DUKE UNIVERSITY WOMAN’S COLLEGE LIBRARY ALTRUISM ITS NATURE AND VARIETIES Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2016 https://archive.org/details/altruism01palm ALTRUISM ITS NATURE AND VARIETIES THE ELY LECTURES FOR 1917-18 BY GEORGE HERBERT PALMER CHARLES SCRIBNER’S SONS NEW YORK $ $ $ $ 1919 D / n / / / A COPYRIGHT, 1919, BY CHARLES SCRIBNER’S SONS Published January, 1919 THE ELY FOUNDATION The Elias P. Ely Lectureship was founded by Mr. Zebulon Stiles Ely, May 8, 1865. The deed of gift contains the following paragraphs: “The undersigned gives the sum of ten thousand dollars to the Union Theological Seminary of the City of New York to found a Lectureship in the same, the title of which shall be the ‘Elias P. Ely Lectures on the Evidences of Christianity,’ on the following conditions: “The course of lectures given on this foundation is to comprise any topics that serve to establish the proposition that Christianity is a religion from God, or that it is the perfect and final form of re- ligion for man. Among the subjects discussed may be the nature and need of a revelation; the char- acter and influence of Christ and His apostles; the authenticity and credibility of the Scriptures, mira- cles, and prophecy; the diffusion and benefits of Christianity; the philosophy of religion in its rela- tion to the Christian system.” Under date of May 24, 1879, Mr. Ely addressed a communication to the Direc- ' 87819 VI THE ELY FOUNDATION tors of the Seminary in which the con- ditions of the Lectureship are amplified as follows: “The conditions of the foundation of the Elias P. Ely Lectureship, dated May 8, 1865, are hereby modified, so that the course of public lectures there- in provided for, may not only be on ‘The Evidences of Christianity,’ but on such other subjects as the Faculty and Directors, in concurrence with the undersigned, while living, may deem for the good of man.” PREFACE I here present the substance of eight Ely Lectures delivered in the spring of 1918 at Union Theological Seminary in New York. They were spoken without manuscript. In writing them out from the stenographer’s notes I have condensed them considerably. In these belligerent days publishers are disposed to economize paper and print, and readers to prize brev- ity in everything except newspapers. Such restrictions force on us loquacious book- makers greater regard for compactness and lucidity, and are thus not altogether an injury. The book seeks to call attention to a section of ethics in regard to which the public mind greatly needs clarifying. Al- truism and egoism, socialism and individual- ism, are in our time sentimentally arrayed against one another as independent and antagonistic agencies, each having its par- tisans. A careful examination will show, PREFACE viii I think, that the one has meaning only when in company with its supposed rival. I have thought to make this clearest by tracing three stages through which the altruistic impulse passes in every-day life, exhibiting their varying degrees of dignity and the helpful presence in all of them of egoistic balance. If through my notion of a conjunct self I have made this curious partnership plain I shall count it no mean contribution to our generous, sacrificial, self-assertive, and perplexed time. George Herbert Palmer. Cambbidge, October 21, 1918. CONTENTS CHAPTEB PAGE I. Introduction 1 II. Manners 13 III. Gifts 32 TV . Defects of Giving 56 V. Mutuality 75 VI. Love 91 VII. Justice 110 VIII. Conclusion 126 ALTRUISM ITS NATURE AND VARIETIES CHAPTER I INTRODUCTION I have been moving about lately through different parts of our country, sitting down to dinner in many homes, and I have everywhere found the family eating bread made of Indian meal, rye, barley, or oat- meal. When I have asked, “Are you es- pecially fond of this sort of food?” I have pretty generally received the answer, “Why, no ! We all like wheat bread better. But we are not eating it now, for other nations need it.” That is altruism, one of the most funda- mental, familiar, and mysterious of all the virtues. This course of lectures will be devoted to elucidating it. To a recognition of it the Western mind has risen slowly. The Greeks attached little importance to it; for though philanthropy, regard for l 2 ALTRUISM man as man, is a Greek word, it is not a Greek idea. Plato does not include it among his four virtues nor anywhere lay stress on its practice. In Aristotle’s Ethics , it is true, there are magnificent chapters on friendship, and friendship plays a great part in the teaching of the Epicureans and Stoics. But all alike speak of attachment to another person chiefly as a means of strength for oneself. The thought of whole-hearted giving without correspondent personal gain would have puzzled a Greek. When we turn to the other branch of our civilization and examine what we have derived from the Hebrews, we find a nearer approach to modern ideas. Com- monly enough the Hebrews speak of mercy and grace, and pair these off against jus- tice and truth. Apparently when these terms are applied to God’s dealings with us, the second pair indicates his exact re- turn for what we have done for him; but the first pair points to something over and above, a surplusage of generosity, lying outside the field of equal pay. God is con- ceived as altruistic and we are summoned to imitate him in this. Jesus develops the thought to such a degree that love be- INTRODUCTION 3 comes the centre of his teaching. We are told that without it all other excellence is worthless. We must love as God loves, letting our sun shine on the evil and on the good. Indeed, we must love even our en- emies. While modern nations have allowed such precepts to stand as counsels of perfection and have been ready to see in occasional acts an embodiment of them, parallel with them they have always recognized a con- trary and more powerful tendency, namely, the disposition to seek one’s own. This they have believed to be essential for carry- ing on the daily affairs of life. At the same time altruistic conduct has ever been thought “superior,” “higher”; egoistic, as containing nothing to call forth admiration. When men, however, began to think seriously about ethics it became impossible to allow two such springs of action to re- main in permanent discord. Attempts were made to bring them into harmony by show- ing that the one is only a disguised form of the other. Hobbes, for example (1588- 1679), the first in his great book, Leviathan, to stir the English mind to ethical reflec- tion, maintains that altruism is strictly im- 4 ALTRUISM possible. Each of us seeks self-preserva- tion and acts through a passion for power. This necessarily brings us into conflict with our neighbors and makes of society a strife of each with all. Such universal war is soon seen to bring damage to every one and social compacts arise, compromises, under which I concede to others the right of act- ing in certain ways on condition of their allowing my action in certain others. While this involves large sacrifice of one’s own desires for the sake of other people, it is endured because it pays, pays egoistically. We gain by it the largest scope for action our crowded world permits. But there is nothing disinterested about it. Genuine altruism is nowhere operative. A man cannot escape from himself and feel an- other’s pleasure as his own. As well might I profess to feel your toothache more keenly than my own as to declare myself more interested in your welfare than in that of myself. Fundamentally, each of us must be egoistic; but we can be success- fully so only by taking others into the ac- count. This attempt of Hobbes to resolve altru- ism into a larger form of egoism naturally INTRODUCTION 5 shocked England, and a century was spent by the English moralists in trying to prove that the benevolent feelings are equally original with the self-seeking. Cumber- land, Shaftesbury, Hutcheson, Butler, ea- gerly demonstrated benevolence to be a constant and independent factor of human life; but when they attempted to show the relation in which this stands to its seeming opposite, they became vague. Apparently there are two rival forces within us. Now one acts, now the other. A few of the attempts that have been made to effect a junction of the two, and to show how we cross from our egoistic to altruistic desires, deserve notice. Hartley ( 1705 - 1757 ) proposed an ingenious one. The two passions become fused through association. We are all familiar with the man who begins to accumulate money in order to supply his daily wants and then by degrees withdraws his attention from those wants and fixes it upon money itself. What was originally a means becomes an end. In just this way Hartley thought our egoistic desires become transformed. To reach satisfaction they usually require as- sistance from other people. Conscious at 6 ALTRUISM first of our dependence on others for aid, we become by degrees interested in others for their own sake, and finally seek to aid them rather than have them aid us. Our self-regarding powers and our extra-re- garding powers are thus by association blurred into one. An important school of ethical writers, among whom the two Mills are the most notable, have held this view. An interesting variation was adopted by Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832). It might be called the quantitative view. The one thing desired by us all is happiness. We seek to produce as much of it as possible, paying little attention to the one on whom it falls. Of course our primary desire looks toward ourselves. But in seeking to in- crease that bulk of happiness from which we draw, egoism largely disappears in the search after the greatest happiness of the greatest number. This formula must al- ways be convenient and valuable in a democratic state. One of the most curious of these meth- ods of extracting altruistic gold from a baser metal is that of Bishop Paley (1743- 1805). According to him we have none of us an interest in our fellows’ happiness and INTRODUCTION 7 should never of ourselves seek it. But we read in our Bibles the command to love our neighbor and are told that we shall fall into eternal misery if we do not. With his customary audacious clearness Paley states the matter thus: “The greatest vir- tue is doing good to mankind, in obedience to the will of God, and for the sake of ever- lasting happiness.” That is, the one thing of importance is altruistic endeavor. But this is so alien to our disposition that it can be brought about only through divine interposition, making it a condition of our own permanent enjoyment. A subtler doctrine, and one much closer to the facts of human nature, is that of Adam Smith (1723-1790). He has ob- served how large a part sympathy plays in our ordinary affairs. If I am near a person when he is moved by any feeling, that feeling tends to jump across and to become mine also. Such identification of myself and him gives pleasure to us both. We all have experienced how sympathy heightens enjoyment and diminishes dis- tress. In sympathy two sets of feelings become so nearly identified that the result can be called neither egoistic nor altruistic. 8 ALTRUISM Now I do not propose in these lectures to combat or defend any of these theories. No one of them seems to me to be without weight, all deserve consideration, and some- thing like the operation of each I trace in people around me. The one with which I am in largest agreement is the last, where Adam Smith would identify the two moral aims. But all the theories are vitiated by a false start, which in these lectures I wish to avoid. Each of them looks upon man in his original estate as a self-centred being, a distinct ego. By degrees this single person discovers other persons about him and learns that he must have relations with them. The relations may be altruistic or egoistic, but they are subsequent and sup- plemental. In himself he is separate and detached. Now, I hold that this concep- tion is altogether erroneous. There is no such solitary person. One person is no person. The smallest known unit of per- sonality is three, father, mother, child. None of us came into the world in sepa- rateness, nor have separately remained here. Relations have encompassed us from birth. Through them we are what we are, social INTRODUCTION 9 beings, members of a whole. While it is true that the ties of parentage loosen as the child matures, these drop away only because others, now more formative, take him in charge. Before we have a separate consciousness we know ourselves as mem- bers of a family, of a state, of the commu- nity of human kind. We never stand alone. Not that it is an error to say “I.” This, properly, is our commonest word and com- monest thought. Only with reference to it does anything else have value. How- ever interlocked the total frame of things may be, at certain centres where relations converge there are unique spots of con- sciousness capable of estimating reality and of sending forth modifying influences. Such a centre of consciousness, unlike all else, we rightly call a person, a self or ego; and because of its importance we often fix attention on it, withdrawing notice for the moment from the relations which encom- pass it. Such an abstraction, if clearly understood, is entirely legitimate. I shall frequently make use of it under the title of the separate or abstract self. But it should be borne in mind that it is an ab- 10 ALTRUISM straction and that the real person is what I shall call the conjunct or social self, made up of that centre of consciousness and the relations in which it stands. While these two are usefully distinguishable, they are not separable. When I try to detach my- self from my surroundings I know I am attempting an impossibility. How much would there be left of me were there no one but this central ego, none with whom I might communicate, no language prepared for communication or thought, no common affections, interests, or undertakings? Evi- dently we are from the start social beings. If with the early moralists we make the opposite assumption, our subsequent inter- est in our fellow men will never quite clear itself of artificiality and mistake. Yet while the separate self and the con- junct self lodge in the same being, the de- gree and kind of attention accorded to the latter marks the stage of moral maturity at which man or nation has arrived. In certain undeveloped forms of social life the conjunctive elements are but slightly em- phasized, while the separate self bulks large. With the advance of morality the opposite principle obtains. Wider and INTRODUCTION 11 more subtle relationships are seen to make our lives our own. Many as are these social varieties, I have thought they might advantageously be examined under three headings, to which I give the rather unin- telligible names of Manners, Gifts, and Mutuality. While recognizing that every phase of human life is altruistic in some degree, I hold that there are higher grades which give to the principle a prominence and scope which the lower lack. My gen- eral subject, then, might be entitled The Forms and Stages of the Conjunct Self. I begin where the conjunctive principle ap- pears in its narrowest range and advance into the broader altruism only as I am logically compelled to do so. Endeavor- ing to see how small a section of human conduct need be affected by altruism, I am ultimately forced to make it as extensive as life itself. Maintaining, however, as I do, that the two contrasted elements always are and should be mutually serviceable, I natur- ally have nothing to say in condemnation of self-seeking. On the contrary, I hold it to be praiseworthy. Rightly does Aris- totle assert that the good man is always a 12 ALTRUISM lover of himself. But of which self is Aris- totle thinking, the conjunct or the sepa- rate? Much of the mystery surrounding the notion of altruism is due to confusion on this point. For example, when a man is charged with selfishness it is usually be- cause he is thought to have obtained some advantage. But why should he not? He is blamable only when he detaches the thought of his own advantage from ad- vantage to others. My good must not be had at another’s expense. When a plate of apples is passed and I pick out the best one, the wrong is not in my obtaining a good apple but in my depriving somebody else of one. That is selfishness. Whenever my gain is not inconsistent with his or, as is usually the case, actually contributes to it, the larger the gain made by me the better. CHAPTER II MANNERS Where, then, does altruism appear in its simplest form ? Whenever one of us comes into the presence of another there occurs a subtle change of personal attitude to which I give the name of Manners. We do not act or speak precisely as if alone. In all our bearing there is a marked adjust- ment of one personality to another. I take on the color of him before whom I stand. I feel his psychological conditions and square myself accordingly. That is, I at once perceive that he and I are not quite independent. An acknowledgment of a certain community between us must be established before either of us can be at ease. Such acknowledgment may have a wide or narrow scope, but it will always imply regard for another for his own sake and not merely regard for my sake. One would expect that the words which name a relation so normal and dignified would be words suggestive of honor. 13 14 ALTRUISM Strangely enough, they are all deprecia- tory. I have sought for a word to describe the consideration of man by man which would be colorless, that neither praised nor blamed, but simply fixed attention on the fact. No such word do I find. A blot of disparagement is on them all. I choose Manners as on the whole the least objec- tionable. Pass them briefly in review. When I say a man is kind in Manners, do I not suggest that there may be a contrast be- tween his outward bearing and his inner heart ? Or shall we call the relation one of Propriety, as Adam Smith does in his mas- terly discussion of this moral situation? Propriety always stirs aversion, because it implies that we have had little share in establishing the standard employed. It has been set up outside us and still we are subjected to it. How exasperated a child is when told to behave properly ! Why should he care for Propriety ? Or shall we say Civility? It is a scrimping, meagre word, announcing that only so much con- sideration is shown as decency requires. When we hear a man say, “John was civil to me,” our thought continues: “Was that MANNERS 15 all? Did he go no further than that?” How would Politeness do ? More than Manners it hints at insincerity and con- duct that hopes to gain something for it- self. Beware of a polite man. He is likely to use you for his own ends. Might we then talk of Good Breeding? When any one calls me well-bred he praises my parents, not me. The excellence on which I pride myself has apparently come from their training. What shall we say of Cour- tesy? That it is a term of dignity, but suggests stooping. The one with whom I deal is accounted my inferior. Or Gentle- manliness? To call a young fellow a gen- tleman makes his heart throb. Yet the word does not escape a certain limitation. It uses the standard of a particular set, “our crowd.” If my conduct does not ac- cord with their usages, I am not a gentle- man. The word lacks universality. By such questionable terms our language names the beautiful relation I am now to set forth. Since Manners is on the whole the least stained word among them, the one most nearly neutral, I adopt it, but I shall read into it much more meaning than people generally intend. To cover its 16 ALTRUISM full meaning I am obliged to frame a statement so burdened with details that it will hardly be recognized as anything commonly called Manners. But it shall be explained clause by clause, and I ask my reader to watch whether I have introduced anything into it which might be omitted or omitted anything which should have been introduced. The definition runs thus: By Manners I mean such a voluntary con- formity to a code of conduct as, within a fixed field of intercourse, insures to each person the least offense and a due oppor- tunity of self-expression. Four elements are here named as belonging to Manners. I will take them up separately and in order. In the first place Manners assume a set- tled code, a social arrangement generally agreed to. They are essentially system- atic, not impulsive and incidental. An ex- clamation of joy uttered when I am happy may or may not be consistent with good manners. That depends on how fully it has been rationalized. I am expected to act to-day as I should wish to act to- morrow. Expression must keep in view the whole personality. Moreover, I must know how other people act and bring my MANNERS 17 action into measurable conformity with theirs. If I am frequently doing what no- body else does, I am sure to be thought rude. I am expected to understand what the social code demands. Perhaps the word “code” is too formal. It pictures a committee drawing up a plan of behavior. Of course no such committee exists. Yet an agreement there has been, a tacit un- derstanding, of how we are to behave to one another. Any one ignorant of this un- derstanding, or neglectful of it, is reckoned boorish and unfit for mannerly intercourse. That usage and not my own liking should direct my bearing toward others. To do something just because I like to shows me uncivilized. My commonest actions should be socialized. They are expected to ex- press something more than my separate self, namely, my conjunct self, showing ac- cordance with myself at other times and also accordance with the persons around me. Is it well or usual to have these under- standings written down? Are manuals of manners useful, teaching us just how to behave in this and that situation? Such books exist, but I believe few would will- 18 ALTRUISM ingly be caught reading one. Formal codes are not what we want. They are not fine enough. They study moral situ- ations too mechanically, with too little re- gard for personality. From them one might pick up a few useful warnings about certain bad habits not previously noticed; but a man who followed such a manual ex- actly would nowhere be a welcome guest. Conformity to a standard, however, is far from the whole of manners. Were it so, the place to find good manners would be the State Prison. A clear code is es- tablished there. Each man is told pre- cisely what he is to do throughout the en- tire day. For that reason we are hardly justified in speaking of convict manners at all. A prison permits no expression of the individual life, and a second condition of good manners was “ voluntary conformity to a social code.” While every child should be trained to know how those who are wisest and kindest are accustomed to meet the little circumstances of daily inter- course, still that child’s actions are worth- less if they do not bear his own stamp. Is not this what we mean by a vulgar man? His manners are not an expression of him- MANNERS 19 self, but of somebody else. Other men have obliterated him. An evident copy is all that remains. Fine manners play around the correct modes, departing from them here and there in little niceties. So far is the code from fettering individuality that it becomes the channel for its easiest outgo. A graceful gentleman is enviable in his freedom. He is at home anywhere. Every situation has been thought out by society beforehand. With its conclusions he has been long acquainted and in his own way swiftly adapts them to the delicate oc- casion at hand. There is no surprise, no awkwardness, no loss of dignity. The separate self is not altogether suppressed, but is present everywhere in the service of the conjunct. There appears in the definition, however, a phrase which clogs it: “Within a fixed field of intercourse.” Why is this neces- sary and what does it mean? Manners need to be adjusted to different occasions. Those that are suitable to the shop do not fit the evening party. When we meet for the exchange of commodities or meet to exchange good wishes and general good cheer, we approach one another from dif- 20 ALTRUISM ferent angles, and our manners should re- flect them appropriately. When again we meet for discussion, the social situation is so peculiar that nothing less than a written code, a Cushing's Manual, will insure free- dom for all. Left to themselves, each person would speak as often as feeling prompted. But such rude manners are not allowed. No one must speak without ap- pealing to the chairman and receiving his permission by word or nod. If a person opposing me in debate makes statements which strike me as absurd and intended to mislead, I am not at liberty to character- ize them so. Debate could not proceed on such terms. Every one must be respectful and conform to a parliamentary standard. Such a standard would be out of place in the home. But much of the beauty of human intercourse arises from noticing these differences in the field and, with full knowledge of what is customary, adapting our manners freshly to what the occasions require. But readers will already be asking, “Why all this pomp and circumstance ? What object can make us willing to accept such constraint instead of approaching one an- MANNERS 21 other as we happen to feel.” That object was the fourth point in my definition: Manners are accepted “in order to insure to each person the least offense and a due opportunity for self-expression.” Expres- sion is dear to all. At least to me it is al- ways a pleasure to give another a piece of my mind. This may not be a pleasure to that other. If, then, we are to be social beings, there must be some security that when I am enjoying speech I cause no dis- turbance to others. Accordingly, the chief object of manners is a negative one, to avoid offense, to put every one at ease. Suppose the contrary; suppose A. B. asks me to meet a group of his friends; suppose I have a fancy for colored waistcoats and dress of fantastic design; suppose me not inclined to subordinate my taste to that of others, but simply to dress as I please. Should I not come as an intruder and dis- turber, preventing my fellow guests from thinking of anything but me? I should not be invited again to that house. To avoid such scenes we willingly accept a common costume, which nobody was ever known to admire. We go out in the eve- ning garbed in black. We know then what 22 ALTRUISM to expect, securing ourselves against shock and curbing the self-asserter. That tur- bulent ego is the chief obstacle to society. Better give up much that is of value if we can thus be brought to conduct which shows consideration for all around. The other part of the aim of manners, self-expression, is subordinate though de- sirable. Living alone, we are small; in contact with our fellow men, we enlarge ourselves. Trouble is worth taking for such a purpose. But there are dangers. Society is possible only where mutual con- sideration is shown. To be a social per- son one must be altruistically minded, con- tinually studying another’s comfort. I am talking with two or three old friends about some experiences of our youth, when John Smith joins us. We go on talking, and soon all the company except John Smith bursts into laughter. He naturally feels shut out and we perceive that we have been rude. Manners are devised to stop such painful feelings. We leave outside social walls whatever cannot be shared by all alike. I have been expounding here something so familiar that it is seldom mentioned or MANNERS 23 even thought of, but is usually taken as a matter of course. Yet surely it is im- portant to perceive how wide is the extent of altruism. It is nothing occasional, call- ing for exceptional heroism. It is common- place, spread all around us, attending the most elementary processes of existence. We never approach one another as sepa- rate beings, but are called on wherever we meet to put each other at ease, whatever may be the cost to ourselves. Well does Bentham write: “Good breeding is that deportment on occasions of inferior, and, when separately taken, of trivial impor- tance by which those acts are abstained from which give annoyance to others. It is to this negative or abstinential branch of benevolence that most of the laws of good breeding are to be referred.” Christ in offering the Golden Rule seems not to be urging unusual conduct, but rather to suggest that we carry out consistently and as a plan of life a principle inwrought into the very structure of our being. We are made conjunctive. Any attempt to ex- hibit the varieties of altruism must take this beautiful fact as its starting-point. No one has set forth more clearly the 24 ALTRUISM scope and delicacy of manners than Adam Smith in those chapters of his Moral Senti- ments which treat of Propriety. He asks what feelings may properly be expressed in company and what others, equally natural, the well-mannered man suppresses. The general principle is that those which have their root in specific circumstances of the individual, as, for example, the physical experiences, should be kept in the back- ground. A gentleman does not talk of his toothache or recent cold, nor does he show his strong appetite at table. While recog- nizing that all may properly be interested in his intended marriage, he dwells on the intensity of his affection only to the lady herself. These are matters relating to the separate self, while manners give expres- sion only to what all can share. Our ar- dent personal passions, even when entirely justified, often need to be flattened down before they can be fit to express. Mani- festations of the social passions, kindness and pity, are seldom improper. These give a double opportunity for sympathy. We share the feelings both of the sufferer and the humane speaker. But the emo- tions that terminate in ourselves, like joy MANNERS 25 and grief, require care. On the whole, Smith thinks we may count on sympathy with our small joys and large griefs. Hap- piness is something delightful to share, at least until it becomes so great as to awaken envy. And though it is disagreeable to hear of petty annoyances, which a gentle- man passes lightly by, serious misfortune is so much a part of the common lot that all will sympathize in hearing of it and be pleased that they have in this instance escaped. The death of a relative may not improperly put its mark on our very clothing, but it is indecent to speak of our vexations from servants and children. Here, then, we see human society repos- ing on a widely distributed and systema- tized altruism. Mutual consideration is here the rule. The apostle states it ad- mirably: “Look not every man on his own things, but every man also on the things of others.” The separate self is allowed no place; the conjunct self is the only person recognized. Surely, any one who under- takes to examine the varieties of altruism must begin with these beautiful and little- noticed moralities. Begin, but not end here. For while I 26 ALTRUISM believe all that has thus far been said is true, I see so much else to be true that I devote a section of this chapter to a criti- cism of manners. Wherein do manners fail to embody altruism completely? In three respects: they are trivial, self-protec- tive, and enfeebling. The study of these deficiencies will show us the way to altru- ism of a higher kind. The triviality of manners requires no long demonstration. All must have felt it and, probably enough, have been surprised at my counting such matters deserving of a place in a serious ethical discussion. It is as if I had devoted a section to brushing the hair. Many things more or less con- nected with the comfort of daily life we do not talk or think much about, and such are manners — never good until they become instinctive. They express merely our super- ficial relations with our fellows, our out- ward behavior, our acts and not our mo- tives. The man of considerate manners may be inwardly considerate, too; but he may be the very reverse and have shaped his conduct with a view to social success. Indeed, it may truly be said that manners become more prominent as the occasions MANNERS 27 of human intercourse diminish in impor- tance. Organized “society,” in which man- ners flourish, is treated as of little con- sequence by the sober body of the com- munity. This, then, is the first defect of manners when regarded as an embodiment of altruism: they are of limited range and do not necessarily involve the whole man. But they are open to a graver objec- tion. They are fundamentally self-protec- tive. If my first account of them were the whole truth, society people would be the least selfish of mankind. That is not their reputation, for manners are, after all, grounded in distrust of our fellow man. I said that the chief aim of manners was to avoid offense; that is, we anticipate being offended when we meet, and take precau- tions against it. The need of such pre- cautions against the turbulent ego I have shown already. Until I can be sure that people will not shock me by tasteless attire and heavy talk, that they will not unload on me what concerns only themselves, that they will not be tedious, didactic, or in- trusive, in short, that they will be trained to play the social game for general enjoy- ment rather than individual gain, I shall ALTRUISM keep away from company. Manners ex- press these doubts. They preserve an in- terval between me and those who might press too near. Emerson says of them that they are a contrivance of the wise for keep- ing fools at a distance. No doubt they may also express affection and pleasure in humankind. I only assert that this is not necessarily their meaning. They may be mere social safeguards, restraints to which each of us submits in Hobbistic fashion in order to protect ourselves. But there is one further point in our dis- paragement of manners. He who accepts the code, indorses, and practises it, finds himself in the long run enfeebled. Accord- ingly, a healthy nature is always a little restive under manners. The child rebels against being taught how to behave. He wants to behave as nature prompts. When full of glee he would laugh aloud, but is told that loud laughter in company is not proper. Is there not danger that the con- tinual check which manners put on exu- berant nature may, in the process of rub- bing off social excrescences, rub off much of nature too? How large will be the “due opportunity for self-expression” in a soci- MANNERS 29 ety whose prime aim is “the avoidance of offense”? It must be remembered that checking expression checks thought. We do not develop strong interests when mov- ing among those who stare if we mention them. In company, people may grow quick, clever, neat in repartee, compliment, and paradox, but they do not become re- flective, solid in judgment, distinctive in individual taste. Such things come more readily in isolation. It is wise advice George Herbert gives: “ By all means use sometimes to be alone. Salute thyself. See what thy soul doth wear. Dare to look in thy chest, for ’tis thine own. And tumble up and down what thou find’st there. Who cannot rest till he good fellows find He shuts up house, turns out of doors his mind.” The fact is that in bidding us all the time to be regardful of others, manners make too sharp a division between the con- junct and the separate self; and it is dis- astrous to each to be set up to the exclusion of the other. In detachment the conjunct self grows empty, the separate self surly and brutish. They belong together. When either has been unduly emphasized, it is 30 ALTRUISM wholesome to give the other a chance. Society, the special field for the cultivation of manners, would soon be sterile soil were it not abandoned during lenten intervals and summers in the country. After meet- ing a multitude of people and being obliged to adjust ourselves to only such matters as all can understand, what a relief it is to be in the open fields, social conventions dropped, responsibilities forgotten, and no regard for others marking our words, acts, or dress ! And now we see why all the words which name the ingenious system of man’s best approach to man contain a tinge of evil. Every one is a disparaging term, though meant for praise. Politeness, courtesy, good breeding, propriety, decency, civility — manners is the best of the long list, for it states with less of praise or blame the mutual consideration expected whenever person meets person. But it is not alto- gether clean. It lingers on the outside and so suggests triviality, suspicion of our neighbor, and the enfeebling of originality. That these baser qualities are not inherent in manners is true enough. A well-man- nered man may have a friendly soul. But MANNERS 31 he may have one of an opposite sort. Man- ners, therefore, though altruistic in form, are not necessarily altruistic in matter. They can, accordingly, be regarded as only the beginning of our inquiry. No human society, it is now evident, can be formed without recognizing the altruistic principle; but in manners that principle may be em- ployed as naturally for an egoistic as for an altruistic purpose. What we are in search of is a situation in which a man sin- cerely prefers another’s good to his own. CHAPTER III GIFTS Such a higher stage of altruism is that which I have called Gifts. When we give, we set ourselves in a low place and some one else in a high, so intentionally putting altruism into the matter of our action and not merely into its form. A definition of giving would therefore run as follows: the diminution by ourselves of some of our possessions, pleasures, or opportunities for growth, so that another person may pos- sess more. Every gift, to be a real gift, must cost the giver something. When I have just received an unexpectedly large payment and am feeling particularly well off, I might easily take pleasure in handing a half-dollar to a beggar. But that is an amusement, not a gift. I have experienced no loss. For both money and beggar I cared little, but the momentary sense of munificence was agreeable. The act was one of pride rather than generosity. On S2 GIFTS 33 the other hand, I give a friend a book I love, one that has deeply influenced my life and I hope may influence his. He has no means of obtaining a copy elsewhere. I shall miss it, no doubt. But remember- ing how long I have had it, and he not at all, I resolve to impoverish myself for his enrichment. The moment I hand it to him he becomes the rich man and I the poor. All ownership on my part ceases. I have cut myself off from something valu- able in order to bring about a certain superiority in him. That is the essence of a gift. To make my friend large I make myself small. It may be said, however, that such damage to the giver is unnecessary. Com- pleter giving would be that where the re- ceiver makes up to me my loss. But would not my act under such conditions cease to be a gift? It would become an exchange, a trade, a bargain. Whether a wise trade or a foolish, there was calculation directed to keeping me as well off at the close of the transaction as at the beginning. On that account no one will call it a gift. Or if, again, I expect positively to profit by what I offered my friend, finding my book- 34 ALTRUISM shelves crowded and resolved to lead a simpler life, my act once more will lack the quality of a gift. Wisely I rid myself of some superfluous possessions, but I did so quite as much for my own advantage as for that of my friend. It is true that often in whole-hearted giving we find ourselves in the end richer than before. But that was not contemplated. What we sought was impoverishment for another’s gain, and it is that purpose which constitutes a gift. As regards what is given, a few words may be well. All gifts are not of the same grade. In thinking of them we generally have in mind parting with a piece of prop- erty. But this is the slenderest of gifts. Accordingly in my definition, side by side with possessions, I named a superior sort of gift, pleasures. To detach a pleasure from myself for another’s sake, and to suc- ceed in the difficult business of transferring it from my enjoyment to his, is surely a larger gift than parting with a piece of property. Indeed, even in giving an ar- ticle, I felt the pleasure involved in it to be the important matter. Having been pleased with it myself I trusted it would GIFTS 35 bring my friend pleasure too. The article was a mere means, a subordinate part of the affair. Could I convey as much plea- sure without it, the gift would gain in delicacy. Suppose then on a beautiful afternoon, when I have been bending over my work all the morning, I am offered a ride in the country. A friend is standing beside me, and to him I turn. “You take this seat. I do not care to go. You need it more than I.” And knowing full well the refreshment that will be had, I per- suade him to take my place. Here is a gift of a higher order than a mere piece of property. Its substance is taken more di- rectly out of myself. But there are gifts higher still, for we may give sections of ourselves more im- portant than pleasure. I may allow my- self to stagnate in order that my friend may grow. In filling out his nature, let him not merely use me; let his use me up. Here altruism reaches its highest point in self-sacrifice. Yet instances of it are com- mon. In almost every home in the land something like this is going on. In many households parents are saying: “That boy shall have the opportunities which we al- 36 ALTRUISM ways longed for but could not attain. He shall go to college. A little pinching on our part will make it possible.” And so the boy goes joyously forth into an invigorat- ing world, provided by the narrowing life of those at home. Such gifts are incom- parable. They are gifts of life-blood. Or do I distort this consummate altru- ism by calling it sacrifice? At least this should be added, that true sacrifice never knows itself to be sacrifice. Joyously the parents send their boy forth and joyously accept their own narrow routine. They do so feeling that he to whom they are giving their life is inseparable from themselves. They have learned to merge their abstract isolated self in him and to conceive them- selves as living the larger conjunct life with him in his new opportunities. How exquisitely astonished are the men in the parable when called on to receive reward for their generous gifts ! “Lord, when saw we thee an hungered and fed thee, or thirsty and gave thee drink? When saw we thee sick or in prison and came unto thee ? ” They thought they had only been following their own desires. Here, then, giving seems to supersede it- GIFTS 37 self, the giver receiving quite as much as he bestows. And some such paradox is unavoidable so long as the thought of self remains properly ambiguous. Our early English moralists saw no ambiguity in it. They understood by self the abstract, unrelated individual. They were conse- quently so puzzled by benevolence as often to deny it altogether. In our age of social consciousness the puzzle has largely disap- peared. We see giving to be as natural as getting, and hardly to be distinguished from it. But it will be well before advanc- ing to criticise the higher forms of altruism to fix firmly in mind some classic state- ment of the two conceptions and once for all to see how absurd each looks from the point of view of the other. When our Lord hung upon the cross the jeering sol- diers cried: “He saved others; himself he cannot save!” No, he could not; and his inability seemed to them ridiculous, while it was in reality his glory. His true self he was saving, himself and all mankind, the only self he valued. Giving has always impressed mankind as singularly noble. Indeed, in the judg- ment of many it outclasses all other ex- 38 ALTRUISM cellence and is the only human action to call forth reverence. So nearly does gen- erosity become identified with goodness that if I should ask a man whether John Smith was good to him yesterday I should be understood to ask if he gave unselfish attention to that man’s affairs. Goodness in this sense, the disposition to give, will in the popular mind cover a multitude of sins. In how many stories have past ages taken pleasure where the robber hero, crafty, merciless, and generous, bestows upon the poor plunder taken from the rich. The man ready to give, whatever else his quality, seemed to our ancestors always to deserve admiration. We have become suspicious. There is a disposition to-day to question this whole- sale praise of giving and to suggest that it is not free from danger. Instead of promot- ing public welfare, generosity may some- times impoverish the community. It may lead people to depend on others, instead of standing on their own feet. And what a general weakening follows ! The two classes into which Society always tends to fall be- come more sharply contrasted — the rich, amusing themselves from time to time with GIFTS 39 officious charity, and the poor through ac- cepting it steadily growing more helpless and cringing. Our fathers, less studious of society than we, did not perceive these dangers, but only the evils of selfishness. They accordingly eulogized giving, what- ever and wherever it was. If a man asks for your outer garment, give him your in- ner one also. Give without calculating re- sults. Against all this a reaction has set in. It is now insisted that giving should no more be freed from rational control than any other impulse. It is too important a mat- ter to be left to caprice and pursued merely to give the giver ease. It should be scien- tifically treated. The circumstances should be studied under which gifts may be per- mitted and under which withheld. We should be clear about the proper grounds for giving. Simply because somebody takes pleasure in giving he must not be allowed that pleasure where it becomes detrimental to the community at large. Such are the questionings of our time. In studying this high form of altruism I cannot pass them by. I may fairly be asked to indicate when it will be safe to 40 ALTRUISM open the hand freely and when we had better keep it somewhat closed. As I try to classify the conditions of giving, I no- tice that two are grounded in the nature of the receiver and two in the nature of the giver; and in that order I will take them up. Obviously, the first condition to be con- sidered is the receiver’s assured need. When we see need and have the means to check it we naturally spring forward and give with reference to that particular need. If a man needs food, I do not offer him a theatre ticket; though if I found him worn with business and needing recreation such a gift would be appropriate. This adapta- tion is the important matter in all true giving. “Find out men’s wants and wills, and meet them there,” says an old poet. To give anything that happens to come into my mind is selfish and shows me un- willing to take trouble for another’s sake; that is, I am shown to lack the very spirit of a giver. The same considerations fix the magnitude of the gift. A small amount given for a large need is often useless and exasperating; a large amount for a small need, wasteful and corrupting. Wise giv- ing demands an obedient mind attentive GIFTS 41 to another’s requirements and not head- strong in insistence on one’s own way. If there is any worth in giving, to keep that giving clear of waste and make it as effec- tive as possible becomes an urgent duty. I have already distinguished three varie- ties of gift: articles of my own possession, pleasures which might be mine diverted to another, and a means of growth imparted to another at my own cost. These form successively higher stages of giving, the greatest gift of all being, in my judgment, the gift of growth. Curiously enough, Kant denounces this as immoral. Man, he urges, is a person, the only being, so far as we know, who is capable of self-develop- ment. To attempt to take away this power and substitute another’s developing agency is an intrusion. A man’s growth is the business of no one but himself. If another person can scatter a pleasure or two in his path, it is a worthy altruistic act. But for any one but himself to undertake his con- struction is presumptuous and, indeed, im- possible. In building a house we use plastic material, which has no will. But a person is essentially active, self-directed, and beyond the reach of agencies other 42 ALTRUISM than his own. When we teachers offer to make our pupils wiser, we promise what we cannot perform. Ourselves we can make wiser. To our pupils we can only offer material for their use. We may tell them that by devoting themselves to study they will reach capacious lives. But such lives we have no power to bestow. If our suggestions are rejected, we are helpless. Such is Kant’s extreme theory. But has he gone far enough? Have I any more ability to impart a pleasure? I certainly cannot pick up a pleasure and put it into another person, regardless of how it will be received. There must be co-operation. The receiver may turn it into either plea- sure or pain. Kant’s objection applies with nearly equal force against the giving of pleasures. In both cases we merely pro- vide material, subject to acceptance or re- jection, material which has proved use- ful in many previous cases. I give my friend a ticket to the theatre, bidding him enjoy himself and get the refreshment he needs. But I cannot be sure what he will get. He may be bored and wish he had stayed at home. There are great uncer- tainties in gifts, for their receivers are in- GIFTS 43 deed persons, the least calculable of all beings. A piece of property I can convey to a person with some certainty that he has received it. But whether it will mean for him what it meant for me I cannot tell. In all the best affairs of life there is risk. If the risks in offering opportunities of growth are somewhat greater than in the case of other forms of gift, the need is greater too, and the results, if accomplished, more considerable. Arrangements for gifts of this highest sort are often properly made on a vast scale. They include churches, colleges, schools, lecture-foundations, mu- seums. These are all public agencies for promoting growth. The private means are surer, family life. Yet here how often parents will offer gifts of an inferior sort, things or pleasures, careless whether they meet the needs of growth. The truest benefactor is he who is willing to disap- point or pain us if by so doing he can open doors for ampler powers. Our greatest need is for enlargement. Whoever con- tributes to that is our most beneficent giver. But human need is only one of the two claims to gifts grounded in the nature of the receiver. We should likewise pay at- 44 ALTRUISM tention to numbers. If I have a loaf of bread to give away, and all about me hun- gry persons stand, I do wrong in handing half of it to one of them for a hearty meal and putting off the others, equally needy, with a small slice. At the beginning I should have studied numbers and kept a fair distribution in mind. In these days when every mail brings us three or four demands for subscriptions to excellent causes, which we would gladly aid, the question of distribution becomes perplexing. We wish to make our gifts go as far as possible. If we are hardy and dutiful, we plan according to need and number; if weak and compliant, we meet each solicit- ing letter with a formal subscription, just enough to be counted, and feel ourselves discharged from a difficult problem. In my own experience it has been helpful to readjust slightly the conception of num- ber and to consider rather the scope of a gift. Many years ago a wealthy man in the West, who had worked his way through Harvard University, said to me that he knew there were many men at Harvard of decided worth but unable to get the full benefit of the place through lack of funds. GIFTS 45 He asked if he might leave a sum of money with me for their benefit. I was not to disclose his name, was to expend the money as if it were my own, selecting the recipi- ents quietly through personal acquaintance and giving account to nobody. I gladly assented and anticipated easy and de- lightful work in distributing bounty where need was abundant. But I soon discovered that giving money away was about as difficult as earning it. I was to make in- vestments, with returns in human power and character — called on therefore to exer- cise no less pains and sagacity than if the investment were for my own benefit. I be- lieve now that much of the money I at first gave away had been better thrown into the sea. It did little good to the one who received it, and still less to the public. I was too tender-hearted and fixed my mind too exclusively on the hardships of some particular student. Pity is dangerous stuff for a charity administrator. Gradu- ally I learned that my true object of con- sideration should not be the individual student but the community. Through the student I was to give to the public. And would that student be a good transmitter? 46 ALTRUISM That became my constant question. In studying how my gifts might get the wid- est scope, I gradually formulated the maxim to help only the strong and let the feeble sink. A merciless maxim it appears at first, and always requiring subtlety in ap- plication. But what right have I, in in- vesting property for the public good, to ignore questions of return? A powerful lawyer, doctor, business man, poet, min- ister, or public-spirited citizen brings bless- ing to a multitude, and I am allowed to share in the shaping of that blessing. Shall I withdraw funds from such a cause and invest them in stock of slender security and low interest, where they can at best only ease the discomfort of an individual? That would be to overlook the scope of my gift. I used to tell my boys that the aid was not intended for their relief, but for the relief of society to which they must carry forth heightened powers. And this, I think, should be the method in all chari- table outlay if we would give to limited means the broadest range of influence. These, then, need and numbers or scope, are the conditions of giving so far as the receiver is concerned. By studying them GIFTS 47 we learn how to proportion our gifts. Two more remain, equally important, grounded in the nature of the giver. They are his ability and his knowledge; but the former, like number, will oblige us to examine it from a twofold point of view. That we are to give only according to our ability seems almost too obvious to state; yet it is something we must never lose sight of. In making this gift shall I have enough left for that? That is our constant question. In answering it I see that ability is only another name for an already accumulated wealth. If our abil- ity to give is to be large, we must in past time, before the demand arose, have ac- cumulated stock, in which accumulation we are likely to receive small approval from anybody. Spending is showy and interesting. It has a liberal air which all commend. While engaged in it we shall not lack those who will cheer us on. But saving is repulsive and suspicious, seldom calling out praise; yet it is an absolute es- sential of subsequent giving. The wealth accumulated may be of many kinds — money, learning, sound judgment — but it must be gathered in the dark, before the 48 ALTRUISM demand for its use becomes clear. How humiliating, when need arises and the dis- position to aid is upon us, to look into our treasury and find it empty ! A perplexed soul turns to us for wise counsel and we are obliged to tell him, if we are honest, that we have never trained ourselves in careful thought and should only mislead him by random suggestions. Preparation beforehand for the numberless occasions of giving is the perpetual business of the gen- erous mind. So, at least, thought Jesus. “For their sakes I sanctify myself.” Other persons, I said, are little likely to assist us here and are perhaps justly sus- picious. Accumulation is likely enough to be prompted by selfishness. When a man withdraws from his fellows every day to his study or store, and isolated there with his own interests regards little besides inflow- ing wealth, he certainly looks self-centred, may actually be so, and should by no means complain if misunderstood. Being misunderstood is, after all, not unhealthy. Without exposing ourselves to that risk few of us can reach our full power of altru- istic service. We need to train ourselves for kindness in the long run, with some GIFTS 49 carelessness as regards the conflicting short. I have been pointing out how largely our ability to give depends on an already ac- cumulated wealth. But into ability enters one thing more, tact. Without a good sup- ply of this, giving irritates and misses its mark. But tact is a word of evil omen and has such synonyms as slyness, adroitness. I am supposed to adjust myself to the pe- culiarities of somebody in order securely to gain what he would be little disposed to give. I have studied the windings of his mind and know just the side on which to approach him. I set myself in the very best light, play on his weaknesses, and skilfully obtain much which in his unman- aged moods he would never think of grant- ing. Well, tact is often exercised in this self-seeking fashion. But that is because it is a great power, egoistic or altruistic. It may be employed with either aim. A good giver needs it no less than a selfish schemer. How many would-be givers do we know who come blundering up with gifts and drop them upon us in a way which utterly shocks and makes us unwilling to receive them. Others have taken some trouble to 50 ALTRUISM be kind, have acquainted themselves with our circumstances, have been able to out- flank our delicacies and hesitations, and so to make their gift received with the least sense of intrusion or obligation. What an exquisite fine art giving may be, and how it increases altruistic power ! But it is ac- quired with effort and will be effective only after it has become instinctive. As in the case of wealth, the gaining of it must not be postponed to the time when it is needed. That will bring merely awkwardness and disappointment. It must be accumulated beforehand. One desiring altruistic skill should be training himself perpetually: as he walks the street, as he meets an ac- quaintance, as he enters a shop, as he sits at table. Every situation affords oppor- tunity for swiftly sympathetic adjustment, for removing self-absorption and substitut- ing for it that generous imagination with- out which no gift is acceptable. A well- equipped giver, putting himself imagina- tively in the other man’s place, perceives at once how his gift may be most easily re- ceived. But besides ability, with its two branches of wealth and tact, there is a final condition GIFTS 51 grounded in the giver, that of knowledge. Of course, we cannot give properly unless we understand the case, and the larger our understanding the greater is our obliga- tion to aid. These simple truths illuminate some moral perplexities. I read a while ago of a famine in China. Crops had failed and there was wide-spread suffering. Tragic tales were reported. In the next column of the paper was an account of air- plane construction. I found both columns interesting. The same day a man I knew broke his leg. An awful affair ! I hurried to his bedside and could think of nothing else than how I might help. Then it oc- curred to me how disproportioned were my sympathies. Thousands of squalid deaths on the other side of the globe made a spec- tacular newspaper item. A broken leg next door engrossed me and called out all my resources. We have all had the experience and, on first reflection, have called our- selves selfish brutes. But I believe that is an error. Helpful sympathy waits on knowledge and proportions itself by this rather than by objective need. The suf- ferings of China are known to us only ab- stractly and in outline, and only in outline 52 ALTRUISM can our sympathies be accorded. But a case which comes under our immediate in- spection, disclosing all its significant de- tails, is a different matter and lays upon us a claim of giving which the other rightly does not. Nearness counts. Knowledge heightens obligation. I would not defend absorption in our narrow circle. I have just been urging the constant enlargement of sympathetic knowledge. But we should never ignore the fact that the unknown is not as the known and that only in propor- tion as we know can we advantageously help. Through overlooking these necessary limi- tations of human sympathy the Stoics were led to denounce patriotism. We should honor man as man. Why, then, regard an American sufferer more than a Chinese ? Because he is my countryman. But that rests philanthropy on selfishness and makes the needy person’s relation to me of more consequence than his suffering. The no- tion of patriotism which masquerades as a virtue should be denounced as a vice. All will recognize in such an argument a valu- able protest against narrowness. But few will accept the principle on which it rests. GIFTS 53 All men are not alike. Relation to me does constitute a special moral claim. Shall I treat my mother as I would any other old lady, as the apple woman at the corner? I say no; and the ground of different treat- ment I do not find in selfishness but in superior knowledge. I have known my mother ever since I was born. In early years she studied my needs and now she is my special charge. I comprehend what she requires in heart, mind, and person as I can comprehend those of no other woman. It is at least uneconomical to lay aside all this equipment for service and give her only the care a stranger might receive from me. The family tie means something. The tie of country means something. I know the habits of thought, the half-conscious turns of feeling, of my own people. In understanding a person of another nation I go about so far, and then run up against a brick wall, beyond which all is blind. This measure of possible understanding is the measure of duty. Knowledge forms one of the two conditions of giving grounded in the nature of the giver. Such are the conditions which the mod- em mind would set upon giving. Our 54 ALTRUISM fathers paid little attention to them. Giv- ing was in their eyes the crowning virtue and they were unwilling to shut it within bounds. Wherever need appeared they urged one another to meet it with chari- ty, pretty indifferent to considerations of knowledge, ability, or social result. The altruistic purpose was so admirable that it seemed to require no scrutiny in applica- tion. But we are not content to leave any- thing uncriticised and have endeavored to rationalize even giving. Not altogether with success, however. On examining closely the conditions I have assembled, certain inner conflicts will be noticed. Take, for example, the case of need; when another’s need is greatest my ability is least. Ability does not accompany need, increasing with its increase, but tends either to remain stationary or to fall behind as need grows. A somewhat similar conflict is unavoidable between knowledge and numbers. I have shown that as numbers grow large they become empty ciphers. The mind cannot grasp their human and detailed significance. Regrettable as this fact is, we had better recognize it as in- evitable, accepting as our particular charge GIFTS 55 those instances of need which lie sufficiently near for careful inspection and leaving the more vast and distant to be cared for by special experts, supplied with our means but not our ignorance. Much of our best charity must be exercised by deputy. The fact that gifts cannot be entirely rationalized suggests a doubt whether they can form more than a subordinate instru- ment for expressing altruism. By what means can their defects be remedied? To answering such questions the next chapter will be devoted. CHAPTER IV DEFECTS OF GIVING A colleague of mine, an excellent clas- sical scholar, received by bequest an ad- mirable collection of Latin authors. In the writers themselves, in the choice editions, and the appropriate bindings he took ex- treme pleasure. When talking with him about them one day I asked what he in- tended to do with the books at his death. Would he have them given to another Latinist as fine as himself? Or would he have them go to some college library where any one might use them? He said the question had often puzzled him, but he had finally decided to send them to the auction- room. They were books he had so much loved that he could not bear to have them fall into unappreciative hands. If he gave them away, what warrant had he that they would be prized? If they were sold, no- body would obtain one unless he were will- ing to get it by some sacrifice. This was not a case where generosity could be 56 DEFECTS OF GIVING 57 trusted. Probably the matter could be more wisely settled by self-interest. This instance makes evident the un- certain character of giving. However su- perior in altruistic fulness gifts are to manners, they are unfit, unless supple- mented by some other principle, to form a practical rule of fife. Let us examine them in detail and see wherein they fail to em- body complete altruism. In their very nature I find them to be exceptional, ir- rational, and condescending; and I will briefly explain each of these points. Giving is occasional and fragmentary. It cannot occupy a life. The great body of our time and attention must be directed upon individual interests. I rise in the morning after eight hours of sleep, go down- stairs to breakfast, take my walk for the needed morning exercise, on returning look over my mail and the morning paper, turn to my stu lies, to my meals, to calling on a friend. It is all egoistic. No doubt during the day I am repeatedly summoned to at- tend to other people’s affairs. Begging letters, interruptions, engagements of a public and business nature are not absent. They intervene and stand out isolated in 58 ALTRUISM my egoistic day. No doubt, too, most of my occupation with myself — in sleep, food, exercise, study — is a necessary preparation for social service. All I am urging is that social service cannot stand alone. It re- quires a large individualistic background. The care one gives to others is occasional, one might even say exceptional. In order to be able to meet it, our primary and pre- ponderant care must be given to ourselves. Such a thing as interest in altruistic giving, separate from personal gain and estab- lished as an independent guiding principle, is altogether impossible. Only at intervals comes the generous act; in general, we are busied with our own affairs. On this inseparability of egoism and altruism I received excellent instruction many years ago out of the mouth of babes and sucklings. A couple of little children, a girl of four and a boy of five years old, had just been tucked into their beds. Their mother in the next room heard them talk- ing. Listening to learn if they needed any- thing, she found them discussing one of the vast problems for which the infant mind seems to have a natural affinity. They were inquiring why we were ever put DEFECTS OF GIVING 59 into the world. The little girl suggested we might have been sent here to help others. “Why no, indeed, Mabel,” was her big brother’s reply. “Of course not; for then what would others be here for?” Pertinent reflection, putting the answer to one-sided altruism into a nutshell ! If our own affairs are worthless, why suppose they can be of worth to others? It is no kind- ness to bestow on another what has never been found good for ourselves. A gift should cost something. Something prop- erly valued by us we part with for an- other’s sake. A strong egoistic sense, then, is a condition of altruistic action. The latter cannot cover the whole of a life. No man is benevolent all the time, but ex- ceptionally, at intervals, when regard for himself may safely be withdrawn. A graver defect of giving is its arbitrary character. Our reformers have been at- tempting to rationalize charity and cer- tainly have devised methods by which some of its worst evils may be lessened. But until they stop it altogether they will not rid it of irrational wilfulness. One would say that in kind and degree my gift should answer another’s reasonable 60 ALTRUISM claim. But it never does. A just claim renders a gift impossible. Gifts come from a region outside claims, outside rational justification. They are the expression of arbitrary will. I give because I want to, and the other knows he has no right beyond my inclination to what he is re- ceiving. Were there legitimate grounds for my pretended gift it would be merely the payment of a debt and would afford no such pleasure as does the over-and- above of a gift. A clerk may have satis- faction in his salary, but his feeling on receiving his employer’s gift is something altogether different. The gift dropped from the sky. He had no idea it was com- ing. He really had done nothing to de- serve it. Others might have had it equally well, but by some fancy he had been picked out for enrichment. It is this unexpected- ness, this incalculably, which makes a gift so good. Gifts at Christmas, which have been systematized, are of a paler order. Even in these there is usually uncertainty enough left to keep them agreeable. Our regular giver may decide to give elsewhere this year, he may forget; what he will select we cannot guess. The important part of DEFECTS OF GIVING 61 the gift is not its intrinsic worth but its ex- pression of the giver’s will. Gladness over the former springs from greed, over the latter from gratitude. This arbitrary will on the giver’s part and the absence of claim in the receiver make a reasonable gift hard to conceive. To be a gift at all it must be capricious, undeserved, and only occasional. But there is a feature of giving more obnoxious than either of these two, yet no less deeply rooted in giving than excep- tionality and caprice. A gift has always something disparaging about it. It pro- fesses to honor, but deep in the heart of it there is disparagement, condescension at least. I declare another to be better than myself, preferring that he shall be the owner of something prized by me. Yet in reality I retain the superior position my- self and make the one whom I honor my dependent. Rightly did Jesus say: “It is more blessed to give than to receive.” How could it be otherwise? The giver is the wealthy man, the man of power and prefer- ence; the receiver confessedly the man of need, passive to another’s will. The very attempt, then, that I make to raise him 62 ALTRUISM up and provide him with something ac- ceptable from my store sets him beneath me. He lacks, I abound. At the very moment when turning to him I say: “I prefer you to myself and desire that you rather than I should possess this,” I am really also saying: “But by all right it belongs to me and I part with it as its and your superior.” However glad, therefore, we may be to get our wants supplied, a disagreeable taste is apt to lurk about the acceptance of a gift. A good share of humility is required of one who will be an altogether happy receiver, a contented in- ferior. Our age has discovered this and has grown restive over charity. It would seem that in past ages those who lacked the things that make life worth living stood with outstretched hands to receive them from their rightful owners, and that those who owned counted it a prerogative of their station thus to assist their inferiors. But this humble attitude of the needy is disappearing, together with many other traditions of aristocratic days. Our poorer classes now have too much self-respect to be at ease in such relations. Certainly the poor to-day are vastly better off than at DEFECTS OF GIVING 63 any other period of the world’s history, yet never more discontented. The new self- respect which has come with easier con- ditions makes them resent charity and dependence. “Give us what belongs to us,” they seem to say. “We want no benevolence. If a better living should be ours, we will take it as of right but not by favor. We stand on our own feet, acknowl- edging inferiority to no man.” This re- jection of charity on grounds of self-respect is not uncommon to-day. I have met it in administering the little trust for the benefit of students of which I spoke. And though I do not altogether sympathize with it, I see in it much to honor. Such are the possible humiliations of the receiver. But the giver is exposed to dangers hardly less. His gifts may be self- ish rather than generous. Few pleasures are greater than giving. In it we feel our power and catch a sense of the creative efficiency of our will. One often gives for the sake of indulging this self-assertion, with small regard for the receiver. Then too, while a true gift costs the giver some- thing, he who gives out of his abundance may hardly feel the loss, though feeling full 64 ALTRUISM well the glow of raising the helpless to prosperity. That glow is by no means reprehensible. It is one of our purest pleasures. “All earthly joys go less To the one joy of doing kindnesses.” But it should not be reckoned as gen- erosity. Should we not, too, in estimating the altruistic worth of gifts deduct the many seeming gifts which are prompted by shame? When asked for a subscription, I cannot well refuse and continue to hold my place in public esteem. Noblesse oblige. One must pay for dignity. It will not do, then, to assume that giving is always an altruistic act. It may be. Yet even where it is genuinely addressed to improving the condition of some needy person, the danger is not absent of lowering the independence of that other, of making him through our will our conscious inferior, and accordingly implying disparagement in our very bounty. If in giving we always keep the better end of the transaction for ourselves and hand the poorer to another, few adjustments of social life will call for more tact. DEFECTS OF GIVING 65 Yet we are all of us receivers and gen- erally manage to be such without loss of dignity. Under what circumstances may we and may we not preserve our self-respect and still take money? If a stranger pass- ing me on the street hands me a five-dollar bill, I should feel myself disgraced if it went into my pocket. If one I did not know wrote from a distant State his en- joyment of a book of mine, enclosing a check, I should return the check. If find- ing a person in distress and helping him he offered me money, I should refuse it. In- dependence is dear to most of us and we do not care to part with it on grounds so casual. This is the condemnation of “tip- ping,” that abominable practice introduced from countries more servile than ours. It cheapens him who gives and him who takes. I see only four occasions where the acceptance of money is compatible with manhood. Where misery is so abject that self-help is impossible it is no disgrace to confess inferiority and lean on a supporting arm. Only we must insist that as strength re- turns the arm be withdrawn. Permanent invalidism is an insidious danger. The 66 ALTRUISM second and best accredited ground for taking money honorably is that of money earned. Here I give as much as I receive. Each of the two parties at some cost gets what he desires and each gives with refer- ence to another’s need. No doubt there are degrees of dignity in the work done. If as a physician I sell intellectual power and special knowledge, I am naturally honored more than if as a day laborer I sell only physical exertion. But work and wages are in themselves honorable, so that if ten cents is of more consequence to me than getting my hands dirty, I am not dis- graced by blacking another man’s shoes. A third case is of almost equal impor- tance, though more complicated and more liable to error. We may accept money in trust, receiving it from an individual and returning its results to the public. I have already spoken of this in connection with scholarship aids. Aids for advanced re- search, whether from the government or private foundations, are of the same na- ture. To be selected for such aid is a high honor, justified, however, only by the re- ceiver’s proving himself a good transmitter. He should regard the money as given not DEFECTS OF GIVING 67 to him but through him and be sure that ultimately it reaches some mark other than himself. This may be accomplished by re- turning an equal sum to the source from which the aid came, by helping some other person equally needy, or by dedicating to public service powers raised by such aid from ordinary to superior rank. Equiva- lence should be brought about. In some way the one benefited should put back what he has received. If he allows it to stick in himself, untransmitted, he is dis- graced. I reserve to the last the completest ground of acceptance, love. Where love is, there is no superior or inferior, no giver or receiver. The two make up a conjunct self with mutual gain. Or shall we say that he who loves delights to think of him- self as inferior, prides himself on it, and would be ashamed not to look up in glow- ing dependence? To him, therefore, gifts bring no disparagement, but happy grati- tude. In such unabashed dependence most of us spent our early years. And if as we grew strong fewer gifts of money came to us, their place was taken by loving tokens more subtle, more pervasive, and coming 68 ALTRUISM from more sources. Possibly we may say that only love and exchange make the tak- ing of money permissible, and that my first and third grounds are only special cases of these two. It has been well said that there can be true giving only where the two parties ideally change places: the giver so putting himself in the receiver’s place that he feels the afforded relief a personal gain; and the receiver sharing the pleasure which under the circumstances the giver must feel. There is always, however, a differ- ence in the way we accept what comes by exchange and what comes by love. In the former our thought is fixed on what is re- ceived, in the latter on him who gave. Such are the characteristics of the second stage of altruism. I proposed to study that great principle from three points of view which would show the successive steps by which, without injury to the individual, it goes on to completeness. At the very beginning of life, and ever after, we are called on to pay attention to others and to subject ourselves to restrictions for their sake. We find ourselves related or con- junct beings, and on our frank acceptance of these relations our power and peace de- DEFECTS OF GIVING 69 pend. Without the restraints of manners life would be, as Hobbes said, “solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short.” But the ever-present altruism here is imperfect be- cause primarily dictated by the desire to protect ourselves. The separate self and the conjunct self are not necessarily united in manners. The form of altruism may be kept for protective purposes when there is nothing of it within. The next higher stage, however, starts from within, the giver seeking to promote another’s welfare at the cost of his own. But there is always uncertainty in accom- plishing this; it extends at best only to brief portions of life, is impossible wherever rational claim enters, and never escapes a suggestion of haughty disparagement. The trouble in both of these stages is, after all, the same. Alter and ego have been con- ceived as distinct, and getting has been separated from giving. But surely this is unnecessary. There are mutual situations in life where each of two parties is at once giver and receiver. The single self may be entirely at one with the conjunct, the con- junct with the single. Only so in mutual- ity can altruism become complete. To ex- 70 ALTRUISM plaining this curious situation I shall de- vote my remaining chapters. But before doing so I wish to turn back and make atonement for a certain erroneous light in which I have placed these earlier stages. When I was analyzing manners my read- ers must have felt that those are not the manners with which they are familiar. They have never felt the need of barriers between friends or thought of manners as a protective agency. Nor in gifts have they come upon my perplexities. Giving and receiving have seemed to them matters usual and pleasant, and no notion of su- periority or inferiority has entered their heads. No doubt this is a more frequent experi- ence than that just described. Yet my account is correct and important. It states the minimum of altruism which necessarily enters into manners, what they are when taken by themselves and unaf- fected by any higher range of our being. As soon as we become acquainted with giv- ing, it reacts on this earlier stage and fills it with new meaning. Egoistic elements are softened. Manners are used as an op- portunity for tactful giving. An atmos- DEFECTS OE GIVING 71 phere of kindness takes the place of re- straint, the formal manners I have de- scribed being reserved for formal occasions. Fortunately this higher civilization is now wide-spread. Yet we can still detect what I would call the guarded manners of some persons and set them in contrast to the generous manners of others. People of guarded manners are ever mindful of their own dignity, hold themselves somewhat aloof, and make much of punctilio. Those of generous manners are ready to spend themselves freely for the pleasure of those about them and seem able to save any oc- casion from dulness with their stores of information, wit, song, and lively anecdote. These persons look after those less accus- tomed to society and unobtrusively help them on. But even their admirable work is exceeded by those accustomed to mutual- ity. These give us no impression of wealthy persons imparting to us their stores. Their work is quieter. Their manners might be called friendly. They set every one at ease and do not so much give as share, appearing as much interested in our af- fairs as we could be in theirs. In their presence we are simpler, cleverer, and less 72 ALTRUISM provincial than we had believed ourselves to be. In a similar way, under the influence of mutuality gifts become transformed. Con- descension disappears. The favor is on both sides. A giver has enjoyed some- thing so much that he wants his pleasure shared. Will we take part with him ? There is no stooping, no handing down to one below. The two parties are on a level, joined in a mutual act. “Will you do me the favor to accept this?” is both the lan- guage and the feeling of the giver. Matters of every-day life, so familiar that we seldom reflect on them, I have attempted in the preceding chapters to analyze with something like scientific precision. By so doing I have turned them into almost un- recognizable abstractions. In closing, I should like to restore them to their right- ful color, and I have searched for a passage which might present the approach of man to man just as we daily see it, with an in- timate blending of all three varieties of altruism — pure manners, giving, and mu- tuality. In a passage from the Eighth Discourse of Cardinal Newman’s Idea of a University I find what I want, expressed DEFECTS OF GIVING 73 in language of extraordinary refinement and accuracy. It will be noticed what prominence lie gives to the negative func- tion of manners, how in depicting generos- ity he sees the danger of condescension, and how he finds the crowning excellence of manners in that self-forgetting mutuality which sets all at their ease. “The true gentleman carefully avoids whatever may cause a jar or a jolt in the minds of those with whom he is cast: all clashing of opinion, or collision of feeling, all restraint or suspicion or gloom or re- sentment; his great concern being to make every one at their ease and at home. He has his eyes on all his company: he is tender toward the bashful, gentle toward the distant, and merciful toward the ab- surd. He can recollect to whom he is speaking. He guards against unseason- able allusions or topics which may irritate. He is seldom prominent in conversation and never wearisome. He makes fight of favors while he does them and seems to be receiving when he is conferring. He never speaks of himself except when compelled, never defends himself by a mere retort; he has no ears for slander or gossip, is 74 ALTRUISM scrupulous in imputing motives to those who interfere with him, and interprets everything for the best. He is never mean or little in his disputes, never takes unfair advantage, never mistakes personalities or sharp sayings for arguments, or insinuates evil which he dare not say out. From a long-sighted prudence he observes the maxim of the ancient sage, that we should ever conduct ourselves toward our enemy as if he were one day to be our friend. He has too much sense to be affronted at in- sults, he is too well employed to remember injuries, and too indolent to bear malice. He is patient, forbearing, and resigned on philosophical principles: he submits to pain because it is inevitable, to bereavement be- cause it is irreparable, and to death because it is destiny. If he engage in controversy of any kind, his disciplined intellect pre- serves him from the blundering discourtesy of better perhaps, but less educated, minds who, like blunt weapons, tear and hack in- stead of cutting clean, who mistake the point in argument, waste their strength on trifles, misconceive the adversary, and leave the question more involved than they found it.” CHAPTER V MUTUALITY We ; have now clearly before us the two imperfect varieties of altruism. While both recognize and honor man’s relation to man, from neither is regard for the sepa- rate self excluded. Each may as well be prompted by an egoistic aim as by an al- truistic. For though in manners we mi- nutely consider how we may save another from annoyance it is always with the un- derstanding that we are thus ourselves protected. Nor does giving escape a similar self-regard. We cannot make a gift with- out implying that the receiver has no right to it, without bringing him into depen- dence, therefore, on our will as his superior. Giving, too, can only intermittently take the place of attention to our own good. It would exhaust itself otherwise. Jesus is reported to have spent thirty years in ac- quisition, less than three in benefaction. Indeed, unless we heartily valued our own possessions, pleasures, and growth we could 75 76 ALTRUISM never count them fit to constitute gifts. It is not strange, then, that to the natural childlike mind manners are unwelcome and that to the disciplined reflective mind gifts are obnoxious. It is true that these disagreeable features are softened as higher altruistic stages throw back an influence over the lower; the mind disposed to give, for example, transforming guarded manners into generous, or even if trained in mutual- ity, making them friendly and cordial. In a similar manner, where the conjunct self has taken the place of the separate the proud giver is superseded by the delicate giver. But these facts only make plain the incompleteness of manners and giving when taken by themselves, and demon- strate that altruism to be really known must be studied in that highest stage to which I have given the name of mutuality. To this intricate and important study I now turn. Giving fails to reach the altruism it seeks because its generosity is confined to one of the two parties engaged, while to the other is assigned the inferior position of egoistic receiver. But is this necessary? May we not conceive of a gift without this blemish, MUTUALITY 77 a giving in which each side gives to the other, thus joining giving and getting, and abolishing all inferiority? To show how this may be I am obliged to enter into more detail than in explaining simpler moral situ- ations. I will, accordingly, offer a gen- eral definition of mutuality and then take up the successively completer forms in which it is realized. By mutuality, then, I mean the recogni- tion of another and myself as inseparable elements of one another, each being essen- tial to the welfare of each. This duality of giving has always been recognized as en- nobling. Even Jesus did not seek simply to give, but to induce in those to whom he gave a similar disposition. Rightly is it counted higher than simple giving, includ- ing, as it does, all which that contains and more. Such mutuality is most familiar to us in certain cases which for convenience I group together under the name of partner- ship. In a partnership a specific field is marked out within which persons agree to consider certain of their interests common. When Brown and I form a firm for the sale of shoes it is understood that thenceforth 78 ALTRUISM lie and I have no separate interest so far as shoes are concerned. The stock in the store does not belong to him or to me; and if some one seeing money in the drawer should ask whose it was, I should have to answer, “It is not mine,” and Brown would similarly disown it. It would be ours. All his would be mine and mine his. Usual thought and speech would require considerable readjustment to fit a con- dition so new. “I” and “he” would pass largely out of use as no longer of practical significance, “we” taking the place of these separate symbols. “Together” would acquire a more intimate and compulsive meaning. Accordingly, if on some bright morning I were inclined to go shooting in- stead of appearing at the office at my usu- al hour, I should know I had no right to the sport without Brown’s concurrence, my time being no longer mine. Mutuality would everywhere supersede private con- trol. All this is familiar enough. Nobody finds it hard to comprehend. But when the moralist urges that higher life is possible only as the separate self becomes merged in a conjunct, it sounds mysterious and seems little likely to occur. MUTUALITY 79 But the partnership principle is wider than the business firm. In some degree it enters into every bargain. Buyer and seller establish a kind of mutuality. Sup- pose a customer on coming to my store and putting down his five dollars for a pair of shoes should suddenly bethink himself and say: “I wonder if you are not cheating me. That pair of shoes cost you not more than four dollars and seventy-five cents. By your price you are taking twenty-five cents more from my pocket than you are delivering to me.” Might I not answer: “It seems to me it is you who are cheating me. You need those shoes more than you need five dollars. You would give five dollars and a quarter rather than go with- out them. Are you not, then, returning to my pocket twenty-five cents less than you are receiving?” In reality neither of us has cheated. We have merely made a legitimate profit from one another. Such mutual profit is involved in all good bar- gaining. It yields a double gain. I gain from my customer and he from me, and both are left in better condition than be- fore. If he had not cared more for the shoes than for five dollars he would not 80 ALTRUISM have come to my store. If I had not counted five dollars of greater worth to me than the shoes I should not have parted with them. A curious situation this, where two persons draw advantage from one another ! But every sound com- mercial transaction proceeds on this as- sumption. In all honest trade there is a gainful partnership. In my last chapter, after discussing gifts, charity, and the generous soul, I promised to turn to a moral situation higher still, one of purer altruism. Are we then keep- ing to the order proposed? Can we sup- pose that a commercial transaction is of a higher order than an act of charity? I believe we can. As we look over the his- tory of civilization we certainly find gifts understood long before trade. The savage is a not ungenerous person. When he takes a fancy to any one he gives pretty freely, not, of course, through any claim or duty but merely in deference to his native feeling. What he cannot conceive is the double gift, a transaction in which each is a gainer. He is ready enough to strip himself of advantage in behalf of one whom he likes and is pleased when he, too, MUTUALITY 81 receives a gift; but that one and the same act can yield a mutual gain he apprehends slowly and rudely. Yet on just this con- dition of mutuality all honest trade is based. It is true I must add the adjective “honest.” One can deceive under the forms of trade as readily as under any other forms. They shelter deception well. In dealing with a customer I may have some special information about the quality of an article which he does not possess. He is therefore at a disadvantage. No one would maintain that all the operations of commerce are of a higher moral order than charity; but it may be said that every honest mercantile transaction shows altru- ism of a more thoroughgoing kind than a gift does. This may be made plainer by a con- trasted vice. Living long among college students and observing their natural plea- sure in all sorts of moral experimentation, I have come to believe gambling the vice most likely to wreck character. All forms of vice are bad enough. It is shocking to see a young man drunk. But drunkenness grows steadily rarer, and, after all, a drinker remains pretty much himself when the fit 82 ALTRUISM is off. I have had friends of this sort who when not in liquor showed the same in- terest in worthy things as other men. But when I see the gambling habit getting hold of a young man I despair of him. For several reasons it is unlikely he will be good for much thereafter. Seldom does a vice or virtue have only a single root. On the one hand the gambler gives up rational modes of guidance, ceases to calculate clearly, lives on the unexpected, and looks for some deliverance to drop from the sky. A hectic anxiety takes possession of him and disorganizes his life. But there are results worse still. Gambling, in con- trast with honest trade, admits only a single gain. I can gain nothing for my- self except by damaging another. I must directly seek his harm. The tradesman benefits himself through benefiting his cus- tomer. His business is grounded on the double gain. He draws profit, it is true, from another man’s pocket, but he does not, like the gambler, stop there. He puts back into that pocket a little more than the equivalent of what he took out. The gambler breaks up this mutuality and lives as a bandit by attack. Thus dehumanized MUTUALITY 83 and shut up to his separate self he rots. When trade allows the double gain to drop out of sight, it too becomes gambling and shows the same predatory tendencies. Hon- est trade is a different matter. Its mutual profit carries altruism through a community more wholesomely than can any arbitrary will. But the partnership principle runs fur- ther still. It is the cement which binds together a multitude of groups. A ship’s crew, a regiment of an army, stands in just this mutual relationship. They represent the will of no one of their members, yet no one must detach his will from the whole. A sailor cannot withdraw to-day because he feels like reading, a soldier because the coming attack is likely to cost his life. Un- der anarchic influence something like this was lately allowed the Russian soldier, and the army ceased to be. It can exist only as a conjunct affair. Our States were once supposed to have established a Union; but when South Carolina set up a separate will, regardless of the rest, chaos came. How transformed the youngster is when he goes out with the baseball team ! He does not mind if he breaks his finger, covers himself 84 ALTRUISM with dirt, or becomes utterly exhausted. What does it matter if only the team wins ? There is no longer any me. He thinks in conjunct terms. He will not shirk, take himself away and leave the others to their harm. How far can such a notion of partnership be carried? Evidently to all clubs whose members recognize themselves as also mem- bers one of another, each forming no de- cisions of his own. Would it apply to churches and learned societies? Not al- together, I think. We have hitherto meant by partnership a terminable union of speci- fied persons for a definite time and in reference to a definite end. In scientific societies, and especially in churches, we do not limit numbers and usually expect the union to be a permanent one. This in- definiteness as regards time and persons is no accident. It rightly belongs to unions like these, which aim at developing per- sonality. A baseball team, a ship’s crew, gather a specially trained company for a particular end. When this end is attained the union naturally ceases. Science and righteousness are never attained, but ap- peal without limitation. Perhaps, then, MUTUALITY 85 such internal and personal associations should not be classed as partnerships at all, but that notion should be reserved for unions of a more external and limited sort. If I am right in this, it may help to explain the hesitation many readers must have felt over my eulogy of business meth- ods as examples of altruism. Certainly we all know that commerce has a barbarous side. Nowhere else among civilized human beings does selfishness become so ruthless. The possibility of this comes through two limitations which partnership sets on mu- tuality. When Brown and I established our firm we limited the persons involved to himself and me, and even we were to have relations only so far as concerned the sale of shoes. Within these two limits mutual- ity was complete, but it did not extend beyond. Supported thus by one another, we two were able to contend with the rest of the world as neither could alone. To- gether we could push our interests with little regard to the general interests of the town. If other trades suffered, we need not care so long as the shoe business flour- ished, and still less need we care if our prosperity crowded out of existence the 86 ALTRUISM shoe store on the opposite side of the street. Such clear limitation of an altruistic horizon is always dangerous. In many restricted unions the danger is noticeable. A family warmly considerate of its own members often shows small sympathy for persons beyond its bounds. A ball club, a secret society will practise trickeries on other leagues which their members as individuals would scorn. In trade, too, the matter is made worse by a second limitation. My partner and I understand that our mutual- ity operates only with reference to the sale of shoes. We do not merge our lives. We keep a sharp line drawn between them and our business. Possibly enough I may have little respect for Brown. As a person I may think so meanly of him that when he suggests being asked to my house and meeting my wife and children I find an excuse for not inviting him. He is excel- lent so far as selling shoes is concerned, but personal relations are quite another thing. Here again the narrowing of the field with- in which mutuality operates lessens its dig- nity and intensifies its aggressive power. No wonder, then, we are apt to picture trade as a conscienceless struggle of com- MUTUALITY 87 petitors for private gain. But the picture is disproportionate and erroneous. Sav- agery is possible here, but so is much else. Commerce has a deep ethical ground and wide ethical opportunities, co-operation be- ing as essential to it as competition. It exists only through service to the commu- nity. The mutual relations of partnership are constantly being extended, single trades organizing to promote their common in- terests, and chambers of commerce over- seeing the business of a whole city. Those who engage in trade are no less human beings than their fellows and are continu- ally discovering that honorable and high- minded methods of conducting business are in the long run profitable. The very com- petitions that arise are useful promoters of efficiency, and the general government stands ready in the background to fix limits beyond which greed shall not go. There are, in short, many circumstances in the life of trade which to a good degree neutralize the limitations which I have pointed out in its application of the prin- ciple of mutuality. That principle, too, runs far beyond the field of partnership. Partnership brings 88 ALTRUISM persons into mutual relations only with reference to certain external ends. Brown and I joined only those fragments of our lives which were connected with the sale of shoes. We might join extensive portions, might merge not merely our occupations but all our personal interests. In him I might discover what contributes to my best growth and he find no less in me. In this way we should reach a new species of existence to which the definition of mu- tuality previously given would apply in a higher sense. I should here recognize an- other and myself as more completely con- stituent members of one another, each be- ing essential to the welfare of each. Here no new elements enter which were not in- cluded in partnership. There as here identi- fication of interests appears, the abolition of mine and thine, the double gain; only here there is no restriction of the field. The lives are identified throughout their full depth and extent. They do not merely collaborate for a specific purpose. Such is the attitude of love, so familiar, so mysterious, so potent in developing whatever is best in us. In it both egoism and altruism have ample room. If I loved MUTUALITY 89 Brown, I should not hesitate to own that I sought him for my own advantage, though I should also bid him to take of me all he wanted — the more, the better. And I should expect the same double response from him. Edmund Spenser has stated the matter with great precision in his “Hymn in Honor of Beauty”: “For love is a celestial harmony Of likely hearts composed of stars’ consent. Which join together in sweet sympathy To work each other’s joy and true content, Which they have harboured since their first de- scent Out of their heavenly bowers, where they did see And know each other here beloved to be.” Spenser intends by “harmony” what I have meant by mutuality, something where several different parts belong together and reach their full significance in union. If the two hearts are similar and each merely re- peats what the other contains, there is no mutual profit. They must fit one another, and in this fitting there is always some- thing of the unknown. They cannot of themselves entirely create the union. The “stars’ consent” must be added. Heaven 90 ALTRUISM must shine upon them. Spenser even sug- gests that their adaptation to one another is not begun in this world, but is merely recognized here as having been ever of old. Once known it brings them full content. This, then, is the topic to which we now turn. It is that which the ethical teachers of every age have counted fundamental. With Jesus it supersedes all else. Writers as unlike as the Catholic statesman Au- gustine, the Jew Spinoza, the Puritan Jona- than Edwards see in love the fulfilment of righteousness. “Love God and do as you please,” says Augustine. It is something we all experience and few understand. In it there are paradoxes not found elsewhere. Delicate analysis will be needed to bring out all that it involves, to show, too, how even here limitations creep in. To this puzzling and attractive work I devote the next chapter. CHAPTER VI LOVE In the Symposium of Plato Socrates is made to say that he can profess knowledge of only a single subject, love, but that through acquaintance with this he has a key to unlock all wisdom. And certainly if Socrates understood love he deserves to be reckoned among the wise. Few have looked into it soberly. To those who are not experiencing it, it is a jest; to those who are, a blind passion. Novelists exploit it for cash; poets, on the whole its most serious students, too often for graceful fancies. Saint Paul’s compact sentences give more of its substance than can be had in the same compass elsewhere. In under- taking an analysis of it I believe I can best fix attention on its more important ethical features if I ask a series of simple questions about it and then develop their compli- cated answers. (1) How does love differ from liking? Quantitatively. The degree of emotion ex- 91 92 ALTRUISM pressed by love is out of all proportion to that of liking. I love my friends and like their surroundings; I like this gift and love the giver. An exchange of terms in either of these sentences would make moral nonsense. Liking touches only the sur- face; I like strawberries. Loving goes all through; I love my old servant. Of course, then, loving includes liking, though liking may or may not be accompanied by loving; and equally, of course, loose talkers, who do not know what they mean, will try to be impressive by using the weightier word. I love automobiling, I love the opera, I love ice-cream; these are all forms of silly exag- geration which no one will seriously defend. But there is a reason for this quantita- tive difference. An additional factor enters into love and greatly increases its depth. Love always implies the possibility of the loved one’s knowledge and his capacity for response. It is applicable therefore pri- marily to persons and the higher animals, and only in a metaphoric way suits things. No doubt the response often fails, but it is always desired and sought. Love seeks to establish a personal tie. No one ever loved without wishing to be loved. LOVE 93 Furthermore, between love and liking there is a sharp contrast of mental attitude. In liking, my thoughts are on myself; in loving, on another. I like whatever brings me pleasure or profit. But Browning rightly asks: “How can one love but what he yearns to help ?” That is, what we love always seems to us to have such worth as calls on us for protection and the offering up of ourselves. To the lover it appears august, superior, and supplemental to any- thing possessed by himself. It fills him with awe and a spirit of sacrifice. Spenser addresses his lady as “My dear dread.” There is nothing of this in liking. Our thoughts are there fixed on ourselves, heedless of the condition of whatever fur- nishes us profit. Oxen we like, because they supply our tables and till our fields. What matter if in doing so they perish? We tend the dog we love and do not let him be harmed in our service. In short, loving is our forthgoing toward one pos- sessing a worth preferred above our own; liking, our feeling toward anything from which we derive benefit, even though in- ferior in general worth to ourselves. On account of this difference love can- 94 ALTRUISM not be confined to persons. Seeing a little girl tending her rose-bush and asking her if she likes it, I shall probably receive the indignant reply: “No, I love it.” She means: “I think as much about giving to it as of getting from it.” It would be im- proper to ask a painter, a scholar, if he likes his work. If he follows it for gain he is untrue to it; he can really succeed only when he loves it, i. e., gives himself heartily to it. In many cases, therefore, where profit is abundant, it would be a kind of impiety to speak of liking. I like my mother, I like God. Certainly ! None gives ampler ground for liking. But for that very reason my mind should be set on the appropriate outgo in return. How- ever much the patriot may like his coun- try, i. e., recognize the opportunities it af- fords for life, he loves it more. Perhaps in all these cases where impersonal beings are loved we inwardly attribute personal- ity to them and feel that we receive from them as much love as we give. For that is an essential in love: it con- templates mutuality. The loved one looks up to the lover as truly as the lover does to the loved. Each counts himself inferior and only through the other capable of pos- LOVE 95 sessing worth. “She is my essence and I leave to be, if I be not through her fair influence,” says Shakespeare’s Valentine; and had love reached its completion, Sylvia would have expressed no less. This double action is characteristic of love, while liking has only a single end. If we will speak ac- curately, then, we shall acknowledge that the real object loved is neither member of the pair but just this mutuality, the “to- getherness,” which blots out regard for any separate self and fills each with passion for the conjunct. “To the desire and pursuit of the whole the name of love is given,” says Plato in the Symposium. In his “Clasping of Hands” George Herbert charmingly develops the puzzling reciproc- ity of love when he tries to comprehend his relation to God: “Lord, thou art mine, and I am thine If mine I am; and thine much more Than I or ought or can be mine. Yet to be thine doth me restore. So that again I now am mine, And with advantage mine the more, Since this being mine brings with it thine. And thou with me dost thee restore. If I without thee would be mine, I neither should be mine nor thine. 96 ALTRUISM Lord, I am thine, and thou art mine; So mine thou art that something more I may presume thee mine than thine. For thou didst suffer to restore Not thee, but me, and to be mine. And with advantage mine the more; Since thou in death wast none of thine. Yet then as mine didst me restore. Oh be mine still ! Still make me thine ! Or rather make no thine and mine !” Of course such a poem can have only two stanzas, and these must closely parallel each other in every part. The resulting definition of love, making it the completed form of mutuality, would run as follows: love is the joint service of a common life. (2) Is the lover, then, an unselfish person and does altruism, here reaching its high- est pitch, exclude all egoistic regard? On the contrary, it includes and magnifies it. I have said that love always involves lik- ing, the knowledge that an object has brought me gain and is capable of bringing more. In his loved one the lover knows a source of incomparable joy. Were his lady once his, it would matter little what else might happen. Never before has he con- ceived a good so great, and he knows that LOVE 97 hardships shared with her would be better than the most favorable fortune alone. He is therefore an eager seeker. Such a pas- sion to possess is seen in no one else. Yet the opposite may be said with equal truth. He has lost all selfishness. No one is so generous as he, so ready for self-sacrifice. To please and benefit the loved one is all his care. Let what he gives have cost him little, and he is dissatisfied. He longs to suffer for her sake. These are not marks of self-seeking. But they do indicate that the lover has reached a new conception of self, for which he is even more ardent than ever he was for the old. That old separate self he now despises, and knows that only as he loses it in the loved one will he have any worth. Until he has thoroughly cut himself off from his own detached interests he will be unworthy of her. A scrap of Persian verse, translated by Bronson Al- cott, states the matter well: “One knocked at the beloved’s door, and a voice asked from within, ‘Who is there?’ And he an- swered, ‘It is I.’ Then the voice said, ‘This room will not hold me and thee’; and the door was not opened. Then went the lover into the desert, and fasted and 98 ALTRUISM prayed in solitude. And after a year lie returned and knocked again at the door. And again the voice asked, ‘ Who is there ? ’ And he said, ‘It is thyself.’ And the door was opened to him.” In the mu- tuality of love egoism and altruism are reconciled. Each of the lovers acquires a new apprehension of self, which conjunct being bears in the mind of each the name of the beloved. (3) Is the lover in his own estimate rich or poor? Incredibly rich in what he has received, but in comparison with his lady how poor ! She is immeasurably his su- perior. How she stooped so low is his daily wonder. But his own inferiority does not disturb him. “Love envieth not. Is not easily puffed up.” On the contrary, he rejoices in emptying himself and seeing how all that is worth while in him proceeds from her. Yet the lover is a paradoxical fellow, full of contradictions and scorning consistency. He prizes himself as he never did before and daily takes on a new im- portance. Never till he loved was he so watchful of his looks, speech, clothes, manners. What he brings to her must be of the finest, and he is pleased to discover LOVE 99 in himself excellences hitherto unsuspected which she may well accept. Tennyson well paints the aspiring lover in “Maud”: “So dark a mind within me dwells, And I make myself such evil cheer That if I be dear to some one else Then some one else may have much to fear. But if I be dear to some one else. Then I should be to myself more dear. Shall I not care for all that I think. Yea, even for wretched meat and drink. If I be dear, if I be dear, to some one else?” (4) When once established, is love per- manent ? Certainly not. Being a per- sonal affair it has no routine fixity, but must continually be created afresh. Effort is in it, intention, readiness to put aside temporary fancies and to practise a loyal patience. It is true that in the wise these practices themselves become habitual and love therefore a matter of happy course. No action is excellent which ceases when not consciously pressed. From the quiet of assured love old lovers look back on the anxious fervors of early days and acknowl- edge them meagre and immature. Yet still within call they keep the resolute will 100 ALTRUISM and guard against decay. For just as my readers find it difficult to hold the thought of the conjunct self steadily in mind and are obliged to resist its tendency to disin- tegrate into separate selves, so do lovers also. By degrees the sense of mutuality may decline, independent interests arise, and then one of the lower altruistic forms may take the place of this its highest. A pair may feel themselves drawing apart and, finding less and less in common, may gradually content themselves with a kind of partnership in place of love. Or one, dis- turbed over the breach of affection, may seek to repair it by acts of generosity. He may be liberal in granting his company, his friendly cheer, to the slightly distant loved one. But that, too, is a slipping down. The two are then no longer in equality. Perfect love knows no giving. What is there to give? All mine is thine, all thine is mine. Together we share, not give. But as we detach ourselves little by little, the old separate self comes back and we hand something across the chasm. How sad when exuberant love thus declines into intentional giving, altering “because it alteration finds and bending with the re- LOVE 101 mover to remove”! But sadder still is it when to formerly abundant love the guarded altruism of manners succeeds and each is satisfied to treat the other with watchful politeness. This is the last stopping-place before confessed bankruptcy. (5) But is not love always open to re- pair through duty ? Being the highest embodiment of morality it would naturally seem peculiarly alive to duty. But the very opposite is the case. It has, in fact, a strange aversion to duty. Any suspicion that we are expected to love a certain per- son alienates us from him. We cannot force ourselves to love even when we see it to be desirable; nor can we expel love when we find it unreturned or unworthy. Love insists on freedom, a certain absence of constraint, either from a person, from circumstance, from collateral advantages, or even from our own volition. Like giving, it recognizes no claim. “Love is a present to a mighty king,” says Herbert. It can- not be bought or sold. But though so lit- tle submissive to obligation, it is highly sensitive to suggestion and unclamorous appeal. Indeed, it soon perishes when fresh suggestion is withheld. Indirectly, 102 ALTRUISM therefore, and accepting time for an ally, we can control love. I have repeatedly spoken of intention, rational guidance, re- sourceful care, as necessities if we would have a wise and lasting love. Those who complain of its decay have generally them- selves to blame. They have imagined it constituted once for all and, while they would be glad to have it continue, have taken little pains for that fresh renewal on which its life is staked. “Keep on court- ing,” said a sagacious mother to a young bridegroom on his wedding-day. And what has here been said of marital love applies also, with adaptations, to the love of God and the love of our fellow men. No- where will love submit to the direct com- mand of duty. But indirectly, gradually, through suggestion and considerate modes of approach, it is well within our control. The Golden Rule, bidding us love God and our neighbor, is not a psychological blunder. (6) How does friendship differ from love? Like love, it differs from partner- ship through having an entirely personal basis. Within its limits partnership is as genuinely mutual as love itself, but its mutuality refers to ends outside the per- LOVE 103 sonal lives. These remain detached and individual, merely co-operating for a time to accomplish an external purpose. In both love and friendship the personalities merge. Their interests become identified, so that one of the parties without the other is but a fragmentary being. But friendship differs from love in the degree of intensity of its emotion and in the extent of the tract of life covered. In these respects it more nearly resembles liking. We all know how slight a friendly feeling may be, even when entirely genu- ine. This is because of the well-recognized limits of friendship, limits sometimes nar- row, sometimes broad. I take John for my friend on account of his wit, James for his scholarship, Henry for discussion of art, Charles for theology. Outside these mat- ters we have little in common. If I try to introduce these friends to other sides of me, I know that our friendship would be strained. Love knows no such limits. In it there is no holding back. There the more we give the more we have. Not that in friendship we set up such limits by our own volition, as is done in partnership. The limits are ingrained in the persons, 104 ALTRUISM and beyond them we know it is futile to press. When two natures have certain sides that fit, to the advantage of each, a friendship springs up. But how embarrass- ing when some friend whom we greatly value has limitations which oblige us to pause and he, not perceiving them, at- tributes to our adverse will the failure in full mutual accord ! Because of its narrow bounds and because it is sought for in- dividual gain, friendship is of far wider currency than love. We make and drop our friendships with comparative ease, hardly from the first expecting them to be lasting. But a love to which we contem- plated an end, either in extent or duration, would be already ended. The Greeks justly eulogized friendship as our best se- curity in an uncertain world. And, ob- viously, he is imprudent who does not sur- round himself with a protecting band of friends. Let me, in closing this section, call at- tention to these varieties of personal con- tact, all of which are desirable. We all need a multitude of acquaintances, can, indeed, hardly have too many. These are persons whose faces and names we know. LOVE 105 with something of their occupations and history. While we know them only on the outside our impressions of them are favor- able, and their nod, smile, or passing greet- ing brightens the moment and makes us feel at one with our species. These do not attain the rank of friends, to whom we ex- pose sections of our lives, in whose char- acters we see admirable traits which are less developed in ourselves, and on whom we lean in times of doubt, trouble, and ignorance. Such steadying friends will not be a large company and should be chosen deliberately, not through juxtaposition, but on grounds of merit and adaptation to our needs. Closer than these, however, should come our intimates, one or two, those to whom we give whole-hearted love. From such an intimate we hide nothing, not even our faults. To him we express our half- thoughts, make up our minds in company with his, find excellence easy in his pres- ence and yet, to our daily astonishment, see that he obtains as much from us as we from him. Him we love. He is another self, and all that is ours is his also. Such, then, is love and such its varieties and shadings. Parted from mutuality, al- 106 ALTRUISM truism has little worth. Only where love is, where the conjunct self has taken the place of the separate self, is altruism com- pletely realized. In such love morality at- tains its goal. Accordingly, in every age those most impassioned for the formation of character have exalted love as its cen- tral principle. The first to perceive its importance and to begin an exploitation of its labyrinths was Plato. To love he has dedicated three of his Dialogues. In the first of them, the delightful little piece called Lysis, he busies himself with the contradictions of love. He does not seek to establish a positive doctrine. No con- clusion is reached, but the enigmatic char- acter of love is brought out with extraor- dinary vividness. The greatest of his love dialogues, and one which has profoundly influenced all subsequent ages, is the Sym- posium, beautifully translated by the poet Shelley under the name of The Banquet. Socrates and his friends assembling one evening, it is proposed that instead of general conversation they shall talk on some specific subject, and love is selected. One speaker after another reports what he has seen in love — its dignity, its heavenly LOVE 107 and earthly types, its universality as an underlying principle of physical nature, the supposed origin of the separate self and its subsequent desire for completion, love as the organizer of human life. Then Socrates points out how the true signifi- cance of love lies in its passion for perfec- tion and how it continually supersedes its lower forms in the interest of what is larger. The most obscuring of these lower forms, the least regardful of anything beyond it- self, is that instinctive passion between the sexes which tries to monopolize the name of love. Friendship is more intelligent. Unities of a still wider and firmer kind are disclosed in the social, artistic, and scien- tific impulses. These are all prompted by love and follow increasing grades of beauty. Religion, however, alone reveals the full significance of these struggles toward con- junction; for God is the only complete wholeness, and every endeavor to unite with other things or persons is but a blind seeking after him. Love appears once more in the Phcedrus, where its deeper implications are traced in connection with rhetoric and general philosophy. At the time of the Renaissance Mar- 108 ALTRUISM cilius Ficinus translated the Symposium of Plato and carried its influence into all the literatures of western Europe. Edmund Spenser reflects that influence in his two superb hymns in Honor of Love and in Honor of Beauty. A vivacious modern statement of the ancient doctrine is that of R. W. Emerson in his Essay on Love; and an amusing disparagement of love, as that which interferes with the comforts and conveniences of the separate self, ap- pears in Bacon’s Essay on Love. It has been well said that any one who imagines Shakespeare’s plays were written by Bacon should read this essay and follow it with Romeo and Juliet. Of course, all the poets linger in the neighborhood of love and de- clare it to be that which makes the world go round. One of them, the mid-Victorian Coventry Patmore, made himself its ex- positor and devoted his entire product to the systematic analysis of its every phase. Perhaps to heighten the impression of ve- racity, he has made the verse of his early volumes, entitled The Angel in the House, approach as nearly as possible to prose, while his later volume. The Unknown Eros, treats the same matter in a series of rap- LOVE 109 turous odes. Admiring them both as I do in an age when they are both out of fash- ion, I take up The Angel in the House when in a psychological mood I am not disturbed by absurdity, and turn to The Unknown Eros when my ear craves music and I wel- come the Platonic madness. CHAPTER VII JUSTICE Before advancing further it may be well to survey the tangled ground already traversed ; for in mutuality, the third great section of Altruism, I have not been able to employ the simple treatment which Manners and Giving received. The prin- ciple throughout is precise and uniform. Within a specified field the interests of two or more persons are to be accounted iden- tical, so that a double gain becomes possible, altruism transforming itself into egoism and egoism into altruism. This is the com- mon principle which shapes every form of mutuality. But the extent of the fields specified differs so widely as to give rise to forms of very unlike moral value, which deserve separate examination. In the field of partnership, for example, it is understood that the union will not continue indefinitely and that it has been no JUSTICE 111 brought about for attaining some external end. Partnership, bargaining, voluntary- association would not come into existence were it not for the prospect of mutual gain. If one party alone gains, we see that some unfairness has occurred. Yet because in these unions mutuality is restricted to a small group and to the accomplishment of external purposes, they often become en- gines for a selfishness more intense than their separate members would approve. A popular proverb exaggerates but little in saying that corporations have no souls. But such perilous restrictions are un- necessary. There can be mutuality with- out them. Instead of referring to an ex- ternal end, unions can be formed for an internal purpose. The very lives and as- pirations of two persons may be joined. That is unnecessary in business relations. I may dislike my partner personally, yet judge it wise to identify my commercial interests with his. When I make a pur- chase at a shop I do not inquire about the character of the dealer. With that I have no concern. His life is his, mine mine. Our mutual relation touches only the value of the article purchased. And something ALTRUISM 112 similar is true of our voluntary associa- tions. I join my political club in the hope of furthering public interests; but, to tell the truth, I am often ashamed of my as- sociates there. We have a common aim, but personally I will keep myself as clear from my fellow workers as possible. Un- der none of the conditions which I have called partnership do lives merge. To these unions for definable ends a termina- tion is sometimes set, sometimes indefi- nitely anticipated. Now, in the case of love, these restric- tions are done away. Accordingly the whole principle of mutuality comes out there with a lucidity, power, and moving appeal which it cannot possibly have in the briefly planned arrangements of trade. For though love often passes away, no such cessation is contemplated. The eternal vows of lovers have always been a subject of jest. No doubt limited marriages have been proposed. But I suspect if they ever come about, what we mean by love will be omitted. It would strike most of us as absurd for me to ask Mary to join me in identifying our lives for a single year, sharing during that time our home, our JUSTICE 113 aims, our inmost thoughts, but always in- tending at the end of that time to go our separate ways, unable to say “we.” Ex- ternal relations can be formed, dropped, and resumed, the persons involved re- maining unaffected. That is not true of interior relations. These fashion a new personality to which old forms of morals, even old forms of language, no longer ap- ply. Before advancing to explain as my final topic the special modifications of mu- tuality which fit it for a world principle, let me sum up the whole doctrine of love in some majestic lines attributed to Shake- speare. In 1601 a curious book appeared called Chester's Love's Martyr, containing a poem to which Shakespeare’s name was affixed. This single fact, and the unlikeli- hood that any one else had such com- pulsive power over words, are our only grounds for thinking Shakespeare wrote the piece. It is entitled “The Phoenix and the Turtle,” and allegorically describes the fu- neral of a pair of married lovers, the man denoted by the turtle, the woman by the phoenix. I quote only the funeral chant, omitting the picturesque introduction and the solemn ending: ALTRUISM “Here the anthem doth commence; Love and constancy is dead, Phoenix and the turtle fled In a mutual flame from thence. So they loved as love in twain Had the essence but in one. Two distincts, division none, Number there in love was slain. Hearts remote, yet not asunder. Distance, and no space was seen ’Twixt the turtle and his queen: But in them it were a wonder. So between them love did shine That the turtle saw his right Flaming in the phoenix’ sight; Either was the other’s mine. Property was thus appalled, That the self was not the same. Single nature’s double name Neither two nor one was called. Reason, in itself confounded, Saw division grow together. To themselves, yet either — neither. Simple were so well compounded That it cried how true a twain Seemeth this concordant one ! Love hath reason, reason none, If what parts can so remain.” JUSTICE 115 What audacity of word and precision of thought ! With what accuracy the para- doxes of love are stated ! “To themselves, yet either — neither.” In the first stanza the sacred word “mutual” is introduced. Where else in our language is the conjunct self so completely set forth ? Yet we cannot pause even here. To make love a principle capable of universal application, it will need to be reconsti- tuted and, while retaining its mutuality, to be stripped of sundry restrictions. For love is ever selective. It chooses one and leaves another. It is exercised only toward definite persons, a little group, pref- erably two. The smaller the number the warmer the love. But what we are trying to discover is how altruism may penetrate the whole of life, organizing society and the state. That was our ambitious ideal, and love is not comprehensive enough for it. When we give ourselves up to the single person or small group fitted to re- ceive our love, will there not be the same danger as appeared in the discussion of partnership, that the rest of the world will be shut out ? A pair of lovers is notorious- ly unpleasing to everybody except them- 116 ALTRUISM selves. In that little world of theirs they are so engrossed with the joint service of a common life that what happens in the needy world beyond is hardly noticed. Love of this sort is pretty far removed from universal altruism. Nor is this danger confined to the pas- sion of man for woman. Broader types of love show the same exclusive absorption. Each member of a household may be de- voted to the rest and find his own gain through devotion to theirs. Here love at- tains a peculiarly beautiful mutuality. But it is still circumscribed. The family be- comes sufficient for itself. Other families do not count. Love has been selective and, fixing its ardor on certain persons, shuts out the rest. Even the love of God and his children may narrow itself to interest in those only who approach him in the same way as ourselves. Our religious sym- pathy may not extend beyond our sect. Similar perils beset national love or pa- triotism. No doubt in all these cases the narrower field may provide training for the broader; but so long as love is selective and waits upon personal interest it will be hard JUSTICE 117 pressed by conditioning accident. Rightly does Spenser declare that for the combina- tions of love the stars’ consent is necessary. Circumstance, juxtaposition, plays a large part at the beginning of love. The one who would interest me may not happen to come my way; and I cannot love one whom I do not know. Obtaining such knowledge, too, even in regard to one very near, is uncertain business. I see some one who calls out what is best in me and am con- fident that joining with her will bring about a glorious life for us both. But can I be sure ? An error in estimating will ruin not me alone but her too, whom I would honor. Knowledge, an important con- dition of love, is hard indeed to obtain. Nor in reckoning the hindrances to love as a universal principle can we pass by the mysteries of temperament. Many a per- son have we known to be lovable whom we could never love. Peculiarities of in- heritance, training, habit, instinctive feel- ing in two persons, while not diminishing their worth, may render hopeless their adaptation to one another. Selective love, then, hampered by its need of acquaintance, nearness, and knowl- 118 ALTRUISM edge, can never become a universal prin- ciple, binding mankind together. It shows, however, what we want. Nowhere else does altruistic fervor attain such depth. But it lacks breadth and is possible only within narrow bounds. We have been seeking to extend mutuality, the double gain, the abolition of both egoism and al- truism, far beyond those bounds and reach a method by which mankind as a whole might engage in the joint service of a com- mon life. Such an ideal would preserve all characteristics of love except its limitations. But the removal of these will affect it so deeply as to oblige a new name. I call it J ustice. Let us examine a case where mutualistic conduct shows traits beyond the reach of selective love. I go to a shoemaker and ask for a pair of shoes. He hands me a pair, I pay his price, and carry them home. As I come to wear them, I find them ad- mirably made. They give me greater com- fort than I have ever had before and wear longer. The leather appears to have been selected with care, and every nail and stitch to have received attention. I return to their maker and say: “That was a remark- JUSTICE 119 able pair of shoes. Did you make them specially for me ? Perhaps you have known me before, have taken a fancy to me, and so have been willing to put yourself to all this trouble for my convenience. That is the way with love. It takes burdens on itself to relieve another.” How astonished the dealer would be at such talk ! Would he not answer: “I had no thought of you, but I made the shoes as well as I could. It is my business.” “But,” I continue, “if you never know to whom your shoes will go, why take such pains?” “Because I mean to be true to my job and not shirk my part in the ongoing of the world. If I do bad work somebody, I don’t know who, will suffer. I mean to be a good shoe- maker.” Here is professional responsibility. The man deals justly with his unknown public. And in such professional responsibility we pass from individual love to that noble public love which I have ventured to call Justice. Love remains, but it is now uni- versal love, love freed from selection and without those restrictions of knowledge, circumstance, and temperament on which selection is based. No doubt in individual 120 ALTRUISM love there is an intimacy and a wealth of feeling which this case has not. But in it selfishness is also more pronounced. Know- ing John well, I am confident that in join- ing my life with his, and with his only, we shall both be enriched. But the shoe- maker carries his blessing to the unknown and joins himself rather with the public good. He gets his gain by giving gain to those whom he has never seen. It is true that the transaction may be partly ex- plained on the grounds already noticed. An exchange has occurred by which buyer and seller have alike profited. But some- thing more than calculation of profit has gone into these shoes. They would have sold readily with half the care. But this man respected business standards, was something more than a trader, gave not by equivalent measure, and was more con- cerned over possible danger to his cus- tomers than over extra labor for himself. That is the essence of professionalism. While frankly seeking mutual gain and de- clining anything one-sided, it abandons all thought of exact equivalence, keeping in the foreground standards of excellence approved by its group and looking to public service. JUSTICE 121 Or is there in the professional man some- thing still deeper than the characteristics just mentioned, something of which these are but the outgrowth? The professional man enjoys his work and would rather do it than not. Many of us, perhaps most, are driven to work by the need to live. We will do that work faithfully and not disappoint those who depend on us. But we often think of work as toil, do as little of it as possible, and find our enjoyment quite out- side it. Days of freedom from that toil are eagerly anticipated. How different is the professional spirit ! It took up its work originally not as a task but as a chance to gratify a personal interest. To following that interest through all its wind- ings its heart has been given. Throughout there has been a passion for perfection, never realized, never abandoned. Each day carries accomplishment forward and discloses wider ranges into which skill might extend. Hardship, lack of gain, failure to be recognized are matters of slender consequence. The work itself is its own rich reward. Such is professional responsibility at its best. It is responsibility to no individual. 122 ALTRUISM not even so much to the general public as to the profession chosen. Perhaps we catch the spirit most readily among artists and scholars, who proverbially show little regard for financial results. But even where regard for money is patent and necessary, this professional spirit is often also present. I am ill and call a physician. He comes to my bedside day by day, studies my case with elaborate care, gives up large amounts of precious time to my whims, and never allows his moods to intrude, so that on my recovery I cannot help saying: “What a sympathetic person you are ! I do not see how you can hold an interest in so many people and feel their afflictions as if they were your own.” Such a remark would be as inadequate as if I had said: “You have thoroughly earned your fee.” Both would be true, and both would point to motives which might rightly influence him. But into that complex motive would go a third factor more influential still, if he was a worthy physician. He cares for the healing art. Of course he is unwilling that I, this individual person, should suffer. But it is not the “me” element nor the JUSTICE 123 money element which made him take his trouble. He would have done the same for a stranger. And this impartial attitude is, on the whole, best. Personal sympathy is often disturbing. Let him coolly survey me as a case of typhus fever, and I shall get his best service. Through me he re- lieves suffering, obtains for himself a due income, gains larger knowledge of disease and skill in combating it; in short, meets the responsibilities of an arduous and in- teresting profession. One may wonder why I call this imper- sonal extension of love Justice. Because justice seeks to benefit all, but all alike. It knows no persons, or rather it knows every one as a person and insures each his share in the common good. All the altru- ism of love is here, but without love’s ar- bitrary selection and limited interest. We do wrong in thinking of justice as chiefly concerned with penalties. These are in- cidental, inflicted on those who refuse to find their gain in the gain of others. The main work of justice is its equal distribu- tion of advantage and its insistence that each individual shall be faithful to what he undertakes for the benefit of all. Justice 124 ALTRUISM is therefore thoroughgoing love, its mu- tuality guarded, rationalized, stripped of personal bias, and brought near us through the avenues of our special work. Only we must not confine the professions to the four usually reckoned: teaching, preaching, medicine, and the law. The professional spirit may vitalize work of every sort. Here is a poor man to whom few enjoyments are open, who goes out morning after morning to shovel gravel or to engage in some other labor equally un- interesting. He earns his two or three dollars a day, takes it home, and hands it to his slatternly wife. Once he was drawn to her by romantic love. With her he figured a real union, each continually happy in the sight of the other and each day bringing to both an inward joy. He did not know her. He had neither the op- portunity nor the ability to study her temperament and learn whether it was ad- justable to his. It proved not to be so. Children came, cares increased, she neg- lected herself, her home, her husband. There was no longer any warmth of affec- tion between them. But still he goes on working for her unmurmuringly. She is a JUSTICE 125 wife and mother, he a husband and father. To these relationships he will be faithful. Is not his a larger love than that of the courtship? I do not see that we can say so. But it is love of a different sort and a very noble sort. We called love the joint service of a common life. Though she no longer joins him, he joins the community in maintaining the family tie. What keeps him going is his professional responsibil- ity. Being a good husband is the task as- signed him in the general division of labor. He recognizes its justice, controls his tem- per, and patiently meets the hardship in- volved. I cannot see how there is less pro- fessional responsibility here than in the case of the shoemaker or physician. Indeed, wherever any one is true to his specific task, puts his heart into it, works not for money alone nor through interest in a sin- gle individual, but, without calculating any equivalence between what he gives and re- ceives, studies how he may most fully per- form the work to which he has been called, that man is exhibiting professional re- sponsibility, honoring love, and exalting justice in a way to deserve profound rev- erence. CHAPTER VIII CONCLUSION Love is so often proclaimed as a social panacea that I have thought it well to subject it to a careful criticism and indi- cate its defects when regarded as a com- plete embodiment of altruism. Some of those defects are incidental. Since it is an affair of human beings it cannot fail to show the imperfections characteristic of such wayward creatures. Seldom does even marriage, love’s best opportunity, attain that full mutuality which I have eulogized. Self-assertion intrudes early. The inter- ests of one or the other party become pre- dominant, and mutuality gradually de- clines. When the simple-minded man was told that in marriage two persons become one, he naturally enough asked: “Which one?” Yet if the completely conjunct life is rare, it is precious as an ideal for di- recting conduct. We often speak of love as something we fall into. Rather it is something to be made, developed, steadily 126 CONCLUSION 127 approximated. The best marriages are ac- complished works of art, yielding large re- wards through all their progressive stages. But love is ever unstable. Unwatched, it slips down among the lower forms of al- truism. These defects of love are, however, but incidental and such as are common in all man’s undertakings. There is nothing in love which can render it immune from human infirmity. But there are also in it certain fundamental defects which prevent it from becoming an organizing world- principle. At least before it can weld in- dividuals into societies and states it must undergo large transformation and appear rather as justice than domestic affection. For love is naturally selective and indi- vidual, picking out one and rejecting an- other. It does not offer its bounty alike to all. Private altruism, it might be called, so that it always seems indelicate to speak of it in public. It concerns only those immediately involved and only their most intimate experiences. From such limita- tions it needs to be freed before it can be- come formative over society. All that is conjunctive in it must be retained and only 128 ALTRUISM its exclusions removed. In this way gen- eral justice will supplement individual love. All the varieties of mutuality are alike in joining self-regard with extra-regard. They differ only in the extent of that extra- regard. In my last chapter I began the discussion of that superpersonal love which I called Justice. It is concerned with functions rather than individuals, and love is thus extended to a multitude who still remain unknown. To keep the framework of society steady large co-operation is re- quired, each of its members becoming re- sponsible for the working of some one among its many functions and having his own well-being bound up with its. To that function each is to devote himself as the lover does to his lady, and through it he sends his benefactions abroad to whoever stands in need. Such is the ideal of pro- fessional responsibility; and whether seen in shoemaker, doctor, or head of a family, it is something of wider scope and more generous impulse than private love. Yet even in professional responsibility an element of selection remains. After study- ing the needs of the community I pick out CONCLUSION 129 what work I will do. On some single need I fasten — the need of settling quarrels, and I become a lawyer; the need of instruction, and I become a teacher; the needs of the breakfast-table, and I become a grocer. In all these cases my service is given not to man as man, but only to a section of men, to those who are conscious of a certain specific need. It is possible, however, to extend justice and, not confining attention to wants already known, to endeavor to enlarge the whole intellectual horizon of our fellows. Thus love becomes peculiarly impersonal and creative. For example, when I become an artist or scientific man I do not know precisely what I shall contribute to the good of the public. The public itself has experienced no want of the wares which I shall furnish. In devoting myself to the higher mathe- matics I am pursuing something for which a practical application may never be found. But that uncertainty should not hold me back. I know that the mind of man moves off in that direction. I will follow and see how far it can be pressed. These investi- gations I am making in astronomy are curious. They satisfy my passion for know- ISO ALTRUISM ing. Believing they will satisfy that pas- sion in others also, I ask no more. Passing beyond the immediate application of my results, I simply aim at developing per- sons more fully as persons, so that their capacity for knowledge may be increased. Just so does the artist attempt to reveal aspects of beauty hitherto unperceived. When he furnishes what has been done be- fore, what men have learned to enjoy and now demand, he is a professional workman and belongs in the preceding class. But a true artist explores phases of unacknowl- edged beauty. Having himself seen what others have not seen, he takes the risk of announcing it, certain that if it is com- prehended he will open men’s eyes to fresh enjoyment. Rightly therefore do we hold artists and scientific men in high honor as enlargers of humanity. We see that altru- ism like theirs calls for risk and special dis- interestedness. They are discoverers, going out into wide lands, far from sure what will be found there, but ready to sacrifice themselves for possible human betterment. Intellectual soldiers, we may call them, ac- cepting the risks of doubtful battle. Theirs is a lofty altruism, and none the less be- CONCLUSION 131 cause success may bring them fame and fortune. Perhaps I strain the word justice in ap- plying it to them, yet they as truly as the professional man do not pick out individ- uals as receivers of their benefits. Indeed, that absence of particularity so empha- sized in justice goes to such a degree with them that their work seems to proceed from the spirit of science or spirit of beauty rather than from a particular person. They strike us as transcending their age, their own peculiarities, and to embody the con- junct self of humanity. Still another form of justice, or of love, which passes beyond the individual, is the service of institutions. Artists, scientific and professional men all follow interests of their own, believing, however, that their work in the long run will benefit the pub- lic. But in the service of institutions not only does the public receive a benefit, it fixes also what our work toward bringing it about shall be. Personal choice, there- fore, altogether disappears. The action is conjunctive throughout. But to under- stand this dark saying we must bring clearly before our minds what an institution is. It 132 ALTRUISM is a large term which we are apt to allow to fill out a big gap in our knowledge. I mean by institutions those fairly per- manent relations between persons which past experience has established for the pro- motion of human welfare and successive generations have approved. Ever since civilization began men have been experi- menting how to live together most help- fully. The results, tested by the induction of ages, become the inherited habits of in- dividuals and the institutions of society. Maintained through passing years, criti- cised, readjusted to meet more fully the needs they were intended to fulfil, they furnish each of us a working capital as soon as we enter the world. We are not obliged to decide in childhood whether to have three meals a day, whether man’s dress shall differ from woman’s, whether to have provision made for our instruction, worship, settlement of quarrels, safety on the street. These matters were considered before we were born, and judgments about them form our most precious inheritance. It is a veritable bank stock of experience on which to draw for our support. We accept it all as a thing of course at first, then be- CONCLUSION 133 gin to scrutinize it, asking how far these particular institutions save social friction, open avenues for enlarged activity, and how far that which once served these ends serves them no more. Such institutions are intended for the general good. By identifying ourselves with them we both share in that good and exercise an impartial love for mankind. For these have an influence over men un- equalled by any other agency. They fash- ion us in our unconscious years and carry forward our purposes in years of discre- tion. To comprehend their consolidated wisdom and conform ourselves to it will be our chief means of serving our fellow men; to neglect or weaken them through in- dividual caprice is to be an enemy of so- ciety. Only we must discriminate in our modes of strengthening. An institution is not proved good by the bare fact of its existence. Perhaps the presumption should be in its favor, for it could hardly get itself established if injurious. But its original adaptation to human wants is unstable, and strengthening it will really mean fitting it more neatly to present circumstances. To maintain its outward form when it no 134 ALTRUISM longer serves its purpose is to be unfaith- ful to it. Constructive criticism is con- stantly required if institutions are to be kept sweet and wholesome. Only it should be borne in mind that changes in the frame- work of society can best come about slowly and only at the desire of large groups of those affected. Presumptuous, indeed, is he who will attempt to stand outside any of our fundamental institutions. The set- ting up of his individual will against the general will proves him no true socialist. He should remember that since everybody is wiser than anybody his first business is to conform to the institutions into which he is born, then to study elaborately their meaning, and finally to persuade his fel- lows to join in readjusting them with a view to their more effective working. Our love for our fellow men is shown each day in our maintenance, critical study, and re- form of the social institutions around us. They survive only through our constant approval, are too important to be neglected or lightly set aside, and too liable to decay to be left uncriticised. It is obvious, however, that institutions are of many grades of importance. Some CONCLUSION 135 are fundamental, as the family, property, democracy; others are local and individual, as Harvard University, Boston, the Epis- copal Church, the Democratic Party. As they become narrower our acceptance of them changes its character, affectionate loyalty playing a larger part, dutiful obedi- ence less. A member of a college, for ex- ample, comes to think of it almost as a person, symbolized in Alma Mater, and gives to it the loving devotion he would feel for a revered friend. Members of in- stitutions so individual are apt to take their membership as something like a per- sonal trust and to pride themselves on fidelity to it. But because such institu- tions are of limited range and not appli- cable to all mankind, failure in allegiance to them is generally regarded not as a moral lapse, but as an error of judgment. Such are some of the aspects of justice, the impartial love of our fellow men. When we are commanded to love our neighbor as ourself, we cannot excuse ourselves by saying that love does not move by com- mand but takes its own way according to individual temperament. Even of the simpler forms of love this is only partially 136 ALTRUISM true; wisdom, purpose, and patience being also essentials of permanence even in our private loves. But that public love to which we are summoned is no mere emo- tion, arising blindly and passing with the mood. It is the rational acceptance of our place in a social organization where all are dependent on each. A good synonym for what I have called justice would be public- mindedness. And in this extended and superpersonal love altruism attains its fullest and steadi- est expression. But so does egoism, too. That abstract egoism, it is r true, which seeks its own gain regardless of that of others, is submerged. It was always fic- titious, and rapidly conducted him who pursued it to emptiness. But that con- junct self, the person constituted through relations, finds in this justicial love his large opportunity. In like manner the abstract and sentimental alter, figured as that uncriticisable idol to which individ- ual interests must daily be offered up, is overthrown and shown to have reality only in the degree in which it fosters personal life. Socialism which does not promote individuality, individuality which does not CONCLUSION 137 tend toward an ever-completer social con- sciousness, are alike delusive. Each must find its justification in the service it is able to render to its pretended foe. Pure gifts, to individuals or the state, are rightly ob- jects of suspicion. Only when transmuted by mutuality can they be kept free from taint. Such at least is the doctrine of this book. In it there is nothing new. Vaguely, waveringly, and with but a half under- standing, I believe it has ever guided the best endeavors of mankind. I have only hoped to drag it into clearer light by a novel sort of approach. The dangers of that mode of approach I readily see and wish my readers also to see. As a peda- gogue I have torn apart things which belong together and have separately exhib- ited our protective, generous, and identify- ing impulses as successively different as- pects of the altruistic life. In this way we teachers are obliged to proceed, picking to pieces a concrete whole, even when our aim is to show wholeness. But my readers will not be so simple as to imagine that things occur in experience so disjointed as on my pages. Life is more closely com- 138 ALTRUISM pacted than our expositions. Higher stages and lower move forward together, assist- ing one another. The disparagements which I put on the lower varieties of altru- ism these deserve only so far as they are detached from the higher. In conjunction, the higher altruisms ennoble the lower and are themselves enriched and diversified by whatever inferior stages they absorb. Among the ingredients of character none can safely be thrown away. We study ethics merely to find a place where each may be helpful to all. I I / I / 171 P174A 87819