\\4bis Number LIBRARY Trinity College Durham, N. C. Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2016 https://archive.org/details/ethicsofhegel01 hege THE ETHICS OF HEGEL Translated Selections from his “ Rechtsphilosophie ” WITH AN INTRODUCTION BY J. MACBRIDE STERRETT, D.D. PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN THE COLUMBIAN UNIVERSITY, WASHINGTON, D C. AUTHOR OF “STUDIES IN HEGEL’S PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION,” ETC. iP O' yO BOSTON, U.S.A. GINN & COMPANY, PUBLISHERS 1893 Copyright, 1893, By J. MACBRIDE STERRETT. ALL RIGHTS RESERVED. ) m,s #U3l P TO MY WIFE EDITOR’S PROSPECTUS. The Ethical Series, of which this book on Hegel’s Ethics, by Professor Sterrett, is the second number, will consist of a number of small volumes, each of which will be devoted to the presentation of a leading system in the History of Modern Ethics, in selections or extracts from the original works. These selections will be accompanied by explana- tory and critical notes. They will also be introduced by a bibliography, a brief biographical sketch of the author of the system, a statement of the relation of the system to preceding ethical thought, and a brief explanation of the main features of the system and its influence on subsequent ethical thought. The volumes will be prepared by experi- enced teachers in the department of Ethics and with special reference to undergraduate instruction and study in colleges. The series at present will include six volumes as follows : Hobbes, Professor G. M. Duncan, Yale University ; Clarke, President F. L. Patton, Princeton University ; Locke, the Editor of the Series ; Hume, Dr. J. H. Hyslop, Columbia College ; Kant, Professor John Watson, Queen’s University, Canada. Hegel, Professor J. Macbride Sterrett, Columbian University. The increasing interest in the study of Ethics and the consequent enlargement of the courses in college curricula, suggest to every teacher the need of better methods of teaching the subject than those which have quite generally EDITOR'S PROSPECTUS. prevailed in the past. Instruction in the History of Ethics, like instruction in the History of Philosophy, has largely been based on text-books or lectures giving expositions of, and information about, the various systems. Such methods, although serviceable, are not as stimulating and helpful as those which put the student in direct contact with the text of the author, enabling him to study the system itself rather than to study about the system. Undoubtedly the best plan would be to have the student read the entire work of the author, but all teachers will probably concede the impracticability of this in undergraduate work, if a num- ber of systems is to be studied, which is usually desirable. Only inferior, in my judgment, to the best, but impracticable plan, is the plan of the “Ethical Series,” — to study selec- tions or extracts from the original works, embodying the substance of the system. The “ Series ” makes provision for such work in a convenient and comparatively inexpen- sive manner. That the plan of instruction on which the “ Series ” is based is in the interest of better scholarship, I am assured by my own experience, and by that of many other teachers in the leading colleges of the country, with whom I have communicated. It is with the earnest hope of facilitating instruction and study in the History of Ethics that this series is issued. E. HERSHEY SNEATH. Yale University. PREFACE. The great revival of interest and work in the department of Ethics during the present quarter of a century has had its chief inspiration and source in the idealistic philosophy of Germany. Of this philosophy Hegel was the culmination and crown. Hence it is not necessary to-day to apologize for “intruding on the public with a work on Hegel,” as Dr. Stirling did in 1865. Apart from the empirical evolu- tionary school, nearly all the prominent writers on Ethics in England have been following quite the spirit and sub- stance of Hegel. These “ Selections ” have been made from his Philosophie des Rechts embracing one-half of its contents, supplemented with some extracts from his Phänomenologie des Geistes , Philosophie des Geistes and his Philosophy of History (trans- lation). The portions of the Rechts Philosophie omitted have chiefly reference to the special organization of the state and are of less obvious ethical import. The task of translating has been a perplexing one. And the task of mastering his thought in translation may be expected to require at least the arduous effort of thought that it requires in the original, even of German scholars. The difficulties of Hegel, and the impossibility of making any adequate and intelligible translation are too well known to need more than passing mention. I have avoided making a free rendering or paraphrase, though this is much more easy and agreeable for both translator and student. I have learned that one invariably regrets having adopted this easier method, because it invariably deforms and dwarfs PREFACE. viii Hegel’s meaning. I have attempted an exact translation, making it as literal as possible with fairly idiomatic English — too literal for intelligibility, unless accompanied with careful study. Hegel’s language is severely scientific and technical, largely the adaptation of ordinary German to extraordinary significations, to which Wörterbücher afford no clue. Common language expresses common thought, but is necessarily inadequate, without great stretching, to philosophic thought or to the scientific expression of it. Hegel’s work is not merely historical or descriptive of ethical phenomena, but a purely scientific theory of the thought or concept ( Begriff ) underlying and animating all forms of morals and manners. I have given a vocabulary of his chief technical terms which it will be well for the student to master at the outset. The Introduction has been made sufficiently popular for all persons interested in ethical thought — too popular for real students of Hegel. I am indebted for valuable assistance in the way of making out some of the most difficult constructions in the German text of Part First of the “ Selections ” and also for aid in looking over the proof-sheets to my colleague, Professor Hermann Schönfeld, Ph.D. I am also indebted to Mr. P. M. Magnusson, Ph.D., for valuable help in my work of translating most of the “ Selections ” in Part Third. J. MACBRIDE STERRETT. Columbian University, Washington, D.C., July, 1893. TABLE OF CONTENTS Bibliography xi, xii Introduction i 1. Biographical Sketch i 2. Relation of Hegel’s Ethics to previous Ethical Thought 8 3. Exposition of Hegel’s Ethics . . . . . 22 4^ Key-Words . 57 5. Abstract of Hegel’s Introduction .... 63 TRANSLATED SELECTIONS. FIRST PART. ABSTRACT RIGHT. Abstract Will and Personality . 1. Property ( a ) Possession .... ( b ) Use or Consumption ( c ) Relinquishment of Property 2. Contract Wrong \ ( a ) Unintentional Wrong . \ ( b ) Fraud .... V ( c ) Violence and Crime (Punishment 7i 76 82 84 87 89 91 92 94 94 98 SECOND PART. MORALITY. iThe Moral Standpoint . 1. Purpose and Culpability 2. Intention and Welfare 3. The Good and Conscience I0 3 108 1 10 1 16 X TABLE OF CONTENTS. THIRD PART. ETHICALITY ( SITTLICHKEIT ). Concrete Character of Ethicality 1. The Family ( a ) Wedlock (£) Family Possessions (c) Education of Children and the Dissolution of the Family 2. The Civic Community ( a ) The System of Wants Satisfaction of Wants . The Nature of Labor W EALTH Classes of the Civic Community C e Administration of Justice Law as a form of Right . Essential Characteristic of Law Courts of Justice Trial by Jury lice and Municipal Corporation 3. The State The State Distinguished from the Civic Community ( a ) Internal Polity Patriotism The State and Religion . ( b ) Monarchy and International Policy . (c) Universal History The Course of Freedom . PAGE r 3 S 148 149 1 54 H 5 159 163 163 166 168 169 174 D 5 178 181 185 187 I89 190 l 93 200 203 206 207 212 BIBLIOGRAPHY. Works of Hegel relating to Ethics. 1. Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts. 1S33. Herausg. von E. Gans, Hegel’s Werke , Band VIII. 2. Phänonie 7 iologie des Geistes. Band II. 3. Philosophie des Geistes. Band VII. 4. The same. Translated into French by A. Vdra : — Philo- sophie de V Esprit de Hegel. Par A. .Vera. 5. Philosophie der Geschichte. Band IX. 6. The same. Translatedby J. Sibree. (Bohn’s Library.) 7. Rechts -, Pflichten- und Religions-Lehre. Band XVIII. 8. The same. Translated into English with notes by Dr. William T. Harris. Jour. Spec. Phil., Vol. IV. 9. The same. Translated with Supplementary Essays by B. C. Burt, 1892. 10. Hegel's Philosophy of the State and of History. An Exposition, by Professor George S. Morris, in Griggs’s Philo- sophical Classics, 1887. '‘Ethical and other Treatises in the Spirit of Hegel. 1. Die me 7 ischliche Freiheit. Von Wilhelm Vatke, 1841. 2. Systetn der philosophische 7 i Moral. Von Dr. Karl L. pichelet, 1828. 3. Die sittliche Weltord 7 i 7 i 7 ig. Von Moritz Carriere. 4. Syste 7 >i der Rechtsphilosophie. Von Adolph Lasson, 1S82. The Natioii. By Elisha Mulford, 1875. The Republic of God. By the same, 1882. The Philosophy of Education. Translated from the German of J. K. F. Rosenkranz. Prolego 7 )ie 7 ia to Ethics. By Thomas Hill Green, 1884. Xll BIBLIOGRAPHY. Outlines of a Critical Theory of Ethics. By Professor John Dewey, 1890. Ethical Studies. By F. H. Bradley, 1876. Constructive Ethics. By W. L. Courtney, 1886. Ethics of Naturalism. By W. R. Sorley, 1885. Introduction to Social Philosophy. By J. S. Mackenzie, 1889. A Manual of Ethics. By the same, 1893. Moral Order and Progress. By S. Alexander, 1891. The Elements of Ethics. By J. H. Muirhead, 1892. Darwin and Hegel. A pamphlet. By D. G. Ritchie. Darwinism and Politics. By the same. Essays in Philosophical Criticism. Edited by Andrew Seth and R. H. Haldane, 1883. The Secret of Hegel. By Dr. J. Hutchison Stirling, 1865. Lectures on the Philosophy of Law. By J. Hutchison Stirling, in Vols. VI. and VII. of Jour, of Spec. Phil. BIOGRAPHICAL. Leben Hegel's. Von Karl Rosenkranz. Hegel’s Werke (sup- plement), Band XIX. Apologie Hegel's gegen Dr. Haym. Von K. Rosenkranz, 1858. Hegel als de 7 itscher Nationalphilosoph. By the same, 1871. Hegel Mid seine Zeit. Von R. Haym, 1857. Hegel. By Professor Edward Caird, 1883. The Spirit of Modern Philosophy. By Professor Josiah Royce, 1892. INTRODUCTION. i. Biographical Sketch. The Philosophy of Hegel is much less personal than most systems, especially in contrast with that of Fichte. His head rather than his heart is what appears through- out both his life and his writings. While this gives his biography less interest, it gives his writings much more scientific form. In speaking of Philosophy, as showing us “ a succession of noble minds, a gallery of heroes of thought,” Hegel him- self has remarked : “The events and actions of this history are, therefore, such that personality and individuality of character do not enter to any large degree into its content and matter. In this respect, the history of Philosophy contrasts with political history, in which the individual, according to the peculiarity of his disposition, talents, affections, the strength or weakness of his character, and in general, according to that through which he is this individual, is the subject of actions and events. In Philosophy, the less deserts and merits are accorded to the particular individual, the better is the history.” 1 It is, therefore, more pertinent for us to ask, What is Hegel l instead of asking, Who was Hegel? In fact, this is the way we ordinarily think of Hegel, as the living sys- tem of thought which he wrought out. The true h istory o f a philosopher is the history of his thought a nd its genesi s. 1 Hegel’s History of Philosophy, translated by E. S. Haldane, 1S92. Vol. I. p. 1. BIO GR A PH IC A L SHE TCII. Hegel’s external biography is even more uneventful than that of most men of thought — the Alexanders and Caesars of the intellectual world. The mere subjective private characteristics, opinions and prejudices of the man need concern us but little in comparison with the universal ele- ment of thought, which was the real heart of the man. The personal character of Hegel is not very interesting: yet it was not unworthy of the philosopher as a man, and upon the whole it may be said that it needs no apology. The two points in which he has been most criticised relate to his treatment of Schelling and his so-called subserviency to the Prussian government. In neither of these respects is the reproach thoroughly justifiable. His life was devoid of romance, being rather that of a prosaic, common-sense man of the intellectual world. Still, as compared with that of Kant, ein alles Zermalmender , the life of Hegel, ein alles Umfassender, was much more that of a citizen of the world. His acquaintance with the great literary and political men and movements of his time was intimate and profound. If he was not a patriot of Fichte’s type, he was not without great interest and influence in politics. We give a brief summary of the events of his outward life . 1 1 The limits of space preclude anything more than a brief biograph- ical sketch of Hegel’s life. One forgoes with regret the task of pre- senting the fuller biography, with temperate estimate of it as a genuine, human, scholarly life of the modern Aristotle. Rosenkranz’s Hegel's Leben and Hegel als deutscher Nationalphilosoph afford ample materials for such work. This, however, has already been used most skilfully by Professor Edward Caird, who gives us a most, admirable exposition and estimate of the whole Hegel in his volume in Blackwood’s Philo- sophical Classics. There is no better introduction to Hegel’s personality and work needed. Professor Josiah Royce (The Spirit of Modern Philosophy ) also gives a brief, but with a smack of sharpness, pen-sketch of Hegel’s personal characteristics, using the material of the hostile critic Haym rather than that of the eulogistic disciple Rosenkranz. Since writing the following sketch I have, for the first time, looked BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH. 3 Georg W ilhelm Friedrich Hegel was born at Stut tgart. the '~capital of Wiirtemberg. on the 27th of August, 1 770, and retained throughout life the Suabian characteristics of bluntness, shrewdness, and of deep interest in religion and in political affairs. His family belonged to the quiet con- servative middie-class. His father was an officer in the fis- cal service and a decided aristocrat. His mother seems to have been a woman of more than ordinary intelligence, and devoted to the instruction of her eldest son. She died when Hegel was thirteen years old. How grateful a remembrance he cherished of her is shown in a letter to his sister when he was fifty-five years old. “To-day is the anniversary of mother’s death, which I always keep in memory of her.” His biographer, Rosenkranz, says that his early youth was passed quietly and cheerfully, without any remarkable ex- periences. The official position of his father brought his family into connection with the higher class of citizens. In his fifth year he was sent to the Latin school, and in his seventh he entered the city Gymnasium. He was always an exemplary scholar, and won the prizes in every class. In the diary which he kept from his fifteenth to his seven- teenth year there are traces of deep ethical sentiments, though none of moral conflicts. Thus early, too, the Auf- klärung possessed him. He inveighs against intolerance and superstition, and asserts the necessity of thinking for one’s self. From this diary we learn, too, that though pedantic as a student, he did not fail to cultivate the social side of life. He frequented concerts, and enjoyed the so- ciety of the pretty maidens he thus met. Rosenkranz notes two peculiarities of Hegel at this time which he preserved through life : he was addicted to taking snuff and devoted to playing cards, especially to whist. through Dr. J. Hutchinson Stirling’s great work on “ The Secret of Hegel," and find scattered throughout his most appreciative and valuable expository work the most scathing and harsh terms used in characteriz- ing Hegel. 4 BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH. In his sixteenth year he began the habit of keeping a Common-Place Book and of writing out analyses, with copious quotations, of every book of importance that he read. He was ready to thus fill his empty self with the best of the best authors — to lose himself in them that he might find himself enlarged and invigorated. For the purpose of putting one’s self at the point of view of great authors, so as to lose one’s petty self in them, he held that there was no better way than this writing out copious extracts from their works. This is the first experience with the principle of edu- cation most resolutely maintained by Hegel throughout life in regard to culture in general, i.e. the principle of self-aliena- tion (Selbst-Entfremdung) in order to true humanization. But even at this time of saturating himself with the thoughts of others, he showed that he was not merely passive, as he ex- presses the greatest admiration of the Greek world of culture, in which he soon found himself no mere pilgrim or alien. He was thus early penetrated by the nobility and serenity of the Grecian spirit, and as early showed his dislike of the prevalent morbid sentimentalism. At this time, too, we find traces of that conservative spirit in regard to the observance of the customary in social life and current affairs which char- acterized him throughout life as a conservative in religion and politics. He thought it to be but vain conceit to be continually protesting against established customs and creeds and to be obtruding one’s own whimsical tastes upon the public. “Virtue,” he said a little later, “is not a troubling one’s self about a peculiar and isolated morality of one’s own. The striving for any such morality is futile and im- possible of attainment.” The first trace of interest in philosophy is found in one of his note-books, when he was fifteen years of age. He defines philosophy to be “the pressing through into the very ground and inner constitution of human conceptions and knowledge of the profoundest truths.” BIO GR A PH IC A L SKE TCH. 5 He also then formed an intimate friendship with the young poet Hölderlin, with whom he studied Plato and the Greek drama. Having been “consecrated to theology” by his parents, he entered the University at Tübingen when he was eighteen years of age. The first three years of the course were devoted to philosophical studies, and the last two to theological. He submitted to the dull routine of the work there in a becom- ing manner, meantime pursuing his own private studies, especially of the classics. It was there he formed that inti- mate and fruitful union with the brilliant, precocious Schel- ling (ein praecox ingeniinn, as his father designated him), five years his junior, that forms such an important chapter in his life. For a time, at least, he was stirred by the revolutionary sentiments that were so mightily working then. Together with Schelling and other students he formed a political club for the discussion of the burning questions of the day, and for the championing of the idea of liberty, equality and fraternity. He was a jovial companion, and entered with zest into the various experiences that characterize the Ger- man student-life. Yet he had that dignified sobriety of manner which won for him the nickname of “old man.” “ God be with the old man ” was found written by a fellow- student in one of his books. Among other tasks, as theo- logical student, he also performed that of preaching sermons. Dry formalism characterized these productions. He studied Kant’s philosophy, and w T as especially inter- ested in his ethical works. But thus early he had got beyond Kant’s dualism, and declared against the possibility of pure moral activity, or of the “ Practical Reason ” apart from the desires of the sensuous nature. Already he looked upon man’s nature as a unitary process of self-realization. He left the University in 1793 with a certificate for good parts and character, and for fair acquaintance with theology 6 BIO GR A PH IC A L SHE TCH. and philology, but with no knowledge whatever of phi- losophy. Like many others, his road to a place among the recog- nized world-thinkers lay through the conditions which hamper one in the situation of a private tutor in a rich family. Six uneventful years were thus spent by Hegel. But they v/ere years of great intellectual activity, years of increase of knowl- edge, but above all of self-activity, in working over in the alembic of his own thought these gathered treasures. His education had given him a bias towards theological studies, and to the end of his life the study of religion fascinated his mind. We find him now busied with exegetical studies. In 1795 he finished writing a Life of Christ. Here, too, we find him noting the essential elements of Judaism as contrasted with the Greek view of religion, and even dis- paraging Christianity in comparison with the former, though a few years later he had worked through to the estimate of Christianity as the absolute religion, or the principle of self-realization through self-sacrifice alike in man and in God, in his relation to man. It is in this period, too, that we find the idea of love as the most significant one to Hegel. In his appreciation of it we find implicit the whole of his later intellectual system. In the movement of love he saw the dialectic leading out of self into its other, in order to its own self-realization. Here, too, we find him making that laborious study of history, which later gave him the basis for his Philosophy of History. His interest in politics also led him to a fresh study of Kant’s ethical treatises, that of the Philosophy of Right , appearing in 1797, and that of The Metaphysic of Ethics, in 1798. Heg el strove to unite the two concept ions of positive law and subjective morality into a higher one, which h e first named “Life,” and later “Social Moralit y (i.e. Sittlichkeit ). He protested against Kant’s utter subjugation of nature and his dismemberment of humanity ( Zerstücklung des Men- BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH. 7 scheu ) into a casuistry arising from the absoluteness of the conception of duty. It was at this time that the Wiirtemberg Diet was held to promulgate a new constitution based upon the principle of the freedom of person and property of all citizens. The king favored this constitution, but the aristocratic classes, with their vested privileges, protested against it in the name of “good old German rights.” Here Hegel took his stand with the king against the prerogative of feudalism, the privi- lege of the guild and the purchased monopoly of the rich, for the king was, in this instance, the representative of rational freedom, of the true idea of the State. Through -all these theological, historical and practical studies there was the nascent life of the Idea Ithrobbing, which was to systematize all into the concrete unity of his later philosophy. It grew and took shape and form through them. He did not at first set himself the task of finding such a concrete principle. He did not “make his studies in public,” as he said of Schelling, but he felt that he was making advances which would eventually come to light in a full orbed system. Beginning with particular questions pressing on him for solution, he was, as he says, “driven onward to philosophy, and, through reflection, to transform the ideal of his youth into a system.” This “system” he put in writing in the year 1798. The above quotation is from a letter to Schelling, appealing to him as the one most likely to aid him in entering upon a public career as phil- osopher. In January, 1801, he went to Jena, where he championed Schelling’s Identity-Philosophy against that of Fichte. In 1802 he united with Schelling in publishing a “ Critical Journal of Philosophy,” in which the common- sense dualism of mind and matter was the stock object of attack, as well as the philosophy of subjectivity. The Identity- Philo sophy , however differently held by Schelling and Hegel, furnished “the conception of a unity above all 8 RELATION TO differences, which manifests itself in all differences, and to which all differences must refer for their explanation.” From Privat-docent he became Professor in the University in 1805. In 1807 he published his first important book, the Phae- nomenologie des Geistes , which he finished amid the thunders of the battle of Jena. He seemed to have been as absorbed in this work as Archimedes at the siege of Syracuse. In “ this voyage of discovery ” Hegel touched and illuminated and criticised all the various standpoints of ethical and speculative philosophy. From 1808 to 1816 he was Pro- fessor in the Gymnasium at Nürnberg, publishing his Logik in 1816. For a year he was Professor at Heidelberg, where he published his Encyclopädie der philosophischen Wissen- schaften, in which he gave his whole system in detail and in scientific form. In 1818 he was called to the most im- portant chair of philosophy in Germany — that recently filled by Fichte in the University of Berlin. From this time till his death in 1831 he was recognized as the greatest teacher of philosophy in Germany. To fill out this out- line of dates and places, so as to give a biography of such a thinker, would require an exposition of the whole of his intellectual deed. To portray him as he was, would be to reproduce him as he thought. In order to determine the place of ethics in his whole system, it is at least necessary to give a brief outline of his Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences. Before doing this, however, we may glance at the ethical thought of his times. II. Relation to Previous Systems. It is scarcely possible to speak of the relation of Hegel’s ethics to previous ethical systems, without giving the relation of his philosophy as a whole to previous systems of phi- PREVIOUS SYSTEMS. 9 losophy. To properly orientate the English student ten years ago by such a statement, would have been the task of a whole volume. But so much has been done within the past decade or two as to render this superfluous here, beyond the general references given in the Bibliography. The Devdop7ne?it from Kant to Hegel 1 is already a well- worn topic even in English, as it has long been in German. Hegel is by common consent the continuator and completor of the idealistic movement begun by Kant. The develop- ment of this movement is an excellent historical illustration of Hegel’s own method, from the abstract universal through difference and particularity to the concrete synthetic uni- versal. Hegel is said to have burned his bridges behind him. Stirling will have it that he was always “ a crafty borrower,” using and then abusing his predecessors. But the bridges of thought are incombustible, and it is not diffi- cult to trace the continuity of Hegel’s thought with that of Kant through the diversity of Fichte and Schelling. Hegel, for the most part, leaves out names and dates, abstracting the essence of systems and integrating them into his own system. His intimate relation to Kant, however, is best shown by the polemic which he constantly wages against all parts of Kant’s system, especially his ethical theory. In relation to Kant, Stirling shuts up Hegel in the single sentence: “Hegel simply conceives the ego to develop into its own categories and, these being complete, externalization to result from the same law.” This was however no simple matter, but rather the prodigious labor of the concept itself. So too, to shut up Hegel in a sentence in relation to Kant’s ethical theory we might say, — he simply (rather, complexly) gave an exposition of the course that the abstract universal law or “Categorical Imperative” of Kant must take and has taken in becoming definite, concrete, realized, incarnate in the ethical life of humanity. 1 The title of Professor Andrew Seth’s volume. IO RELATION TO The starting point of both Kant and Hegel was man as thinking will. But Kant considers the will of subjective man in unattainable identity with the universal will of the tran- scendent intelligible world, while Hegel gives us the vital synthesis of these two in his conception of the ethical world in which each one has his station and definite duties. The categorical imperative upon both was Tvwdt aeavrov on its practical side, the will. They differed chiefly in their con- ception of the aeavrov. whose exegesis they attempted . 1 With Kant it was the abstract, subjective self ; with Hegel it was the concrete, objective, the completely ethicized or socialized self. Kant lived and labored under the concep- tions of the eighteenth century rationalism, which held that reason was innate in every man as a sum total of clear, fixed notions, while Hegel considered reaso n as an immanent impulse of r ationality that was c ontinually realizing itself in li hinan experience . They both had a metaphysic of ethics. But with Kant this was forever unutterable, with Hegel it had been continually uttering itself in the institutions of man. With one it was formless, with the other it was the continuously self-realizing Word that from the beginning was formative of the moral organism of humanity. The one looked solely within, the other looked outward for the self to be studied. Again with Kant the true res interna was absolutely supersensible. With Hegel it was expressed in definite and increasingly adequate forms in the res publica of the external world of man’s activity. H ence he make s his “ Philosophy of History” an illustrative exposition of his science of ethics. The State, in the most concrete sense of this termpif the aeavrov manifesting itself in temporal con- ditions. The history of the world is the tribunal through which man utters the forms of the categorical imperative heard in the supersensible world. Let us say in brief, then, 1 I quote here and elsewhere in this Introduction from my article on Hegel's Ethics in “The International Journal of Ethics,” January, 1892. PREVIOUS SYSTEMS. 1 1 that the difference between Kant and Hegel may be formu- lated as the difference between an abstract and a concrete atavTov. Hegel never ceased to inveigh against the vice of abstract- ness. His whole work consists in starting from, criticising, and passing beyond various abstract conceptions to a real concrete in which alone they find their place as organic phases or members. That which is true relatively to its correlate is false when abstracted from its correlate. And both correlates are true only when they pass through this category of reciprocity to the organism which they both imply and demonstrate. The empirical and the noumenal self; the pure reason and the practical reason; subjective freedom and conditioning environment; duty and the good, — these are some of the elements of ethical man that Kant abstracted from their organic process, wherewith to build his airy castle of morality. Abstractions, every one of them, says Hegel, who endeavors to lead through them to the more concrete view. We may, however, select two terms which will illustrate the difference between Kant and Hegel in ethics, — i.e., Moralität and Sittlichkeit , both of which are used by the Germans for what we call morality. The first denotes the morality of the heart or of the conscience. The latter denotes conventional morality, or the objective cus- toms that are recognized as moral mores , Sitten ). The first is the individual conscience, the second is the social conscience. Hegel would say that there would be no Moralität without Sittlichkeit , while Kant, with his categor- ical imperative, would make each individual an Athanasius contra mundum. Hegel would say that there could be no duty without some objective good as content for the formal good-will. [That is, there can be no abstract self-realiza- tion by the conscientious man, no good-will without good manners. To realize himself the individual must do it in the forms of social man, must go beyond himself to be him- 12 RELATION TO self. He must erect himself above himself and expand him- self beyond himself in his actualizing of his good-will. Only in the objective forms of his station can he find his duties. Otherwise his morality is sure to be peevish, cranky, and" tyrannical, though, as a Simon Stylites, he may write the title of saint before his name. Hegel makes most trenchant criticisms 1 of Kant’s formal law, showing that as an abstract universal it can neither suggest any particular duties nor test the rightness of rules otherwise suggested. It can only be a voice thundering in the inner Sinai, “thou shalt,” with- out power to proceed to decalogic or monologic specification of what to do. Only an objective standard of right can afford the ground of private judgment and render it other than mere wilfulness or mis-judgment. Pythagoras had this in view when he said that the best education one could desire for his son would be to have him become a citizen of a nation with good institutions. On the other hand, such good institutions are impossible without the element of Moralität. Society does not exist apart from the individual. It is rather an organism of organisms, whose Sittlichkeit expresses the immanent Moralität of its people. It exists in and through the life of its members. Hegel’s conception combatted both an abstract individualism and an abstract societarian- ism. His ethics are the result of the organically related ele- ments of abstract personal, or external, rights and Moralität. Plis Sittlichkeit is the very life of the most concrete form of the self or man, — i. e., the State. It is the science of this body politic in its movement of self-realization, in which also the individual realizes himself, because its realization is what he must enter into in order to be what he ought to be. We should note that nothing could be more false to Hegel than to translate his Sittlichkeit by mere conventionality or his Sitten by mere customs. This would be to take out the 1 Hegel’s Werke , i. 313, referred to by Professor Caird, “The Phi- losophy of Kant,” ii. 186. PREVIOUS SYSTEMS. *3 vital heart which formed, received and obeys loyally its own customs. The child thoroughly permeated by the family spirit yields glad obedience to family customs. The patriot, in peace as in war, observes his national customs and laws as expressions of his own true will. There is no mere blind conservatism in all this, but rather the same vital spirit which goes on to reform old customs, adapting them to the new and higher forms of life. The morality of the individual is possible only in this realm of the ethical ( sittlich ) world. He must have suckled at the breast of his environing ei9os and have converted it into flesh of his flesh and bone of his bone. There is to be found the material and the standard of his own morality. “ The ethical life of the individual is but a pulse-beat of the whole system and itself the whole system.” All education is the art of making men ethical (sittlic/i), of transforming the old Adam into the new Adam. “The child is the mere possibility of a moral being.” 1 Obedience is the beginning of practical morality. His dis- cipline is the entering fulness, through which he becofnes a son, brother, husband, father, citizen and a cultured man. Hegel throughout holds in organic relation both elements of solidarity and independence. Nothing could be fur- ther than his theory from the mechanical, conservative conventionality of Chinese morality. He says that “the distinguishing feature of the Chinese is that everything belonging to the spirit — unconstrained morality, heart, in- ward religion - — is alien to it.” Again, he says : “Custom, activity without opposition, for which there is only a formal duration, in which the fulness and zest that originally characterized the aim of life, is out of the question. This is death to individuals and nations, or mere nullity and tedium. Only the adoption of some new purpose can awaken, can revivify such people.” 2 1 Cf. Hegel’s Werke , Band I., 396 and 399. 2 Hegel’s Philosophy of History, pp. 144 and 78. 14 RELATION TO The difference between the ethics of Kant and Hegel may also be expressed in these two formulas: “Duty for duty’s sake” and “ My station and its duties.” With Kant Duty is the abstract transcendent law of the intelligible world which no man can ever realize, and which Duty yet commands man to realize for its own sake. The absolute- ness of Duty was sometimes insisted upon by both Kant and Fichte in a thoroughly inhuman way, as utterly divorced from all joys of the heart and secular happiness. It was against this moral rigorism of formal duty, slighting all regard to the phase of subjective needs and to the diversi- ties of individualities and situations that Jacobi made his now classical protest: “Nay, I am that atheist, that profane person, who in despite of the will that wills nothing (i. e., in despite of the abstract formal precepts of morality) will lie, like the dying Desdemona; prevaricate and deceive, like Pylades representing himself to be Orestes; will murder, like Timoleon; break law and oath, like Epaminondas and Johann de Witt; resolve on suicide, like Otho; commit sac- rilege, like David; nay, pluck ears of corn on the Sabbath, only because I am hungry and the law was made for man and not man for the law,” claiming the right for such deeds against the absolute irrational letter of the law. Though Hegel (in 1802) criticised 1 Jacobi very severely and pointed out the danger of “Jacobi’s principle of the beauty of indi- viduality ” leading to the exalting of sentiment and instinct to be the judge of the ethical, he afterwards (in 1817) recog- nized the element of truth in Jacobi’s fierce protest against moral rigorism. Kant’s emphasis on this element of morality was a needed corrective of hedonism, but it could afford no table of definite duties to be performed: He was himself no Moses to bring it down from the mount on tables of stone. Indeed to define or particularize the law would be to destroy its universality and thus its imperativeness. The 1 Hegel’s Werke, Band I., 105-111. PREVIOUS SYSTEMS. 15 good will could not be found on earth, because the law could give no laws. “Obey duty” could therefore mean, do no particular deed, because no particular is equal to the uni- versal. It could only be done by the absolute annihilation of the individual, for you cannot universalize any particular maxim, nor can you particularize the formal universal law without marring it. Hegel was the Moses to bring the law down from the mount. The tables of stone were the deposit of reason, realized more or less consciously, in the practical ways of a people, in the substantial constitutive spirit of men as expressed in traditional and current codes. Against Kant’s dictum “ The good ought to be ” Hegel opposed the assertion “The good is." The law was found throbbing through the social organism of humanity, its vital and syn- thetic principle. In living the concrete life of one’s station and people, the individual was fulfilling duty. The life of the social community (family, society, nation) exemplifies the concrete, objective, inclusive law. It is the moral organism in which the individual must be a vital organic member. At every stage of every community there is present a world so far moralized. The ethical man is the wise man who knows and identifies himself with his community. The immoral man is the one who is out of harmony with this good will, the will for the good of the community. We should know better than to think that we know better than this larger, communal self. Duty thus becomes definite and concrete. I belong to certain circles of fellow-men. I live in certain social tissues. This is my station in life. To know this is to know my duties. I must realize myself by fulfilling all the rela- tions about my station. I must fill my place, perform a definite function in a definite organism, be a vital mem- ber of it. Organs and organism mutually live and work for each other. “The individual’s morality is a pulse-beat i6 RELATION TO of the whole system and itself the whole system.” Thus the abstract formal universal law of Kant is exchanged for a reflection in the individual of the concrete, objective ethical world of his community. It becomes an immanent intelli- gible universal, definite and concrete. In Kant we find the emphasis put on the individual. Hegel emphasizes rather the function of the obj ective social organism, which he calls the State , to rear the individual i nto that condition where respect for th e right is combin ed with ethical bea.ii.t v. “This lofty intuition,” says Rosen- kranz, “is the Hellenic trait in Hegel, which, however, did not lead him to abate a tittle of the sharpness and energy of the Germanic principle of individuality.” Hegel himself declared that the study of the master-pieces of classical literature should be “the spiritual bath, the profane baptism which imparts to the soul the first and inamissible tone and tincture of good taste and science.” 1 Certainly the anarchic conception of “ Man versus the State ” was as foreign to Hegel’s thought as it would have been to a citizen of Athens. He would rather say, you cannot be a man without the State, you cannot be a whole unless you are a vital member of a whole. This, perhaps, is as far as Hegel brings us in the present treatise. But, as we shall show, this is only a part of a larger whole into which Hegel carries up the self-realizing process of the will into the absolute realm, carries up humanity on the mount of transfiguration, — into the realm of Absolute Spirit, which is the real presupposition, cause and end of objective spirit , or of man in secular relations. We might thus go per saltum , as Hegel himself did, from Kant to Hegel. But we should at least notice the media- tion of the ethical philosophy of Fichte, whose personality and ethical enthusiasm really eclipses his philosophy in worth and interest. Like Jacobi, he had a heart of fire, ] Karl Schmidt’s Geschichte der Pädagogik, TV., 678. Edition of 1862. PREVIOUS SYSTEMS. J 7 but unlike him, he followed his head, endeavoring to com- plete the work of Kant. Kant refused to own this work, being unable to recognize the skeleton which he had formed when clothed in flesh and blood by Fichte. Fichte claimed to harmonize Kant’s two Critiques , reducing his dualism to the monism of subjective idealism in morals as weil as in philosophy. Fie made the ego to be the author of both the moral law and of the endeavor to realize it. The prin- ciple of unity thus attained is the ego itself. This alone, he claimed, could be the true significance of Kant’s autonomy of the will. Beyond the ego there is naught, not even the ghostly Ding an sich , nor the suprasensible intelligible world. This is subjective idealism, where the ego both forms (macht) and creates ( schafft ) its own world, in definite contradiction to Kant’s dictum, macht zwar der Verstand die Natur , aber er schafft sie nicht. It was owing to this character of sub- jective idealism that Flegel relegates it to the rank of an historical and superceded system. He says that Fichte denied all external reality, making the ego to produce its own non-ego for conduct as well as for thought. Still Fichte held that in morality the identity — ego=non-ego — was never fully realized, the identity thus remaining a subjective one, and a struggle with self the essence of morality. Thus, the highest point of the system is only a must ( sollen ) and a striving (streben). In showing this impossible demand, never able to attain objectivity, Hegel leaves the system as nothing more than subjective idealism of the empirical ego . 1 That Hegel failed to do Fichte justice is evident to any reader of Fichte, though we feel this to be a slight done to his personality and moral enthusiasm rather than any injustice to his theory of ethics .' 2 1 For Hegel’s criticism of Fichte cf. Hegel’s Werke, Band I. 2 “ It is difficult to speak calmly of Fichte. His life stirs one like a trumpet. Fie combines the penetration of a philosopher with the fire of a prophet and the thunder of an orator ; and over all his life lies the beauty of a stainless purity.” — Chamber's Encyclopedia. iS RELATION TO Accepting this criticism as true, taking Fichte at his word as a subjective idealist, we may say that he utterly outdid Kant’s boasted Copernican feat, not only making the stars to revolve around the ego as the central sun, but making the ego to be the creator of the whole moral firmament itself. Thus in morals with Fichte the appeal must always be to the individual’s conviction of duty. Ffe must act according to his conscience. I am not aware that Hegel or any other one has directly charged Fichte with the evils that naturally flow from the principle of the right of private judgment, the evils of individualism, moral atomism, moral mis-judgment, though these are consequences of all subjective idealism. The private conscience can have no judgment, for a judg- ment is essentially a universal as Kant taught. It can only have whims, caprices, likings and opinions of a private and therefore of a particular and partial character. Unsaturated with the communal universal life, ceasing to be a pulse-beat in the system, his judgment loses the character of a judg- ment or law. Following Kant, Fichte at first separates even more sharply between the spheres of Right (legality) and Ethics (morality), making the former to be utterly independent of the latter, and excluding it entirely from the realm of morality. Right (legal) is merely mechanical, external force holding individuals in the bonds of civil society. In morality the individual is purely autonomous. The State is merely a social compact, proceeding from the want of confidence and sociality. In his later philosophy, however, he puts more emphasis upon the State as the condition of morality, making it to rest, not on the compact of individuals, but upon the aim of the species. To it belongs the imposition of all forms of culture and activity. Its final aim is to make ethi- cality ( Sittlichkeit ) possible. Its power is both obligatory and enfranchising, in the education of the race . 1 Thus he 1 Cf. Adolph Lasson’s Rechtsphilosophie, 6 and 100-102. PREVIOUS SYS TEA/S. 1 9 approaches more nearly the position of Hegel’s Philosophy of the State , though in no scientific form. Like Schelling, in his latter day he ran into mystical pantheism and abso- lutism. We need say but little of the relation of Hegel to Schel- ling, of their early pact, of Hegel’s apparent discipleship, of the lasting unpleasantness between them after the publica- tion of the Vorwort to Hegel’s Phänomenologie des Geistes. Beginning as an ardent Fichtean, Schelling soon developed in his Identity-Philosophy an abstract pantheism. The Program of the Critical Journal of Philosophy , which Schel- ling and Hegel edited jointly, asserted that “the great imme- diate interest of philosophy is to put God again absolutely at the head of the system, as the one ground of all, the principium essendi et cognoscendiP Hegel took this in earnest, and ever remained faithful to it, applying it to the solution of ethical antinomies and to the explanation of the ethical life of mankind. His course onward was towards a more concrete conception of the Absolute as Subject, as Spirit, while Schelling’s course was the reverse, making the Abso- lute to be the mere indifference point or the identity of in- determinate substance. It is with this blank, unspiritual principle that Hegel definitely breaks in his Preface to his first independent work, Die Phäno7netiologie des Geistes. “ In such philosophy,” he says, “the Absolute is, as it were, shot out of a pistol.” “ It is the night in which all cows are black.” That is, in it all different things — right and wrong, good and bad — are the same. This blank Absolute Substance of Schelling furnished no foundation for ethics, while the eternally self-realized and self-realizing Subject of Hegel does. God is the beginning and the -goal, the orderer of the moral order of the world and the creator of the moral ideal. It is this divine principle which constitutes the intellectual and ethical cosmos into which man is born for self-realiza- tion. For the individual, self-realization is to come through 20 RELATION TO renunciation of the empty self in favor of the larger and truer self mirrored for him in the various circles of the social organism, and ultimately in the institutions of Absolute Spirit — Art, Religion and Philosophy. As to Hegel’s crafty indebtedness to Fichte and Schelling, it is to be con- sidered that we may make and read a patchwork of the two that seems like Hegel, but that we read it in the light of the full, organic, scientific work of Hegel himself. At best, his predecessors’ works were but the quarry whence his genius builded a great structure. Hegel’s ethical view was also in marked contrast with and opposition to the ethics of the general eighteenth century view known as the Aufklärung , edairdsscment and free thought or rationalism. The Aufklärung was essentially a protest against all tra- ditional dogmas, cults, creeds and institutions . 1 The trans- cendent worth of the illuminated and enfranchised individual of that time was a very delirium of self-conceited private judgment, setting up private reason as the valid tribunal before which to summon all manner of hitherto valid laws and customs. It was a conceited enlightment ( edairdsse - ment) or a clearing up {Auf klärung) that, as Schelling said, had turned into a clearing out (H^jklärung) of all the wisdom and practical experience of the race. This produced that ethical atomism in which each atom was independent of every other one and of all forms of association in which they had been enslaved by priestcraft and statecraft. Rousseau asserted this freedom and validity of the merely “ natural man,” decivilized as far as possible. But the natural man was not large enough to measure all things, to appreciate and estimate rightly the universal human reason already done into ethical forms of life. Hence it virtually dropped all judgment, all application of universal principles, and 1 For Hegel’s exposition and criticism of this movement consult Phän. des Geistes, 356-437 ; and Philosophy of History , 456-474. PR E VI O US S YS TEAIS. 2 X stuck to its own private pint-cup measure. Kant, in refut- ing Hume by demonstrating the existence of a priori princi- ples of judgment, of categories absolutely independent of experience, did not himself attain to real objectivity and validity. While proclaiming universal and objective princi- ples he still made them subjective , and hence his philosophy could not stem the current which insisted upon privatizing these universals instead of insisting upon the private con- science universalizing itself in the communal traditional conscience. Hegel asserts 1 that tiu s-fce cd o m ar wl- mdt^wd- ence and validity of private judgment belongs to th e Kantian ]^Tt te50^ hyi In Germany, however, he thinks it remained rather a “tranquil theory,” while in France it was tried in practical life, where it culminated in the Reign of Terror. Now, Hegel polemicized persistently and strenuousl y against the moral as well as against the intellectual views of th is rationalism of the u nderstanding. He had been early attracted by the glamour of its enthusiasm for the abstract rights of man, as against all enslaving customs of existing ethical institutions. He also early saw its utter negativeness, “ignoring the holy and tender web of human affections.” He insisted that Reason was not so late born as the eig h- teenth century, but that it had always been regnant in the p ractical world ; that it had always been operative in th e formation of all social custo ms and institutions which bo und men together; that it was the realsubstance of the concrete life ot civilized man. Thi s enabled him to m p^r a 11 t 1 ^ negati ve criticism of existing institutions ( family, soc iety, state a nd church) and to vindicate their validity and rati on- ality as institutions of the spiritJfoj.- the. -educatio n of man into fr eedom — into humani ty. Such, indeed, we shall find to be the whole argument of his Ethics as contained in the following “ Selections.” Against the whole rationalistic movement of free thought (better designated anti-rationalism) Philosophy of History , p. 462. 22 EXPOSITION. Hegel dared to maintain that “ The Real is the Rational .” Even the most superficial acquaintance with his philosophy, especially with his dialectic, suffices to guard this expression from being considered the equivalent of a pet phrase of the very movement he was combatting, i. e., that “ Whatever is, is right.” The “ Real,” he explains ( Logic , § 6), is not the accidental actuality of any and every sham, but the vital substance of the Divine Reason in past and present institu- tions — the throb of real rationality which alone enables them to arise and thrive, and to nurture man into humanity. Whatever is, is because of its seed or web of rationality. The 11 is” is always a phase of the ought. The real is not and never has been “ so feeble as merely to have a right or an ought to exist without actually existing ” (Logic, § 6). To be a man, one must at least wear the clothes of a man. The disrobed “ natural man ” of the Aufklärung needs to be assured that clothes are rational, and Hegel’s task in his Ethics is to reclothe the perishing nude infant of vulgar rationalism. His Philosophie des Rechts is a philosophical Sartor Resartus. III. Exposition. We have said that it would be necessary to give an outline of Hegel’s Encyclopädie in order to see the place that ethics holds in his whole system. It is also necessary to give this for another reason. It has sometimes been maintained that Hegel never gave any thorough exposition of ethics. Any adequate knowledge of Hegel, however, easily disposes of this objection. Hegel’s doctrine of ethics is found chiefly in the Philosophie des Rechts , which is an enlarged exposition of Part Second of his Philosophie des Geistes. With this goes, as an interpreting and fulfilling sequel, his Philosophy of History. We have made but EXPOSITION. 2 3 slight reference to his Phänomenologie des Geistes, which contains not only his ethics, but nearly all other parts of his Philosophy, in brilliant and somewhat imaginative form. Apart from this earlier and graphic work (1807) Hegel only published the following works. 1. The Science of Logic — called his Larger Logic, 1811- 1816. 2. The Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences, 1817 and 1827. 3. The Philosophy of Right, 1821. All the other volumes of his Works were edited from his manuscripts by his friends after his death. The Encyclopedia contains the whole system in the scien- tific form given by himself. It is his attempt to exhibit his system in its entirety. As we now have it, it is Hegel’s own revised and enlarged edition, together with additions made from his manuscripts used in the Lecture-room. This Encyclopedia is not a mere compend of heterogeneous parts, but a systematic exposition of all parts of philosophy in their organic relations; that is, an exposition of all the connected phases of reality that come under the cognizance of the philosopher. It is concerned with Absolute Reality in the phases of unity, difference and totality. Hegel’s term for this Absolute Reality is the Ldea (/dee) or God. He makes three divisions of the Ldea as 1. Reason ( Vernunft). 2. Nature. 3. Spirit (Geist). Otherwise, as he denominates them : 1. Logic, or the Science of the pure Ldea. 2. The Philosophy of Nature. 3. The Philosophy of Spirit. 1. The first might better be termed Metaphysics or Ontology. It makes abstraction from the reality of nature and finite spirit and considers only thought in the abstract. 24 EXPOSITION. It takes up all the various predicates or categories by which human reason has sought to define and comprehend the Universal, the Absolute, beginning with the most abstract and empty of them all (mere being) and showing how each lower one criticises and elevates itself into the next higher one, until restless thought rests in the most concrete and absolute category possible — the Idea , God. It exhibits the interconnectedness of all categories by means of the vital dialectic of difference. It is a criticism of the Cate- gories of thought by itself, in its march to thorough compre- hension of Reality, through partial conceptions, ending with Absolute Personality as that which all the others imply and as that which includes and explains them all . 1 How have men named this reality? Hegel takes up the various answers, only in scientific rather than in historical forms, and shows their mutual limitations and filiations, arranging them in the order of their comparative capacity to express truth in the totality of its relations. To stop here would be to stop with the metaphysics of Reality. But »zrAzphysics implies physics, presupposes a realm which it enswathes and sustains. 2. This realm Hegel takes up in his Philosophy of Nature. The transition which he makes from the Logic to Nature is confessedly obscure. It is, however, none other than the difficulty of the question of creation by God, the transition from God, into the act and processes of self-alienation or creation. Hegel, at all events, makes this a free act of God. He says, in the last paragraph of his Logic: “ The 1 It was in regard to this work of the Logic in giving a critical exposition of the categories of thought that Hegel made the following striking remark : — “If it is held a valuable achievement to have dis- covered some sixty odd species of the parrot, a hundred and thirty-seven of Veronica, and so forth, it should surely be held a far more valuable achievement to discover the forms of reason : Is not a figure of the syllogism something infinitely higher than a species of parrot or of Veronica?” Hegel’s Werke, Band V., 139. EXPOSITION. 2 5 Idea is absolutely free; and its freedom means that it does not merely pass over into life, or, as finite cognition, allow life to show in it, but in its own absolute truth resolves to let the element of its particularity or of the first determina- tion and other-being, the unmediated Idea, as its reflection, go forth freely itself from itself as Nature.” That is, we have the Idea in its most abstract form passing over into the phase of time and space existence, progressively, how- ever, realizing or objectifying reality through various forms up to finite spirit, and then, through the various stages and grades of finite spirit, ultimately up to God again. His philosophy is no me re naturalism or materia lism. Nature is not the first with Hegel. Nor is it the essentially evil, as with the Gnostics. But it is essentially rational as the creation of the Divine Reason, progressively ascend- ing to more adequate rational forms, collecting and elevating itself till it reaches the form of organic life and passes into soul as the first form of finite spirit. Nature is the matrix and the cradle of finite spirit, not because its potency brings forth man in and of itself, but because it is so used by the immanent Divine Reason. He says: “The end of nature is to destroy itself, to break through its immediate sensible covering, and, like the Phoenix from its flames, to arise from this externality new-born as spirit .” 1 Sjfirit is really the g round of the possibility of nature, rather than a natural product of natu re. Nature is simply the Idea displaying its own element of particularity in the form of otherness, and the gradual reduction of this form to its own absolute form. In the last paragraph of this work he says: “The aim of this treatise is to give a picture of nature in order to conquer this Proteus; to find in all its externality only the mirror of ourselves; to see in nature the free reflexion of the spirit; to recognize God in this His immediate form of determinate being.” 2 1 Hegel’s A T atur-philosophic, 696. 2 Ibid., 698. 26 EXPOSITION. 3. The Philosophy of Spirit. Hegel’s transition from Nature to Spirit is thus readily seen to be clear, explicit and satisfactory. Nature culmi- nates in man, the interpretation as well as the interpreter of nature. His Philosophy of Spirit includes Subjective Spirit (Anthropology and Psychology), Objective Spirit (Rights, Morality and Social Ethics), and Absolute Spirit (Art, Re- ligion and Philosophy). It is with the second division, that of Objective Spirit, that we are here concerned, though we must note in the sequel how Hegel carries the whole process of finite Spirit up into the sphere of Absolute Spirit. All three parts form an exposition of the actualization of spirit, of its progressive self-realization from the lowest form of consciousness to its highest, its return through im- mense labor to its own true, rational and divine self. Thus no one part can be taken as complete in itself. It is only the taking of the whole as one high argument that preserves any part from the unjust criticism so often offered. In fact, the whole of the Philosophy of Spirit is an ethical treatise, if we use the term ethics in the broad sense of the self-real- ization of the human spirit. The “ Selections ” in this volume are, however, confined to his treatment of Objective Spirit , as fully elaborated in a separate treatise, the Philoso- phie des Rechts," which exhibits the free spirit as it actually stands or lives as thinking will in the world. It is an exhi- bition of spirit as objectified in the institutions of law, the family, and the state, set between subjective spirit and Absolute Spirit. Thus his Ethics start from the natural con- dition of man, and lead on to man in his highest relations, exhibiting the perfection of his spiritual character in the realms of art, religion and philosophy, ■ — the three media of perfect self-realization or of comprehension of his rela- tions with the Absolute Spirit of whom and through whom and to whom are all things. We shall note, in our criticism, Hegel’s apparent failure to carry ethics up into this sphere of the Absolute Spirit. EXPOSITION. 2 7 Hegel’s method is always that of beginning with the most abstract phase of his topic and following through the imma- nent self-criticism of one abstract phase to another until the organic concept (. Begriff ) is reached, which is then seen to be the real presupposition throughout, instead of being an in- ductive result. His true first principle, his most concrete statement, is scarcely perceptible in his first advances, but it comes more and more clearly to light, as the immanent and organic principle that lives in, through, and above all the abstractions that strut dogmatically, aping the real. Objections will be continually raised against the dogmatic utterances of Hegel as to the earlier phases of right and freedom, these being taken to represent his own full opinion on the topic in hand. But he is only stating the various dogmatic standpoints that have been, or may be, held on the subject — the crude and imperfect opinions upon which he is to let loose the dialectic fire to purge them of their dross. “The will is absolutely free.” “The will wills the will and always wills itself.” “The ‘Person’ (abstract) has the right to put his will into everything and thereby make it his own.” These and other examples will readily be noted by the student. Again he often speaks of the immature as the fully ripened, of the acorn as an oak, the materials and plan as the ca- thedral. But the one who reads him closely can generally find how he guards against misunderstanding by means of one of those many troublesome phrases noted in the Vocabulary. The true way to read Hegel, in one sense, is to read him backward — his end is his real beginning. This, however, he always announces at the first in its poten- tial form and then follows through its stages of realization. His order, moreover, is always the logical one from the ab- stract universal through the particular to the universalized individual. In other words it does not follow the empirical or historical order of the development of an institution. He 28 EXPOSITION. starts with the concept of the will. A concept is relatively a causa sui, a logically self-determining force, potentially containing all the contradictory phases taken on in the course of its self-revelation. Just how or when any of these phases occur empirically is a matter of no consequence so far as the science is concerned. It is a matter of greatest consequence that they should thus occur and be the revela- tion of the concept. But the chronological order of the various empirical phases does not necessarily coincide with the logical order of the concept. The speculative method is to exhibit all these phases as inherently interrelated and as the self-characterizations of the concept itself. The external manifestation or history of a concept is generally a scene of contingency. The speculative method takes and arranges all these partial and miscellaneous forms in accordance with the concept, stripping them of contingency and organizing them into system ; thus exhibiting the rationality (the self- developing concept) of their history. Thus we have the real history of any institution, as Wallace says, “written, as if it had been, in evanescent inks — dates are wanting — individualities and their biographies yield up their place to universal and timeless principles .” 1 This exposition of any concept is made by means of its own dialectic. That is, the scientific method of Hegel is the dialectical^ope. The dialectic is neither mere subjective nor exTernal criticism. It is the immanent life of the con- cept, criticising itself from lower to higher forms. Starting from a dogmatic assertion of the undeveloped universal, we see the dialectic gradually specifying, particularizing it and successively transmuting each dogmatic particular form into a higher form, until the abstract universal becomes fully particularized, defined, realized — the concrete universal — the individual or the concept itself. First we have the abstract thesis, then the special antithesis and finally the full syn- 1 The Logic of Hegel, p. LXIII. EXPOSITION. 29 thesis, all of which is the self-realization of the concept. The growth of the tree from the seed represents this inner dialectic of the concept of a tree. The process is not deductive or a priori , proceeding from a first principle which remains valid and normative through- out. It starts rather from an undeveloped first principle and shows how inadequate it is, presupposing always a more con- crete principle as its logical condition. This concrete prin- ciple is at once the logical and the chronological presupposi- tion. “In the beginning God (created).” /Th e dialectical procedure is a retrograde movement from the abstract to the concrete, from error to truth, from the dependent to the infinite, the self-determining. That is, the procedure is always towards the first principle which is ultimately seen to be the true, the first and the final cause of the whole process. Each higher stage is reached, not by a mechanical evolution from the lower one, but by means of the imperfections and impli- cations exhibited by the lower one. All nature, all life, all thought, except Absolute Thought exhibits this immanent dialectic.^ So much has already been written about this dialectic method of Hegel that we need do no more here than give one illustration from the text. The first form of the ethical concept is the family — an inclusive universal or unit. But soon the diversities or distinctions of parents and children appear. A married couple do not constitute a family. Children break in upon this simple unity, and remain always children to their par- ents. But they do not always remain children. They grow to maturity, leave their parents’ roof and establish new families. Family property is divided, the family broken up, resolved into mutually independent individuals with various interests, thus merging into the realm of civil society. Here the particular interests of individuals jog and jostle each other through civil relations till the ethical realm of an organic nation is reached in which both family and civil society are integrated, preserved and fulfilled. 3 ° EXPOSITION. Hegel’s Philosophie des Rechts may be called the doc- trine of the will. The will is the man, and ethical man is will realized in his social institutions. To reach this con- ception, however, he starts with the most abstract conception of will, which he takes as ready to hand. He divides the whole work, as usual, into triadic form : 1 I. The will as immediate, undeveloped potentiality, which gives the sphere of abstract or formal right. II. The will self-reflected, or subjective individuality, op- posed to objective will. This gives the sphere of Moralität , or of conscience contra mundum. III. The will as the unity and truth of these two abstract phases, the realm of formal freedom and objective right realized in the world. This gives the realm of Sittlichkeit , or the ethical world, as the concrete realization of man as will. This includes the sphere of (a) the family, ($) civil society, ( c ) the State in the most concrete sense of the term, such as Dr. Mulford construes “the Nation.” Under this last he embraces (a) internal polity, (ß) external polity, (y) international polity, merging into Universal History, as the realization of man in the most cosmopolitan sense of the term. We give a translation of the larger half of this volume, and here offer a brief and free exposition of its contents, referring the student to the fuller and admirable exposition given by Prof. Geo. S. Morris in his volume on “ Hegel’s Philosophy of the State and of History.” We recommend this volume as a companion book to this translation . 2 1 § 33 - Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts. Berlin, 1848. All the references in this volume are to this later edition of the work. 2 It seems fitting that we should pay a brief tribute to the memory of one of the chief philosophical teachers of America, the late Prof. Geo. S. Morris, of whom the English quarterly, Mind, says : “ He had gained a most enviable name and influence among philosophical students and writers and teachers. There is every reason to regret deeply his untimely death at the age of forty-eight.” He was the centre of a deep religious and ethical influence extending far beyond the limits EXPOSITION. 3 1 The subject-matter of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right , or of the State, is the human will, and thus it is essentially a treatise on Ethics. But the will, as Hegel tells us (§ 4), is a particular form of thought , — thought translating itself into determinate being, thought as impulse to self-actual- ization. The will, too, is essentially free. At first it is only formally, potentially free. It is only through a long series of mediations, — through many advances, retreats, and ultimate conquests of itself in diverse and apparently foreign forms, — that this, its essential nature, is realized. Put in another way, the subject-matter is the human will, as respects the relation of particular (private) to universal (public, social) will of man, and ultimately of this universal human will in relation to the absolutely universal Divine will, though this latter belongs to the subsequent and concluding portion of his Encyclopedia. Cognition completed passes into practical activity. To think or know an object is to create, determine and possess an object ; but intelligence, which determines objects, is will. It is spirit willing, or realizing itself. But will is taken at first in its potential, undeveloped form, — will, as it were, in the state of nature rather than in state of civili- zation. It is rather the instinct of the needs and greeds directed to the satisfaction of the individual ; it is poten- of the University of Michigan. I quote the following from a private letter of Prof. Williston S. Hough, of the University of Minnesota, a former student of Dr. Morris, and, at the time of his death, his assist- ant in Philosophy : — • “At times he spoke almost as one inspired with the melodious rythm of a poet and the illumination of rare philosophic insight. Yet the chief source of his power was unquestionably his own character. He will live in our thought as a remarkable exemplification of sweetness and light. His loss to Philosophy in this country is great and twofold : ist, as a teacher who would have inspired a genuine interest in Phi- losophy in every student who came under him, and who would have educated many special and useful scholars in this field ; and, 2d, as a writer who doubtless had his greatest work still before him.” A brief personal acquaintance more than confirmed the high estimate formed of him from his books. 32 EXPOSITION. tially universal, and yet has no content. Its aim is to have only its fully realized self as content, and thus be free. To reach this, however, it must descend into the realm of par- ticularities, — into particular will, willing something. The movement is from within outward ; but the movement, even through the satisfaction of instinctive needs and greeds, is from the pure self-reference of the individual as universal. It is still abstract, formal, internal. Such a single will Hegel denominates a person in the most abstract, formal sense of the term. It is the first stage of the realization of such formal personality that Hegel treats in his Part First. Abstract Right. To be a person is, in one sense, the highest within human , capacity. But, as used here, the term refers to a mere indi-. vidual will maintaining its single right as universal. It is the rude, uncultured man, stubbornly sticking for his will- | fulness, while the true person has an eye for all sides and ■relations of a complex social life. Such a will demands full j sway for itself without having as yet conscientious aims or I convictions. It is the right of such a person to cast his will over every external thing, making it his own. Confronted with other such wills, however, the formula of abstract rights is “be a person and respect others as persons.” Hegel warns us against putting into this formula all that it would imply in an ethical, social state. Nothing like humaneness is yet present. In such respect for others the person only cares for himself. Such a “ person ” is nowhere to be found. But the conception necessarily results from, and is the first phase of, the abstract concept of will. Such a potential, universal will, however, cannot remain utterly abstract. It finds itself confronted by a world of external nature. The alternative comes to succumb to this, or to rise and conquer it and so to be free. Alles ist Ich. The world is by right EXPOSITION. 33 its oyster. It actualizes itself only by making the world: to be really its oyster. Abstract will asserts itself against its environment, lays its hand upon its rights. It thus achieves objective existence and takes the first step towards actualization. Things are soul-less, will-less, and the “ per- son ” has the right to subject them all to his will, to put his will into them, and thus achieve their true destiny. Here appears the distinction between persons and things. \ Things are rightfully a part or property of the person, and become such through his act. Will is thus objectified in property, and things cease to be mere things, and become properties of the will through seizure, use and alienation. Property is thus something rational, necessary and sacred. First, the body of the person is thus made a possession or property. Both body and soul (life) are taken possession of, the will making them its instruments. Hence, too, the sacredness of “person” or of one’s body and life. The will being thus placed in them secures them from slavery. Slavery can come only where one will not maintain the rights of person and property to the death. It depends upon each person’s will, whether he will be a slave or not. If he prefers mere continuance of existence to independence, he becomes the slave of the first person who can make him his property. Slavery, in primitive times, is rather a wrong suffered or chosen than a wrong- done. I put my will in a thing, and make it an attribute or property of myself. This involves the further rights of using, consuming and alienating possessions. Will changes things into properties. Thus the relation between things becomes the relation between wills. Persons are related to each other through their properties. They can hold property only as they also respect each other’s property. This is the sphere of contract. Property here comes to be held through the will of others as well as through one’s own will. Instead of one abstract will, we have several 34 EXPOSITION. partially realized wills. The consent of other wills strength- ens my property-rights. In .t his mammon will of contract the abstract will of the mere individual or “ pers on ” att ains its fir st stage of co n.cr.ele_Limversality. It is mediated by the i w ill of some- Qtkers. f But such a common will is still far from being that o f the ■universa l will of s ociety. Its elements are accidental and particular, and can give no guarantee of fulfilment. Frau d. j vi olenc e and crim e are inevi table. In “crime” will violates * itself: that is, violates itself as explicitly common will and as implicitly universal will. The formal common will of con- tract, considered as yet abstracted from the concrete uni- versal will of ethical society, is sure to be violated. Penalty follows this negation as the next step forward toward true rights and the objectification of the universal will. Con- j tract is a step forward, crim e a st ep backward, and pena lty another advance in the relation of the particular will to univers al wi ll, or in the self-realization of will as the science jof-ethics. Penalty is the negation of the negation (crime), j or a reaffirmation of the universal. The criminal really commits the crime against himself as potentially universal will. Punishment springs from the conception of true will and of justice. In the very will of the criminal lies the universal which is to complete his crime in the penalty. This is an act of justice to the criminal himself as well as to the com- mon will. Punishment really honors the criminal — treats him as a person, according to his universal element rather than as a will-less thing. Theories of punishment on the ground of the reformation or terrorization of the criminal, or of the protection of society, do not duly respect the manhood of the criminal. Punishment is only justice to the criminal himself. The universal in him cries out, Give me my due, let justice be done by having penalty complete my crime. Penalty is but the reaction upon the criminal of his own EXPOSITION. 35 negative act. It is equally the act of his own will; it is his own right. But in this as yet unorganized nnrl nnethi ralj condition, where there is no valid universal will of society to mediate between crime and penalty, we find punishmen t in the form of revenge, mob-law and Judge Lynch. The I common will of the abstract contract stage becomes again a state of nature, an aggregate of at best only semi-civilized Ishmaelites. Here retaliation becomes endless. Family- feuds to the death in the sphere of organized society is but a relapse to such barbarism. True punishment is impossible without the mediation of a true universal or ethical will of society. This demand brings the judge, who is to be the disinterested repre- sentative of the true will of man. As legal judge he is to have no private views or feelings. He is simply to wrong the wronger till he renders right. But as dispenser of retributive justice, the judge appeals beyond the letter of the law to an inward forum, to the universal will, and renders decisions that must commend themselves to the conscience of both criminal and society. Property, contract and punishment are alike seen to be impossible without the presence and mediation of a relatively universalized or ethical will. Death or sjavery can be the only logical issue to abstract will seeking its abstract rig hts. With no other elements at work, such a state of nature could never give rise to the institution of the State. Some judge more just and universal must be found. The demand is for a particular will which can at the same time will the universal or the “infinite subjectivity of freedom.” Such a will must reflect upon itself, retire from mere objectivity to the internal forum. This forum is that of Conscience. Here all externalities are reflected and transformed into ideal principles of right and wrong as regards all human actions. This phase Hegel calls that of 3 6 EXPOSITION. Morality (. Moralität ) or Abstract Duty. In this sphere we have to do with man as a subjective being rather than a merely formal “person.” Here person- ality becomes inwardly reflected, exists for itself, and thus of infinite worth. Here “person” becomes more personal — becomes a “subject,” who is absolutely beyond any power, which may commit violence against his objectified will and person. Here, within, the will is absolutely its own lord and master. The stand-point now is the right of the subjective will. At first, however, this merely subjective will is abstract, formal and limited. Hegel shows the pro- cess from the most abstract form of this subjectivity through the phases of (a) purpose and responsibility , ( b ) intention and welfa>-e to (r) the good and conscience ,• where abstract right is-translated into duty and virtue or good-will. First, it is held that responsibility is only commensurate with knowledge. Next, the quality of the will depends upon the “intention” and its objective results, which are never restricted to particular selfish ends. They must (thirdly) be judged according to their universal worth. Hence “the good” as the reconciliation of the particular subjective will with the universal will, or with the rational. The ideal here, in this third phase, is that of duty for duty’s sake. The duty, however, is yet abstract. No con- tent can be furnished by itself. The universal element is merely formal, unspecified as to content, giving no answer as to what one’s duty is in any situation, except the grand- iloquent one of “do right though the heavens fall.” An objective system of principles and duties, and the union of the subjective knowledge with them, is plainly impossible on this standpoint. Hegel, here and elsewhere, makes, as we have said, trenchant criticism of Kant’s doctrine of duty. This formal law divorces duty from all interest or desire — a psychological impossibility. It takes no cognizance of EXPOSITION. 37 the concrete situation and can suggest no present duty. It cannot discriminate between particular actions sö as to call one of them a duty. Finally, it must equally uni- versalize all particular actions, and thus bring about con- fusion and collisions. Only in view of the institution of property in the State can it say, “Thou shalt not steal.” In the abstract form of Kant it must equally say, “Thou shalt steal.” That is, if we abstract all social rela- tions, which ex hypothesi Kant does, we can universalize any particular rule without contradiction. In the realm of the concrete morality of social life, however, we cannot do this. What will be the result of such an abstract subjective con- ception of duty ? Plainly the individual must become the law-giver and the judge of what is absolute good. He must trust to his own private judgment without the mediation of existing codes of society. He must give a purely subjective individual determination of the content of the lofty but formal universal. The individual becomes the measure of the moral quality of objective actions. There is no public source and standard for the guidance of private judgment. Hegel does not neglect the important function of the duty of private judgment, but is here only showing its capricious- ness when taken out of the concrete relations of an ethical world. Antinomianism is a logical and historical outcome of such abstract private judgment, which runs riot and plays the tyrant for lack of an objective concrete social system of duties. It is the making of self a statesman to represent a concrete state that ex hypothesi does not yet exist. The eccentric is made the normal, the crooked the straight. This elevation of the capricious individual subjective judg- ment to be the measure and definition of the universal finally results in the evil. “ The highest summit of subjectivity asserting itself as the absolute is the bad ” (das Bösel) It is at this abstract standpoint of the natural (unethicized) will that he finds the origin of moral evil. 38 EXPOSITION. While thus criticising this standpoint, Hegel does not fail to render homage to Kant for having brought out the significance of duty. But he shows how this standing upon one’s own subjective insight and will eventuates in the morally evil — in that which, being private and particular, asserts itself as the universal — the sin of the creature Satan usurping the throne of God. Here enters antinomianism in all its forms. One’s own likings are liable to become the norm of conduct. A clergyman urging a man to do a certain duty was met with the reply, “My conscience forbids me to do it.” In reply as to how his conscience told him this he said, that he felt some- thing thumping in his breast saying “/ won't , I won't." Such a merely subjective norm dissolves all fixed and de- finite laws of order and right. Hegel says that he is not here treating of the religious conscience, and also allows that in certain rotten stages of society, as in the times of Socrates and the Stoics, this concept of private judgment has its place and worth in the work of reformation. But the subjective conscience which dissolves all external forms of duty and retires within to its own little Sinai is likely to make it a Mount Moriah, for the sacrifice of the tenderest of human ties. If subjective conviction, unenlightened by traditional and current codes and institutions, insists upon its private views as absolute, we have the destruction of all morality. The highest summit of evil is extreme subjectivity asserting itself as the absolute, the good — God, changing good into evil and calling it good. Here delusion has equal right with sound sense, and reason no longer has any right. Hence we see that conscience at this stage cannot be true or good conscience. This abstraction in turn demands as its correlate that which it was called out to correct, — i. ) Let the content have some particular form from any source, it still must be conformable to the implicit will. But as this will is still formal, this conformity is only a demand and contains the possibility of being non-conformity. (y) Inasmuch as I attain my subjectivity in the accomplish- ment of my aim, I thus annul my immediate undeveloped subjectivity. But this external subjectivity is the will of others (§ 73 ). Hence the accomplishment of my aim im- plies the identity of my will with that of others. The utter- MORALITY. 107 ance of the subjective or moral will is found in action. Such action implies that I know it as mine, in essential relation to the concept (as obligatory) and to the will of others. Thus a moral action is distinguished from a legal one. § 114 . The right of moral will has three sides: (A) The abstract or formal right of action, in such a way that the content of the action, carried out into immediate determinate existence, be mine and represent the purpose of my subjective will. (i?) The special character of the action is its inner con- tent (a) as it is for me, v^hose universal character is deter- mined by the worth of the action and what it avails for me — that is inner intention — (/?) its content as the special aim of my particular subjective being, that is, individual well-being. (C) This inner content in its universality, as elevated into absolute, existing objectivity, is the absolute aim of will as will — that is the Good. This is in the sphere of the reflexion with the antithesis of subjective universality, partly of evil, and partly of conscience. Supplementary. — In order to be moral, every action must primarily harmonize with my purpose , for the right of the moral will consists in recognizing in any action only that which was internally designed. Purpose thus makes the formal demand that the objective will be also the internal thing willed by me. In the second phase, that of inner intention , the question is concerning the relative worth of the action in reference to myself. The third phase concerns not only the relative but the absolute worth of the action, that is, the Good. The first breach of the action is between something proposed, and some definite accomplished affair. Then follows the breach between that which is external as uni- versal will and the inner particular character which I give it. Thirdly we have the demand that the intention have io8 MORALITY. universal validity. The Good is intention elevated to the concept of the will. FIRST SECTION. Purpose and Culpability. § 115 . The limitation of the subjective will in external action arises from the fact that in all such action there is the pre- supposition of an external object and its manifold environ- ment. A deed implies the working of a change in this external realm, and the will is culpable in so far as the change thus wrought can be called mine, as being that pro- posed by me. . . . Supplementary. — What was in my purpose can be imputed to me. It is with this proposed deed that we are chiefly concerned when dealing with crime. But in culpability (Schuld) there is the merely external judgment as to whether I have done a certain thing or not. Culpability does not primarily imply the quality of imputability. § 117 . In proposing to work a change in the given external realm, the self-acting will has a general idea of the circum- stances. But as these circumstances limit it, the objective phenomenon is accidental and may contain something quite other than one’s general idea of it. The subjective will claims as its right, that, in any of its deeds, it recognize as its own and be held responsible for only what it proposed to do. The deed can only be imputed to the will, and for this the will demands the right of knowledge. PURPOSE AND CULPABILITY. 109 § 118 . The action, passing from the internal will into an external realm where external necessity binds all together, is followed by many consequences not calculated upon. In one way, the consequences properly belong to the action, as being what was aimed at. But at the same time the deed passes over into the dominion of external powers which add to it many foreign consequences. It cannot reckon all the con- sequences as its own, as being aimed at by itself and so it disclaims responsibility for all consequences not contained in its original design. It is difficult, however, to distinguish between the accidental and the necessary or proper consequences of one’s own ac- tion, for the inner purpose or plan is nothing, for others at least, till it enters the objective realm, and, once there, inex- tricable complication bids defiance to perfectly clear de- markation between the two sorts of consequences. The principle is sometimes announced that in acting we may de- spise consequences. On the other hand it is proclaimed that actions are to be judged solely by their consequences. Both of these principles are abstract and untrue. . . . Supplementary. — This disclaiming responsibility for all consequences not proposed soon leads to the next phase — that of Intention. But there are consequences beyond the known and proposed external effects. Although my deed is some one particular thing, it yet contains necessary and uni- versal qualities. I cannot forsee all external effects of a proposed action, but I must know the universal element im- plicit in every deed. The transition from Purpose to Intention consists in the recognition that I ought to know the universal element in every action so as to will it, to intend it. I IO MORALITY. SECOND SECTION. Intention and Well-being. § 119 . The external form of an act is a manifold context of countless particularities. The act may be considered in such a way that at first cognizance is taken of only one of these many particularities. But the truth of the individual is the universal, — the real character of the act as such is not merely an isolated external thing, but it is rather a uni- versal embracing the whole of a manifold context. Purpose, proceeding from a thinking being, contains not only the indi- vidual, but also essentially the universal side. Such purpose we call Intention. Intention is really an abstraction. The attempt at justifi- cation through one’s intention is really the isolating of a single aspect of the deed, which is maintained as the sub- jective essence of the deed. But the universal quality of the deed is also manifested in its accomplishment. Incendi- arism is the actual result of the intention to set fire to only a little pile of kindling wood. Murder is the result of cutting out a pound of flesh from a living body. That is, one cannot really intend an isolated single side of an action. . . . In acting a man has to do with external consequences. An old proverb says : “A stone flung from the hand is the very devil.” A man has to face the bad as well as good consequences of all his deeds. These are really definite qualities of his own will. § 120 . The right of Intention is that the universal quality of the act be not only implicit, but be fully known to the one doing the act, as having been the real purpose of his will. INTENTION AND WELL-BEING. Ill On the other hand the right, as regards the external form of the act, is the right of its being considered as something known and willed by a rational being. This right to such insight implies the slight or total lack of responsibility of children, the feeble-minded and insane for their actions. But as all such actions have numerous contingent effects, we can say that their subjective quality has that lack of character, as regards the power and strength of self-consciousness and thoughtfulness. Only such particular conditions annul the character of thought and freedom of will, and lead us to consider these actions not according to the worth which they would have as pro- ceeding from a rational will. § 121 . The universal quality of an act is its manifold content in general, reduced to the simple form of universality. But the subjective individual, as contrasted with the objective particularity of his deed, has in his aim his own peculiar intent, which is the determining soul of the act. The fact that this subjective phase is contained and accomplished in the act, constitutes the concrete character of subjective freedom, the right of the subject to find his satisfaction in the act. [In a supplementary note Hegel illustrates this right of intention. Murder may have been committed. We ask whether it was the intent of the doer rather, than an unin- tentional consequence of some action. It is the motive that constitutes primarily what is called the moral element. This moral element has the sense of the universal in purpose and the particular of the intention. In modern times, the chief question concerns the motive of an act, while formerly it was merely asked : Is this man honest, does he do his duty ? To-day we look at the heart and I I 2 MORALITY. presuppose a breach between the external action and the inner subjective motive. The higher moral standpoint, however, is that of a harmony between the two sides, so that the external side corresponds to and satisfies the subjective purpose. The merely objective method of esti- mating the worth of deeds has its epochs both in the history of the world and of individuals.] § 122. Through the motive, the action has personal subjective worth and interest. In reference to this subjective aim, the wider effects of the act are reduced to means. But, in so far as such an aim is a finite thing, it can in turn be reduced to a means to a further design, etc., ad infinitum. § 123 . As regards the content of such aims, we have here (a) merely the formal activity — that the person’s activity be limited to what he considers his aim. One wishes to work only for his own interests, or for what should be his interests, (ß) Such abstract formal freedom has, however, further definite content only in the natural phases of its subjective determinate being — needs, inclinations, passions, opinions, fancies, etc. The satisfaction of such a content is Well-being , in particular and in general. This is the sphere of finite aims. [In a supplementary note Hegel asks whether a man has the right to choose such un-free finite aims, and gives an affirmative answer. It is not a mere accident, but according to reason, that man is a living being, and, so far, he has a right to make his wants his aim. There is nothing degrad- ing in being such a living creature, and there is also no higher form in which he can manifest his spirituality.] INTENTION AND WELL-BEING. "3 § 124 . . . . The series of man’s deeds constitutes the very man. If this series of actions be worthless, so also is the subjectivity of his will worthless. If on the contrary the series of deeds be substantial, so also is the inner will of the individual substantial. This right of subjective freedom constitutes the turning point between antiquity and modern times. This right in all its infinitude is pronounced, and raised into being a universal principle, by Christianity. Subordinate elements of this principle are love, Romanticism, the eternal bliss of the individual ; further, morality and conscience ; further, the principles of civil order, and the forms in the history of art, science and philosophy. But abstract reflexion may so emphasize this element in opposition to the universal, as to lead to a view of morality that makes it to consist in a perpetual hostile conflict with one’s own satisfaction — the demand “ to do with aversion what duty commands.” Such an abstract view gives rise to the “psychological view” of history, which seeks to belittle all great deeds and heroes by reducing the primary intentions which found their satisfaction in substantial activity, to mere morbid cravings for glory and renown, as the real motives of the actions. . . This is the view of “ psychological valets to whom no men are heroes because they themselves are only valets.” § 125 . The subjective, in connection with the particular content of well-being, stands (as being inwardly reflected, as some- thing infinite) at the same time in relation to the universal, i.e., to the potentially existing will. This phase, primarily posited in the form of particularity, is the well-being of others also — yes even, in a perfect yet empty definition, the welfare of all. Thus the essential aim and right of subjectivity is ii4 MORALITY. really the welfare of many other persons. But inasmuch as such absolute universality, as distinguished from such par- ticular content, has not yet been defined further than as being the right, these particular aims distinguished from uni- versal aims may or may not be consonant with them. § 126. My own right, as well as that of others, is a right only in so far as 1 am a free being. Hence it cannot maintain itself in opposition to this, its substantial foundation. Further, any plan for the welfare of myself or of others (which we call moral design) cannot justify a wrong deed. Supplementary. — Even life is not a necessity when in con- flict with the higher freedom. The famous answer given to a libeller who excused himself by saying, il faut done que je vive, was je n'en vois pas la necessity. When St. Crispen stole leather to make, shoes for the poor, his action may be called moral , and yet it was unlawful and therefore unsound. § 127. We may embrace under the term life, as personal exist- ence, the whole of the interests of the natural will. Life, in cases of extreme danger or in collision with the legal property of others, has a claim to the right of necessity (not in equity but as a right). It has such claim inasmuch as on the one hand we have the absolute violation of the total personality and, consequently, the total lack of right as concerns the individual, while on the other hand we have only the violation of a limited form of freedom. At the same time, however, the right as such is acknowledged as well as the claim to right of the one injured in this special property. Out of this right of necessity arises the beneficiuiti com- petentiae ; that to a debtor must be left his tools, farming im- INTENTION AND WELL-BEING. 115 plements, clothing — in a word, as much of his property as is absolutely necessary for his maintenance according to his condition of life. Supplementary. — Life has its claims as against any merely abstract right. Hence stealing a loaf of bread to preserve one’s life is of course an unlawful act, but cannot be treated as common theft. If one, in immediate danger of losing his life, should not be permitted to preserve his life at all hazards, he would be void of all rights. The loss of life implies the negation of the totality of his freedom. § 128 . This right of necessity reveals to us the finitude and con- sequently the contingency of right under the form of well- being. This form we see to be that of the abstract determi- nation of freedom, without its being the existence of the particular person. It is that of the particular will without the universality of the right. Its onesidedness and ideality (/. e., its being reduced from independence to the form of being a constituent element in a larger whole) is accordingly posited, as it has in itself been already determined in the concept. Right has formerly characterized its determinate being as the particular will ; and subjectivity in its inclusive particularity is itself the determinate being of freedom, as it is potentially that of infinite relation of the will to itself, the universality of freedom. Both phases in them thus unified to their truth, to their identity (though at first only in relative relation to each other) constitute the Good as the perfected, the independently characterized universal, and Conscience as (in itself knowing and in itself determining of content) infinite subjectivity. ' MORALITY. 1 16 THIRD SECTION. The Good and Conscience. § 129. The Good is the Idea , as the unity of the concept of the will and of the particular will. It is realized freedom, the absolute final purpose of the world. In this unity, abstract right, as well as well-being , and the subjectivity of knowledge and the contingency of external determinite being are an- nulled as independent in themselves, but at the same time are contained and preserved in it as to their essence. Supplementary. — Each phase is properly the Idea. But the earlier phases contain the Idea only in abstract form. Thus, for example, the Ego as personality is already the Idea , but in its most abstract form. Hence the Good is the more fully determined Idea , the unity of the concept of the will and of the particular will. It is not an abstract legal thing, but it is full of content. And it is this content which constitutes right as well as well-being. § 130. In this Idea , well-being has no actual validity, as the deter- minate being of a particular individual will, but only as universal well-being and, essentially, as universal in itself, i. e., according to the concept of freedom. Well-being is not good when devoid of right, nor is the right good when devoid of well-being. ( Fiat justitia must not have as its consequence pereat miindus.) Consequently, the Good (as the necessity of actuality through the particular will and at the same time as its substance) has absolute right against the abstract right of property and any particular ends of well-being. Each of these phases, so far as distinguished from the good, has validity only in so far as it is in accordance with the Good and subordinate to it. THE GOOD AND CONSCIENCE. § 131 . Thus the Good is the absolutely essential for the subjective will, which has worth and dignity only in so far as, in its insight and intent, it corresponds with the good. So far as the good is, at this stage, still the abstract Idea of the good, the subjective will has not yet been taken up into it and made conformable to it. Hence subjective will is in a relation to the good, inasmuch as the good is its substantial content. It is obligated to make the good its purpose and accomplish it. On the other hand the good is only actual- ized through the mediation of the subjective will. Supplementary. — The will is not absolutely good, but can only become the good that it is potentially, through its own labor. So, too, the good without the subjective element is only an abstraction. The development of the Good con- tains three stages: (i) The good for me the willing one, is particular will and I know it as such. (2) We define the Good and develop its particular characteristics. (3) We have the act of pointing out definitely what is the good as such, the particularity of the good as infinite self-dependent subjectivity. This internal act of specifying just what is good is the Conscience. § 132 . It is the right of the subjective will that whatever it is to recognize as binding be apprehended by it as good. This right involves, further, that a person be held responsible for any external action, only so far as he knows its external value, whether it be right or wrong, good or bad, lawful or unlawful. [Hegel further maintains, that as the good is only the truth of the will, it is only possible in thought and through thought. Hence all agnosticism is fatal to morality. It is indeed the highest right of the subject to recognize nothing MORALITY 1 18 as obligatory which he, as a rational being, does not see to be such. But this subjective standpoint neglects the right of objective rationality. The insight of subjective reason is liable to be a mere fancy or an error. It is a proper part of one’s subjective culture, that he attain to this right of insight. 1 must have the conviction of a duty on good grounds, and must recognize it to be essentially my duty. . . . This right of insight into the very nature of good differs from the right of zwAsight, of knowledge as to the external conse- quence of an act. The first has to do only with the inward peace of a quiet conscience. The latter concerns the con- formity of intention with external consequences. Hence it is that in the state, legal culpability cannot be restricted to the dictates of private conscience as to what is right or wrong. Here the citizen can only claim the right to have the laws so explicitly promulgated that he may know what is legal and illegal. Private conscience may be allowed to have its own convictions so long as these do not go forth in opposition to the existing ethical conditions of society. The law indeed judges children and the feeble-minded quite leniently. But it is the nature of man as man to be rational — to will the universal, and he must be held responsible for doing so. The incendiary is not only guilty of lighting a bundle of straw, but of burning down the house. He is responsible not only for the proposed external consequences of his deed, but also for his inner purpose to commit the deed, for his bad will. It is on this standpoint of con- science that responsibility for its dictates is demanded. . . . § 133 . The good stands in its relation to the subject as his own essential will, and hence as his bounden duty. However, there is still a distinction between the good and any par- ticular choice of the subjective will. At this stage the good has only the character of abstract universality. That is, it THE GOOD AND CONSCIENCE. 119 has the form of Duty. Hence the maxim, “ Duty must be done for duty’s sake.” Supplementary. — ... It is the merit of the lofty stand- point of Kant’s philosophy to have emphasized the signifi- cance of duty. § 134 . Every action demands some definite content and aim. But abstract duty does not contain such. Consequently the question arises, what is duty ? The only reply that can be given from this standpoint of duty is, to do right and to care for the welfare of one’s self and of all his fellows. § 135 . [In this paragraph Hegel maintains that Duty is an abso- lutely abstract, contentless universal, and hence stigmatizes Kant’s theory of duty as being an empty formalism, and his moral science, as mere talk about duty for duty’s sake. This standpoint affords no immanent doctrine of particular duties. One can only arrive at particular duties by import- ing something into this empty principle from without. It contains no criterion as to whether any particular act is a duty or not. In truth, one may say that any and every illegal and immoral act might be justified on Kant’s maxim. It is only so far as the right of property and life are pre- supposed, that theft and murder contradict the maxim. Abstractly considered, however, the maxim does not con- tain this, but must borrow it from concrete ethical condi- tions already attained. 1 ] § 136 . The nature of the good being thus abstract and formal, causes the other element of the Idea (that of particularity) 1 Hegel refers to his fuller criticisms of Kant’s principle made in his Phänomenologie des Geistes, which are reproduced by Prof. Edward Caird in his Critical Philosophy of Kant, Vol. II, pp. 186-1S8. 120 MORALITY. to fall within the sphere of subjectivity. This subjectivity is (in its universality turned back into itself) its own abso- lute certitude of itself ; it is the specifying, the determining, the deciding element — in a word it is the Conscience. Supplementary . — We may speak in very lofty terms of duty. To do so elevates man and enlarges his heart. But such talk becomes tedious when it fails to point out and lead to the accomplishment of any single duty. The spirit requires some specific form as that to which he is obligated. But duty, as used by Kant, is that inner abysmal solitude, which excludes all specification. A man on the standpoint of mere Conscience is, indeed, freed from all shackles of special commands. In one way this is a higher standpoint. It is the modern world that first attained to such conscious- ness. Previous ages have been more sensuous. They have had some external positive forms to guide them, either of a religious or legal sort. But Conscience knows and identifies itself with every thought. What is my own sub- jective thought, that alone is binding upon me. § 137 . The genuine conscience is that frame of mind ( Gesin- nung ) which wishes for that only which is absolutely good. Hence it has well-established principles — the current explicit virtues and duties. As distinguished from this concrete content, the truth, it is only the formal side of the activity of the will which, as such, has no particular content. But the ol^ective system of these principles and duties, and the union of the subjective knowledge with them, is first attained on the succeeding standpoint — that of Ethicality ( Sittlichkeit ). On the formal standpoint of morality, con- science lacks all such objective content. It is merely the infinite formal certitude of itself — -of the subjective indi- vidual. THE GOOD AND CONSCIENCE. 12 i Conscience expresses the absolute right of the subjective self-consciousness, to know perfectly just what the right and the obligatory are. It can acknowledge nothing but that which it knows as absolutely good. Further, it must maintain as truly right and obligatory, whatever it thus knows and wills. Conscience is the unity of subjective knowledge and of the absolute truth. It is a holy of holies, to meddle with which would be sacrilegious. But it is only the definite content of what is esteemed to be good, which can decide whether the conscience of any particular indi- vidual corresponds to this Idea of the Conscience. Right and duty, as the absolutely rational characteristics of the will, are neither the particular quality of an individual’s will, nor a mere sentimental form, but they are universal laws and principles. Through these alone it is to be deter- mined whether one’s conscience is true or not. Any appeal to only its own arbitrary views, is directly opposed to what it professes to be, that is, to the rational and absolutely valid modes of conduct. Hence the state cannot acknowledge the validity of any merely private conscience, any more than science can accept merely subjective views. Still the private conscience can separate itself from this true content and degrade it to a mere form and semblance, by standing upon its own views. Hence ambiguity in regard to conscience lies in the pre- supposed identity of subjective conscience with objective good, which renders it sacred. Private conscience, however, may claim the validity which belongs only to this absolutely rational content. We are now treating of the moral stand- point as distinguished from the ethical ( sittlichen ) standpoint. We have spoken of the true conscience here only to avoid any misunderstanding. Our criticisms of the formal conscience do not apply to the true conscience, which belongs to the ethical frame of mind treated of in Part Third. We note, too, that the religious conscience is not to be treated of here. 122 MORALITY. § 138 - This form of private conscience really dissolves all definite forms of right and duty. It is the judge which determines its content from within. At the same time it is the power which actualizes any conjectured and obligatory good. [Hegel says that in epochs when the current forms of right and good could not satisfy the better will, philosophers like Socrates and the Stoics sought to find within themselves and to determine out of their own minds, truer forms of right and good. . . . Supplementary. — We may grant that no current form of morality is absolutely true and final. When any current form has become insufficient or obsolete, it is the preroga- tive of subjectivity to evolve another one. In truth every existing form of ethicality (concrete social morality) has been produced through this subjective activity of the social spirit. We may grant this without retracting our criticisms upon the formal and formless character of mere subject- ivity, before it has produced new forms. It is only in times when the current codes are empty and spiritless and exist as a mere dead letter, that it is right for the individual to withdraw to his own inner sanctuary. This was the case of Socrates. The same is also more or less true in some present conditions of society.] § 139 . The subjective will may thus refuse to acknowledge the validity of definite current forms of duty and insist upon maintaining its own inner convictions. In so far as it does so, it is really the possibility of elevating its own arbitrary caprice to supremacy over the true universal, and of actual- izing this usurpation in actual deed. That is, it is the possibility of being morally Evil {böse). Mere private conscience is thus actually upon the very threshold of changing into the bad. Both morality and that THE GOOD AND CONSCIENCE. 123 which is morally bad, have their common root in that certitude of itself which insists upon existing, knowing and choosing in an arbitrarily independent way. The origin of evil lies in tire region of the mysterious, i. e., in the speculative nature of freedom. Freedom must neces- sarily advance beyond the mere natural will, and must put itself in internal relation to it. This naturalness of the will comes into existence as the contradiction of its very self, and as incompatible with itself in this opposition. Thus it is this particularity of the will itself that characterizes itself as the evil. There is here an opposition of the merely natural will to the subjectivity of the will. In this oppo- sition, the subjective will is only relatively and formally independent being, as it can draw its content only from the properties of the natural will, — from its cravings, instincts, inclinations, etc. These latter may be either good or bad. But the will having such contingent content, is opposed to the universal, to the good. Hence its internality is really evil. Thus man is bad potentially or by nature, as well as through his intellectual advance, though neither mere nature nor thought, as such, are in themselves bad. But this side of the necessity of evil, absolutely implies that this evil be characterized as necessarily that which ought not to be, i. e., that it ought to be negated, not that it should not have appeared. This constitutes the distinction between the irrational beast and man. It must needs be that the offense come, but not that man should hold to it, to his own destruc- tion. . . . The individual subject as such, is therefore abso- lutely responsible for the guilt of his own evil. Supplementary. — Man has the possibility of the good, that is of willing the universal. But he has also the possi- bility of evil, that is of identifying some particular form with the universal. He is thus good only inasmuch as he has the possibility of being bad. Moral good and evil are inseparable, through the concept becoming objective, and 124 MORALITY. as such having the property of difference. The bad will chooses something different from the universal will, while the good will chooses what is conformable to its genuine concept. . . . But the question of the origin of evil relates more strictly to the transition of the positive into the nega- tive. If God is held as being Himself the absolute Positive (i Gesetzte ) in the creation of the world, there is no possible entrance for the negative. It would be an unsatisfactory and empty relation to suppose the admission of the negative by God. In mythology the origin of evil is not really com- prehended. The good and bad are not recognized as having any connection other than an external one. But this will not satisfy thought, which demands to see how the negative is rooted in the positive. This solution is contained in the very concept, or in its self-developed form of the Idea. The Idea , as active, is essentially self-distinguishing, posits its other or its opposite out of itself. Thus the bad has its root in the self-activity of the will. The will, in concept, is good as well as bad. The natural will is potentially this contra- diction ■ — it must distinguish itself from itself in order to be developed and internal. The merely natural will is opposed to the contents of concrete freedom. The child and the savage are thus held to a less degree of responsibility than the fully developed and civilized man. The merely natural will, in its naive state, is neither good nor bad. It is only when it is brought into conscious relation to the will as freedom, that it gets the property of being that which ought not to be and thus becomes the morally bad. The natural will, when still remaining in the educated, civilized man, is no longer merely natural will, but is an element positively opposed to the good. It is false to say that man is without guilt when he once sees that the morally evil is a necessary element in the concept of will, for man’s own choice of his deed is the act of his freedom and he is responsible for it. It was in man’s getting the knowledge THE GOOD AND CONSCIENCE I2 5 of good and evil that he was said to have become like God. But this knowledge of good and evil is no merely natural necessity. It is rather the freely chosen solution of the immanent opposition of good and evil. Both are present, and I have the choice between them. It is thus the nature of moral evil that it is the choice of man, but not that he be compelled by any natural necessity to choose it. § 140 . Self consciousness has the wisdom and power to give its aims external form. Every such aim must have this posi- tive side, because purpose implies concrete external action. Thus it is nominally for the sake of a duty and a good purpose, that self-consciousness is able to maintain an action as a good one, both as regards one’s self and others, though the action be merely the identification of an arbi- trary subjective aim with the true universal. If one insists upon carrying out, under the guise of duty, such a sub- jective aim so as to affect other people, we have Hypocrisy. If it affects only the man himself, we have the very acme of mere subjectivity usurping the throne of the Absolute. We call this last and most abstruse form of moral evil the highest summit of subjectivity on the moral standpoint. Here we find the bad changing into the good and the good into the bad, through consciousness knowing and insisting upon its own power as absolute. This is the form in which we meet with moral evil in our day. Shallow thought, in the name of philosophy, has thus distorted a profound concept and arrogated the title of the good for the morally bad. [Hegel here treats at some length of the current forms of this false subjectivity : (a) There are three phases in the development of hypocrisy : — MORALITY. 126 (a) The knowledge of the true universal, either in the form of the feeling of right and duty, or in the form of thorough knowledge of them. (ß) The choosing of something particular in opposition to this known universal. (y) The conscious choice of evil as such. These phases represent the acting with a bad conscience, rather than hypocrisy as such. It is a weighty question whether an action is bad only in so far as it is done with a bad conscience. This is very well expressed by Pascal, who says : ( Les Provinc. p lettre'). I/s seront tons damnes ces demi-pecheurs , qui ont quelque amour pour la vertu. Mais pour ces francs-pecheurs, pecheurs endurcis , pecheurs sans melange , . pi eins et acheves , Venfer ne les tient pas: ils ont tromp'e le diable ä force de s’y abandonner } The subjective right of knowing the moral character of one’s deed, must not be thought to be in collision with absolute objective right, in such a way as to regard them as distinct and mutually indifferent to each other. The bad is formally the very core of the individual wrong-doer, inas- much as it is the assertion of absolute egoism. Hence, he is guilty of it. Yet man is inherently rational, in his capacity for knowing the absolutely universal. It would not be treating man in accordance with his high capacity, if we should not attribute his evil deed to him as really part of his very self. 1 Pascal refers to Christ’s prayer on the cross for the forgiveness of his enemies on the ground that “ they know not what they do.” This would have been a superfluous prayer if their ignorance had changed the character of their deed so as to make it not to be evil and thus not to need forgiveness. Pie also adduces Aristotle’s distinction as to an act being owe eiSws or ayvoCiv. The former refers to ignorance of the external conditions. As to the other he says : “ Every bad man is ignorant of what is to be done and what is left undone. And it is just this defect (dp-apria) that makes men unjust and wicked. But such ignorance does not make their actions involuntary (and not imputable), but only makes them bad.” THE GOOD AND CONSCIENCE. 127 ( 'b ) But badness from a bad conscience is not yet hypo- crisy. Hypocrisy is rather the maintaining before others that one’s bad deed is really good, and the external simulation of being good, pious, etc. — an artifice of fraud to deceive others. The bad man can, moreover, appeal to his general goodness and piety as grounds of self-justification for his bad action, using them as a cloak for perverting the bad into that which is good for himself. (y) To this perversion belongs that form known as Proba- bilism. Probabilism maintains the principle that any action is permitted for which any good reason may be found, even if this be only the opinion of a learned Doctor, however it may differ from the opinion of other Doctors. It, however, acknowledges that such an authority gives only probability, though it asserts it to be sufficient for quieting the con- science. It concedes that there may be other reasons just as good. It also acknowledges the necessity of some ob- jective ground for right conduct. The decision as to what is good (or bad) is placed upon the many good reasons including those authorities. But these are numerous and contradictory. Hence it is the arbitrary choice of the indi- vidual which must ultimately decide the case. This under- mines all ethicality and religious life. But, because Proba- bilism does not acknowledge this choice of the individual as the ground of decision, it is a form of hypocrisy. ( d ) The next phase is that which maintains that the good will consists in merely willing the good; that all which is needed to make an action good is that one wills the good in general. But the action has a content only as far as it is a specific choice. The good, on the other hand, is not specific, and thus it is reserved to private choice to give it a content. In Probabilism some reverend Father is an authority. Here every one has the dignity of being an authority, specifying just what is good. But what one calls good may be only one side of the concrete case, and thus 128 MORALITY. it may be really bad, all things being considered. This is the phase of Intention previously considered (§ 119). Here we have a conflict of qualities of a deed, it being good ac- cording to the one, and bad according to the other. Hence the question arises whether the intention is really good. But the individual always intends the good. The particular deed intended is still good (it is held), in spite of some of its sides being criminal and bad,- — because it was intended. If the individual had intended some one of these bad sides instead of the one he did, it would still have been good, — because intended. Theft and murder are really, as deeds, the satisfaction of such a will as wills them. Thus they have a positive side in the will, and in order to make the deed good it is only necessary to intend the gratification of such a will. Theft and flight from battle for the sake of one’s life or that of his family, murderous revenge for one’s gratification of his feeling of his own rights, killing a man because he is bad, — all such maybe stamped as good deeds because of the good intention with which they are done. Thus it has even been said that there is no really bad man, as no one ever wills the bad for the sake of the bad, but always wills something positive, something which satisfies his will, — something good. Thus we find that all difference between good and evil, and all real duties, have disappeared in this abstract good. Therefore, to merely will the good, or to merely do a deed with good intention, is rather evil. Here we may consider the maxim: the end sanctifies the means. It might be replied: certainly a holy aim does, but an unholy aim does not sanctify the means. If the end is holy, the means are also holy. This would be a tautological expression, if “means” were used in its strict sense, that is, if it be strictly a means. But the real meaning of this expression is that even a bad “ means,” yes, even a crime, is permissible or obligatory if it leads to a good end. Thou THE GOOD AND CONSCIENCE. 129 shalt not kill, and yet courts of justice and soldiers have not only the right but the duty to kill men. But in these cases it is strictly defined as to what kind of men and under what circumstance this is a right and a duty. Thou shalt preserve thy own life and that of thy family. But even this duty is subordinated to a higher end, and thus reduced to a means. But what is designated as a crime is not an indefinite thing still open to discussion, but has its clearly- defined character. The sacred aim which is opposed to the criminal means, is nothing more than a private opinion as to what is good or better. Finally, we have mere private opinion expressly proclaimed as the rule of right and duty. ( e ) That is we have private conviction as to what is right made the judge of the ethical (sittliche) nature of an act. The good, which a man wills, has no specific content as yet, and the principle of private conviction demands that the individual subsume an act under the character of that which is good for himself. Here even the appearance of any ethical objectivity has disappeared. Such a doctrine is directly connected with the so-called philosophy which denies the knowableness of truth and consequently that of ethical laws. As such a philosophy esteems the knowableness of truth to be an empty conceit, it must make the merely outward appearance of an action the measure of its truth, and con- sequently place the ethical in the peculiar world-conception and private conviction of the individual. Such a degraded form of philosophy may seem to be the idle talk of scholas- tics, but the evil of it is that it gradually makes its way into ethical thought and then shows its real baseness. When such views as those we have mentioned obtain currency, there is no longer either vice or hypocrisy. Everything is justified by the intention and by the outward appearance . 1 1 I do not doubt but that one may be thoroughly convinced. But how many men undertake the worst crimes out of just such felt convic- tions. If this ground were allowed there could be no longer any 130 MORALITY. But the possibility of error must sometimes force itself upon those holding this principle of private conviction, and thus give rise to the demand for an absolute and universal law. But law does not act. It is only the real man who acts. In measuring the worth of a man the only question is con- cerning how far he has received the law into his heart and mind, — how far his conviction has been affected by it. But if man’s actions are not to be judged according to that law it is hard to see what purpose that law serves. Such a law is degraded to a mere outer letter, for it is only through my conviction that it becomes a law binding me to the obli- gatory. Such a law may have the authority of God, of the State, of millenniums in which it was the bond uniting men in all their manifold relations ; and yet against all these authorities I oppose the authority of my subjective con- viction. Such self-conceit appears at first as tremendous, and yet this principle of private judgment which we are here considering justifies this conceit. Shallow philosophy and bad sophistry may lead to such higher inconsequence. And if they then admit the possibility of error, and consequently of crime, they still seek to reduce it to its minimum. For, say they, to err is human. Who has not daily erred concern- ing more or less important things. And yet even the dis- tinction between important and unimportant things vanishes, when private conviction is considered to be ultimate. The admission of the possibility of an error is changed into the assertion that a wrong conviction is only an error. This is but a step removed from dishonesty. For at one time all ethicality and human worth are placed in private conviction, thus elevating it to the highest and holiest position. At another time private conviction is regarded as merely an rational judgment as to good and bad, right and wrong or the noble and ignoble. Delusion would have equal right with sound sense. Reason would have no right, or validity — only the one who doubted would be in the truth. I shudder before the consequence of such tolerance, which would be exclusively to the advantage of un-reason. — Fr. A. Jacobi. THE GOOD AND CONSCIENCE. 13 1 error. In fact my conviction is extremely insignificant. If I cannot know anything true, then it is a matter of indiffer- ence how or what I think, and there remains for my thought only that empty good of the abstract understanding. Moreover, there results the consequence that others, who act according to their convictions, may regard my actions (from conviction) as crimes, and that they are quite right in doing so. Thus I am cast down from the pinnacle of free- dom and honor into the condition of slavery and dishonor. Thus the principle of private conviction (of others) meets me as an avenging judge. (/) The highest form of the expression of this subjectivity (a term borrowed from Plato, though used in a different way) is that of Irony. This is the conviction not only of the unreality and vanity of all rights, laws, duties and vir- tues, but it is the recognition of its own vanity, and, at the same time, of itself, as absolute. The ego is all. It has become conscious of its own utter emptiness, and yet main- tains itself as the ultimate and fundamental reality in an empty world. The ego which creates, names and destroys its own good and evil has become conscious of its own utter invalidity and vanity. Such Irony is only possible in a period of great culture, when all earnest belief has vanished and the vanity of vanities appears as the only reality. Here there is no real good acknowledged, either objective or sub- jective. One’s own desires, aims, and good, are recognized as equally invalid with current codes of morality, and yet they are deliberately maintained as having absolute validity.] Transition from Morality to Ethicality ( Sittlichkeit ). § 141 . The good is as yet abstract. But, as the concrete sub- stance of freedom, it demands determinations or qualities in general, as well as the principle of freedom, as identical with the goad. Conscience , which is yet only an abstract principle J 3 1 2 MORALITY. of determination, likewise demands that its determinations be given universality and objectivity. We have seen how both good and duty, when either of them is raised to inde- pendent universality, lack that specific definite character which they ought to have. But the integration of both the good and Conscience, as relatively independent, is potentially accomplished in their organic unity. For we have seen sub- jectivity vanishing into its own emptiness, already posited (in the form of pure self-certitude or conscience), as identical with the abstract universality of the good. This integration of the good and Conscience is the real truth of them both. It is their concrete organic unity. This unity is the sphere of Ethicality , or the concrete ethical world of social life. This transition is more scientifically developed in the Logic. We are here concerned with its finite abstract side, i.e., with good demanding actualization and with conscience demanding the good for its content. But both of these, as yet partial phases, are not yet explicitly developed into that which they are potentially. This development of both the good and of conscience, so that neither lacks the other; this integration of both into an organic unity, in which each is retained as a member rather than as an independent thing, is the realized Idea of the will. In this each one attains its true reality. . . . We found the first definite characteristic of the determi- nate being ( Dasein ) of freedom to be that of Abstract Right. This, however, passed through the reflexion of self-conscious- ness into the form of the good. Here now we have the truth of abstract right as well as of. both the good and conscience. The Ethical (, Sittliche ) is subjective disposition of mind, but only in reference to implicit 1 (an sich ) rights. That this 1 It seems that Hegel’s thought requires some other term than im- plicit (an sich) here. The ethical in general has to do with the explicit. Hegel’s reference to it here as subjective disposition in reference to implicit rights is only made in passing and without further elucidation, and is inexplicable. THE GOOD AND CONSCIENCE. r 33 Idea is the truth of the concept of freedom, cannot be merely an accepted presupposition, but must be demonstrated by philosophy. This demonstration is simply that of showing how both abstract right and conscience lead back into this organic unity as their truth. Supplemeivmry . — Both the standpoints previously con- sidered lack their opposites. Abstract good vanishes into perfect powerlessness, and conscience shrivels into objective insignificance. Hence there may arise a longing for objec- tivity. A man would sometimes gladly humble himself to slavish dependency in order to escape the torture and empti- ness of mere negativity. This accounts for the many recent perversions to the Catholic Church. Such persons have found no definite codes and dogmas within their own spirit and have reached out after something stable, after an authority, even if what they obtained was devoid of the substantiality of thought. Ethicality ( Sittlichkeit ), or the ethical world of social life, is the absolute unity of sub- jective and objective good. In this sphere is found the solution of the antinomy in strict accordance with the con- cept of freedom. Ethicality is not merely the subjective form and the self-determination of the will, but it has real freedom for its content. Both right and morality need the ethical for their foundation, as without it neither has any actuality. Only the Idea , the true infinite is actual. Rights exist only as the branch, or as a plant clinging round a firm tree. THIRD PART. ETHICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). § 142 . Ethicality, or the ethical world of concrete social life, is the Idea of freedom, as the vital and virile good. It is in self-consciousness that this good attains to its knowledge and volition, and through their activity to its own actualiza- tion. On the other hand it is in this ethical substance that self-consciousness has its absolute ground and efficient end. Ethicality is the concept of freedom, developed into the present existing world and into the nature of self-consciousness. § 143 . Since this unity of the concept of the will and its determi- 'nate being (Dasein), which is the particular will, is know- ing, the consciousness of the difference between these moments of the Idea is present, but in such a manner that now each moment by itself is the totality of the Idea , and has the Idea as ground and contents. § 144 . (a) The objective ethical ( objektive Sittliche), which takes the place of abstract good, is substance, concrete through its subjectivity as infinite form. This substance posits thence differences in itself, which thereby are determined by the concept, and through which the ethical concept gains a fixed content, which is explicitly necessary and elevated above subjective opinion and inclination. This content consists of the in and for themselves existing laws and institutions. J 3 6 E THICA LITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). Supplementary. — In all ethicality ( Sittlichkeit ) both the objective and the subjective moments are present ; but both are its forms only. The good is here substance, that means the filling up of the objective with subjectivity. When ethicality is viewed from the objective standpoint, it may be said that the ethical man is unconscious of himself. In this sense, Antigone declared that no one knew whence the laws had come ; that they were eternal : that is to say, they are the absolutely independent realities, the determinations proceeding from the nature of the case. But none the less this substantial has also a consciousness, although this con- sciousness has always, on this standpoint, only the position of a phase. § 145. In the fact that the ethical is the system of these determi- nations of the Idea , consists its rationality. In this manner it becomes freedom, or the in and for itself existing will as the objective, the sphere of necessity, whose moments are the ethical powers that rule the lives of individuals and are actualized and revealed in them as their attributes ( Accidenzen ) and conceptions. Supplementary. — Since the concept of freedom consists in the ethical determinations, these are the substantiality or the universal essence of the individuals, who, consequently, are related to this universal factor as something accidental. Whether the individual exists or not is indifferent to objective ethicality, which alone is the enduring and the power through which the lives of individuals are ruled. Hence, ethicality, or concrete morality, has been represented to mankind as eternal justice, as gods existing in and for themselves, against whom the vain striving of the individuals becomes only a fluctuating play. E THICA LIT Y (. SITTLICHKEIT ). (ß) The substance is, in this its actual self-consciousness , cognizant of itself, and hence object of knowledge. On the one hand, by virtue of the fact that they exist in the highest sense of independence, the ethical substance, its laws, and domination, have for the subject an absolute authority and force, infinitely more stable than the mere being [das Seif of nature. The sun, moon, mountains, rivers, objects of nature in general, exist; they have for consciousness the authority not only of mere existence in general, but also of having a particular nature. Consciousness respects this- particular nature, and is guided by it when employed with objects of nature. But the authority of ethical laws is infinitely higher, since the things in nature present rationality only in a wholly external ( äusserliche ) and particular manner, and conceal this rationality under the form of the contingent. § 147. On the other hand, the ethical substance, its laws and authority, are nothing foreign to the subject, but they afford the subject the testbnony of the spirit , as being of its own essence , as that in which it feels itself to exist (, Selbstgefühl ), and in which it lives as in its proper element, undifferen- tiated from itself, — a condition that is unmediated and as yet identical, even as faith and trust are. Faith and trust belong to incipient reflection, and pre- suppose a conception and differentiation; as, for example, believing in a heathen religion is different from being a heathen. This relation, or rather relationless identity, in which the ethical is the actual vitality of self-consciousness, can under all circumstances resolve itself into a relation of faith and conviction, and into something mediated by further reflection, into insight founded on reasons. This insight 138 E TH 1 CALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). may also begin from any particular aims, interests or con- siderations, from fear or hope, or from historical antecedents. But its adequate recognition belongs to the thinking con- cept. § 148. For the individual, who distinguishes himself from these substantial determinations as the subjective and in himself indeterminate, or as the particularly determined, and to whom they hence stand in the relation of substance, these substantial determinations become duties which, in relation to his will, are obligatory. The ethical doctrine of duties (that is, as it is objectively , and not as conceived according to the empty principle of moral subjectivity, according to which, indeed, nothing determines it [§134]) is, consequently, the systematic devel- opment of the sphere of ethical necessity. This forms the content of this Part Third of this treatise. The difference of this presentation from the form of a doctrine of duties con- sists in this alone, that, in what follows, the ethical deter- minations present themselves as necessary relations, without any further consequence being added to each of them. Hence this determination is a duty for man. A doctrine of duties, when not a philosophical science, takes its subject- matter from conditions and relations contingently presented, and shows their connection with individual conceptions, with those principles and thoughts, aims, motives, feelings, and the like, which are generally entertained, and can add as reasons the further consequence of each duty in reference to other ethical relations, as well as in reference to common welfare and opinion. But an immanent and consistent doctrine of duties can be nothing else than the evolution of those relations which become necessary through the Idea of freedom, and hence actual throughout their whole extent, in the State. E THICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). r 39 § 149. Obligatory duty can appear as a limitation , only to undetermined subjectivity or abstract freedom, and to the desires of the natural will, or to that moral will which deter- mines its indeterminate good through its own caprice. But the individual has in duty rather his liberation , on the one hand, from the dependence imposed on him when under the influence of natural desires alone, as well as from the oppression which he suffers as subjective particularity in the moral reflexion as to what ought and what may be done ; and, on the other hand, from the undetermined sub- jectivity which does not express itself and thus attain the objective characteristics of action, but remains in itself as a non-actuality. In duty the individual shakes off subjective fetters and attains substantial freedom. Supplementary .- — Duty limits only the caprice of subjec- tivity, and comes in conflict only with the abstract good to which subjectivity clings. When men say, “We wish to be free,” this means at first only, “We wish to be free in an abstract sense,” i. e., free from objective laws. Hence every determination and organic differentiation in the State is held to be a limitation of this freedom. Duty is not a limitation, or restriction of freedom but of the abstraction of freedom, that is to say, of the opposite to freedom : duty is the arrival of freedom at determinate being, the gaining of affirmative freedom. § 150. The ethical, in so far as it reflects itself in the individual character, as such is determined by nature, is virtue. Inasmuch as this shows itself as nothing but the simple conformity of the individual to the duties of the situation in which he finds himself, virtue is rectitude. 140 ETHICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). What man should do, what duties he must fulfil in order to be virtuous, is easily determined in an ethical community. There is nothing else for him to do than that which is pre- scribed, proclaimed and made known to him in his ethical relations. Rectitude is the universal, that which can be promoted in him partly as the ethical and partly as the legally right. But for the moral standpoint, rectitude easily appears as something subordinate, over and above which one must demand something still more in one’s self and others. The desire to be something particular is not satisfied with conformity to the universal and objective forms of duty as existing in the current conventional morals. Such a desire finds only in an exception the consciousness of the desired peculiarity. The different sides of rectitude may just as properly be called virtues, since they are just as much the property (though in the comparison with others, not the particular property) of the individual. But discourse about virtue borders easily on empty decla- mation, since it treats only of an abstract and indefinite matter. Such discourse with its reasons and manner of presentation also appeals to the individual, as to a being of caprice and subjective inclination. In an ethical condition of society, whose relations are fully developed and actual- ized, such peculiar forms of virtue have a place and actuality only in extraordinary circumstances and collisions of these relations — that is, in actual collisions , for moral reflection can, indeed find collisions under any circumstances, and obtain for itself the consciousness of having made sacri- fices and of being something particular and peculiar. For this reason this form of virtue as such occurs oftener in undeveloped states of society and of the community. In such earlier stages the ethical and its actualization is more of an individual choice and a genial nature peculiar to the individual. The ancients, we know, predicated virtue especially of Hercules. In the ancient state however, ETHICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). 141 ethicality had not grown to this free system of an independ- ent development and objectivity — thus the deficiency had to be supplied by the geniality of the individual. The doctrine of virtues, when not simply a doctrine of particular duties, includes the character which is founded in natural determinations. Thus it embraces a spiritual history of the natural man. Since the virtues are the ethical in reference to the par- ticular, and from this subjective side something undetermined, the quantitative “more” or “less” appears as their deter- mination ; and their contemplation brings up the opposite defects as vice. Thus Aristotle determined the correct signification of the particular virtues as the mean between a too-much and a too-little. The same content which takes the form of duties and then that of virtues, has also the form of impulses. These, also, have the same fundamental content. But since this content of the impulses belongs still to the immediate will and the natural sensibilities, and has not been developed to the determination of ethicality, the impulses have only the abstract object in common with the content of duties and virtues. But this abstract object, being without determination in itself, does not contain the limits of good and evil in itself. In other words, the im- pulses are good according to the abstraction of the positive, and conversely bad, according to the abstraction of the negative (§ 18). Supplementary. — Where a person does this or that ethic- ally good act, he is not straightway virtuous, but this he is when ethical behavior is a stable element in his character. Virtue is rather ethical virtuosoship. The reason that we do not speak so much of virtue now as formerly, is that ethicality is no longer so much some peculiar quality of a particular individual as formerly. The French are, in the main, the people who speak most of virtue, because among them the individual is considered rather as something pecu- 142 E THICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). liar, and as having a natural (i. e., not yet ethical) manner of action. The Germans, on the contrary, are more thought- ful, and among them the same content gains the form of universality. § 151 . But in the simple identity with the actuality of individuals, the ethical appears as their common manner of acting, as custom. This habitual manner of acting becomes a second nature , which takes the place of that which at first is simply natural will. It becomes the penetrating soul, meaning, and actuality of its existence, the living and present spirit as a world, whose substance first then exists as spirit. Supplementary. — As nature has her laws, as the animal, the trees, the sun, fulfil their law, so also is custom the law belonging to the spirit of freedom. That which legal right and morality have not yet attained, that custom is, namely, spirit. For in legal right the particularity is not yet that of the concept, but only that of the natural will. Likewise, at the stage of morality, self-consciousness is not yet spiritual consciousness. The question is, then, only concerning the worth of the subject in himself ; that is to say, the subject which determines himself in accordance with the good against the evil, has still the form of arbitrariness. On the other hand, at the ethical stage, the will is the will of the spirit and has a substantial content adequate unto itself. Pedagogy is the art of making men ethical : it considers man as a merely natural being — it shows the way to a new birth, how to convert his first nature into a second spiritual 1 nature, so that this spiritual becomes a habit in him. In this habit the opposition of the natural and subjective will disappears and the struggle of the subject is broken. Thus habit belongs to ethicality to the same extent as to philo- sophic thought, for the latter demands that the spirit shall be cultured so as to be opposed to arbitrary notions, and that E THICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). J 4 3 these shall be crushed and conquered, in order that rational thought have free course. But man also dies of habit, that is, he is dead when he has fully habituated himself to life, when he has become spiritually and physically obtuse, and when the opposition belonging to subjective consciousness and spiritual activity has disappeared. For man is active only as long as there is is something he has not attained, in reference to which he wishes to be productive and effective. When this is accom- plished, virile activity and vitality ( Lebendigkeit ), disappear, and the absence of interest that then ensues is spiritual or even physical death. § 152 . In this manner, ethical substantiality comes to its right and this right gains its realization. For the self-will and independent conscience of the individual, which existed as for itself only and produced an opposition against the concrete ethical life, disappear, when the ethical character recognizes as its motive and end ( bewegende Zweck ) the un- moved universal that has been reduced by its determina- tions to actual rationality ; and when this ethical character recognizes its value, as well as the persistence ( Bestehen ) of particular ends, as being grounded and having its actuality in this determined universal. Subjectivity is the absolute for?n itself and the existing actuality of substance. The distinction of the subject from substance, viewed as the objects, ends, and power of the subject, is nothing but the likewise immediately ( unmittelbar , i. e., not mediately) van- ished distinction of form. Subjectivity, which is the ground of existence for the con- cept of freedom (§ 106) and which, on the moral standpoint, is still differentiated from said concept, becomes, in the ethical sphere, the adequate existence of the concept of freedom. 144 ETHICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). § 153 . The right of individuals to their subjective determination of freedom has its realization in the fact that they belong to ethical reality, inasmuch as the certitude of their freedom has its truth in such objectivity, and they (the individuals) actually possses in the ethical sphere their essential being ( Wesen) and their inner universality (§ 147). To a father who asked how he might best bring up his son, a Pythagorean (it is also attributed to others) answered: “By making him the citizen of a state with good laws.” Supplementary. — The pedagogical attempt to keep pupils away from the common (i. e., communal) life of the present, and to bring them up in the country (Rousseau in “ Emile ”) has been a vain experiment, for to estrange men from the laws of the world cannot prove a success. Even if youth is educated in solitude, it is certainly unwarranted to think that no fragrant breeze from the spirit-world should ever invade this solitude, and that the power of the world-spirit is too weak to take possession of this little separated terri- tory. When he is the citizen of a good state , the individual first gains his just rights. “ The realm of morality ( Sittlichkeit ) is nothing but the absolute spiritual unity of the essence of individuals, which exists in their independent reality. . . . This moral sub- stance, looked at abstractly from the mere side of its uni- versality, is the law as the expression of such thought. But from another point of view it is also immediate actual self- consciousness as custom. On the other hand, the individual consciousness exists as a unitary member of the universal consciousness. Its action and existence are the universal custom ( Sitte or Wo%), in which it lives and moves and has its being. . . . “Any merely particular action or business of the individual relates to the needs of himself as a natural being. But ETHICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ) !4S these, his commonest functions, are saved from nothingness and given reality solely by the universal maintaining medium, that is, through the power of the whole people of which he is a member. It is this power, too, which gives content as well as form to his actions. What he does is the uni- versal skill and custom of all. Just so far as this content completely individualizes itself, is its reality inwoven with the activity of all. The labor of the individual for his own wants is at the same time a satisfying of the needs of others, and reciprocally the satisfaction of his own needs is attained only through the labor of others. Thus the individual un- consciously does an universal work in doing his own indi- vidual work. But he also does this consciously. The whole, as his object, is that for which he sacrifices himself, and through which sacrifice he fulfils himself. Here there is nothing but what is reciprocal; nothing even in the appar- ently negative activity of the independent individual, but such as enables him to attain the positive significance of independ- ent being. This unity, which throbs through both the nega- tion and the affirmation of the individual, speaks its universal language in the common custom and laws of his people. Yet this unchanging essence, — the spirit of his people, — is itself simply the expression of the single individuality which seems to be opposed to it. The laws proclaim what each one is and does. The individual recognizes this essence as not only his universal outward existence, but also as that which is particularized in his own individuality and in that of fellow-citizens. Hence each one has in this universal spirit nothing else than assurance of himself, and finds in existing reality nothing but himself. In it I behold only independent beings like myself. In them I see the free unity of self with others, which exists through others as it does through me. I see them as myself and myself as them in this free unity or universal substance. Thus reason is realized in truth in the life of a free people. It is present, 146 £7HJCAL1TY {SITTLICHKEIT). '.’ .•ini: spirit, in which the individual not only finds his char- acter. . .. universal and particular essence, proclaimed and prepared ready to hand, but also hnds that he himself is this essence, and has attained his definite character. Hence the wisest men of antiquity have proclaimed the maxim: that wisdom and virtue consist in living in harmonv with the Ires morals of one's own people ." 1 § 154. The right of individuals to special characteristics, is con- tained in ethical substantiality, since particularity is the manner of the external appearance in which the ethical exists. § 155. In this identity of the universal and particular will. ,:h/v and -vglr consequently coincide, and man has in the ethical sphere duties to the same extent as rights, and rights to the same extent as duties. In abstract legal right, the op has the right and another has the dun - : in the moral sphere, only the right of my own knowledge and will, together with my welfare united with duty, are demanded. — The slave can have no duties, for duties belong to the free man alone. If all rights were on one side and all duties on the other, the whole 'das G would dissolve, for identity alone is the foundation which we here must hold fast. § 156. The ethical substance, as containing the independent self- consciousness that coincides with its concept, is the actual spirit of a family and a people. 1 Hegel's £r.i: vrV S.s (hvav. pp. r; 6 -S. cf. Bradley's Etc::£ Studies, pp. 167 -S. ETHICALITY (SITTLICHKEIT). !47 Supplementary. — - The ethical is not abstract like the good , , but is, in an intensive sense, actual. The spirit has actuality, and individuals are the accidents of this actuality. Conse- quently, in the ethical sphere, there are only two points of view possible : either to start from substantiality, or to proceed in an atomistic manner and rise from individuality as foundation. But the latter point of view is spiritless, since it leads only to a conglomeration ; for the spirit is nothing individual, but it is the unity of the individual and universal. § 157 . The concept of this Idea is only spirit, self-knowledge, and actuality, when it is the objectification of itself, the move- ment through the form of its moments. It is, therefore : (a) The immediated, or natural ethical spirit ; — the family. This substantiality changes at the loss of its unity into that of separation (of the members of the family) and to the standpoint of the relative, thus becoming, (b) The civic community , a union of the members as independent individuals (i. e., as private persons) in a formal universality, through their needs, and through the legal con- stitution as a means for the safety of persons and property, and through an external order for their individual and com- mon interests. This external state centers itself together (c) In the end and actuality of the substantial universal, and of the public life devoted to the common weal — in the constitution of the State. 148 ETHICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). FIRST SECTION. The Family. § 158 . The family, as the unmediated substantiality of the spirit has its emotional sense of unity, love , for its characteristic ; so that the disposition is to have the self-consciousness of one’s individuality in this unity as in an independent essentiality, in order to be united to the family not as a person for himself, but as a member. Supplementary. — Love means in general the conscious- ness of my unity with another ; so that I do not remain isolated for myself, but gain my self-consciousness only as the renunciation of my exclusive independence (Fursich- seins), and thereby know myself as the unity of myself with the other and of the other with me. But love is feeling, that is, it is ethicality in the primitive natural form. In the State we do not find love. ; there one is conscious of the unity as the unity of laza, there the content must be rational and I must know it. The first phase of love is that I wish not to be an independent person for myself, and that, if I am, I feel myself defective and incomplete. The second phase is that I win myself in another person, that I am recognized in him as he is in me. Love is, hence, a most monstrous contradiction to the understanding, which it can not solve, since nothing harder is found than this punctili- ousness of self-consciousness which is denied, and which I am still said to have affirmed. But love is at once the source and the solution of the contradiction ; as solution it is ethical concord. § 159 . The right which belongs to the individual on the ground of family-unity, and which at first is his life in this unity THE FAMILY. 149 itself, appears only in the form of (legal) rights as of the abstract phase of the determined individuality , when once dissolution of the family takes place. Here, those who have been its members, become independent persons in their disposition and actuality, and receive separately (and consequently in an external way, as wealth, support, cost of education, and the like) that which they obtained in the family as their natural heritage. Supplementary. — The right of the family consists properly in this : that its substantiality shall have determinate exist- ence ( Dasein ). Consequently, it is a right against any external impediments, and against secession from this unity. But on the contrary, again, love is a feeling, a subjective affair, against which the unity ( Einigkeit ) cannot make itself effective. Hence, when unity is to be promoted it can be done only by the agency of such things which, according to their nature, are external and not dependent on feeling. § 160. The family consummates itself on three sides : ( a ) In the form of its immediate concept, as wedlock. {IP) In external existence ( Dasein ), in the property and goods of the family, and in the care of the same. (r) In the bringing up of the children and the dissolution of the family. A. Wedlock. § 161. Wedlock contains, as the inwicdiate ethical relation, first the moment of natural vitality (Lebendigkeit), and, indeed, as substantial relation, life in its totality, viz., as actuality of the species and its process. But, secondly in self-conscious- ness the implicitly existing unity of the natural sexes, which for that reason is only an external unity, is transformed into a spiritual one, into self-conscious love. JS 0 E THICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). Supplementary. — Wedlock is essentially an ethical relation. Formerly, especially in most treatises on natural rights, it has been considered only from the physical side, from what it is on its merely natural side. Hence it has been con- sidered as a sexual relation only, and has remained closed in every way to the other characteristics of wedlock. But it is just as crude to conceive wedlock as nothing but a civil con- tract, a conception that occurs even with Kant, for then the mutual arbitrary choice makes a compact for the individuals, and wedlock is degraded to an ordinary mutual contract. A third conception, just as reprehensible, is to hold that wedlock is founded on love alone. For love, being a feeling, is always open to chance — a form which the ethical must not have. Hence wedlock is more closely determined as legally ethical love. With this determination, the transient, capricious and subjective in the concept of wedlock disappear. § 162 . As the subjective point of inception for wedlock, either the particular inclination of the two persons entering the relation, or the plans and arrangements of the parents, etc., appear the more prominent. The objective point of incep- tion is the free consent of the persons in question, a consent, indeed, to be henceforth one person, to resign their natural and individual personality for this unity. This is a self- limitation in this respect, but also, since in it they gain their substantial self-consciousness, it is their liberation. It is therefore the objective destiny and ethical duty of man to enter the state of wedlock. As to the matter of the external point of inception of wedlock, it is, according to its nature, accidental, and depends especially on the culture of reflection. The two extremes are : either the arrangements of well- meaning parents is the first step, and, as a result of the prearranged acquaintance, an inclination arises in the persons THE FAMILY. I S I who are being selected for each other for the union of love ; or the inclination appears first in the persons in question, as diversely constituted as they may be. The former extreme, or in general, the way in which the resolve to marry takes its beginning, and has the inclination as a result so that at the actual marriage both are united, may be considered the more ethical way. In the other extreme, the infinitely particular individuality gets its pretensions recognized and is connected with the subjective principle of the modern world. (See above § 124.) But in modern dramas and other produc- tions of art, where sexual love is the fundamental interest, there is an element of penetrating chilliness. In the heart of the passion presented, through the thorough arbitrariness connected with the same, this chilliness is brought about by presenting the whole interest as depending on these (persons) alone, when, indeed, it may be of infinite importance for them but is not of such interest when in its merely natural form. Supplementary. — In nations where the feminine sex is less respected, the parents arrange marriage as they please, without consulting the individuals in question, and these are content with this arrangement, since any special definite direction of sentiment has as yet no pretensions. The maiden desires a husband, and he a wife in general (/. e., without caring for more particular characteristics of the desired consort). In other states of society, considerations of fortune, connections, and political ends may be the de- termining factors. Here great hardships are possible, since wedlock is made a means for other ends. In modern times, on the other hand, the subjective point of inception (falling in love) has come to be considered the only one of import- ance. The moderns imagine that each must wait till his hour has struck, and that each can give his love only to one certain individual. I S 2 ETHICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). § 163. The ethical, in wedlock, consists in the consciousness of this unity as a substantial end in love, in trust, and in the community of the whole individual existence. In this disposition and actuality, the natural sexual im- pulse is reduced to a mere phase of nature, which perishes in the instant of its gratification. Meanwhile the spiritual bond, in its right as the substantial essence of wedlock, elevated above the caprice of passion and of temporal and particular liking, becomes potentially indissoluble. That wedlock is not a contract-relation as to its essential foundation, has already been noted (§ 75), for, from the standpoint of contract, which starts from the abstract per- sonality of independent individuals, wedlock is a contract to pass out of and above the sphere of contract. The identification of the personalities, through which the family is one person , and its members properties, is the ethical spirit. It is this ethical (social) spirit which, stripped of the manifold externality which belongs to spirit in the form of a definite individual and in special temporal and well- defined secular interests, that is sometimes elevated into a pictorial conception and honored as the penatcs and the like, and, in general, gives to wedlock and the family its piety (in the Roman sense of the word) and its religious character. It is a further abstraction when the divine, the substantial in this phase of sentiment is separated from its proper sexual side, and from the feeling and the consciousness of spiritual unity, and falsely given a separate existence as Platonic love. This separation is connected with the monkish view, accord- ing to which the phase of natural life is determined as some- thing absolutely negative, ahd just through this is falsely given an infinite importance for itself. THE FAMILY. *53 § 164. As the stipulation of contract already contains for itself the true transference of property (§ 79), so the solemn ( feierliche ) declaration of agreement to accept the ethical bonds of wedlock and the corresponding recognition and sanction of the same by the family and community (that the church also enters as a further party to the union is not to be fully considered here), are the formal conclusion and actual- izing of wedlock. Hence this alliance is ethically constituted only when preceded by this ceremony, as the performance of its substantial essence, through sign and language, as the outward and visible form of the spiritual (§ 78). Thereby the sensuous sexual element belonging to natural life, re- ceives, in its ethical relation, the position of a consequence (Folge) and accidentality, which belongs to the external form of the ethical alliance. But the meaning of this alliance itself can be exhausted only in that of mutual love and support. . . . [Hegel further insists, in this paragraph, upon the neces- sity of the sacred solemnization of marriage, rather than degrading the ceremony to the mechanical work of a civil or ecclesiastical clerk, who performs it without any sense of its ethical significance. This is only rightly appreciated and honored by the sentiment and ceremonies of religious people. Wedlock has both great intellectual and ethical import and results for both sexes. It elevates both to higher labors and aims. A new and broader unity is therein accomplished in the sphere of domestic life. It becomes a veritable school for ethical culture. He also opposes marriage between blood-relations, saying that inti- macy and similarity of tastes and aims of the couple rather succeed than precede wedlock. These should be the ethical results of this school of virtue.] J 54 E THICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). § 167 . Wedlock is essentially monogamy , since it is the person- ality, the immediate, exclusive individuality that devotes and surrenders itself to this relation. The truth and the in- ternality {the subjective form of substantiality) of this relation results, therefore, only from the mutual undivided devotion of this personality. This realizes its right to be conscious of itself in another, only when the other enters this identity as a person, that is, as an atomic individuality. Wedlock, and especially monogamy, is one of the abso- lute principles on which ethicality (/. e ., concrete morality) of a communal life depends. Hence the institution of wed- lock is referred as a phase of the divine or heroic founding of states. § 169 . The family has, as person, its external reality in its prop- erty, in which it has the specific character of its substantial personality only when this property has the form of means or possession. B. The Possessions of the Family. § 170 . The family has not only property, but with its being a universal and enduring person, there comes the need and the characteristic of having an enduring and certain estate or fortune. The arbitrary phase of abstract property, belong- ing to the particular needs of the single individual and to the self-seeking of the desires, transforms itself here into the care and acquisition for a common weal, into an ethical activity. The introduction of fixed property appears in the tradi- tional accounts of the foundation of the State in connection with the introduction of marriage, or at least with the THE FAMILY. !55 beginning of a social and orderly life. — Wherein further, these possessions consist, and how they may gain true stability, is a problem that belongs to the sphere of the civic community. The Educatmi of Children and the Dissolution of the Fa?nily. § 173. «u. TV TT TT '7V' Supplementary. — ■ Between man and wife the relation of love is not yet objective; for, although feeling is the sub- stantial unity, this has no objectivity. Such an objectivity the parents first gain in their children. In these they have the totality of their union before themselves. The mother loves her husband, and the husband his wife, in their child. Both have in the child their love incarnate before them- selves. While in the family possessions the unity is only in an external thing, in the child this unity is in a spiritual being, by whom the parents are loved and whom they love. § 174. The children have a right to be educated and supported from the common family possessions. The right of the parents to the service of the children, as service, is estab- lished and limited by the common interest in the cares of the family. The right of the parent to limit the freedom of their children exists for the purpose of discipline and educa- tion. The end of punishment is not justice as such, but is of a subjective, moral nature ; its purpose is to deter the freedom that is only of uncultured nature [is naturalistic only], and to aid and elevate the universal in the child’s consciousness and will. Supplementary. — [Hegel further maintains that the child’s right of education rests upon the necessity of aid in his 156 ETHICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). self-development of potential manhood. The parent should only require such service from him as promotes this educa- tion. On the other hand, children should not be permitted to do just as they please, though the breaking the will of children should not be merely arbitrary. Obedience is to be demanded on the ground of the parents’ larger knowl- edge of what is best for them. Parents should remember that their children are potentially free spiritual beings, and so never treat them as slaves or mere soulless things. They should make it the primary end to educate them so that their ethical substance, and their hearts and wills should first come to flower and fruitage in the form of love, confi- dence and obedience. They should further seek to develop in them the sense of independence and free personality, that they may in due time be prepared to go out from the natural unity of the family and take their places as free and equal personalities with their parents in the civil community, form- ing for themselves new domestic circles. This leads to the topic of the Dissolution of the Family-relation .] § 176. As wedlock, primarily, is only the immediate ethical Idea , and hence has its objective actuality in the intimate inter- nality of the subjective disposition and feeling, we find in this the first contingent element of its existence. Just as little as compulsion to enter the state of wedlock is possible, just so little can a merely legal, positive bond keep the subjects (of wedlock) together, when averse and hostile sentiment and actions gain the ascendancy. Hence a third ethical authority is necessary that shall secure the legal right of wedlock, of ethical substantiality, against the bare opinion of such sentimental disposition and against the accidence of only temporary moods and the like — an authority that shall distinguish these temporary moods from THE FAMILY. 1 S 7 total estrangement, and decide where the latter occurs, in order to be able in such cases to dissolve the marital bonds. Supplementary . — When wedlock depends on merely sub- jective and accidental feeling alone, it can be dissolved. The State, on the contrary, is not subject to division and dissolution, since it is founded on law. Wedlock ought , certainly, to be indissoluble ; but here it comes no farther than to the ought. But since wedlock is something ethical (belonging to an ethical community), it cannot be dissolved arbitrarily, but only through an ethical authority, whether this be the church or a court of justice. When the parties are totally estranged from each other, as in a case of adultery, even the religious authority must allow divorce. § 178 -§ 180 . [The dissolution of the family thus occurs (i) through the death of the parents and the consequent distribution of the common property among the natural heirs, (2) through the total alienation of the married couple and their consequent separation, and (3) in the normal way, through the growth and development of the children into maturity.] The Transition of the Family into the Civic Community. § 181 . The family transforms itself in a natural way, and espe- cially through the principle of personality, into a plurality of families outside of one another. These families are related to one another, in general, as independent concrete persons, and consequently in an external manner. Or, the inter- locked moments (which are as yet undeveloped in their concept ) in the unity of the family, as the ethical Idea , must be allowed independent reality in the concept. This is the stage of differentiation. First, abstractly expressed, this gives the determination of particularity. This particular refers ! 5 8 ETHICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). itself, indeed, to universality, but in such a manner that the universal becomes as yet only the internal ground which consequently exists in a formal and only apparent manner 1 ( scheinende Weise ) in the particular. The expansion of the family in its transition into another principle, happens, in actual history, partly as the quiet expansion of a family into a people, a nation , which hence has a common natural origin, and partly as the association of dispersed family communities, either through military force or through voluntary alliance, furthered by common needs and by the reciprocal activity necessary for their satisfaction. Supplementary. — Universality has here as its point of inception, the independence of the particular, and, hence ethicality appears lost at this stage, since, for consciousness, the identity of the family is that which is regarded as the first, the divine, the source of duty. But now a condition begins in which the particular demands the first place for itself, and consequently the primary form of ethical determi- nation (the domestic life) is abolished. But, in reality, I only err in making this demand, for when I believe that I hold fast to the particular, the universal and the necessity of the interdependence of the universe still remain the first and the essential : I am consequently on the stage of appearance , and while my particularity continues to deter- mine me (that is to say, continues to be my purpose), I thereby serve the universal, which, in reality, retains the final power over me. 1 In Hegel scheinend , “apparent,” does not. have the connotation false , deceptive, as in English; for with Hegel, ground and appearance are categories of equal importance to essence ( Wesen.) Hence the reader must understand appearance and apparent as referring to the expression, the phenomenalization of the ground, or internal nature, of Wesen. This reflexive relation presents at first the loss of ethicality; but, since, as essence, it is necessarily phenomenal (must reveal itself as phenomenon), it produces the phenomenal world of ethicality (of the ethical Idea), the civic community. THE CIVIC COMMUNITY. 159 SECOND SECTION. The Civic Community. § 182. The concrete person who realizes himself as particular end (literally : is himself as particular end), as a total of wants with a mixture of natural necessity and arbitrary choice, is the special principle of the civic community. But here is meant the particular person that has his essence in his relation ( Beziehung ) to other particular persons, so that each satisfies and realizes himself as mediated through the others, and (hence) at the same time absolutely through the form of universality only. This universal or common ele- ment forms the second principle of civil society. Supplementary.- — The civic community is the difference (intermediate stage) that stands between the family and the State, even though its evolution follows later than the evolution of the State ; since as the intermediate, the civil society presupposes the State, as it must have something independent to rely on, in order to endure. The creation of the civic community belongs, moreover, to the modern world, as here first all the determinations of the Idea have received their just recognition. When the State is conceived as a unity of different persons, but as a unity that is only a community ( e . g., of interest), there is reference only to the determinations of the civic community. Many of the later writers on politics and law have not been able to advance to any other view of the State. In the civic community I each one is his own end, all others are nothing to him. But, without reference to others, no individual is able to pealize his end to its full extent ; these others, hence, become the means to the end of the particular. But the particular aim takes on a form of universality through its i6o E TH1CALITY ( SITTLICHKEIT ). reference to others, and satisfies itself by simultaneously satisfying the weal of others. Because particularity is bound up along with the conditions of universality, the whole is the ground of mediation in which all individuali- ties, all talents, all accidence of birth and fortune liberate themselves. In this too the currents of all passions empty themselves, passions that are ruled only by permeating reason. Particularity limited by universality is alone the measure through which every particular individual furthers his own welfare. Thus the Civic Community is what we understand by “ the state on its external side ” or as Government, arising from needs as presented to the under- standing. § 184 . The Idea , at this its stage of differentiation, contains the phase of existence peculiar to the individual ( eigenthiimliches V Dasei/i), of pandicula-rity — the right to develop and extend one’s self in all directions, and also the phase of universality ■ — • its right to prove itself the ground and necessary form of particularity, as well as the power over it, and its ultimate end. It is the system of an ethicality lost in its extremes that makes up the abstract phase of the reality of the Idea which here exists as the relative totality and inner necessity to this external appearance. Supplementary. — The ethical concept has here been lost in its extremes, and the unmediated unity of the family has been disorganized into a collected multitude. The reality is, at this stage of externality, the dissolution of the concept , the independence of the liberated and existent phases. Yet even here men are conditioned by their reciprocal needs and welfare. In seeking one’s own aim and well-being, a person necessarily seeks more universal ones, and, in turn, the more universal ones are only attained through this self- seeking of each one. . . . THE CIVIC COMMUNITY. 161 Abstract of § 185. This development of the individual personality of all citizens sometimes seems to create an arena in which rampant individualism begets great excesses, misery and moral corruption. In ancient states it led to the destruc- tion of ethical relations and thus to the downfall of nations. These ancient states were founded on such an undeveloped form of the universal element that they could find no place for individualism. It is only through the Christian religion that this principle of subjective freedom, and of the inde- pendent and infinite worth of the individual has come to its just recognition. The task of modern states is to welcome this principle and to incorporate it in harmonious unity with the larger ethical element. On the other hand, it is the task of individualism to learn that its real and substantial freedom can oniy be found in the sphere of a common weal and life, where helping others is the best form of helping one’s own self. § 187. The individuals are, as citizens of this civic community, private persons , who have their own interests as their end. Since this end is mediated through the universal, which, consequently, appears to the individuals in question as means, this end can be attained by them only in so far as they themselves determine their will, desires, and acts in a universal manner, and make themselves links in the chain of this connected whole. As the civic community does not exist as such in the consciousness of its members, the interest of the Idea lies here in the process of elevating the individual and natural elements of the Idea , through the necessity of nature as well as through the arbitrariness of wants, to formal freedom and formal universality of knowledge and will. In other words, this is the process of developing IÖ2 ETHIC ALI TY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). subjectivity in its phase of particularity. . . . Hence educa- tion , in its real essence, is liberation , and that the work of the higher liberation. It is the point of transition to that infinite subjective substantiality of ethicality, which is no longer unmediated and natural, but spiritual, being elevated to the form of universality. In the subject this liberation is hard toil as compared with the bare subjectivity of mere conduct, and with the immediacy of the desires and sub- jective vanity of feeling and the arbitrariness of inclination. That this liberation is hard work causes a good deal of the ill favor to which it is subject. But it is through this hard work of education, that the subjective will itself gains that objectivity in which alone, on its part, it becomes worthy and capable of being the actuality of the Idea. This form of universality to which particularity has developed and elevated itself, and that has effected that particularity, becomes true independent existence of indi- viduality ; and as it gives to universality its adequate content and its infinite self-determination, this particularity remains, even in ethicality, as infinite, independent, free subjectivity. This is the stage which exhibits education as an immanent phase of the absolute, and proves its infinite value. We may define the man of culture to be a person who can do everything that others do, without losing his individuality. Culture is the rubbing off of angular peculiarities, and enables one to appreciate univeral interests. The civic community contains three phases : (A) The mediation of the desire and satisfaction of the individual through his work and through the work and the satisfaction of the wants of all the other individuals, — the system of wants. (B) The actuality of the immanent universal freedom, the protection of property through the administration of justice. (C) The precaution exercised against the remnant of chance in this system, and the management of the particular THE CIVIC COMMUNITY 163 interests as of something possessed in common , through police and the corporations. A. The System of Wants § 189. In its first aspect ( zunächst ) particularity, being the determined, in general, as over against the universal element of the will, is subjective want. These wants gain their objec- tivity, i. e., satisfaction , through the means (a) of external things, which include the property and products of the wants and wills of others, and ( 'b ) through the means of activity and labor as the mediation of the two sides (the particular and universal element). Since the aim of activity is the satisfaction of particular subjective wants, and since, in relation to these same wants and to the free choice of others, the universal realizes itself, we have the appearance of rationality in this sphere of the finite in the form of the understanding. This is the phase on which the discussion here turns, and which constitutes, in this sphere, the recon- ciling element itself . . . This mutual interaction between individuals and society, in a realm of apparently unbridled individualism, is quite remarkable. It is like the apparently unregulated movement of the heavenly bodies whose law, however, can be discovered and understood. (a) The Nature of Wants and their Satisfaction. § 190. The animal has a limited range of ways and means of satisfying its likewise limited needs. But man shows even in this condition of dependency at once his transcendence over dependency, and his universality, first in the multipli- cation of wants and means, and then through the distinction and separation of the concrete want into different parts and 164 ETHICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). phases. Thus differentiated and particularized , they become abstract watits. In the sphere of legal right, it is the person; in that of morality, the subject ; in the family, the fmnily-number ; in the civic community in general, the citizen , the burgher (as bourgeois ), and here, at the stage of wants (comp. § 123, note), it is the general conception ( Vorstellung ) that is called man. It is consequently here, and strictly here only, that we speak of man , in this sense. Supplementary. — The animal is something particular, having its instinct and its limited means for satisfaction, which are not to be transcended. There are insects that are limited to a certain species of plants alone, and though there are other animals that have a wider sphere, and can live in different climates, they are still limited in comparison with the sphere of man. § 191. Likewise the means for the particularized needs, and, in general, the ways of satisfying them, differentiate and multi- ply themselves, and thus become relative ends and abstract needs. Hence we have here an infinite progression of multiplication which, in the same measure, consists in dis- tinguishing these determinations and in judging of the suitability of means to their ends ; in other words, it is refinement. The condition which Englishmen call “ comfortable ” is something inexhaustible, ever leading on to a more com- fortable one. § 192. Wants, and the means of satisfying them, become in their extraneous forms, at the same time, a set of relations to other people , through whose wants and work satisfaction is mutually conditioned. The abstraction (see preceding §), THE CIVIC COMMUNITY. 165 which becomes a quality of wants and means, becomes also a determination of the mutual relation of individuals to one another. When recognized, this universal element is the phase which gives these individual and abstract needs, means, and forms of satisfaction a concrete and social char- acter. § 194 . Since in social want, as the connection of immediate or natural and of spiritual wants of the general conception , the latter, as the universal, is the more important, the phase of liberation lies in this social phase in this manner : the stern necessity of nature belonging to the wants is lessened, and man comes in relation to his own, indeed, to a universal significance and to an only self-made necessity. Instead of coming in relation only to an external world, he has to do with an internal world of contingency and free choice. The opinion that when man lived in the so-called state of nature, in which he had only so-called simple, natural wants, and used only such means for their satisfaction as nature chanced to offer, he then, in reference to his needs, lived in freedom, is, without reference to the liberation that lies in work (of which later), a false view. Natural wants as such and their immediate satisfaction represent only a spirituality which is submerged in nature, and which is, therefore, rude- ness and thralldom under nature. Real freedom, however, consists only in the reflection of the spiritual upon itself, in its differentiation from the natural and in its reflex-spiritual determination of nature. § 195 . This liberation is formal , since the particularity of the ends remains the fundamental content. The tendency of the social state towards unlimited multiplication and special- ization of wants, means, and enjoyment, which, like the i66 E THICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). differentiation between natural and uncultured wants, has no limits, — in other words, luxury , is likewise an endless augmentation of dependence and distress. These must, in order to reduce it to the property of the free will, do battle with a matter that presents an endless opposition, that is, do battle with external means of different kinds, consequently they have to do with absolute hardship. Supplementary. — Diogenes with all his cynicism is strictly nothing but the product of the social life of Athens, and what determined him was the view against which the sages of Athens in general agitated. This view is hence not independent, but arose from the social conditions them- selves, and is, indeed, an unhealthy product of luxury itself. Wherever luxury is at its height, there also distress and profligacy are just as great, and cynicism results as the opposition to refinement. ( 'b ) The Nature of Labor. § 196 . The mediation that is to prepare and procure for the particularized wants the adequate and equally particularized means, is labor. Its purpose is to specialize the material immediately given by nature through the most manifold processes for this multitude of ends. It is this formative activity that gives to the means their value and appropriate- ness, so that, in consumption , man is related chiefly to human productions. It is human exertions that he consumes. Supplementary. — The immediate material which does not need to be prepared for use by human labor, is insignificant. One must earn the very air he breathes, since he must temper it to his comfort and safety. Water alone, perhaps, can be used in its natural state. The sweat of the human brow and the work of the human hand procures for man the means for satisfying his wants. THE CIVIC COMMUNITY 167 § 197. In the multiplicity of interesting characteristics and objects, theoretic culture develops for itself not only a mul- tiplicity of conceptions and intellectual acquirements, but also a mobility and rapidity of the mind in conceiving and in passing from one conception to another, and a power of grasping involved and universal relations. This is the culture of the understanding, along with which goes the development of speech. Practical education through labor consists in the want that causes it and the habit of being occupied with some employment, and, secondly, in the limitation of one' s activity so as to correspond partly to the nature of the material, but more especially to the will of others ; lastly, practical culture consists in that habit of external activity, and universally valid skill which is gained by this training. Supplementary. — The barbarian is indolent, and distin- guishes himself from educated man in brooding in an atmos- phere of stupidity. For practical education consists just in the habit, desire and need of productive employment. The unskilled workman produces always something else than he intended, because he is not master of his own activity. He is a skilled workman who brings forth his product as it should be, and who finds no discrepancy between his sub- jective activity and the end attained. § 198. The universal and objective element in labor is contained, however, in the abstraction which causes the differentiation of means and of wants, and thereby also differentiates pro- duction and gives rise to the division of labor. The work of the individual becomes simpler by this division and con- sequently his skill in his abstract work, as well as the amount of his production, greater. Hence this abstraction neces- 1 68 ETHICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). sarily brings to perfection at once the skill and the means of dependence and the mutual relation of men in the satis- faction of other wants. The abstraction of production makes the work ever more mechanical , thereby finally leading to its transference from man to the machine. (c) Wealth. § 199 . Because of this dependent and mutual character of work and of the satisfaction of wants, the subjective self-seeking transforms itself into a contribution to the satisfaction of every- body' s wants , that is, into the mediation of the particular through the universal as dialectic movement, so that while each one earns, produces and enjoys for himself, he thereby also produces and earns for the enjoyment of the rest. This necessity, which consists in the perfect interconnection, in dependence of all with all, has the form of what is called general permanent wealth (see § 170), which contains for each one the possibility of partaking in the common prop- erty, through his education and skill, in order to be assured of subsistence. On the other hand the individual’s earnings, mediated by his labor, sustains and increases the common possessions. § 200 . The possibility of individuals partaking in the common possessions depends, partly on an immediate foundation (capital), and partly on the skill of the individuals. This skill, in its turn, depends again on capital, and then on the chance circumstances of the case. Owing to these diverse circumstances the natural unequal bodily and spiritual ten- dencies and talents are unequally developed. This diversity presents itself in this sphere of particularity in all directions and at all stages, and has, with other elements of chance THE CIVIC COMMUNITY. 169 and arbitrariness, the unequal distribution of property and the difference between individuals in skill and attainments as a necessary consequence. The spirit’s objective right to particularity , which is con- tained in the Idea, not only does not abolish, in the civic community, the natural dissimilarity between men, but produces it in a spiritual form, and elevates it to a dissimi- larity of skill, of possessions, and even of intellectual and moral development. To oppose to this the demand of equality , is characteristic of the empty understanding, that mistakes this, its ought, and its abstract conception for the real and the rational. This sphere of the particular which the universal has adopted attains only relative identity with the universal. There still remains in it much of the natural and arbitrary particularity, the state of nature. Further, it is Reason as immanent in the system of human wants and activities that articulates this system into an organic whole of different members. § 201. The infinitely manifold means and their just as infinite self-limitation, in the activity of the mutual production and exchange, are unified through the permeating universal element, and again differentiated into masses with conmion characteristics ; the connected total evolves itself to particular systems of wants, of their means and trades, of the kind and manners of satisfaction for wants and of the theoretical and practical education (systems into which individuals naturally enter) ; in short, this organized totality is differ- entiated into classes of civil society. If the family be recognized as the primary basis of states, classes must be recognized as the second one. Through them, the individual seeks at least relatively broader aims than mere private interests. 170 ETHICALITY {SITTLICHKEIT). § 202 . Classes thus formed are distinguished as the substantial class (agriculturists), the reflective or formative class (arti- sans), and lastly, the universal class (the learned and office-holding class). § 203. The substantial class has its possessions in the natural products of the soil which it cultivates. It must have land suitable to be exclusive private property, and demands not only chance-gathering of usufruct (as the gathering of wild berries, breadfruit, etc.), but objectively formative labor. Against the connection of labor and its result with special fixed seasons, and the dependence of the crop on the variable natural processes, the aim of satisfying wants becomes provident care for the future. On account of these conditions, the manner of subsistence in this class is but little mediated by reflection and individual will. It retains, in general, the substantial disposition of an unmediated ethicality, depending on confidence (in nature) and on family relations. [Hegel continues here to show why the begin- ning of agriculture should be placed side by side with wed- lock as the first foundation of the state and its civilization. Both agriculture and wedlock are in the nature of li??iitation of the arbitrariness of the individual. Both tend to make the mode of life more stable,- more dependent on the uni- versal laws of the spirit than on the particularity and caprice of the individual. Hence, the mythologies of the ancients represent the introduction of agriculture as a divine deed, worthy of being commemorated in religious festivities and worship. To be sure, the factory methods of cultivating the soil, which, even in Hegel’s time began to be prominent, tend to obliterate the distinction between the agriculturist and the THE CIVIC COMMUNITY. 171 artisan ; but still, Hegel thinks, the patriarchal mode of life of the agriculturist is rather gaining than losing vitality. Here man lives in unmediated communion with nature. The yield of his acres comes to him as a direct gift, for which he gives thanks to God. He lives in the confident trust that this goodness of God will continue. What he gets • is enough for him ; he uses it freely, for more is coming. This is the old nobility disposition and view of life of this class.] In the production of this class, nature is the chief factor and man the secondary. In the second class (the forma- tive), the human intellect is the essential element and nature’s product only the material. § 204. (b) The industrial class has as its business the change of form of the products of nature, and depends, especially, for its subsistence, on its labor and on the use it makes of the reflective powers of the intellect, as well as essentially on the skill with which it can deal with the wants and work of others. For what it possesses and enjoys, it scarce need to thank any one but itself, its own activity. This activity may be divided as follows : work for individual needs in a concrete manner and at the request of individuals, the work of the artisan or manual laborers ; work in the more abstract form for the sum total of individual wants, but hence for a universal need, the work of the manufacturers ; and the work of exchange of the individualized means of want and satisfaction for one another through the common medium of exchange, 7noney, in which the abstract value of all goods exists as an actuality. This is the work of the commercial or trading class. The sense of freedom and of order is especially developed in this class, depending, as it does, so largely upon its own foresight and intelligence. 172 E TH I CA LIT Y (. SITTLICHKEIT ). § 205. (c) The common , or universal, class has as its business the universal , or common interests of the social state. Hence this class should be relieved from the direct work for the satisfaction of private wants, either by their own private fortune or by being compensated by the state, which demands their activity. Their private interests should be guaranteed to them while they work for the common weal. § 206. Thus the classes as particularity, having become objective, differentiate themselves, according to the concept, into these fundamental distinctions. On the other hand, however, the question as to which class any particular individual is to belong depends to some degree on his natural gifts, nativity, and other circumstances. Still, the final and essential deter- mination rests with the subjective opinion and particular choice of the individual. In this sphere, subjective opinion and free choice find their right use and honor, so that what here happens because of inner necessity is likewise mediated by free choice , and has hence, for the subjective consciousness, the form of a product of its own will. We find here the difference between the practical life of the Orient and the Occident, and between the ancient and modern world. In the former this division into classes arises objectively and necessarily, the principle of subjective individuality being thus deprived of its right. For the assignment of individuals was there left to the rulers (as in the Platonic Republic), or made a mere matter of birth, as in the Hindu castes. Thus, not being recognized in the organization of the state and so harmonized with it, the principle of subjective individuality, which is an essential factor of society, is rendered hostile and destructive of the social order, and either succeeds in destroying it, as in the THE CIVIC COMMUNITY. *73 Grecian States and the Roman Republic, or else, attaining power or some sort of religious authority, it results in internal corruption and complete degradation, as was the case, to a certain extent, among the Lacedemonians and is now (1820) being thoroughly illustrated among the Hindus. But when this principle is duly recognized in the organization and integrated with it, and thus maintained in its right, it becomes the very animating principle of civil society, of the thinking activity of men and of personal merit and honor. The recognition that what is necessary and rational in civil society is mediated and brought about through the liberty of individual choice, — this is what constitutes the ordinary idea ( Vorstellung) of freedom. § 207. The individual acquires actuality by entering into some determmate form of existence, the interest and labors of some one of these classes, whereby he limits himself exclusively to one of the particular spheres of wants. Hence the ethical disposition in this sphere is that of rectitude and class honor. The object is to make and maintain one’s self freely, as a member of one phase of the civil community, by one’s own industry and skill, and to provide for one’s self only through this mediation with the universal, as well as to be recognized herein by one’s self and others, as a vital member of society. Morality has its proper position in this sphere, where reflec- tion on one’s actions, the end of the particular want and welfare is the ruling conception, and where the accidental nature of their satisfaction elevates into a duty even a single and accidental act of assistance. Supplementary. — By the principle that man must be some- thing in particular we understand that he should belong to a definite class. It is this which makes this being something mean that he then is something substantial. A human being that does not belong to one of the classes is only a *74 E THICALIT Y (. SITTLICHKEIT ). private person and does not partake in the universal element. ' To be sure, the individual may esteem his private personality as the highest form of life, and believe that if he should enter a class (i. e., take up a trade or profession) he would thereby lower himself. This is founded on the false concep- tion that where anyone gains thiough his own exertion any definite class mode of existence he thereby limits and degrades himself. § 208 . The principle of this system of wants is a special form of knowing and willing independent universality or of freedom. But as this is still in its abstract form it is that of the right of property in itself. But this right exists here no longer only potentially as in “abstract right ”, but as a valid actual- ity, as the protection of property through the administration of justice. B. The Administration of Justice. § 209 - The relative element of the mutual dependence of wants and of work for these wants has, primarily, its refledion-into- itself in the infinite personality (abstract) justice [legal right]. But it is this sphere of the relative itself which, as education , gives to legal justice its existence and character of being universally acknowledged , known and willed, , and, when medi- ated through this knowing and willing, of having validity and objective actuality. It belongs to culture (to thought as the consciousness of the individual in the form of universality) that the ego be conceived as universal Person, in which all are identical. Man has so high a worth because he is man, not because he is Jew, Catholic, Protestant, German or Italian. This con- sciousness, to which thought gives validity, is of infinite THE CIVIC COMMUNITY. *75 importance, and is faulty only when it settles, as cosmopoli- tanism, into opposition to the concrete life of the state. § 210. Objective justice implies on the one hand that it be some- thing well known, on the other that it have such reality and power as to make it recognized as universally valid and authoritative. ( a ) Right in the Form of Law. § 211 . Just what is implicitly right is, at this stage, explicitly set forth in objective form, i. e. it is determined through thought for consciousness. As that which is right and valid it is set forth as something known , — it is the law. Right, or justice, becomes through this determination positive (legal) right . 1 Abstract of Remainder of §. [To posit anything as universal is to think it. Thought, in fact, according to Hegel, is always a universalization. Hence the great, yet boundless importance of expressed or written laws. For written and codified law is not merely an expression of what was found formerly in custom and opinion. In the very act of thinking out the life-giving con- cept of the law, the codifier brings out the universal element which before existed only implicitly in custom. Customary law has hence a lower value than written law. Its uni- versality is recognized only in a subjective and accidental 1 The German words Gesetz , “law,” and gesetzt “posited,” like dtois and TidrujLL in Greek, have of course the same root. Law is something posited (gesetzt), something set down as a universal principle and im- movable rule. Hegel, who is always fond of utilizing the derivation of words, feels therefore that the connection is here self-evident. This must be borne in mind in reading the above paragraph, as the English cannot preserve the etymological argument. — r p. M. M. 176 £ THICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). way, that is, as far as the chief, judge, jury or mob are able or willing to give its latent universality practical validity. Hence, the opinion that customary law is more vital than codified law, is a grave misconception. Certainly a law does not cease to be customary by being written down. England’s common law is an excellent example of the con- fused conceptions that rule the present administration of justice. Theoretically, it is an unwritten law, the “ mores majorum ” of the English nation ; but, practically, no law is more written than the common law. In fact there is no end to the writing of it. Every judge and court are supposed and expected to found their decisions on the recorded decisions of former judges and courts. But, according to the theory of the unwritten law, these predecessors did nothing but expressed the unwritten law, and this customary unwritten law exists just as authoritatively in the present court and judge as in any of their predecessors. A similar confusion arose in the later Roman administration of justice. To refuse to believe that a nation’s laws may be adequately codified is to offer the greatest possible insult to such a nation and to its legal profession.] The sun and planets have laws, to be sure, but they know them not : likewise the barbarian. It is only when civilized man is conscious of his laws, that the arbitrary and accidental elements of feeling and opinion, such as revenge and sym- pathy, are purified from his administration of justice. Con- flicts, “collisions,” and inconsistencies in laws cannot be avoided ; these also serve to make the judge to be some- thing higher than a machine. But to try to avoid conflicts of laws, by allowing a wider field for the arbitrary decisions of the judge, were a retrogressive step towards chance and particularity again. This is, in fact, a great fault of juris- prudence founded on custom. Digests of decisions, though certainly superior to the bare records of the courts, still THE CIVIC COMMUNITY. 1 77 contain so much adventitious and merely historical matter, as the English practice shows, that they are far from being satisfactory from a philosophical point of view. § 212 . In this identity of implicit (Ansichsein) and explicit ( Gesetzsein ), in civil conduct only that which is law is binding as right, or justice. Since the characteristic of being expli- citly set forth contains also the accidental element of the private choice and other arbitrary elements, it is quite pos- sible that that which is law may be quite different in content from that which is in itself right. In positive law, we have the source of the knowledge of the just in cases of litigation. Positive jurisprudence is largely a historical science resting upon authority. § 213. Since justice first arrives at definite existence in the form of statute law, it comes into application , as far as its content is concerned, in relation to the 7?iaterial furnished by the civic community, in its endlessly special and complicated relations and forms of property and contract. Further material is furnished by the ethical relations depending on disposition, love, and confidence, though, naturally, only in as far as they contain the element of abstract justice (§ 159 ). The moral element and moral commandments, which have to do with the will in its most intimate subjectivity and particularity, cannot be objects of positive legislation. Still further material is furnished by the rights and duties that come into existence in the administration of justice itself and from the organization of the state and the like. Supplementary. — As regards the higher relations of wed- lock, love, religion and the state, legislation can only take cognizance of their merely external sides. In this respect great difference is found in the legislation of various 178 ETHICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). peoples. ... In regard to the oath, however, where the matter is left to the conscience of the individual, the courts must insist upon strict honesty and truthfulness. § 214 . There is always one essential phase of the law and its administration that contains an accidental element. This depends on the necessity of the law’s being a universal decision, that must be applied to particular cases. To declare against this accidental element is to utter an abstrac- tion. The quantitative measure of a punishment, for ex- ample, can never be made adequate to any speculative concept. (Pure reason can never determine the measure of punishment.) Whatever the sentence may be, it is, on this side, always somewhat arbitrary. This contingent element is, however, itself necessary in this sphere and to reason against a code on the ground, that it is not perfect, is to misunderstand this phase in which no perfection is possible, and which hence must be taken as it is. (b) The Essential Characteristics {das Dasein) of the Law. § 215 . The obligation to obey the laws contains, from the side of the right of self-consciousness (§ 132 with note) the (moral) necessity of the laws being made universally known. Abstract of Remainder of §. [To hang the tables of the laws so high over people’s heads that no citizen can read them, as the tyrant Dionysius did, is an injustice and a crime. But what else does a government do that hides the law in numberless quartos, and in conflicting decisions of courts and opinions of jurists — yes, even in a foreign language ? On the other hand, THE CIVIC COMMUNITY. 179 Justinian and other codifiers, however imperfect in their work, should justly be praised as the greatest benefactors of their nations. The legal profession should indeed consider law their speciality, but not, as they often do, their monopoly. They do, however, often object to the layman’s knowing the law in the same spirit as the physicists objected to Goethe’s dissertation on color. He, a poet, invade the territory of the physicist ! But one need not be a shoemaker to know where the shoe pinches, nor a specialist to understand what belongs to the universal interests of mankind. For this is the foundation of liberty, the holiest and noblest in man.] Abstract of § 216. [Two characteristics are essential to the public code : first, simple universal principles ; and secondly, sufficiently explicit application of these principles to the infinite compli- cations to which human relations are subject. Hence it is not to be reckoned a fault that no code can be complete in the sense of having a ready-made application to every possible case. The only reasonable claim is that all the fundamental principles should be plainly expressed. One great source of legal confusion is, no doubt, the injustice upon which many historical institutions are founded. When later ages have tried to read into these institutions a rationality that they originally lacked, this misinterpretation in favor of justice necessarily complicates the system. The change of the Roman law from the narrow national prejudice of the republic to the lex gentium and lex naturae of the later prudentes, is an example. But the chief cause of the necessary incompleteness of a code, lies in the finite nature of the subject-matter to which these universal principles are to be applied. This must of necessity produce infinite progressions in the application. i8o ETHICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). To argue against a code on this ground, i. e., that it cannot be completed, is to fail to remember that Le plus grand ennemi du bien c'est le mieux. No art, no science, no undertaking would be worth while, according to such reasoning, for nothing can be complete in its application, not even geometry. The noblest, grandest, and most beautiful were then worthless, since there might be some- thing more noble, grand and beautiful not yet discovered. But a great tree may continually put forth more branches and still it is not a new tree ; and it would certainly be foolish never to plant a tree because it might get, after a while, additional branches.] § 217. As in the civic community implicit justice becomes law, so also my formerly individual unmediated and abstract right is transformed, by being recognized, into an element of the universal will and knowledge. Acquirement of property and all activity relative to it must therefore adopt that form which is characteristic of property, in its universal relations. Property depends solely on contract and on the legal formalities necessary to prove such contract. . . . Supplementary. — Hegel notes the necessity of the formal- ities connected with the holding of property in a community. In reply to those who would dispense with them, he says, that they are the essential element, making explicit and positively asserting the existence of property rights. All mere sub- jectivity has here to give place to this objective form or reality, and receive from it security and stability. § 218. Since property and personality have legal recognition and validity in the civic community, lazu-breaking is not only an offence against some subjective-infinite , but against a universal THE CIVIC COMMUNITY. 181 principle, whose existence has a sure and strong foundation in itself. We arrive here at the point of view that estimates the offence according to the dangerous tendencies it has for the community (society). Such tendencies certainly add to the magnitude of the crime ; but, on the other hand, a community whose government feels secure, overlooks the external bnportance of an offence, and practices greater clemency in its punishment. {c) The Court of Justice. § 219. When justice, in its legal form, gains actual existence it is self-dependent ( für sich ) ; that is, stands independent over against the particular will and opinion of justice, and has to make itself valid as being universal. This recognition and realization of justice in the particular cases, without the subjective feeling of particular interests, belongs to a public power, to the court of jjistice. As to the historical origin of courts of justice and of judges, it matters not whether they arose from patriarchal relations, from force or from free choice. § 220. The right against crime in the form of revenge (§ 102) is only an wiplicit right and has not the form of justice, i. e., is not just as to its mode of existence. In the place of the offended party (the individual), the offended universal (the community), which has its characteristic actuality in the court, enters, and undertakes the prosecution and punish- ment of crime. Hereby the penalty of crime ceases to be the merely subjective and accidental retaliation of revenge, and is transformed into the true reconciliation of justice with itself in punishment. This punishment is, from the objective side, the reconciliation, through the negation of the 182 E THI CALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). crime, of the self-restoring law , which thereby gives itself valid actuality. From the subjective side of the offender, it is the reconciliation of his own law, known by him and established for his protection , in whose execution on himself he consequently finds the satisfaction of justice, in fact, nothing but his own deed. § 221 . The member of the civil community has the right to appeal to the courts , as well as the duty to appear in court, and to accept his disputed right from the court only — (to allow the decision of the courts of justice to be supreme and final over his disputed rights). Supplementary. — Every individual must not only have the right to appeal to the courts, but must also know the laws, else this right would be of little use to him. But it is also the duty of the individual to appear in court. In feudal times, the powerful nobles often refused to appear, chal- lenged the court, and acted as if it had been an injustice of the courts to demand their appearance. But this is a condition that contradicts the true conception of a court of justice. In more modern times the prince must recognize the authority of the court over himself in private affairs, and in free states his cases are generally lost. § 222 . Before courts, justice must have the characteristic of being demonstrable. The legal procedure enables both parties to bring forward effectively their evidence and legal claims, and the judge to get fully acquainted with the case. These steps are themselves rights, and hence their manner of pro- cedure must be legally determined. Therefore procedure is an essential part of the science of law. THE CIVIC COMMUNITY. i8 3 § 224 . Just as the public proclamation of the laws is a right of the subjective consciousness, so also is the publicity of the administration of justice. It follows from the right of know- ing the laws, that the possibility of the actualizatio/i of the laws in particular cases, should be publicly known, both as to the course of external events and as to legal principles, since the history of a case is a universally valid history ; and, though the case, as far as its particular content is concerned, is of interest only to the parties in question, its universal content is concerned with a principle of justice, whose ' ‘ tion touches the interest of all. The ons of the members of the court among themsf the case before decision, are expressions of opinions and views that are still particular, and conse- quently not of public nature. Judicial activity, as the application of the law to par- ticular cases, has two sides : first, an ascertaining of the nature of the case in its immediate detail, as, for example, whether there was a contract or not ; whether a certain illegal act has been committed; who has committed it; and, in criminal cases, the ascertaining of the thoughts and volitions that led to the action, according to their substan- tial, culpable character (§ 119, note); secondly, the sub- sumption of the case under the law, whose purpose is to restitute justice. In criminal cases, the determination of the punishment falls under this head. These two classes of decisions, that constitute judicial activity, are two (essen- tially) different functions. § 225 . 184 £ TH IC A LI TV (. SITTLICHKEIT ). § 227 . The first side, the ascertaining the case in its immediate details and qualifications, contains by itself no judicial func- tion. It is a piece of information such as any educated person may have. Since the subjective element of the comprehension and intention of the agent (see Part II) is essential for the qualification (a true estimate) of an act, and since the evidence without this element is not concerned with objects of Reason and the abstract understanding, but only with details, circumstances, and objects of sense- perception and subjective certainty ; and since, hence, such evidence contains no absolutely objective determination, therefore, the ultimate factor in the decision is the subjective convictio?i and conscience (animi sententia), as in regard to the evidence, which depends on what others depose and affirm, the oath is the ultimate, though subjective test. Supplementary. — There is no reason to hold that only the judge (juristische Richter) should determine the facts in the case, for this belongs to common intelligence and not merely to legal learning. The decision as to what are the facts in the case depends on empirical circumstances, on witnesses of the act and the like, and then again on facts from which conclusions as to the act in question may be drawn, and that make it probable or improbable. Here certainty is sought, not a truth in the higher sense, for truth is something altogether eternal. This certainty is here the subjective conviction, conscience, and the question is, what form this certainty should take in the administration of justice. To demand confession of the culprit, as is common in German courts of justice, has this truth in it, that by so doing the subjective self-consciousness is satisfied, since the sentence which the judge pronounces should not differ in the consciousness of the convicted person, from the sentence of his own conscience, and since the judgment does not cease THE CIVIC COMMUNITY. 185 to contain an alien element to the transgressor until he has confessed his offence. Here is the difficulty however, that the transgressor may refuse to confess, and thereby the interests of justice be endangered. But, again, if the subjective conviction of the judge is to be supreme, there is once more a hardship, since man is no longer treated as a free agent. This mediation, however, takes place when it is demanded that the verdict of guilty or not guilty should come, as from the soul of the transgressor, through the verdict of a jury . 1 The Trial by Jury. § 228. * * * * * The right of self-consciousness, the moment of subjective freedom, may be considered as the substantial point of view in the question of the necessity of public trial and trial by jury. To this, the essential of what can be said on the score of utility in favor of these institutions, can be reduced. From other considerations and upon other grounds, it is quite possible to dispute and defend one way or another this or that advantage or disadvantage, but, like all reasons of forensic argumentation, these arguments are secondary and hence not decisive, or else they are taken from other, and perhaps higher, spheres of thought. That it were possible to administer justice well, perhaps better, with purely juristic courts (i. e., courts without juries) than with other institutions, does not here concern us ; for if this possibility increased to a probability, yes even to a necessity, the right of self-conscious- ness would ever retain its demands, and not find itself satisfied. 1 Hegel’s substitute of the verdict of a jury for the confession of the criminal is clear, if we remember that he is giving an exposition of the common consciousness which the criminal implicitly acknowledges. His twelve peers state their opinion of the relation of the criminal’s particular act in regard to the acknowledged common good. — p- m. m. 1 86 ETHIC ALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). When the knowledge of jurisprudence (owing to the character and scope of this science), the transactions of the courts (legal proceedings) and the possibility of legal prose- cution, become the property of an exclusive class (the legal profession); and when the very terminology is in a language that is unknown to those of whose rights it treats ; the members of the civic community being dependent on their onoi activity, their oum knowledge ami will, are held as aliens, and as minors, in relation to their right, a relation that is really a species of serfdom under the legal profession. And this, though their rights form not only the most personal and intimate, but the substantial and rational element of their knowledge and will. Even though they have the right to come bodily into court (in judicio stare ), this is a right of small value when they may not be present spiritually with their own intelligence, and the justice that they gain, remains for them an external fate. § 229. In the administration of justice the civic community brings itself back to the co7icept of the unity of the implicitly universal with subjective particularity, although the latter is found in individual cases and the former in the sense of abstract justice. This is effected by the Idea' s losing itself in the particularity and by its separation into an internal and an external moment. The realization of this unity in the extension of the whole sphere of particularity, at first as relative unification, constitutes the organization for police- protection, and in the more limited but more concrete totality, the 9)iu?iicipal corporate. Supplementary. — In the civic community the universal is only the necessary ; in the social relation of wants, right alone, as such, is the fixed. But this right, a limited sphere, has reference only to the protection of what I have : right as such is welfare, something external. But this welfare is, THE CIVIC COMMUNITY. 187 however, in the system of wants, an essential characteristic. Consequently the universal, which at first is only the right, must spread itself out over the whole field of particularity. Justice is something great in the civic community : good laws make the state flourish, and free (private) property is a fundamental condition for its splendor ; but since I am totally entwined in particularity, I have a right to demand that in this connected whole (the civic community) my particular welfare also, shall be furthered. My welfare, my particular interests, must be taken into consideration, and this is done by the police-organization and the municipal corporation. C. The Police and the Municipal Corporation. § 230. In the system of wants, the subsistence and welfare of each individual exists as a possibility whose actuality is conditioned by the individual’s choice and natural peculiarities, as well as by the objective system of wants : through the adminis- tration of justice the violation of property (property-right) and of personality is annulled (is guarded against). The right that is actual iti particularity contains, however, also the demand that the accidental infringements of the rights of this or that end shall be abolished , and that undisturbed safety of person and property shall be established in the form of the assurance of the subsistence and welfare of the individual — in other words, justice, or right, as actualized in the par- ticular, demands that the particular welfare (i. e ., the welfare of each individual) shall be treated as a right , and shall be actualized. § 256. The aim of the municipal corporation, being limited and finite, has its truth in the independent universal aid (the < i88 ETHICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). State) and its absolute actuality. The same, too, is true of the police functions. The sphere of the civic community is thereby merged into the State. City and country — the former the location of civic industry, that is, of the reflexion that individualizes itself and centres in itself ; the latter the location of the ethicality that rests on nature, the individuals that mediate their self-preservation in relation to other legal persons, and the family, constitute the two still ideal phases out of which, as their true ground , the State develops. This evolution of unmediated ethicality through the differentiations (. Entzweiung ) of the civic com- munity to the State, which proves itself their true ground, and only such an evolution, or derivation, is the scientific demonstration of the concept (. Begriff ) of the State. Because in this evolution the scientific concept of the State appears as the result , while it shows itself as the true ground. Hence that mediation and that appearance abolish and transform themselves into immediacy. In reality, therefore, the State is always rather the first , in which, later, the family develops into the civic community. It is the Idea of the State which separates itself into these two moments. In the develop- ment of the civic community, the ethical substance wins its' infinite form , which contains the following two phases : (i) The infinite differentiation down to the self-dependent ( für-sich-seyende ) existence-in-itself of self-consciousness ; and (2) the form of universality which is in education and culture, the form of thought in which the spirit becomes objective and actual unto itself in laws and institutions, that is, in its thought-out will as organic totality. THE STATE. 189 THIRD SECTION. The State. § 257 . The State is the actuality of the ethical Idea; it is the ethical spirit as the manifest { offenbare ) substantial will that is fully self-cognizant ( sich selbst deutliche'), and that thinks and knows itself and realizes {vollführt) what it knows and in as far as it knows. The State has its immediate existence in the ethical life {Sitte) and in the self-consciousness of the individual ; in his knowing and doing (in his knowledge and activity) it has its mediated existence, just as the individual has his substantial freedom in the State as in his own essence, seed and product of activity. The penates are the intimate, lower gods, the national spirit {Athene), the divine that k?iows and wills itself ; the devotion to family ties {pietät) is ethicality deporting itself in feeling : and political virtue is the willing of the conceived independent end (of the independent ideal end). § 258 . The State, as the actuality of the substantial will, (which actuality it has in the particular selfconsciousness raised to its universality) is the independently {an und für sW/i) rational. This substantial unity is absolute, stable end-for-itself {Selbstzweck) in which freedom gains its supreme right, just as conversely this final end {Endzweck) has the supreme right over against the individuals, whose supreme duty it is to be members of the State. Abstract of Remainder of §. As long as the interest of the individual as such is alone the final end of human federation, we have only the civic com- ETHICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). 190 munity, not the State. Those who confound these two concepts ascribe to the State no higher purpose than the protection of person and property. But the true State is objective spirit, and the individual is not himself, has not objectivity and truth, and cannot live an ethical life except as a member of the State. To live a universal life, that is, to live in organic communion with his neighbors, is the aim and purpose of the individual. Rationality in general is the union of the universal and particular, and here it is the union of objective and subjective freedom. But objective freedom is the freedom of the universal substantial will, and subjective freedom is that of the individual. Hence rationality, or concrete freedom, has the form of activity determined by ideal and hence universal laws. Here we have nothing to do with the historical origin of the State. Prove, if you please, that this or that State began with patriarchs or social contract, arose from fear or confidence, that the rulers claimed divine right, or ruled by pure force of custom ; and you have only shown the historical manner in which this or that State appeared, and not at all what the State is. Philosophy has to do with the inner thought-out concept of all this. Rousseau’s “social contract” theory has the merit of having, both as to form and content, made thought in the form of will , , the principle of the State. But as he knew of no will but the individual will, his universal rational Will became nothing but a sum of individual wills ; and con- sequently his State was founded on nothing better than arbitrary choice, inclination, and express, free agreement. For results, see the French revolution and what came after it. The objective will is the rational State, whether the individual recognizes it or not ; and subjective freedom is only half of the truth. But the State may be falsely founded not only on internal particularity, but also on mere external elements, such as THE STATE. 191 the vicissitude of wants, the need of protection, brute force, wealth, and the like. Now these are indeed elements in the . historic development of the State, but certainly not in its substance. To mistake such empirical particularities for the foundation of the State is to be a degree more superficial than Rousseau. Not only is the foundation not universal, but it is not even the particular as thought and will , but only as empirical particularities. So void of reason is this view, which overlooks the infinite and rational elements in the State, that it cannot, in its utter lack of thought, even be said to be inconsistent with itself. Supplementary to § 258. The State in and for itself, is the ethical totality, the actualization of freedom ; and actual freedom (freedom actually) is the absolute end of Reason. The State is the spirit that dwells in the world and realizes itself in the world through consciousness , while in nature the spirit actualizes itself only as its own other, as dormant spirit. Only when present as consciousness, knowing itself as existing objectivity, is this spirit the State. When reasoning about freedom one must not start from the individual self-consciousness, but only from the essential nature of self-consciousness, for whether one knows it or not, this essence still realizes itself as an independent power in which the single individuals are only moments : it is the course of God through the world that constitutes the State. Its ground is the power of Reason actualizing itself as will. When conceiving the State, one must not think of particular States, not of particular institutions, but one must much rather contemplate the Idea , God as actual on earth ( wirk - lieh), alone. Every State, though it may be declared wretched according to somebody’s principles, though this or that imperfection in it must be admitted — possesses always, if it belongs to the developed States of our times, the essen- 192 E THICALITY (SITTLICHKEIT) . tial elements of its true existence. But since it is easier to discover faults than to understand positive characteristics, it is easy to fall into the error of overlooking the internal organism of the State itself in dwelling upon extrinsic phases of it. The State is no work of art, it exists in the world, and hence in the sphere of choice, accidence, and error. Hence the evil behavior of its members can disfigure it in many ways. But the most deformed ( hässlichste ) human being, the criminal, the invalid, and the cripple are still always living human beings : the affirmative, life, remains in spite of all defects, and here we have to do with this affirm- ative alone. § 259 . The Idea of the State has (a) immediate actuality, and is the individual state as a self-related ( sich auf sich beziehender) organism, i. e., the constitution , or internal national organiza- tion (inneres Staatsrecht ) ; ( b ) the Idea passes over into the relations of the single State to other States : the inter- national rights; and (c ) it is the universal Idea as gejius and absolute power in relation to single states ; it is the spirit, which gives itself its actuality in the process of the world's history. Supplementary. — The State, as actual, is essentially an individual state, and, still more, a particular state. Individ- uality must be distinguished from particularity. The former is a moment of the Idea of the State itself, while particularity belongs to history. The States, as such, are independent of one another, and, consequently, the relation between them can be only external. Hence the need of another synthetic power to unite them. This third is the Spirit (of humanity) which gives itself actuality in the world’s history, and which is the absolute judge over single States. Several States may, as a federation, form a supremacy over others, and confederations, like, for example, the Holy Alliance, may THE STATE. 1 93 be formed, but these are always only relative and limited, like “the eternal peace.” The only absolute judge who ever makes himself valid against the particular is the independent spirit who presents himself as the universal and as the active genus in the history of the world. (The spirit of humanity is the spirit of God as actual on earth.) A. Internal Polity or National Organization. § 260 . The State is the actuality of concrete freedom. In con- crete freedom all personal individuality and its particular interests find their complete development and the recogni- tion of their independent rights (as we have seen them in the sphere of the family and of the civil community) in this larger unity. This occurs, partly through these individual interests being transformed into universal interests, and, partly through individuals recognizing in thought and deed this universal as being their own substantial spirit, and energizing for it as for their own final end. Thus, neither is the universal valid or realized without the particular interests, intelligence, and will of individuals, nor do individuals live only for the latter as private persons, but have also an independent will for the universal and an activity conscious of this end. The principle of the modern State has this enormous strength and depth, that while it allows the principle of subjectivity to evolve itself into the independent extreme of personal particularity, it, at the same time, brings all this back to substantial unity, and thus gains the subjective extreme in the substantial unity. Supplementary. — The Idea of the State in modern times has the peculiarity that it constitutes the realization of freedom not according to subjective inclination, but accord- ing to the concept of the will, that is, according to the universal and divine element of freedom. Those are i94 E TII IC A LITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). imperfect States in which the Idea of the State is not yet out of the husks, so to- speak, in which its particular deter- minations have not yet come to free independence. In the States of classical antiquity, the universal element was already present, but the particularity was not yet liberated and brought back to universality, i. e., to the common end of the whole. The essence of the modern State lies in this, that the universal is allied to the full liberty of particularity and to the well-being of the individuals. Consequently, the interests of the family and the civic community combine themselves in the State. But they do so in such a way that the universality of the end cannot advance without the individual’s own knowledge and will, which must retain their right. The universal must consequently manifest itself in action, but subjectivity must also be fully and vitally developed (be developed in all its fulness and life). Only when the two elements are preserved in their full force, can the State be considered fully articulated and truly organized. § 261. In reference to the spheres of private rights and private welfare, the spheres of the family and the civic commu- nity, the State is, on the one hand, an external necessity. It appears as their own higher power, to whose nature their laws, as well as their interests, are subordinated and dependent. But on the other hand, the State is the immart&nt end of these lower spheres and has its strength in the unity of its universal final aim, and the particular interests of the individuals, because they have duties toward the State in just so far as they have rights in reference to it (§ 155). Montesquieu, especially, as we have before remarked, has grasped and attempted to develop in detail in his renowned work, The Spirit of the Law , the thought of the THE STATE. J 95 dependence of laws (especially those relating to private rights) on the definite character of the State. In other words, he holds the philosophical view that considers the part only in its relation to the whole. Duty, primarily, is conduct towards something inde- pendent, universal, and substantial for me, and on the other hand, rights are the determinate existence of this substantial element, and hence the side of its particularity and of my particular freedom. Hence duty and right appear, at the formal stage, as divided among different phases and persons. The State, as the ethical sphere, as the interpenetration of the substantial and the particular, contains the principle that my obligation to the substantial is likewise the characteristic form of existence ( Dasein ) of my particular freedom, that is to say, in the State duty and right are united in one and the same rclatio)i. But further, in the State the different moments (duty and right) arrive at their characteristic form and reality, and thus the distinction between duty and right reappears. Hence they are (just because they are implicitly, (an sich), i. e., formally, identical) distinct as to their content. In the moral sphere and in that of private right, the actual necessity of the relation is not present, and hence there is only an abstract similarity of content ; that which, in this abstract sphere, is a right to one ought also to be the right to another, and what is one’s duty should also be other’s duty. Such absolute identity of rights and duties exists only as similar identity of content in the determination that this content is itself the wholly universal principle, that is, the One Principle of duty and right, the personal liberty of man. Slaves have, therefore, no duties because they have no rights, and, conversely, no rights because no duties. (We do not here speak of religious duties.) But in the concrete Idea developing itself in itself, these its moments differentiate themselves, and in their full determination they I9 6 E THICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). have also a different content. In the family, the son has not rights with the same content as he has duties in relation to the father, nor has the citizen rights with the same content as duties in relation to prince and government. This concept of the union of duty and right is one of the most important characteristics of States, and constitutes their inner strength. The abstract side of duty comes no further than to ignore and condemn the particular as an unessential and, in itself, unworthy element. But the concrete conception, the Idea , shows that the element of particularity is just as essential, and hence its satisfaction absolutely necessary. The indi- vidual must in one way or another, in his performance of duty, find his own interests and his own satisfaction or recompense ; some right must grow out of his relation to the State, by reason of which the universal interest becomes his particular interest. Particular interests are surely not to be put aside or simply suppressed, but should be harmonized with the universal interest. The individual, being a subject 1 in relation to his duties, finds in their performance, as a citizen, protection of his person and property, care for his own particular welfare, and the satisfaction of his substantial essence, the personal consciousness of being a member of this totality. Such fulfilment by citizens of duties, as labors and business for the State, constitutes the preservation and permanence of the State. But according to the abstract view, the universal interest would only be that its work and business should be performed as duties. Abstract of Supplementary §■ Everything depends on the true union of universality and particularity in the State. In the ancient States the will of the State was absolute, without reference to the subjective interests of individuals. The modern State honors the 1 Subject in the political sense ( Unterthan not Subjekt). THE STATE. 1 97 individual. Every duty to the State is also a right of the individual. The State is simply the organization of the con- cept of freedom. It is the universal condition necessary for the realization of particular end and individual welfare. § 262. The actual Idea , the Spirit, divides itself into the two ideal spheres of its concept (the family and the civic com- munity). This is the sphere of its finitude. Here, in order to return from this explicit ideality of phases as infinite actual spirit, it assigns these spheres the material for this its finite actuality. This finite actuality is given to indi- viduals as a multitude , so that this , allotment to particular individuals appears to be mediated through circumstances, chance, and free choice (§ 185 and note). Abstract of § 263, § 264 and § 265. In place of an abstract of some of these paragraphs, I borrow the following expository paraphrase from Dr. Morris’ volume. 1 “ The State, we have said, is the actualization of concrete freedom. And this is the same as to say that the State is, in its measure, the actualization of the Idea of Man ; that it is not simply a contingent means of human perfection, but is also this perfection itself ; that, in brief, the State is Man, standing relatively 2 complete in that fulness and wholeness 1 Hegel’s Philosophy of History, by Geo. S. Morris, Ph.D. pp. 84-S6. Griggs & Co. Chicago, 1887. 2 “ Relatively,” I say, in order to prevent a possible misconception. Relatively, though with an inferior degree of truth, the same may be said of the Family which, in the text, is asserted of the State. But, as we shall see later, the State itself is organic to a larger life and actuality of the human spirit, or of the “ idea of man,” in universal history; while universal history, again, is organic to the perfect consummation of humanity through the discovery of the true will of man in the will of God, the adoption of the latter as the inviolable norm of human action, and the consequent establishment of man in his spiritual perfection and completeness as a co-worker with and child of God. E THICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). 198 of developed being which the idea of man as a rational being implies. And it is this by virtue of a process which, just because it is rather organic than merely mechanical, has the form of a process of self-realization. To illustrate : The actual tree is such only by virtue of a process of growth. In this process the tree becomes nothing other than itself, — it realizes itself. It does this, further, by separating itself into its natural parts or members, — roots and branches. To each it allows a separate or distinct existence, and yet holds them all together in the unity of one organic and living whole. We may say that the tree disperses or distributes itself among its members, and this as the very condition, on the ful- filment of which, the manifestation of its universal life and power, and the actualization of its organic unity (or the actualization of the “idea of the tree”) irrevocably depend. Moreover, the tree is not an after-result of the existence of the roots and branches : when they begin to exist, its existence also begins. So it is with the State. The roots of the State are families, and its branches are the institutions of civil society. Its material is individuals. These take their places under the mentioned institutions, directed by circumstances, by caprice, or by personal choice. The element of “subjective freedom” has here its play. But these institutions themselves have obviously a universal or general character ; and the individual in recognizing them, and in maintaining himself in his own chosen place under them, recognizes and devotes himself to the service of a universal with which, by his own deliberate choice, he has identified himself. But the universality of these institutions has its ground in, and is the manifestation and reflection of, that ethical “universal” which we term the invisible State or nation, or, more explicitly, the spirit of the nation, — the universal spirit of man, as it takes form and declares itself THE STATE. 199 in the particular life of the nation. Thus regarded, they make up the constitution of the nation ; they are the reason of the nation, developed and actualized in particular forms. They are, therefore, the ‘ steadfast basis of the State ; they immediately determine the temper of the individual citizens toward the State, and especially their confidence in it ; and they are the pillars of the public freedom, since in them particular (individual) freedom is realized in a rational form; and they thus involve an intrinsic union of freedom and necessity,’ or are, as it were, the living and visible body of an interior, organic, and steadfast liberty. “ But institutions by themselves are impersonal and uncon- scious. Their existence, as the above comparison of them to the branches of a tree implies, is assimilated in kind to that of a natural organism. The law of freedom, as exempli- fied in than alone , is like a natural law, inflexible, unreflecting, without shadow of turning. In particular, they contain in themselves, as thus viewed and existing, no germ of develop- ment. They are the phenomena and product of a public spirit, which they accordingly implicitly presuppose, and which must distinctly declare and develop itself in the form of clear, self-knowing intelligence and will, in order that the form of necessity under which institutional freedom existed may itself be changed to freedom. This spirit we must consider and speak of as the true substance of the State.” Supplementary to § 265. It has already been noted that the sacredness of the oath, and the institutions in which the civic community appears as ethical, constitute the stability of the whole (the State). Through these institutions the universal becomes the concern of each and every citizen. It all depends on this, that the law of reason and the particular freedom of individuals penetrate each other, so that my particular end becomes identical with the universal; else the State is a 200 E TH IC ALI TY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). castle built in the air (else there is absolutely no rational foundation for the State). The feeling of self-possession ( Selbstgefühl ') of the individual constitutes its actuality, and its stability consists in the identity of these two sides of its being (universality and particularity). It has often been said that the end of the State is the happiness of the citizens, and this is, indeed, true. If it goes ill with the citizens, if their subjective ends are not satisfied, if they do not find that the State, as such, is the mediation of this satisfaction, the State stands on a very weak foundation. § 266. But the spirit is not only actual and objective unto itself as this necessity and as a realm of appearance, but also as the inner essence and ideality of such appearance. Thus this substantial universality is object and end unto itself, and this necessity exists hereby just as much in the form of liberty. § 267. The necessity in the ideality of these elements is the evolution of the Idea within itself. It is, as subjective sub- stantiality, the political disposition: and as objective , in distinction from the o?-ganism of the State, it is the political State proper and its constitution. Supplementary. — The unity of the freedom that knows and wills itself, exists primarily as necessity. The sub- stantial is, at this stage, the subjective existence of the indi- viduals ; the other phase of the necessity is the organism; that is to say, the spirit is a 'process in itself, articulates itself in itself, posits distinctions in itself, through which it circulates. § 268. This political disposition is termed patriotism in general, as certainty resting in truth (mere subjective certainty THE STATE. 201 does not proceed from truth and is nothing but opinion); and the will that has become custom is simply the result of the institutions existing in the State, as of those in which rationality is actually present. So, too, patriotism is manifested by activity in harmony with these institutions. — This disposition is, in general, confidence in the State, which may attain to more or less cultured insight. It is the consciousness that my substantial and particular interest is preserved and contained in the interest and aim of an other (here the State) in its relation to me as an individual. Hereby the State immediately is no longer an other , a stranger to me ; and the ego is free in this consciousness. Abstract of Rest of §. We ought not to understand by patriotism only extraor- dinary actions and sacrifices. It is essentially that dispo- sition which is accustomed to recognize the communal life, in the ordinary circumstances and relations of life, as the substantial foundation and final purpose of all activity. But as men find it easier to be magnanimous than just, so they also easily convince themselves that they possess that heroic patriotism, in order to save themselves the trouble of having this everyday patriotism. It is very much easier to criticise an institution than to understand the truth and necessity at its bottom. In questions of religion it is easy to say that this or that is superstition, but infinitely harder to understand the truth of it. We forget, for our particular interests, that on which our whole existence depends. Few of us are conscious of the fact when safely passing down a street at night, that this safety is the result of an institution ; and if we are, we are likely to ascribe it to the mere force of the State, when, in reality, the State coheres because of the funda- mental sense of order which the great majority have. 202 ETHICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). § 269 . -V. .U. .U. -M. •7T Tv "vr "7v Tv Supplementary. — The State is an organism, that is, it is the evolution of the Idea into all its differentiations or different forms or organs of itself. These differentiated sides are thus the different powers of the State and its affairs and activity, through which the universal continues to bring forth itself and maintain itself in a necessary manner, in conformity with the Idea (of the State). This organism is the political constitution ; 1 it proceeds eternally from the State, as also the State maintains itself through the constitution. If the two fall outside of each other ; if the two sides become free from each other, there is no longer that unity posited which the constitution as an organism produces. Here the fable of the stomach and the other organs finds its application. For it is the nature of an organism that, if its parts do not all merge into unison of activity ; if one posits itself as independent, all go to destruction. In considering the State, one gets nowhere with predicates, principles, and the like, since the State must be comprehended as an organism. To attempt any other course, is just as idle as to try, by the aid of predicates, to comprehend the nature of God, whose life I must, much rather, behold (anschauen) in its very self. § 270 . That the purpose and end of the State is the universal interest as such, and the satisfaction therein of the particular interests as to their substance, is (i) the State’s abstract actuality , or substantiality ; but this is (2) the State’s necessity when the actuality of the State divides itself in the 1 By constitution ( Verfassung ), Hegel does not refer only to the constitution on paper, but to the principle on which and by which the State is constituted. THE STATE. 203 conceptual distinctions (concept-distinctions) of its activity. These distinctions become, through this substantiality, really actual and stable determinations, or powers ; (3) but this substantiality itself is the self-conscious and self-willing spirit, as having passed through the forni of culture and educa- tion. Hence the State knows what it wills, and knows it in its universality as something thought. Therefore the State acts according to conscious ends, known principles, and according to laws that exist not only in themselves (implicitly), but also for consciousness ; and, also, in as far as its actions have reference to present circumstances and conditions, they are determined by the exact acquaint- ance with such relations. It is not too much to say that Hegel always and every- where shows his deep and vital interest in religion, as one of the absolute forms of truth. He is perpetually recurring to it and giving extended expositions of its character, function and place in the system of absolute truth. We are not surprised, therefore, at finding here a long digression on the relation of the State to Religion. In place of this long translation, however, we deem it of more value to give Dr. Morris’ 1 very free exposition of Hegel’s general view on the subject : “ Is religion the foundation of the State ? Undoubtedly it is, and the whole of his Philosophy of the State and of History is a progressive demonstration of this truth, and of the sense in which it must be understood. The State, history, and indeed all natural existence, are the gradual actualization or manifestation of an Absolute Reason, which can and must exist in its eternal fulness only as Absolute Spirit, or God. In the ethical world, in particular, we are in process of seeing how each lower grade presup- poses, as its substantial foundation, proximately the next higher one and then absolutely all higher ones. So the 1 pp. 88 and 89 of volume previously cited. 204 E TH I CA LI TV (. SITTLICHKEIT ). Family presupposes or calls for Civil Society, while the State is similarly presupposed by both. The particular State, again, the nation, with its definite national spirit, is organic to, and hence presupposes, a still larger life of the human spirit, — a life which at once takes up into itself and also transcends the limits of separate national exist- ences, and of which universal history is both the expression and the demonstration. But man, conceived and known as the spirit immanent in universal history, as universal humanity, or Weltgeist , is found to be unable to stand alone. He is relative to something else, which he presupposes as his ‘substantial foundation’; he is not absolute. The whole historic life of humanity is organic to, and dependent on, the life and operation of the absolute and eternal Spirit, of whose thought and will it closes the demonstration, begun at the lowest grade of finite existence. When the natural and ethical worlds are comprehended as the progressive incarnation of reason in ‘reality,’ God, who is the ‘absolute truth,’ is seen to be the eternal presupposition and the omnipresent and actual condition of all existence whatever, but most conspicuously of the existence of the ‘ethical world.’ If all things whatsoever are, in their degree, the revelation and incarnation of that supreme reason in which absolute and eternal Being — God, Absolute Spirit — consists, and if it is thus true of all things that they are a present and actual revelation of divine will and spiritual being, much more obviously is this true of an ethical organism, an historic power, like the State. So Hegel declares that ‘ the State is divine will, in the form of a present (national) spirit, unfolding itself in the actual shape and organization of an (ethical) world.’ The whole normal process of history, to which all the life of man, in Family, Civil Society, and State is organic, consists in the progressive realization of concrete human freedom, — THE STATE. 205 that is, of the essential spiritual nature of man, through the consc'ous recognition of God as the ‘foundation’ of all the true life of the human spirit, and of the divine will as the true substance or content of the human will. In the whole process of history, or of the ‘ethical world,’ humanity is progressively learning, and showing that it is learning, that its true language is, ‘ Lo ! I am come to do thy will, O God ! ’ And so the foundation of the State is indeed, and in the most radical and comprehensive sense, religion, which, says Hegel, has ideally ‘the absolute truth for its content.’ Upon this general truth, both in its generality and in its specific applications, our author finds occasion, as we shall see, to insist at almost every step in the develop- ment of the philosophy of history, — the spiritual story of humanity. But when religion is otherwise regarded ; when it is identified with immediate feeling, or with an intuition which claims exemption from the arduous labor of philosophic comprehension ; when, accordingly, it degenerates into fanaticism and narrow dogmatism, restricting the presence of God in history within the limits of a select religious organization, and treating the State as at the best only a soulless and godless mechanism, — then the claim that religion is the foundation of the State must be rejected, or rather corrected. Then, especially, must the spiritual character of the State and its inherent divine right be emphasized.” § 272 -§ 341 . It is not necessary, for the purpose of the present volume, to give even a rhumb of Hegel’s exposition of the political state, as the organized and publicly-expressed will of its people. Its articulate form follows from the distinction of the universal, the particular, and the individual, and their combination in a concrete and living activity. He declares 2o6 ETHICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). that, as to form, that of a constitutional monarchy is the peculiar achievement of the modern world, emphasizing the constitutional and representative elements as well as the monarchical one. We have essentially the same articu- lation of the three elements in our monarchical democracy, and England the same in her democratic monarchy. He was specially favorable to the English form, in reference to which he uttered his well-known saying that the king was “ but a dot upon the The King or the President may equally be the mouth-piece of the personality of the State, the crown, — or the necessary dot over the — of the whole moral organism of the State. What he says about laws, as the express forms of the content of substantial freedom ; of the constitution as the express will of the people ; of the function and moral temper of the officers in the whole department of civil (public) service ; of suffrage being restricted to representatives of definite interests organized under the commonwealth; of freedom and equality ; of the double form and worth of public opinion, and of war as an ethical factor, is admirable. So, too, what he says as to ( b ) international policy is admirable. He recognized that any one national spirit is a limited one, that no one State can be the “ terrestrial god,” or realize the full nature of man as a political animal. Hence he turns to (c) universal history to find the law of the development of man as man. Here he gives his inter- pretation of the autobiography of humanity, whose indi- viduals are nations, progressively and consciously realizing the idea of freedom, and entering upon their rightful heritage. It is thus throughout an ethical consideration of universal history, an ethical estimation of the course of man’s thoughts and deeds, under Divine guidance, to the largest and most rational form of self-realization. THE STATE. 207 C. Universal History. § 341. Universal spirit has the element of determinate being in several forms : — in art, that of sensuous form and symbol, in religion, that of sentiment and pictorial conceptions, in philosophy, that of pure, free thought ; while in universal history it is that of the spiritual actuality of humanity in the whole circle of its internal and external activity. The history of the world is the judgment of the world, because it contains, in its self-dependent universality, all special forms — the family, civil society, and nation, reduced to ideality, i. e. to subordinate but organic members of itself. It is the task of the spirit to produce all these special forms. § 342. Further, universal history is not the mere judgment of its own power, i. e ., it is not the abstract and irrational necessity of blind fate. But inasmuch as it is inherently rational and self-conscious, it is rather the evolution of the phases of reason and, consequently, of its self-consciousness and freedom ; it is the actualization and interpretation of universal spirit. § 343. The true history of the spirit is its own deed, for spirit is real only so far as it is activity. And the true deed of spirit is to make itself its own object, to comprehend itself in its own self-exposition. Such comprehension is its vital prin- cipal, and the fulfilment of this comprehension is at the same time its own alienation ( Entäusserung ) and transition. And spirit returning back into itself out of this alienation is the spirit of the higher stage in relation to itself as it existed in its first comprehension. 2o8 £ THICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). Here arises the question concerning the education and perfectibility of the human race. Those who maintain the perfectibility of humanity have intuitively anticipated some- thing of the nature of spirit — of its nature to have Tvwdi crsavrov as the law of its being and to thus reach a higher stage than that of mere existence. But, for those who deny this view, spirit has been a mere name, and history a merely superficial play of accidental human passions and struggles. Though they professedly hold to faith in a supreme power and plan of providence, these terms remain dead con- ceptions, for they expressly say that the plan of Providence forever remains inconceivable and unknowable. § 344 . In this labor of the world-spirit, nations and individuals appear in all their special forms, which have their actuality and exposition in their whole circle of existence. They are conscious of these latter and profoundly interested in them, and yet they are, at the same time, the unconscious tools and organic phases of that inner labor of the world-spirit. They arise and they also vanish in this task of the world- spirit, which thereby prepares and works out its transition into the next higher stage. § 345 . Justice and virtue, violence and vice, talents and their deeds, small and great passions, guilt and innocence, the glory of individuals and nations, independence, the fortunes and misfortunes of empires and individuals have their definite significance and worth in this sphere of conscious actuality and find therein their judgment and their still imperfect justice. But the history of the world lies beyond all such points of view. In it, that necessary phase of the Idea of the world-spirit, which is at any time existent, receives its absolute right: people, with all their deeds, who THE STATE. 209 live in this phase, receive their completion, their fortune and renown. § 346 . History is the formation of spirit into deed, into the form of immediate natural actuality. Hence the phases of the development are present as immediate natural principles. And because of their being merely natural, they are various and disconnected. Hence each people has its own peculiar natural principle — its geographical and anthropological character. § 347 . The world-spirit, in its onward march, hands over to each people the task of working out its own peculiar vocation. Thus in universal history each nation in turn, is for that epoch (and it can make such an epoch only once), dominant. Against this absolute right to be the bearer of the present stage of the development of the world-spirit, the spirits of the other nations are absolutely without right, and they, as well as those whose epochs are passed, count no longer in universal history. The special history of any world- historical nation contains, partly the development of its genius from its infantile state to its bloom, when it attains to free ethical self-consciousness and holds the wheel of the world’s destiny ; partly, it also contains the period of its downfall and destruction. For thus the rise of a higher principle appears as only the abrogation and the fulfilment of its own earlier form. . . . § 348 . At the head of all great historical events we find individuals who accomplish the essential destiny of a people or an epoch. As tools of the world-spirit, they do the deed without conscious design of its full significance 210 ETHICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). and consequences. Their contemporaries and even pos- terity may decline to bestow due honor upon them for the deed. But the true view of their mission, gives them their part in immortal renown. § 349 . A people is not directly a State. The transition of a clan, horde, tribe or multitude into the make-up of a state constitutes the formal realization of the Idea as such in it. A people is potentially ethical substance, but unless it is formed into State it lacks the determinate being which fixed laws can give it, both for itself and others, and, hence, can have no recognition and can assert no sovereignty. § 350 . It is the absolute right of the Idea to appear in laws and objective institutions, springing from wedlock and agriculture, whether the form of this realization appears as divine legislation and grace, or as violence and wrong. Such right is the right of heroes to found states. § 351 . Hence it also happens that civilized nations consider and treat such nations as represent a lower stage, as barbarians, esteeming their rights as inferior and their independence as merely nominal. Their wars are of significance in the world-history, only as representing the element of the struggle for recognition. § 352 . The genii of peoples as concrete Ideas , have their truth and character in the Absolute Idea. They stand around the throne of the world-spirit as the executors of its realization, and as witnesses and ornaments of its glory. As world- THE STATE. 2 I I spirit it is only its own deed of coming to itself — to conscious knowledge of its own being and mission of freedom. There are four marked principles of the forma- tion of this self-consciousness in the course of its freedom, i. e., the four world-historical empires. These are : (i) The Oriental, (2) the Greek, (3) the Roman and (4) the Germanic Empires. § 353 . In the first of these it (the world-spirit) has the form of substa?itial spirit, in which all individuality remains suppressed and without the right of existence. The second principle is the ktiowledge of this substantial spirit. It is the positive content and fulfilment and inde- pendency as the vital form of the world-spirit, which is beautiful ethical individuality. The third is the self-involution of this knowledge and independence to abstract universality. It thus renders all objectivity spiritless and comes into infinite opposition to it. The principle of the fourth form is that of the change of this opposition of Spirit, so as to receive inwardly its own truth and concrete nature, and to be reconciled with objectivity, and thus to be at home with itself in the sphere of the secular. This change also involves its creating and knowing its truth as thought and as the real definite world. It involves this, because it is spirit which has overcome its opposition to secular objectivity and returned, ladened with all the spoils of victory, to universal Spirit. This division gives the skeleton outlines, which Hegel’s Philosophy of History clothes with all the vitality of the spirit of God, as the spirit of humanity. This work is already so well known in translation 1 as to render un- 1 Lectures on the Philosophy of History, by G. W. F. Hegel, translated by J. Sibree, M.A. Bohn’s Philosophical Library, 1861. 2 12 ETHIC ALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). necessary more than commendatory reference to it. We, however, select a few paragraphs as the fitting close of this volume on Hegel’s Ethics : — “The History of the world is the progress of man in the consciousness of freedom. ... It is the discipline of the uncontrolled natural will, bringing it into obedience to a universal principle and conferring subjective freedom. . . . The Orientals knew that one is free, who was only a despot not a free man. The Greeks and Romans knew that some are free, — not man as such. The Germanic nations, under the influence of Christianity, were the first to attain the consciousness that man, as man, is free — that it is the freedom of spirit which constitutes his essence. . . . But to introduce this principle into the various relations of the actual world, involves, besides its simple implantation, a severe and lengthened process of education .” 1 “The spirit of God lives in the Church, but it is in the world, as a yet inharmonious material, that spirit is to be realized. The world, or secular business, cannot be repudiated, and ultimately the discovery is made that spirit finds the goal of its struggle and its harmonization in that very sphere which it made the object of its resistance — it finds that secular pursuits are a spiritual occupation.” 2 “This fourth phase of World-History answers to the old age of man’s life. The old age of nature , however, is weakness ; but the old age of spirit is its perfect maturity and strength, in which it returns to unity with itself, but in its fully developed character as spirit. This fourth phase begins with the Reconciliation presented in Christianity — but only in the germ, without national or political develop- ment.” 3 After portraying the terrible but wholesome discipline of the middle ages, under the two iron rods of ecclesiastical power and serfdom, he says : — 1 pp. 19 and 1 10. p. 368. P- THE STATE. 2i 3 “ Humanity has now attained the consciousness of a real internal harmonization of spirit and a good conscience in regard to actuality — to secular life. The human spirit has come to stand on its own basis. In the self-consciousness to which man has thus advanced, there is no revolt against the Divine, but a manifestation of that better subjectivity which recognizes the Divine in its own being ; which is imbued with the Good and the True, and which directs its activities to the general and liberal objects bearing the stamp of rationality and beauty.” 1 In speaking of the Reformation, he says : “ This is the essence of the Reformation : man, in his very nature, is destined to be free.” 2 In showing how the modern spirit has taken up and made its own “the absolute inwardness of soul,” and yet demands the surrendering of one’s mere private subjectivity to substantial truth, required by Christianity, he says : — “In the proclamation of these principles is unfurled the new and final standard round which the nations rally — the banner of Free Spirit , independent, while finding its life in the truth and enjoying its independence only in the truth. This is the banner which we bear and under which we serve. Time has no other work to do than the formal imbuing of the world with this principle, in bringing the Reconciliation implicit in Christianity into objective and explicit realization. . . . This is the sense in which we must understand the State to be based on Religion. States and Laws are nothing else than Religion manifesting itself in the actual relations of the secular world.” 3 “ Secular life is the positive and definite embodiment of the Spiritual Kingdom — the Kingdom of Will manifesting itself in outward existence. . . . That which is just and moral belongs to the essential, independent and intrinsically universal will ; and, if we would know what is right, we i p. 425. P- 434- P- 434- 214 E THICALITY (. SITTLICHKEIT ). must abstract all subjective inclinations and desires, i. e., we must know what the Will is in itself. The Will is free only when it does not will anything alien to itself (as universal) but wills itself alone- — wills the Will (universal ).” 1 Then, after making most trenchant criticism of this principle when applied in the abstract way which led to “the Age of Reason,” the French Revolution and the Aufklärung , ruthlessly destroying all the holy web of human institutions, he says : — “It is a false principle, that the fetters which bind justice and liberty can be broken without the emancipation of the Conscience — that there can be a Revolution with- out a Reformation. . . . Mere external power can affect nothing in the long run : Napoleon could no more coerce Spain into freedom than Phillip II. could force Holland into slavery .” 2 “In the Protestant world there is no sacred or religious conscience in a state of separation from or, perhaps, even of hostility to secular right. This is the point attained by the modern Consciousness. . . . Objective freedom — the laws of real freedom — demand the subjugation of the arbitrary, formal, subjective will. Yet while the objective is the rational for man, there is the further demand that insight and conviction correspond with the Reason which the objective embodies. Thus we have the other essential element — subjective freedom — also realized .” 3 “ That the History of the World, with all the changing scenes which its annals present, is this process of the development and actualization of Spirit — this is the true Theodicy, the justification of God in History. Only this insight can reconcile the human spirit with the course of Universal History — viz., that what has happened and is happening each day is not only not without God, but that it is essentially His work .” 4 2 P- 47 2 - 1 p. 461. p. 476. P- 477- INDEX. Abstractness, vice of, II, 27. Aufklärung, ethics of the, 20. Chinese morality, 13. Church and state, 47, 203. City and country, 188. Classes of civil society, 1 70-1 74. Community, the civic, 159, 187. Conscience, 116-133. private, 117. ■ the true, 120. Contract, 33, 89. Corporation, the municipal, 187. Crime, 34, 94. Culpability, 108. Dialectical method, 28. Divorce, 1 56. Duty for duty’s sake, 14. Education of the race, 208. of children, 208. End, the, sanctifies the means, 128. Ethicality, n, 39, 67, 135. Ethics, absolute, 53, 204. Christian, 56. Evil, moral, 37, 122. origin of, 123. Family, the, 41, 148. Fichte, 7, 17. Finality in morals impossible, 51. Fraud, 94. Freedom, steps in progress of, 52. Green, T. H., 51. Hegel, a Moses, 15. biographical sketch of, 1-8. method of, 27. relation of to previous ethical thought, 8, 22. History, universal, 207. epochs in, 209. Hypocrisy, 127. Intention, the right of, no. Irony, 131. Jacobi, 14, 129. Jury, trial by, 185. Justice, administration of, 174. courts of, 1 8 r . Kant, criticism of, 9, 16, 36. Key words, 57. Know thyself \YvC161. creavriv], 10. Labor, nature of, 166. division of, 167. Logic (Hegel’s) as metaphysics, 23. Love, 148. Man, how good and evil by nature, 123 - Marriage, 42, 90, 150. ethical duty of, 150. solemnization of, 153. Monarchy, 206. INDEX. 216 Montesquieu, 194. Morality, 11, 36, 67, 102. laws of, 1 42. Morris, Prof. Geo. S., 30. quoted, 197, 21 1. Mulford, Rev. Dr. E. 44. Nature, philosophy of, 24. Pascal, 126. Patriotism, 200. Pedagogue, the right of the, 144. Person, the abstract, 32, 72. Personality, 73. Philosophy, the task of, 63. Police, 187, Possessions, 82, 84. Probabilism, 127. Property, 33, 76, 154. equality of, not rational, 80. Punishment, 34, 95. false theories of, 98. Purpose and culpability, 108. Rationalism, eighteenth century, 20. Reformation, the, 213. Religion and the state, 47, 203. Revenge, 99. Revolution, the French, 214. Right, abstract, 32, 71, 75. of necessity, 114. Rousseau, 190. Royce, Prof. Josiah, VIII., 2. Schelling, 7, 19. Secular affairs, sacredness of, 212, 213 - Slavery, 33, 88. State, the, 44. an organism, 198, 202. ancient and modern, 196. and individual's, 198. and institutions, 198. and religion, 203. and the church, 47. distinguished from civil so- ciety, 189. rights and duties in, 195. Spirit, the philosophy of, 26. the testimony of the, 137. Station, my, and its duties, 14. Stirling, Dr. J. H., V., VIII., 3. Suicide, wrong, 87. Superstition, 87. Theodicy, Hegel’s, 214. Virtue, talk about, empty, 140. Wants and their satisfaction, 163. Wealth, 168. impossibility of equality of, 169. Wedlock 149. Will, the, as thought, 64. • as infinite and free, 65. Wrong, 91. ADVERTISEMENTS. PHILOSOPHY. Empirical Psychology ; or, The Human Mind as Given in Consciousness. By Laurens P. Hickok, D.D., LL.D. Revised with the co-operation of Julius H. Seelye, D.D., LL.D., Ex-Prest. of Amherst College. 12mo. 300 pages. Mailing Price, $1.25; Introduction, $1.12. rPHE publishers believe that this book will be found to be re- markably comprehensive, and at the same time compact and clear. It gives a complete outline of the science, concisely pre- sented, and in precise and plain terms. It has proved of special value to teachers, as is evidenced by its recent adoption for several Reading Circles. John Bascom, formerly Pres. Uni- versity of Wisconsin, Madison : It is an excellent hook. It has done much good service, and, as revised by President. Seelye, is prepared to do much more. I. W. Andrews, formerly Prof, of Intellectual Philosophy, Marietta College, 0. : This new edition may be confidently recommended as pre- senting a deliueation of the mental faculties so clear and accurate that the careful student will hardly fail to recognize its truth in his own ex- perience. Hickok’ s Mora! Science. By Laurens P. Hickok, D.D., LL.D. Revised with the co-operation of Julius H. Seelye, D.D., LL.D., Ex-Prest. of Amherst College. 12mo. Cloth. 288 pages. Mailing Price, $1.25; Introduction, $1.12. A S revised by Dr. Seelye, it is believed that this work will be found unsurpassed in systematic rigor and scientific precision, and at the same time remarkably clear and simple in style. G. P. Fisher, Prof, of Church His- tory, Yale College : The style is so perspicuous, and at the same time so concise, that the work is eminently 135 adapted to serve as a text-hook in colleges and higher schools. In mat- ter and manner it is a capital book, and I wish it God speed. 13(3 PHILOSOPHY. Lotze’s Philosophical Outlines. Dictated Portions of the Latest Lectures (at Göttingen and Berlin) of Hermann Lotze. Translated and edited by George T. Ladd, Pro- fessor of Philosophy in Yale University. 12mo. Cloth. About 180 pages in each volume. Mailing price per volume, $1.00 ; for introduc- tion, 80 cents. T“ German from which the translations are made consists of the dictated portions of his latest lectures (at Gottingen, and for a few months at Berlin) as formulated by Lotze himself, recorded in the notes of his hearers, and subjected to the most competent and thorough revision of Professor Heimisch of Got- tingen. The Outlines give, therefore, a mature and trustworthy statement, in language selected by this teacher of philosophy him- self, of what may be considered as his final opinions upon a wide range of subjects. They have met with no little favor in Germany. These translations have been undertaken with the kind permis- sion of the German publisher, Herr S. Hirzel, of Leipsic. Outlines of Metaphysic. This contains the scientific treatment of those assumptions which enter into all our cognition of Reality. It consists of three parts, — Ontology, Cosmology, Phenomenology. The first part contains chapters on the Con- ception of Being, the Content of the Existent, Reality, Change, and Causa- tion ; the second treats of Space, Time, Motion, Matter, and the Coherency of Natural Events; the third, of the Subjectivity and Objectivity of Cog- nition. The Metaphysic of Lotze gives the key to his entire philosophical system. Outlines of the Philosophy of Religion. Lotze here seeks “ to ascertain how much of the Content of Religion may be discovered, proved, or at least confirmed, agreeably to reason.” He discusses the Proof for the Existence of God, the Attributes and Personality of the Absolute, the Conceptions of the Creation, the Preservation, and the Government, of the World, and of the World-time. The book closes with brief discussions of Religion and Morality, and Dogmas and Confessions. Outlines of Practical Philosophy. This contains a discussion of Ethical Principles, Moral Ideals, and the Freedom of the Will, and then an application of the theory to the Indi- vidual, to Marriage, to Society, and to the State. Many interesting remarks on Divorce, Socialism, Representative Government, etc., abound throughout the volume. Its style is more popular than that of the other works of Lotze, and it will doubtless be widely read. Outlines of Psychology. The Outlines of Psychology treats of Simple Sensations, the Course of Representative Ideas, of Attention and Inference, of Intuitions, of Objects as in Space, of the Apprehension of the External IVorld by the Senses, of Errors of the Senses, of Feelings, and of Bodily Motions. Its second part is “theoretical,” and discusses the nature, position, and changeable states of the Soul, its relations to time, and the reciprocal action of Soul and Body. It closes with a chapter on the “Kingdom of Souls.” Lotze is peculiarly rich and suggestive in the discussion of Psychology. PHILOSOPHY. 137 Outlines of /Esthetics. The Outlines of Esthetics treats of the theory of the Beautifm and of Phantasy, and of the Realization and Different Species of the Beautiful. Then follow brief chapters on Music, Architecture, Plastic Art, Painting, and Poetry. This, like the other volumes, has a full index. Outlines of Logic. This discusses both pure and applied Logic. The Logic is followed by a brief treatise on the Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, in which are set forth the definition and method of Theoretical Philosophy, of Practical Phi- losophy, and of the Philosophy of Religion. This volume is about one-fifth larger than the others, and makes an admirable brief text-book in Logic. Mind, London, Eng. : No words are needed to commend such an en- terprise, now that Lotze’s importance as a thinker is so well understood. The translation is careful and pains- taking. The Philosophical Reuiew , A Bi-monthly Journal of General Philosophy, Edited by J. G. Schurmax, Dean of the Sage School of Philosophy and President of Cornell University. Subscription price, $3.00. Single copy, 75 cents. Foreign Agents: Great Britain, Edward Arnold, Lon- don; Germany, Mayer & Müller, Berlin; France, E. Leroux, Paris; Italy, E. Loescher, Rome. Volume II. began with January, 1893. rpHE PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW is intended as an organ for the publication of the results of investigation in every branch of Philosophy. It is made up of original articles, reviews of books, and classified summaries of periodical literature. The Review will not enter into competition with those special- ized or technical journals which are already engaged in the minute cultivation of particular branches of Philosophy. Its domain is the still unoccupied field of General Philosophy : that whole which includes, along with the older subjects of Logic, Metaphysics, and Ethics, the newer subjects of Psychology, ^Esthetics, Pedagogy, and Epistemology, both in their systematic form and in their his- torical development. Its field is as broad as mind. And it will be an open forum alike for those who increase the stock of positive data and for those who strive to see new facts in their bearings and relations, and to trace them up to their ultimate speculative implications. With the generality of its scope, the Review aims to combine an impartiality and catholicity of tone and spirit. It will not be the organ of any institution, or of any sect, or of any interest. It will maintain the same objectivity of attitude as a journal of Math- ematics or Philology. All articles will be signed, and the writers alone will be responsible for their contents. 138 PHILOSOPHY. A Brief History of Greek Philosophy. By B. C. Burt, M.A., formerly Docent of Philosophy, Clark University. 12mo. Cloth, xiv + 296 pages. Mailing price, $ 1.25 ; for introd., §1.12. FJIHIS work attempts to give a concise but comprehensive account of Greek Philosophy on its native soil and in Rome. It is critical and interpretative, as well as purely historical, its para- graphs of criticism and interpretation, however, being, as a rule, distinct from those devoted to biography and exposition. The wants of the reader or student who desires to comprehend, rather than merely to inform himself, have particularly been in the mind of the author, whose aim has been to let the subject unfold itself as far as possible. The volume contains a full topical table of con- tents, a brief bibliography of the subject it treats, and numerous foot-notes embracing references to original authorities and assist- ing the student towards a real contact with the Greek thinkers themselves. G. Stanley Hall, Pres. Clark Uni- versity : His book is the best of its kind upon the subject. Geo. S. Morris, late Prof, of Phil- osophy in Michigan University : What Professor Burt has done is to collect in compendious form what is most characteristic and of most essential significance in these results of philosophical investigation, and then to re-interpret or re-exhibit them in the light of the more mature fruits of modern inquiry. This is the best and most serviceable kind of originality. W. T. Harris, Editor Jour. of Spec- ulative Philosophy : I have found this work in philosophy to possess high merit. His grasp of the history of the subject is rare and trustworthy. The Modalist; or. The Laws of Rational Conviction. A Text-Book in Formal or General Logic. By Edward John Hamil- ton, D.D., formerly Albert Barnes Professor of Intellectual Philosophy, Hamilton College, N.Y. 8vo. Cloth. 337 pages. Price, by mail, $1.40; for introduction, $1.25. TjJHIS book restores modal propositions and modal syllogisms to the place of importance which they occupied in the Logic of Aristotle. The author thinks that universal and particular cate- gorical propositions cannot be understood, as principles of reason- ing, and as employed in “ mediate inference,” unless the one be regarded as expressing a necessary and the other a contingent sequence. Therefore, also, he explains the pure syllogism by the PHILOSOPHY. 139 modal. Moreover, there are modes of reasoning which can be formulated only in modal syllogisms. Henry Coppee, Prof, of English Literature in Lehigh University : The Modalist is evidently the work of a writer who has studied logic with great care and pleasure, and will prove a valuable text-book with the Professor’s aid to the student in studying it. The Christian Union, New York : In it the author aims to give a clear definition of the science, to determine exactly its scope and sphere, to base it properly upon perceptionalism, and to exploit thoroughly the theory of inference and illative judgment. His discussion of the new analytic and of contingency in the twenty- first and two following chapters is extremely interesting, and his criti- cism of Euler’s diagrams and of Hamilton’s notation is acute. While somewhat minute, it is, on the whole, the best text-book in logic we have seen iu the English language. Mechanism and Personality. By Francis A. Shoup, D.D., Professor of Analytical Physics, Univer- sity of the South. 12mo. Cloth, xvi + 341 pages. Price by mail, $1.30 ; for introduction, $1.20. rpHIS book is an outline of Philosophy in the light of the latest scientific research. It deals candidly and simply with the “burning questions” of the day, the object being to help the general reader and students of Philosophy find their way to some- thing like definite standing-ground among the uncertainties of science and metaphysics. It begins with physiological psychology, treats of the development of the several modes of personality, passes on into metaphysic, and ends in ethics, following, in a general way, the thought of Lotze. It is strictly in line with the remark of Professor Huxley, that “the reconciliation of physics and metaphysics lies in the acknowledgment of faults upon both sides; in the confession by physics that all the phenomena of nature are, in their ultimate analysis, known to us only as facts of consciousness ; in the admission by metaphysics that the facts of consciousness are, practically, interpretable only by the methods and the formulae of physics.” George Trumbull ladd, Prof, of I Philosophy , Yale University : I find | Dr. Slioup’s “ Mechanism and Per- sonality ” an interesting and stimu- lating little book. Written, as it is, by one whose points of view are somewhat outside of those taken by professional students of philosophy, it is the fresher and more suggestive on that account. At the same time, the author has kept himself from straying too far away from the con- clusions legitimate to disciplined students of the subject, by a some- what close adherence to Lotze, and by a considerable breadth of philo- sophical reading. 140 PHILOSOPHY. ETHICAL SERIES. UNDER THE EDITORIAL SUPERVISION OF Professor E. IIershey Sneath of Yale University. rpHE primary object of the series is to facilitate the study of the History of Ethics in colleges. This History will be in the form of a series of small volumes, each devoted to the presentation of a representative system of Modern Ethics in selections from the original works. The selections will be accompanied by notes, and prefaced by a brief biographical sketch of the author, a statement of the relation of his system to preceding and subsequent ethical thought a brief exposition of the system, and a bibliography. All teachers will doubtless concede the advisability of placing original works in the hands of students instead of mere expo- sitions — such as are contained in the various Histories of Ethics. In a number of instances, however, the original editions are exhausted, and only a few copies are available ; and, in other instances, the books are too elaborate and expensive, if a number of systems are to be studied. The series will make provision for these difficulties by presenting each system in carefully edited extracts, and in a form which will entail comparatively little expense upon the student. See also the Announcements. The Ethics of Hume. By Dr. J. H. Hyslop, of Columbia College. 12mo. Cloth. 275 pages. Mailing price, $1.10; for introduction, $1.00. rpiIE present volume contains the whole of the third book of the Treatise of Human Nature, and such portions of the second book as throw light upon or are connected with Hume’s moral theory. The analysis and criticism of his system follows lines somewhat different from that of Green, and are designed to present Hume in another light. In all respects it is hoped that the volume may prove helpful to those who wish to study the ethical system of Kant’s predecessor. POLITICAL SCIENCE. 143 Political Science and Comparative Constitutional Law. By John W. Burgess, LL.D., Professor of Constitutional and Inter- national History and Law, and Dean of the School of Political Science in Columbia College. Two volumes. 8vo. Cloth. 781 pages. Retail price, $5.00. Special terms to teachers and for introduction. rjJHE first Part of the work is devoted to the general principles of political science. It is divided into three Books. The first book treats of the nation as an ethnological concept ; the second treats of the state, its idea, its origin, its forms, and its ends ; and the third shows the historical development of the four typical constitutions of the modern age, those of England, Germany, France, and the United States. The second Part is devoted to a comparison of the provisions of these typical constitutions and a generalization from these provis- ions of some fundamental principles of constitutional law. The three Books of this Part treat, the first of sovereignty within the constitution, the second of civil liberty, and the third, which con- stitutes the second volume , of government, legislative, executive, and judicial. The London Times : A very learned, elaborate, and suggestive work. . . . His work ... is full of keen analysis and suggestive com- ment, and is a noteworthy contribu- tion to the comparative study of political science and jurisprudence. Currency, Finance, and Banking. Laws of the United States relating to Currency, Finance, and Banking; with Vetoed Bills and other documents. Compiled by Charles F. Dunbar, Professor of Political Economy in Harvard University. 8vo. Cloth. 309 pages. Mailing price, $2.50 ; special terms for use in classes. rjJHis book presents in chronological order the exact text of all important acts of Congress relating to currency, finance, coin- age, and banking from 1789 to 1891, with carefully edited abstracts of acts or sections of minor importance. The Nation, New York : A work of obvious utility and convenience. . . . Professor Dunbar’s task has been most scrupulously executed, and a hare statement of the nature of it will stand in lieu of praise. The volume is beautifully printed. BOOKS IN HIGHER ENGLISH. Introd. Price. Alexander: Introduction to Browning $1.00 Athenaeum Press Series : Cook: Sidney’s Defense of Poesy 80 Gummere: Old English Ballads 00 Schelling: Ben Jonson’s Timber 80 Baker : Plot-Book of Some Elizabethan Plays 00 Cook : A First Book in Old English 00 Shelley’s Defense of Poetry 50 The Art of Poetry 1.12 Hunt’s What is Poetry? 50 * Newman’s Aristotle’s Poetics 30. Addison’s Criticisms on Paradise Lost 1.00 Bacon’s Advancement of Learning 00 Corson: Primer of English Verse 1.00 Emery : Notes on English Literature 1.00 English Literature Pamphlets: Ancient Mariner, .05; First Bunker Hill Address, .10; Essay on Lord Clive, .15; Second Essay on the Earl of Chatham, .15; Burke, I. and II. ; Webster, I. and II. ; Bacon ; Wordsworth, I. and II.; Coleridge and Burns; Addison and Goldsmith Each .15 Fulton & Trueblood : Practical Elocution Retail 1.50 Choice Readings, $1.50; Chart of Vocal Expression . 2.00 College Critic’s Tablet (10 Garnett: English Prose from Elizabeth to Victoria .... 1.50 Gayley : Classic Myths in English Literature 1.50 Genung : Outlines of Rhetoric 1.00 Elements of Rhetoric, $1.25 ; Rhetorical Analysis . 1.12 Gummere: Handbook of Poetics 1.00 Hudson : Harvard Edition of Shakespeare’s Complete Works : — ■ 20 Vol. Ed. Cloth, retail, $25.00; Half-calf, retail . 55.00 10 Vol. Ed. Cloth, retail, $20.00; Half-calf, retail . 40.00 Life, Art, and Characters of Shakespeare. 2 vols. Cloth, 4.00 New School Shakespeare. Each play : Paper, .30 ; Cloth, .45 Text-Book of Poetry ; Text-Book of Prose . . Each 1.25 Classical English Reader 1.00 Lockwood: Lessons in English, $1.12; Thanatopsis 10 Maxcy : Tragedy of Hamlet 45 Minto : Manual of English Prose Literature 1.50 Characteristics of English Poets 1.50 Newcomer : Practical Course in English Composition 80 Phelps : English Romantic Movement 00 Sherman: Analytics of Literature 1.25 Smith : Synopsis of English and American Literature ... .80 Sprague : Milton’s Paradise Lost and Lycidas 45 Thayer: The Best Elizabethan, Plays 1.25 Thom: Shakespeare and Chaucer Examinations 1.00 White : Philosophy of American Literature 30 Whitney : Essentials of English Grammar 75 Whitney & Lockwood : English Grammar 70 Winchester : Five Short Courses of Reading in English Literature, .40 AND OTHER VALUABLE WORKS. GINN & COMPANY, Publishers, Boston, New York, and Chicago. /*v wp- Date Due ** if W v ” v '- Mi' " 7S > F ) ' AUG 1 2 '49 MAR 1 y - L. B. Cat. No. 1137 Duke University Libraries DO 1 334221 G