details. See Grundzuge, as before, part ii. p. 486. 2 T he more experien ced both parties arCj and the more familiar with the con- dition of the market-t he shorter will be the time s pent in “ tr ying the m aakfit” by preliminary offers. In an old and well-organised market competitors will save themselves the trouble of making offers that are not meant to be taken, and will make their first offers at least somewhere near that zone within which the market price will finally be fixed. Th e extreme lim it of t his curtailment is . given in th^'ijfixed prices ” of sellers. In this case, trying the market is entirely dispensed with, and sellers undertake at one throw, as it were, to hit the very zone into which the condition of the market will force the price. They m u st try CHAP. IV SEVERAL BUYERS AND SEVERAL SELLERS 205 Suppose the buver.s bpgin with an nFfer of £ 1 It is at once clear that — putting aside the case of gross error as to the condition of the market — the buying cannot be concluded at this price. For at £13 all the ten buyers would be willing to buy, since all of them put a greater value on the horse than £13; Irut, at that price, only two horses, those of and E,j. could reconomically) he offered for sale^ Now evidently Bj and. B., would be very poor sellers if they did not make use of the active competition of buyers to raise their price, and the others would be as poor buyers if they let the best chances of pur- chasing be snatched away by two of their members without attempting to obtain the preference by bidding a price some- what higher, but still advantageous to themselves. Exactly, then, as in the case discussed in last chapter, the surplus buyers, will be w^eeded out by means of mutual overbidding . How long will this weeding process go on ? At any price under XI 5 all ten buyers can compete. From that point the least capable competitors must, one after _ another, withdraw, from the cmnpe tvtioiL At £15 Aj,, is knocked out, at £17 Ap, at £18 Ag, at £20 A-. But as the bids rise on the one side, the number of those sellers who, eco- nomically, become capable of selling increases on the other side. At any price above £15 Bj may seriously think about selling, above £17 B 4 , and above £20 B 5 Thus the marked dispro- portion, which existed at first between the horses demanded and the horses actually offered for sale, is graduallj^ reduced. At £13 there was an effective demand for ten horses, and only two could, economically be offered ; while, at any price over £ 20 , only six horses are demanded and five offered, the majority t of buyers over sellers being thus reduced to one. So long, however, as the rival buyers are in the majority, and this fact is accurately known in the market, there can be no final settle- ment. For, on the one hand, the sellers have always the chance, and the temptation, to take advantage of the excess of buyers and stand out for higher prices ; and, on the other hand, to hit this zone quite exactly ; for if they put the price lower they lose their profit, while if they put it higher the buyers in the market get supplied by other competitors, and the sellers are left with their commodities. Fixed prices , however, are less common, in the open market than in shops , where selling is never conducted under the full pressure of competition, and where, consequently, any mistake in the price asked is not so hazardous. 206 TWO-SIDED COMPETITION BOOK IV the miitiially opposed interests of the rival hiiyp.ra noTnpftl them to Jaid still higher again st each ptbfx. Obviously, Ag would scarcely consult his own interests if he were calmly to look on while his five rivals went off with the five cheapest horses, and left him no chance of an exchange, and, therefore, no chance of a profit.^ But, at the same time, no oue of these rivals would allow Ag to purchase one of the five horses most “ strongly ” offered for sale. For, if so, the man who withdrew in favour of Ag might indeed purchase a horse, but only under less favourable conditions — the conditions, that is, offered by the most conservative sellers Bg, By, and Bg, and at a price which, at least, exceeds the subjective valuation of £2 1 : 1 Os. that Bg puts on his horse. Thus if the buyers know their own interests, the whole body of them wiU feel impelled to continue their bidding against each above the level of £20. Finally, the situation becomes essentially different when the rising bids have reached the limit of £21 . At that price Aa is compelled to ceas e biddin g, and t here are now only, five sellers against five buyers. These buyers can all be satis- fied simultaneously, and there is no occasion for further com- petition among themselves : on the contrary, as against the sellers, their common interest is to close at the lowest possible price. The bidding of buyers against each other, which hitherto has prevented the final settlement, now comes to an end, and the bargains may be concluded a.t the p rice of £21^ But, th ey need not be concludeff-aLAha t price. The sellers may possibly be stiff and refuse £21, in hope of a still higher offer. What will happen in this case ? First of all, the buyers, rather than have a fruitless errand and go away without making any exchange, will bid higher. But their limit is now very near at hand. If the sellers stand out for a price abo ve £ 22, A.; must give up all id e a of purchase, and there wiU be five sellers against four b uyers.^ One of the sellers, then, will have to fall out, and as no one would care to be that seller there will — from motives quite analogous to those which before prompted the surplus buyers to overbid each other — ens ue a, ^ If the horses of Bj to Bj are sold, the most capable seller remaining is Bg, ■who values his horse at £21 : 10s. — that is, higher than Ag. As we know, then, an exchange between Ag and Bg is economically impossible, and the same is true « fortiori of the. less capable sellers By and Bg. CHAP. IV RELylTION FAVOURABLE TO SETTLEMENT 207 mutual iiTH^ ftp. spiling a-mong the si^rplns sp.np.r.s, till sucb time as the fifth seller meets a huve iL: this will be the case some- where under the limit of £22.^ Indeed, in the present case, the limit must go still lower. So long as a price over £21 : 10s. was possible, there would be a sixth possible seller in the person of Bg ; this would give the sellers a majority of one over tlie five buyers, and compel them to offer under each other, if they are not to be shut out from the exchange. In this competition the weakest must first go to the wall, and this fate will overtake Bg the moment that his rivals are content to take a price below the level of £21 : 10s. — at which figure the number of competitors on either side will be equalised, and the level of price found at which the competition may cease. Thus assuming, as we do in this illustration, that each competitor knows what is the condition of the market, and intelligently foUows his own interests, the limits within which the price must necessarily be det^ermiuer ! are narrowed to £2 1 and £21:1 Os. ; those being the only limits within which there occurs the relation favourable to the final settlement — that all who are able to take a share in the business find it their advantage to do so^ while all who do not find it their advantage, the unsuccessful competitors, have no power to prevent the others from coming to terms.^ Let us try now to apply the results of these lengthy analyses to our theory of price. We notice, first, that what decides succes s ^mppiitinn is, as in the case of one-sided competition, the degree of " capability ” for exchange, Dn either side ^ It need scarc ely be sa id that the gradual bidding Up of buyers, and the. gradual under-offering of sellers, do not usu ally take place i n two separate and succeeding stages, but generally occu r simuItane niiHl y. ^ In the nature of things the result shown in our abstract scheme will be the more exactly realised in practice, the better known the total condition of the market is to all interested ; that is to sav. the more organic the market, and tbe_ more publicly the negotiations a re conducted. Where, on the other hand, as is usually the case, transactions are conducted in groups that are, indeed, in com- munication, but are yet somewhat separated from each other either in space or time, the relations of competition that would prevail over an entire market will, naturally, not be quite active in the single groups, and this ha.s for re.siilt that the prices formed in the single groups are frequently only more or less app ro.x imate to the ideal market price represented in our scheme, without necessarily exactly coinciding with it. 208 TWO-SIDED COMPETITION BOOK IV it is the most capable competitors wlio ooirifi to t.p.rms^ namely, those biiyers who put the highest value on the commodity (A^ to Aj), and those sellers who put the lowest value (Bj to Bg), while all less capable competitors are ex- cluded. And, indeed, if we look more closely, we shall find that tlie series of snccessful competitors includes all competing paii-s. arranged by c a pability, between whom there exists the rplflti'nn iipppsigar y for exchange, viz, tb nt. th e IniypT considers Ihe 0OT'P^^'>^'b'ly •v yortk more than the seller does. In our illustration Ag considers Bg’s horse worth more than Bg himself does, and, accordingly, they can exchange with each, other.^ Ag, on the other hand, values the horse of By at £21 only, while Bg values it at £21 : 10s., and therefore they cannot come to terms — and still less can those competitors who are less capable. Very closely related to the grounds on which are decided the successful competitors in the struggle of competition are, secondly, the grounds on which is decided the market pric^ that results from this struggle . This price — to recur to our illustration — cannot, in any case, be higher than the valuation of Ag, nor less than that of Bg ; otherwise the fifth buyer in the one case and the fifth seller in the other would not have come to terms. But, again, the price cannot in any case be higher than the valuation of Bg, nor less than that of Ag ; otherwise in the former case a sixth buyer would begin com- peting with the other five buyers, and in the latter case a sixth seller competing with the other five sellers ; the equi- librium would thus be destroyed, and the overbidding and under-offering would inevitably be continued till such time as the price was forced within the limits already indicated. To put these results in general form; — In two-sided com- petition the market price is determined within a latitude of which ttip npppv limit, i.s p. Qnstituted bv the va luation of the Iqpt buyer who actually exchanges (the last buyer) a nd that of th , p, moHf, fLa. pah I^ seller excluded^ /the first excluded seller), and the laffifiX-limit by the valuation of the least capable seller who actu- ally effects a sale (the last seller) and that of the most capable buyer excluded (the first excluded buyer). The meaning of this 1 Or with one of the more capable c'ompetitors, but in no c^ase with a weaker one. See more e.xactly on this point in my GrundziXge, p. 499. CHAP. IV ANALOGIES WITH SUBJECTIVE VALUE 209 double limitation is that, jn every onse. it is the .narro wop b'niiJ: i.hat deeidesd If, finally, we substitute the short and signi- ficant name of “ Marginal Pairs ” for the detailed description of the four parties whose competition determines the price, we get this very simple formula : yhgjnarbct price i s limifprl a-url rlatpr- mimai by t.bc subjective vnlnnt.imis of t.bft two M n rgTrnTl~-P!riTs, This suggests a number of refiectioli^ ' Tlic tirsi, thing tbnt, .strikes ns is t h e, analogy between thg formation of~price~~aTrdHihe--fermntd(yrr^^ -^lue. We saw that the subject!^ value of miy~^od, unaffi:cted by the more important uses to which s ingle mem bers of the same stock might be put, was a “ marginal value^’^^^^^^aTvahie deter- mine d by the good’s marginal ut ilitY. or that utility which stands on the very limit of the economically^efmissible. we see tlnrt-^wgcy i-rrarkt^ price is a “ marginTrh price, ” — a price determined by the economical relations of those competing pairs_:ivhicli, also, stand on~the very limrC~Df exchan^ability. Ii is easy to see that the analogy here is no chance coincidence, but one that results from closely-related and internal causes. In the case of subjective valuation, the moti ve of economical advantage demanded that the available stock of goods should be employed in satisfying the wants that stood highest on each man’s scale, the last of the wants thus supplied indicating the “ marginal utility.” In the case of the formation of price, the motive of the competitors’ economical advantage demands that the pairs which are most capable on the scale of competi- tors should come to terms, and one of these again is the last, the “ marginal pair.” In the fo rmer case, the provision for all satisfactions more important than the marginal utility was assured without the particular good whose value was the subject of discussion, and the only utility dependent on this latter good was the last, the marginal utihty. In the latter case, all the contracting pairs more capable than the inavgriTar pairs may com e to terms at prices higher or lower, and here again it is o nly the fate of the last, t he mar ginal _p aiiv-that ^ In our illustration it is the valuation of the excluded parties A3 and 63. If, however, the valuatio.n of Ab, instead of being £21, had been £19, and that of Bg, instead of £21 :10s., had been £23, the limits would have been determined by the Valuation of the last pair who actually Kime to terms : the price would have been fixed between £20 and £22. 210 TWO-SIDED COMPETITION BOOK IV [ depends on the_ prirp, just rea ching a de finite hei£ht, neither greater nor less. Ahd,_jda ally, _ as in the former case the importance of the last dependent wantT^n virtue "of its dependent relation, gave the good its value, so, in the latter case, the economical circumstances of the last dependent pair — here also in virtue of their dependent relation — confer on the commodity its price. But this analogy does not exhaust the connections between price and subjective value. Of still greater consequence is the fact that price, from beginning to end, is the product of sub - je ctive valuations. Look back over what we have said. It is the relation of the subjectfaa valuation of commodity and price- equivalent which decides ItiB persons who may consider ifaw ofth thei r, while to com pete., either as bujfaFs or sellerTjthat is to say, clecidesAvhichparties are “ capable of exchange.’^^t is the same relation which decides on the degree of each com peti ton’ s capability, of exchange. With perfect exactness it decides for each man the figure at ^vhich his advantage calls him to join in the competition, and it decides, at~the same time, the limit at which he is beatSTra^d— ehhged-to-wvrthdluw 'frbin:^ As further result, it decides the parties -who. among the most capable competitors, act u.a.11y come to terms, ; it decides to which pair falls the role of being marginal pair ;^^d, finally, i t decides on. tbe , pric e at which the bargains are concluded, in the market. Thus, as a fact, in the whole course of the formation of price — so far as it is conducted on purely egoistic principles — ^^there is not a single phase nor feature which is not traceable, wholly and entirely, to the position of subjective valuations as its cause. And this is at bottom perfectly natural. For, as we know, t^ftse .subj aative — va,lua,tions point out w hether any ^ im portance, great nr little, attaches to a good as regards our economic wellbeing, and how great the importance is ; and, consequently, these valuations, wherever we acquire or part with goods solely with regard to our economic wellbeing,- mark out the natural, indeed the only poSsil^le compass of our trans- actions. We are, therefore, fully justified in defining price as the resulta,nt of subjective valuations put upon commodity k and price-equivalent withi ii_a^ market. ^ s > ^ Sax, who, in his theory of value and price, stands wholly and entirely on the fousadation laid by Menger, repeatedly atid with emphasis characterises market j CHAP. IV RESULTANT OF SUBJECTIVE VALUATIONS 211 Of course it is a resultant of a peculiar kind. The amoun t • of price is not the resultant of the sum, or of the n ypraffe of-aJ-l ^ t he valu a tions that come to the surfac e : io the forTmtioTi Ui J price these take very different share& >>ip T^>ne~ class of them has no effect on price at all : viz. thoskValu p^^^^Ti« mprio iw q 11 the unsuccessful competitors except ■ valuations made by all^ , SueJcoT the most_ capaMe__paii> It is aU the same whether there are no such valuations, or aa/c whether there are scores of them in the market ; they make not the slightest difference on the resultant price. In our illustration, whether there are unsuccessful buyers A7 to A^q or not, whether the category of the unsuccessful is composed of them alone, or of a hundred others besides, — so long as they cannot bid more than £20, it is easy to show that the resultant price will always run between £21 and £21 : 10s. The excluded competitors may increase the congestion of the i narket, but they are not factors in th at conditio n iiLthe_. market which determines the formation of price.^ A second gi'oup plays a very peculiar part in this resultant, VIZ. that consisting of the valuations of all the contract ing parties who actually come to terms, excln.qi vp. of the la.9t. What th^ do is simply to bind and neutralise each other. Eecur again to our typical illustration. If we inquire what, for instance, the presence of Aj contributes to the formation of price, we find . that he takes up one member of the opposing series, namely, Bj, with the result that now the formation of price proceeds exactly as if neither Aj nor Bj were in the market. Similarly it is not difficult to see that the efficiency ol; A, , Aq, and A, simply consists in cancelling the efficiency of . B. ,, Bgj and Bj_: if they are in tlie competition the resultant I price as an “ave rage o f in dividual valnes ” (Theoretische Ch-tnullegung der Staats- wirthschajt, p. 276 and passim). This expression, if given without commentary, is exceedingly unfortunate, indeed directly misleading. As may be seen from what follows above (and more exactly from what I wrote in my Grimdziige, pp. 505 and, particulars^ 522), the chara cteri stic thing, on the contrary, as regards the resultant price, is that it is an “average” ip the, nsnal .seii.se of the word . ^ At least under the assumi)tjon distinctly made in our inquiry, that the com- petitors who appear in the market have a correct knowledge of the condition of the market. If we depart from this assumption, the appearance of more than a hundred demanders might give rise to the erroneous opinion that there may be among them a great many persons of higher “capability,” and this might mislead Xhe few capable comhetitors who are present into rashly making higher offers. I 212 TWO-SIDED COMPETITION BOOK IV price falls between £21 and £21 : 10s.; if they were all absent A- and Bj would still make their exchange at a price between £21 and £21 : 10 s. And it is worth empha,aising that the cltgrcc of the subjective vnliintions made in this group is q uite ind ifferent to the result Aj, for instance, whose valuation, in our scheme, is put down at £ 30 , would cancel Bj not less thoroughly if his valuation amounted to only £25 or £22 ; and, conversely, suppose that his estimate were £200 or £2000, of this enormous amount absolutely nothing would affect the result- ant price except the sum, in any case, absorbed in neutralising Bj. If, however, the valuations of this group have no direct influence on the formation of price, it cannot be said that they are quite without effect When the valuations of Aj to A4 cancel those of B^ to B^ they have a twofold result. First, they prevent any stronger seller than B^ getting into the marginal pair which immediately determines the price. And second, they prevent the strongest sellers from cancelling the next strongest buyers— as they might do if not cancelled ali'eady — and they thus prevent any weaker member of the buying series than Ar, from getting into the marginal pair.^ The part played by all those exchanging pairs who are stronger or more capable than the last may therefore be accurately characterised in the following words ; Their valuations coi u- tribute-nothing directly to the formation of the resultant price. but they do indirectly, in so far as they neu tralise each othe£. and thus reserve tlie role of m argi nal pair for anoth er coup le. Finally, the real decision of price lies exc] usLvelv__wiJ±L^ * To show this, suppose we leave Ai to A4 out of our illustration. The position of the parties, then, is as follows : — Ag . A7 • A. . A.J . . £22 . £21 . £20 B., B:, £18 . £17 . £1.5 B5 Be B7 Bs £10 £11 £15 £17, . £2a . £21 :10s. . £25 . £26 Here we see that the last pair within which the economical conditions of exchange are pre.sent consists of As and B4. The buyers, therefore, are now represented in the decisive marginal pair by _a„we,ake r member, the sellers by a stidnger one. -Accordingly the limit of price, which in the last case stood between £21 and £21 : 10s., moves down to between £17 and £18. CHAP. IV EFFECT OF THE VARIOUS VALUATIONS 213 roup, ana tnat a smalL-Oiie— the, valuiLtions of the two ^ Tuarp ^inal paivs . All weaker competitors being, abs olutely, with - out influence, and all stronger ones cancelling each other, they and they alone are the directly effective components, and the market price is their resultant. At first sight it may appear strange that so fevy persons , and those so little conspicuous, should decide the fate of the whole market, but on closer examination this will be found quite natural If aU are to exchange at one market price, thp price must be such as to su it ah excha.Tifflrig partip.s ; and since, naturally, the price which suits the least capable contracting party suits, in a higher degree, all the more capable, it follows, quite naturally, that the relations of the last pair whom the price must suit, or, as the case may be, the first pair whom it cannot suit, afford the standard for the height of price.3 ^ Students of economic literature will not fail to notice an interesting relation in wliich. the above theory stands to certain doctrines that have for long obtained full recognition. When Thiinen — and with him the whole body of economic doctrine — said that the rate of interest was determined by the p roducti vity o f the “portion of capital last applied.” a nd t he rate o f wage b y the_ rejtupa of the “last worker em ployed in th e undertaking” ; or when, much earlier, the question as to which, among several costs, regulates market price was decided in favour of the “highest costs of production that were still necessary to provide for the market,” i.e. in favour of the “last seller,” — we recognise in all these, with- out difficulty, adaptations to special cases of the same principle on which we have built the doctrine of marginal utility and the theory of the formation of price. The only thing is that at that tim e economists were not ^et conscious jot thj6 univ ersal importance of these peculiar lines of thought. They meant simply to state a couple of special rules of limited range, while in reality they had hit upon the dominating Leitmotiv, which underlies the entire mechanism of industry carried on under the guidance of self interest, and which, therefore, runs through the entire formation of value and price. CHAPTEK y THE LAW OF SUPPLY AND DEMAND The zone within the limits of which the struggle of competi- tion forces the formation of price is, as we have seen, character- ised as lying between the subjective valuation s of the ma rginal pairs, and on this characteristic feature we have formulated our law of price. But this zone has a second characteristic feature : it is that i n which exactly as ma ny commodities a re ■off^rl fhr salft a s are wanted to "^urjp iase^^ Dr, to use the common expressions, in which supply and demand are q uan- tit atively in equilib rium. In our scheme, at a price which did not rise to £21 more horses were demanded than were offered ; at a price which rose above £21 : 10s. more horses were offered than were demanded ; while in the zone indicated by our law of marginal pairs — that between £21 and £21 : 10s. — the position requisite to end the competition was reached, and at p rice exactly as m any horses were asked as wer e offere d How, if it should be thought preferable, the formulation of the law of price may be based on this second characteristic feature, and it will then take the following shape : Th e mark et pri^is found in that zone in which supply and demand quanti^iti’^y bSance each other. This formula is as correct as the other. It indicated the same zone in another way. But it is less expressive (1) in so far as it only points to the level of the determining zone in ^a roundabout way. ^ I need scarcely say in so many words that it is not the number of persons wishing to buy and sell on which the formation of price depends, but the mass of commodities desired and offered, and that in the typical scheme it is only for simplicity’s sake that I have assumed each person to desire and offer for sale only one commodity, whereby number of persons and mass of commodities go •pari passu. CHAP. V ANOTHER FORMULATION OF OUR LAW 215 while, by our formula, the limits of this zone are directly and positively indicated ; (2) as it has to contend t o soin e extent with .the difRculty of hn.ving to use tlm .expressiona_Supp1y and Pemand, — for the ptotean ambiguity of these terms is sure to bring innumerable errors and misconceptions in their train, just as it has brought the terms themselves into thoroughly bad repute with many.^ Still, these drawbacks may very well be overcome by critical attention ; a nd there is no nbjp.etinn in my opinion, to treat the theory nf prir.e under the good old catchwords Supply and Demand, if care is only taken to avoid the errors and misunderstandings which so plentifully surround them, and to inform the old forms and formulas with new and clear knowledge.^ In one special case this sep.nnd formulation of our law of price is even the more exaet of the-twe r- In the vast majority of cases, the zone 'within which supply and demand ju^balance each other exactly -Coinnide..s --witlL...the zone whose limits are marke d out by the valuations of the mai^naT pairs. But there is one quite definite coincidence of circumstances in which it may happen that the equilibrium between supply and demand does not make its appearance within the whole of the last-mentioned zone, but only within a distinctly narrower part of that zone ; and, in such cases, the price is always fixed within these narrower limits. The very peculiar coincidence of circumstances which produces this result occurs very rarely indeed in economic life, but, among the cases where it does occur, t here is one that is very important for the theoretical explanation of interest , and for that reason, in spite of its somewhat “ exotic ” character, I must devote a few words to it. The casuistical conditions of this case are the following. Fi rst, there must be con siderable latitude between the valua- tio ns of the margina l paira This^wndition is most thoroughly fulfilled where all the competing exchangers come to terms (there being, therefore, no excluded competitors), and when, at the same time, the buyers, as a body, value the commodity ^ See my Orundziigc, p. 525. ■ On the relation of the above theory of price to the old doctrine of Supply and Demand, as well as on the truth and error contained in that doctrine, I hare already written at length in my Q-rundzuge, pp. 524-534 ; here it is sufficient to refer to that work. 216 THE LA W OF SUPPLY AND DEMAND BOOK IV considerably higher than the selleis do. If there are, for instance, ten buyers who each value the commodity at £10, and ten sellers wlio each value it, subjectively, at £1, obviously all the ten pairs can come to terms, and the zone which lies between the valuations of the last buyer and the last seller represents the wide latitude between £1 and £10. Secondly, that this latitude sh ould be narrowed do wn, the further circum- stance must be present, that the desire of the buyers is directed to an unlimited nu mber of goods, •whil e, at the same time, the total amount of means of nurchase must be strictl-y limited , and the buyers must be determined to spend the whole of this sum in purchase of the commodities in question — in the pur- chase of fewer goods if the price be high, in the purchase of a proportionately larger number of goods if the price be low. To put it in terms of our illustration. Say that each of the ten buyers is resolved to spend the sum of £100 in buying cotton goods; that is to say, at any price under £10 he will buy as many pieces as he can obtain for £100. And suppose that against this total competing demand of £1000 there is a supply of 200 goods, which their owners are inclined to let go at any price above £1. T t is easy to see that the price must be fixed at £5 the piece. For if the price were to be less, say £4, the 200 pieces offered would be purchased for £800, and £200 of the available means of purchase would remain unemployed. Here the owners, acting on the motto “rather a small gain than no exchange,” will continue bidding up against each other, and so raise the price to £5, at which figure the whole capital of £1000 finds employment If, on the other hand, the price were to be put still higher, say £8, only 125 pieces of cotton goods could be bought with the £1000 available, and 75 would remain unsold. Now, obviously, no seller (considering that the price remains profitable to him till it is brought down as low as £1) would willingly forego taking part in the exchange, and thus the sellers, in fear of being shut out, would offer below each other, a. nd the price would be pressed down to the equi - l ibrium point of £5. Inside the wider zone, then, of £1 to £10 — that determined by the valuations of the marginal pairs — t he necessity for equilibrium between supply and demand determines the price with much more exactitude, and fixes it at £5, that being the point at wln'cli, if the competitors follow CHAP. V IN SOME CASES A MORE EXACT LAW 217 their own interests without let or hindrance, the market price must be fixed. As we have already said, the extremely peculiar coincidence of circumstances necessary to this result occurs very seldom, but, as it happens, the cases where it does occur are very not,- nhle. One of these is the formation of the price of Money — which, however, does not concern us here.^ A second is. the. tormatiou of price in the T,ahmir market , a nd this is the case which we shall have to take up later on, on account of its close connection with the origin and height of Interest. It should, liowever, be carefully noted that, even in these two cases, the conditions under which this special form of the law of price appears are seldom met with in economic life in entire isola- tion. Thus the practical importance of such cases is stiU further diminished, and, if the recognition of them cannot well be ignored in the course of any theoretical exposition, stUl, as regards the infinite majority of cases, the first formulation of the law of price — that which determines the height of priee Ly the subjective valuations of the marginal pairs— mav be relied on with perfect confidence. T1iis form nlatinri is always correct. and, for the infinite nmioiity of cases, is sufficiently exact. Moreover, without losing its practical usefulness in the majority of cases, it permits of being still further simplified. Before going on to this, however, some other explanations are necessary. 1 Without being a blind adherent of the “ Quantit)’ theory.” I believe that , along with other important circumstances, the quantity of money, the amount of the supply of money, exerts a powerful influence on its p ur chasing pow er. But the supply of money has. exactly the peculiarity described in the text, that, rather than let money lie entirely unused, holders will be content with a comparatively unremunerative employment, and that, at the same time, the entire given quantity of money strives to realise itself in the purchase of an unlimited quantity of commodities — the more the better. CHAPTER VI THE INDIVIDUAL DETERMINANTS OF PRICE In the chapter before last we saw that price is determined at a level fixed by the valuations of the marginal pairs. We have still to ask, W hat; are the circumstances w hich determine whether jhis level itself is high_o^low^ ? The first few steps in the answer are very easy. It is clear at a glance that the two things which must have the decisive intluence on the position of the marginal pairs are the num h er and the intm.sitv of the desires or val nations oiiJ anth s ides . In this way. The level of the valuation of the marginal pairs will tend to be high when, on the side of the buyers, there are very high valuations, and, relatively, a great many of them, and when, on tlm side^ of the sellers, the low valuations are relatively few. For, in this case, the few low valuations of the sellers will be cancelled by a portion of the more numerous high valuations of the buyers, and since, after this is done, there are still buyers with a high valuation, while at the same time the only remaining sellei’s also have a high valuation, the marginal pairs on both sides are composed of persons with high valua- tions. On quite analogous grounds the level of the valuation of the marginal pairs will tend to be low when, on the aide of the buyers, there are (relativelvl few high valuations, and on the - ^de ofthe sellers thor p. a.rp._.(.rp.1fi.ti velvl many low valuations . If we single out the individual factors from the combined action of which, as we have shown, the vaktat ion level of the marginal pairs results, we get the following individual deter- minants of price : ^ — ^ T .shmilil Vilcfi to .say that I Iiere bringr fonMi' d the theory of t lie d eterminants aLpticS-OJilx-iiLthe biiefest af^e.pLtgines^ because the details of it have no imnie- CHAP. VI FACTORS OF DEMAND 219 1. The number of desires directed towards the commodity ( Extent of Demand .^ 2. The figures which the buyers put upon their valuations ( Intensity of Demand) . The latter, however, is not a simple matter. The figures in which valuations are expressed are in no wise simple expressions of the absolute amount of subjective value which the commodity has for the valuer. They only express a relation obtained by comparing two different valuations — ^that of.thgj commo dit y and that of the equivalent price. When we said in our scheme that A, values a horse at £30, that is not to say or prove anything of the absolute importance of a hors e to A’s wellbeing ; all that it expresses is the relation in which the value of the horse to A stands to the value of the money to A. It simply says that A values the horse thirty times more highly than he values one pound sterling. If, therefore, we wish — and this is the task in which we are at present engaged — to lay down the elementary factors in the formation of price, we must put down, instead of the combined amounts which make up the figures of our valuation, the elements out of which they are combined. ' These elements are two-^ first, the absolute amount of subjective value which the commodity has for the valuer ; 'aii3^“second, the absolute amount of the sub- jective value which the unit of the equivalent price has for the- valuer. And, indeed, they obviously work towards com- bihatioh in this sense, that the figures are high in direct ratio to the absolute value of the commodity, and in inverse ratio to that of the equivalent, and vice versd. Thus, in our scheme of the determinants of price, instead of the valuation figures, we have to lay down as the deter- minants of these figures — [а) The subjective valuation of the commodity by the buyers (which itself, again, according to the law of marginal utility already laid down, depends on the relation of wants and provision for want) ; and (б) The subjective valuation of the equivalent fricc hY the buyers." Since, undeFpresehl conditions, it is money diate interest for the theory of capital. Any one interested in the theory of price as such, I would refer to the full statement in Conrad’s Jahrhucher, vol. xiii. pp. 508-524. 220 INDIVIDUAL DETERMINANTS OF PRICE book iv that mostly serves as equivalent, and since, as we saw in a former chapter, the unit of money has a smaller subjective, value for the rich than for the l^oor, it is, in the last instance, the standard of comfort of the buyers which has the preponderating influence on the formation of this determinant.^ Continuing our enumeration we 'have — 3. The number in which goods are offered for sale ( Extent of Supply ). 4. The figures which the sellers put upon their valuations ( Intensity of Supply !. As in the former case, this latter determinant may be split up into two simpler factors — (a) The subjective valuations of the commodity by the sellers. (J) The subjective valuations of the equivalent pric e ly the sellers. These two find their own further determination according to the law of marginal utility. But frequently this leads to a very noteworthy peculiar ity. In the present condition of industry most sales are made by men who are producers and merchants by profession, and who hold an amount . o f their commoditie s entirely beyond any needs of their own . Consequently, for them the subjective use- value ^ of their own wa,re.s is. for the most part, very nearly nil ; and the figure which they put on their valuation (in which the subjective use -value is the standard element) also sinks almost to zero. Finally comes the result that, in such sales, the limiting effec t which, accord- ing to our theoretical formula, would Vip PVPrfpH V>y^tb p, val na- tion of the last seller, practically does not come into play, and price is actually limited and determined by the valuations of th^^ buyers alone. In other words : when goods are once ' 4>roduced, and the owner can do nothing with them for ...hia own per sonal want.c;, t.fifi y must. all' the" same, seek a market. To find-4his market the seller must, in the usual way, put his 1 The older theory Tvas misl ed by t his into substituting, for the de terminant “ subjective valuation of the equivalent price.” the “ability to pay ” of the buyers, which is not exactly false, but is very one-sided. See the more exact statement in Conrad’s Jahrhiicher, pp. 520, 527. * This, and not subjective exchange value, is the important thing for the formation of price. See the Grundzuge, p. 516. CHAP. ■- I FACTORS OF SUPPLY 221 goods at a price low enough to find hny(H\s for the whole stock he olfCT^f5r~ sale. In the case of a stock of 1000 pieces, for instance, he will find his market at a price which is somewhat less than the valuation of the thousandth buyer, and somewhat higher than the ^'aluation of the thousand and first If, now, the relations of production and ^ale are normal, the whole stock offered will, almost invariably, be taken off by the demand at a price which is far above the minimum use-value nf tbp. com- moditv to the sellers, and which, beyond the full amount of costs, brings them a business profit . If the circumstances, how- ever, are unfavourable, it may well happen that the seller must seek for his market at considerably lower levels of demand, and b e content to take prices which show a loss w hen compared with costs of production. But, as^a_rule,_evem those forced prices are still above the subjective use- value of the commodity to the seller, and the funcdqn of this icjnbjp cti ivp. u a&r.value,_aa lower limit of price, does not come into operation . It is only if the price should sink almost to zero that it would be checked in its descent by this latter limit, the valuation of the seller, finally coming into play. But it can scarcely ever come to this : in almost all cases the competition of buyers is suffi- cient of itself to stop the downward movement at a higher point on the scale. Thus, in regard to the prices actually established within a large and organised market, the law of price undergoes a great simplification . Of the four valuations which, as “ valuations of the two marginal pairs,” limit the zone within which price is determined, th e valuatio ns of the seller, for the reasons mentioned above, fall out altogether. But, if the buyers' are very numerous, the interval between the figures which two successive buyers put on their valua- tion is so small, that the zone limited by the figure of the last buyer and that of the first unsuccessful competitor, is narrowed almost to a point. And so far as this is the case it may be asserted, with sufficient exactness, of the economic exchange which goes on in large markets, that the market price is determ iripd bv the. V.a1n ation of the Last Buven^ 1 This may be a suitable place to finish the analysis of Scharling’s argument, which I began on p. 160. Scliarling explains (Conrad’s Jahrbiicher, vol. xvi. p. 542) that in all essen tial respects he can agree with my theory of prire ; only , he says, it does not go far enonghiT Mv “determinants." and even the deter- INDIVIDUAL DETERMINANTS OF PRICE book iv 222 miiiaiits of these determinants, do not go to the very root of the explanation ; tliere is still something wanting ; and this something, this Schlussstein or “ element which, in the last resort, determines the conditions for an exchange,” Scharling thinks that he has found in the “ exertion ( Anstre.naunn') which is spa r ed the ttia n who wishes ... to obtain possession o f a good by the fact that the good is transferred to him, in the case in question, by the other party in the exchange” (p. 551). If Scharling here were to mean by Anstrcngwig the toil of production which must otherwise be expended, directly or indirectly, for the acquisition of the good, his proposition would be positively false (see above, p. 160 in note), and this, indeed, Scharling himself seems to see and, indirectly at least, to admit (pp. 531, 554). But he goes on to give this expression a wider meaning. Under it he now embraces, among other things, the exertion which it c ost s to induce ag owner to part with his commodity (p. 554), or “ to meet competitors ” (p. 556), or “to meet other suitors by overbidding” (p. 558), or “ to overcome the indisposition of the owner to part with the good ” (p. 558), and so on. “The right of the owner to possess the good,” explains Scharling in the most significant passage of this kind, “ is the last hindrance which stands in the way of the buyer’s acquisition of the same, and this is now the thing to remove. The exertion which is required for t his determines the va lue, the conditions for the exchange ” (p. 658). Now, what kind of “ exertion ” is t his ? ■ Scharling himself speaks of it more than once with all desirable plainness (e.g. p. 555, line 15 ; p. 558, lines 5, 16, etc.) It consists .simply in the offering of a sufficiently high or higher price , in a bidding up or bidding higher. And now I ask : First, is there any justification, material or linguistic, for calling the offering of a price an “ exertion,” and, specially, for calling the offering of a price of £20 twice as great an exertion as offering a price of £10 ? Second; is- the “exertion ” which consists in offering the purchase price, e.g. at an auction, snared the purchaser, or must he not rather take the exertion on himself if he is to obtain the good ? And, third and principally, is it explain- ing the formation of price, or going round about the explanation in a manifest circle, to account for the height of price by the amount of the exertion which the meeting of competition and the inducing of the owner cost, and then explain this exertion again as the offering of a sufficiently high or higher price ? Is this not rather to say directly ; — the price is high when and because much must ho paid to get the good, and it is low in another case when and because but little n eed be paid. ? Who will be inclined to accept this as “ der Weisheit letzten Schliiss,” as the long -sought -for coping-stone of the theory of price? — And now one more remark in case of misunderstanding. I am very far from deny- ing that “difficulty of attainment” or “amount of toil of production” may, and very often actually does, afford one single important secondary determinant for the relation of want and provision for want, thereby for the height of marginal utility, and so, finally, for the amount of value. But this determinant only works in the way, and within the limits, which I have indicated in my theory (see in particular the statement of the “ exceptional case,” where the amount of a pain or strain averted determines the value of a good, Grundziige, p. 42, and especially the statement of the influence of costs of production on value and price, p. 61 ; then pp. 521, 532, 534). On the other hand, the more extensive claim that Scharling puts forward with so much emphasis (vol. xvi. pp. 551, 652), that diffi culty of attainment by itself alone is the last universal determinant and measure of value. I can only most emphatically reject. CHAPTEE Vll THE LAW OF COSTS In the sphere of price, as in the theory of subjective value, we find a law firmly rooted in economic literature and accredited by conimon experience. It tells us that the market price of goods reproducible^ at will tends. .±o. e qjmlise itself, i n the loj ig-T-nn, v^n' th Costs of rroduction . Tlie following perfectly valid line of argument is usually adduced in proof of this. The market price of goods reproducible at will cannot, in the long-run, be maintained either much above or much below their cost. If at any time the price of an article rises appreciably above the cost, its production will be particularly profitable to the undertakers. This will not only induce the latter to extend their already flourishing businesses, but will encourage new undertakers to enter the same remunerative branch of industry. Thus the amount of product brought to market will be increased, and finally — according to the law of supply and demand — a fall in price will ensue . If, conversely, at any time the market price falls below costs, continued pro- duction will show a loss ; many undertakers will reduce their output ; the supply of the commodities will be reduced ; and this, finally, in virtue of the law of supply and demand, naust lead to a raising of the market prica Eound this law of costs has gathered a great mass of theo- retical detail,^ which may, for our purposes, be left entirely on ^ Thus the question as to costs of production or costs of reproduction ; whether, in the case of a variety of costs, it is the hi e ;hest, the low est, or an average cost t hat is to h e taken_M standard ; what elements are to be reckoned among costs, and so on. 224 THE LA W OF COSTS BOOK IV one side. Our whole interest is-eeatrBfLd n the question as to the position wh inh the law^.sn wp.11 Rop.rp.dited by exp erience, takes in the s-v^tem atic theo ry . of price. Does it run counter to our law of mai^ginal-pairs or not ? Onr nnsw pr is tha t it does no t. It is as little of a con- tradiction as we before found to exist between the proposition that the marginal utility determines the height of subjective value, and the other proposition that the costs determine it. The line of thought which, in both cases, leads to the solution of the apparent contradiction is the same, feature for feature ; except that, in the present case, in virtue of the intervention of exchange, — in virtue, that is, of the translation of the phenomena out of individual economy into social economy, — there appear richer developments at every station on the line of thought. In what follows I shall try, as briefly and clearly as possible, to describe the concatenation between Value. Price, and Costs,: and I think I am not exaggerating when I say that, to understand clearly this connection, is to understand clearly the bett er part of Political EconomY- The formation of value and price takes its start from the subjective valuations nut upon finished products by their con- sumers. Tliese valuations determine the demand for those products. As supply, over against this demand, stand, in the first instance, the stocks ol hnished commodities held hv^ rb- ducers. The point of intersection of the two-sided valuations, t he valuation of tl^ie marginal pairs, det e rmines, as w e know. t lie jiricR . and, of course, determines the price of each kind of product separately. Thus, for instance, the price of iron rails is determined by the relation of supply and demand for rails ; the price of nails, by the relation of supply and demand for nails ; and, similarly, the price of every other product made out of the productive good iron — such as spades, ploughshares, hammers, sheet-iron, boilers, machines, etc. — is determined by tlie relation between tl m supply and demand which obtains for these special kinds of products. To make this perfectly clear, let us assume tliab tlie relations between reqiiirements and .<;tncks of the various iron products — and, accordingly, their prices to begin with— a re very various ; that the price of a quantum of commodity which can be made out of one and the CH. VII CONCATENATION OF VALUE, PRICE, COSTS 225 same unit of productive material^ — for instance, from a cwt. of iron — varies from 2 s. for the cheapest to 20 s. for the, dearest class of products. These prices are the result of the position of the market at the moment, and we have first assumed that the stocks of products (the supply! are a q'iven quantity . But they are only for the moment a given quantity. As time goes on, they are always getting supplemented from production, and this makes them a variable quantity. Let us follow the circum- stances of this production. For the manufacture of iron fabrics producers, of course, require iron.^ Under the system of division of labour they must buy this in the iron market. The manu- facturers represent this demand for iron. As jegards the e xtent of the demand, it is clear tha,t every producer will buy as much iron as he reqiiires to produce that amount of the commodity which he may expect to sell among his customers. But how wil l it be as regards th e intensity of the demand ? Obviously no producer will give more for the cwt. of iron than he can get for it^ from his own customers in the shape of price; but, up to this point, even in the worst case, he can and will compete rather than let his production come to a standstill for want of raw material. The manufacturer, therefore, who can profitably employ the cwt. of iron if he gets 20 s. from his customers will be a buyer in the iron market up to the price of 20 s. as maximum ; he who can profitably employ the cwt. of iron at 16s. will, naturally, not buy at a price over 16s., and so on. In this way the market price which each producer of iron wares gets for his particular wares (or the share of the market price which falls to iron according to the law of complementary goods) furnishes hiin with the p o nfrptp yalnat.inn whipy 1-LP. ling in his mind when joining in the demand fo rjron. ^ To simplify the matter, we shall omit for the moment the co-operation of any other complementary means of production. ^ Again, for simplicity’s sake, I leave out the other requisites of production. ® It must be remembered that here we are making abstraction of the co-opera- tion of other complementary means of production, as Labour, Tools, Coal, etc. If otherwise, of course, according to the principles laid down above (p. 170) on the value of complementary goods, we should have to put a portion of the value of the product to the account of the other co-operating goods, and assign only a quota of the product’s value to the iron. But, in that case, exactly the same relations, as are shown in the text to exist between the value of iron and the full value of the product, would hold between the value of the iron and that quota of the product’s value. Q 226 THE LA W OF COSTS BOOK IV The s upply, which stands over against thi s demand, consists of the stocks of iron held by the mine-owneri~ahd ironmasters. These stocks will pass, in methods familiar to us, into the possession of the most capable buyers, and at a price which, approximately, corresponds to the valuation of the last buyer.^ Suppose the stocks of iron are sufficient to meet the demand of all those buyers who value iron from 20 s. down to 6 s. per cwt., tll£. ^al na tion _of th e last buyer, and thus the marke t pH ^of the iron, will sta.nd at 6s. And now we have to consider the causal connectiou which has ended in this price. It runs, in the clearest pos.sible way in an unbroken cha i n f r om value a nd pxricp. of products to vpl ne and price of costs — from iron wares to raw iron, and not con- j ^"ersely^ The links in TEe~chain are these. The, valuation which consumers subjectively put upon iron products forms the first link. This helps, next, to determine the figures of the I valuation — the money price at which consumers can take part in the demand for iron products. These prices, then, deter- mine, in methods with which we are now familiar, the resultant price of iron products in the marke^t for such pro- ducts. This resultant price, again, indicates to the producers ' the (exchange) valuation which they in turn may attach to the productive material iron, and thus the figure at which they may enter the market as buyers of iroj i. From their figures, finally, results the market price of iron. But still another and very important connection may be gathered from all this. It is that, here, we have simply the great law of marginal, ^ utility fu lfilling itsel f. Ac cording to that law the ava il able stock of goods is, successively, conducted into ^ the most remunerative em^ym ents — put to the mo st advan tageous uses, — and the last use to which the goods are put "^termines their v alue. In any individual ^onomy the most remunerative uses are seen to be those which express the most urgent subjective wants, and the value which emerges, as result of these individual relations, is purely personal subjective value. In the mor e extended_sp]iere__ of a market, on the other h and, everything is referred, no longer directly to^s ub- jective wants, but to those wa nts as Tnp.di>.t,p.fl b y mone y — money being, as it were, the ne utral commoTi de un miuntion - f o r * ^ See above, p. 221. CHAP. VII FROM PRODUCT TO COSTS 227 wan ts and feelings of various subjects which are not im medi- at ely commensurable . Here emerge, as the most remun- erative employments, not tho se which express t he wants absolutely most urgent, bu t those which are represented by the hi ghest money vnluatlo n"; that is. the ^st paying employments;^ and the value which results is objective exchange value. Thus it is, first of all, with iron products. In their respective markets they pass to the best paying buyers, and the price which expresses the valuation of the last buyer determines their market value and price. But so it is also, in the second nlace, in a slightly roundabout way, with the “ cost good,” iron, itself. In the iron market it goes to the best paying producers, and the valuation of the last of these determines its price. But here the producers are simply mediators. In their conducting of the iron to the best paying consumers, the stock of iron really passes successively to the most remunerative forms of consumption, and the last of these forms pro vided for determines — through the valuation n amed by the last producer who enters the market as buyer— the mark et price of the cost good, ir on It is not this cost good , then, that dictates its fixed price to the products that proceed from it ; on the contrary, it receives its own price hv the, medium of the price of its products, in conformity with the great law of marginal utility, according to which the available stock is forced into the most remunerative employments, and receives its price from the money valuations of the last of these. But connected with this is a series of subsequent pheno- mena, which, obviously, have given rise to the opinion that costs exert a causal influence on the price of products. So long as the price of various products made from iron varies between 20s. and 2s., while the price of the unit of iron stands at 6s., it is an evidence that the economical principle which should guide the stocks of iron into the most remunerative employments is not fully carried out. Iron is being used in employments where the products fetch only 2s. or 3s., where, accordingly, the use is less than the “ last ” economically per- missible ; and, on the other hand, there are still numerous ^ That tt Rse two, unfortunately, are not usually the same I have shown at length in Conrad’s Jahrbiicher, pp. 510-513, when discussing the causes and effects of this fact. 228 THE LA W OF COSTS BOOK IV employments unprovided for, where the products would obtain a greater value than 6 s. If, for instance, the market price of an iron product stands at 20 s., it is a proof that only those consumers of that product who value it at 20 s. and upwards are actually purchasing, while other consumers, whose valua^ tions range from 18 s. down to 6 s.. are not supplie d in the mari^ t. Similarly with products whose market price stands at 163. ; there will be an unsatisfied layer of demand, with a use for the product corresponding to the prices 14 s. down to 6 s., and so on. Now this must be corrected — ^^and the e nterpris e of Iinrlertakftr.q will nsnally r»r.t hp long in . supplying the needed correction. The production of those iron wares, the price of which still stands above 6 s., will, under the inducement of the premium offered by the difference between price and cost, be increased till all those employments where the utility is greater than the amount of 6 s. are supplied. Of course this increase of supply has the effect of always reducing the level in which the “last” buyer is found, and thus the market pri^p ginVg^ till such time as the money valuation of the last buyer, and with it the market price, comes to the normal level of . 6 s. Conversely, where iron has been put to employments whose products fetch less than 6 s., the loss that ensues will prevent more iron being thus employed. This will be brought about by a temporary suspension or limitation of the production of those iron wares, the market price of which is under 6 s. T his limita - jjoTi n£ supply will soon have the effect of raising the price to 6 s... and now, as the state of the case demands, the commodity, iron, will only be attainable by those buyers who can use it to make products that will fetch at least 6 s. Thus, from above and from below, all iron products come together at the price of 6 s., the amount of their costs ; but, qu ite evidently, the cau se of this is ne t that the cost good, iron, can force i ts own arbitrary fixed price on its products, but that al l the produ cts involved, including the cos t good, iron, conform to the law of m arginal utility, find their way successively into th e most remunerat ive employments, and togethex -xece ive their price a s regu late by the last of. these.^ 1 It is possible that- the amount of costs may itself be shifted — raised, for instance — by the process of correction just described. It may happen, that is to say, that in order to satisfy the demand, hitherto unsatisfied, which is desirous CHAP. VII FROM PRODUCT TO COSTS 229 Empirical proofs of this may be had ia abundance. It is a very well known fact that active building of railways raises the price of rails, and, through this, the price of iron; that the present strong demand for copper wire in electric lighting^uts up the price of coppe E In these cases iTis evident that the upward movement of price takes its start from the finah products, and is transferred from these to the cost goods. But the objection will probably suggest itself to many readers, that there are also cases where the movement of price is from costs to nroducts . The stocks of iron, for instance, of which we have been speaking in our illustration, are not a fixed amount, but are smaller or greater according to the circumstances of iron production. Now if there is an exten- sion of this production, and the supply of iron increases, its price will certainly fall, and that from causes peculiar to the iron ; and this fall in prices will drag down the price of iron wares. Does the causal connection here not run from co.sts to price of products ? To answer this objection we have only to carry the con- catenation, of which we have hitherto examined only a few links, back to its beginning. It is quite correct to say that stocks of iron are not a fixed amount, but the varying result of a production which is cap able of being extended or limite d at will. For the productionof iron two things are necessary, — mines, and (to put it shortly) direct and indirect labour. The mines are a given quantity, and cannot be devoted to the production of anything but iron. On the other hand, the quantity of labour available as a whole for economical emplojnnent, is an amount given and limited by the current state of population, but this is not the case with that particu- lar labour which is employed in the production of iron. Labour is a productive power capable of being employed in any number of ways, and all the branches of production carried on in the community compete for it. Who or what, now, is it that decides what exact proportion of the original productive powers of buying iron products at a higher price than 6s., so much iron is taken out of the iron market that the stock is uo longer sufficient for the demand that is willing to pay just 6s. This latter, then, will, of course, be shut out by the stronger competitors, and the market price settles at a higher figure than 6s. — another proof that costs are not the fixed point to which the price of products adapts itself, but vice versd. 230 THE LA W OF COSTS BOOK IV at the disposal of industry, namely labour aorl osp r of lanrl^ jg employed in the production of iron, and who and what is it that decides on the value and price of the unit of those productive powers ? Here, then, for the last time, is repeated, in the elements of all economy, the movement which we saw in the case of final products and intermediate products. The original pro - dji ptdve powers of the nation force themsplvas into the most smunerative employments one, alta r another., and receive their value and price from tho last of these. As little as, perhaps even less than, any other good have they any a priori fixed value : they receive it only from the opportunities of employ- ment. Whether the day’s work is worth 2 s. or 6 s. depends on the worth of the product which can be turned out in the day’s work, and, indeed, on the “ last ” product — the one worst paid — for the production of which there is still enough labour of the necessary quality left, after all the better paid employ- n^ts have been supplied. ' Production mav be compared to a giair t_ pump. Every branch of want has its separate pipe sunk down to the great reservoir of the original productive powers, and competes with all the other branches of want in trying to draw its supply by suction from that reservoir. Every branch has a different power of suction, the power increasing with the number and the remunerativeness (that is to say, in the case of organised exchange, the money value) of the employments it embraces. In the nature of the suction pipes, too, there is a difference. Many are quite simple : others have independent intermediate lengths, that convey the pressure that comes from the want, as it were, by stages ; and, in correspondence with that, the productive powers which supply the want are raised by stages. The sumle extends still furtlier. Such wants as demand personal services for their satisfaction, attract labour quite directly, according to the payment which they can and will give for them. Such wants, again, as demand material goods for their satisfaction, get these supplied, first, by payment of a market price which is remunerative in itself, and then the remunerative price of the products must attract the productive p owers to their manufacture. Sometimes this is done through one or two, sometimes through twenty or thirty, members. In CHAP. VII PRODUCTION A KIND OF GIANT PUMP 231 our illustration, human demand asked and paid for iron wares : the market price of iron wares attracted people to the purchase of iron : the price of iron, finally, attracted the original prp - ductive powers to the production of iron. In the case of other consumption goods, the number of intermediate members, or, to keep to the terms of our comparison, the number of intermediate lengths in the suction pipe, may be double or twenty times as great. But the principle of the movement, and what chiefly interests us, the result, is always the same. - Whether there are many or few intermediate mem- bers may hasten or hinder the result, hut it cannot weaken__or strengthen it : in the end every want, according to the power expressed by its money valuation, draws to itself, mediately or immediately, the productive powers required for its supply. To supply the wants of the rich innumerable productive powers are always active, even if, simultaneously, at other points of the economy, there is want both of men and goods. The reason of this is that the high figures, which the rich are able to offer for the satisfaction of their wants, never fail to exert and continue their attractive force through all the stages of production, right down to the reservoir of the original productive powers. Th us all human wants exert, as it were, a suction p ower indicated b y the fig ures of their valuation . Now, that layer of wants whiclTTs willing and able to pay, say, 20s. and upwards, for the day’s work devoted (mediately or immediately) to its satisfaction, is soon entirely provided for. After it those layers, in succession, draw supply to themselves which can and will pay the day’s labmir with 18s., 16s., 14s., and 12s., even down to 10s., 8s., 6s., and 4s. If, at the limit of 4s., the entire stock of original powers is required and is taken, this decides two things : — All wants which will not, or cannot, pay the day’s labour devoted to their service at 4s., remain unsupplied ; and the market price of the day’s labour will stand at the fi gure of the last buyer, namely, 4s. But if, as we may rather assume, theavailable quantity oF labour is greater than this, the wants of still lower levels may be supplied. The last needs — mediate or immediate — which are supplied may be those that pay the day’s labour at 2s. only ; and, in conformity, the market price of labour also will be fixed at this lower figure of 2i i. And, 232 THE LA IV OF COSTS BOOK IV indeed, this market price wUl be a general one : the uppermost layer will not be paid 20s., and the lowest layer 2s. for the same work or the same commodity : the market price will he the same for all buyers. And now we come in sight of the answer to th e doubt suggested by ouTformer i llustration. Suppose that the price of the day’s labour is 2 s., an3~the price of a cwt. of iron, which takes three days to produce, is 6 s. Suppose now that, all of a sudden, new and productive mines are opened? or some great improvement in process discovered, which makes it possible to produce the cwt. of iron in two days’ labour. What is the consequence ? So long as the iron and its products maintain the old price of 6 s., only those wants in the department of iron wares are supplied which are able and willing to pay 6 s. for two days’ work ; that is, to pay the day’s labour at the rate of 3s., while all round, in all other departments of want and branches of production, that layer of want is supplied which pays only 2s. for the day’s labour. On economic principles — which are willingly carried out by undertakers of industry, who ^ are always ready to seize the chance of a profit when offered opportunities of employment which pay the day’s re than 2s., and have hitherto been unsupplied, supplied : more original productive powers will, be invested in the production of iron ; apd tha - supplv of iron and iron products will be inr.rpasp.d till such time as, here as elsewhere, that level of wants which is willing A to pay the day’s labour at 2 s. is satisfied, and therefore the cwt. of iron, which costs two days’ labour, fetches 4s. Parallel with this, of course, the price of iron and iron products ^ goes down to the level of 4s. And all this is not in opposition to. but in real fulfilment of our law of Marginal Utility, of which the law of costs, rightly understood, is only a special expression suitable to a special group of phenomena. 1 It must not be forgotten that we are simphfyiiig the matter by leaving out of account the co-operation of other complementary goods in the production of iron products. If we were to take these into consideration, and assume, for instance, that, to change the iron into the iron product, the expenditure of other two days of immediate or mediate labour was necessary, then 8s. , as the price of iron product, would correspond to 4s. as the price of iron, and of this, according to the law of complementary goods, 4s. would be reckoned to the productive good, iron, as its share. them — those work at moi will now be accordingly. CHAP. VII DISTURBING CAUSES 233 If- — what is practically inconceivable — production were carried on in ideal circumstances, unfettered by limitations of place and time, with no friction, with the most perfect knowledge of the position of human wants . requiring satis- faction, and without any disturbing changes of wants, stocks, or technique, then the original productive powers would, with ideal and mathematical exactitude, be invested in the most remunerative employments, and the law of costa, so far aa we can speak of such a law, would hold in ideal completeness. The complementary groups of goods from which, in the long- run, the finished good proceeds, would maintain exactly the same value and price at all stages of the process ; the com- modity would be exactly equal to its costs ; these costs to their costs, and so on, hack to the last original productive powers from which ultimately all goods come. But this ideal svm^ metry is traversed by two disturbing j;auses. The^'''fii^r~of these I may call by^j^he general name of Fr iction. A lmost invariably there is some hindrance, great or small, permanent or temporary, to the due investment of the original productive powers in the employments and forms of consumption which are the most remunerative at the time. In consequence the provision for wants, and likewise the prices, are somewhat unsymmetrical. Sometimes it is that individual branches of want are, relatively, more amply supplied than others ; so that, for instance, in woollens, those wants are supplied which pay the day’s labour indirectly at Is. 8d. only, while it may be that, in copper goods, no wants are satisfied which can- not pay 3s. for a similar day’s labour. But sometimes it may be that groups of productive materials, successively transformed till they are changed at last into the finished commodity, are not equally valued at all stages of the process. If we compare th e means of production to a, Rtrea.-m . we might say th at the .strearu.is. not, as it should he, of equal breadth at all stages of its course: from some disturbing cause or other there may be dams at certain particular points, and leakages at others; and these cause an unsymmetrical divergence of price compared with the priees obtained at stages before and after, or, as it is usually con- ceived and expressed, a divergence of the price of a product (or intermediate product) from its costs. Thus it is, in our illustra- tion of the iron, when production is suddenly cheapened from 234 THE LA VV OF COSTS BOOK IV 6s. to 4s. As a consequence the production of iron is at first increased, and presses down the price of raw material, wliile the products of iron may still for some time maintain a price greater than their costs. But gradually the increase of supply presses forward to the later stages of production, — passes from the production of raw materials to the manufacture of final products, — and by reducing the price here also to 4s. restores the disturbed symmetry between pidce and costs. In practical life such frictional disturbances are innumer- able. At no moment and in no branch of production are the^ entirely absent. And thus it is that the T.aw of Costs is recognised as a law that is only approximately valid.: a law riddled through and through with exceptions. These in- numerable exceptions, small and great, are the inexhaustible source of the undertakers’ profits, but also of the undertakers ’ es. The second disturb ing c^use is the Lapse of Tim e — the weeks, months, years which must stretch between the inception of the original productive powers, and the presentation of their finished and final product. The difference of time, in exerting a far-reaching influence on our valuation of goods, makes a normal difference between the value of the productive groups standing at different points of the production process through which they must all pass ; and is, therefore, a difference to be kept quite distinct from the unsymmetrical divergences caused by frictional disturbances. It is this second disturbing cause which gives rise to Interest. Our further task will be to intercalate the theory of interest in its place within the value and price theory already outlined. BOOK V PEESENT AND FUTUEE CHAPTER I PRESENT AND FUTURE IN ECONOMIC LIFE Present goods are, as a rule, worth more than fattire goods of like kind and number. This proposition is the kernel and centre of the interest theory which I have to present. All the lines of explanation, by which I hope to elucidate the phenomena of interest, run through this fact ; and round it, both essentially and superficially, is grouped the whole of the theoretical work we have to do. The first part of mir planation will trv to prove the truth of the propn.sit.iou : the second will then show that, out of the fact, spring, naturally and necessarily, all the manifold forms which the phenomena of interest take. In the present book we have to take up the first part, and I shall try to go into it with that minuteness which is due to the cardinal importance of such a proposi- tion. To this end we sViall firgl. all , -maVp .g p rpnorgl anr- vev of the relations between present and future in human economy — a subject, obviously, of the highest importance, but one which, strangely enough, has up till now attracted but scanty scientific attention.^ 1 A history of the theory of this subject — which I have no intention of writing here — would probably start with Adam Smith’s emphatic opposition of “ present enjoyme nt” to “futu r e profit” (ii. 1). In more recent times there are some good observations on the subject in Senior {Political Economy, third edition, p. 58) under the headings of “ Abstinence ” and “ Capital ” ; in Rae {New Principles of Political Economy, quoted in Mill’s Principles, book i. chap. xi. ) ; and in Menger {Grundsdtze der Vollcswirthschaftslehre, p. 127). The first, so far as I know, to treatjt as a subje ct by its elfLwas-Jeyons {Theory of Political Economy, 1871, second edition, 1879). Jevons’s work is exceedingly interesting and suggestive, but, on the whole, it is rather imperfect — as could scarcely be otherwise in a first attempt, and on a field of speculation hitherto all but un- touched. It shows a good deal of incorrectness, a good many contradictions, and, in particular, many obvious gaps. Jevons may be said rather to have 238 PRESENT AND FUTURE IN ECONOMIC LIFE book v In the present we live and move, but our future is not a matter of indiffe rence to ns^ and our desires are, with reason, directed towards a wellbeing not limited by the present. It is only as the logical carrying out of this general principle that we set before us, in our economical arrangements, the larger object of providing for our future as weU as for our present weUbeing. As a fact, the f uture has a great place m opj - economical provision : a greater, indeed, than people usually think. It is, of course, a commonplace, but, all the same, it is a truth seldom seen in all its bearings, that our economical conduct has exceedingly little reference to the present, but is, almost entirely, taken up with the future. ( shown, by a bold stroke of genius, that here was a new circle of ideas waitinfr to be taken up , than shown what was to be done with them. Closely following Jevons, without going beyond their master, are, quite recently, Launhardt {Mathemalische Begriindung der Volkswirthschaftslehre, 1885) and Emil Sax {Grundlegung der theoretisehen Stoats wirthschaft, 1887, pp. 178, 313). A little before these G. Gross {Die Zeit in der Volkswirthschaft, in the Zeitschrift fur die ges. Staatswissenscha/t, 1883, p. 126) had made a well-meant suggestion, — which, however, was by that time carried out by Jevons and then by myself, — that the element of time in economical theory was worthy of a fuller consideration. Finally, as concerns mv own work, I owe it to myself to say that I arrived at my views on this subject in comnlete-indeiLejidence. and altogether uninfluenced by Jevons — and, naturally, still less by later writers. I first became acquainted with Jevons’s writings in 1883, — shortly before the printing of my Capital and Interest , — when completing the historical material already collected in that work by a review of the latest English literature on the subject. Th e principles of i ny own theory of capital, on the o ther h and, were laid down by me as early as 1876 . In that year I first suggested them in a youthful work never published. In later writings I gave many plain, if still cautious, hints of my leading ideas {e.g. in Rechte und Verhdltnisse, p. 68 in note bn the phenomenon of Abniitzung, pp. 76 and particularly 109, 115 in note, on the computation of the future use, and p. 152 ; in Capital and Interest, pp. 257, 276, 343, 424, and particularly on p. 428 where I formulated the programme of my positive theory in saying that the explanation of interest was to be deduced from the influence of Time on human valuations of goods). The cautious tone which I still deliberately adopted in giving these hints was due to my desire not to compromise my new ideas by any premature or incomplete formulation of them. I meant that they s hould not go before the public till I was in a position„tQ produce them-a.S-a, finished whole, all harmoniously fitted in to a system of carefully planned economic doctrine. That is why I preferred to work for ten years at laying the foundation of the present theory by completing the theory of goods ( 18811. the criticism of the theories of cap ital (1884), and the t heory of vf^m (1886), rather than snatch, as I might easily have done, at the glory of priority by publishing original but still immature ideas a decade earlier. Moreover my theory, if it t ouches that o f Jevo ns at several points , by no' means agrees with it in essence ; and in the most important points, such as the explanation of interest, it is in distinct opposition to h is. CHAP. I JEVONS 239 Let us clearly understand what this latter statement means. It means that our anxiety in the present is to have / pt nnr di.^pn.cial, in the future, means for the satisfaction of / wants that will not emerge till the future. In other words, it means that pleasures or pains, which we will only experience in the future, determine las now to provide goods or services, which, again, will only assert their use in the future. But how is it possible that feelings which are not yet felt, and therefore feelings which, essentially, do not exist, can be motives to will and deed ? Xow, as a suggestive \vriter has said, we do rint - ijide ed possess the gift of feeling future sensations, but we possess the other gift of anticipating them in imagination.^ Either it is 1 When Jevons calls that intellectual phenomenon which impels us to provide for future wants and to value future goods, a “ present anticipated feeling ” {Political Economy, second edition, p. 37), the expression is very apt to be mis-^ leading. We must distinguish between two fundamental ly distinct—things. which Jevons seems to me not to have sufficiently kept apart. It is one thing to represent to ourselves, or imagine, a future pleasure or future pain, and to estimate its presumable intensity on the ground of this imagination. It is quite another thing to experience, in this imagination itself, a pleasure, an actual present pleasure of anticipation. To give an example. I think of taking a pleasure trip to Italy. From personal experiences, or from travellers’ tales heard or read, T represent to myself the pleasures of the journeY, and I put the intensity of these plea sures so high , that it seems to me worth the sacrifice of £50 to realise them’ But, beyond this, in picturing to myself the future pleasure of the journey, a real present pleasure of anticipation is kindled. Thinking on the journey affords me an actual pleasure, but, in any case, it is an entirely different pleasure and, in all probability, its intensity is ever so much less than the pleasure of the journey itself. If I value the latter at £50, the pleasure of anticipation is, perhaps, not worth more than lOs. — of which it may be sufficient proof that I am willing to lay out so much money, and no more, in buying a book of travels that lifts me into the pleasant world of thought. The concrete figures here are of no moment. Ho constant or normal quantitative relation can ■ be established between unanticipated pleasure and a pleasure of anticipation : t^ relation will vary in the wildest way according to persons, motives, and circum- stances. With dreamy imaginative men, for instance, who are apt to be strongly excited by their own imaginings, the pleasures of anticipation may be relatively strong ; with hard-headed unimpassioned men, on the other hand, they will be disproportionately weak. For our nurpose it is sufficient to establish two things first, that the intensity of the represented future pleasure and that of the actually felt pleasure of anticipation, are two different quantities and second, in the vast j majority of cases, the intensity of. the pleasure of anticipation is less than the \ anticipated pleasure, not by a few per cent, but infinitely. ' The question now is : When we value future goods, and when in conformity with that valuation we are making these economical determinations on which we provide for future wants, with which of these two intensities have we to do ? On 240 PRESENT AND FUTURE IN ECONOMIC LIFE book v that wft hn,vp! alrofidv in the past, once or many ± imes_£x perienced \Xtlip, samo want a s we expect in the future, and retain a picture tliis, at any rate, there can be no doubt : we shall all agree that it ia the intensity of tlie future pleasure (or of the averted future pain) valued on the representation or imagination of it. A good which 1 have every reason to expect will bring me an intensity of satisfaction indicated by 100, I shall value at 100 and not at 1, even if, in anticipating the same, I experience only an actual pleasure of anticipa- tion of the intensity 1. And, in the same way, in choosing whether I shall provide for any definite future want, in general, or to which of several I should give the preference, I shall try to decide, as impartially as possible, according to my reasonable valuation of the future pleasure, and not according to the degree of my momentary feeling of pleasure. (That we not seldom have our clear judg- ment clouded by the latter, and that it thus obtains an indirect influence on our determinations, is a phenomenon which belongs to quite another sphere.) If, after what has been said, there should still be any doubt on the subject — which I do not anticipate — it may be removed by pointing to the well-known fact, that enthusiastic dreamers, in whom the anticipation of future events excite very lively present emotions, are not at all the sort of people who are given to provide economically for their future needs in the most efficient way. On the contrary, it is the cold calculating men who do so ; men whose sober intellectual judgment of future situations is little or not at all affected by accompanying excitement. Now Jevons has fundamentally confused these things. He makes out that our economical transactions have for their motive present feelings, which, accord- ing to the distance of time, remain a few per cent behind the intensity of future pleasures and pains — standing to the latter, perhaps, in the ratio of 95 to 100. But nothing is more certain than that, while we represent to ourselves feelings of that i ntensity and anticipat e them, we do not experience them as present feelings. Sax, again, who, in this respect, has obviously followed Jevons without proving the facts of the case for himself, has made the same blunder in a ruder way. He speaks of a Tm'empjindung of future wants — to be distinguished from a simple prescience {Grundlcgung, p. 178), and out of these “previous feelings” ho even construes actual “present wants” and “feelings of want,” which should be only a little weaker, according to the distance of time, than the corresponding immediate want of the present itself (p. 314). Surely Sax has scarcely considered what tortures we must constantly endure if all the future pleasures and pains, against which we protect ourselves by forethought, are really to be experienced by us in anticipation, and only a few per cent less vividly than in reality ! — Let me add the following remark. I am quite aware that the psychologists attach two distinct conceptions to the words “feeling” and “sensation” {GefiXhl and Empfiiidung). The speech of economics, however, has not yet carried out this distinction and it is usual to speak either of sensations or feelings of want, pain, and so on. I retain these common expressions because, by giving them up, I should probably lose more, among economic readers, in plainness, than I could gain in exactness. Note by Translator. — I may su ggest here that, so far as concerns Jevons. the above criticism scarcely anulies . It is based on a literal reading of two unfortunate expressions, “ present anticipated feeling ” and “ vague though powerful feeling of the future.” The whole passage, however, shows that Jevons did not mean the present feeling, but the represented future feeling — what he himself calls the “ actual amount of feeling anticipated.” The criticism, however, probably finds its mark in those German writers who have too faithfully followed the letter of Jevons. — W. S. CHAP. I ANTICIPA TION 241 of it in o»p THFiTnnry ; or, at least, W8 have already experienced wants or feelings that bear a certain resemblance to the feelings we are expecting, and can, from such analogous reminiscences, construct for ourselves an imaginative picture which is more or less true. On such pictnre.s of mem n-ry and in-iapiii,q- Ijon we ba.<^e niiv p.eonomicn.l calculations and our economical decisions ,. Certainly, as many a one wHi be apt to object, it is an unsafe and deceptive foundation, but, all the same, it is almost the only one that we have. It is the rarest possible thing for us to base a valuation of goods, or an economical decision, on a pain that we are feeling at the very moment. It is, indeed, one of the characteristic.^ of n. civilised community rhat it anticipates want by providing for it, and does not allow the pain of emptiness, which the unsatisfied want would involve, to get to its full height. We do not begin to prepare our meals when hunger has reached its highest point of torment : we do not wait till the flood has overwhelmed house and home before we think of putting up the dam : we do not delay building the fire-engine till the flames have broken over us. At the moment when we decide on an economical action . the wants which cause us to make the decision are, abrio.st always, in the future, and so, however near that future may be, they are acting on us, not as actual feelings, but as simple anticipations. How many a man has never, even in the past, fully felt the want which makes him value the goods he daily uses ! How many rich people know only from hearsay what real hunger is ! Hence it is obvious that, however deceitful and unsafe this ■gift of an tir.ipation mpy bo and however far astray it may lead us in individual cases, we still have every cause to be heartily thankfi il thet we hRve it Otherwise, neither actually feeling the future wants, nor yet forewarned of them by anticipation, we could not, of course, provide for them in advance ; once want had made itself felt, any measures we could take would be miserably inadequate to provide for it; and, poorer than the poorest savages, we should drag but a hazardous hand-to-mouth existence. But economical action means something more than thinking generally about the wants which are to be provided for. As, indeed, all economising arises from the quantitative insufficiency ■242 PRESENT AND FUTURE IN ECONOMIC LIFE book v of the means of satisfaction as compared with the wants requir- ing satisfaction, so it demands a constant selection, a constant I / choosing between those wants which can and shoidrl bo pro - ^ v ided for, and those others which cannot be provided for . The selection naturally proceeds on a comparison of the importance and urgency — or, as we may say, the intensity — of the feelings of pleasure and pain which are associated with individual wants and their satisfaction. Now, if it is seldom that, in the moment of an economical decision, we actually feel that one want to which it refers, it is much more seldom that, on the moment of our choice, we experience, as actual feelings, all those sensations of pleasure and pain between which we have to choos_e . Our comparisons must, almost invariably, be, partially and very (_^'Often completely, made on imaginative anticipations which we make of future feelings. And this leads us to a fact which I should like to emphasise: The future feelings we imagine i a re commensurable.^ They are "commensurable with present^ actually-felt sensations, and they are commensurable with one another, and that too without reference to whether they belon g to the same or to different levels of time. It is as easy for me to choose between a pleasure which seems desirable at the moment and another pleasure which I can obtain in eight days, as between two different pleasures which are both obtainable in eight days, or, again, as between two pleasures of which the one is obtainable in eight days, the other in eight montlis, or eight years. The fact that ve borrow from future sensations the motive for our” present actions,~is biie side of our connection with the future. Another side is that, by our present actions, we prepare goods or material services ^ for the benefit of the fu ture. If we analyse the totality of goods which constitutes our wealth we shall find that by far the greater part has the character of '^what, for want of a better name, we may call “ future goods ” {Znkunfisguter). AU productive goods, without exception, are destined altogether to the service of the future. Durable con- sumption goods give off only a fraction of their material services in the present, and all the remainder in the future. If a dwelli n g - house, for instance, remains occupied for a hundred years, and affords shelter and comfort all that time, 1 Oil the conception of Mateiial Services see Capital emd Interest, p. 223. CHAP. I FUTURE FEELINGS AND FUTURE GOODS 24.3 only an infinitesimal fraction of these services is rendered to- day; a still very small fraction is rendered in the present year ; the great hnlk of the service is spread over remote future periods. Even in the case of those perishable goods, such as meat and drink, wood and candles, which we keep ready for immediate consumption in our domestic economy, only one portion of their nsp. is strictly speaking, devoted to the service of the moment ; the greater part is carried over into the future, although it may be the immediate future. As, among our motives, future feel- ings are the dominant ones, so, among the goods we possess and use, “ future goods ” occupy the larger place. And there is yet another important analogy. As future\ feelings, whether they belong to the near or to the far future, are commensurable, alike with one another and with present feelings, so are future goods commensurable, alike with one j another and with present goods. We can compare the value of a camellia which fades in an hour, with that of a ticket for a next week’s concert, or with that of a bunch of next year’s roses ; or we can give one of these goods for the other. It makes no difference to the matter whether the “ future good,” which we compare or barter, is at hand and ready for delivery now, or whether it is represented in bodily shape by nothing more than the means of production out of which it will come, or whether, at the moment, it is neither itself ready nor is capable of being palpably represented — is, that is to say, a “ future good,” in the narrowest and strictest sense of that word* Thus we give present money in exchange, not only for the present consumption good Bread, but also for the present productive good Meal, in which the future good, bread, lies concealed. But just as easily can we buy from a farmer, for money down, his next year’s harvest. Tn reserved seats ” we, buv the future services of actors and singers. In buying Consols we give our present money for a series of future pay- ments. fufure goods and services are to us — I have cause to emphasise this — entirely familiar objects of economic dealing. just as future feelings are entirely familiar economic motives. Both have their ultimate ground in the continuity of our personal life. What we shall experience in a week or a year hence afiects us not less than what we experience to-day, and has, therefore, equal claims to be considered in our economic 244 PRESENT AND FUTURE IN ECONOMIC LIFE book v arrangements. Both arrangements have for their end om- wellbeing. hether this tjTforptiVplly similar claim of fntnre and Present is always f nlly rp.pngm'sp.rl i n prar.tiea.l lifs, is another question which will require much consideration. Provision for the future mates no inconsiderable demands on our intellectual strength; makes some demands, even, on y/ our moral strength ; and these demands are not equally met by men at all stages of civilisation. The present, alwavs gets its rights. It forces itself upon us through our senses. To cry for food ^en hungry, occurs even to . a baby. But the future we must anticipate and picture. Indeed, to have any in the future, we must form a double series of antici-_ nations. We must he able to form a mental picture of what will be the state of our wants, needs , feehngs, at any particular ■ point of time. And we must be able to form another set of amticipations as to the fatp. of those measure s which we take at ^the moment with a view to the future. Our knowledge of causal processes must enable us beforehand to form an -adequate picture of the forms which goods will take, of the quantity of them, and of the time when they will come to maturity as result of those productive or commercial activities which we are now commencing. To make this double work of anticipating a comparatively remote future clear and true to fact, is not pq s.sible to the infant , and not much more than possible to the child and the savage. Civihsation of course teaches us this difficult art gradually. But, even among the most advanced peoples, the art is still very far from being perfect, and the practical economic provision for the future is correspondingly inadequate. But, be the degree of anticipation and provision for the future what it may, wherever it exists in the most general way — and that is even among the most barbarous tribes — future goods and future ser-vices are as much actual objects of economical dealing as present goods . We strive to get them; we produce them ; we valu e them ; we buy and sell them. I say, we value them; and this is a point that must be looked more closely into. On what nrincinles do we estimate t he value of future goods ? The answer is : On the same princ iples as we estima te the value of goods in general : that is, according to the marginal utilitv which fEeT will brilig us CHAP. I THE ELEMENT OF UNCERTAINTY 245 in the circumstances, of Want and Provision for want. But here, 'naturally, we have not to deal with the relations of want and provision that ohtain at thp. but with the want and provision of that future pe riod when the goods in question will be at aur disposal. To the inhabitants of a besieged town, threatened with starvation, grain that was promised for delivery a year after the raising of the siege would certainly not be valued and paid according to the standard of tlie moments need ; while, on the contrary, a brewer who, in January, concludes a purchase for a hundred cubic feet of ice to be delivered in July of the coming summer, will, just as certainly, not measure the value of the ice according to the over-supply that obtains at the moment when the bargain is concluded, but according to the scarcity which is likely to come with the summer.^ Very frequently, however, there enters into the valuation of future goods an element which causes us to value them a little — or even a great deal — under their future marginal utility. but which — as I shall show presently — has no connection with the phenomenon of interest. This is the element of Uncertainty. To us nothing future is absolutely certain. However closely we may have bound present and future together in economical connection, and however much reason we may have to expect the future to bring certain goods into existence, or put them at our disposal, still the actual fulfilment of our expectations is never, in the strict sense of the word, certain,: it is always more or less probable. Of course, the probability is often so great that, practically, it amounts to certainty : as, for instance, the expectation that pajonent will follow an acceptance by the EothschUds. In such cases we do neglect the infinitely small amount that is wanting of full certainty, and deduct nothing from the valuation we put upon the acceptance on the ground of uncertainty. But, frequently, the probability falls considerably short of full certainty. The farmer, for i astajice. may have done everything in his power to obtain a harvest by ploughing, manuring, sowing, and so on : but the harvest may be destroyed, wholly or in part, by hail, frost, flooding, or insect ravages. Sometimes, indeed, the probability sinks to the level of a very faint possibility, as, for example, when a ' Menger. Grundsdtze.. p. 124. 246 PRESENT AND EUTURE IN ECONOMIC LIFE book v man holds one of a hundred tickets in a lottery where there is only a single prize. Cases like these cause a certain amount of hesitation to economic men. Are they to value uncertain future sums of goods exactly as if they were certain ? Impossible ! For then V/6very lottery ticket that carried the chance of winning £100 would be valued at £100, and every claim, even the most doubtful, at its full nominal amount ; — a course which, obviously, would land the men who tried to do business on these lines in the bankruptcy court in the shortest possible time. Or are the uncertain future sums of goods not to have an y value put upon them ? is no importance whatever to be attached to them with respect to our wellbeing ? As impos - sible. and as ruinous. ! For then no man would give the smallest price for a chance in a lottery, or even for nine hundi’ed and ninety-nine chances out of a thousand ; no one would dare to make the slightest sacrifice to sow when harvest was uncertain. From this dilemma there is only one escape : we must ascribe to uncertain future sums of goods an importance as regards our wellbeing, but, at the same time, wp . rrmst takp. ap.pminf-, of the uncertainty of thei r acquisition according to tbp dpgrpp of that uncertainty- But, practically, this cannot be done otherwise than by transferring the gradation from where the gradation exists, but cannot be expressed — that is, from the degree of probabihty, — to where the gradation is not, but where alone it can be expressed — that is. the deg re e of the expected utihty^: thus equalising a greater, but less probable nf.ility, t o a less, but more probable utihtv . and this again to a still less but absolutely certain utility. In a word, we reduce all possibihties of utility to oertainty, and restore the balance by deducting from this utility or value the amount we must add to the probability of the expected utility to raise it to certainty. Thus we reckon a claim on the Eothschilds at its full nominal value (disregarding for the moment the discount, as belonging to an entirely different sphere of phenomena), vEile one lottery ticket of a thousand, where the chance is a prize of £100, we value perhaps at 2s., one of a hundred at 20s., and one of ten, perhaps, at £10. Strictly looked at. this k ind, of valuation — except where the certainty of the anticipated future utility is practically CHAP. I UNCERTAINTY NO ELEMENT IN INTEREST 247 assured — is always iiieorrect., For, to recur to our illustration . the ticket will either draw the prize or it will draw a blank . In the former case it will have been, as the events show, worth a hundred pounds ; in the latter, worth nothing at all. In no case will it have been worth 2s., or 20s., or £10. But, how- ever false this method of valuation is in the indiAudual case, it comes at least approximately right, according to the law of / averages, over a great many cases ; and, in the absence of anyt/ better method of valuation — which is denied us by the dulness of our imaginative forethought — it is well justified as a practical make-shift.^ I repeat that, the element of uncertainty , which is the cause of a lesser value being put upon particular classes of future goods, has no causal connection with the phenomenon , qfintergsL The lesser valuation which is its effect is a special ^ one, and extends to one class of future goods only,® and there it bears the character of a deduction as premium for risk. With the exception of this peculiarity, the valuation of present and future goods is made on identical principles. But, to conclude from this that the amnu7U of value of present and future goods must he identical, wou ld he ton hasty. On the contrary, since present goods are available at a different time from future ones, and therefore come under different actual circumstances, and are intended for the service of a different set of wants, it is to be argued, from all we know about value, that the value of such goods must, as a rule, be diff'erent .J And so it is in fact. We arrive thus at a proposition which is a fundamental one in our inquiry : As a^^^e present goods ^ This proposition has lately been disputed by Mataja {Das EecJil des Schadcner- satzes vom SfandpuTikte der NcUiorialdkoTumie, Leipsic, 1888, p. 149, note 1) on the ground that, in the selling of such goods, one might actually obtain their average return as price, and therefore, quite correctly, value them according to this. But Mataja forgets that the market price is not the cause, but is itself the result of the fact that the individuals, who appear as buyers and sellers of such goods, value them in tlie Arst instance — that is, in the individual case, object- ively falsely — according to the average return . ^ See my former tract on Rechte wnd Verhdltnisse, p. 85, where I brought out the same idea in a somewhat different connection : also Mataja, ihid. p. 139. ^ It embraces also goods which, materially, are present, but are intended for future consumption ; for instance, productive goods, the technical transfor- mation of which into consumption goods is accompanied by a danger of not succeeding. 248 PRESENT AND FUTURE IN ECONOMIC LIFE book v have a higher subjective value than future goods of like kind and numbe r. And since the resultant of subjective valuations determines objective exchange value, present goods, as a rule, have a higher exchange value and price than future goods of like kind and number. Tl iis phenomenon is the result of the co-operation of a. number of causgs ; — causes which, individually, are of very different natures, but which, as it happens, work in the same direction. These causes we shall consider in order. CHAPTER II DIFFERENCES IN _WANT AND PRQY ISIQN FOR WANT The first great cause of diffftrftncfi in vain ft between present and future goods consists in the different circumstances of want and provision {Bednrf v.vd fiprkvm.^) in present and future . Present goods, as we knovr, receive their value from^ the circumstances of want and provision in the present : future goods from the same circumstances in those future periods of time when they will come into our disposal. If a person is badly in want of certain goods, or of goods in general, while he has reason to hope that, at a future period, he will be better off, he will always value a given quantity of immediately available goods at a higher figure than the same quantity of future goods In economic life this occui’s very frequently, and may be considered as typical in the two following cases. Fir.g.t. in all pagpg nf immediate distress and nep.e.s.qity. A peasant who has had a bad harvest, or sustained loss by fire, an artisan who has had heavy expenses through illness or death in his family, a labourer who is starving; all these agree in valuing the present shilling, which lifts them out of direst need, ever so much more than the future shilling, — the proof b eing, th e usuripjas conditions to which such people often submit in order to raise money at the moment.^ Seoond, in the case of persons who hnve reason to look forward to economical circumstances of increasing comfort. Thus all kinds of beginners who have no means, such as young artists, lawyers, officials, budding doctors, men going into busi- ness, are only too ready, in return for a sum of present goods ^ The proverb his dai qui cito dot has therefore a quite sound economical basis. 250 DIFFERENCES IN WANT AND PROVISION book v which assists them to start in the vocation they have chosen, and acts as foundation of their economical existence, to promise a considerably larger sum on the condition that they do not require to pay it until they are in receipt of a decent income.^ Of course the contrary also occurs not unfreouently in economical life. There are persons who are compai-atively weU off at the moment, and who are likely to be worse off in the future. To this category belongs, among others, that very considerable number of people whose income is obtained, mostly or altogether, by personal exertions, and will, presumably, fall away at a later period of life when they become unfit for work. A merchant’s clerk, for instance, who is in his fiftieth year, and has an income of £100, cannot expect to have any- thing better ten years later than, perhaps, a small retiring allowance of £30, or an annuity which he may secure by purchase at an assurance office. It is evident that to such people the marginal utility that depends oir a shilling spent now is smaller than that depending on a shilling available in the more badly secured future. It would seem that, in such cases, a present shilling should be less valued than a future one. And so it would be if present goods were necessarily spent in the present, but that is not the case. Most goods, and among them, particularly, m oney, which represents all kinds of goods indifferently, are durable.. an(j . can, therefore, be reserved for the service of the futu re. The case, then, between present and future goods stands thus. ^ The only possible uses of future goods are, naturally, future, \ while present goods have the same possibility , of future „use, \ and have besides — according to choice — either the present useg , or those future ones which may turn up in the time that intervenes between tlie present moment and -the future point of time with which the comparison is being made. Heiy the n are two possibilities . Ei^er it is the case that all those uses of the present and near future , which are generally taken into consideration as regards the good in ' For this reason the well-known postponement of university fees in the case of poor students in Germany (Stuiidung) is found to be a relief not much inferior to the total exemption of the same class in Austria {Befrnung). Or we may think of the conditions of the contract which the impresario makes with the singers he educates and brings out. CHAP. II SUPERIORITY OF THE PRESENT SHILLING 251 question, are less important than the future uses ; and in this case the present good will he reserved for these future uses, will derive its valrrhTfom them,^ and wull be just equal in value to a future good similarly available. Or it is the case that one of the earlier uses is more important : and then the present good gets its value from this use, and has, therefore, the advantage over the future good, wliich can only obtain its value from a less important future employment. But, usually, one never knows that some unforeseen occurrence in the near future may not give rise to some more urgent want . At any rate such a thing is possible, and it gives a chance of profit-, /' able employment to a good already on hand, such as, naturally,!/ a good that will only come into our possession in the future has not got : — a chance which, as we have seen, is calculated in the amount of the value, and assessed, according to practical although incorrect methods, as an increment graduated according to its probability. To put it in figures. With £100 which will come info my hands at the end of five years, I can only aim at a marginal utility determined by the situation of things in the year 1896 ; we shall put this utility down at 1000 ideal units. With £100 at my disposal now, I can, at the h ast, realise the same marginal utility of 1000 units, b ut if an urgent want, arising m the meantime, gives me an opportunity of obtaining a marginal utility of 1200,1 may, possibly, realise it. Say, now, that the probability of such an opportunity occurring equals one-tenth, I shall estimate the value of the present £100 at 1000 units certain and, beyond that, at one- tenth of the possible surplus of 200 : that is, in aU, at 1020 units.‘‘‘ Present goods are, therefore, in the worst case. \ equal in value to future goods, and, as a rule, they have the \ advantfl gp nv^r them in being employed as a reserve. The only exception occurs in those comparatively rare cases where it is difficult or impracticable to keep the present goods till the time of worse provision comes. This happens, for instance, in the case of goods subject to ra^jid deterioration or decay. ^ According to the law laid do^ni above on p. 162, for the case of alternative. employments witii different marginal utilities. - I need scarcely say that, in practical life, we seldom or never make out our valuations with such minute exactitude as in the above Dlustration. But it does give a faithful picture of the hind of considerations of which we a vail ourselves in such cases. 252 DIFFERENCES IN WANT AND PROVISION book v such as ice, fruit, and the like. Any fruit merchant in harvest time will put a considerably higher value on a bushel of grapes to be delivered in April than on a bushel of grapes in his store at the time. Or say that a rich man is anticipating a long period of arrest, during which his hving will be conformed to the hard fare of prison regime, how willingly would he give the price of a hundred present luxurious meals if he could ensure ten such meals during liis captivity ! We may, then, draw up the balance-sheet which shows the influence of the different circumstances of Want and its Provision in present and future as follows. A great many persons w ho are- not so well provided for in the present as they expect to be in the future, set a considerably Tn'gbp.r vainp. V' on pre se nt goods than on future . A great many persons who are better provided for in the present than they expect to be ^ in the future, but who have the chance of preserving present goods for the service of the future, and, moreover, of using them as a reserve fund for anything that may turn up in the meantime, vahie-pr esent goods either at the same figure as fatnrp nr q, littl e higher . It is only in a fractional minority of cases, where communication between present and future is hindered or threatened by peculiar circumstances, that present V goods have, for their owners, a lower subjective use value than future. This being the state of things, even if there was nothing else co-operating with this difference of want and provision in present and future, the resultant of the subjective valuations, which determines the objective exchange value, would obviously be such that present goods must maintain a ]woportionate advantage, a proportionate agio over future. But, besides this, there are other co-operating circumstances which work, even more distinctly, in the same direction. CHAPTER III TJNDERESTIMATE OE THE FUTURE It is one of the most pregnant facts of experience that we attach a less importance to fntnre pleasures and pains sim ply lipp.ansp. they are future, and in the measure that they are future. Thus it is that, to goods which are destined to meet the wants of the future, we ascribe a value which is really less than the true in- tensity of their future marginal utility. We systematically under- estimate future wants, and the goods which are to satisfy them. Of the fact itsetf there can he no doubt ; hut, of course, in particular nations, at various stages of life, in different in- dividuals, the phenomenon makes its appearance in very vary- ing degree. We find it most frankly expressed in children and savages.. With them the slightest enjoyment, if only it can be seized at the moment, outweighs the greatest and most lasting advantage. How many an Indian tribe, with careless greed, has sold the land of its fathers, the source of its main- tenance, to the pale faces for a couple of casks of “ firewater ” ! Unfortunately very, much the same may be seen in our own highly civilised countries. The working man who drinks on Sunday the week’s wage he gets on Saturday, and starves along with wife and child the next six days, is not far removed from the Indian. But, to a smaller extent, and in more refined form, the same phenomenon is, I venture to assert, not quite unknown to any of us, however prudent, or cultured, or highly principled. Which of us has not been surprised to find that, under the pressure of momentary appetite, he was not able to refuse some favourite dish or cigar which the doctor had forbidden — knowing perfectly that he was doing an injury to his health, which, calm consideration would tell him, was 254 UNDERESTIMATE OF THE FUTURE BOOK V much more considerable than the pleasure of that trifling indulgence ? Or, which of us has not, to avoid a little momentary embarrassment or annoyance, plunged headlong into a much greater ? Who is there that has never postponed some troublesome hut unavoidable call, or business, or work wluch had to be done within a certain time. tiU the day was past when it could be done with Little trouble, and has had to do it in more difficult circumstances, in haste and hurry, with over- exertion and ill-humour, to the displeasure of those who were injured or wounded by the delay ? Any one who knows himself, and keeps his eyes open to what is going on around him, will And this fact of the underestimate of future pleasures and pains exhibited under a thousand forms in the midst of our civilised society. Of the fact, then, there is no doubt. ' VYhy it should be so is more difficult to say. The entire psychological relations, indeed, through which future feehngs in general act on our judgments and our actions, are still very obscure, and it will be understood that the same obscurity covers the reasons why future feelings act with greater weakness on our judgments and actions than present feelings. Without meaning to fore- stall the pronouncement of the psychologists, who seem to me more competent to decide on both questions than the economists, I venture to think that this phenomenon rests, not on one ground, but on the joint action of no less than three different grounds. The first ground seems to me to he the incompleteness of the imaginations we form to ourselves of our future wants, Whether it be that our power of representation and abstraction is not strong enough, or whether it be that we will not take the necessary trouble, the consideration we give our future and, particularly, our far-away future wants, is more or less im- perfect. Naturally, then, all those wants which we have not considered remain without influence on the valuation of such goods as are destined to serve those future wants, and, conse- quently, the marginal utility of such goods is put too low. While this first ground is very much a peculiar defect in estimate, the second seems to me to rest on a defect in will. I believe it frequently occurs that a man, called on to make choice between a present and a future pleasure or pain, decides for the present pleasure altliougli he knows perfectly. CHAP. HI THREE GROUNDS EOR THIS 255 and is even conscious while choosing, that his-fature loss will outweioh his present ^aiiu and that, taking his welfare as a whole, the choice is unprofitable. How well many a “good fellow ” knows the painful embarrassments and privations he is bringing on himself, by running through his salary on the day he gets it, and yet has not the strength to resist the temptation of the moment ! Or, how often does a man, “ from weakness,” let himself be hurried into taking some step, or making some promise, which he knows at the moment he will rue before twenty -four hoiirs are over ! The cause of such defects in conduct, I say, appears to me, in distinction from the former case, to rest, not on want of knowledge, but on defect of will. I should not be surprised, however, if the psychologists were to explain this case also as only a variation of the former : it may be that the weaker feeling of the moment prevails over the stronger feeling of the future only because the latter, while present in consciousness in a general way, is not lively enough and strong enough to take possession of the mind. Tor our purpose, however, it is a matter of no consequence. Finally, as third groimd, I am inclined to name tlie consider - ation of tlie shortness and uncertainty of life. In the case of future goods, their ohjective acquisition may be practically certain,^ and yet it is possible that we may not live to acquire them. This makes their utility a matter of uncertainty for us. and causes us — in perfect analogy with the case of objectively uncertain goods — to make a deduction from their value corre- sponding to the degree of uncertainty.^ A utility of 100, as to which there is 50% of probability that we shall not live to see it, we certainly do not value so highly as a present utility of 100; probably we value it as we do a present utility of 5 0 ; and I am convinced that any of us who was promised, to-day, a cheque for £10,000 on his hundredth birthday, would be glad to exchange this large, but somewhat uncertain gift, for a, very small sum in present money ! To determine correctly the practical inflnence of this factor, howeyer, we must make a ^ See above, p. 245. - If there is objective uncertainty as well as subjective there will, paturally, be t^vo deductions. Of these the one made on account of objective uncertainty, as a particular phenomenon of certain kinds of goods, has nothing to do with interest ; we have only to deal with the deduction on account of .subjective unr.PTt.aint,y. 256 UNDERESTIMATE OF THE FUTURE BOOK V somewhat more accurate calculation, both of the extent to which it prevails, and the way in which it works. As regards this I think we shall be able to establish what follows. The factor in question is directly active only in a minority of cases : in most cases its action is indirect. It works in the most direct and powerful way in those not very numerous cases where men have the thought of death forced on them by peculiar circumstances ; for example, among very old men, people sufiering from fatal diseases, those placed in ^ dangerous situations or engaged in very perilous callings, such as people in times of plague or soldiers before an engagement, and so on. The disregard of a future so uncertain not seldom find s drastic expression in the mad extravagance which seizes people in such circumstances : a fact in the history of civilisation which has often been noted — by Adam Smith among others. On the other hand, the thought of the uncertainty of life seems to me to exert no direct influence at all in that vast maiorit v o f cases where we are dealing with men in normal circum- stances, and dealing, at the same time, with the valuation of goods belonging to a time not very far in the future ; say, goods that would come into their possession in a couple of days, or months, or even years. I am convinced that a healthy middle-aged man, to whom a payment of £100 next year was due for certain, would not value it a single penny less on the ground that he might not live to see next year. Tt is only where very long periods of time are concerned thfiit among normally situated men, oj2taina__fiilly — and — directly. Payments which faU due in a hundred, fifty, or even twenty years, lose in value from the consideration of the uncertainty of life as regards all payees ; payments which fall due in ten years lose in value as regards a great many. Anri hftTP finq lly wft have the point from which this third motive may rjse to universal indirp H efficiency — although, at j the same time, a very much weakened efficiency. If certain differ- ences of valuation have once become established as regards long intervals of time, they must , through the agency of exchange transactions, to some degree affect shorter intervals. For the mechanism which determines objective value abhors any sudden leap in value. It is not possible, for example, that a payment of £100 which will be made on 1st January 1900 certain, CHAP. HI ARBITRAGE 257 should be worth only £80 till 31st December 1889, and should jump up to the full value of £100 at twelve o’clock that night, because the due date is now only ten years off. Equalising tendencies, and transactions which I can best com - pare with stock exchange arbitrage, spread the differences of yajne, wliich obtain as regards long periods, uniformly over the entire intermediate period. — Putting all these peculiar circum- stances together, I should be inclined to consider the practical efficiency of this factor not altogether trifling. Still I should not place it very high, especially as it is weakened, to a not inconsiderable extent, by the consideration of closely related heirs. In any case, the two motives fimt mentioned have con- siderably more to do with the undervaluation of the future utility than the third.^ All three causes of our underestimate of future utility — errors of valuation through faulty represent- ation of coming needs, defects of will, and consideration of the uncertainty of life — manifest themselves in extremely i different degree-ci in diffprpnt inrlivirlnfllq, and even in the same ' individual at different times, according to differences of temper- j ament and mood. For the same interval of time they may cause one to make an undervaluation of 100^, another of 50^, a third of 1% or 2^ ; while they may sena fanatics in the matter of foresight and precaution to the opposite extreme of overvaluing future utility. I should like to call special attention, further, to the fact, that the undervaluation which results from these causes is not at all graduated bar- / moniously.. in the subjective valuation of the individuals, ^ according fo thp length of the time that intervenes. I mean, it is not graduated in this way, for example, that the man who discounts a utility which he expects to get in one year by 5%, must discount a utility due in two years by 10%, or one due in three months by 1^%. On the contrary, the original ^ subjective undervaluati nria are, in the highest degree, unequal and irregular . In particular, so far as the undervaluation is caused by defects of will, there may be a strong difference between an enjoyment which offers itself at the very moment, and one which does not ; while, on the other hand, there may be ^ An effect analogous to that of the uncertainty of life might be exerted by the uncertainty of the duration of our capacity of enjoyment ; but in any case the limits of the efficiency of this motive are much mor closely drawn. S 258 UNDERESTIMATE OF THE FUTURE BOOK V a very small aifference, or no difference at all, between an enjoyment which is pretty far away, and one which is farther away. Uniformity is practically introduced into the various undervaluations^ as w e_shall- see , later, only through the media - tion of exchange business.. At any rate — and this is sufficient for us here — all three causes have one common result ; that, under their influence, we estimate the utility of future goods at a lower figure than expresses their true value : we look at the mai^iual utility of future goods diminished, as it were, in perspective.^ Now it is easy to show that this phenomenon must sub- stantially contribute to strengthen the effinienr.y nf the first factor in the undervaluation of future goods, the difference in the provision of goods for present and future. All persons who are worse off in the present than they expect to be in the future, — persons to whom, therefore, the true marginal utility of a future good is already less than the marginal utility of a similar present good, — are led by this second firctor to put the future marginal utility still lower than it really is, and this increases the difference in value to the further prejudice of future goods. If, for example, the marginal utility of a definite present good is 100, and the true marginal utility of a similar good in a better -provided future is 80, the future good will be rated, perhaps, at 70 only, thanks to this second factor, and thus the difference of valuation rises from 20 to 30. In the same way those persons who may be supposed to be in approximately similar circumstances in present and future, and would, other things being equal, value present and future goods at approximately the same figure, will fall under the category of those who value present goods more highly than future. This second factor, then, increases both the number and the ^ Jevons, like his I'ollower Sax, as we saw in the note to p. 239, fell into a misunderstanding as to the entire nature of the phenomenon mentioned in the text, in confusing the representations and valuations which we make as regards future feelings with actuall}' present feelings. We need not wonder, then, at not finding in these writers any sound thorough -going explanation of the phenomena, or even an attempt at such. They accept the supposed “weakened anticipated feelings” of future needs simply as fact, as a “well-known psycho- logical fact,” and the^ pass over much of its detail — which really very much requires explanation — without comment as “self-evident” (see, e.g., Sax as before, p. 178). CHAP. Ill HOW IT AFFECTS THE FIRST FACTOR 259 intensity of the differences in valuation to the prejudice of future goods, and, naturally, in the market where present goods are exchanged against future, this must make the resultant exchange value more unfavourable to the latter. The agio on present goods moves upwards.^ 1 Indirectly this effect will be strengthened by the fact that, through the under- valuation of the future utility, men will refrain from providing for the future so amply as they would otherwise have donp.. In other words, this under estimate acts to the prejudice of saving and accumulation of wealth , and still further reduces the number of persons who have to throw an accumulated surplus of present goods on the market. CHAPTEE IV THE TECHNICAL SUPERIORITY OF PRESENT GOODS There is still a third reason why present goods are, as a rule, worth more than futur e. The fact on which it is based has long been known in a general way, but its essential nature has been thoroughly misunderstood. Hidden in a perfect wilderness of mistakes, economists ever since Say and Lauder- dale have been in the habit of going to it, under the name “‘productivity of capital,” for their explanation and justifica- tion of Interest.^ This name, which has already been the cause of so many errors, and which, besides, does not altogether correspond with what it is intended to convey, I shall lay on one side, and shall confine myself to the facts of the case pure yand simple. These facts are as follows: — J^y value of tbe unit of product (as that value shows itself with regard to the relation of want and provision for want in the particular economic period, and with regard to the diminution which future goods undergo from perspective), gives the greatest amount of value. We shall put our illustration in figures chosen at random. I wish to emphasise that the figures can be chosen quite at it is not a matter of employing a month’s labour in one aTid more years’ pro- dnctioD, but in one or more years’ prodnction. And of these alternative emplov- ments, naturally, the most important has the preference. 266 TECHNICAL SUPERIORITY OF PRESENT GOODS bk. v random and varied by the reader at will, for our proposition maintains its validity in every conceivable position of subjective valuations. Moreover I intentionally take figures varying very greatly and irregularly, it being obvious enough, without any special demonstration, that, if the value of the unit of goods were not to vary for the different periods, or not to vary much, the present means of production, as giving a greater quantity of products, would inevitably give us also a greater sum of value. Assume, then, quite at random, that, for a certain individual, the true marginal utility and value of the unit of product — ^taking into account his special circumstances of provision, which we shall suppose are, on the whole, gradu- ally improving — are as follows : in 1888, 5 units, of value (pounds, shillings, or units of any ideal standard); in 1889, 4 ; in 1890, 3'3 ; in 1891, 2‘5 ; in 1892, 2'2 ; in 18^3, 2'1 ; in 1894, 2 ; and in 1895, 1’5. This true marginal utility, then, by reason of perspective, experiences, for the later periods, an irregularly progressive reduction of this kind: for 1888 it is, subjectively estimated, 5 (without reduction) ; for 1889, instead of 4, it is 3'8 ; for 1890, instead of 3‘3, it is only 3 ; for 1891, 2-2; for 1892, 2; for 1893, 1-8; for 1894, 1-5; and for 1895, 1. If, now, on t he basis of these figures^ we calculate the sums of value represente d by the difierent possible- products of a month’s labour falling due in the various years, from 1888 to 1891. we get the following tables : — A MONTH’S LABOUR AVAILABLE IN 1888 YIELDS For the Economic Period. Units of Product. True Marginal Utility of Unit. Marginal Utility reduced in Perspective. Amount of Value of Entire Product. 1888 100 5 5 500 1889 200 4 3-8 760 1890 280 3-3 3 840 1891 350 2-5 . 2-2 770 1892 400 2-2 2 800 1893 440 2-1 1-8 792 1894 470 2 1-5 705 1895 500 1-5 1 500 CHAP. IV INVESTED IN VARIOUS PERIODS 267 A MONTH’S LABOUR AVAILABLE IN 18S9 YIELDS For Economic PerioA Units. True Marginal Utility. Reduced Mar- ginal Utility. Value. 1888 5 5 1889 100 4 3-8 380 1890 200 3-3 3 COO 1891 280 2-5 2-2 616 1892 350 2-2 2 700 1893 400 2-1 1-8 720 1894 440 2 1-5 660 1895 470 1-5 1 470 A MONTH’S LABOUR AVAILABLE IN 1890 YIELDS For Economic Period. Units. True Marginal Utility. Reduced Mar- ginal Utility. Value. 1888 5 5 1889 — 4 3-8 — 1890 100 3-3 3 300 1891 200 2-5 2-2 440 1892 280 2-2 2 560 1893 350 2-1 1-8 630 1894 400 2 1-5 600 1895 440 1-5 440 A MONTH’S LABOUR AVAILABLE IN 1891 YIELDS For Economic Period. Units. True Marginal Utility. Reduced Mar- ginal Utilit)'. Value. 1888 5 5 1889 — 4 3-8 — 1890 — 3-3 3 — 1891 100 2-5 2'2 220 1892 200 2-2 2 400 1893 280 2T 1-8 504 1894 350 2 1-5 525 1895 400 1-5 1 400 268 TECHNICAL SUPERIORITY OF PRESENT GOODS bk. v The conclusion we draw from these tables is the follow- ing. The highest value of product obtainable by the morith’s labour awa.i Table in — — that, whipVi d^ti^ rTniries its own valuation — is 840 ; the highest value obtainable by a month’s labour available in 1889 is only 720; while the highest value obtainable by a month’s labour available in 1890 and 1891 is 630 and 525 respectively. A-& a. bip. t. therefore the present month’s labmir is superior to all future onea. not - only in- t,p.ebmV.a.1 prodnet iyeness, but also in marginal utility a.ud value . I repeat emphatically that this result is not an accidental one, such as might have made its appearance in consequeKce of the particular figures used in our hypothesis. On the single assiunption that longer methods of production lead generally to a greater product, it is a necessary result ; a result which must have occurred, in an exactly similar way, whatever might have been the figures of quantity of product and value of unit in the different years. I must, further, lay particular weight on the fact, that this result does not make its appearance simply because, in our hypothesis, we have introduced, as already active, those other two circumstances which are fitted to account for a surplus value of present as against future goods — namely, a difierence in the circumstances of provision at the various periods of time, and a diminution of the future utility by way of perspec- tive. The superiority in value of present means of production. which is based on their technical superiority, is not one borrowed from these circiimstanCes : it would emerge of its own strength even if these were not active at all. I have introduced the two circumstances into the hypothesis only to make it a little more true to life, or, rather, to keep it from bemg quite absurd. Take, for instance, the influence of the reduction due to perspective entirely nnt, nf the illustration. and- we get the foll owing fignre.s .• — CHAP. IV INDEPENDENT CAUSE OF SURPLUS VALUE 269 A ^ilONTH'S LABOUR OF THE YEAR U .o ao 3 3 ! 1888. 1889. 1890. 1891. 1888 500 _ 1889 800 400 — — / 1890 924 660 330 — 1891 875 700 500 250 1892 880 770 616 440 1893 924 840 735 588 1894 940 880 800 700 1895 \ 750 705 660 600 We see that now the absolute figures of the sums of value are increased throughout, and also that the economic centre of gravity is transferred to another year but the thing which concerns us is that the result remains imchanged ; — -the month’s labour of 1888 shows the hi ghest figure of va.lnp. , and aU the others a decreasingly smaller one . But if we were also to abstract the difference in the circumstances of provision in different periods of time, the mtuation would receive the sta.mp of evtreme imprnha.hility ^ even of self-contradiction . If the value of the unit of product were to be the same in all periods of time, however remote, the most abundant product woidd, naturally, at the same time be the most valuable. But since the most abimdant product is obtained by the most lengthy and roundabout methods of production, — perhaps extending over decades of years, — the economic centre of gravity, for aU. present means of production, would^ on this assumption, be found at exv t remelv remote periods of time ^ — which is entirely contrary to all experience. And, besides, if such a state of things were to emerge at any particular point of time, i t would im m^tlU ately bring its own correctio n- For if every employment of ^ e.g. the economic centi’e of gravity for the month’s labour of 1888 in the former case lay in the product attainable for the year 1890 ; it now lies in that attainable for 1894. ^ But here, all the same, the month’s labour of 1888 remains superior to that of 1889. For, as regards any one remote period, say, the year 1988, the former, as employed in a process longer by one year, could produce a somewhat greater product than the latter. 270 TECHNICAL SUPERIORITY OF PRESENT GOODS bk. v goods for future periods is, not only technically, but economic- ally, more remunerative than the employment of them for the present or near future, of course men would withdraw their stocks of goods, to a great extent, from the service of the prpfipnf, and dirp.p±.. them to the more remunerative service of the future . But this would immediately cause an ebb-tide in the provision for the present, and a Hood in the provision for the future, for the future would then have the double advan- tage of having a greater amount of productive instruments directed to its service, and those instruments employed in more fruitful methods of production. Thus the difference in the circumstances of provision, which might hav e disappear^ for the moment, would recur of its own accord . But it is just at this point that we get the best proof that the superiority in question is independent of differences in the circumstances of provision : so far from being obliged to borrow its strength and activity from any such difference, it is, on the contrary, able, if need be, to call forth this very difference. — Thus we get, as result of our digression, the assured con^dction of two things ; — first, that the productive superiority of pre- sent goods assures them, not only a surplus in product, but a surplus in value, and, second, that, in this suppriority, we have to deal with a third cause of the surplus vabm^ anr] oiqe which is independent of any of the two already mentioned,^ We have now to ask : To what extent is this third cause Of this our former analyses give a poor and inade- quate picture. Wliat has been said is only sufficient to explain how present Means of Production are worth more than future means of production. But, from the same cause, as we b ^^e now to show, present cous ninptinn aon ds also oihain q ^ Those who prefer somewhat more venturous generalisations might, perhaps, be inclined to put the first and the tl'.ir d. caus e , together under or e enniman eateornry. that of the “technical superior ity” of present goods. For the prefer- ence given to present goods in virtue of the different relations of provision also rests peculiarly on a technical circumstance ; namely, that they allow of a “greater choice of employments, both as regards present and future wants, while future goods, naturally, are adapted to serve future wants only. At all events, this teclinioal superiority is so essentially distinct from the other of the greater technical prud/acUAty, that the two elements would require again to be kept separate frorn each other. It appears to me, therefore, in the interests of clear- ness tliat they should he kept entirely distinct from the first. CHAP. IV EVEN AS CONSUMPTION GOODS 271 preference over future consumption goods, so that, in this third cause, we have a quite universally valid reason for present goods having a greater value than future. The connection is as follows. Command over a sum of. prese nt s consumption goods provides us with th ^ Tnefli"^ '^■f snVifiist.pnr-p dippi ng the Current economic period. This leaves the means of production, which we may have at our disposal during this period (Labour, Uses of Land, Capital), free for t he technically more productive service of the future, and gives us the more abundant product attainable by them in longer. . methods of production. On the other hand, command over m' sum of future consumption goods leaves, of course, the present unprovided for, and, consequently, leaves us under the necessity of directing the means of production that are at our command in the present, wholly or partially, to the service of the present . But this involves curtailment of the production process, and as consequence, a diminished product. The difference of the two products is the advantage connected with the possession of present consumption goods. To illustrate this by an example as simple as it is well- worn. Imagine, witli Ensr-.hp.rd a, trilie of hsher-folk without capital, subsi stin g on fish left in pools on the shore by tlie*^ ebb-tide and caught with the bare hand. Here a labourer may catch and eat three fish a day. If he had a boat and net he could catch thirty fish a day, instead of three. But he cannot have these tools, for their making would cost him a month’s time and labour, and, in the meantime, he would have nothing to live upon. To save himself from starvation he must con- tinue his wretched and costly fishing by hand. But now some one cleverer than the rest borrows ninety fish, promising, against the loan, to give back a hundred and eighty fisii after one month. With the borrowed fish he supports liimself during a month, makes a 1)oat and net, and, during the next month, catches nine hundred fish instead of ninety. From tins take, not only can he make the stipulated payment of a hundred and eighty fish, but he retains a considerable net gain to himself, and thereby affords a striking piuof that the ninetv (present) fish he borrowed were worth to him- not only nmch more^than the ninety, but even more than the hundred and eighty (future) fish he paid for them. 1 Grundlagcn, § 189. 272 TECHNICAL SUPERIORITY OF PRESENT GOODS bk. v Now, of course, the differences in value are not always so great as in this example. They are greatest among people who live from hand to mouth, For them to get command over present consumption goods means the transition to capitahst production. Less striking, but always present, is the difference where people already possess a certain stock of goods. If for cyamplR^ their stock of goods is sufScient for three years, they may realise their means of production in an average three y ears’ pr oduc tion process. If, now, by some means or other, they obtain another year’s supply of present means of sub- sistence, they may extend their average production period from three to four years, and obtain thereby an increment of product which, absolutely, is always important, but, relatively, will be much less than in the first case. We can see that here, again, the matter of fact, on which I base my conclusions, is an old and well-known one ; e ven in the time of. ^AdaiB-gnait h and Turgot, it was notorious tha|. the possession of present consumption goods confers certain advantages. But as the older theory of capital was, generally speaking, a nest of warped conceptions and incorrect explana- tions, this fact also was put down in a form as singular as it was inappropriate. Consumption goods- — goods for immediate consumption — were looked on as productive goods, or means of production ; as such they were counted capital ; and then all the advantages inherent in them were explained by the pro- ductivity of capital. Indeed, a writer of the standing of Jevons , simply through dwelling on the great importance which attaches to the command over present goods, was misled into ascribing to consumption goods the high pogit iorL-mf-h eing the only: ca pital ! In face of such misinterpretations our business now is to get at the truth of facts. And the. facts are very simple. Consumption goods are not means of production : they are, therefore, not capital ; and the advantages which they confer do not proceed from any productive power they possess.. Everything turns on the simple fact that, according to the quite familiar laws of value, present goods, in virtue of the above stated casuistical connection of circumstances, are, norm- ally, the means of obtaining a higher marginal utility, and receive thereby a higher value, than future goods. CHAPTEE V CO-OPERATION OF THE THREE FACTORS To put together the results at which we have arrived thus far. We have seen that there are three fa ctoig . each of which, in - dependently of the other, is adequate to account for a difffirp.ucp. in value between present and future goods in favour of the former. These three factors are : The difference in the “N circumstances of provision, between present and future ; the / nnrlp.rpst,iTna.tp. , due to perspective, of future advantages and \ future goods; and, finally, the greater fruitfulness of lengthy j methods of production. The question now is ; — how do these / factors, working simultaneously, affect each othnr ? About the two first factors we know already : their effects are cumulative. In the case of a man badly provided for in the present, if the marginal utility of a present good were 100, and its true marginal utility in a future period only 80, the present good would be valued, relatively to the future, in the ratio of 100 to 80, if no other influence intervened. Put if there is, besides, a, persnective diniinution of the true future marginal utility , say by one-eighth, the marginal utility would be put at 70 instead of 80, and the superiority of the present good to the future would be in the ratio of 100 to 70. It is essentially different with the co-operation of the third factor. Trun. it also tends to str pngthp.n the ant-m" r>f other factors, hut it does so alternatively, not cumulatively ; that is to say, that factor which confers the greater advantage on present goods always stands out from the other as the active agent. Say, for example, that the first factor (the cir- cumstances of provision), together with the second factor (that of perspective), taken cumulatively, would give present goods T 274 CO-OPERATION OF THE THREE FACTORS book v an advantage of 30^, while the factor of productivity would give an advantage of 25^, we should not get a total advantage of 55*^, but of 30^, the advantage being based ou the atrongp.v factors^ yy The matter stands thus. The , superiority of present goods , as making roundabout and more fruitful ways of production possible, Qannot be increased by the perspective undervaluation of future goods, because the utihtv got from lengthy processes is itself a future utility , to which the perspective undervaluation applies as mu(A as it applies to the future goods with which the present goods are compared. Say that, by employing a month’s labour now, in 1888, in a one year’s process, I can make, for 1889, a product of 200 units, and, by employing a month’s labour of 1889, I can make for that same year — on account of the short and unproductive method — a product of 100 units only, it will he a reason for my valuing the present month of labour at double the next year’s month. If, now, there comes in a ten per cent imdervaluation of next year’s utility, I shall, of course, value the next year’s 100 units at 9 0 present units only ; but, for exactly the same reason, I shall value the 200 units at 180 present units only; and the ratio of valuation, two to one, remains exactly as if the perspec- tive undervaluation had never come iuto play at all. / As little c ap the third factor he strengthened by the first factor, namely, the consideration of a greater present want. For, evidently, employing a good to a great future productive utility, and employing it to satisfy an immediate pressing want, are mutually exclusive employments ; and it is clear tha t-a good, which can ouly he employed in the one wav or the other., cannot obtain a cumulative advantage from the two togethe r. But these two factors do work into each other’s hands in the following way. Present goods may he used to meet present wants, or they may be invested in production for the future. These are the two possible employments to which each indi- vidual may put his present goods. According to principles with which we are familiar, the stock of goods wiU be guided into these employments in such a way, that the most important c hances of using the goods are utilise d first, the next important second, and so on down the scale. Here, however, it is to be noted that the employments in prodiicing for the future, as CHAP. V CUMULATIVE AND ALTERNATIVE 275 Standing over against the employments in the satisfaction of immediate wants, must submit to the perspective diminution ^Yith which we are familiar . Say, for instance, that a man’s particular circumstances are such that he estimates a utility, falling due in the following year, at 10^ less than an equally great present utility ; then a future utility of 110 becomes equal to a present utility of 100, and, on that account, when there comes to be a choice between employments, the future utility of 110 may be postponed to a present utility of 102. The last employment, then, which, on these principles, is still supphed from the stock of goods, indicates, as we know, the marginal utnity, and, at the same time, the value of the unit of goods. Now the following cases may occur. JFirst. the indi^ddual may be badly off in the present In that case the pressing wants of the moment will, by themselves, absorb the small stock of present goods, and, on the ground of this bad provision' in the present, these goods will obtain a high value and a prefer- ence over future goods. The needy man prefers present goods because he w/iist consume them in the present. The opportuni- ties of employing the goods for productive purposes in the future remain in this case — since the poverty-stricken present, naturally, cannot afford any goods for purposes beyond itself — out of court as economically impossible, and, of course, without any influence on the A^alue, or preferable value, of present goods. Or, second, the nidividual may be equally well provided as regards both present and future, but mav have less forethought This case leads to a similar result. Before, it was urgent want that prevented portions of the stock of goods from being with- drawn from the service and enjoyment of the present, and invested in future production : now, it is want of thought for the future : and this want of thought confers, at the same time, on the present enjoyment, and on the present goods which minister to it, a preference over future. The spendthrift, greedy of pleasure, values present goods more highly than future, because he wishes to enjoy them in the present. — If bad provision goes along with small foresight, the two effects, as we have seen, are cumulative. Ox. third, the individual is well provided, and takes due thought for the future . In this case, of course, the two former 276 CO-OPERATION OF THE THREE FACTORS book v sanctions of the preference do not come into play at all, or scarcely at all. Tn this case, beyond the satisfying of the immediate wants, the-othp.^ ennrse is ppoTim nieHlIy open, — of investing a portion of his present goods in production for the future : thereby their economic centre of gravity, their marginal utility, and the formation of their value, are shifted to a sphere in which present goods enjoy a preference in value under the third sanction, that of their greater productiveness. A moderately rich and prudent man who has £10,000, must not, and will not Consume his £10,000 in the present, but will, in any case, save for the service of the future. But if any one were to make him the proposal, to exchange his £10,000 of present money for £10,000 of future money, he would be fully justified in declining the transaction ; as, with £10.000 faowl he can provide more effectually and richly for the future than with £10.000 at a future period. But, finally, there is still a fourtb_ -case— co nceivable : an individual may be so badly off in the present, or have so little thought for the future, that, on those two accounts, he values present goods more highly than future. At the same time, however, he is tempted by business which promises him so good a return in the future that he stints himself Still further in his present provision, and engages in the business. Here, after the analogy of the case worked out on p. 165, the avail- able sums of goods are directed, successively, into the most important employments of the two spheres taken together, and the competition of these future employments has for result^ ^hat the satisfaction of present wants is broke n off point or level than it would otherwise be.. This must, in the end, xaise the value of present goods, and indirectly increase their superiority over future.^ Thus the various sanctions come alternatively into play. 1 Suppose, e.;/., that a man has 6 units of goods, say 6 five-pound notes, at his disposal. There are present groups of wants, whicli these nt)tes could sujjply, and their importance ia indicated by the figures 10, 9, 8, 7, 6, 5. Now there appear opportunities of employing these in business transactions which will not yield any result for a year, but are so profitable that, even after deducting the necessary dis-agio on account of the year’s delay, they are equal to a present utility of 7. The following will evidently be the disposition of the notes. Four of them will go to the present wants which bear the utility 10, 9, 8, 7, the remaining two to the future employments which, likewise, show the (reduced) CHAP. V IN FA VO UR OF PRESENT GOODS 277 Where the lirst two are active the third is suspended : but where ^e first two are riot active, or not sufficiently active, there comes in the actiou of the thirfl . One can easily understand how very directly this circumstance is calculated to give the phenomenon of the higher valuations of present gnod.q a.n almost universal vahditv. The needy and the careless value present goods more highly because they urgently require them in the present, or only think about the present : the w ell-nff ami, the saving value them because they can accomphsh more ^ ^'tb them in the future : and thus, in the long-run, every one, whatever his economical position, and whatever his economical temperament, has some ground for valuing present goods more highly than future. And, further, it is easy to understand how much the universal emergence of subjective differences in valua- tion must favour the extension of this phenomenon to the spheru of objective exchange value and pric e. If the third factor were to act cumulatively with the two first there would, indeed, be many who would value present goods at an extravagant rate, but it is not certain that there would not be as many; perhaps an overwhelming majority, who would have no preference for present goods, and it is doubtful how, in this case, the resultant of exchange value would turn out. "Rut as tbp, tbirrl factor is alternative in ite ant, inn, it levels up. as it were, the f|pprp.c;sinug iustpafl nf PYag gprating individual heights ; thus it brings about a general raising of subjective valuations; and this is necessarily connected with a raising of the average line, the resultant exchange value.^ figure 7. The marginal ut ility which attaches to the present five-pound note is . therefore, 7, while, without the competitiou of the profitable future e niployTnp.Tira, it would have been only 5. ^ The statement of how the productivity of capital works into and together with the other tWo grounds of the higher valuation of present goods. I consider one of the most diflScuIt points in the theory of interest, and, at the same time, the one which must decide the fate of that theory. It is just at this point that we discover the chief weakness in Jevons’s otherwise suggestive work. None of the groups of phenomena concerned escaped his keen observation ; what did escape him was the way in which they work into one another. Consequently his work remains an eclectic piece of patchwork instead of being welded into an organic theory. He gathers together quite correctly all the primary phenomena required for the explanation. But he does not find the common channel through which they qll work together to the one common end, and so he explains it differently from each diflferent point of view, with a result that is eclectic and self-contradictory. After a most promising beginning he quite loses sight of the element of the different valua- 278 CO-OPERATION OF THE THREE FACTORS BOOK V Here we come to our last duty in this book : to show how the ratio that obtains between p re sent and future goods in subjective valuations is transferred to their objective p.vchange value. In the case of the single individual, extremely various sub- jective valuations will be formed, according as the one or the other of the above-mentioned factors is stronger or weaker. These encounter each other on the market where present goods are exchanged against future . There are many such markets and they take many different forms. In the next book we shall more exactly examine their constitution. In the meantime we must be content to examine the method in which prices are formed in its most general and typical outlines. Indeed the formation of price here takes the same course as it does else- z^here. The divergence of the subjective valuations which encounter each oth er o n the market makes possible, economically . the exchange of property between the twn^arties.^ Those who, on any subjective grounds, put a relatively high value on present goods, appear as buyers of present against future commodities ; those who put a relatively low value,^ as sellers : a nd the mark e t price will be se tied betweeiL t h e snbjectiyg va luations of the last competitors who actually exchange , and the first competitors who are shut out, or, as we have put it. tions put upon present and future wants, and for the rest gives a double explanation, full of contradictions, and scarcely rising much above the level of the old classical economy, — part of it taken from the Abstinence, part from the Productivity theory. (See my Capital and Interest, p. 400. ) The not very independent treatment which the subject has received from^Sa^ is in one respect better, while in another it is even more incomplete than that of Jevons. I t shows an advance to find the element of the undervaluation of future wants generally interwoven into the explanation of interest. (See also on this point Launhardt, Mathematisclie Begriindung dcr Volkswirthschaftslehre, Leipsic, 1885, § 2, and again my Capital and Interest, pp. 344, 427. ) But, on the other hand, it is a sensible omission that the difference between the values of present and future goods is traced exclusively to this factor, and t hat the much more important factor that co-operates with it, that of the greater nroductivenes ^does not get e vrp scanty c onsiHeratirm it gets from Jevons. (Sax, Orandlegung, p. 314.) ^ See above, p. 195. - For reasons with which we are now familiar almost all t he com petitors. whether buyers or sellers, will value present goods, absolutely, above fu tuie. But the valuation will be higher on the part of the buyers, as a class, than on the part of the sellers. CHAP. \' IN OBJECTIVE EXCHANGE VALUE 279 between the valuations of the two marginal pairs. We may represent the position of the market by the following scheme : — Intending Buyers. Present goods in units. Next year’s goods in units. Intending Sellers. Present goods in units. Next year’s goods in units. A, values 100 = 300 B, values 100 = 99 Ao J) 200 Jf 100 ^3 150 91 101 120 B4 ft 102 jy 110 B5 ft 103 >> 103 Be It 105 107 B. 19 106 -^8 106 Bg t1 107 ^9 104 B9 t1 108 Aio 102 Bio ft 110 In the circumstances of tlie market which this scheme represents. A, and B.,. form the upper marginal pair, Ag and the lower. The market price for 100 present units of goods will be fixed between 106 and 107, say at 106^ next year’s units, and this determines an agio of in favour of present goods. Once a market price of this kind for present goods has been established, it exerts a reflex levelling influence on the subjective valuations which were originally so strongly divergent. Even those who, from personal circumstances, would value future goods only a little under, or perhaps at equal terms with, present goods, now value present goods according to the higher e: ^<-^h^^g^ valnp wi nch the position of the market 1end.s_ to them . This is the reason, and the only reason, why, in practical hfe, scarcely any one would be willing to exchange present goods against an exactly equal sum of future ones. There are plenty of people whose circumstances of want and provision for want are of such a kind, that the subjective use value of present and future goods to them stands almost equal. But the general nosition of the market is. almost invariably. so strongly in favour of present goods, that it assure.s th £>iri_a. preference in exchange value, of which, naturally, every one takes advantage. Developed market exchange, however, brings with it a l evelLing effect from another side ; that is to say, it brings the 280 CO-OPERATION OF THE THREE FACTORS book v amount of agio in favour of present goods, as against future goods which fall due at variously remote points of time, into one normal ratio with the length of the elapsing time. It might easily he the case that the causes which tend to the xindervaluation of future goods might chance to he quite dis - proportionately effective on goods belonging to different periods of time. Indeed, in the very nature of several of those causes (for instance, the consideration of the shortness of human life) they would scarcely obtain at all as against goods of the near future, while, as against goods of remote periods, they would obtain strongly and irregularly. In itself, therefore, it might be quite possible that, while 100 present units of goods, as against 100 units of next year’s goods, obtained, in the market, an agio of 5 units only, as against goods of the next year they might obtain an agio of more than twice that, sav 20 . and, as against the third year’s goods, perhaps an agio of 40. But such disproportionate prices for goods of different periods of remoteness could not long hold. By a kind of time arbitrage they would very soon be brought into an equal ratio. If, for instance, the various market prices mentioned above were found quoted at one given moment, speculators would immediately appear on the scene, who would sell present goods against two years’ goods, cover the purchase by buying present against next year’s goods, and arrange for paying the latter a year later by a second purchase of present against next year’s goods. The busi- ness would work out thus. In 1888 the speculator buys 1000 present units for 1050 units of the year 1889, and sells them at the same time for 1200 of the year 1890. In 1889 he has to deliver 1050 units, and he gets them by buying, again with a agio of 5^, the then present (1889) goods for the then next year’s (1890) goods. For the 1050 units he requires to deliver he must thus give 1102-|- units of 1890. But, from the first transaction, he then receives 1200 of these very (1890) units. He has thus, on the whole business, a utility of about 100 units . Such arbitrage transactions must evidently bring the prices obtainable for goods of various future years to a level. The speculative demand for the much under- valued two years’ goods must raise their price; the supply of next year’s goods must depress their price ; till such time as the agio is brought directly into proportion with the length of the timq. CHAP. V SUMMARY OF PRESENT BOOK 281 Whp.Ti this h a ppftB fl — f^r pYampIp., 1 .V>p agio has hpp.nmp. equalised at 5^ y^r year, it may hold on fit , that ratp HnHiRtnrhp.fl. I^r then it is equally remunerative tp exchange present goods against next year’s goods for three years, successively, or to exchange present goods directly against three years’ goods, and the arbitrage we have just sketched has no further occasion to interfere in the formation of price. Thus we may accept the following as positive result of the present book. The relation between want and provision fqr want in present and future, the undervaluation of future pleasures and pains, and the technical advantage residing in present goods, have the effect that, to the overwhelming majority of men, the subjective use value of present goods is higher than that of similar future goods. From this relation of subjective valuations there follows, in the market generally, a higher objective exchange value and market price for present goods, and this, reflecting back on present goods, gives them a higher subjective, (exchange) value even among those whose personal circumstances happen to be such that the goods would not naturally have any preference in subjective use value. Finally, the levell iTi g tp.ndencie.s of the market bring the reduced value of future goods into a regular proportion to their remotp,np.R.s in tim e. In the economic commiinity,. then, we find universally that future goods have a less value, both subjective and objective, corre- sponding to the degree of their remoteness in time. BOOK VI TirE SOURCE OF INTEREST CHAPTEE I THE LOAN AND LOAN INTEREST In the previous book I tried to show, and account for, the natural difference that exists between the value of present and the value of future goods. I have now to show that this difference of value is the sour c e and - origin nf . all Interest on C apita l. But as the exchange of present commodities for future commodities takes various forms, the phenomenal forms of interest are as various, and our inquiry must necessarily deal with them all. In the following chapters, therefore, _I intend to take up. in succession, all the principal forms of interest , and I shall endeavoiu’ to show that, notwithstanding all differences in shape and appearance,(^e active cause in them all is one and the same, namely, the difference in value between present and future good^ By far the simplest case of this difference in value is presented in the Loan. A loan is nothing else than a real an d true exchajig e of present goods for future goods ; indeed, it is the simplest conceivable phenomenal form, and, to some extent, the ideal and type of such an exchange. The “ lender,” A, gives to the “ borrower,” B, a sum of present goods — say, present pounds sterling. B gets full and free possession of the goods to deal with as he Hkes, and, as equivalent, he gives into A’s fuE and free possession a sum of entiiely similar, but future, goods — say, next year s pounds sterling. Here, then, is a mutual transfer of property in two sums of goods, of which one is given as recompense or pajunent for the other. Between them there is perfect ho moge nei ty,, but for the fact that the one belongs to the present, the other to the future . I cannot imagine how an exchange in general. 286 THE LOAN AND LOAN INTEREST BOOK VI and an excliange between present and future goods in particular, could be expressed more simply and clearly. ISTow, in the last chapter, we proved that the resultant of Jdie sii b jeetiv-c vahiations which determines the marlcet price o f present and future goods is, as a rule, in favour of present goods. The borrower, therefore, will, as a rule, purchase the money wliich he receives now by a Imger sum of money which he gives later. He must thus pay an “ agio ” or nre - miuin (Anfqdd), and this auio is iuteroat . Interest, then, conies, in the most direct way, from the difference in value between present and future goods. This is the extremely simple explanation of a transaction which, for hundreds of years, was made the subject of inter- pretations very involved, very far-fetched, and very untrue. Since the days of Mohnseus and Salmasius,^ the T.oan has been conceived o f as a transaction ana logous to the Hire ; as a transfer of the temporary use of fungible goods. This method of interpretation seems simple and natural enough. It has, too the advantage and support of being in harmony with popular ideas and popular speech. We do not say, “ I sell you, or exchange you £100,” but, “I lend you £100.” The tiansaction is a loan, and interest a usura.^ a use of money . But, before a scientific basis could be given to this popular conception, a whole series of subtilties had to be in- vented, and to obtain these out of the circumstances of actual life taxed all the resources of sophistry. First it had to be shown that, in transferring a thing, it is ■ pos.sibift to transfer more than the whole _Qf it ; namely, that in giving the borrower possession of the loaned thing, it is possible to transfer to him the right to all and every use that can be made of the thing, even to the consumption that annihilates it, and, besides that, the right to a separate kind of remnant use, for whicli a separate claim, the claim of interest, can be made. Then the further subtiltv had to be ■in vented . that, in peri shable goods — goods which perish in the act of use — there is. all the same, a continuous use, ever rising anew from its own ashes ; a use which lasts even when the good “ used ” has long ceased to exist ! It had to be discovered that a cwt. of coal can be burned to cinders on 1st January ^ .See my Capital and Interest, p. 29. CHAP. I MIS UNDERS TANDINGS 287 1888, and yet be “ used ’ uninterruptedly throughout the whole year, and, perhaps, for five, or ten, or a hundred years to come ; and, what is best of all, that this lasting use can always be bought for a particular price, although and after the coal itself, and the right to consume it to the last atom, has been given away for another and a different price ! In my former book, Ca^pital and Interest, I subjected this singular theory to a searching critical examination. I showed how, under peculiar historical conditions, it came into the world as the birth of circumstances, in which, to save interest and justify it against the unquestionably unjust attacks of the canonists, a decent foundation had to l^e found for it at any price, or, if not found, invented. T _ s Kowed that this theory had its troubled source in a fiction . It was a fiction adopted, in its time, by the old jurists, in full consciousness that it was simply a fiction set up for certain practical legal purposes ; but afterwards, by a strange misunderstanding, this fiction was adopted as a sufficient scientific fact. I tried, further, to show that this theory is, in itself, full of mistakes, internal contradictions, and impossibilities, and how, finally, when carried to its logical conclusion, it leads inevitably to further contradictions and impossibilities. In opposition to it. and in place of it, 1 now offer my own positive theory , then unpublished, and confidently leave it to the reader to judge on which side lies illusion and error, and on which truth.^ I would gladly refrain from any further commentary here, were it not that, quite recently, we have had a new literary pronouncement in favour of the Use theory which I opposed, and directed against the Exchange theory which I advocated ; and were it not that this revived pronouncertient emanates from no less authority than Karl Knies. In 1885 Knies published a second edition of his book Das Geld. In it he replies to the criticism I made on some passages of his first edition, and, at the same time, expressly Tepee.ts certain positive objections he had made to the conception of the loan as an Exchange., On both counts I feel bound to anSwer. It is unfortunate that Knies’s reply touches only one of the many points on which I attacked his Use theory. I had, ^ See Capital and Interest, pp. 214-259. 288 THE LOAN AND LOAN INTEREST BOOK VI among other objections, put forward this; — that bis mp.t-.bnfi of nroviiig the actual existence of a durable use, in penshable^ goods rested on a dialectical confusion ; and I had endeavoured to strengthen my contention by an exact analysis of the very words of his arguments To this Knies answers that I have, notwithstanding, mistaken his meaning, and he repeats his positive statement in such “altered expression, and with such additions ” as may put his real meaning beyond question. As now put, K'nies’s demonstration is vp.T-y Tnnp.b amplified (in the first edition it occupies pp. 7 2 and 7 3 ; in the second editiop, pp. 106 to 114h but, substantially. I cannot consitler it any more satisfactory . On the contrary, it seems to me to bring out more clearly that the existence of this durable use, which I disputed, is not proved, but only assumed. In one of the weightiest of the new passages (p. 109), Knies has no hesitation in explaining, in so many words, that in the Loan, although “ not the same individual grains of corn and pieces of money are returned, but (only) an equally large and equally valuable amount of grains of corn and pieces of money,” stiU, “ to economical consideration, the same goods are given back .” Here he sanctions the fiction of identity between fungible goods , in optima forma, within the sphere of economical theory and economical discussion. AU that follows he bases on the foundation thus obtained. He finds the essence of hire and lease in the fact that here “the hirer, leaseholder, etc., gets the land, house, or the like, transferred to him to use for his own purposes for such and such a continuous 1 See Capital and Interest, p. 239, It goes without saying that I could mean nothing else than an involuntary dialectical confusion in the writerls mind , and nothing was further from my intention than to charge a scholar, so much esteemed by myself and by all the world, with wilfully misleading his readers. I should have thought that the very sincere expressions, in that and other writings, of the respect in which I have always held the person of that past master of our science, and particularly the express recognition of his “thorough and conscientious efforts” with which I introduced this very criticism (p. 239), might have sufficiently protected me against any such mis- conception. I was therefore more than astonished to learn that Professor Knies had taken my words as conveying an offensive imputation of wilful misleading of his readers. Although I scarcely think that any one of my readers will have understood me in this sense, I do not hesitate to explain here, emphatically and publicly, not only that I had not the slightest intention of any offensive imputation, but that 1 am exceedingly sorry if m y in con si derate choice of words should unwittingly have made such an interpretation possible. CHAP. I KNIES’S CRITICISM 289 period, at the expiry of which he has to give back the good in question.” In the Loan, perishable goods are Likewise transferred “ to be employed by the borrower for such and such a continuous but limited period of time.” Consequently Hire and Loan are, essentially, analogous transactions — which was the point to be proyed. To this I would simply answer, that the second premiss is not truth but poetry. The sober, prosaic truth is that, in the Loan , perishable goods are not transferred to the borrovyer “ for a continuous but limited period of time ” ; they are transferred definitely and for eyer : they are never giyen Ifflck . What is given back is, in fact, other goods. WTiat now becomes of the inferred analogy ? I am not blind to the use of analogies, and even to the demonstrative force which analogies may have under certain circumstances. I have myself often used them in the course of this book to drive home an argument. But an analogy is a ^ weapon which requires careful handling . Comparisons, as every one knows, are always imperfect ; if the compared things have one side in common, they have always another in which they differ. The “legal person,” for instance, may very well be compared with the physical person in questions relating to property, while, in questions relating to the family, it would scarcely be safe. If, then, we draw some conclusion from the similarity of two things, our conclusion must keep within the sphere in which the similarity actually exists ; from similar circumstances in one sphere we cannot draw a conclusion that the circumstances are similar in another sphere to which the similarity does- not extend. No one, for instance, would consider an argument like this legitimate : — the legal person is as much a person as the physical person ; a physical person can marry ; therefore, a legal person also can marry ! Vc>t-. if. that it i. s into this vicious a,nd false. use of ana logies, that Knies and the other theorists of his, s^ool have fallen. I grant at once that, in a certain point of ■view, the individual goods replaced may be looked upon as if they actually were the same individual goods which were given away in the loan : they have identically the same effect on the pcouoTnical position of the lender who receives them. Now, so far as the ground of this identification extends, so far 290 THE LOAN AND LOAN INTEREST BOOK VI also is one justified in drawing conclusions from it — but no further. The analogical conelusiuns of tlie TTse tliooristg ^ however, are entirely beyond this justifiable sphere. What lias the theoretical question whether, in perishable goods, a continuous use is possible or not, to do with the fact that it is all the same, as regards the interests of the lender, whether he gets the individual goods X or the indiAidual goods Y ? Nothing at all^ — -any more than the question of the marriage- ableness of a legal person has anything in common with the fact that, in matters relating to rights of property, an institu- tion or a corporation may without hesitation be conceived of as an independent “ person ” ! Indeed, if the reader will excuse a ridiculous but, as I think, a convincing example, one might as well use the identity of funoible goods to prove that oysters may keep fresh for ten years : they have only to be lent out for ten years, and the lender receives “ them ” back still fresh oysters ! The application is so evident that I need scarcely put it in words. The identity of the oysters lent with the oysters returned is no true identity, but only an identity assumed ad hoc. So far as concerns the practical interests of the lender the identity may pass, but, as a scientific c[uestion of fact, like the physical question whether oysters can remain fresh for ten years, there is no identity at all. And just su’ch a scientific Question of fact is the question whether, in perishable goods, there is a continuous one year’s or ten years’ use . It is a question that must find its answer in considering the nature of the perisliable good and the nature of the use ; properly speaking, not the shadow of an argument can be got from the fact that it is of no moment, as regards the practical interests of a person, whether he receives the particular good X or the particular good Y ! Now Knies does make the attempt — and this is a second and indeed the weightiest of the new passages in this edition — really to point out a dura ble use in perishable goods , and to give some indication wherein that use consists. He names, by way of illustration, “ the maintenance of life, and of labour power, the averting of a loss, the attainment of a business return or profit” (p. 112), as useful effects of this sort, which the borrower “ may obtain and make for himself from the consumption (of the loaned goods) during the entire CHAP. I JCN/ES’S CRITICISM 291 period of time before the similar quantum of perishable goods is given back.” But by illustrations like this Knies again shows that he is on the wrong track. T he enjoyment of effects indirectly obtained from the consumption of goods is not in the least a utility which we get in addition to the consumption : it is just the utility we from the consump- tkm. Accordingly it can never be the ground of a special equivalent which we should have to pay over in addition to the equivalent of the perishable good itself. What would be said of a person who proposed to sell a cwt. of corn on the following terms ; — “ For the quarter of corn itself, that is, for all the useful services which may be got from the corn by its — sudden or gradual — consumption, I want thirty shillings. But for the lasting indirect use of the corn — the use which consists in the subsequent enjoyment of useful effects, such as life prolonged, labour power maintained, and so on — I want another shilling.” Now, if , — as probably no one will deny.- — in sdlinq grain, it is not possible to conceive of the subsequent en joyment as the ground of a special equivalent ; if the subsequent enjoyment is obviously included in the purchase prihe of the good transferred into the buyer’s possession ; it is inconceivable that, all at once, in the case of the loan (where, too, the quarter of corn passes into the full possession of the borrower, and justifies him in drawing all the uses he can from it), every indirect use is to be separately paid for. And why, again, should this indirect use be paid for only during one, five, ten years, or for so long as the loan runs ? Is the utility of sustained life not enjoyed so long as life lasts ? Is the utility of preserved labour power not one which lasts so long as we can work ? In Capital and Interest I had so thoroughly and, in my own opinion at least, so clearly laid down the facts about the lasting “ indirect use.” and shown the impossibility of its being the ground of loan interest,^ that I really did not expect to see the thing emerge once more as stay and support of the Use theory. Least of all did I expect it from a writer who knew what I had said on the subject, and that without a single word of explanation being vouchsafed in answer to the objec- tions I had raised meantime. I cannot but express my 1 P. 229, and pp. 235-239. 292 THE LOAN AND LOAN INTEREST BOOK VI regret — not indeed for personal reasons, but in the interest of our science — that Knies has taken so little notice of, and given such meagre answers to the theoretical considerations which I brought against the Use theory. He replies on nrip single point , and that a point which, however important it may be in itself, has only the importance of an incident in the struggle that is to decide the victory or defeat of the Use theory; while, to the multitude of really cogent considerations directed against that theory as a whole, — considerations which, quite apart from the issue of this incidental question, show it to be internally contradictory ^ and theoretically inadmis- sible,^ — d m has. nnfnrtimat el y . -f Qnnd no word of rejoim ler. Once submitted for discussion these considerations must be met, and certainly no one was more called on to speak in the defence of his own Use theory than was Knies.® Hitherto the discussion has been limited to attack and defence of the Loan theory of other economists. I have now to reply to an attack made on my own theory . The dis- tinguished writer we have just been discussing has now repeated the objection he urged some years ago against mv concention of the loan as a true exchange ; it is, he says, in contradiction of the hitherto estatilished conception of what an exchange is. “ For an exchange — as we are not taking into account senseless and frivolous actions — takes place only 1 Capital and Interest, pp. 228, 247. ® Ibid. p. 264. * The criticism which Knies directs against me in the note to page 106 of his second edition is limited unfortunately to a few passing remarks on points which are, for the most part, of secondary importance. Moreover, several errors of fact have slipped into these, and two of them I cannot let pass unchallenged. First, I cannot admit that I have done what Knies ascribes to me, and explained that the replaceableness of goods — that is to say, the fact that one sample of a class can be adequately replaced and represented by another — is simply a legal fiction. T only sa.id that the acltml identity of replaceable goods was a legal fiction ( Capital and Interest, p. 253) ; and these are two very different statements. And, further, in my book I do not regard it as certain that, if a person speaks of uses in respect to perishable goods, he ought to point out, and wishes to point out, exactly the same kind of process of use as is to be observed in non-perishable goods. On the contrary, my entire criticism of Say and Schafiie (p. 232), of Hermann and even of Knies himself (p. .233), rests on the idea that it was a matter for the opposed theory to point out the existence of a something otherwise f-nnctUiitarl tVnn fVip material servi ces, and tba^'- it KaA-nat. succeedeii iji this attempt. CHAP. I KNIES’S CONCEPTION OF EXCHANGE 293 when goods different in some way or other are bartered. But fimgible goods, sixch as grain of similar kind and quality, are, economically, recognised as entirely similar goods.” ^ I mnst say that this statement seems to me to beg the whole questioq . Instead of inquiring what the connotation of the conception of exchange is, and arguing from that whether the loan can be called a true exchange or not, Knies starts with a preconcei'ved conception of exc han ge , and that an arbitrarily and unnaturally limited conception. As a fact, Knies’s limitation of the conception of exchange to the barter of goods of different kinds is one we do not find in the nature of exchange, nor does it correspond with the “ hitherto , estabhshed ” xxse of the conception. In the nature of exchange what is involved is that two goods are given, the one for the other — nothing more ; as to “ established usage,” it is very easy 7 to show that transactions in which entirely similar fungible goods are bartered for one another are considered by all the world true exchanges, and are called so. In proof of this I might point out that two people, simply from whim or fancy, will “ exchange ” two fungible goods, the one for the other, two new copies of the same book. Knies guards hhnself, indeed, against this argument by saying that “ we are not taking into account frivolous and senseless actions,” but this is making too light of the matter. For, certainly, it cannot be denied that such capricious actions may happen, and occa- sionally do happen, and it cannot very well be denied that such transactions, when they do happen, are neither Hire nor Loan, nor anything else than true Exchange. But there is no need to appeal to rare cases like these. Th&pe is one group of instances where men, quite deliberately and on entirely rational economic grounds, do barter ftimilar fungible goods : that is where goods, otherwise perfectly similar, are available under different modalities — to use a philosophic term — as, for instance, in different places. Take the ease of a farmer A, who owns a plantation of trees two hours’ journey away from his farm, while there is a plantation belonging to his neighbour B immediately beside him.- In both plantations, the wood, cut or ready for cutting, is of ^ Der Kredit, part i., Berlin, 1876, p. 10: shortly repeated without new arguments in the second edition of the book Bas Geld, p. 106, note 1. 294 THE LOAN AND LOAN INTEREST BOOK VI exactly the same quality. Now, evidently, it is more convenient and more profitable for A to have ten loads of wood near his house than ten loads ten miles away from it. It will, there- fore, be considered quite reasonable, and quite intelligible, to propose that B should make over to A ten loads from the near plantation, i n return for which A will give B ten loads, — or perhaps twelve loads, including a premium — of the simila r wood from his far-awav plantation . And if this is agreed to, everybody would pronounce it a real and true exchange. Or can we imagine anybody, from the fiction of identity between fungible goods, drawing an analogical conclusion like the following about the nature of the transaction : — “ A makes over to B ten loads of wood at a spot ten miles away from his house, and receives from B ten loads of wood here at his house. It is all the same to A whether he receives back the same ten loads or ten other loads. ‘From an economic point of view,’ therefore, it is essentially the same ten loads which he receives back, only at a different place. The essential nature of the transaction is, accordingly, not an exchange — since no exchange takes place between similar goods — but a transfer of the same goods to a different point in space, — that is to say, a freight transaction. And if, for the advantage which hes in this transfer from one place to another, A pays B a premium of two loads, the payment is essentially, from an economic point of view, an expense of carriage .” I very much doubt whether anybody would foUow him in this conclusion from analogy, although it is, feature for feature, the same as the one above. We should rather have expected that Knies would have been ready to own that the exchange of two amounts of wood, alike in every respect except that they are available in different places, was a real and true exchange.^ And now I ask : If it falls within the limits of the conception of exchange when goods present in one place are bartered for goods entirely similar but present in another place, with what right can we -exclude from the -Conception tbp. nasp. where goods present at one time arp ba.rtp.rp.d for ^ I may note that it would be easy to multiply examples in which the same state of things occurs. Grain merchants, c.g., may find it to their advantage to exchange stocks held in dififerent stores ; bankers, to exchange sums of money disposable at diflTerent places, etc. CHAP. I FALLACY OF THE ENDURING USE 295 goods entirely similar, but present at another timp. ? When so much has been made of analogies in the whole course of this controversy, why exclude the one analogy which is, most evidently, the appropriate one ? Tf the difference of the place at which goods are available is a sound econ omie reasmi for exchanging fungible goods that are in other respects entirely similar, and if the advantage and convenience of the present place may justify the claim and allowance of a premium, j ust as much may the differ pupp o f the time at which similav goods are availabl e be a s ound reason for their exchange, and a guarantee that there will be a. premium on the — more valuable — present goods. This premium, and nothing else, is Interest. A great tree does not fall at one blow. And I cannot expect that a loan theory, which has dominated human intel- lects for centuries, shoidd fall at the first attack. But I venture to hope that I have at least awaked a general feeling that it is necessary to submit the principles of that theory to critical revision. There is one task which the next economist who proposes to maintain the Hermann-Knies loan theory will not, I imagine, venture to omit ; namely, once and for all, to. point out positively the existence of that “ enduring use ” of perishable goods, distinct from their consumption, for which, interest is supposed to be paid , and to say, clearly and dis- tinctly, wherein that use peculiarly consists. Up tiU now its defenders have acted in a somewhat curious way ; they have pointed out, by more or less questionable analogies, that, in the loan; a temporary use is transferred, and concluded from this that there must be such a use ; the consequence being that — with the exception of this last unfortunate attempt of Knies’s — the nature of the use, its contents and so on, were left entirely in the background. I consider that our science has a right to demand the opposite and the natural method of demonstration. Let it first be shown that there is sp^.b a. nse , and wh erein it consists : if that can be done, we shall willingly believe that it is transferred in the lo an. If that cannot be done — and I doubt very much if it can — then I shall have the greater confidence in pointing to my solution of the question. To the latter, at any rate, I have no fear that the stigma of sophistry and unnaturalness can be attached. 296 THE LOAN AND LOAN INTEREST BOOK VI Passing from this polemical digression — which I considered only due, as well to the importance of the subject under dispute, as to the scientific standing of my esteemed opponent, — let us return to the main subject. According to our con- ception interest is a complementary part of the price payable for a su m of present goods in future goo^ . It is a part- equivalent of the “ principal ” lent. In itself there would be nothing to prevent this part-equivalent being paid along with the bulk of the price ; in other words, interest and “ principal ” might be put together in one single payment s,t the end of the whole loan transaction . Reasons of practical convenience have, however, made it the general rule that, jn loans made for any considerable length of time, the premium should be paid s eparately , and in rates graduated according to time, — monthly, half-yearly, yearly, etc. With the essential nature of interest this method of payment has nothing to do ; it may, indeed, be expressly provided otherwise by the loan contract. But quite possibly it is the case that this custom, which, practically, has^ prevailed from time immemorial, of separating the payment of interest from the payment of principal, has assisted — perhaps, even, directly caused the popular opinion tbnt the prinr.ipa. 1 sum pai d back is. by itself, the equivalent of the sum originally given, and that interest is a thing by itself, an equivalent for another and separate something. Now and the n a l oan may be granted without interest ; but the reason of this is seldom or never that the market price of present goods, as against future goods, is so favourable to the latter, that, in the general loan market, they can purchase an equal amount of present goods without premium. Almost invariably these are cases where the lender dispenses with the payment of premium on some special personal ground, such as friendship, charity, humanity, class obligation, and so on. It has been usual to conceive of the loan without interest as a gift of the temporary “ use ” of the thing lent.^ Our theory, of course, demands another conception. We put this kind of loan simply among cases where a man, from some personal Tuntivp, parts wi th hi.s p.ommodi ty L under the— m arket price . We say it is the same thing as where a manufacturer gives 1 “A loan without interest is a gift of the use of so much capital,” Roscher, Grundlagen, § 189. CHAP. I INTEREST A PART OF PRICE 297 personal friends at the cost price, say, of 4s. the article wnich he can sell anywhere at the general market price of 5 s. Lastly, it very seldom occurs , and then neyer as regards present and future goods in general, but only as regards one particular kind of goods, that the relations of supply and demand are such, that future goods obtain a higher price than pre.^^ent gnnd.s of the same kind , and that a premium in present goods must be paid for future goods. It will only happen in cases where, presumably, the relations of supply and demand in the future will be essentially more unfayourable than in the present, and where, at the same time, for personal or technical reasons, it is not possible to preserye the present ample stocks till that future point of time when they are assured of a higher yalue.^ Suppose the case of a brewer whose ice- cellars are too small for his requirements. If in January he puts in as much ice as the cellars will hold, and has still two hundred carts of ice_o yer, he may be yery willing to exchange these for one hundred carts of ice deliyerable in August.^ But the possibility of such a case seems to me rather to aff ord a. nnt i nsignificant proof of my loan theory . For, I should like to ask, how would the Use theorists explain this ? As a transfer of use like the loan ; only that the use has a negative yalue. and that the borrower, instead of paying a premium, dema,nds a premium? Or, perhaps, as a storage transaction, the difference between the quantity giyen and that receiyed being considered a fee for safe deposit ? I think both interpretations are so clearly artificial and fictitious that yery few people would seriously entertain them. Probably the Use ' theorists would be qmte willing to admit this as a case of real exchange ; but, so far as they did so, they would be untrue to their own contention, according to which exchange is only possible between goods of different kinds, and not between fungible goods of the same kind. Our theory, on the other hand, explains eyerything naturally. and— hy one formula . Without forcing an interpretation, it can recognise that, here, the position is exactly the same as in the loan. There is a mutual transfer of property ^ See above, p. 251. - Similar cases may perhaps occur after very abundant harvests, where the producers have not enough storage accommodation to secure the surplus. 298 THE LOAN AND LOAN INTEREST BOOK VI in two sums of goods, which are entirely similar in every other respect but that of being disposable at different points of time. And to this entirely similar state of matters it gives an entirely similar explanation : that, in both categories, there is an exchange b etw een present and future goods, the prices of PTP t.hp rpan1f.^nt. £>f the Subjective valuations put up on these two-jcl asses of goods within the market . CHAPTEE II THE PROFIT OF CAPITALIST UNDERTAKING. PRINCIPLES OF EXPLANATION We come now to the principal form assumed by the interest problem . Among the phenomena of interest it is the one which has, practically, been of most importance. Usually, indeed, it passes for the spring and source from which all the others are derived. And it has chiefly been the attempt to explain this form of interest that has led to the terribly involved war of opinions which gave only too ample material for my Capital and Interest. A word or two will indicate generally the peculiar kmd of activity which the und erta kers exert , and from which they draw their profit. They buv goods of remoter rank , such as raw materials, tools, machines, the use of land, and, above all, labour, and, by the various processes of production, transform them into goods of flrst rank, finished products ready for con- sumption . In doing so they obtain — independently of com- pensation for their own personal co-operation in the work of production as leaders of industry, head-workers, etc. — a gain approximately proportioned to the amount of capital invested in their business. This gain is called by some “Uatural Interest on Capital” or “Profit,” and, by others, “Surplus Value.” How is this gain to be explained ? I must introduce the explanation by estabhshing one important fact. Goods of remoter rank, although, materially. present commodities, are, economically, future commodities. As present commodities they are incapable of satisfying human want ; they require first to be changed into consump- tion goods; and since th isApr ocess, naturally, takes time, they 300 THE PROFIT OF CAPITALIST UNDERTAKING bk. vi can only render their services to the wants of a future period. — at the earliest, that period distant by the time which the productive process necessarily takes to change them into consumption goods. A group of productive instruments, such as Seed, Manure, Agricultural Implements, Labour, etc., which cannot he transformed into the finished product Grain under a year’s process, can _ only serve for the satisfaction of next year’s subsistence wants. In this respect, then, goods of remoter rank available in the present (present productive goods) are similar to future consumption goods ; their utility is a future utility ; they are “ future commodities.” It is evident that this fact cannot be without some far- reaching influence on the value which such goods obtain. As we know, we value goods of remoter rank, in general, accord- ing to the marginal utility a nd val ue of their finished a,nd final products. The group of productive instruments from which we get one hundred bushels of corn, has exactly the same import - ance for the satisfaction of our wants as the hundred bushels of corn into which it is transformed. But these hundred bushels, the value of which is the standard for the value of the productive group, are still, for the time, a hundred ftdiire bushels, and, as we saw in previous chapters, future goods are worth less than present goods. A hundred future bushels are, therefore, worth, we may say, only as much as ninety-five present ones. From this i t. follows that Means of E rodu ction^ also, if estimated against 'present aoo(h, are fm] ud ^f than the amount of finished , and-final products^which can be made out of them. Our group of productive instruments which, in a year’s time, will furnish us' one hundred quarters of grain, is equal in value to one hundred quarters of next year’s grain ; but, like that grain, is equal to, say, only ninety- five quarters of this year’s grain. Or, if we translate the whole matter into terms of money economy, and assume that, next year, the quarter of corn will be worth twenty shillings, then our group of produc tivejiiateriala. wherewith we Jiold in our hands the condition of our obtaining a money return of £100 next year, is equal in valu e to £100 nexlLJg&ar. MLIO-OQ more than £95 now . If, then, we buy or exchange these means of production now, the purchase price, naturally, is measured in present money, and we buy them for a smaller number CHAP II PRINCIPLES OF EX PLANA TION 301 of pounds sterling than they will bring their owner in the future. This, and nothing else, is the foundation of the so-called “ chea p” hiiying of prndiietivp. instriiment.s, and especially of l abour, which the Sociahsts rightly explain as the source of jn’ofit on capital, but wrongly interpret, in round terms, as the result of a robbery or exploitation of the working classes by the propertied classes. The buying is not so cheap as it seems. The appearance of cheapness comes, for the most part, from this ; that the price is measured by a different standard from the commodity ; measured, as it were, by one of these cheap measuring tapes which stretch with wear and indicate a foot ^ by ^ niches. The means of production, and their result. — X the finished product towards wliich the buyer is looking in purchasing them, — are future commodities, and the pn'ce i.s measur ed and paid in (more valuable) present g oods. That, in this case, the greater number of less valuable future goods is purchased by a smaller number of more valuable present goods, is not “ cheap buying,” any more than it would be cheap to acquire one hundred florins of fifty florin standard for nmety pieces of forty-five florin standard. The circumstances of possession are only to a very limited extent responsible for the fact, that the future commodity which the lahoux ers— have Tq sell (their labour), is less valuable than the present goods which the capitalists ha ve to offer fwagesl For the most part, it is elementary facts of human nature and the techniq ue of production that are to blame : facts which we have gone into in detail in the foregoing book. The social importance of the phenomenon of interest, however, will take up our attention later on ; in the meantime I have only to explam what Interest is. and why it is. Knowing now that the undertaker buys the future com- modity, “Means of Production,” for a smaller number of pieces of present goods than the number of pieces which will compose their future product, we ask. How does he come by his profit ? The answer is very simple. From his “ cheap ” purchase, indeed, he does not get any result ; for, estimated by its present value, the commodity is dear.^ ^ Of course it may happen in individual cases, that, outside of the reasons for apparently cheap buying discussed in the text, there may be other reasons fo r. 302 THE PROFIT OF CAPITALIST UNDERTAKING bk. vi The profit comes first into existence in his hand. It is during the progress of production that the future commodity ripens gr aduaUv into the present commodity, and grows at the same time to the full value of the present commodity. Time elapses ; what was next year becomes this year ; and on the great changing stage of life everything — man himself, his wants and wishes, and with them the standard by which he measures his goods — shifts one scene forward. The wants which, last Year, were future wants, and little thought of as suchu_a ttain their full strength and their full right of present wants ; and a similar advance attends the goods which supply these wants. A 'year ago they were goods of the future, and had to be content with the lower value that attached to them as such : to-day they are present goods, ripe for consumption, and enjoy the full value of such goods. A year ago it was to their preju- dice that they were measured in the, then, “ present ” goods. To-day that standard has sunk into the past, and if the men of to-day measure them again in “ present ” goods, they stand equal with them in the first and chief est rank, and suffer nothing by the comparison. Tn short, as time passes it cancels the causes by reason of which the then future commodity suffered a shrinkage of value, and brings it up to the full value of the present good. The increment of value is the profit of capital. This is not to say, of course, that, to make present goods out of future goods, it is sufficient that time should elapse and the future become the present. The goods themselves must^ n ot remain stationary . On their part they must bridge over the gap which divides them from the present, and this they do through the production which changes them from goods of remote rank into finished and final products. If there is no product ioiL process, if , the cap ital is left dead, the means of really abnormal cheat) bitving : as, e.g., skilful utilisiug of favourable conjunct- ures, usurious oppression of the seller, and, in particular, of the labourer. The emergence of such factors in this case results in a still further limitation of the purchase price, and in the obtaining of an extra profit. This extra profit is to be distinguished from Jiormal pro tit^Qn__capita^l_injyery respechi in its nature — for it is not a true profit on capital but strictly a profit of the undertaker ; iujts theoretical e^lanation — for it owes its origin to other and quite special causes : and, finally, in the social and political judgment we must form of it. I need scarcely say in so many words that what is said in the text has only to do with profit on capital pure and simple. CHAP, il PRINCIPLES OF EXPLANATION 303 pvodHotiou always remain undervalued future goods . In the year 1888, a group of means of production which can be changed into a finished product in a year’s process, — that is to say, by 1889, — is one year away from satisfying the wants of the present. If this group is left unused till 1889, its product, of course, cannot now be obtained till 1890 at the earliest, and it remains, as before, one year away from satisfy- ing the wants of the present ; its value has no opportunity to expand, and suffers the common fate of “ dead ca,pital-” ; it bears no surplus value, and no interest. This is the truth about Undertakers’ Profit, and I trust it will be found simple enough. The Socialists are fond of caUing this profit “ surplus value.” The name is more applicable than they have any idea of. It is, literally, a profit from the increment of value of the future commodi ty transmuted, in the hand of the undertakers, into a finished present good. CHAPTER III THE PROFIT OF CAPITALIST UNDERTAKING. COMPLICATIONS The principle laid down in last chapter is simple, but Jn practical life it is. as usual, obscured by a multitude of casuist- i cal details and developments. These do not, indeed, prevent its operation, but they conceal it under various phenomenal forms such as make recognition of it not always easy. Some of these developments we must take up, and we shall begin with one of the simplest. The contraction of value, from which, in our estimation, future goods suffer, is, as we know, by no means uniform for all future goods. It is graduated according to the time which intervenes between the present and the date at which the goods are ready for use. £100, for iiistanee, which will be available in a year’s time, will be valued at, perhaps, something like £95 in present money; £100 available in a couple of years, at £90; £100 available three years hence at £85, and so on.^ To this graduated contraction of value corresponds a steady graduated increase in value of those goods wl iich are-ln- process of ripening into present goo ds. A group of instruments which, at the end of a three years’ production process, promises a product of the value of £100, and, in virtue of that promise, is valued at £85 at the beginning of the process, does not remain stationary at the value of £85 till the moment when the production is completed, and then make one bound up to its full present value of £100. Its value increases gradually as the time passes which divides the group from maturity, and the production process nears its completion. This circumstance 1 Not quite exactly ; for easier understanding the figures in the text are calculated roughly, and without consideration of compound interest. CHAP. Ill COMP Lie A TIONS 305 is of great practical importance. Under the division of labour, scarcely anv kind of production is carried through; The from beginning to ( separate stages of production become branches of production, visibly independent, and conducted by separate undertakers. t.hp valnp tbn g increases bv stg gpg, « pnrrpgpnTir^iT^o gain accrues, as profit on capital, not only to the last undertaker. — the one in whose hand the good becomes an actual present commodity, — but to eachj of- the undertakers , even to one who has brought the product only a single step nearer maturity. A very cornmnn^cemplication arises from the fact that productive goods contri bute jra rious portions of their us eful content to the making of various final products, which pro ducts. arrive at maturity at various points of time . This is the case with aU durable productive goods. A plough, for instance, which lasts twenty years, will contribute a twentieth part of its Life-work and use to the ingathering of twenty different harvests. Corresponding with this twofold property — that of being means of production, and at the same time durable goods — such goods, both in the formation and in the increase of their value, manifest a peculiar combination of phenomena ; they unite the phenomena already known to us as characteristic of ‘productim goods with certain other sp e cial - phenomena which accom - pany all durMe goods — even those that are not devoted to productive purposes. We have, however, to deal particularly with this latter class of phenomena in a later chapter, and accordingly we must postpone the full explanation of this complication until then. Another complicii.tinn arises from the fact, that almost all productive instmrnents ad -mif-, of wn'nns ki nds of employment. and that these employments turn out their finished products at different points of time.^ The same fuel, for instance, may be employed in cooking a meal, or in keeping up a smithy fire where the tools are made for boring a coal seam. In the ^ The analysis which follows is devoted to the circumnavigation of one of those hidden rocks which, I suspect, might rise suddenly in the way of those readers who venture on their own account to go further into the circle of ideas here opened up. The digression which it necessitates forms one of the numerous sacrifices of time which I imagine myself compelled to make with a view to the safety of my theory, at the cost of brevity and ease of comprehension. 306 THE PROFIT OF CAPITALIST UNDERTAKING bk. vi first ease, only a few hours elapse till the finished product is ■turned gu t ; in the latter it may be years, perhaps decades of years. This is true in particular of that most important productive good, “ unskilled labour.” Various portions of it are always being employed simultaneously for productive purposes that come to maturity in the most varying periods of time. Some labourers must always get finishing work, which pays its wages almost on the moment ; others must be em- ployed in the intermediate stages; others, again, at the very beginning of the total work of production. Yet none of them has it written on his forehead whether his work is spent for the present, or for the coming year, or for the remote future. At first sight it might appear that this complication must sensibly prejudice what we have laid down as to the formation and the increase of value. Here is a good which will he used, perhaps as a present good, perhaps as a future good . Suppose that it is valued as a future good, and therefore suffers a proportionate diminution of value, it seems as if this diminu- tion were unjustifiable if, after all, the good is used as a present good. But, again, suppose it is valued, without deduc- tion, as a present good, and is, after all, employed as a future good, there is no room for increase of value. But obviously. again, it is least of all possible to estimate different portions o f the same commodity at different values, — one portion as a present good without deduction, another as a future good with deduction. Of ten loads of fuel of exactly the same kind and quality, one load is worth just as much as the other, as well to the householder as in the timber market. Tlie apparent difficulty, however, entirely disappears if we apply the universal law of value carefully to the special cir- cumstances of the case. The value of a good is determined ^ by its marginal utility . This marginal utility is _thp. IpAst. i mpor^t~~use' or employment that is provided for nut o f the available stock of goods. Suppose the stock contains five hundred pieces of a kind which we shall call A. These goods possess the three-fold capabihty of serving (1) immediately as consumption goods, (2) as means of production in a five years’ process, or (3) as means of production — in another branch of employment — in a ten years’ process. If they are used for CHAP. Ill COM PLICA TIONS 307 immediate consumption the capabilities are as follows : — one hundred pieces can he used with a useful result which we shall represent by the figure 6, another himdred with a result which we shall call 5, and a third hundred with a result which we shall call 4. But if the goods are employed in a five years’ produc- tion process, there will be a product — call it X — of which the first himdred can be remunerative at 9, the second at 8, and the third at 7 per piece.^ But these products will not he available before five years. In to-day’s estimate, therefore. their value, hhe the value of aU future goods, suffers a reduc- tioa: the amount of this reduction depends upon the amount of the agio which emerges in favour of present goods as resultant 1 of the many intersecting subjective valuations in the market. 1 If this agio, for mstance, amount to 5%, the value of the products available in five years, as compared with present goods, suffers a reduction of a httle over a fifth part.^ In the valuation of to-dav. therefore, the prospect of obtaining in fi ve. years, from one of the pieces employed as a means of produc- tion, a product which will then have the value of 9, is equal to a use reahsahle at the moment of 7 ‘05. In the same way the prospect of obtaining products of the value of 8 and 7 in five years is equal to present uses valued at 6 ’2 6 and 5 ’4 8 respectively. Similarly if the goods are employed in a ten years’ production process. If this gives the prospect of obtaining a product — call it Y — of which the first hundred can be remunerative at 16, the second hundred at 12, and the third hundred at 8, these products, as not avaOable before ten years, suffer a reduction in to-day’s estimate of somethiug hke two-fifths, and’ are equal, respectively, to 9’82, 7'35, and 4-91. If we group together the present valuation of aU these possibihties. we get the following table. ^ In order to remain true to actual cases, so far as possible within the narrow limits of the illustration, I purposely assume that the value of product decreases as production in the same branch increases — the more units the less the value of each unit. The fact that even the most remunerative branch of production ceases to be remunerative when it is over-stocked, is the very thing that makes it possible for means of production to seek different employments simultaneously ^ To be accurate it is 21 •65%, or as 100 :78'35. 308 THE PROFIT OF CAPITALIST UNDERTAKING bk. vi POSSIBILITIES OF EMPLOYING 100 PIECES In immediate consumption. In a five years* prcMjess. In a ten years’ process. 6 705 982 5 6-26 7-37 4 5-48 4-91 The- atock of five hundred pieces admits of only five of the abcffi g possibilities being utilised Nafrurallv those fivp. will bp. ta.kp.Ti whic h irv I, bp vain a linn nf — the only standard for to-day’s decision — are the most remunera tive. They are indicated in the above table by black figures, and we find them to be as follows : — 100 pieces used in immediate consumption; 200 pieces employed in a five years’ process, in making the goods XL; 200 pieces employed in a ten years’ process, in making the goods Y. The least r e munerative of th e employmen ts indicates the marg inal utility, and with it the value of the single good A. That least remunerative use bears the value 6, and, as it happens, belongs to the present. A good of the class A, then, will be valued at 6. How does this stand now as regards the increment of value and the interest on capital? In the case of the hundred pieces which are employed in the service of the present, and fetch a utility measured by 6, there is no room for an incre- ment of value. But as they afford their marginal utility immediately, they do not require to bear any interest. Th^ pieces invested in the five years’ process are worth 6. and ip fi ve years turn out a product which wiU be worth 8.^ Here there is room for an increase, — at the usual rate of 5^ for five years, — in the ratio of, say, four to five ; that is, from 6 to 7 ‘5. ^ If 200 pieces of the good are produced naturally aU the pieces obtain one equal value, and not only the second hundred but the firs t h nuHred gets its value according_to^ tl^ lower^rat^ of 8, at which the second hundred can be made remunerative. CHAP. Ill COM PLICA TIONS 309 Indeed, the room for increase, and the gam in value, is much greater. Beyond the normal interest, which is secured when fee product obtains the value of 7‘5. there is a further profit of 0'5 per piece as premium for finding and utilising the most/ favourable opportunities of employment in the present coni, juncture ; in other words, as imdertaker’s profit. But usually this premium will not long continue According to principles with which we are familiar, its existence attracts competition, and competition depresses p rice How far will it depress it ? — Hot lower than 7’5. for 7 ‘5, obtainable in five years, is equal, in present valuation, to 6 of present money, which is just the value of the productive good itself. Anything less than this price of 7 '5, consequently, would not be thought a sufficient equivalent for the sacrifice of a good valued at 6, and, in this un- remunerative branch, production would be suspended until the linlitation of supply again raised the price of the product to 7‘5 of future money, as equal to 6 of present money. This being a state of things favourable to permanence, although the produc- tive (and, therefore, future) good has rp.r.ftivp.d its value of 6 fron^ a marginal utility which belongs to the sphere of the present, and so suffers no deduction on account of its future nature, there remains quite sufficient room for a rise to the high er value of the future product. It is the same with the value and increase of value of those pieces invested in the ten years’ process. At the moment , valued at the common marginal utility, they are worth 6 . Their product, which becomes attainable in ten years, will then be worth 12. This leaves room for the normal increase of 5^ per annum, from 6 to 10; and, therefore, over ten years, makes possible an increment of about two-thirds of the original value. Beyond this again it 1pji.vp.a rnnm — at least in the first instance — for the obtaining of an undertaker’s profit . Should this profit disappear later on in consequence of competition, the future value of the product remains, aU the same, at 10, and thus leaves room permanently for the normal increase of value, in which consists the customary interest. Thus we see that, although all the pieces of class A were valued at the one figure, this one value ■g uamp-teas-tn each of— fee jpossible uses ex actly that room for increase of v al ue wh i^h. t he remoteness of i ts finishe d^ and final result demands. To 310 THE PROFIT OF CAPITALIST UNDERTAKING bk. vi the immediate use, where the utility of the good is at once realised, it guarantees nothing; to the five years’ process it allows an expansion of about one-fourth ; to the ten years’ process an expansion of about two-thirds more than the original value. Perhaps there is even a greater expansion, in which case there remains a premium to the undertaker, but, in any case, it guarantees the expansion just named. And this nice harmony is easily explained from what has just been said. Tn estimating the present value of_ the man y; sided good, its possibl e future employments had already heeji reduced to present value , whereby they experienced a discount in exact ratio to their futurity. But only those future employments are foimd economically permissible, whose present (reduced) value is, at least, equal to the fixed value of the good, and whose effective future importance, therefore, is at least greater by the amount of the discount made pro rata temporis. Therefore each of these future uses has assured it in advance a corresponding scope for recovery of its value. The lapse of time replaces the value which was taken from the estimate by wav of discount, and this, in the near-hand uses which require to bear little interest, is small, and is correspondingly great in the remote uses which must bear much interest.^ What has here been represented on a s mall scale b y one I'ngjgnpp ob tains over the w hole field of ipd ustrial employ- ment. It is not a few hundreds, but millions of productive units — days of labour, tons of coal, bars of iron, and so on — that are invested ; they are invested, not in two, or three, but in hundreds and thousands of separate employments ; and each of these employments has a different p eriod of production. All those means of prodixction enjoy one homogeneous market price. That price is formed by the available stock being ^ By varying the figures the reader may very easily convince himself that exactly the same result emerges if the marginal utility, which determines the value, lies within the sphere, not of the immediately remunerative, bnt of the productive employments. T ]he only differenceJs that, in this case, the, chances of a temporary “conjuncture profit” between the individual branches of employment, are somewhat altered. That production which itself yields just the marginal utility bears no conjuncture profit, while such a profit is now possible temporarily in the present employments, and in the other branches of production. CHAP. Ill COM PLICA TIONS 311 distributed out among the most remunerative employments, and according to the degree of advantage which they bring.^ The most remunerative branches, in virtue of having the strongest purchasing power, are supplied lirst and with the greatest certainty ; then the next remunerative branches ; and so on down the scale till the stock gives out. Some last porHnn nf thp. stock, then, is taken for some last branch of employme nt, and the modest advantage that accrues determmes the modest measure of what those last buyers can pay for the productive unit. But as the market price for all portions of the commodity is a homogeneous one, the value of the employment last supplied determines the total market price o f the means of productioii But how, then, has the advantage and value of the individual kinds of employment been determined ? — By applying the same discount to employments for future advan tage as has been described in our illustration l only that, in rough, practical life, the discounting is made in a rough way that takes a great deal for granted. In| practical life men generally find already in existence the things of which we have tried to explain the elements, and are glad to accept them, without much reflection, as accom- plished facts. In the same way do they take interest for granted as an every-day fact, and without more ado, in all calculations relating to future employment, they add or deduct it. If an undertaker is considering whether or not he should lay out one hundred pounds on a productive instrument which will yield a result in two years’ time, he aimplv calculates whether the future return will leave, at least, o ne hundred pmmd s ov er and above the two years’ interesf. . and after deduction of the same. If he has thus deducted, in advance, from the future result an amount of interest propor- tioned to time and capital, it is a very natural thing that the future proceeds, when actually realised, should contain and yield that very amoimt of interest. The foregoing cases do not by any means exhaust the series of casuistical comnlications- which obscure the working of our principle in the infinite variety of practical life. Happily it is not necessary to exhaust them. Many are not 1 See above, p. 230. 312 THE PROFIT OF CAPITALIST UNDERTAKING bk. vi of sufficient importance to justify us going into the tedious abstract demonstrations that would be needed to explain them, and, for the rest, I venture to hope that, in what has been already said, the careful reader will find enough to guide him among complications not expressly discussed, without further assistance from me. There still remains for us, however, another important and by no means easy task. I t is, in _ a word , t.n fnlln-yy f.]^p abs tract into the actual, and give it fonn and colour . Hitherto, by an argument which I hope is incontrovertible, but which I know to be highly abstract and general, I have tried to prove that it must be as I have maintained : I have now to show deduced everything from the general proposition that pro-^ ductive goods are, by nature. “ future commodities,” I have shown that, as logical result, the general reasons which explain how future commodities have a less value, must also apply to productive goods, and thus explain how there is room for expansion into the full value of present goods, and for the ''appearance of a surplus value. H shall now attempt, to show positively that all this is as I have said, and why it is . To this end I shall give a description of the markets, where, in economic life, means of production or productive instnunents are exchanged against present goods, and shall try to show that, in these markets, the same motives, to which we ascribe in general the power of calling forth a difference of value between present and future goods, do reaUy emerge, and emerge indeed in such combinations, and with such strength, that, as the result of the formation of price, there must always appear a disagio to the prejudice of the means of production. In doing so I hope not only to bring forward an adequate proof of the correctness of my general deductions, but also to obtain a number of new and important lights on the subject generally. CHAPTEE IV THE PROFIT OF CAPITALIST UNDERTAKING. THE LABOUR MARKET The eyp-hanpf! of Mpjjns nf Prnrliip.tion against final and finished present goods — practicaUv against Money — is made in three kinds of market : t he Labour market, the market for Uses, of Land , and the market for Intermediate Prndnets, such as raw materials, tools, Machines, factories, etc. Inasmuch as ; labour and uses of land, are the original means of production f from the co-operation of which all finished products come into existence, the formation of their price is peculiarly the one which decides the existence of profit on cn,pital . In the markets for intermediate products we have only the continu- ance of a process which has received its own peculiar impulse in the other two markets. And, of these two ■markets^ again , the labour market is hv far the more important. I shall, then, first take up the circumstances of this market, and shall endeavour to show and explain how tlie markeLptfice of the pr oductive goo d_l!JL abou r ” must always he less th an the value an d prm e of the finished produpk^fjahour. Eet us assume^ that, in~the methods of production current in ecmomical society at the moment, the making of a produc t ready for consnmptinn require.s a period of time- extendi ngL iiL _alL over two— ypR ,r§. The technical productiveness of this method, we shall assume, is such that it takes a week’s labour to turn out a product which will have the value of 20s. The same product may be turned out by shorter methodST^ut the result will be disproportionately unfavourable. If a three months’ process is adopted, the technical result falls to one-half.: if the worker has no capital, and his process is, accordingly, one 314 THE PROFIT OF CAPITALIST UNDERTAKING bk. vi that yields its return immediately, th e nroduetiveuess falls to one -quarter: — that is. respectively, to -lik- and Rr. The price which can be paid for the commodity “ labour ” in these circumstances is the question now under discussion on the labour market between the labourer and the employers I of labour. The price is fixed, in methods with whick -we are f amiliar, as re^tont of Jjie subjective valuations of both parties . How is it ndw^ith these valuations ? \ In the circumstances of modern industry, the wage workers scarcely ever possess sufficient means to utilise their own lA&hovLT in methods of production extending over years.^ They have, therefore, to face the alternative of selUng their labour. or of employing it o n their o.wn ^ a ccount in such short and unproductive processes as the scanty means at their disposal permit. Naturally they will make that choice which is most advantageous to them. Those workers who are well enough off to embark, on their own account, on a production process lasting at least three months, and yielding a return of 10 s. per week, will be willing to seU their labour at any price ^ver IQs. at any price under 10s. they will rather work on r their own account. On the other hand, those workers who are entirely without means, and who, working on their own account in a hand-to-mouth process, coidd only have a return of 5 s., will be willing to sell their labour at any price above 5s. As. unfortunately, the labourers w ho pnt.i-pply - without capital, form to-day the great majority, we may assume for our illustration that the “ Supply ” of labour will be repre- . sented by a long row of workers who are ready, in the worst •/ case, to sell the week’s labour for 5 s., and a shorter row who will do the same for 10s present money How is it now with the Demand for labour that confronts this supply ? ^ Whether it take the form of completing the two years’ production process ^ from beginning to end by their own labour, or that of introducing their own labour at a later stage, — e.g. in the fourth half-year of the total production process, — an d buying the fruits o f the prepa ratory labour. — raw materials, tools, etc., — from the others who have performed that previous labour. " T he pleasure of an independent position may indeed very often create a preference for labour on one’s own account, even although the labourer might obtain a somewhat greater income by taking a wage. Influences of this kind, however, can alter only the figures, not the principle. ^ Of course the possibility open to the -labourer in question of realising CHAP. IV THE LABOUR MARKET 315 The demand comes from the Capitalist-Uiidertakeiir ^he valuation they put upon the labour thev wish to buy is so far more definite, inasmuch as the commodity labour, capable of so many employments, is looked at by them in connection with one definite employment; namely, the one carried on[yA by themselves. To them, accordingly, the week’s labour, which they wish to buy for the capitalist process, is worth just so much as the product which it will turn out in this capitalist process. On our assumption, this will be 20 s. available in two years. But the question for the undertaker still remains : what are 20s.. available in two years, worth in rpj^f.lnn tn t.hp present shillings in which he must pay tire- week’s lahmin Once for aU, let us make this entirely clear. If the capitalists were to realise their entire resources as present goods, — that is, to consume their wealth in present enjoyment, — the want of the present would evidently be provided for in superfluity, while the want of the future would have no provision whatever. Thev must, therefore, find pnsil.ivply advantageous to change a part of th eir— re sources into future goods of some kind or other . In other words : if we look only at the relations of want and provision for want in present and future, present goods, as such, are worth even less than future to the owner of a stock of wealth which is greater than his present wants. It is true, of course, that there is a very J simple wav of changing present goods into future : they can be stored away either in natura, or in the neutral form of j jiture money. This possibility naturally saves them from the prejudice to their value, which would, in itself, result from the overabundant provision for the present, but, on the other hand, it does not give them any positive advantage in value, or, at any rate, a very trifling one.^ his labour in other branches of activity, can do little or nothing to alter the position of circumstances assumed in the text. For if the other branches are such as likewise demand a somewhat long production period the matter stands just the same with the labourer of this branch ; and the few branches which a man with no capital, or almost no capital, can take up with any result. — such as in particular the performance of personal services, domestic service, and the like, — can, from their nature, afford a remunerative refuge only to a l imited number o£ w o rk e r s, while any strong pressure would immediately result in overstocking and a corresponding curtailment of the advantage. 1 See above, p. 250. 318 THE PROFIT OF CAPITALIST UNDERTAKING bk. vi Nor can the n nrlPirfAstiTnnrp. .of future wants form a reason - able any juch advantage. ^TlTv^i seldom be strong enough to outweigh the counteracting consideration of the overabundant provision for the present, and to prevent the capitalists from preferring to employ part of their wealth in the service of the future. Persons, moreover, in whom this want of foresight might, exceptionally, be found, are not, or at least would not long remain, capitaUsts. An estimate like theirs, dictated by momentary desire and carelessness of the future, would soon bear its consequences, and bring their fortunes into spendthrift consumption. Of the three considerations, therefore, which, as we have seen, generally serve as foundation for the preference of present over future goods, the first two do not apply as regards the_ great majority of capitalists. It is our third consideration . the well-known technical superiority of presen t_gqpdg, or, as it is usually called, the “ productivity of capital.” which is decisiv e w ith them . The way in which it takes effect is essentially different in simple circumstances from what it is in the full development of our modern economic life. In simple circumstances, where the undertaker is himself a worker, and has no capital to speak of, present goods imme- diately obtain a higher use value. An undertaker, for instance, has just enough wealth to defray the subsistence of one working person for four years, — or to advance that amount. The choice is now open to him, either to work by himself iu a four years’, process, or to assume a helper and work alongside of-iiinLin a, two years’ process . In a two years’ process the week’s labour yields, as we have assumed, 20s.: in a four years’ process — since longei; methods are, technically, more productive — it will yield, say, 24s. The balance now stands as follows. If our capitalist pays his helper, for the week’s work, the full 20s. in present money, he has to pay him £104 for the two years’ work ; from its product he recovers just this sum of £104; and finally, he can pay himself only 20s. a week, that is, in aU, £104. His total net income, for the two years, thus amounts to £104. On the other hand, if. instead of spending £104 in paying a labourer, he spends it on his own mainte- TT g.ucp. during a third and fourth year of production, he may , from the 104 weeks of his own labour time at the higher CHAP. IV THE LABOUR MARKET 317 rate of 24s. per week, reenver £1 24 : 1 6s. : so that his two ypars’ ne t income is increasefi hy £20 1 1 6.s. Tn these circmn- stances it is obviously more advantageous for the capitalist to have no helper. To obtain any advantage from a helper it must be possible to pay him at such a price, t hat the capitalist gains more by the buying of another person’s labour than what h e loses in the realisation of his own labour, b v the shortening of the production period: in other words, that 20s. a week present money paid in wages should bring him more than 24s. a week, future money, in products. This will only be the case if he can pay a weekly wage that is under 1 6s. 8d4 Were the circumstances of capitalist production generally so simple as this, the value to the undertakers of 20s. in future products would, speaking generally, be equal to the value of 16s. 8d. present money, — the actual figures varying a little, but not the tendency. And if the buyers value the commodity labour at not more than 16 s. 8d., while the sellers value it at, perhaps, 5 s. or 10 s., it is clear that the resultant of these valuations, the price of labour. wiU. in no case, exceed the amount of 16s. 8d.. and must a foi'twri come under 20s.. the fu11_ j^uTn of the future product — which was the point to be proved. But the circumstances of present-day industry are not so simple. The great majority of our undertakers are not them- selves workers, and their capitals, moreover, are generally so great as to be far above what any one man coiQd use for hi& subsistence during the very longest practicable process. Th^ possibility, which capital gives it s o wner, of employing his ovmi labour in long er production proce ss es does not, therefo 7^ aj rule, under present conditions, give any higher use value to l present -goodsr- Our illustration of simple circumstances has'^ very great importance in other lines of proof, — of which later, — ‘ but it does not suffice to explain the profit of capital in the circumstances of capitalist industry. These very complicated circumstances, however, develop a phenomenon which works, in another form, to the same end ; this phenomenon is Credit. The capitalist cannot use his present~goods to make his^wn labour more fruitful, but others are willing to take them in , exchange for future goods to make their labour more profitable. ' 1 16s. 8d. : 20s. =£104: £124 :16s. 318 THE PROFIT OF CAPITALIST UNDERTAKING bk. vi nd are very willing to pay an agio in future goods. An d, ^vidently, the capitalist need not barter his present money at par with the workers for their future product, when he can obtain on the loan market, for a certain sum of present goods, greater sum of future goods. One is tempted to apply this fact to the explanation of profit, as if it were owing to the chances offered on the market for loans that the capitalist’s present goods had, in all j cases, a higher subjective exchange value than future goods. But this is not my idea of explanation. We have no right either to represent loan interest as a faii acc.om,pU, and pyplaip na tural profit on capital from it. or, conversely, to represent the latter as a fait accompli, and explain loan interest thereby. The fact is that the Loan market and the Labour market are two markets on which one and the same commodity is mutually offered and demanded, viz. Present (lond.c!. On both markets the demand is for means of subsistence, with the view of making labour more profitable by longer processes of production; only the circumstances of demand are different. Por the present goods which he receives the wage worker gives. wholly and entirely, the indefinite future nrod upt. wViir^h labour mav create : the borrower in productive cred it — con- sumptive credit is much less important, but manifests its effects, in the long-run, in exactly the same direction — gives, in exchange for present goods, a definite quantity ef future products , and, if the actual product differs from this quantity, may gain or lose by it. Thus wage workers and borrowers form two branches of the same demand ; they mutually support its effect ; and jointly help to form the resultant price. Only in outside appearance are they two distinct markets ; in reality they overlap each other ; and the market price of present goods is their joint result. To get to the root of the matter therefore, before consider- j ing isolated and partial markets, we must take a. cnmprphftnaivp. / survey of that total market for advances of subsistence which, L. in every economic community, is built upon numerous com ' municating partial markets. CHAPTEE V THE PROFIT OF CAPITALIST UNDERTAKING. THE GENERAL SUBSISTENCE MARKET At the outset we must enunciate a proposition, as simple as it is fundamental, but one on the proper understanding of which everything depends : In any economical p.nTr|prn,n{:t$rFFj>;’ supply of subsistence, available for advances of subsistence, is V — with one trifling exception — represented by the total sum | of its wealth (exclusive of land). The function of this wealth J {Vermogm) is to maintain the community from the time that their original productive powers are put in motion till these y powers obtain their final and mature fruits — i n^otlier words. tn(^ mninta in- rh^ -^o m mnnity during t h e average social period of' productio n. The greater the total stock of wealth in the com-/ munity the longer may be this social period of production. Here we really have three propositions, but they are so in- timately connected that they may be conveniently grouped into one, and explained and proved by one and the same argument. If we look at the uses to which a country’s accumulated wealth is destined and put — leaving land out of account — we get something like the following picture. Some few owners of wealth, whether from necessity or from prodigality, tbero^- selves consume it . Others who produce on a moderate scale for their own account spend their wealth in furnishing them- selves with the necessary maintenance, during their production period. But all other wealth — and that is by far the greater amount — is, in some form or other, brought to the great market for Advances of Subsistence as Supply . The owner either puts it into some undertaking carried on by himself, or he lends it to other people. If be pu ts •'nt» his own 320 THE PROFIT OF CAPITALIST UNDERTAKING bk. vi business it is, directly or indirectly, employed in giving a dvances of subsistence to labourer s. I say directly or /indirectly, for the division of labour, splitting up, as it does, the one united work of production into a series of apparently independent stages, causes an important distinction in form, although it does not affect the essence of the matter. If the different stages of one and the same production process were united in the hand of one and the same undertaker, he would n ot 'buy any previous product : all previous and intermediate products needed would be made, from the beginning, by the workers in his employment. Here, therefore, his entire “ business capital ” would evidently be directly devoted to advancing subsistence to labourers. As it is, under the division of labour, he gets his previous products made by other undertakers, and buys them from these other undertakers. This amounts to saying that, by this purchase, he takes upon himself the burden of the advances hitherto borne by the othe^- [y undertakers, and thus puts them again in a position to take upon themselves the burden of advancing subsistence for the following period of production. These previous and inter- mediate products, then, thus purchased, he gets worked up by labourers who are directly in his pay. In this way, there- fore, by his wage payments he advances subsistence directly to one set of workers, and indirectly by his “ outlays ” to a number of other sets (employed in the preceding stages).^ ' It will perhaps be objected that the purchase amounts which the under- takers of the previous stages receive contain, not only a simple replacement of the advances of subsistence paid by them to workers, but frequently also replace- ment of the uses of land consumed, and, in any case, some profit o n capi tal. The fact is correct, but it makes no difference in the conclusions which I think are to be drawn from what I have said above. The necessity of paying in advance for uses of land, the return of which will not be obtained till after long methods of production have been completed, has the same effect on the price relation between finished present goods and original productive powers, as the necessity of paying for labour in advance has. The market for uses of land is only a third part-market in addition to the market for credit and the market for labour, 3 a!li£ie, in similar ways, present goods are sold agains t future go.oda_(see above, p. 313), and, consequently, as^egards its effects on price, the demand of this market for present goods mutually assists, and is assisted by, the demand of the other part- markets. This, however, will be made clearer as we go on. Finally, T must here leave nut of consideration the profit of the undertaker, if I would not beg the question . Its existence is the result of a certain market condition in the subsistence market, and therefore cannot be assumed. It is not because tne CHAP. V THE GENERAL SUBSISTENCE MARKET 321 If, again, the owner Ip.nd his wpalt.h to others, it may be either for nnri.qnmpl-ioTi nr for production. If the former, the sum lent is a direct advance of subsistence to the borrower : if the latter, it passes, as already described, from the borrowing employer to the labourers, as advance of subsistence. Thus a the entire accumulated wealth of society — with the very trifling j exception of that portion which the owners themselves con-/ sume ^ — is really brought into the market as supply of advances, of .qubsistencp. But the objection may be raised : How can the entire -^ stock of wealth be offered as advances of .subsistence .whop that stock consists only partially , and, indeed, to a very small extent, of actual mpaos of Rnb.sistencp such as food, clothing, dwelling-houses, etc., while the great bulk of wealth is represented by goods that are not adapted for immediate consumption, such as tools, machines, raw' materials, factory buildings, and the like ? The seeming inconsistency is, however, easily explained ; it is simply that men never need their subsistence for the entire production period all at once. If, in any community, ten millions of men invest their original productive powers, Labour and LTses of Land, in an average production period of two years, it is quite unnecessary — indeed undesirable — that at any one moment the means of subsisting the ten millions for the whole two years should be accumulated in finished form. It is sufficient if there is enough in finished form for . sav, one month^ and if, in the meantime, the means of subsist- ence for the following month are ripening into finished goods. / profits of the undertaker absorb a part of the available means of subsistence that the sunnlv of means of subsistence is so weak as to give them an agio as against productive ^ood s^ It is because the supply of means of subsistence, even without consideration of profit, is insufficient, that these means of subsistence receive an agio, and the undertakers who advance them receive a profit. More- over it is easily seen that, by eliminating profit from the argument with which I started in the text, I do not make it any easier to reach the final result, that of giving a reason for the agio on means of subsistence, bu t make it more difficult. That is to say, if, as I assume, the whole stock of means of subsistence is dis- posable for the granting of advances to labourers, it will be more difficult in any case for this more ample supply to be exceeded by the demand, than if a portion of the supply appears to be already hypothecated to profit. ^ The much more important matter of the consumption of the income from capital does not belong to the present question : as was shown in last note it is only a result of the supply of wealth being insufficient as against the demand. Y 322 THE PROFIT OF CAPITALIST UNDERTAKING bk. vi Tn other words, all that is needed is that previous labour pT-nviflpd so many gOOc1s-rr:^.pflrt,1y rparly for rr|n- gnmptinn . partly in the intermediate foriiL of products ripening successively into consumption goods — as will cover the sub- sistence needs of two years, and thereby make it possible for the workers to invest their current labour in methods of production that will turn out the finished product in two years. Here we come to the second part of our threefold proposi - tiiin. The entire wealth of the economical community serves as subsistence fund, or advances fund, and, from this, society draws its subsistence during the period of production customary in the community. All good s which appear to-day as the stock or parent wealth of society, so far as they are not already consumption goods, will, in the more or . less near future , after a certain addition of finishing labour, ripen into consumptio n g(2£4^ and will consequently cover, for a more or less lengthy t im e to come, the people’s demand for consumption. Of course this must not be understood as if there were some sharp line of division separating the period which is covered by the wealth, already on hand from that later period which is not yet covered, and for which, consequently, provision must he made through the current productive powers. What I mean is that tfie stock of wealth projects itsp K intn fhe. future, as prri visin n. for the consu m ption of the future, as it were by stages, and not all at once. It does so in two respects : in respect of the number of classes of goods for which provision is made, and in respect of the rlp pfpp of maturity at which the work of production stands in the present. As regards the first ; it is to be noted that, for technical reasons, in many classes of goods in various foods) provision is limited to th e near „ future., perhaps to a couple of months, while, simultaneously, in other classes of goods, provision may be made for a couple of years. In others, again, where permanence is aimed at, or goods must be got ready long in advance {e.g. in dwelling-houses, mining products, machinery, and the like), the means of provision must be prepared perhaps twenty or fifty or even a hundred years before. Tims , tfipn, it is in the nature of things tha t goods required in the Im r mediate future must _naw,be.ready_or al most ready: ; for goods needed later, it is enough if, at the moment, they have gone CHAP. V THE GENERAL SUBSISTENCE MARKET 323 through, perhaps, half of the production process; whi le, for goods recjuired still later, it may be enough if their production should have just begun. If a commodity, for instance, requires five years to make, then, in the year 1888, the goods of this class destined to be used in the year 1889 must be ready, perhaps to the extent of four-fifths ; those to be used in 1890 to the extent of three-fifths ; those to be used in 1891 to the extent of two-fifths ; while, as regards goods destined for the service of the year 1892, it is enough if, at the moment, they have gone through the first fifth of their total production process. Thus it comes that the stock of wealth existing at the moment makes provision for the future in a doubly decreasin raUo : in proportion as the time of consumption is remot^ there are fewer classes, and the goods in these classes are less advanced or mature. To get an adequate representation of the circumstances of provision, then, we should have to suppose that thp .qfnpV nf wpn ith existing on 1st January 1888 ^ con- tai ns of the goods required during 1888 and tbn.<^p. gonds; are, on the average, finishecL. so that, on the whole, the labour required for the needs of 1888 is already finished and incorporated in the existing wealth to the extent of : that, further, it contains of the goods required during the year 1889 finished, thus incorporating of the labour required for 1889 : that it contains ^ of the goods wanted for 1890 finished, thus incorporating of the labour required for 1890, and so on for 1891, 1892, 1893, incor- porating respectively and of the total labour required for the service of these years. Adding up these amounts we come to the result which I wished to elucidate by this illustration ; viz., that the entire p.yisting stnp.V nf wealth provides in advance for something like two years’ ^ demand of the population, with this peculiarity that the stock of wealth, instead of covering the exigencies of two continuous years, covers successively a decreasing portion of the exigencies of a greater number of calendar years. Now the way in which this provision is made by the existing wealth, and the extent to which it is made, exercise ^ The figures are, of course, only chosen for illustration. 2 0-81-i-0-56-l-0-24-tO-12 + 0-06-t-0-04+. . . 324 THE PROFIT OF CAPITALIST UNDERTAKING bk. vi a very suggestive and impoitant influence on the employment of the original productive powers, labour and uses of land, coming into operation in the current year. For dmplicity’s sake we shall consider the former only in detail. If the stock of wealth in existence in 1888 covers the want of the current year to the extent of 3 ^, it is clear that from the / labour of this year the other ^ will first be covered. But it is as certain that the remainder of the current labour will not be devoted to tbe service of the year 1888. and that for two reasons : ( 1 ) that any return in the year 1888 could only be obtained by an unremunerative han d-to-mouth method of production, and ( 2 ) that the few products thus obtained would come upon a market already .stockejl and find poor sale and poor prices. The other of the labour of the year will, ! therefore, be directed to the service of later years. And here, again, the following is clear : the fewer the -wants of 188D covered by the existing stoc k j)f^ wealth, the g reater will l ;)e tb^ amount of the c urrent .year’s labour directed to the service of th e, year 1889 — if there is not to be a gap in the provision from year to year — and the smaller will be the amount of labour directed to the service of the years that come after it. Conversely if the wants of 1889 are already (relatively speak- ing) amply covered by the stock of wealth, only a small fraction of the current labour will go to the service of 1889, and a proportionally greater amoimt can be reserved for remoter periods.^ The current labour thu s adapts — itself naturally to the existing stoc k of wealthy The one begins where the other ends. If it were to begin sooner, and so duplicate the provision already existent, it would come under the double disadvantage, already inen tinned, of overstocked markets and less productive methods of production ; and if it were to begin later, there would be a ga p in the provision which would immediately cause scarcity prices, and thus call out speedy assistance from the productive powers. 1 It would be erroneous to assume that, after the demand of the current year is Covered, the current la bour must be directe d to the demand of the next annual period till such .time as this is /M based Oil the assumption that the whole year’s utility is obtained all at once, and, indeed, obtained in anticipation at the beginning of the year ; e.g. by hiring the good at a year’s interest of 100 payable on each 1st January. If, on the other hand, the year’s use can only be had at the end of the year, a valuation undertaken at the beginning of the year will show figures not inconsiderably lower. , That is to say, on 1st January 1888, the present year’s use which will be obtained only by 31st December, — that is, practically, a whole year later, — will not be valued at the full 100, but at 95-23 only ; and again the “next year’s use,” that obtainable 31st December 1889, — that is, practically, two years later, — will be valued at 90-70, and so on. Now this shows, for the whole good, a sum of value of 95 -23 + 90-70 + 86 -38 + 82 '27 + 78 -35 + 74 -62 = 507 -55. Jk finally, the utility were always obtainable in the middle of the year, or, what comes to the same thing, were to be spread equally over the whole year, the figures would be — for a valuation taken on the 1st January — 97-56 + 92-85 + 38-38 + 84'12 + 80-07 + 76-21 = 519‘19. — That the figures should alter according as the date of the valuation stands nearer or farther from the date of obtaining the utility, is an entirely natural thing, and one quite familiar in financial life. The value of pap£ r — which is just a “durable good” with annual uses — always stands a little higher shortly before the interest or d ividend terms than some time before. I may note that the above figures are taken as before from Spitzer’s Tables, and are based on an interest rate of 5%. .344 INTEREST EROM DURABLE GOODS BOOK VI siiffipTR during the yp-ar’s iisp, turns ri-.it initial value of the most remote service inherent in the goo^ . This value, of course, is less than the value of the present service, the service known as the “ current return ” : and thus it happens again that, to the owner of the durable good- something of the current ret urn always remains- -over L as net profit or net interest , after deducting the loss of value which the good suffers during its year of use (that loss of value familiarly known as “ wear and tear ”). This “ something ” amounts exactly to the cpstomary percentage of the total value (the “ capital value ”) of the parent good, the bearer of the utility — a coincidence which it is the easiest thing in the world' to explain. For this “something” is got from the increasing value of the total services of the goods as these services come nearer to the present. ISJ'ow, naturally, each service increases in value as it comes nearer the time of its realisation in the same ratio as it was underestimated formerly by reason of its remoteness : that is to say, it increases in va1ue _b y: the usual nj a-rkel ^ percentage on its individual value . But since, as we saw, the sum of the individual values of all the services inherent in a good constitutes the value of that good, the increment of value of all the services added together must be exactly equal to the usual market percentage on the total value of the good. To put all this into figures. At the beginning of the first year of its use the good, as bearer of six annual services, was worth in present value 100 + 95'23 + 90'70 + 86’38 + 82‘27 -1-7 8 ‘3 5; that is, 532'9_ ^ At the end of the first year, as now capable of five annual services of the present value of 100 -H 95-23 + 90-70 + 86-38 -f 82-27, it is worth 45 4-58. The loss in value is, therefore, 78-35, which is exactly the same as the former most remote service was. But since the sum received from the current years service — the value of the ser-vice sold and now deducted — amounted to 100, there remains a net gain of 21-65, which is exactly 5% of 43 2' 9 3^ the sum which the good became worth immediately on deduc- tion of the first service realised, as one might say, to account.^ 1 On the part return of 100, wliich was separated off from the good on the first day of the year, the good naturally will no longer yield any interest. If, on the other hand, the year’s utility is only obtainable at the end of the year, it must naturally pay interest on the full initial value of the bearer of the utility, as will be brought out somewhat more fully later on. CHAP. VII GROSS RETURN LESS WEAR AND TEAR 345 Similarly, in the second year’s use, the owner again realises the service now become present and worth 100, This comes off the value of the parent good. But the succeeding service, which before had become worth 9 5 '2 3, now arrives at the fidl value of 100: that succeeding it, becomes worth 9 5 '2 3, and so on. Only the last service, that originally worth 8 2 ’2 7, finds nothing to replace it. At the end of the second year’s use, then, the gooff as capable of four remaining annual services of the individualvalues of 100 + 95'23 + 90-70 + 86-38, i.s worth 372-31. As against the value of 454-58 which it had at the beginning of the year, it has suffered a loss of value of 82-27 which is equal to the value of what was the last service ; and as against the receipt of 100, it returns 17-53 net, the interest on the somewhat reduced capital ^ that remains. And thus it goes on from year to year, the gross return always remaining the same (because by hypothesis the amounts of service remain unchanged in technical quality), the quota for wear and tear always increasin g (because the marginal service, that which determines the loss of value, stands nearer to the present, and so to the full present value), and the net interest always de- p.rpa.m'ng (in correspondence with the decrease of the capital, owing to wear and tear, on which interest has to be paid), till finally the good has entirely given up its useful content and is, as we say, consumed. Put in general terms, then, we get the following very simple explanation of the phenomenon of interest on durable goods. The owner of a durable good can always realise ^ the full (higher) value of the then present utility, and this represents the “ gross return ” of the good, its “ gross interest.” fie loses, on the other hand, on account of the steady advance of the more remote services towards the presen t, onlY the smaller value of the last service then inherent in the good. This smaller value determines the amount of the “ wear and tear,” afid thus there is always a difference between g ross interest and the amount of wear and tear, which differ- ence forms his net profit or net interest. Thg ^cause, then, to^ t^jp.b np t interest owes its existe nce , is nothinq _-eh;ft— tha. Ti an ^ Of 354-58, because again the 100 taken off at the beginning of the yeai— which may independently obtain interest — need no longer obtain interest through the good. 346 INTEREST FROM DURABLE GOODS BOOK VI increase of value of the future services — services which were previously of less value, but during the period of the good’s use have pressed forward into or towards the present.^ Thus our theory traces back the profit which durnble goods yield their owner to the selfsame causes as explain interest on lo ans and undertakers’ profit on production . I think I am justified in claiming this as the peculiar merit of the theory, and, at the same time, as a strong proof of its correctness. For it was just this interest on durable goods {Nutzungsguter) that formed the stone of stu mbliiig to all earlier interest theories, and stood, as it were, a standing contradiction of them. Supposing that the other kinds of interest could be explained by the productivity of capital, obviously this was no explana.- tion of the interest yielded by a durable co nsumption good which produced nothing, such as a dwelling-house, household furniture, a hired piano, the books of a lending library. Or, if undertakers’ profit was traced, with more or less appearance of justification, to an exploitation of the labourers, the ques- tion remained : What labourers are _ex ploited by the ownen-oT a house ? Suppose he has paid away the whole £2000, the worth of his house, in wages to the labourers who built it, so that in the origin of the house there is not a particle of profit from exploitation : still, the house, year after year, yields him £100 of interest on capital. Where shall we find the worker from whom the £100 could have been taken either by fraud or force ? The “ Use theory ” appears, at first sigh t at least, better ^ If the y ear’s service can be obta i ned only at the y e ar’s end, ths fig iirm of the valuation, and with them the figures of the interest, will be altered, hut the principle of the process, and, in particular, the reduction of value by the amount of the then last service, remains unchanged. I shall put together in the follow- ing tables the course of the value movement for one such case. The initial value of a good which will last six years, and has an annual utility, obtainable at the end of the year, of 100, is, as stated above (p. 343 in note), equal to 95‘23 -f 90-70 -f 86-38 + 82-27 -H 78-35 4- 74-62 Value on Value on Tear. 1st Jan. 31st Deo. 507-55. Gross Int. Wear and Tear. Net Int. 1888 507-55 432-93 100 74-62 25-38 1889 432-93 354-58 100 78-35 21-65 1890 354-58 272-31 100 82-27 17-73 1891 272-31 185-93 100 86-38 13-62 1892 185-93 95-23 100 90-70 9-30 1893 95-23 — 100 95-23 4-77 CHAP. VII UNEXPLAINED BY OTHER THEORIES 347 able to acoount for this form of interest, since it borrows its special foundation directly from the phenomenon of the durable use of non-perishable goods.^ Ent-ne ither does it get beyond t he mere semblance of an explanation . It gets entangled in subtleties of a “ wider ” and a “ narrower ” use, of a “ gross ” and a “ net ” utility, — terms, by the way, which may be quite proper as convenient expressions to indicate certain pheno- mena, but represent anything but clear and definite conceptions — and leaves entirely unexplained the nature of the relations existing between the value of the net and the value of the gross use, between the value of the parent good and the amount of its wear and tear. Whether net intp.rp..c!t is higb *-^ bp.cH,iisp. the value of the capital is high, or whether capital value is high because net interest is high ; whether the amount of gross interest is cause or effect of the value of the other tw'o amounts — on these questions we should seek in vain, in the writings of Hermann, Knies, or Schaffle, for anything approaching to clearness of inquiry and for anything like a real explanation. To all thes'e questions our theory give s one concise answ er. The value of material services (Gross Use) forms the first link in the causal chain. The value of^ the “ bearer of the use,” the parent good, is the sum of the individual values of its material services. Wear and tear is a result of the diminution of the services which still reside in the good, and is, on account of the progression in time of the later services, neither equal to the value of the material service de tached during the year of use, nor yet corresponding to the degree of physical wear and tear^ (which, if the good last six ^ See Capital and Interest, p. 194, and particularly p. 233. ^ ^ very Tif^tpwnrtliy which theory Up till uow has left entirely without notice and entirely without explanation. I have already called attention to it in my book Rechte und Verhdltnisse, p. 68, note 6. As to the actua l Fact that the successive diminution of value, which a good suffers in the course of its wear and tear, does not go parallel with the desfree of its physical wear and t ear. ,b ut is slower at the beginning and quicker as time goes on, there can be no doubt. It may be seen in its purest form, because there it is not confused through subjective inexactnesses or caprice, in the rating of valuable paper which brings in a fixed annual amount for a limited number of years. A bond, e.g., which assures its owner the right of drawing ten years’ coupons of £1000, and possesses (on a calculation of 5% compound interest) an initial course value of £7722 (Spitzer’s Tables, p. 274), does not lose £772'2 for each of the ten years which make up ^ts lifetime , although in each of these years it loses exactly one-tenth of its content. In the first year it loses £614, in the second £645, in the third £677, 348 INTEREST FROM DURABLE GOODS BOOK VI years, would amount yearly to one-sixth of the whole useful content), but is equal only to the value of that service which is the last, the most remote, at the time of calculation. And it is this same progression in time which causes the increase in value of the later services and from which comes a net gain, the interest on capital. The same considerations that have elucidated the cause of interest from durable goods throw a strong light on anothe r ])henomenon, equally familiar and equally misunde r stood. — ^that of Capitalisation . It is a well-known circumstance that, to such goods as yield us a more or less permanent return, we ascribe a certain “ capital value ” in consideration of this return. We estimate them as equal to a money capital which, at the ruling rate of interest in the particular country, would yield a similar amount of return for the same period. Thus a house which returns £500 a year, we value at £10,000 if the usual rate of interest is 5^, or at £12,500 if the rate is 4^ ; or we value a machine wliich, for six years, throws off annually a gross amount of £100 and certain net decreasing amounts, at something over £500. Why do we attach just this value to them ? The com- mon explanation is ; Because these goods yield a certain net return we must hold them equal in value to a sum of money which yields just the same net retxirn. This, however, is incorrect, or rather it is not an explanation at aU but a reasoning in a circle. The existence of a net return is not the primary fact, which can be given as cause of the parent good having a definite value, but, conversely, a definite value must already be put on the good if this net return as such is to appear . If, in our example, the machine, which in six years returns in all £600, had been valued at £600, its whole return evidently would have been absorbed by the “ wear and and .so on successively £710, £747, £783, £823, £864, £907, and, finally, in the tenth year, £952, the sum it was still worth at the beginning of this latter year. But in all other kinds of durable goods the same course of wear and tear may be observed with sufficient accuracy, although, for obvious reasons, we seldom make so exact and mathematical a calculation. Later on I shall have another occasion to mention cases of this kind. Now in all the literature known to me I have found no attempt to give an explanation of this fact. — which is certainly notable enough to deserve explanation. Indeed, such an explanation is simpl}' not to be got from the machinery of previous theories, particularly the “Use theory,” while it offers itself unsolicited on the lines of my theory. CHAP. VII CAPITALISA TION 349 tear,” and there would have been nothing left over as net return. It is simply because it was valued at less, at some - thing only a little over £500, that there remains a net interes t after deducting the quota for wear and tear. And it is exactly the same, as I shall show farther on in another connection, as regards the return and capital value of houses, lands, etc. The only correct conception, and the only conception which really gives an explanation of the phenomenon, is the one now stated. The true primary fact is the lower vabie of fntnfo goods and future services : next we have the parent good, as capable of containing future services, estimated at a less amount than the total value which the services successively given off will represent as they are given off : and finally, as consequence, comes the fact that the capitahsed sum is le.ss than the sum of the amounts realised.- J3y-the_services.JiL the course of time, and that there is a net surplus from the current return. That, on the one hand, the value of the bearer of the use, and, on the other, its net return, are represented by such figures that the former may be held equivalent to a money capital yielding, at the current rate of interest, exactly the same net return, is a coincidence which I have already explained.^ And, in virtue of this coincidence, it is. finally, as intelligible as it is justifiable thaT , in practical economic life which finds and adopts, as facts ready to its hand, the things which we try to explain, the net return of gnndg . should be taken as foundation for acts of valuation. It is an abbreviated method which, practically, is quite appropriate, although it turns the relation of cause and effect exactly the other way.^ 1 See above, p. 343. ^ In Menger^ most valuable contribution Zur Tlieorie des Kapitales (Conrad’s Jahrbilcher, vol. xvii. p. 47), which appeared while this was passing through the press, the author likewise has urged against the Use theory that, in its conceution of canitalisation. it has not solved its problems, but only gone round about them. CHAPTEE VIII INTEREST FROM DURABLE GOODS {continued) To proceed. The phenomenon of interest-, jnst explained is characterist i c of alL dumMe-goads^ousiimptiQn, arKL^raductioii priva te persons in the present day, would be happily stopped up. But certain opportunities would still remain open if exchange transactions between individuals were not entirely forbidden. Suppose, for t instance, that free exchange were allowed jo rlnraMe gnnH^J agio and interest would immediately sl ip in. as it were, by a /■ back door. Say that a good lasts one hundred years, and that its (present) year’s service is worth £100, £10,000 must be the price of the good if the hundredth year’s service — rendered perhaps to some grandchild or great-grandchild — is to be paid fuU £100. No man would be willing to pay this price. But the moment that the purchase price is calculated at less than £10,000, the owner receives, in course of time, an income greater than the purchase price, and harvests the excess as true interest. But much more important than any such sporadic obtain- ing of interest by_private indi v idual s is t he fact that , in the Socialist state, the commonwealth itself, as against the citizens, would m^e use of the pi^ciple of interest wEich to-daY it re viles as “ exploitation ” and deduction from the product of labour. The Socialist state, as possessing all means of produc- tion, gets all the citizens to work in its factories, and pays them a wage. It conducts, therefore, on the largest scale the buying — forbidden to private individuals — of the future good Labour. Now, on technieal grounds, various portions of the labour it buys it necessarily sets to wor k simultaneously to - wards various pro ductive ends widely rem oved in point of time. One group of labourers, for instance, it sets to baking ; another it sets to sink mining shafts, which, perhaps, assist in turn- ing out consumption goods only twenty years later ; another it sets to replant a forest. The labour directed to distant ends , for reasons with which we arfi nn w fa.Tnilia.r, obtains a greater t.p,chnica.l prndnrt^ and that product when ripe wUl possess also a greater value. While, for instance, the produet that a baker turns out in a day is worth, perhaps, 4s., a labourer engaged in 368 INTEREST UNDER SOCIALISM BOOK VI w 3 forestry may plant one hundred oak saplings in a day, and these saplings, without added labour, may mature in a hundred years' time to strong oak trees worth 20 s. apiece. Now how much can and should the Socialist state pay as wage to those workers whose labour it directs to these far-away \ but productive ends ? Will it pay the forostprs thp whnlp \ vahip. of thoir fut ure product, sav. £100 a day? — Tmp o.ssihfe. That would be a glaring injustice to the workers of other departments.' If the entrance to individual branches of employ- y^ent were left free to all comers, everybody would he a forester /and nobody would hake bread; the country would relapse to j primeval forest ; and the present, with its pressing needs, would I remain unprovided for.^ If, on the other hand, the entrance was not free, and a very favoured minority were to be paid £100 a day, while the others received 4s. or 6s., a plutology would emerge again in optima forma ; only that it would not be based, as now on property, but, more fatally, on favour and protection ! But if foresters are paid exactly like baker s at 4Si_ per d ay, they ax e exploited . just as they are by the capitalist undertakers under the present system. In buying the future commodity, labour, an agio is put on present goods, and the labourer, instead of his future product of £100, is put off with a present wage of 4s., which represents the present value of the planted saplings. But the surplus value which these s aplings take on as they grow into oak trees ready for cutting, the So cialist I commonwealth puts into its pocket as real interest. Perhaps, ' — probably, it is to be hoped, — not to keep it in its pocket, but to employ it in a general bettering of the wages of its workers. But any such supplementary common purse distri- bution of the interest thus pocketed does not make any differ- ence in the fact that interest, as interest, has been received. \ In this the Socialist state only acts like a capitalist in the ^ present day, who accumul ates a fortune fr om his .surplus values,'^ 1 It may, perhaps, be pointed out in reply that, owing to the increasing supply of wood, its value would be press ed down, and so, by and by, forestry would become only as remunerative as baking and such like. I would, however, suggest that this result would only be reached when the value of hundred-year- old timber had come down to a halfpenny ; and to press down the value of wood so low, in the midst of a dense population, an enormous portion of the country would require to be turned into forest again ! CH. X COULD ONLY BE DIFFERENTLY DISTRIBUTED 369 and then (disposes nf it fnr pnrpnsfts nf f,hf> g eneral good. A wage earned can be disposed of egoistically or altruistically, and interest received can be disposed of egoistically or altruis-i tically, but it would be as rash to assert that a wage becomes' an interest by being egoistically spent, as to assert that an interest changes its nature, and turns into wage, when it is altruistically spent ! It is, too, well worthy of remark that an equal distribution of the interest obtained by the Socialist state does not establish the ^ same economic conditions as if the interest had not been taken' at all. In this distribution it is not the persons to whose labour and product the interest was due that get the interest, but en- tirely different people. The forester has an amount of £99 : 16s. deducted from the value of his future product as interest. If, now, through the distribution of aU the interests thus obtained, the average day’s wage is raised from 4s. to 6 s. per day, the forester gets a couple of shillings returned him of the £99 : 16s. taken from him ; the remaining £99 : 14s. other people get and get, indeed, just as at present, not by the title of wage, bu' by tl^ title of property, — or rather of ioint-nronertv . The' people who are employed in immediately remunerative produc- tion, such as baking, and create a day’s product of 4s., could, as labourers, ask and receive a wage of only 4s. The other 2 s. the y receive only because they are at the sa,Tnp. timp. jnin.t owners in the national wealth , and because the Socialist state which administers the common national wealth, as proprietor of this wealth, brings its entire right of property to bear on those workers whose labours are directed to more remote pro- ductive ends. In the Socialist state, therefore, exactly as in a capitalist society, interest is deserved by the proprietor of present goods as against those labourers who creati future product by their labour. The only^ifference is that in the capitalist society p roperty is unequally divided, and interpat, falls to a few pronrietors in great amounts^ while in the Socialist society all are joint owners to an equal a mount, and all obtain an equally sm all quota of the total interest. In the above analyses I have taken my illustration from forestry because it illustrates the circumstances in question in the most striking and unambiguous way. In the most striking way, because the difference of time between the forth-putting 2 B / 370 INTEREST UNDER SOCIALISM BOOK VI of labour and the receiving of the mature product, and, with it, the difference in value between labour a.iiH future product . "^ is at its maximum, : in the most unambiguous way, because here no additional labour of any sort is necessary, and, conse- t^uently, the calculation of the final product produced by a definite expenditure of labour is quite simple. But it surely needs no further demonstration tha t exactly the sa.mp. rplatinna occur, in more or less weakened dearree, in the case of all labour which is directed to more remote goals nf production. They are all technically more productive than those which yield their results on the moment. Their abundant future product, too, must always have a greater future value, because it could not, economically, have been produced at all if already its present value, reduced by perspective, were not equal to the otherwise normal value of a similar amount of labour.^ Since, finally, the wage for similar and similarly valuable labour cannot be assessed at different levels according as the Socialist state directs its labour to a near or a remote goal of production, the. wage of those labourers who are put to more remote ta,sks must. Tiece.s sari1y, be measured M?i( f.er__th B full valu e- X)f their future, product ^^ and this secures that, to a greater or less extent, there appears a surplus gain for the community which is the owner of the present goods.^ Nor does it require any demonstration that the phenomenon of interest must emerge to a still g reater-degree if the-Socialist 1 See above, p, 310. 2 The levelling up of wages — that is, up to the value of the future product of the most remuneratively employed labour — is, of course, impossible, because the national product would not suffice for that. ^ I may remark in passing that the same position holds in the case of land. rent. It is obvious that, even in the Socialist state, a labourer working on a peculiarly fruitful piece of land, e.g. in a Kiidesheim vineyard, will produce a greater or more valuable product than one who puts forth the same exertion and skill on a common piece of land or vineyard. But it is as evident that it would be insufferable “protection” to allow the former labourers their entire greater product as wage. To avoid injustice the wage here must be levelled down ; that is to say, of the product of the more frui tful lands, the “lan d re n t” mu.st be first of all retained for the comm on purse, to be divided afterwards to all the citizens in their capacity as joint, owners of the national land. Land rent, therefore, pven in the Socialist state, would exist, would come into operation as against the labourers cultivating superior land, and would only be divided according to another plan than now, on account of the equal share of all in the nationalised land. CH. X INTEREST INDEPENDENT OF ORGANISATION 371 society be organised, not nnp. imitftd po mmunity. but as a system of independent economic proups. ^ For in this case, at every exchange between mature and immature commodities, each group would appropriate surplus value, not only as against its own workers employed to remote productive ends, but, in a much greater degree, as against the other groups, and would divide out this surplus value to the shareholders of the wealth belonging to the group, as dividend. Thus we come to a very remarkable and noteworthy result. Interest, which to-day the Socialists abuse as a gain got by exploitation, a robbery from the products of labour, would not disappear eveu in the Socialist state , but would remain, in promise and potency, as between the community organised under Socialism and its labourers, and must so remain. The new organisation of society may make some change in the persons who receive it, and in the shares into which it is divided, by altering the relations of ownership ; but the fact that the owners of present commodities, in exchanging them for future commodities, obtain an agio, it neither will nor can alter. And here, again, it is shown that interest is not an accidental “ historico-legal ” category , which makes its appear- ance only in our individualist and capitalist society, and will vanish with it ; but an economic category, which springs from filementarv economic causes, and therefore, without distinction of social organisation and legislation, makes its appearance wherever there is an exchange between present and future goods. Indeed, even the lonely economy of a Crusoe wo not be without the basis of the interest phen omenpn,_ the increasing value of goods and services preparing for the service of the future ; only, of course, that, in the absence of exchange transactions, there would be wanting the chief occasion to put exact figures on the value of goods, ‘and therewith almost the only opportunity of calling attention and giving fixity to the phenomenon. > On these forms of organisation see Anton Menger, Das Recht auf den vollen Arheiisertrdg, Stuttgart, 1888, pp. 104, 112. BOOK VII THE EATE OF INTEREST CHAPTEE I THE RATE IN ISOLATED EXCHANGE The exchange of present goods for future, in which interest has its origin, is only a special case of the exchange of goods in general. It goes, then, without saving that the formation V n ^ of price in this case is subject to the same laws as govern the formation of price in economical exchange gene rally. The question whether present goods in general obtain an agio, and also the further question of the height of that agio, are both to be answered according to the rules laid down in Book IV. as regards prices of goods in general. What remains for us here is only to amplify and vivify the colourless scheme which demonstrated that the current price of goods is the resultan t / of subjective valuations coming together in a markeA by pointing out those concrete circumstances which in this case — the exchange of present against future commodities — influence the mutual valuation of both. As before, it is advisable to distinguish between isolated ✓ exchange and competitive exchange. In the exchange which takes place between an owner of a present commodity and a suitor for it, the price, according to the formula laid down on p. 199, will be fixed some- where between the value of the present good to its owner as , under limit, and its value to the suitor as upper hmi t. If, i for instance, £100 present money are worth to their owner/ exactly as much as £100 of next year’s money while to thej suitor they are worth, on subjective grounds (say, on account of ^ An aaanmpHoii w hich, for the reasons shown on p. 31 5, h olds very widely ; — that is to say, among all persons who own more wealth than they can or will spend in their own productive equipment. 376 THE RA TE IN ISOLATED EXCHANGE book vn temporarily pressing circumstances), as much as £200 of next year’s money, the price of £100 present money will be fixed somewhere between £100 and £200 of next year’s money, and the agio at something between nothing and 100°/- The precise figure that is fixed, in the individual case, within these ^ wide limits, depends on the skill and “ staying power ” dis- played by both parties in conducting the negotiations. As a rule, the owner of present goods will be in a position of advantage , because he can do without the exchange and yet suffer no loss, while the suitor is often driven to pay any price for present goods. Hence the familiar cases where, in the absence of competition, usuriousiy high rates of 50%, 100%, even 200% and 300%, are extorted. Wlien we go farther, and inquire as to the deeper reasons which affect the subjective valuation of the suitors,^ and thus affect the economic upper limit of the agio, we find them a little different in the case of the consn-mptinu Ina.u fr o m what they are in the p rodji rtirm Inau^ tn'wTric.h latter the buying of laboui' is closely allied. In the case of the consumption loan the determinants are ; I — the urgency of want at the time, the probable provisio n / at the time when the loan is to be paid back, and, finally, the A degree of the suitor’s underestimate of the future. The more \ urgently he requires the loan, the more easily he expects to be V able to replace it and the less he takes thought for the morrow, the higher the agio to which he will, in the worst case, consent and vice versd. In the production loan we find different concrete deter- minants. Here the important thins is tbf^ diffp.rp.ucc in pro- 1 ductiveness between the methods open to him w ho get.s_-tha. \loan>_aiiiL.thqse_qpen to him who has to do withou t., it. To recur to our old illustration. If the fisher, who has no capital, and can catch only 3 fish a day by hand, gets a loan of 90 fish, and is thus put in a position to make a boat and net in the course of a month, and with these to catch 30 fish ^ AS regards the sellers of present goods, for simplicity’s sake, we shall, adhere throughout the argument to the assumption that their personal circumstances are such that they value present and future commodities alike. * We may take the case, e.g., of a youth standing on the brink of manhood, kept very short of cash at the moment by his tutor, but with the prospect of a great fortune coming into his absolute disposal in a few months. CH. I DETERMINANTS IN THE PRODUCTIVE LOAN 377 a day for the remaining eleven montns, the balance stands as follows : — without the loan he catches in a year 3 x 365 = 1095 fish; with the loan he catches nothing in the first month, but 30 per day for the other eleven months, that is, 335 X 30 = 10,050, or a surplus of 8955 fish. So long, then, as he has to give anything less than 8955 (next year’s) fish for the borrowed 90 (present) fish, he gains by the transaction. In this illustration the difference in possible return between the two productive methods, and, with it, the upper limit of the economically possible agio, is absurdly high — 8955 next\^ year’s units for 90 present units is something like 10,000%. But there will always be a very important difference when tlm choice lies between capitalist production and hand-to-mouth production, as the latter is, of course, always extremely un- remunerative. The difference, again, will tend to prow less, \ ^hen the choice lies between two different napitalist methods: and -will become more rapidly less in proportion to the length of the process already secured without the loan. This fact is of very great importance as regards the rate of interest, not only in isolated, but also in competitive exchange. If we put it in the clearest possible way now, it will give a good basis for what comes later. In an earlier chapter I called attention to the well-attested, fact that the lengthening of the capitalist process always leads to extra returns, but that, beyond a. certain point, these extra returns are of decreasing amount. Take again the case of fishing. If what we might call the one month’s production process of making of a boat and net leads to the return of the day’s labour being increased from 3 to 30, — ie. by 27 fish, — ^it is scarcely likely that tlm lengthening. oLthe proce^ ^ two or ^ree months^vdll _^uWe or treble the return. Certainly the lengthening it to 100 months will ^not Increase the surplus by a hundredfold. The surplus return — for there will always be a surplus return — .will increase by a slower progr^sion than the production _period. We may, thereTore, mth approximate correctness represent the increasing productivity of extending production periods by the following typical scheme. 378 THE RATE IN ISOLATED EXCHANGE book vii Production Period. Return per annum. Surplus. Without Capital £15 — 1 year 35 £20 2 years 45 10 3 „ 53 8 4 „ 58 5 5 ,, 62 4 6 „ 65 3 7 „ 67 2 8 „ 68 : 10s. 1:; 9 „ 69 : 10s. 1 10 „ 70 0;: It must be understood that I do not attach any importance to these particular figures. Everybody knows that, in every branch of production and at every stage of techriical know- ledge, the figures will differ. In one branch the fall of surplus return may be slower, in another it may be more rapid. All I lay stress on is the fact that the figures express the genera l tendency of surplus returns to fal l. — Assume, to complete the hypothesis, that a worker needs £30 a year to maintain him in suitable circumstances, and let us try to find out on this basis the limit of the economically possible agio which a suitor for productive credit may, in the worst case, offer for a loan of £30 a year . If the suitor has no capital whatever, he can get a return of only £15 without the loan: with the loan, in a one year’s production period he can get a return of £35. In the most extreme case he may therefore, without altering his position for the worse by the transaction, offer an agio of £20 : that is 66|-^. If, on the other hand, the suitor already has a capital of .£30 (whence he gets it — whether it is his own or advanced from other quarters — does not affect the case), he can, without borrowing, engage in a one year’s process and obtain a product of £35, and all that dejends on his getting the loan is the extension of the process from one year to two, and the raising of the return from £35 to £45 ; i.e. a yearly surplus of £10.^ Here, then, the suitor can eeonn Tnir.a.n.y 1 The total surplus return, due to the loan, figures out at £20, since, in each of the two years of the extended production period, the surplus return to labour is £10. But this surplus return is all the same divided over two years , sn that. o nly the amount of £10 is to be reckoned to one Year. In more skilful disposition, however, the bon-ower need not take up, at the beginning of the production CHAP. I FALLS WITH EXTENSION OF PROCESS 379 offer, at the most, an a^o of £10 on £30 : i.e. an interest rate of Similarly, if the suitor, by whatever means, is already equipped for a two years’ process, the loan of £30 is now the cause of a surplus return of £8 (£53 — £45) = 26|-^. Thus the more ample the suitor’s equipment is already — the more capital he has — the lower fall the surplus returns and the ratio of agio dependent on the loan. Tliat is to say, the surplus falls to £5. £4. £3. £2. 30s.. 2Qs.. 10s.. and the rat^o 16|-, 13;^, 10, 6|-, 5, 3^, 1|- per cent. This fall is bound to emerge unless the returns obtainable in 1, 2, 3, 4, X production periods should run, not, as we have assumed, in the progression of 35, 45, 53, 58, 62, etc., but steadily in the much sharper progression of 35, 45, 55, 65, 75 105 1005, etc. In this latter case, on every one-year extension of the production period made possible by the £30, there would depend a constant surplus return of £10, and the upper limit of the economically possible agio would remain uniform at 33-j%. But a ratio of increase like this cannot in any case go beyond a few stages in some few productions it cannot go on permanently and without limit in any production. We come, then, to the important proposition that to in- tendmg producers, generally speaking, a present loan has less value in proportion to the length ■'*1 prAflnotion periods already provided for from r>i->ipr gnnrpps The proposition directly appHes to the rate of interest in isolated exchange, inasmuch as the valuation of the borrower for productive period, the whole amount of the loan from which he defrays his subsistence dur- ing that period : he may raise the' loan by successive instalments,- and this has for result that the loan is outstanding and requires to pay interest only for half the production period. If such a disposition is arranged the yearly surplus return may in the most extreme case be offered as a half-year’s interest on the subsistence loan, and in this case the most extreme interest rate economically possible is double the figures given in the text. The raising of such subsistence loans by instalments thus exerts exactly the same influence on the relation between sub- sistence fund and surplus return, and, at the same time, on the height of the interest rate, as does a suitable “ Staffelung” of production (see above, p. 32.5), with which phenomenon, as may be easily seen, it is closely and intimately connected. ^ Up to a certain point the surplus return may now and then increase even in a greater ratio than the duration of the production period. It may, e.g., happen that the transition from rod -fishing to net -fishing shows a greater advance than the transition from primitive modes of fishing to rod-fishing. But beyond a certain point this cannot be maintained, and the surplus returns show a decreasing ratio. 380 THE RATE IN ISOLATED EXCHANGE book vii purposes directly gives the upper limit of the economically possible rate. It also allows us. however, to judge in what direc - tion this proposition must influence the rate of intere&t in competitive exchange, where the price is the resultant of the subjective valuations of individuals, of whom many are intending producers. As has been said above, the case of productive credit is closely related to the case of the purchase of labour, the employment of productive labourers by the capitalists them- selves. Here, however, there enter certain complications which may be as easily and briefly stated under competitive exchange. I shall not, therefore, discuss them separately, but shall go on at once to explain the rate of interest in developed competitive exchange. THE RATE IN MARKET TRANSACTIONS The character of the market in which present goods are ex- changed against future goods has already been described.^ We now know the people who appear in that market as buyers and sellers. We know that the supply of present goods is repre- sented by the community’s current stock of wealth — with certain unimportant exceptions — and that the demand for them ^ comes n ) from the suitors for nroductive credit who wish to equip themselves for their own work in production, (2) from the suitors for wage-paid labou r, and (3) from the suitors for con- s umption- credit. - To these three categories we may add, under certain reservations, the maintenance of the landowners. Finally, it will be remembered that the resultant market price must, as a rule, be in favour of present goods, and must lead to an agio on the same. What we have now to do is to _grnnp t ngpthp.r the ca uses which determine the, heigh t nf thig agip in one adequate and typical picture. If we were to attempt all at once to draw a picture like this, covering, as it does, the whole area of the varied influences that cross and intersect each other on the market, we should meet with great, indeed insuperable difficulties, in the way of statement. I shall, therefore, act on tlie principle, divide et impera, and first consider how the price is determined xmder the assumption that, confronting the supply of present A goods, there is one single branch of demand, though, in present# circumstances, by far the most important branch, viz. the^ demand of the Wagp ,-Ea,mers Once we have drawn in broad clear lines the most important and difficult part of the whole ^ See above, p. 319, and particularly p. 330. 382 THE RATE IN MARKET TRANSACTIONS book vii picture, it will be relatively easy to define the kind and measure of the share which all the remaining market factors have in ^forming the resultant, and so gradually to make the picture true to the full complexity of practical life. For good reasons ) I also retain provisionally the former assumption, that the whole supply and the whole demand for present goods meet in one single market embracing the entire community . And, finally, we shall suppose meanwhile that all branches of pro- duction show the same productiveness, and also the same increment of productiveness on each extension of the production period : that is to say, we shall assume an identical scale of surplus returns. Suppose, then, that in our community the stock of wealth in the market, as supply, amounts to £1500,000,000, and that there are 10,000,000 of wage-earners. Following the scheme on p. 378, the annual product of each worker increases in all branches of production, in proportion to the length of the pro- duction period, from £35 (in a one year’s process to £7 0 (in a ten years’ process). The question is; — in these circum - ^ stances of the market how high wHI rise th e aghum presenl. goods? It is quite certain, as we have already explained, that the agi o will settle at that level where sup ply and demand exactly ^/ balance each other, and this lies between the subjective valua- tions of the last pair who actually exchange. But the fixing of these valuations here encounters a quite exceptional difficulty, and one which does not occur in any other exchange transac- tion, but has its basis in a special peculiarity of the commodity “ labour.” Every other commodity, that is to say, has a pre- determined subjective value to the one who wishes to buy it. Labour has not, and for this reas on. It is valned according to its prospective product, while the prospective product varies according as that labour is invested in a short or in a long production process. We said above that, in the subjective circumstances of the capitalist, a sum of present goods was, as / a rule, worth eis much as the same sum of future goods. The capitalist will, therefore, count the value of labour equal to 1 Tlia p.aRft nf production carried on entirely without capital, w hich, accordiug to the scheme, would return only £15, w e may leave out of account as practically of no importance. CH. II VALUE OF LABOUR NOT PREDETERMLNED 383 just as many present shillings as it will bring him in in the future. But, according as this labour is invested in a short or a roundabout process, it may bring him in £35 or £58 or £70. At which of these figures is the capitalist to value it ? It may be answered : According to the product aimed at in entering upon the method of production which is, economically, the most reasonable. He will, therefore, value the year’s labour at £35 if, on reasonable grounds, he meditates adopting a one year’s process; at £70 if he considers a ten years’ period the/^^ most suitable. This would be very well if only it was certain beforehand what period was the most suitable for the undertaker. But this is not certain : on the contrary , the length of the process is itself dependent on the rate of wage fived as resultant price on the labour market- If the wage, for instance, stands at £25, a one year’s process is the most favourable for the undertaker. At £25 he gains £10 in the year — or, to put it exactly, in the six months, since, on the average, the advance extends over only six months ; ^ that is, 80^ per annum. In a ten years’ pro- cess for the £25 in wages he gets £70, and the surplus return of £45 is, absolutely, much greater, but, when divided as profit over an average of five years,^ gives only £9 for one year, or a profit of 36%. On the other hand, if the year’s wage is £ 50, it is quite clear that it would be as absurd to choose a one year’s process7 with its product of £35 . as it was most reasonable in the previous circumstances, and only those longer production periods which show an annual product over £50 could be thought of. The matter, therefore, stands as follows. Elsewhere, in the case of other commodities, th^ pinpInympTif. for which th e buyers wish to acquire them is already determined . It is the / fixed point, — the thing which first of all helps to determine the price offered by the buyers, and then through that the resultant market price. Here, in the case of the comTundity / ^ OnlY the wages of the first month are outstanding nearly a whole year..: those of the second month are outstanding only eleyen months, and so on ; all wages of the first six months outstanding more than half a year. Against this the wages of the second six months are outstanding for as much less than the half-year. ^ The calculation is exactly similar to the foregoing. 384 THK RATE IN MARKET TRANSACTIONS book vii Labour on the contrarY. the employment is an undetermiTiftf^ amount, an x, which is first determined by the resultant price. In these circumstances it is clear that the fixed point of the price transactions must be got somewhat differently from the ordinary way ; not, of course, according to different principles or laws, but with a certain casuistical modification in detail which we have now to examine.^ In place of the fixed point, which is not available because the employment of the labour itself is not fixed, we find a substitute in the fact that another amount, usually indetermined, is here fixed, viz, the quantities sold. It may be taken as certain that all the labour offered. like the whole snTn nf p resent goods offered, fin ds a market. The certainty of this is based on a peculiar circumstance. Exactly as, in the " science of money, it is a familiar dogma that, in the long-run, any sum of money, be it great or small, is sufficient to do the work of circulation in a community, so is it true that any 1 Perhaps one or other of my readers will take exception to my looking upon the production period, in which the work of undertaking is carried on, as not a fixed immovable amount. It will be said that each undertaker haa madp. the arrangements for his production on a quite definite footing , and works in any case in the production period corresponding to and determined hy these given arrangements. This is not the case. Even -where the visible outlines of the arrangements, such as workshops, number and kind of employes, and so on, may be pretty permanent, yet, within these fixed lines, a number of litt.lp noticed alterations are possible, by which the length of the production perind might be changed not inconsid etablY, In the simplest shoemaking shop, e.g., the buying of a new machine-made tool, th® wholesale purchase of finished uppers, or, above all, the acquiring of labour-saving instruments such as sewing- machines and the like, involves no unimportant extension of the production period. True, in the shoemaking shop itself one does not notice that the pro- duction of shoes has now become a more lengthy process. But all the more noticeable will it be in those preparatory stages of production where, on account of the shoemaker’s demand — not, of course, the demand of the one shoemaker, but of many, — people jnust now stretch away back in time , as it w ere, and invest original p roductive powers i n machine-making, founding nf factories, and so on. The shoemaker, therefore, according as he covers his demand for the instruments of his business in one way or the other, may as a fact cause a lengthening or shortening of the total production period, and naturally he makes the choice which, in the circumstances, is economically the more advantageous. If, e.g., the lev el of wages is very high, he will prefer to buy machine-made uppers, put up a sewing-machine in his own shop, etc. ; that is to say, in entire correspondence with the statement given in the text, he will prolong the p roduc- tion^perisd : while, if the level of wages is low, he will prefer directly to employ the cheap hand labour, — that is to say, so far as in him lies, to keep the production period short. CHAP. II PRESENT WEALTH BUYS UP LABOUR 385 five hundred millions of capital on that account : only, of course, a sum of present goods, be it great or small, is sufficient to buy up the whole supply of wage labour that exists in the com- munity, and to pay its wages. All that requires to be done is to co n tract or extend the production neriod^. If there are ten million wage workers, and fifteen hundred millions of capital, this stock is just sufficient to pay the ten million workers £30 a year each over a ten years’ production process.^ If there are only no labourers need go idle they cannot ha’i'e their maintenance advanced them for ten years’ process, but (at the same wage of £30) only for a three and a third years’ process, and the average duration of the production period must be curtailed accordingly. Sup- pose there are only fifty millions of capital, all the labour covdd still be bought, but now only for a four months’ process. and it must be secured, by a further shortening of the produc- tion period, that the scanty amount of present goods is renewed after every short period by the accession of fresh returns. It is, therefore, always possible for the existing stock of wealth to buy all the labour, and there are certain reasons in this case that work very strongly towards always making the possible into the actual. Between capitalists and labourers the economic conditions are — with very few exceptions — ex- tremely favourable to the effecting of exchang e. The labourers urgently need present goods, and cannot, or can scarcely turn their own labour to any account ; they will, therefore, to a man rather sell their labour cheaply than not sell it at all. But very much the same is true of the capitalists. In their peculiar circumstances of want and provision for \ want, theii' present goods — which they, in any case, would j lay up against the future — are not worth more to them ‘ than a similar sum of future goods. T hey will, therefore, prefer any purchase of labour where there is an agio, how- ever little it may be. rather than let their capital lie dead ; and the consequence is that aU capital, like all labour, actually comes to a sale. As a fact we see that, in all economic com- munities, although the quantitative relations between wealth ^ On the assumption of a production arranged in the form of stages, whereby (as shown on p. 328, and in Appendix I.) the initial fund need only con tain sub- sistence for half the production period. 2 C y / 386 THE RATE IN MARKET TRANSACTIONS book vij and number of wage -earners are extremely various, these two amounts exactly buy up each other. There are everywhere a few labourers who have no work, and a few capitals which are not employed, but this is, of course, not in contradiction to what has been said. I need scarcely point out that the presence of such unemployed is never traceable to the pur- chasing power of capital be ing insuffi cient to the whole nu mber of the labour ers — in a poorer country, indeed, a capital of half the amount would have to pay the same number of labourers, and actually does pay them — but always to jcertain frictional and temporary disturbances of organisation, ssuch as are inevitable in a mechanism so complicated as the lindustrial division of labour in a great country. ' We may, therefore, assume it as certain that the whole /supply of labour, and the whole supply of present goods, come Ito mutual exchange. Tn this fact the lengtk of the produc- tion period, and thus the amount of product which the under- t aker may obtain through the labour be bny. 97, 100, 103, 237. Spitzer, 354. Strasburger, 75, 178. Supino, 23, 39. Thunen, 87, 213, 394, Turgot, 25, 35, 42, 49. Umpfenbach, 23, 25, 50. Wagner, 23, 29, 39, 62, 67, 72, 100. 119. Walker, F., 100. Walras, 33, 50, 132, 149, 179, 396. Weiss, 53. Wieser, 148, 178, 185, 187, 414. THE END I 331 B67IP (D Bohm-Bawerk, Eu|en V. The Positive Theory of Capital ^51 3671F 65538 - m-y ! ^ f ^ ) \ '}' ’I"'' ■ }': '■ - # (' ■ ' ■".V'*' I ■■ W m