1 MnffniFSSMfPMifiiwtfiiiti mo ^rxxmW Slaiu i>rl]aol Htbrarg Digitized by Microsoft® K 190.M22°i906 "'"""" """^^ 'ISMiML'ffi.,iI,?,S°""6<:«'on with the ear'^^ 3 1924 021 104 421 yuM4 DATE t-mtm- DUE /_ 1^^^ ^-.^^w^^" 1^ T7^ Mild , iiw* te^ GAYUDRD PRINTED IN U.S.* Digitized by Microsoft® This book was digitized by Microsoft Corporation in cooperation witli Cornell University Libraries, 2007. You may use and print this copy in limited quantity for your personal purposes, but may not distribute or provide access to it (or modified or partial versions of it) for revenue-generating or other commercial purposes. Digitized by Microsoft® The original of tliis book is in tlie Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924021104421 ' Digitize by Microsoft® Digitized by Microsoft® ANCIENT LAW Digitized by Microsoft® By SIR HENRY S. MAINE ANCIENT LAW. Its Connection with the Early History of Society, and its Relation to Modem Ideas. Introduction and Notes by the Rt. Hon. Sir Frederick Pollock, Bart. gs. net. ANCIENT LAW. 7S- 6d. net. INTRODUCTION AND NOTES TO MAINE'S ANCIENT LAW. By the Rt. Hon. Sir Frederick Pollock, Bart. 3s. 6d. net. LECTURE ON THE EARLY HISTORY OF INSTITUTIONS. 7S- 6d. net. POPULAR GOVERNMENT. Four Essays. 7$. 6d. net. INTERNATIONAL LAW. Whewell Lectures, delivered at Cambridge, 1887. 7s. 6d. net. A BRIEF MEMOIR OF HIS LIFE. By the Rt. Hon. Sir M. E. Grant Duff. With some of his Indian Speeches and Minutes. Selected and edited by Whiteley Stokes. With Portrait. i6s. net. All Rights Rbservbd Digitized by Microsoft® ANCIENT LAW ITS CONNECTION WITH THE EARLY HISTORY OF SOCIETY AND ITS RELATION TO MODERN IDEAS BY SIR HENRY SUMNER MAINE K.C.S.I., LL.D., F.R.S. FOKEICN ASSOCIATE HBMBElT^F THB IHSTITUTS OF PKANCS WITH INTRODUCTION AND NOTES BY THE RIGHT HON. SIR FREDERICK POLLOCK, BART. LL.D., D.C.L. LONDON JOHN MURRAY, ALBEMARLE STREET, W. Digitized by Microsoft® /3 z / / ^ f , n First Edition, with Sir Frederick Pollock's Notes . . January 1906 Reprinted August 1907 Reprinted /une 1909 Reprinted /a/y 1913 Reprinted , July 1916 Reprinted April 1920 Reprinted . March 1924 Reprinted February 1927 R es LcAn Digitizge by4^icrosoft® / ij^ PREFACE TO THE TENTH EDITION OF THE ORIGINAL WORK The theory of legal development propounded in this volume has been generally accepted ; but it has been thought that, in his Fifth Chapter on " Primitive Society and Ancient Law/' the Author has not done sufficient justice to investigations which appear to show the existence of states of society stiU more rudimentary than that vividly described in the Homeric lines quoted at page no, and ordinarily known as the Patriarchal State. The Author at page io6 has mentioned " accounts by contemporary observers of civilisations less advanced than their own," as capable of affording peculiarly good evidence concerning the rudiments of society ; and, in fact, since his work was first published, in 1861, the observation of savage or extremely barbarous races has brought to light forms of social organisation extremely unlike that to which he has referred the beginnings of law, Digitized by Microsoft® PREFACE TO THE TENTH EDITION and possibly in some cases of greater antiquity. The subject is, properly speaking, beyond the scope of the present work, but he has given his opinion upon the results of these more recent inquiries in a paper on " Theories of Primitive Society," published in a volume on " Early Law and Custom " (Murray, 1883). H. S. M. London . November i88^ Digitized by Microsoft® PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION The chief object of the following pages is to indicate some of the earliest ideas of mankind, as they are reflected in Ancient Law, and to point out the relation of those ideas to modern thought. Much of the inquiry attempted could not have been prosecuted with the slightest hope of a useful result if there had not existed a body of law, like that of the Romans, bearing in its earlier portions the traces of the most remote antiquity and supplying from its later rules the staple of the civil institutions by which modern society is even now controlled. The necessity of taking the Roman law as a typical system, has compelled the Author to draw from it what may appear a disproportionate number of his illustrations ; but it has not been his intention to write a treatise on Roman jurisprudence, and he has as much as possible avoided all discussions which might Ix Digitized by Microsoft® X PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION give that appearance to his work. The space allotted in the Third and Fourth Chapters to certain philosophical theories of the Roman Jurisconsults, has been appropriated to them for two reasons. In the first place, those theories appear to the Author to have had a much wider and more permanent influence on the thought and action of the world than is usually supposed. Secondly, they are beUeved to be the ultimate source of most of the views which have been prevalent, tiU quite recently, on the subjects treated of in this volume. It was impossible for, the Author to proceed far with his undertaking, without stating his opinion on the origin, meaning, and value of those speculations. H. S. M, London : January 1 86t. Digitized by Microsoft® CONTENTS rAGE Introduction. By Sir Frederick Pollock . . . xiii CHAPTZR I. Ancient Codes i Note A. Antiquity of Roman Law . . .18 „ B. Customary Law in Homer . . .20 „ C. Early Forms of Law : " Written " and " Unwritten " Law : Early Codes . 32 II. Legal Fictions 26 Note D. English Case-Law and Fiction . . 46 III. Law of Nature and Equity .... 48 Note E. The Law of Nature and " lus Gentium " 73 „ F. Equity 77 IV. The Modern History or the Law of Nature 79 Note G. Medieval and Modern Treatment of the Law of Nature : Bracton : French Publicists 114 „ H. The Origins of the Modern Law of Nations 120 V. Primitive Society and Ancient Law . . 123 Note I. Montesquieu, Bentham, and Historical Method 174 „ K. The Patriarchal Theory . . .176 „ L. Status and Contract .... 183 «l Digitized by Microsoft® Xn CONTENTS CHAPTER PAOB VI. The Early History of Testamentary Suc- cession i86 Note M. Testamentary Succession . . **4 VII. Ancient and Modern Ideas respecting Wills AND Successions Note N. Primogeniture .... VIII. The Early History of Property Note O. Capture, Occupation, Possession . „ P. The Indian Village Community „ Q. Res Mancipi; Alienation in Early Life IX. The Early History of Contract Note R. Contract in Early Law . . . X. The Early History of Delict and Crime Note S. Archaic Procedure 331 256 311 315 317 319 374 377 405 Index 408 Digitized by Microsoft® INTRODUCTION Sir Henry Maine's " Ancient Law " is now ja classical text. The object of this edition i^o reproduce it, accompanied by such help to right understanding and profitable use as a younger generation may reasonably require. More than forty years have passed since the book was first pubUshed in 1861. During those years, and to a great extent under the influence of Maine's own work, research into the early history of laws and institutions has been more active, systematic, and fruitful than it ever was before. Many new facts have been disclosed ; our know- ledge of others has been freed from error and misconception ; as many, perhaps more, which were formerly accessible, but neglected as being insignificant or of merely local interest, have found their due place and importance in a wider field of knowledge. The materials thus acquired enable us to confirm and supplement Maine's work in many points. If they also show us that it calls for amendment in some places, no one who is at all acquainted with the progressive character of legal and historical learning will find in this any cause for disappointment. The wonder is not that Maine's results, after more xiU Digitized by Microsoft® MV INTRODUCTION than a generation, should stand in need of some correction, but that, in fact, they need so little as they do. Later speculation and research have, on the whole, confirmed Maine's leading ideas in the most striking manner, partly by actual verification of consequences indicated by him as probable, partly by new examples and appUca- tions in regions which he had not himself explored. There is no better witness to the intrinsic weight of Maine's work than the nature of some criticism it has met with, from competent persons on the Continent rather than at home. So far as those learned persons complain of anything, they miss that symmetrical construction of a finished system to which their training has ac- customed them. Now it is to be observed that no words of Maine's own ever gave his readers the promise of a systematic doctrine. Not one of his books professed on the face of it to accoimt for the ultimate origin of human laws, or to settle the relations of jurisprudence to ethics, or to connect the science of law with any theory of pohtics or of social development. Yet it does not seem to have occurred to the critics in question to charge Maine with remissness in not having attempted these things. The disappointment ex- pressed was that he did not fuUy accompHsh them, or that, if he had a solution, he never sufficiently declared it. Regret that Maine's work was not more openly ambitious is legitimate, though I do not share it ; expression of it might have signified much or Uttle. It might have been thoroughly sincere, and due to imperfect under- standing of the relations to time, circumstances Digitized by Microsoft® INTRODUCTION XV and materials, which determined Maine's manner of working, and, as I beUeve, determined it for the best. It might also have been, in the critic's intention, the easy comphment of the professional and disciphned scholar to a brilliant amateur. Very different from this was the actual criticism. It assumed that the author had proved himself a master, and that, accordingly, the highest and most exacting standard was to be applied both to his method and to his results. When we turn from Dareste or Vanni to the original preface to " Ancient Law," we are astonished by the studiously modest terms in which Maine defined his own undertaking : " The chief object of the following pages is to^ indicate some of the earliest ideas of mankind as they are reflected in ancient law, and to point out the relation of those ideas to modern thought." In Uke manner, on the first pubhcation of the lectures on Village Communities, he apologised for their fragmentary character, and in the height of his mature fame he described " Early Law and Custom " only as an endeavour " to connect a portion of existing institutions with a part of the primitive or very ancient usages of mankind, and of the ideas associated with those usages." It is worth while to observe Maine's caution in disclaiming authority to lay down what ancient usages, if any, are really primitive — a caution sometimes neglected by his followers, and often by the champions of other theories. Maine's dignified and almost ironical reserve about his own work has certainly made it rather difficult for a student approaching it for the Digitized by Microsoft® XVI INTRODUCTION first time to form any general notion of what it has really done for legal and historical science. Although Maine himself was the last person of whom the answer to such a question could be expected, we who are in no way bound to reticence must say that he did nothing less than create the natural history of law. He showed, on the one hand, that legal ideas and institutions have a real course of development as much as the genera and species of Uving creatures, and in every stage of that development have their normal characters ; on the other hand, he made it clear that these processes deserve and require distinct study, and cannot be treated as mere incidents in the general history of the societies where they occur. There have been complaints, often too well justified, of the historical ignorance prevaihng among lawyers. " Woe unto you also, ye law- yers 1 " Freeman said — whether in print in those terms, I know not ; but I have heard him say it — ^when he was grieved at the fictions about mediaeval institutions that still passed current for history twenty-five or thirty years ago. But Maine has taught us that the way to impart a historical habit of mind to lawyers is to show them that law has an important history of its own, not at all confined to its pohtical and con- stitutional aspects, and offers a vast field for the regular appUcation of historical and comparative method. When once a lawyer has grasped this, he is entitled to point out in turn that a historian who is not content to be a mere chronicler can hardly do without some understanding of legal ideas and systems. And the importance of the Digitized by Microsoft® INTRODUCTION XVll legal element, so far from diminishing as we retrace the growth of our modern institutions into a semi-historic past, rather increases. Others have shown this besides Maine, but none before him. It is easy to underrate his originaUty now that his points have been taken up by many teachers and become current in the schools. Any student who harbours doubt as to the extent of Maine's contributions to the historical philosophy of law may do weU to ask himself in what books, legal or historical, of earlier date than " Ancient Law," he could have found adequate perception, or any distinct perception, of such matters as__ these : The sentiment of reverence evoked by the mere existence of law in early communities ; the essential formahsm of archaic law ; the pre- dominance of rules of procedure over rules of substance in early legal systems ; the funda- mental difference between ancient and modern ideas as to legal proof ; the relatively modern character of the individual citizen's disposing power, especially by will, and freedom of con- tract ; and the stUl more modern appearance of true criminal law. Nowadays it may be said that " all have got the seed," but this is no justification for forgetting who first cleared and sowed the ground. We may tiU fields that the master left untouched, and one man will bring a better ox to yoke to the plough, and another a worse ; but it is the master's plough still. It will now be proper to consider in a general way what resources were available for Maine's purposes when he wrote " Ancient Law," or rather when he prepared and delivered the lectures b Digitized by Microsoft® XVIU INTRODUCTION of which it was a revised publication (" Early Law and Custom," p. 194). We shall be pretty safe in taking legal and historical scholarship as they stood, for an English student who had not frequented Continental seats of learning, about the middle of the nineteenth century. First, in Roman law Savigny, then still living, was the person of greatest authority ; the historical school which he took a principal part in founding was dominant in Germany and beginning to prevail elsewhere. Savigny's work, as well as that of his contemporaries and im- mediate followers, dealt only with the Roman materials. Comparative investigation of archaic legal systems had scarcely been undertaken at all, certainly not on any considerable scale, and this may perhaps account for more than one conjecture of Savigny's which has not proved tenable. The work of Rudolf von Ihering, the character of whose genius, individual as it was, perhaps most nearly resembled Maine's in the same generation, was only beginning. His views on the evolution of modern from archaic law V coincide remarkably with those of Maine in several points ; for example, in the position that all jurisdiction, if we could trace it far back enough, would be found to be in its origin not compulsory, but voluntary. But there can be no question of borrowing either way. Maine had formed his own ideas before any part of Ihering's great work, " Der Geist des romischen Rechtes," was published ; and Ihering was never in a position to make much use of Maine's work, even if he had the time ; for, as I came to know from Digitized by Microsoft® INTRODUCTION XIX himself, he could not read English with any facility. The Uterature of Roman law to be found in our ^p " own system to the spirit of ancient societies, tending, as they always did, to spht into distinct orders which, however exclusive themselves, toler- ated no professional hierarchy above them. It is remarkable that this system did not produce certain effects which might on the whole have been expected from it. It did not, for example, 'popularise the Roman law, — ^it did not, as in some of the Greek republics, lessen the effort of intellect reqmred for the mastery of science, although its diffusion and authoritative exposition were opposed by no artificial barriers. On the contrary, if it had not been for the operation of a separate set of causes, there were strong probabilities that the Roman jurisprudence would have become as minute, technical, and dif&cult as any system which has since prevailed. Again, a consequence which might still more naturally have been looked for, does not appear at any time to have exhibited itself. The jurisconsults, until the liberties of Rome were overthrown, formed a class which was quite undefined and must have fluctu- ated greatly in numbers ; nevertheless, there does not seem to have existed a doubt as to the particu- lar individuals whose opinion, in their generation, was conclusive on the cases submitted to them. The vivid pictures of a leading jurisconsult's daily practice which abound in Latin Uterature— the clients from the country flocking to his ante- chamber in the early morning, and the students standing round with their note-books to record the great lawyer's replies— are seldom or never identified at any given period with more than one or two conspicuous names. Owing too to the Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. II] ANSWERS OF THE LEARNED 4I direct contact of the client and the advocate, the Roman people itself seems to have been always alive to the rise and fall of professional reputation, and there is abundance of proof, more particularly in the well-known oration of Cicero, "Pro Muraena," that the reverence of the commons for forensic suc- cess was apt to be excessive rather than deficient. We cannot doubt that the peculiarities which have been noted in the instrumentality by which the development of the Roman law was first effected, were the source of its characteristic excellence, its early wealth in principles. The growth and exuberance of principle was fostered, in part, by the competition among the expositors of the law, an influence wholly unknown where there exists a Bench, the depositaries intrusted by king or commonwealth with the prerogative of justice. But the chief agency, no doubt, was the uncontrolled multiplication of cases for legal decision. The state of facts which caused genuine perplexity to a country chent was not a whit more entitled to form the basis of the juriscon- sult's Response, or legal decision, than a set of hypothetical circumstances propounded by an ingenious pupil. AH combinations of fact were on precisely the same footing, whether they were real or imaginary. It was nothing to the juris- consult that his opinion was overruled for the moment by the magistrate who adjudicated on his chent' s case, unless that magistrate happened to rank above him in legal knowledge or the esteem of his profession. I do not, indeed, mean it to be inferred that he would wholly omit to consider his cUent's advantage, for the client was Digitized by Microsoft® 42 LEGAL FICTIONS [chap, ii in earKer times the great lawyer's constituent and at a later period his paymaster, but the main road to the rewards of ambition lay through the good opinion of his order, and it is obvious that under such a system as I have been describing this was much more Ukely to be secured by viewing each case as an illustration of a great principle, or an exemplification of a broad rule, than by merely shaping it for an insulated forensic triumph. It is evident that powerful influence must have been exercised by the want of any distinct check on the suggestion or invention of possible questions. Where the data can be multiplied at pleasure, the faciUties for evolving a general rule are immensely increased. As the law is administered among ourselves, the judge cannot travel out of the sets of facts exhibited before him or before his pre- decessors. Accordingly each group of circum- stances which is adjudicated upon receives, to employ a GalUcism, a sort of consecration. It acquires certain qualities which distinguish it from every other case genuine or hypothetical. But at Rome, as I have attempted to explain, there was nothing resembling a Bench or Chamber of judges ; and therefore no combination of facts possessed any particular value more than another. When a difficulty came for opinion before the jurisconsult, there was nothing to prevent a person endowed with a nice perception of analogy from at once proceeding to adduce and consider an entire class of supposed questions with which a particular feature connected it. Whatever were the practical advice given to the client, the responsum treasured up in the note-books of Digitized by Microsoft® «5HAP"] LATER ROMAN LAW 43 listening pupils would doubtless contemplate the circumstances as governed by a great principle, or included in a sweeping rule. Nothing like this has ever been possible among ourselves, and it should be acknowledged that in many criticisms passed on the Enghsh law the manner in which it has been enunciated seems to have been lost sight of. The hesitation of our courts in declaring principles may be much more reasonably attributed to the comparative scantiness of our precedents, voluminous as they appear to him who is ac- quainted with no other system, than to the temper of our judges. It is true that in the wealth of legal principle we are considerably poorer than several modern European nations. But they, it must be remembered, took the Roman jurispru- dence for the foundation of their civil institutions. They built the debris of the Roman law into their walls ; but in the materials and workmanship of the residue there is not much which distinguishes it favourably from the structure erected by the Enghsh judicature. 'The period of Roman freedom was the period during which the stamp of a distinctive character was impressed on the Roman jurisprudence ; and through all the earlier part of it, it was by the Responses of the jurisconsults that the develop- ment of the law was mainly carried on. But as we approach the fall of the republic there are signs that the Responses are assuming a form which must have been fatal to their farther expansion. They are becoming systematised and reduced into compendia. Q. Mucins Scsevola, the Pontifex, is said to have published a manual of Digitized by Microsoft® 44 LEGAL FICTIONS [chap, n the entire Civil Law, and there are traces in the writings of Cicero of growing disrelish for the old methods, as compared with the more active in- struments of legal innovation. Other agencies had in fact by this time been brought to bear on the law. The Edict, or annual proclamation of the Praetor, had risen into credit as the principal engine of law reform, and L. Cornelius Sylla, by causing to be enacted the great group of statutes called the Leges Cornelice, had shown what rapid and speedy improvements can be effected by direct legislation. The final blow to the Responses was dealt by Augustus, who limited to a few leading jurisconsults the right of giving binding opinions on cases submitted to them, a change which, though it brings us nearer the ideas of the modern world, must obviously have altered fundamentally the characteristics of the legal pro- fession and the nature of its influence on Roman law. At a later period another school of juriscon- sults arose, the great hghts of jurisprudence for all time. But Ulpian and Paulus, Gains and Papinian, were not authors of Responses. Their works were regular treatises on particular departments of the law, more especially on the Praetor's Edict. The Equity of the Romans and the Praetorian Edict by which it was worked into their system, wiU be considered in the next chapter. Of the Statute Law it is only necessary to say that it was scanty during the republic, but became very voluminous under the empire. In the youth and infancy of a nation it is a rare thing for the legis- lature to be caUed into action for the general reform of private law. The cry of the people Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP.u] ROMAN STATUTE LAW 45 is not for change in the laws, which are usually valued above their real worth, but solely for their pure, complete, and easy administration ; and recourse to the legislative body is generally directed to the removal of some great abuse, or the decision of some incurable quarrel between classes and dynasties. There seems in the minds of the Romans to have been some association between the enactment of a large body of statutes and the settlement of society after a great civil commotion. Sylla signalised his reconstitution of the republic by the Leges Cornehse ; Juhus Caesar contemplated vast additions to the Statute Law ; Augustus caused to be passed the all-important group of Leges Juhae ; and among later emperors the most active promulgators of constitutions are princes who, like Constantine, have the concerns of the world to readjust. The true period of Roman Statute Law does not begin till the establishment of the empire. The enactments of the emperors, clothed at first in the pretence of popular sanction, but afterwards emanating undisguisedly from the imperial prerogative, extend in increasing massive- ness from the consolidation of Augustus's power to the publication of the Code of Justinian. It will be seen that even in the reign of the second emperor a considerable approximation is made to that condition of the law and that mode of administering it with which we are all familiar. A statute law and a limited board of expositors have arisen into being ; a permanent court of appeal and a collection of approved commentaries will very shortly be added ; and thus we are brought close on the ideas of our own day. Digitized by Microsoft® 46 NOTES [CHA'- ; NOTE D ENGLISH CASE-LAW AND FICTION About the middle of the nineteenth century, and somewhat later, the language currently used by text-writers was such as to warrant Maine's selection of the authority of decided cases in England as an example of legal fiction. But the twentieth-century reader, if he has taken to heart Maine's brilliant generalisation in the earlier part of the chapter, will hardly expect the ideas and formulas even of English lawyers to have remained stationary in the midst of a progressive society ; and in fact, though probably no society has ever made progress at a uniform rate all along the line, and there may quite conceivably be stagnation or even falling back in some departments while there is advance in others, criticism of legal ideas has advanced a good deal in the English-speaking world. No intelligent lawyer would at this day pretend that the decisions of the Courts do not add to and alter the law. The Courts themselves, in the course of the reasons given for those decisions, constantly and freely use language admitting that they do. Certainly they do not claim legislative power ; nor, with all respect for Maine, do they exercise it For a legislator is not bound to conform to the known existing rules or principles of law ; statutes may not only amend but reverse the rule, or they may introduce absolutely novel principles and remedies, like the Work- men's Compensation Act. Still less, if possible, is he bound to respect previous legislation. But English judges are bound to give their decisions in conformity with the settled general principles of English law, with any express legislation applicable to the matter in hand, and with the authority of their predecessors and their own former decisions. At the same time they are bound to find a decision for every case, however novel it may be ; and that decision will be authority for other like cases in future ; therefore it is part of their duty to lay down new rules if required. Perhaps this is really the first and greatest rule of our customary law : that, failing a specific rule already ascertained and fitting the case in hand, the King's judges must find and apply the most reasonable rule they can, so that it be not inconsistent with any established principle. They not only may but must develop the law in every direction except that of contradicting rules which authority has once fixed. Whoever denies this must deny that novel combinations of facts are brought before the Courts from time to time, which is a truth vouched by common experience and recognised in the forensic phrase describing such cases as " of the first impression " ; or else he must refuse to accept the principle that the Court is bound to find a decision for every case, however novel It is true that at many times the Courts have been over-anxious to avoid the appear Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. II] NOTES 47 ance of novelty; and the shifts to which they resorted to avoid it have encumbered the Common Law with several of the fictions which Maine denounces (p. 32) as almost hopeless obstacles to an orderly distribution of its contents. Observe that the process of making case-law cannot properly be called legislation even with any qualifying epithet intended to mark it as an exercise of limited or subordinate power. Many law-making authorities in the world are not sovereign, being merely delegated, or otherwise restrained, but are still sources of enactments which are verbally and literally binding within their competence. But the judicial authority of precedents is not of that kind. Under our system the Court is bound to give judgments consistent with former judgments of higher or equal rank, so far as their effect has not been abrogated by legislation or overruled by still higher authority ; but it is not bound to follow their very words. Only the principle is binding, and it must be collected from the decision as a whole, and not assumed to be completely expressed by this or that sentence in a reported judgment, however carefully framed. Perhaps Maine's exposition hardly brings out the prevailing motive for introducing fictions, the desire of obtaining a speedier or more complet,e remedy than the strictly appropriate form ot procedure affords. Among the regular though not invariable marks of fictions in modem English law is the use of the word " constructive " or the word " implied," as any careful student may note for himself. It would be rash to suppose that the age of legal fictions is wholly past. When "Ancient Law" was written, one example was quite recent in our Courts, the rule that a man who professes to contract as an agent is deemed to warrant that he has authority from his alleged principal. This is a fiction, but bene- ficent and elegant, and it is now fully accepted. Digitized by Microsoft® CHAPTER III LAW OF NATURE AND EQUITY The theory of a Set of legal principles entitled by their intrinsic superiority to supersede the older law, very early obtained currency both in the Roman State and in England. Such a body of principles, existing in any system, has in the foregoing chapters been denominated Equity, a term which, as wiU presently be seen, was one (though only one) of the designations by which this agent of legal change was known to the Roman jurisconsults. The jurisprudence of the Court of Chancery, which bears the name of Equity in England, could only be adequately discussed in a separate treatise. It is extremely complex in its texture, and derives its materials from several heterogeneous sources. The early ecclesiastical chancellors contributed to it, from the Canon Law, many of the principles which he deepest in its structure. The Roman law, more fertile than the Canon Law in rules appUcable to secular disputes, was not seldom resorted to by a later generation of Chancery judges, amid whose re- corded dicta we often find entire texts from the Corpus Juris Civilis imbedded, with their terms unaltered, though their origin is never acknow- ledged. Still more recently, and particularly at the middle and during the latter half of the Digitized by Microsoft® «**••• "0 ROMAN EQUITY 49 eighteenth century, the mixed systems of juris- prudence and morals constructed by the pubUcists of the Low Countries appear to have been much studied by English lawyers, and from the chan- cellorship of Lord Talbot to the commencement of Lord Eldon's chancellorship these works had considerable effect on the rulings of the Court of Chancery. The system, which obtained its ingredients from these various quarters, was greatly controlled in its growth by the necessity imposed on it of conforming itself to the analogies of the common law, but it has always answered the description of a body of comparatively novel legal principles claiming to override the older jurisprudence of the country on the strength of an intrinsic ethical superiority. The Equity of Rome was a much simpler structure, and its development from its first appearance can be much more easily traced. Both its character and its history deserve attentive examination. It is the root of several concep- tions which have exercised profound influence on himian thought, and through human thought have seriously affected the destinies of mankind. The Romans described their legal system as consisting of two ingredients. " All nations," says the Institutional Treatise pubUshed under the authority of the Emperor Justinian, " who are ruled by laws and customs, are governed partly by their own particular laws, and partly by those laws which are common to all mankind. The law which a people enacts is called the Civil Law of that people, but that which natural reason appoints for all mankind is called the Law of Digitized by Microsoft^) 4 50 LAW OF NATURE AND EQUITY Lchap. in Nations, because all nations use it." The part of the law " which natural reason appoints for all mankind " was the element which the Edict of the Praetor was supposed to have worked into Roman jurisprudence. Elsewhere it is styled more simply Jus Naturale, or the Law of Nature ; and its ordinances are said to be dictated by Natural Equity (naturalis cequitas) as well as by natural reason. I shall attempt to discover the origin of these famous phrases, Law of Nations, Law of Nature, Equity, and to determine how the con- ceptions which they indicate are related to one another. The most superficial student of Roman history must be struck by the extraordinary degree in which the fortunes of the repubUc were affected by the presence of foreigners, under different names, on her soil. The causes of this immigration are discernible enough at a later period, for we can readily understand why men of aU races should flock to the mistress of the world ; but the same phenomenon of a large population of foreigners and denizens meets us in the very earhest records of the Roman State. No doubt, the instabihty of society in ancient Italy, composed as it was in great measure of robber tribes, gave men consider- able inducement to locate themselves in the territory of any community strong enough to protect itself and them from external attack, even though protection should be purchased at the cost of heavy taxation, poUtical disfranchisement, and much social humiUation. It is probable, however, that this explanation is imperfect, and that it could only be completed by taking into account Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. Ill] LAW OF NATIONS 51 those active commercial relations which, though they are little reflected in the miUtary traditions of the republic, Rome appears certainly to have had with Carthage and with the interior of Italy in pre-historic times. Whatever were the cir- cumstances to which it was attributable, the foreign element in the commonwealth determined the whole course of its history, which, at all its stages, is Uttle more than a narrative of conflicts between a stubborn nationality and an alien population. Nothing like this has been seen in modem times ; on the one hand, because modern European communities have seldom or never received any accession of foreign immigrants which was large enough to make itself felt by the bulk of the native citizens, and on the other, because modern states, being held together by allegiance to a king or pohtical superior, absorb considerable bodies of immigrant settlers with a quickness unknown to the ancient world, where the original citizens of a commonwealth always believed them- selves to be united by kinship in blood, and re- sented a claim to equality of privilege as a usurpa- tion of their birthright. In the early Roman repubhc the principle of the absolute exclusion of foreigners pervaded the Civil Law no less than the constitution. The aUen or denizen could have no share in any institution supposed to be coeval with the State. He could not have the benefit of Quiritarian law. He could not be a party to the nexum which was at once the conveyance and the contract of the primitive Romans. He could not sue by the Sacramental Action, a mode of litigation of which the origin mounts up to the very infancy Digitized by Microsoft® 52 LAW OF NATURE AND EQUITY [chap, iii of civilisation. Still, neither the interest nor the security of Rome permitted him to be quite outlawed. All ancient communities ran the risk of being overthrown by a very shght disturbance of equiUbrium, and the mere instinct of self- preservation would force the Romans to devise some method of adjusting the rights and duties of foreigners, who might otherwise — and this was a danger of real importance in the ancient world — have decided their controversies by armed strife. Moreover, at no period of Roman history was foreign trade entirely neglected. It was therefore probably half as a measure of poUce and half in furtherance of commerce that jurisdiction was first assumed in disputes to which the parties were either foreigners or a native and a foreigner. The assumption of such a jurisdiction brought with it the immediate necessity of discovering some principles on which the questions to be adjudicated upon could be settled, and the principles appUed to this object by the Roman lawyers were emi- nently characteristic of the time. They refused, as I have said before, to decide the new cases by pure Roman Civil Law. They refused, no doubt because it seemed to involve some kind of degrada- tion, to apply the law of the particular State from which the foreign litigant came. The expedient to which they resorted was that of selecting the rules of law common to Rome and to the different Italian communities m which the immigrants were born. In other words, they set themselves to form a system answering to the primitive and literal meaning of Jus Gentium, that is. Law common to all Nations. Jus Gentium was, in fact, the sum Digitized by Microsoft® <=K*f-'"] LAW OF NATIONS 53 of the common ingredients in the customs of the old Italian tribes, for they were all the nations whom the Romans had the means of observing, and who sent successive swarms of immigrants to Roman soil. Whenever a particular usage was seen to be practised by a large number of separate races in common, it was set down as part of the Law common to all Nations, or Jus Gentium. Thus, although the conveyance of property was certainly accompanied by very different forms in the differ- ent commonwealths surrounding Rome, the actual transfer, tradition, or delivery of the article in- tended to be conveyed was a part of the ceremonial in all of them. It was, for instance, a part, though a subordinate part, in the Mancipation or con- veyance peculiar to Rome. Tradition, therefore, being in all probability the only common ingredient in the modes of conveyance which the jurisconsults had the means of observing, was set down as an institution Juris Gentium, or rule of the Law common to all Nations. A vast number of other observances were scrutinised with the same result. Some common characteristic was discovered in all of them, which had a common object, and this characteristic was classed in the Jus Gentium. The Jus Gentium was accordingly a collection of rules and principles, determined by observation to be common to the institutions which prevailed among the various Italian tribes. The circumstances of the origin of the Jus Gentium are probably a sufficient safeguard against the mistake of supposing that the Roman lawyers had any special respect for it. It was the fruit in part of their disdain for all foreign law, and Digitized by Microsoft® 54 LAW OF NATURE AND EQUITY [chap, iii in part of their disinclination to give the foreigner the advantage of their own indigenous Jus Civile. It is true that we, at the present day, should probably take a very different view of the Jus Gentium, if we were performing the operation which was effected by the Roman jurisconsults. We should attach some vague superiority or pre- cedence to the element which we had thus dis- cerned underlying and pervading so great a variety of usage. We should have a sort of respect for rules and principles so universal. Perhaps we should speak of the common ingredient as being of the essence of the transaction into which it entered, and should stigmatise the remaining apparatus of ceremony, which varied in different communities, as adventitious and accidental. Or it may be, we should infer that the races which we were comparing once obeyed a great system of common institutions of which the Jus Gentium was the reproduction, and that the comphcated usages of separate commonwealths were only corruptions and depravations of the simpler ordinances which had once regulated their primi- tive state. But the results to which modem ideas conduct the observer are, as nearly as possible, the reverse of those which were instinctively brought home to the primitive Roman. What we respect or admire, he disliked or regarded with jealous dread. The parts of jurisprudence which he looked upon with affection were exactly those which a modern theorist leaves out of consideration as accidental and transitory ; the solemn gestures of the mancipation ; the nicely adjusted questions and answers of the verbal contract ; the endless Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP- 1"] JUS NATURALE 55 formalities of pleading and procedure. The Jus Gentium was merely a system forced on his attention by a political necessity. He loved it as Uttle as he loved the foreigners from whose institutions it was derived and for whose benefit it was intended. A complete revolution in his ideas was required before it could challenge his respect, but so complete was it when it did occur, that the true reason why our modern estimate of the Jus Gentium differs from that which has just been described, is that both modern jurisprudence and modern philosophy have inherited the matured views of the later jurisconsults on this subject. There did come a time when, from an ignoble appendage of the Jus Civile, the Jus Gentium came to be considered a great though as yet imperfectly developed model to which all law ought as far as possible to conform. This crisis arrived when the Greek theory of a Law of Nature was applied to the practical Roman administration of the Law common to aU Nations. The Jus Naturale, or Law of Nature, is simply the Jus Gentium or Law of Nations seen in the light of a peculiar theory. An unfortunate at- tempt to discriminate them was made by the jurisconsult Ulpian, with the propensity to dis- tinguish characteristic of a lawyer, but the lan- guage of Gains, a much higher authority, and the passage quoted before from the Institutes, leave no room for doubt, that the expressions were practically convertible. The difference between them was entirely historical, and no distinction in essence could ever be established between them. It is almost unnecessary to add that the confusion Digitized by Microsoft® 56 LAW OF NATURE AND EQUITY [chap, m between Jus Gentium, or Law common to all Nations, and international law is entirely modern. The classical expression for international law is Jus Feciale, or the law of negotiation and diplo- macy. It is, however, unquestionable that indis- tinct impressions as to the meaning of Jus Gentium had considerable share in producing the modern theory that the relations of independent states are governed by the Law of Nature. It becomes necessary to investigate the Greek conceptions of Nature and her law. The word ^6criv Selden speaks of two cases in a certain Inner Temple MS. of Year Books ot Ed. II., where Roman texts are even cited with precise reference in the accustomed form of civilians. But this MS. is not now to be found, and, such references being otherwise unknown in other extant Year Books, it is safer to think that they were added by a specially learned scribe. See Maitland's Intro- duction to Y.a 3 Ed. II., Seld. Soc. 1905, p. xx. Digitized by Microsoft® Il8 NOTES [CHAP. IV called Shardelowe an old savage on the strength of Blackstone's misunderstanding. What is really curious in the matter is that Blackstone appears to have been misled by Selden (ad Fletam, P- S33)> ■who cites this to prove that Roman law had become unknown in the King's Courts in the reign of Edward III., though he does not use anything like Blackstone's rhetorical language about contempt and aversion. With all respect for Selden, I see no room for doubt that he did misunderstand the case ; perhaps he was nodding a little, for he calls Shardelowe J. " Shardus." His general thesis that knowledge of Roman law in England, except among professed canonists, declined rapidly after the reign of Edward II., is doubtless correct. But there was no question of hostility. Not the fourteenth or thirteenth, but the sixteenth century was the time of recrimination between common lawyers and civilians, and perhaps of some real danger to the Common Law (Maitland, "English Law and the Renaissance" ; Pollock, "The Expansion of the Common Law," p. 88). Maine's remarks on the enthusiasm of French lawyers for natural law (p. 88 sqq.) seems rather to ignore its general reception by Continental publicists ; though the centralization of the French monarchy no doubt made it easier for them to have something like uniform official doctrine. The enfranchising ordinance of Louis Hutin cited at p. 97, which asserts that all men ought to be free by natural law, repeats an earlier one issued by Philip the Fair in 1311 (" Journ. Soc. Comp. Legisl.," 1900, pp. 426-7). It is not very clear that the framers of this ordinance were thinking of the Roman maxim, " omnes homines natura aequales sunt" (or rather "quod ad ius naturale attinet omnes homines aequales sunt " : Ulpian in D. de div. reg. 50, 17, 32) ; for the general tone is decidedly more religious than secular, and the Church had always favoured manumission as a pious work. If they had wanted to vouch the authority of the Digest or the Insti- tutes that slavery was not recognised by the law of nature, they might easily have made the reference more pointed. That Ulpian did not mean to preach an ethical or political creed of equality is, as Maine says, plain enough ; his assertion is that slavery (like other inequalities of condition) is justified only by positive law. At the same time no medieval publicist who desired to use the passage for his own purposes would have troubled himself about the author's original intention. In Justinian's authoritative declara- tion on the subject, already referred to in Note E, there is an ethical element which Maine seems to me to have underrated ; and this is the passage of the Corpus luris, if any, which was present to the mind of King Philip's counsellors. At p. 90 there is a statement about Dumoulin's opinions which I have not been able to verify. Charles Dumoulin (properly Du Molin, latinized as Molinaeus, 1500- 1566) was a profound jurist Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. IV] NOTES 119 and a famous champion of Gallican liberties against the Papal claims. He was for some time a Calvinist, and afterwards a Lutheran, but his biographer Julian Brodeau, whose book' seems to be the ultimate authority, was anxious to make it clear that he died a Catholic ; which from the Gallican point of view was only natural. His life was wandering and troubled, and is a striking example of the general disturbance into which the world of letters as well as of action was thrown by the Reformation contro- versies ; twice he fled from Paris, and twice his house was sacked under colour of zeal for Roman orthodoxy. The standard edition of his works was printed at Paris in 1681 in five volumes, folio, and is copiously indexed, I have not found in them anything about the law of nature except one depreciatory remark in a note on the Decretum of Gratian (Annotationes ad ius canonicum, in vol. 4): "politia externa regitur iure naturali et politico, sed utrumque subest divino quod altius est naturali." This directly contradicts the received theory, which put the law of nature (principles of right revealed in human reason) before the Law of God (interpretation of specific precepts communicated by external revelation). I suspect that Du Molin, writing at that time as a Protestant, took the Law of God to be the text of Scripture, and meant that the text was to be preferred to the reasonings of the schools : compare the so-called Protestant declaration formerly in use on the admission of Fellows at Trinity College, Cambridge, " verbum Dei iudiciis hominum praepositurum." Whatever the exact significance may be, Du Molin's observation is the reverse of a panegyric on the law of nature. One can only suppose that the rhetorical passages of which Maine appears to have had a pretty distinct recollection occur in some other French jurist of the time, and that the introduction of Du Molin's name was due to a slip of memory or to some accidental dislocation or misreading of manuscript notes It has already been pointed out that Maine greatly exaggerated the place of the " state of nature " in the doctrines of natural law. This comes out again in a startling manner in his remarks on Rousseau (p. 92).' Whatever Rousseau may have said elsewhere, we shall not find anything about the original perfection of man- kind in the " Contrat Social," to which Maine apparently meant to refer. Rousseau believed, certainly, in natural law, and to some extent in the virtues of the " natural man " as an individual; but his " state of nature " is not much better than Hobbes's ; it is ' La vie de Maistre Charles Du Molin, advocat au Parlement de Paris . , . et sa mort chrestienne et catholique. Par M" Julien Brodeau, advocat au mesme Parlement. Paris 1654, 4°. ' "Nothing that Rousseau had to say about the state of nature was seriously meant for scientific exposition, any more than the Sermon on the Mount was meant for political economy " (John Morley, " Rousseau," i. 183). Digitized by Microsoft® 120 NOTES [CHAP. IV unstable and becomes intolerable, and the social contract is dictated by the need of self-preservation (liv. i. ch. vi.) ; justice, which did not exist in the state of nature, is due to the establishment of political society (ch. viii.). This is not the place to speak at large of Rousseau's influence on the founders of American independence and the leaders of the French Revolution, ; but the careful research of American scholars has lately shown that the Principles of 1789 owed more to the American Declaration of Independence and the earlier Bills of Rights of several States than we used to suppose, and less to Rousseau, and that the language of the American constitutional instruments proceeded firom the school not of Rousseau but of Locke (Scherger, " The Evolution of Modem Liberty," New York, 1904). NOTE H THE ORIGINS OF THE MODERN LAW OF NATIONS Maine's statement (p. 100) seems to ignore the continuity of Grotius and his immediate precursors with the scholastic doctrine. It is true that the spread of the New Learning, and still more the Reformation, did largely increase the weight of the classical and diminish that of the medieval elements ; but it is also true that Grotius did not rely exclusively on Roman or on legal authorities. That Grotius and his contemporaries misunderstood the classical ius gentium, or supposed the modem rules of conduct between sovereign states to be contained in it, I am unable, with great respect for any suggestion of Maine's, to believe. The term had become less common than its practical synonym ius naturale in the Middle Ages, but came into fashion again with the Renaissance. Grotius, like Alberico Gentili, takes ius gentium as the rule of natural reason attested by general agreement, and makes it the starting-point of a new development. He may or may not have known that in its classical meaning it could, and sometimes did, include, among other rules of conduct sanctioned by general usage, whatever rules are reasonable and customary as between sovereign states. But as a scholar he must have known that genies is not the plural of civitas ox fo^ulus, which are the only apt words in classical Latin for a state or nation in its political capacity. At the same time Suarez had spoken of iura gentium, with an approach to the modem "law of nations," and Hooker had used the English term in a fully international sense (" Eccl. Pol." I. x. § 12). There was no reason for Grotius to refuse the assistance of a verbal ambiguity, so far as it existed and could further his purposes (cp. L.Q.R. xviii. 425-8). The modem law of nations embodies certain distinctly legal conceptions. These are Roman and purely Roman. Inasmuch as, from the sixteenth century onwards, Roman law was generally received throughout Western Christendom, with the one Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. IV] NOTES 121 material exception of England, as a kind of universal law, there is nothing surprising in this fact, and indeed nothing else could have happened. Maine's following observations (p. 105 sqq.) as to the application of Roman ideas in the modern law of nations, and especially the treatment of every independent State, with regard to its territory, as if it were an owner or claimant of ownership under Roman law, and the relatively modem character of purely territorial dominion, show the author at his best. The theoretical equality of independent States naturally follows from their recog- nition as analogous to free persons, who must have full and equal rights in the absence of any definite reason for inequality. This indeed is all that the maxim of men's equality before the law of nature declares or involves according to its classical meaning (p. 118 above). It is interesting in connexion with Maine's thesis to observe how in our time the usual rules of international law cease to be applicable, or fail to give an adequate solution of difiBculties, just in proportion as the fact of territorial sovereignty is not complete and definite. This is now of frequent occurrence in cases of "spheres of influence" in unsettled parts of the world, of pro- tectorates, and of what are called semi-sovereign States dependent in various degrees on other and more powerful ones. In the last- named class we may notice a certain reversion to feudal con- ceptions. It would have been much easier to express the relations of Great Britain to the late South African Republic in medieval than in classical Latin. As to the Anglo-Saxon kingship, it should be remembered that the English kings never owed or rendered any temporal allegiance to the Empire or any other power, and that the assumption of the imperial title " Basileus " involved a pretty strong claim to temporal supremacy within approximately certain territorial limits. In this respect the situation of England was peculiar. Modem national sovereignty may be regarded, in a general way, as a reaction against both the feudal and the imperial conceptions. Rulers of the Middle Ages, as and when they felt strong enough, expressly or tacitly renounced both homage to any overlord and submission to the Emperor. A German electoral prince or grand duke in the decadence of the Holy Roman Empire, say the Elector of Brandenburg, is firom the strictly feudal point of view an overgrown tenant of the Emperor who has added one " immunity " to another till he has strained the tie of fealty to the breaking point. From the strictly imperial point of view, if it had been maintamed to any practical purpose, he would or might be a rebel. Feudal tenure, however, probably led to the notion of the territory ruled by a sovereign prince being really — not by mere analogy to ownership in private law — his property. For, so long as overlordship was a reality, every principality, short of the Empire and the few monarchies which did not acknowledge the Digitized by Microsoft® 122 NOTES [CHAP- »* Emperor as superior, tifas in theory a "tenement"; and in the feudal system a tenement is indistinguishable from property; for absolute property is not recognised save in the supreme overlord, as is the strict theory of English and Scottish law to this day. This ultimate and now shadowy feudal superiority has nothing to do with the modem and purely political conception of Eminent Domain, though more than once they have been confused by able writers. It must not be supposed, however, that medieval lawyers were incapable of distinguishing between territorial sovereignty and feudal overlordship. The distinction was clearly made in 1284 by the framers of Edward I.'s Statute of Wales. In its preamble the king is made to acknowledge the bounty of Providence whereby the land of Wales, formerly subject to him as a fief, has been wholly reduced into his lordship in possession and annexed to his crown as part of the body of the kingdom. " Divina Providentia . . inter alia dispensacionis sue munera quibus nos et regnum nostrum Anglie decorare dignata est terrain Wallie cum incolis suis prius nobis iure feodali subiectam iam sui [sic] gratia in proprietatis nostra dominium . , . totaliter et cum integritate convertit et corone Regni predict! tanquam partem corporis eiusdem anneiuit et univit " (" Statutes of the Realm," i. 55). Digitized by Microsoft® CHAPTER V PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW The necessity of submitting the subject of juris- prudence to scientific treatment has never been entirely lost sight of in modern times, and the essays which the consciousness of this necessity has produced have proceeded from minds of very various calibre, but there is not much presumption, I think, in asserting that what has hitherto stood in the place of science has for the most part been a set of guesses, those very guesses of the Roman lawyers which were examined in the two preceding chapters. A series of explicit statements, recog- nising and adopting these conjectural theories of a natural state, and of a system of principles congenial to it, has been continued with but brief interruption from the days of their inventors to our own. They appear in the annotations of the Glossators who founded modern jurisprudence, v and in the writings of the scholastic jurists who succeeded them. They are visible in the dogmas of the canonists. They are thrust into prominence by those civilians of marvellous erudition, who flourished at the revival of ancient letters. Grotius and his successors invested them not more with brilliancy and plausibility than with practical importance. They may be read in the intro- ductory chapters of our own Blackstone, who has Digitized by microsoft® 124 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW [chap, t transcribed them textually from Burlamaqui, and wherever the manuals published in the present day for the guidance of the student or the practitioner begin with any discussion of the first principles of law, it always resolves itself into a restatement of the Roman hypothesis. It is however from the disguises with which these conjectures sometimes clothe themselves, quite as much as from their native form, that we gain an adequate idea of the subtlety with which they mix themselves in human thought. The Lockeian theory of the origin of Law in a Social Compact scarcely conceals its Roman derivation, and indeed is only the dress by which the ancient views were rendered more attractive to a particular generation of the moderns ; but on the other hand the theory of Hobbes on the same subject was purposely devised to repudiate the reality of a law of nature as conceived by the Romans and their disciples. Yet these two theories, which long divided the reflecting politicians of England into hostile camps, resemble each other strictly in their fundamental assumption of a non-historic, unverifiable condi- tion of the race. Their authors differed as to the characteristics of the prae-social state, and as to the nature of the abnormal action by which men lifted themselves out of it into that social organi- sation with which alone we are acquainted, but they agreed in thinking that a great chasm separ- ated man in his primitive condition from man in society, and this notion we cannot doubt that they borrowed, consciously or unconsciously, from the Romans. If indeed the phenomena of law be regarded in the way in which these' theorists Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP- V] MONTESQUIEU 125 regarded them — that is, as one vast complex whole — it is not surprising that the mind should often evade the task it has set to itself by falling back on some ingenious conjecture which (plausibly interpreted) will seem to reconcile everything, or else that it should sometimes abjure in despair the labour of systematisation. From the theories of jurisprudence which have , the same speculative basis as the Roman doctrine two of much celebrity must be excepted. The first of them is that associated with the great name of Montesquieu. Though there are some ambiguous expressions in the early part of the Esprit des Lois, which seem to show its writer's unwillingness to break quite openly with the views hitherto popular, the general drift of the book is certainly to indicate a very different conception of its subject from any which had been entertained before. It has often been noticed that, amidst the vast variety of examples which, in its immense width of survey, it sweeps together from supposed systems of jurisprudence, there is an evident anxiety to thrust into especial prominence those manners and institutions which astonish the civilised reader by their uncouthness, strangeness, or indecency. The inference constantly suggested is, that laws are the creatures of climate, local situation, accident, or imposture — the fruit of any causes except those which appear to operate with tolerable constancy. Montesquieu seems, in fact, to have looked on the nature of man as entirely plastic, as passively reproducing the impressions, and submitting implicitly to the impulses, which it receives from without. And here no doubt lies Digitized by Microsoft® 126 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW [chap, t the error which vitiates his system as a system. He greatly underrates the stabiUty of human nature. He pays Httle or no regard to the in- herited qualities of the race, those qualities which each generation receives from its predecessors, and transmits but sUghtly altered to the generation which foUows it. It is quite true, indeed, that no complete account can be given of social phe- nomena, and consequently of laws, tiU due allow- ance has been made for those modifying causes which are noticed in the Esprit des Lois ; but their number and their force appear to have been over-estimated by Montesquieu. Many of the anomaUes which he parades have since been shown to rest on false report or erroneous con- struction, and of those which remain not a few prove the permanence rather than the variableness of man's nature, since they are reUcs of older stages of the race which have obstinately defied the influences that have elsewhere had effect. The truth is that the stable part of our mental, moral, and physical constitution is the largest part of it, and the resistance it opposes to change is such that, though the variations of human society in a portion of the world are plain enough, they are neither so rapid nor so extensive that their amount, character, and general direction cannot be ascertained. An approximation to truth may be all that is attainable with our present knowledge, but there is no reason for thinking that it is so remote, or (what is the same thing) that it requires so much future correction, as to be entirely useless and uninstructive. The other theory which has been adverted to Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. V] BENTHAM 127 is, the historical theory of Bentham. This theory which is obscurely (and, it might even be said, timidly) propounded in several parts of Bentham's works is quite distinct from that analysis of the conception of law which he commenced in the " Fragment on Government," and which was more recently completed by Mr. John Austin. The resolution of a law into a command of a particular nature, imposed under special conditions, does not affect to do more than protect us against a diffi- culty — a most formidable one certainly — of lan- guage. The whole question remains open as to the motives of societies in imposing these com- mands on themselves, as to the connection of these commands with each other, and the nature of their dependence on those which preceded them, and which they have superseded. Bentham sug- gests the answer that societies modify, and have always modified, their laws according to modifica- tions of their views of general expediency. It is difficult to say that this proposition is false, but it certainly appears to be unfruitful. For that which seems expedient to a society, or rather to the governing part of it, when it alters a rule of law, is surely the same thing as the object, whatever it may be, which it has in view when it makes the change. Expediency and the greatest good are nothing more than different names for the impulse which prompts the modification ; and when we lay down expediency as the rule of change in law or opinion, all we get by the proposition is the substitution of an express term for a term which is necessarily implied when we say that a change takes place. Digitized by Microsoft® 128 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW [chap, t There is such wide-spread dissatisfaction with existing theories of jurisprudence, and so general a conviction that they do not really solve the questions they pretend to dispose of, as to justify the suspicion that some Hne of inquiry, necessary to a perfect result, has been incompletely followed or altogether omitted by their authors. And indeed there is one remarkable omission with which all these speculations are chargeable, except perhaps those of Montesquieu. They take no account of what law has actually been at epochs remote from the particular period at which they made their appearance. Their originators care- fully observed the institutions of their own age and civihsation, and those of other ages and civilisations with which they had some degree of intellectual sympathy, but, when they turned their attention to archaic states of society which ex- hibited much superficial difference from their own, they uniformly ceased to observe and began guessing. The mistake which they committed is therefore analogous to the error of one who, in investigating the laws of the material universe, should commence by contemplating the existing physical world as a whole, instead of beginning with the particles which are its simplest ingre- dients. One does not certainly see why such a scientific solecism should be more defensible in jurisprudence than in any other region of thought. It would seem antecedently that we ought to commence with the simplest social forms in a state as near as possible to their rudimentary condition. In other words, if we followed the course usual in such inquiries, we should penetrate as far up as Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. V] XHE GERMANY OF TACITUS I29 we could in the history of primitive societies. The phenomena which early societies present us with are not easy at first to understand, but the difficulty of grappling with them bears no pro- portion to the perplexities which beset us in con- sidering the baffling entanglement of modern social organisation. It is a difficulty arising from their strangeness and uncouthhess, not from their number and complexity. One does not readily get over the surprise which they occasion whpn looked at from a modern point of view ; but when that is surmounted they are few enough and simple enough. But, even if they gave more trouble than they do, no pains would be wasted in ascer- taining the germs out of which has assuredly been unfolded every form of moral restraint which controls our actions and shapes our conduct at the present moment. The rudiments of the social state, so far as they are known to us at all, are known through testi- mony of three sorts — accounts by contemporary observers of civilisations less advanced than their own, the records which particular races have preserved concerning their primitive history, and ancient law. The first kind of evidence is the best we could have expected. As societies do not advance concurrently, but at different rates of progress, there have been epochs at which men trained to habits of methodical observation have really been in a position to watch and describe the infancy of mankind. Tacitus made the most of such an opportunity ; but the Germany, unlike most celebrated classical books, has not induced others to follow the excellent example set by its Digitized by Microsoft® 9 130 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW [chap, v author, and the amount of this sort of testimony which we possess is exceedingly small. The lofty contempt which a civilised people entertains for barbarous neighbours has caused a remarkable negligence in observing them, and this carelessness has been aggravated at times by fear, by rehgious prejudice, and even by the use of these very terms — civilisation and barbarism — which convey to most persons the impression of a difference not merely in degree but in kind. Even the Germany has been suspected by some critics of sacrificing fidelity to poignancy of contrast and picturesque- ness of narrative. Other histories, too, which have been handed down to us among the archives of the people to whose infancy they relate have been thought distorted by the pride of race or by the religious sentiment of a newer age. It is important then to observe that these suspicions, whether groundless or rational, do not attach to a great deal of archaic law. Much of the old law which has descended to us was preserved merely because it was old. Those who practised and obeyed it did not pretend to understand it ; and in some cases they even ridiculed and despised it. They offered no account of it except that it had come down to them from their ancestors. If we confine our attention, then, to those fragments of ancient institutions which cannot reasonably be supposed to have been tampered with, we are able to gain a clear conception of certain great cha- racteristics of the society to which they originally belonged. Advancing a step further, we can apply our knowledge to systems of law which, like the Code of Manu, are as a whole of suspicious Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP, y] PATRIARCHAL THEORY I3I authenticity ; and using the key we have obtained, we are in a position to discriminate those portions of them which are truly archaic from those which have been affected by the prejudices, interests, or ignorance of the compiler. It will at least be acknowledged that, if the materials for this process are sufficient, and if the comparisons be accurately executed, the methods followed are as Uttle objec- tionable as those which have led to such surprising results in comparative philology. The effect of the evidence derived from com- parative jurisprudence is to estabUsh that view of the primaeval condition of the human race which is known as the Patriarchal Theory. There is no/ doubt, of course, that this theory was originally based on the Scriptural history of the Hebrew patriarchs in Lower Asia ; but, as has been ex- plained already, its connection with Scripture rather miUtated than otherwise against its recep- tion as a complete theory, since the majority of the inquirers who till recently addressed themselves with most earnestness to the coUigation of social phenomena, were either influenced by the strongest prejudice against Hebrew antiquities or by the strongest desire to construct their system without the assistance of religious records. Even now there is perhaps a disposition to undervalue these accounts, or rather to decline generalising from them, as forming part of the traditions of a Semitic people It is to be noted, however, that the legal testimony comes nearly exclusively from the insti- tutions of societies belonging to the Indo-European stock, the Romans, Hindoos, and Sclavonians supplying the greater part of it ; and indeed the Digitized by Microsoft® 132 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW [chap, v difficulty, at the present stage of the inquiry, is to know where to stop, to say of what races of men it is not allowable to lay down that the society in which they are united was originally organised on the patriarchal model. The chief hneaments of such a society, as collected from the early chapters in Genesis, I need not attempt to depict ■with, any minuteness, both because they are familiar to most of us from our earhest childhood, and because, from the interest once attaching to the contro- versy which takes its name from the debate be- tween Locke and Filmer, they fill a whole chapter, though not a very profitable one, in English litera- ture. The points which Lie on the surface of the history are these : — The eldest male parent — the eldest ascendant — is absolutely supreme in his household. His dominion extends to life and death, and is as unqualified over his children and their houses as over his slaves ; indeed, the re- lations of sonship and serfdom appear to differ in little beyond the higher capacity which the child in blood possesses of becoming one day the head of a family himself. The flocks and herds of the children are the flocks and herds of the father, and the possessions of the parent, which he holds in a representative rather than in a proprietary character, are equally divided at his death among his descendants in the first degree, the eldest sor. sometimes receiving a double share under the name of birthright, but more generally endowed with no hereditary advantage beyond an honorary precedence. A less obvious inference from the Scriptural accounts is that they seem to plant us on the traces of the breach which is first effected Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP.v] CYCLOPEAN FAMILY I33 in the empire of the parent. The families of Jacob and Esau separate and form two nations ; but the families of Jacob's children hold together and become a people. This looks like the immature germ of a state or commonwealth, and of an order of rights superior to the claims of family relation. If I were attempting, for the more special pur- poses of the jurist, to express compendiously the characteristics of the situation in which mankind disclose themselves at the dawn of their history, I should be satisfied to quote a few verses from the Odyssey of Homer • Toio-iv 8" out' ayopaX jSovXrjtjiopoi oSre Oi/JLiOTK, iraiSoJC ^8' aXo^ayv, oiS" dAA^Xcuv aXiyovcriv. " They have neither assemblies for consultation nor themistes, but every one exercises jurisdiction over his wives and his children, and they pay no regard to one another." These lines are applied to the Cyclops, and it may not perhaps be an altogether fanciful idea when I suggest that the Cyclops is Homer's type of an alien and less advanced civilisation ; for the almost physical loathing which a primitive community feels for men of widely different manners from its own usually expresses itself by describing them as monsters, such as giants, or even (which is almost always the case in Oriental mythology) as demons. However that mayi be, the verses condense in themselves the sum of the hints which are given us by legal antiquities. Men are first seen dis- tributed in perfectly insulated groups, held to- gether by obedience to the parent. Law is the Digitized by Microsoft® 134 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW [chap, t parent's word, but it is not yet in the condition of those themistes which were analysed in the first chapter of this work. When we go forward to the state of society in which these early legal conceptions show themselves as formed, we find that they still partake of the mystery and spon- taneity which must have seemed to characterise a despotic father's commands, but that at the same time, inasmuch as they proceed from a sovereign, they presuppose a union of family groups in some wider organisation. The next question is, what is the nature of this union and the degree of intimacy which it involves ? It is just here that archaic law renders us one of the greatest of its services, and fills up a gap which otherwise could only have been bridged by conjecture. It is full, in all its provinces, of the clearest indications that society in primitive times was not what it is assumed to be at present, a collection of individuals. In fact, and in the view of the men who composed it, it was an aggregation of families. The contrast may be most forcibly expressed by saying that the unit of an ancient society was the Family, of a modern society the individual. We must be prepared to find in ancient law all the consequences of this difference. It is so framed as to be adjusted to a system of small independent corporations. It is therefore scanty, because it is supplemented by the despotic commands of the heads of households. It is ceremonious, because the transactions to which it pays regard resemble international concerns much more than the quick play of intercourse between individuals. Above all, it has a peculiarity Digitized by Microsoft® c»^r-y] THE FAMILY GROUP 135 of which the full importance cannot be shown at present. It takes a view of life wholly unHke any which appears in developed juris- prudence. Corporations never die, and accordingly primitive law considers the entities with which it deals, i.e., the patriarchal or family groups, as perpetual and inextinguishable. This view is closely allied to the peculiar aspect under which, in very ancient times, moral attributes present themselves. The moral elevation and moral de- basement of the individual appear to be con- founded with, or postponed to, the merits and offences of the group to which the individual belongs. If the community sins, its guilt is much more than the sum of the offences committed by its members ; the crime is a corporate act, and extends in its consequences to many more persons than have shared in its actual perpetration. If, on the other hand, the individual is conspicuously guilty, it is his children, his kinsfolk, his tribesmen, or his fellow-citizens who suffer with him, and sometimes for him. It thus happens that the ideas of moral responsibility and retribution often seem to be more clearly realised at very ancient than at more advanced periods, for, as the family group is immortal, and its liability to punishment indefinite, the primitive mind is not perplexed by the questions which become troublesome as soon as the individual is conceived as altogether separate from the group. One step in the tran- sition from the ancient and simple view of the matter to the theological or metaphysical ex- planations of later days is marked by the early Greek notion of an inherited curse. The bequest Digitized by Microsoft® 136 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW [chap, v received by his posterity from the original criminal was not a liability to punishment, but a liability to the commission of fresh offences which drew with them a condign retribution ; and thus the responsibility of the family was reconciled with the newer phase of thought which limited the consequences of crime to the person of the actual delinquent. It would be a very simple explanation of the origin of society if we could base a general con- clusion on the hint furnished us by the Scriptural example already adverted to, and could suppose that communities began to exist wherever a family held together instead of separating at the death of its patriarchal chieftain. In most of the Greek states and in Rome there long remained the vestiges of an ascending series of groups out of which the State was at first constituted. The Family, House, and Tribe of the Romans may be taken as the type of them, and they are so described to us that we can scarcely help conceiving them as a system of concentric circles which have gradually expanded from the same point. The elementary group is the Family, connected by common subjection to the highest male descendant. The aggregation of Families forms the Gens or House. The aggregation of Houses makes the Tribe. The aggregation of Tribes constitutes the commonwealth. Are we at Uberty to follow these indications, and to lay down that the common- wealth is a collection of persons united by common descent from the progenitor of an original family ? Of this we may at least be certain, that aU ancient societies regarded themselves as having proceeded Digitized by Microsoft® <=»*'•■'] FICTION OF KINSHIP I37 from one original stock, and even laboured under an incapacity for comprehending any reason except this for their holding together in poUtical union. The history of political ideas begins, in fact, with the assumption that kinship in blood is the sole possible ground of community in political functions ; nor is there any of those subversions of feeling, which we term emphatically revolutions, so startling and so complete as the change which is accomplished when some other principle — such as that, for instance, of local contiguity — establishes itself for the first time as the basis of common political action. It may be affirmed, then, of early commonwealths that their citizens considered all the groups in which they cMmed membership to be founded on common lineage. What was obviously true of the Family was believed to be true first of the House, next of the Tribe, lastly of the State. And yet we find that along with this belief, or, if we may use the word, this theory, each community preserved records or traditions which distinctly showed that the fundamental assumption was false. Whether we look to the Greek States, or to Rome, or to the Teutonic aristocracies in Ditmarsh which furnished Niebuhr with so many valuable illustrations, or to the Celtic clan associations, or to that strange social organisation of the Sclavonic Russians and Poles which has only lately attracted notice, everywhere we discover traces of passages in their history when men of alien descent were admitted to, and amedgamated with, the original brother- hood. Adverting to Rome singly, we perceive that the primary group, the Family, was being Digitized by Microsoft® 138 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW [chap, t constantly adulterated by the practice of adoption, while stories seem to have been always current respecting the exotic extraction of one of the original Tribes, and concerning a large addition to the Houses made by one of the early kings. The composition of the state uniformly assumed to be natural was nevertheless known to be in great measure artificial. This conflict between behef or theory and notorious fact is at first sight extremely perplexing ; but what it really illus- trates is the efficiency with which Legal Fictions do their work in the infancy of society. The earliest and most extensively employed of legal fictions was that which permitted family relations to be created artificially, and there is none to which I conceive mankind to be more deeply indebted. If it had never existed, I do not see how any one of the primitive groups, whatever were their nature, could have absorbed another, or on what terms any two of them could have combined, except those of absolute superiority on one side and absolute subjection on the other. No doubt, when with our modern ideas we contemplate the union of independent communities, we can suggest a hundred modes of carr5ang it out, the simplest of all being that the individuals comprised in the coalescing groups shall vote or act together accord- ing to local propinquity ; but the idea that a num- ber of persons should exercise political rights in common simply because they happened to live within the same topographical limits was utterly strange and monstrous to primitive antiquity. The expedient which in those times commanded favour was that the incoming population should Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP.T] CLAN AND COMMONWEALTH I39 feign themselves to be descended from the same stock as the people on whom they were engrafted ; and it is precisely the good faith of this fiction, and the closeness with which it seemed to imitate reality, that we cannot now hope to understand. One circumstance, however, which it is important to recollect, is that the men who formed the various poUtical groups were certainly in the habit of meeting together periodically for the purpose of acknowledging and consecrating their association by common sacrifices. Strangers amalgamated with the brotherhood were doubtless admitted to these sacrifices ] and when that was once done, we can believe that it seemed equally easy, or not more difficult, to conceive them as sharing in the common lineage. The conclusion, then, which is suggested by the evidence is, not that all early societies were formed by descent from the same ancestor, but that aU of them which had any permanence and solidity either were so descended or assumed that they were. An indefinite number of causes may have shattered the primitive groups, but wherever their ingredients recombined, it was on the model or principle of an association of kindred. Whatever were the facts, all thought, language, and law adjusted themselves to the assumption. But though all this seems to me to be established with reference to the communities with whose records we are acquainted, the re- mainder of their history sustains the position before laid down as to the essentially transient and terminable influence of the most powerful Legal Fictions. At some point of time — probably as soon as they felt themselves strong enough to Digitized by Microsoft® 140 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW [chap, v resist extrinsic pressure — all these states ceased to recruit themselves by factitious extensions of consanguinity. They necessarily, therefore, became Aristocracies, in aU cases where a fresh population from any cause collected around them I which could put in no claim to community of [origin. Their sternness in maintaining the central principle of a system under which political rights were attainable on no terms whatever except connection in blood, real or artificial, taught their inferiors another principle, which proved to be endowed with a far higher measure of vitaUty. This was the principle of local contiguity, now recognised everywhere as the condition of com- munity in poUtical functions. A new set of political ideas came at once into existence, which, being those of ourselves, our contemporaries, and in great measure of our ancestors, rather obscure our perception of the older theory which they vanquished and dethroned. The family, then, is the type of an archaic society in aU the modifications which it was capable of assuming ; but the family here spoken of is not exactly the family as understood by a modern. In order to reach the ancient conception we must give to our modern ideas an important extension and an important limitation. We must look on the family as constantly enlarged by the absorption of strangers within its circle, and we must try to regard the fiction of adoption as so closely simulating the reality of kinship that neither law nor opinion makes the slightest differ- ence between a real and an adoptive connection. On the other hand, the persons theoretically Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP, y] PATRIARCHAL AUTHORITY I4I amalgamated into a family by their common descent are practically held together by common obedience to their highest living ascendant, the father, grandfather, or great-grandfather. The patriarchal authority of a chieftain is as necessary an ingredient in the notion of the family group as the fact (or assumed fact) of its having sprung from his loins ; and hence we must understand that if there be any persons who, however truly included in the brotherhood by virtue of their blood-relationship, have nevertheless de facto with- drawn themselves from the empire of its ruler, they are always, in the beginnings of law, con- sidered as lost to the family. It is this patriarchal aggregate — the modern family thus cut down on one side and extended on the other — which meets us on the threshold of primitive jurisprudence. Older, probably, than the State, the Tribe, and the House, it left traces of itself on private law long after the House and the Tribe had been forgotten, and long after consanguinity had ceased to be associated with the composition of States. It wiU be found to have stamped itself on aU the great departments of jurisprudence, and may be detected, I think, as the true source of many of their most important and most durable character- istics. At the outset, the pecuUarities of law in its most ancient state lead us irresistibly to the conclusion that it took precisely the same view of the family group which is taken of individual men by the systems of rights and duties now prevalent throughout Europe. There are societies open to our observation at this very moment whose laws and usages can scarcely be explained unless they Digitized by Microsoft® 142 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW [chap, v are supposed never to have emerged from this primitive condition ; but in communities more for- tunately circumstanced the fabric of jurisprudence fell gradually to pieces, and if we carefully observe the disintegration we shall perceive that it took place principally in those portions of each system which were most deeply affected by the primitive conception of the family. In one all-important instance, that of the Roman law, the change was effected so slowly, that from epoch to epoch we can observe the line and direction which it fol- lowed, and can even give some idea of the ultimate result to which it was tending. And in pursuing this last inquiry we need not suffer ourselves to be stopped by the imaginary barrier which separates the modern from the ancient world. For one effect of that mixture of refined Roman law with primitive barbaric usage, which is known to us by the deceptive name of feudalism, was to revive many features of archaic jurisprudence which had died out of the Roman world, so that the decom- position which had seemed to be over commenced again, and to some extent is still proceeding. On a few systems of law the family organisation of the earliest society has left a plain and broad mark in the Ufe-long authority of the Father or other ancestor over the person and property of his descendants, an authority which we may con- veniently call by its later Roman name of Patria Potestas. No feature of the rudimentary associa- tions of mankind is deposed to by a greater amount of evidence than this, and yet none seems to have disappeared so generally and so rapidly from the usages of advancing communities. Gaius, writing Digitized by Microsoft® <»*'•▼] PATRIA POTESTAS I43 under the Antonines, describes the institution as distinctively Roman. It is true that, had he glanced across the Rhine or the Danube to those tribes of barbarians which were exciting the curiosity of some among his contemporaries, he would have seen examples of patriarchal power in its crudest form ; and in the far East a branch of the same ethnical stock from which the Romans sprang was repeating their Patria Potestas in some of its most technical incidents. But among the races understood to be comprised within the Roman Empire, Gains could find none which exhibited an institution resembUng the Roman " Power of the Father," except only the Asiatic Galatae. There are reasons, indeed, as it seems to me, why the direct authority of the ancestor should, in the greater number of progressive societies, very shortly assume humbler proportions than belonged to it in their earUest state. The implicit obedience of rude men to their parent is doubtless a primary fact, which it would be absurd to explain away altogether by attributing to them any calculation of its advantages ; but, at the same time, if it is natursil in the sons to obey the father, it is equally natural that they should look to him for superior strength or superior wisdom. Hence, when societies are placed under circumstances which cause an especial value to be attached to bodily and mental vigour, there is an influence at work which tends to confine the Patria Potestas to the cases where its possessor is actually skilful and strong. When we obtain our first glimpse of organised Hellenic society, it seems as if super- eminent wisdom would keep alive the father's Digitized by Microsoft® 144 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW [chap, v power in persons whose bodily strength had de- cayed ; but the relations of Ulysses and Laertes in the Odyssey appear to show that, where extra- ordinary valour and sagacity were united in the son, the father in the decrepitude of age was deposed from the headship of the family. In the mature Greek jurisprudence, the rule advances a few steps on the practice hinted at in the Homeric literature ; and though very many traces of stringent family obligation remain, the direct authority of the parent is limited, as in European codes, to the nonage or minority of the children, or, in other words, to the period during which their mental and physical inferiority may always be presumed. The Roman law, however, with its remarkable tendency to innovate on ancient usage only just so far as the exigency of the common- wealth may require, preserves both the primeval institution and the natural hmitation to which I conceive it to have been subject. In every relation of Ufe in which the collective community might have occasion to avail itself of his wisdom and strength, for aU purposes of counsel or of war, the Filius FamiUas, or Son under Power, was as free as his father. It was a maxim of Roman jurisprudence that the Patria Potestas did not extend to the Jus PubUcum. Father and son voted together in the city, and fought side by side in the field ; indeed, the son, as general, might happen to command the father, or, as magistrate, decide on his contracts and punish his delinquen- cies. But in all the relations created by Private Law, the son lived under a domestic despotism which, considering the severity it retained to the Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. V] PATRIA POTESTAS I45 last, and the number of centuries through which it endured, constitutes one of the strangest problems in legal history. The Patria Potestas of the Romans, which is necessarily our type of the primeval paternal authority, is equally difficult to understand as an institution of civiUsed Ufe, whether we consider its incidence on the person or its effects on property. It is to be regretted that a chasm which exists in its history cannot be more completely filled. So far as regards the person, the parent, when our information commences, has over his children the jus vitcB necisque, the power of life and death, and d fortiori of uncontrolled corporal chastisement ; he can modify their personal condition at pleasure ; he can give a wife to his son ; he can give his daughter in marriage ; he can divorce his children of either sex ; he can transfer them to another family by adoption ; and he can sell them. Late in the Imperial period we find vestiges of all these powers, but they are reduced within very narrow limits. The unqualified right of domestic chas- tisement has become a right of bringing domestic offences under the cognisance of the civil magis- trate ; the privilege of dictating marriage has decUned into a conditional veto ; the hberty of selling has been virtually abolished, and adoption itself, destined to lose almost all its ancient im- portance in the reformed system of Justinian, can no longer be effected without the assent of the child transferred to the adoptive parentage. In short, we are brought very close to the verge of the ideas which have at length prevailed in the modern world. But between these widely distant Digitized by Microsoft® ^^ 146 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW [chap, v epochs there is an interval of obscurity, and we can only guess at the causes which permitted the Patria Potestas to last as long as it did by rendering it more tolerable than it appears. The active discharge of the most important among the duties which the son owed to the state must have tem- pered the authority of his parent, if they did not annul it. We can readily persuade ourselves that the paternal despotism could not be brought into play, without great scandal, against a man of full age occupying a high civil office. During the earUer history, however, such cases of practical emancipation would be rare compared with those which must have been created by the constant wars of the Roman repubUc. The miUtary tribune and the private soldier, who were in the field three-quarters of a year during the earher contests, at a later period the proconsul in charge of a province, and the legionaries who occupied it, cannot have had practical reason to regard them- selves as the slaves of a despotic master ; and aU these avenues of escape tended constantly to multiply themselves. Victories led to conquests, conquests to occupations ; the mode of occupation by colonies was exchanged for the system of occupying provinces by standing armies. Each step in advance was a call for the expatriation of more Roman citizens, and a fresh draft on the blood of the failing Latin race. We may infer, I think, that a strong sentiment in favour of the relaxation of the Patria Potestas had become fixed by the time that the pacification of the world commenced on the establishment of the Empire. The first serious blows at the ancient institution Digitized by Microsoft® <^*''] P ATRIA POTESTAS I47 are attributed to the eariier Caesars, and some isolated interferences of Trajan and Hadrian seem to have prepared the ground for a series of express enactments which, though we cannot always de- termine their dates, we know to have limited the father's powers on the one hand, and on the other to have multipUed facilities for their voluntary surrender. The older mode of getting rid of the Potestas, by effecting a triple sale of the son's person, is evidence, I may remark, of a very early feeUng against the unnecessary prolongation of the powers. The rule which declared that the son should be free after having been three times sold by his father seems to have been originally meant to entail penal consequences on a practice which revolted even the imperfect morality of the primitive Roman. But even before the pubUca- tion of the Twelve Tables, it had been turned, by the ingenuity of the jurisconsults, into an expedient for destroying the parental authority wherever the father desired that it should cease. Many of the causes which helped to mitigate the stringency of the father's power over the persons of his children are doubtless among those which do not lie upon the face of history. We cannot tell how far public opinion may have paralysed an authority which the law conferred ; or how far natural affection may have rendered it endurable. But though, the powers over the person may have been latterly nominal, the whole tenour of the extant Roman jurisprudence suggests that the father's rights over the son's property were always exercised without scruple to the full extent to which they were sanctioned by law. Digitized by Microsoft® 148 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW [chap, v There is nothing to astonish us in the latitude of these rights when they first show themselves. The ancient law of Rome forbade the Children under Power to hold property apart from their parent, or (we should rather say) never contem- plated the possibility of their claiming a separate ownership. The father was entitled to take the whole of the son's acquisitions, and to enjoy the benefit of his contracts, without being entangled in any compensating liability. So much as this we should expect from the constitution of the earliest Roman society ; for we can hardly form a notion of the primitive family group unless we suppose that its members brought their earnings of all kinds into the common stock, while they were unable to bind it by improvident individual engagements. The true enigma of the Patria Potestas does not reside here, but in the slowness with which these proprietary privileges of the parent were curtailed, and in the circumstance that, before they were seriously diminished, the whole civilised world was brought within their sphere. No innovation of any kind was attempted till the first years of the Empire, when the acquisi- tions of soldiers on service were withdrawn from the operation of the Patria Potestas, doubtless as part of the reward of the armies which had overthrown the free commonwealth. Three cen- turies afterwards the same immunity was extended to the earnings of persons who were in the civil employment of the state. Both changes were obviously limited in their application, and they were so contrived in technical form as to interfere as little as possible with the principle of Patria Digitized by Microsoft® CKAPv] PATRIA POTESTAS I49 Potestas. A certain qualified and dependent ownership had always been recognised by the Roman law in the perquisites and savings which slaves and sons under power were not compelled to include in the household accounts, and the special name of this permissive property, Peculium, was applied to the acquisitions newly relieved from Patria Potestas, which were called in the case of soldiers Castrense Peculium, and Quasi-castrense Peculium in the case of civil servants. Other modifications of the parental privileges followed, which showed a less studious outward respect for the ancient principle. Shortly after the introduc- tion of the Quasi-castrense Pecuhum, Constantine the Great took away the father's absolute control over property which his children had inherited from their mother, and redticed it to a usufruct, or life-interest. A few more changes of slight importance followed in the Western Empire, but the furthest point reached was in the East, under Justinian, who enacted that unless the acquisitions of the child were derived from the parent's own property, the parent's right over them should not extend beyond enjoying their produce for the period of his fife. Even this, the utmost relaxation of the Roman Patria Potestas, left it far ampler and severer than any analogous institution of the modern world. The earliest modern writers on jurisprudence remark that it was only the fiercer and ruder of the conquerors of the Empire, and notably the nations of Sclavonic origin, which exhibited a Patria Potestas at all resembling that which was described in the Pandects and the Code. All the Germanic immigrants seem to have Digitized by Microsoft® 150 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW [chap- ▼ recognised a corporate union of the family under the mund, or authority of a patriarchal chief ; but his powers are obviously only the relics of a decayed Patria Potestas, and fell far short of those enjoyed by the Roman father. The Franks are particularly mentioned as not having the Roman Institution, and accordingly the old French lawyers, even when most busily engaged in filling the interstices of barbarous customs with rules of Roman law, were obliged to protect themselves against the intrusion of the Potestas by the express maxim, Puyssance de fere en France n'a lieu. The tenacity of the Romans in maintaining this reUc of their most ancient condition is in itself remarkable, but it is less remarkable than the diffusion of the Potestas over the whole of a civilisation from which it had once disappeared. While the Castrense PecuUum constituted as yet the sole exception to the father's power over property, and while his power over his children's persons was still exten- sive, the Roman citizenship, and with it the Patria Potestas, were spreading into every corner of the Empire. Every African or Spaniard, every Gaul, Briton, or Jew, who received this honour by gift, purchase, or inheritance, placed himself under the Roman Law of Persons, and, though our authorities intimate that children born before the acquisition of citizenship could not be brought under Power against their will, children born after it and aU ulterior descendants were on the ordinary footing of a Roman filius familias. It does not fall within the province of this treatise to examine the mechanism of the later Roman society, but I may be permitted to remark that there is Uttle Digitized by Microsoft® •^*'-^] PATRIA POTESTAS I51 foundation for the opinion which represents the constitution of Antoninus Caracalla conferring Roman citizenship on the whole of his subjects as a measure of small importance. However we may interpret it, it must have enormously enlarged the sphere of the Patria Potestas, and it seems to me that the tightening of family relations which it effected is an agency which ought to be kept in view more than it has been, in accounting for the great moral revolution which was transforming the world. Before this branch of our subject is dismissed, it should be observed that the Paterfamilias was answerable for the delicts (or torts) of his Sons under Power. He was similarly liable for the torts of his slaves ; but in both cases he originally possessed the singular privilege of tendering the dehnquent's person in full satisfaction of the damage. The responsibihty thus incurred oiT behalf of sons, coupled with the mutual incapacity of Parent and Child under Power to sue one another, has seemed to some jurists to be best explained by the assumption of a " unity of person " between the Paterfamilias and the Filius- familias. In the Chapter on Successions I shall attempt to show in what sense, and to what extent, this " unity " can be accepted as a reality. I can only say at present that these responsibilities of the Paterfamilias, and other legal phenomena which will be discussed hereafter, appear to me to point at certain duties of the primitive Patriarchal chieftain which balanced his rights. I conceive that, if he disposed absolutely of the persons and fortunes of his clansmen, this representative Digitized by Microsoft® 152 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW [chap, v ownership was coextensive with a habiUty to pro- vide for all members of the brotherhood out of the common fund. The difficulty is to throw our- selves out of our habitual associations sufficiently for conceiving the nature of his obligation. It was not a legal duty, for law had not yet penetrated into the precinct of the Family. To call it moral is perhaps to anticipate the ideas belonging to a later stage of mental development ; but the ex- pression " moral obhgation " is significant enough for our purpose, if we understand by it a duty semi-consciously followed and enforced rather by instinct and habit than by definite sanctions. The Patria Potestas, in its normal shape, has not been, and, as it seems to me, could not have been, a generally durable institution. The proof of its former universahty is therefore incomplete so long as we consider it by itself ; but the demon- stration may be carried much further by examining other departments of ancient law which depend on it ultimately, but not by a thread of coimection visible in all its parts or to all eyes. Let us turn for example to Kinship, or in other words, to the scale on which the proximity of relatives to each other is calculated in archaic jurisprudence. Here again it wiU be convenient to employ the Roman terms. Agnatic and Cognatic relationship. Cog- natic relationship is simply the conception of kinship familiar to modern ideas : it is the relation- ship arising through common descent from the same pair of married persons, whether the descent be traced through males or females. Agnatic relationship is something very different : it ex- cludes a number of persons whom we in our day Digitized by Microsoft® oiAP-T] AGNATION AND COGNATION 153 should certainly consider of kin to ourselves, and it includes many more whom we should never reckon among our kindred. It is in truth the connection existing between the mernbers of the Family, conceived as it was in the most ancient times. The limits of this connection are far from conterminous with those of modern relation- ship. Cognates then are all those persons who can trace their blood to a single ancestor and ances- tress ; or if we take the strict technical meaning of the word in Roman law, they are all who trace their blood to the legitimate marriage of a common pair. " Cognation " is therefore a relative term, and the degree of connection in blood which it indicates depends on the particular marriage which is selected as the commencement of the calculation. If we begin with the marriage of father and mother, Cognation wiU only express the relationship of brothers and sisters ; if we take that of the grandfather and grandmother, then uncles, aunts, and their descendants wiU also be included in the notion of Cognation, and following the same process a larger number of Cognates may be continually obtained by choosing the starting point higher and higher up in the Une of ascent. All this is easily understood by a modern ; but who are the Agnates ? In the first place, they are all the Cognates who trace their connection exclusively through males. A table of Cognates is, of course, formed by taking each hneal ancestor in turn and including all his de- scendants of both sexes in the tabular view ; if then, in tracing the various branches of such a Digitized by Microsoft® 154 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW [chap- ' genealogical table or tree, we stop whenever we come to the name of a female and pursue that particular branch or ramification no further, all who remain after the descendants of women have been excluded are Agnates, and their connection together is Agnatic Relationship. I dwell a httle on the process which is practically followed in separating them from the Cognates, because it explains a memorable legal maxim, " Mulier est finis famiUae " — a woman is the terminus of the family. A female name closes the branch or twig of the genealogy in which it occurs. None of the descendants of a female are included in the primitive notion of family relationship. If the system of archaic law at which we are looking be one which admits Adoption, we must add to the Agnates thus obtained all persons, male or female, who have been brought into the family by the artificial extension of its boundaries. But the descendants of such persons will only be Agnates, if they satisfy the conditions which have just been described. What then is the reason of this arbitrary in- clusion and exclusion ? Why should a conception of Kinship so elastic as to include strangers brought into the family by adoption, be nevertheless so narrow as to shut out the descendants of a female member ? To solve these questions we must recur to the Patria Potestas. The foundation of Agna- tion is not the marriage of Father and Mother, but the authority of the Father. All persons are Agnatically connected together who are under the same Paternal Power, or who have been under it, or who might have been under it if their lineal Digitized by Microsoft® CHA'- ▼] AGNATION 155 ancestor had lived long enough to exercise his empire. In truth, in the primitive view, Relation- ship is exactly Umited by Patria Potestas. Where the Potestas begins. Kinship begins ; and there- fore adoptive relatives are among the kindred. Where the Potestas ends. Kinship ends ; so that a son emancipated by his father loses all rights of Agnation. And here we have the reason why the descendants of females are outside the hmits of archaic kinship. If a woman died unmarried, she could have no legitimate descendants. If she married, her children fell under the Patria Potestas, not of her Father, but of her Husband, and thus were lost to her own family. It is obvious that the organisation of primitive societies would have been confounded, if men had called themselves relatives of their mother's relatives. The in- ference would have been that a person might be subject to two distinct Patriae Potestates ; but distinct Patriae Potestates imphed distinct juris- dictions, so that anybody amenable to two of them at the same time would have lived under two different dispensations. As long as the Family was an imperium in imperio, a community within the commonwealth governed by its own institutions of which the parent was the source, the Umitation of relationship to the Agnates was a necessary security against a conflict of laws in the domestic forum. The Paternsil Powers proper are extinguished by the death of the Parent, but Agnation is as it were a mould which retains their imprint after they have ceased to exist. Hence comes the interest of Agnation for the inquirer into the history of Digitized by Microsoft® 156 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW [chap, v jurisprudence. The powers themselves are dis- cernible in comparatively few monuments of ancient law, but Agnatic Relationship, which implies their former existence, is discoverable almost everywhere. There are few indigenous bodies of law belonging to communities of the Indo-European stock, which do not exhibit pecu- Harities in the most ancient part of their structure which are clearly referable to Agnation. In Hindoo law, for example, which is saturated with the primitive notions of family dependency, kin- ship is entirely Agnatic, and I am informed that in Hindoo genealogies the names of women are generally omitted altogether. The same view of relationship pervades so much of the laws of the races who overran the Roman Empire as appears to have really formed part of their primitive usage, and we may suspect that it would have per- petuated itself even more than it has in modem European jurisprudence, if it had not been for the vast influence of the later Roman law on modern thought. The Praetors early laid hold on Cognation as the natural form of kinship, and spared no pains in purifying their system from the older conception. Their ideas have descended to us, but still traces of Agnation are to be seen in many of the modern rules of succession after death. The exclusion of females and their children from governmental functions, commonly attri- buted to the usage of the Salian Franks, has certainly an agnatic origin, being descended from the ancient German rule of succession to allodial property. In Agnation too is to be sought the explanation of that extraordinary rule of EngUsh Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP.v] GUARDIANSHIP OF WOMEN I57 Law, only recently repealed, which prohibited brothers of the half-blood from succeeding to one another's lands. In the Customs of Normandy, the rule applies to uterine brothers only, that is, to brothers by the same mother but not by the same father ; and, Umited in this way, it is a strict deduction from the system of Agnation, under which uterine brothers are no relations at all to one another. When it was transplanted to Eng- land, the Enghsh judges, who had no clue to its principle, interpreted it as a general prohibition against the succession of the half-blood, and extended it to consanguineous brothers, that is to sons of the same father by different wives. In all the literature whch enshrines the pretended philosophy of law, there is nothing more curious than the pages of elaborate sophistry in which Blackstone attempts to explain and justify the exclusion of the half-blood. It may be shown, I think, that the Family, as held together by the Patria Potestas, is the nidus out of which the entire Law of Persons has ger- minated. Of all the chapters of that Law the most important is that which is concerned with the status of Females. It has just been stated that Primitive Jurisprudence, though it does not allow a Woman to communicate any rights of Agnation to her descendants, includes herself nevertheless in the Agnatic bond. Indeed, the relation of a female to the family in which she was born is much stricter, closer, and more durable than that which unites her male kinsmen. We have several times laid down that early law takes notice of Families only J this is the same thing as saying that it only Digitized by Microsoft® 158 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW [chap. ▼ takes notice of persons exercising Patria Potestas, and accordingly the only principle on which it enfranchises a son or grandson at the death of his Parent, is a consideration of the capacity inherent in such son or grandson to become himself the head of a new family and the root of a new set of Parental Powers. But a woman, of course, has no capacity of the kind, and no title accordingly to the liberation which it confers. There is therefore a peculiar contrivance of archaic juris- prudence for retaining her in the bondage of the Family for Ufe. This is the institution known to the oldest Roman law as the Perpetual Tutelage of Women, under which a Female, though reheved from her Parent's authority by his decease, con- tinues subject through life to her nearest male relations, or to her father's nominees, as her Guardians. Perpetual Guardianship is obviously neither more nor less than an artificial prolongation of the Patria Potestas, when for other purposes it has been dissolved. In India, the system survives in absolute completeness, and its opera- tion is so strict that a Hindoo Mother frequently becomes the ward of her own sons. Even in Europe, the laws of the Scandinavian nations respecting women preserved it until quite recently. The invaders of the Western Empire had it universally among their indigenous usages, and indeed their ideas on the subject of Guardianship, in all its forms, were among the most retrogressive of those which they introduced into the Western world. But from the mature Roman jurisprudence it had entirely disappeared. We should know almost nothing about it, if we had only the com- Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP.v] ANCIENT ROMAN MARRIAGE IgQ pilations of Justinian to consult ; but the discovery of the manuscript of Gains discloses it to us at a most interesting epoch, just when it had fallen into complete discredit and was verging on extinction. The great jurisconsult himself scouts the popular apology offered for it in the mental inferiority of the female sex, and a considerable part of his volume is taken up with descriptions of the numerous expedients, some of them dis- playing extraordinary ingenuity, which the Roman lawyers had devised for enabling Women to defeat the ancient rules. Led by their theory of Natural Law, the jurisconsults had evidently at this time assumed the equality of the sexes as a principle of their code of equity. The restrictions which they attacked were, it is to be observed, restrictions on the disposition of property, for which the assent of the woman's guardians was still formally required. Control of her person was apparently quite obsolete. Ancient law subordinates the woman to her blood-relations, while a prime phenomenon of modern jurisprudence has been her subordination to her husband. The history of the change is remarkable. It begins far back in the annals of Rome. Anciently, there were three modes in which marriage might be contracted according to Roman usage, one involving a religious solem- nity, the other two the observance of certain secular formaUties. By the reUgious marriage or Confaneation ; by the higher form of civil marriage, which was called Coemption ; and by the lower form, which was termed Usus, the Husband acquired a number of rights, over the Digitized by Microsoft® l6o PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW [chap, v person and property of his wife, which were on the whole in excess of such as are conferred on him in any system of modern jurisprudence. But in what capacity did he acquire them ? Not as Husband, but as Father. By the Confarreation, Coemption, and Usus, the woman passed in manum viri, that is, in law she became the Daughter of her husband. She was included in his Patria Potestas. She incurred all the liabilities springing out of it while it subsisted, and surviving it when it had expired. All her property became abso- lutely his, and she was retained in tutelage after his death to the guardian whom he had appointed by will. These three ancient forms of marriage fell, however, gradually into disuse, so that at the most splendid period of Roman greatness, they had almost entirely given place to a fashion of wedlock — old apparently, but not hitherto con- sidered reputable — which was founded on a modi- fication of the lower form of civil marriage. With- out explaining the technical mechanism of the institution now generally popular, I may describe it as amounting in law to a little more than a temporary deposit of the woman by her family. The rights of the family remained unimpaired, and the lady continued in the tutelage of guardians whom her parents had appointed and whose privileges of control overrode, in many material respects, the inferior authority of her husband. The consequence was that the situation of the Roman female, whether married or unmarried, became one of great personal and proprietary independence, for the tendency of the later law, as I have already hinted, was to reduce the power Digitized by Microsoft® CHAJ. vl CONDITION OF WOMEN l6l of the guardian to a nullity, while the form of marriage in fashion conferred on the husband no compensating superiority. But Christianity tended somewhat from the very first to narrow this remarkable liberty. Led at first by justifiable disrehsh for the loose practices of the decaying heathen world, but afterwards hurried on by a passion of asceticism, the professors of the new faith looked with disfavour on a marital tie which was in fact the laxest the Western world has seen. The latest Roman law, so far as it is touched by the Constitutions of the Christian Emperors, bears some marks of a reaction against the liberal doctrines of the great Antonine jurisconsults. And the prevalent state of religious sentiment may explain why it is that modern jurisprudence, forged in the furnace of barbarian conquest, and formed by the fusion of Roman jurisprudence with patriarchal usage, has absorbed, among its rudi- ments, much more than usual of those rules concerning the position of women which belong peculiarly to an imperfect civilisation. During the troubled era which begins modern history, and while the laws of the German and Sclavonic immigrants remained superposed like a separate layer above the Roman jurisprudence of their provincial subjects, the women of the dominant races are seen everywhere under various forms of archaic guardianship, and the husband who takes a wife from any family except his own pays a money-price to her relations for the tutelage which they surrender to him. When we move onwards, and the code of the middle ages has been formed by the amalgamation of the two systems, the law Digitized by Microsoft® jj 1 62 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW [chap, v relating to women carries the stamp of its double origin. The principle of the Roman jurisprudence is so far triumphant that unmarried females are generally (though there are local exceptions to the rule) relieved from the bondage of the family ; but the archaic principle of the barbarians has fixed the position of married women, and the husband has drawn to himself in his marital character the powers which had once belonged to his wife's male kindred, the only difference being that he no longer purchases his privileges. At this point therefore the modern law of Southern and Western Europe begins to be distinguished by one of its chief characteristics, the comparative freedom it allows to unmarried women and widows, the heavy disabihties it imposes on wives. It was very long before the subordination entailed on the other sex by marriage was sensibly diminished. The prin- cipal and most powerful solvent of the revived barbarism of Europe was always the codified jurisprudence of Justinian, wherever it was studied with that passionate enthusiasm which it seldom failed to awaken. It covertly but most effica- ciously undermined the customs which it pre- tended merely to interpret. But the Chapter of law relating to married women was for the most part read by the light, not of Roman, but of Canon Law, which in no one particular departs so widely from the spirit of the secular jurisprudence as in the view it takes of the relations created by marriage. This was in part inevitable, since no society which preserves any tincture of Christian institution is likely to restore to married women the personal liberty conferred on them by the Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. V] CONDITION OF WOMEN 163 middle Roman law, but the proprietary disabilities of married females stand on quite a different basis from their personal incapacities, and it is by the tendency of their doctrines to keep aUve and consolidate the former, that the expositors of the Canon Law have deeply injured civiUsation. There are many vestiges of a struggle between the secular and ecclesiastical principles, but the Canon Law nearly everywhere prevailed. In some of the French provinces, married women, of a rank below nobility, obtained aU the powers of dealing with property which Roman jurisprudence had allowed, and this local law has been largely followed by the Code Napoleon ; but the state of the Scottish law shows that scrupulous deference to the doctrines of the Roman jurisconsults did not alw^ays extend to mitigating the disabilities of wives. The systems however which are least indulgent to married women are invariably those which have followed the Canon Law exclusively, or those which, from the lateness of their contact with European civilisation, have never had their archaisms weeded out. The Danish and Swedish laws, harsh for many centuries to all females, are still much less favourable to wives than the generality of Continental codes. And yet more stringent in the proprietary incapacities it imposes is the English Common Law, which borrows far the greatest number of its fundamental principles from the jurisprudence of the Canonists. Indeed, the part of the Common Law which prescribes the legal situation of married women may serve to give an Englishman clear notions of the great institution which has been the principal subject Digitized by Microsoft® 164 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW [chap. ▼ of this chapter. I do not know how the operation and nature of the ancient Patria Potestas can be brought so vividly before the mind as by reflecting on the prerogatives attached to the husband by the pure EngUsh Common Law, and by recalling the rigorous consistency with which the view of a complete legal subjection on the part of the wife is carried by it, where it is untouched by equity or statutes, through every department of rights, duties, and remedies. The distance between the eldest and latest Roman law on the subject of Children under Power may be considered as equivalent to the difference between the Common Law and the jurisprudence of the Court of Chan- cery in the rules which they respectively apply to wives. If we were to lose sight of the true origin of Guardianship in both its forms, and were to employ the common language on these topics, we should find ourselves remarking that, while the Tutelage of Women is an instance in which systems of archaic law push to an extravagant length the fiction of suspended rights, the rules which they lay down for the Guardianship of Male Orphans are an excimple of a fault in precisely the opposite direction. Such systems terminate the Tutelage of Males at an extraordinary early period. Under the ancient Roman law, which may be taken as their type, the son who was delivered from Patria Potestas by the death of his Father or Grandfather remained under guardianship till an epoch which for general purposes may be described as arriving with his fifteenth year ; but the arrival of that epoch placed him at once in the fuU enjoyment Digitized by Microsoft® CH*»- ▼] GUARDIANSHIP 165 of personal and proprietary independence. The period of minority appears therefore to have been as unreasonably short as the duration of the disabilities of women was preposterously long. But, in point of fact, there was no element either of excess or of shortcoming in the circumstances which gave their original form to the two kinds of guardianship. Neither the one nor the other of them was based on the slightest consideration of pubUc or private convenience. The guardianship of male orphans was no more designed originally to shield them till the arrival of years of discretion than the tutelage of women was intended to protect the other sex against its own feebleness. The reason why the death of the father delivered the son from the bondage of the family was the son's capacity for becoming himself the head of a new family and the founder of a new Patria Potestas : no such capacity was possessed by the woman, and therefore she was never enfranchised. Accord- ingly the Guardianship of Male Orphans was a contrivance for keeping aUve the semblance of subordination to the family of the Parent, up to the time when the child was supposed capable of becoming a parent himself. It was a prolonga- tion of the Patria Potestas up to the period of bare physical manhood. It ended with puberty, for the rigour of the theory demanded that it should do so. Inasmuch, however, as it did not profess to conduct the orphan ward to the age of intellectual maturity or fitness for affairs, it was quite unequal to the purposes of general con- venience ; and this the Romans seem to have discovered at a very early .stage of their social Digitized by Microsoft® l66 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW [chap, v progress. One of the very oldest monuments of Roman legislation is the Lex LcBtoria or Plcetoria, which placed all free males who were of full years and rights under the temporary control of a new class of guardians, called Curatores, whose sanction jvas required to validate their acts or contracts. The twenty-sixth year of the young men's age was the hmit of this statutory supervision ; and it is exclusively with reference to the age of twenty-five that the terms " majority " and " minority " are employed in Roman law. Pupil- age, or wardship, in modern jurisprudence has adjusted itself with tolerable regularity to the simple principle of protection to the immaturity of youth both bodily and mental. It has its natural termination with years of discretion. But for protection against physical weakness, and for protection against intellectual incapacity, the Romans looked to two different institutions, distinct both in theory and design. The ideas attendant on both are combined in the modem idea of guardianship. The Law of Persons contains but one other chapter which can be usefully cited for our present purpose. The legal rules by which systems of mature jurisprudence regulate the connection of Master and Slave, present no very distinct traces of the original condition common to ancient societies. But there are reasons for this exception. There seems to be something in the institution of Slavery which has at all times either shocked or perplexed mankind, however little habituated to reflection, and however sUghtly advanced in the cultivation of its moral instincts. The compunc- Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. T] SLAVERY 167 tion which ancient communities almost uncon- sciously experienced appears to have always resulted in the adoption of some imaginary principle upon which a defence, or at least a rationale, of slavery could be plausibly founded. Very early in their history the Greeks explained the institution as grounded on the intellectual inferiority of certain races, and their consequent natural aptitude for the servile condition. The Romans, in a spirit equally characteristic, derived it from a supposed agreement between the victor and the vanquished, in which the first stipulated for the perpetual services of his foe, and the other gained in consideration the Hfe which he had legitimately forfeited. Such theories were not only unsound but plainly unequal to the case for which they affected to account. Still they exer- cised powerful influence in many ways. They satisfied the conscience of the Master. They perpetuated and probably increased the debase- ment of the Slave. And they naturally tended to put out of sight the relation in which servitude had originally stood to the rest of the domestic system. This relation, though not clearly ex- hibited, is casually indicated in many parts of primitive law, and more particularly in the typical system — that of ancient Rome. Much industry and some learning have been bestowed in the United States of America on the question whether the Slave was in the early stages of society a recognised member of the Family. There is a sense in which an afiSrmative answer must certainly be given. It is clear, from the testimony both of ancient law and of many Digitized by Microsoft® r68 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW [chap. » primeval histories, that the Slave might under certain conditions be made the Heir, or Universal Successor, of the Master, and this significant faculty, as I shall explain in the Chapter on Suc- cession, impUes that the Government and repre- sentation of the Family might, in a particular state of circumstances, devolve on the bondman. It seems, however, to be assumed in the American arguments on the subject that, if we allow Slavery to have been a primitive Family institution, the acknowledgment is pregnant with an admission of the moral defensibihty of Negro-servitude at the present moment. What then is meant by saying that the Slave was originally included in the Family ? Not that his situation may not have been the fruit of the coarsest motives which can actuate man. The simple wish to use the bodily powers of another person as a means of ministering to one's own ease or pleasure is doubt- less the foundation of Slavery, and as old as human nature. When we speak of the Slave as anciently included in the Family, we intend to assert nothing as to the motives of those who brought him into it or kept him there ; we merely imply that the tie which bound him to his master was regarded as one of the same general character with that which united every other member of the group to its chieftain. This consequence is, in fact, carried in the general assertion already made, that the primitive ideas of mankind were unequal to com- prehending any basis of the connection inter se of individuals, apart from the relations of family. The Family consisted primarily of those who be- longed to it by consanguinity, and next of those Digitized by Microsoft® •="*'■ *J SLAVERY 169 who had been engrafted on it by adoption ; but there was still a third class of persons who were only joined to it by common subjection to its head, and these were the Slaves. The born and the adopted subjects of the chief were raised above the Slave by the certainty that in the ordinary course of events they would be relieved from bondage and entitled to exercise powers of their own ; but that the inferiority of the Slave was not such as to place him outside the pale of the Family, or such as to degrade him to the footing of inanimate property, is clearly proved, I think, by the many traces which remain of his ancient capacity for inheritance in the last resort. It would, of course, be unsafe in the highest degree to hazard conjectures how far the lot of the Slave was mitigated, in the beginnings of society, by having a definite place reserved to him in the empire of the Father. It is, perhaps, more probable that the son was practically assimilated to the Slave, than that the Slave shared any of the tenderness which in later times was shown to the son. But it may be asserted with some confidence of ad- vanced and matured codes that, wherever servitude is sanctioned, the Slave has uniformly greater advantages under systems which preserve some memento of his earUer condition than under those which have adopted some other theory of his civil degradation. The point of view from which juris- prudence regards the Slave is always of great importance to him. The Roman law was arrested in its growing tendency to look upon him more and more as an article of property by the theory of the Law of Nature ; and hence it is that. Digitized by Microsoft® 170 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW [chap, v wherever servitude is sanctioned by institutions which have been deeply affected by Roman juris- prudence, the servile condition is never intolerably wretched. There is a great deal of evidence that in those American States which have taken the highly Romanised code of Louisiana as the basis of their jurisprudence, the lot and prospects of the Negro-population were better in many material respects, until the letter of the fundamental law was overlaid by recent statutory enactments passed under the influence of panic, than under institutions founded on the Enghsh Common Law, which, as recently interpreted, has no true place for the Slave, and can only therefore regard him as a chattel. We have now examined all parts of the ancient Law of Persons which fall within the scope of this treatise, and the result of the inquiry is I trust, to give additional definiteness and precision to our view of the infancy of jurisprudence. The Civil laws of States first make their appearance as the Themistes of a patriarchal sovereign, and we can now see that these Themistes are probably only a developed form of the irresponsible commands which, in a still earlier condition of the race, the head of each isolated household may have ad- dressed to his wives, his children, and his slaves, But, even after the State has been organised, the laws have still an extremely Umited apphcation. Whether they retain their primitive character as Themistes, or whether they advance to the condition of Customs or Codified Texts, they are binding not on individuals, but on FamiUes. Ancient jurisprudence, if a perhaps deceptive Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. V] DISINTEGRATION OF THE FAMILY I71 comparison may be employed, may be likened to International Law, filling nothing, as it were, excepting the interstices between the great groups which are the atoms of society. In a community so situated, the legislation of assemblies and the jurisdiction of Courts reach only to the heads of families, and to every other individual the rule of conduct is the law of his home, of which his Parent is the legislator. But the sphere of civil law, small at first, tends steadily to enlarge itself. The agents of legal change, Fictions, Equity, and Legislation, are brought in turn to bear on the primeval institutions, and at every point of the progress, a greater number of personal rights and a larger amount of property are removed from the domestic forum to the cognisance of the public tribunals. The ordinances of the government obtain gradually the same efficacy in private concerns as in matters of state, and are no longer liable to be overridden by the behests of a despot enthroned by each hearthstone. We have in the annals of Roman law a nearly complete history of the crumbling away of an archaic system, and of the formation of new institutions from the re- combined materials, institutions some of which descended unimpaired to the modern world, while others, destroyed or corrupted by contact with barbarism in the dark ages, had again to be re- covered by mankind. When we leave this juris- prudence at the epoch of its final reconstruction by Justinian, few traces of archaism can be dis- covered in any part of it except in the single article of the extensive powers still reserved to the living Parent. Everywhere else principles Digitized by Microsoft® 172 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW [chap, v of convenience, or of sjnnmetry, or of simplifica- tion — new principles at any rate — ^have usurped the authority of the jejune considerations which satisfied the conscience of ancient times. Every- where a new morality has displaced the canons of conduct and the reasons of acquiescence which were in unison with the ancient usages, because in fact they were bom of them. The movement of the progressive societies has been uniform in one respect. Through all its course it has been distinguished by the gradual dissolution of family dependency, and the growth of individual obligation in its place. The Indi- vidual is steadily substituted for the Family, as the unit of which civil laws take account. The advance has been accomplished at varying rates of celerity, and there are societies not absolutely stationary in which the collapse of the ancient organisation can only be perceived by careful study of the phenomena they present. But, whatever its pace, the change has not been subject to reaction or recoil, and apparent retardations win be found to have been occasioned through the absorption of archaic ideas and customs from some entirely foreign source. Nor is it difficult to see what is the tie between man and man which replaces by degrees those forms of reciprocity in rights and duties which have their origin in the Family. It is Contract. Starting, as from one ' terminus of history, from a condition of society in which aU the relations of Persons are summed up in the relations of Family, we seem to have steadily moved towards a phase of social order in which aU these relations arise from the free Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. V] FROM STATUS TO CONTRACT 1 73 agreement of Individuals^ In Western Europe the progress achieved in this direction has been considerable. Thus the status of the Slave has disappeared — ^it has been superseded by the con- tractual relation of the servant to his master. The status of the Female under Tutelage, if the tutelage be understood of persons other than her husband, has also ceased to exist ; from her coming of age to her marriage all the relations she may form are relations of contract. So too the status of the Son under Power has no true place in the law of modem European societies. If any civU obligation binds together the Parent and the child of fuU age, it is one to which only contract gives its legal vaHdity. The apparent exceptions are exceptions of that stamp which illustrate the rule. The child before years of discretion, the orphan under guardianship, the adjudged lunatic, have aU their capacities and incapacities regulated by the Law of Persons. But why ? The reason is differently expressed in the conventional lan- guage of different systems, but in substance it is stated to the same effect by aU. The great majority of Jurists are constant to the principle that the classes of persons just mentioned are subject to extrinsic control on the single ground that they do not possess the faculty of forming a judgment on their own interests ; in other | words, that they are wanting in the first essential I of an engagement by Contract. ' The word Status may be usefully employed to construct a formula expressing the law of progress thus indicated, which, whatever be its value, seems to me to be sufficiently ascertained. All the forms Digitized by Microsoft® 174 NOTES [CHAP.* of Status taken notice of in the Law of Persons were derived from, and to some extent are still coloured by, the powers and privileges anciently residing in the Family. If then we employ Status, agreeably with the usage of the best writers, to signify these personal conditions only, and avoid appljdng the term to such conditions as are the immediate or remote result of agreement, we may say that 'the movement of the progressive societies has hitherto been a movement from Status to Contract. , NOTE I MONTESQUIEU, BENTHAM, AND HISTORICAL METHOD Maine's judgment of Montesquieu is, in effect, that, notwith standing inevitable defects of method and some individual faults, he came nearer than any other man to founding the historical and comparative study of institutions. It is true, as Sir Courtenay Ilbert has said in a fuller criticism (" The Romanes Lecture : 'Montesquieu,'" Oxford, 1904), that "his appreciation of the historical method was imperfect, and his application of it defective " : at the same time his work " prepared for and gave an enormous stimulus to those methods of study which are now recognized as indispensable to any scientific treatment either of Law or of Politics " {oj>. cit. pp. 35-6). In 1903, on quitting the chair which I had the honour of holding in succession to Maine at Oxford, I thus endeavoured to sum up Montesquieu's relation to these studies : — " If we hesitate to call him the founder, it is only because neither his materials nor his methods of execution were adequate to do iustice to his ideas. He aimed (if I may repeat my own words, first written many years ago) at constructing a comparative theory of legislation and institutions adapted to the political needs of different forms of government, and a comparative theory of politics and law based on wide observation of the actual systems of different lands and ages. Hobbes was before him in realising that history is not a series of accidents, but Montesquieu was the first of the modems to proclaim that a nation's institutions are part of its history, and must be considered as such if we are to understand them rightly. Much of his history is sound, and many of his judgments are admirable. Yet he failed to construct a durable Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. V] NOTES 175 system, and 'L'Esprit des Lois' cannot even be called a systematic book. The materials were still too scattered and uncertain to be safely handled on Montesquieu's grand scale. Perhaps he would have done better to confine himself to Western Europe. The main defects of his method may be reduced, I think, to two. First, he overrated the influence of climate and other external conditions, and underrated, if he did not wholly neglect, the effects of race and tradition. Next, he had not even an inkling of what is now a fundamental rule of this kind of enquiry: namely, that there is a normal course of development for communities as well as for individuals, and that institutions which belong to different stages are not commensurable terms in any scientific comparison. This is as much as to say that even Montesquieu could not wholly escape from the unhistorical dogmatism of his time. It is perhaps a minor drawback that he constantly seeks for reasons of deliberate policy to account for seemingly eccentric features of outlandish customs, rightly or wrongly reported by missionaries or others, instead of endeavouring to connect them with their historic and racial sur- roundings. But the result is that many chapters of his great work amount, taken by themselves, to little more than collections of anecdotes and conjectures in which the most incongruous elements, such as the customs of China and the laws of Spain, are brought together at random. Also Montesquieu is not free from the very common error, especially prevalent in the eighteenth century, of attributing a constant and infallible efficacy to forms of govern- ment. In short, Montesquieu saw the promised land afar off, but was not equipped for entering it. I do not wish to be understood as affecting to find any fault with him. The greatness of Montesquieu's conception was his own, and the shortcomings in execution were at the time necessary, or at least natural " ("The History of Comparative Jurisprudence, a farewell Public Lecture " : Joum. Soc. Comp. Legisl., 1903, at pp. 83-4). The " historical theory " ascribed to Bentham (p. 127) seems to be not quite so unfruitful as Maine's criticism supposes. If it is said that societies modify their laws according to modifica- tions of their views of general expediency, this must mean views formed by actual observation and experience, as opposed to the application of dogmatic or traditional rules ; and it must be implied that such views have a greater part in the changes of legal institutions than is avowed, or perhaps realised, by the actors and promoters. Doubtless Bentham underrated the power of tradition and custom. Probably he underrated it very much in the case of archaic societies. But his proposition, understood as above explained, is a substantial one and capable of discussion. It is not reducible to the truism that people make changes because they think change expedient, or in other words because they desire change ; it signifies that the reasons professed or admitted for making particular changes are often not the real or the most operative reasons. Apparently the passages to which Maine alludes are scattered about various works of Bentham's and not expressed in clear or positive terms ; it therefore does not seem practicable, Digitized by Microsoft® 176 NOTES [CHAP. T in the absence of any specific reference, to identify them. But it was obviously natural for Bentham, with his thoroughgoing- con- viction that all ethical problems can be solved by the utilitarian calculus, to maintain that in fact the greater part of mankind are utilitarians without knowing it. Maine's claim of scientific validity for the historical treatment of jurisprudence (p. 128) is now disputed by no one; indeed, if we now find any difficulty, it is in remembering that in 1861 it was still novel, and that its champion at that time had need of much insight and some boldness. His precepts as to the need of observing the caution approved by experience in other kinds of scientific enquiry, beginning with the best evidence and working gradually firom what is known to what is obscure or unknown, are still in full force, and might easily be illustrated by the failure of ambitious reconstructions of later date whose authors have neglected them. NOTE K THE PATRIARCHAL THEORY In the preface to the tenth edition, reprinted in all subsequent issues, Maine himself referred to the chapter on Theories of Primitive Society in "Early Law and Custom." The note on the Gens in the same volume (p. 286 sqq.) should also be consulted. In 1886 Maine replied in the Quarterly Review to the criticisms of the McLennan brothers (Q.R., vol. 162, p. 181) ; no secret was made of the authorship, though the practice of the Review, as it then stood, did not allow signature or public acknowledgment. It should be noted that the supposed ancient Slavonic poem cited at p. 196 of this article is a modem forgery : see Kovalevsky, "Modem Customs and Ancient Laws of Russia," p. 5. The last- named learned author made fuller contributions to the subject in his lectures delivered and published in French at Stockholm (" Tableau des origines et de revolution de la famille et de la propriety," 1890: some account of this book, which may not be easily accessible in England, was given in the Saturday Review of October 18 and 25, 1890). Still later Dr. Kohler of Berlin has dealt systematically with the whole topic of archaic marriage and kinship, following and applying Morgan's doctrine with less reserve than Lord Avebury and Dr. Tylor, who do not accept Morgan's inferences ("Zur Urgeschichte der Ehe: Totemismus, Gruppenehe, Mutterrecht," reprinted from " Ztschr. fur vergleichende Rechts- wissenschaft," Stuttgart, 1897 • ^.nd see a more summary statement by the same learned author in the " Encyklopadie der Rechtswissen- schaft," re-edited by him in 1904, vol. i, pp. 27 sqq.). Most English readers, however, will find in the latest edition (1902) of Lord Avebury's " Origin of Civilisation," and in Dr. E. B. Tylor'f article on the Matriarchal Family System, Nineteenth Centurj i. 81 Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. V] NOTES 177 (1896), and in Mr. Andrew Lang's "The Secret of the Totem" (1905), the easiest and certainly not the least profitable guides, among writings published since Maine's death, to what is now known or conjectured in this extremely difScult inquiry. Much trouble and confusion might have been saved if Maine had in the first place expressly confined his thesis, as for all practical purposes it was confined, to the Indo-European family of nations. Herbert Spencer, whose courteous treatment of "Ancient Law" set a good example not always followed, gave a hint of this long ago. When Maine wrote " Ancient Law " there were no trustworthy materials for dealing with the social history of other races on a large scale. It is certain that from the earliest times at which we have any distinct knowledge of Indo-European society we find families — or communities which may be considered as expanded families — tracing descent through males, and living under the authority, more or less tempered by custom, of the eldest male ascendant. The worship of ancestors in the male line is of extreme antiquity in every branch of the stock; it is in full force at this day among the Hindus, and there are quite recent traces of it elsewhere. This is enough for the historian of Indo-European institutions ; for the remaining evidences of a different earlier system are mere survivals at best, and of no importance for any subsequent development, however interesting they may be for prehistoric anthropology. My own judgment, so far as I have been able to form one, is that many of them are no better than ambiguous. Further, it is to be observed that local survivals of " matriarchal " institutions, where their existence is made out, may quite possibly not be Indo-European at all, but belong to the customs of the non-Aryan tribes who were subdued by Aryan invaders in India, or in Eastern Europe, or in the Mediterranean countries. We have been asked to regard the Erinyes prosecuting Orestes for matricide as the champions of a more ancient " mother- right " against the paternal system : as if the natural tendency of that system were to treat matricide as venial. Surely the question whether the son is bound to take up the father's blood-feud even against his own mother is hard enough to make a dramatic problem under any system which admits private vengeance at all. But in any case the Erinyes were autochthonous deities, looking on the gods of Olympus as intruders (roiavra Spacrw oi vei>T€poi Oeoi). If their failure in the suit against Orestes is a symbol of anything, it may well symbolise the triumph of Hellenic over aboriginal customs. The existence of non-Aryan elements in the Mycenaean and even the later historical civilisation of Greece is accepted for independent reasons by some of our best archaeologists (P. Gardner in Eng. Hist. Rev. xvi. 744). Again (to take a Semitic example) we are told that Gideon avenged the sons of his mother upon the kings of Midian (Judges viii. 19). But there was no one else Digitized by Microsoft® ^ ^ 178 NOTES [CHAP. T to do it, asd the men of Israel who, as we read only a few verses below, said unto Gideon : " Rule thou over us, both thou and thy son, and thy son's son also," were certainly familiar with succession through males. The German, Scandinavian, and Celtic tribal customs as disclosed in the earliest known history of those branches appear to be thoroughly paternal, though not without traces of preference for relatives on the mother's side.' Summing up the results, Dr. Tylor says (Nineteenth Century, xl. 04) : " There is no proof that at any period the maternal system held exclusive possession of the human race, but the strength with which it kept its ground may be measured by its having encompassed the globe in space, and lasted on from remote antiquity in time." For different views as to the significance of some archaic Indo-European customs, see J. D. Mayne in L.Q.R. i. 485, 494, and Kovalevsky, " Droit coutumier Ossetien,'' Paris, 1893, p. 181. It is no doubt possible, as suggested by Mr. Kovalevsky, that survivals from an earlier system may be maintained under a later one for reasons different from the original ones. But if patriarchal reasons are enough to account for the custom as we find it, we can hardly assume that in a given case it was formerly matriarchal, merely because for all we know it might have been. This would be to assume the very thing to be proved, namely that the society in question was in fact maternal at some earlier time. On the whole the safest opinion appears at present to be that the Indo-European race may have gone through a stage of " matri- archy" at some remote time, but at any rate before the great migration which dispersed the several branches. This was Ihering's conclusion in his brilliant posthumous work, " Vorgeschichte der Indo-Europaer " (p. 40 of Eng. tr., 62 of original). It would seem, again, that the transformation, if such a transformation there was, must not only have taken place very early, but must have been singularly rapid and complete. Thus we are brought face to face with Maine's original problem : How and why did the Indo-Euro- peans become progressive ? In this connexion I cannot forbear from citing some profitable words of my lamented friend Professor F. W. Maitland, though their immediate subject-matter is the history not of the family but of property. " Even had our anthropologists at their command material that would justify them in prescribing a normal programme for the human race and in decreeing that every independent portion of mankind must, if it is to move at all, move through one fated series of stages which may be designated as Stage A, Stage B, Stage C, 1 It is now admitted that marriage by capture was part of the earUest Germanic law, but it is very doubtful whether it survived the introduction of Christianity in England. The Anglo-Saxon bride-price appears to have been paid not for the wife's person but for the rights of wardship (Hazehine, " Zur Geschichte der Eheschliessung nach angelsachsischem Recht," Berlin, 1905). Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. ▼] NOTES 179 and so forth, we still should have to face the fact that the rapidly progressive groups have been just those which have not been independent, which have not worked out their own salvation, but have appropriated alien ideas and have thus been enabled, for an)rthing that we can tell, to leap from Stage A to Stage X witli- out passing through any intermediate stages. Our Anglo-Saxon ancestors did not arrive at the alphabet, or at the Nicene Creed, by traversing a long series of ' stages ' ; they leapt to the one and to the other (" Domesday Book and Beyond," p. 345). The accident of borrowing one alphabet rather than another, or in one stage rather than another, may determine the affinities of a literature and a civilization for many generations. All the tendency of modem research is to show that deliberate imitation was earlier, easier, and commoner than scholars formerly supposed ; and that people will imitate pretty odd things is amply shown by modem experience. Maine was not the first to discover that the ancient Indo-European tribe or city, as the case may be, is an expanded family with the tie of actual kindred supplemented, so far as needful to keep the community together, by adoption or even by bolder fictions ; indeed, the conception is in its essential points as old as Aristotle. But he was, I think, the first to call attention in an adequate manner to the general existence and importance of this feature in archaic society. His view has been strikingly confirmed by the researches in the history of Slavonic institutions which are mentioned in " Early Law and Custom" under the head of East European House Communities. The family element in the Indo-European com- munity has now and then been unduly suffered to drop out of sight. Thus the exclusiveness of the archaic village or township is simply and adequately explained as the exclusiveness of a community which had been or pretended to be a clan, and no deeper mystery need be sought in the much discussed Salic rule De Migrantibus. Maine's original thesis was further developed by himself in the lecture on Kinship as the Basis of Society in " The Early History of Institutions," pp. 64 sqq. It is impossible here, and I hardly think it would be relevant if possible, to enter at large on discussion of the " matriarchal " 01, as Dr. Tylor prefers to call it, maternal family system. But it may be pointed out that, whatever else it is or has been, primitive it is not. It goes along with an elaborate and complex nomenclature of kindred and affinity, of which the interpretation is much dis- puted,' and often though not always with other usages of the ' J. F. McLennan's opinion, whicli he intended to develop farther and prove in detail, was that this classification had nothing to do with consanguinity, but was a system of modes of salutation ; and this is also maintained by Dr. Westermarck. Morgan, on the other hand, would allow no merit to McLennan's work and thought the term " exogamy," now generally adopted, useless. Professor Kohler, Digitized by Microsoft® t8o notes [chap. V most artificial kind, of which the explanation is no less con- jectural, and as obscure to the modem historian as the facts to be explained are repugnant to modem civilized manners. Dr. Tylor has observed that its real characteristic point is the continuance of the wife in her own family, who do not lose her property or the value of her work, and gain the husband's alliance. If these or such-like politic motives were the true determining causes of " matriarchy" — and Dr. Tylor makes out a case which is none the less strong for being simple and using the general known materials of human nature instead of hypothetical superstitions — we are a long way off from primitive man, and the problem of what came before all this remains open. Here Maine's appeal to the Homeric description of the savage (not merely barbarous) Cyclopes is probably nearer to the truth than the state of promiscuity — surely the least likely state of nature ever heard of — which some anthro- pologists have postulated. At any rate it has, in substance, Dr. Tylor's support. "The claim of the patriarchal system to have belonged to primitive human life has not merely long acceptance in its favour, but I venture to think that those who uphold it have the weight of evidence on their side, provided that they do not insist on its fully developed form having at first appeared, but are content to argfue that already in the earliest ages the man took his wife to himself, and that the family was under his power and protection, the law of male descent and all that belongs to it gradually growing up afterwards on this basis. . . . Among the great ancient and modem nations within the range of history, the paternal system becomes so dominant as to be taken for granted, and the existence of any other rule seems extraordinary" ( Nineteenth Century, xl. 84, 85). So far as the evidence has gone, the maternal system appears to be unstable when people who live under it come into contact with paternal families : in such cases the husband's predominance pretty soon begins to assert or re- assert itself. It is also remarkable that a received custom so lax as not to seem to civilized administrators fit to rank as any kind of marriage law has been found compatible with fairly strict monogamy in practice (on both these points see H. H. Shephard, " Marriage Law in Malabar," L.Q.R. viii. 314). It seems fairly certain that both the frequency and the importance of polyandry have been exaggerated, and that, where it occurs, it can be explained, by those who regard "group-marriage" as proved, as a limiting case of group-marriage determined by special and less decidedly Mr. Kovalevsky, are, I believe, the only recent authors pre- pared to accept as a whole the consequences drawn by Morgan himself from the " classificatory " system. Subject to what McLennan might have added if he had lived, his particular line of objection just mentioned does not seem sufficient. Mr. Andrew Lang's conclusions are about equally remote from both schools . Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. V] NOTES l8l conditions. Thus we are rather led to regard the maternal system as a product of social necessities, not yet very well understood, which, although they have prevailed at some time in many or most inhabited parts of the world, may be fairly called abnormal with respect to the most original and persistent instincts of mankind as a species. When the maternal is supplanted by the paternal society, those instincts come to their own again in surroundings that no longer demand the highly artificial discipline of matriarchy. Much more evidence is needed both as to the origins of the maternal family, and as to the causes and manner of its transformation into the paternal type, before anything like a comprehensive statement can be made. We should remember that, as Professor Maitland says, continuing the passage already quoted, "we are learning that the attempt to construct a normal pro- gramme for all portions of mankind is idle and unscientific." Probably no one would now maintain that either marriage by capture or matriarchy is primitive. Any such position is formally disclaimed, for example, by a recent learned and ingenious author. Dr. Richard Hildebrand, " Recht und Sitte auf den verschiedenen Kulturstufen," i'" Teil, Jena, 1896. It is perhaps needless at this day to refute the formerly current opinion that the customs of savages are the result of degradation from a more ancient state of innocence or civilization. Partial backsliding into barbarism over a considerable range of both time and space is of course possible, as shown in the decline of the Roman and the Mogul empires. But tiying to account for the systems of kinship (if it is kinship) investigated by Morgan as fallings off from monogamy or patriarchal polygamy is, if I may repeat an illustration I have already used in an earlier note, like expecting to find chalk under granite. Finally Mr. Lang, in "The Secret of the Totem," agreeing in the main with Darwin on this point, wholly rejects the hypothesis of a promiscuous horde having been the earliest state of human life, and holds that "men, whatever their brutal ancestors may have done, when they became men indeed, lived originally in small anonymous local groups, and had, for a reason to be given " — the jealous despotism of the eldest male, as is explained in a later chapter— "the habit of selecting female mates from groups not their own." McLennan' s explanation of exogamy is dismissed as wholly inadequate, and the facts supposed by Morgan and his school to establish a general epoch of "group-marriage" are treated as exceptional and belonging to a relatively advanced stage. I do not presume to appreciate Mr. Lang's theory, or make any critical comparison of it with those of other anthropologists who differ widely from Mr. Lang and from one another. But it is legitimate to observe that Mr. Lang, as well as Dr. Tylor, appears to justify Maine's opinion as to the primitive character of the Cyclopean family, and that it is less plausible now than it wp.s Digitized by Microsoft® l82 NOTES [CHAP. V twenty years ago to regard Maine as an old-fashioned literary scholar standing out against the lights of modem research. No doubt Maine, when he wrote "Ancient Law," conceived the tran- sition from the savagery of the Cyclops to the archaic civilisation of a Roman paterfamilias under the Kings o'r the early Republic as having been a far more direct and simple process than we can at this day think probable. This is so common an incident of historical speculation, in the absence of full and trustworthy material, that there is nothing in it to derogate from Maine's credit. With regard to the extreme form of paternal power which, as Maine says (p. 142), we may conveniently call by its later Roman name of Patria Potestas, it is not clear that it is a mere incident of family headship. Some competent persons, such as Mr. Kovalevsky, hold it to be derived from the notion that the wife is the husband's property, and therefore her offspring must be in his power too. If this be so, the right, being proprietary and not merely social, would belong exclusively to Private Law, and the " maxim of Roman jurisprudence that the Patria Potestas did not extend to the Jus Publicum" would be strictly logical as well as politic. But some, again, think that the paternal family itself was developed through marriage by capture or purchase, causing the wife so acquired to be regarded as the husband's chattel (Kohler, " Encykl. der Rechts- wissenschaft," i. 30, 33 ; " Das Vaterrecht entwickelt sich . . . zunachst als Herrschaftsrecht : der Ehemann ist Herr der Frau und damit Herr ihref Frucht "). Not that lordship in a rudimentary society can safely be identified with our modem legal ownership. Dominus is an ambiguous word except in strict Roman law. At all events we cannot disregard the testimony of Gains that the Patria Potestas of the Roman family law was, in the time of Hadrian, singular among the Mediterranean nations ; and, so far as we know anything of the provincial customs of the empire, they seem to have been not less but more archaic than the law of Rome. The responsibilities of the Roman paterfamilias, on the other hand, are not distinguishable in character or extent from those of the patriarch in other Indo-European family systems. Another reason against regarding the Roman Patria Potestas as of the highest antiquity is that at an earlier time the paterfamilias was regarded not as owner, but as an administrator of the family property which in some sense already belonged to the heirs as well as himself. Indeed, this idea survived as late as the classical ages of Roman law in the untranslatable term of art sui heredes, of which " necessary heirs " is perhaps the most tolerable rendering, and the comments of the jurists upon it (Paulus in D. 28, 2, de liberis eiposiumis, 11, cited by Holmes, " The Common Law," p. 342). We are fully confitmed in this by the history of the Hindu Joint Family. In Bengal the change from the position of an Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. V] NOTES 183 administrator with large powers to that of an owner is known to have taken place in relatively modem times. Finally, I venture to ifecord, for what it may be worth, my impression that recent inquirers, with the notable exception of Mr. J. G. Frazer, have somewhat neglected the part of superstitions and magical or pseudo-scientific beliefs in the formation of social customs. There is no presumption whatever that the true ex- planation of any savage practice is that which to us appears most reasonable or natural. The fundamental difiference between religion and magic has been explained by Lord Avebury and Sir Alfred Lyall. Religious offerings and ceremonies, apart from the higher ethical and philosophical developments of advanced theology, seek to propitiate supernatural powers, magical ritual to control both natural and supernatural agencies. The priest is, in the current phrase, a minister, that is to say a servant of whatever gods he worships ; he begs their peace and alliance with tribute in his hand. The magician or wizard acts as a master ; he aims at using the secrets of nature, or commanding for his own use or that of his clients, and at his own will, the " armies of angels that soar, legions of demons that lurk." Solomon's seal is magical, his dedication of the temple is religious. The facts that magic and religion are often intermixed, and that the priest is very apt to revert to the position of a mere thaumaturgist, do not appear to alter the importance of the distinction. But this has little, if anything, to do with the present subject NOTE L STATUS AND CONTRACT Maine's now celebrated dictum as to the movement from Status to Contract in progressive societies is perhaps to be understood as limited to the law of Property, taking that term in its widest sense as inclusive of whatever has a value measurable in ex- change. With that limitation the statement is certainly just, and has not ceased to be significant. The movement is not yet com- plete, for example, in England, where the emancipation of married women's property has been proceeding in a piecemeal fashion for more than a generation, and is at present in a transitional state capable not only of raising hard questions but of producing, within a few years, decisions not easy to reconcile. As regards the actual definition of different personal conditions, and the more personal relations incidental to them, it does not seem that a movement from Status to Contract can be asserted with any generality. For example, the tendency of modern legislation has been to make the dissolution of marriage less difiScult, and in some jurisdictions this has gone very far. But it has nowhere been enacted, and I do not think any legislator has yet seriously proposed, that the parties Digitized by Microsoft® i84 NOTES [CHAP. shall be free to settle for themselves, by the terms of the marriage contract, whether the marriage shall be dissoluble or not, and if so, on what grounds. Assimilation of marriage, as a personal relation, to partnership is not within the scope of practical jurisprudence. Again, a minor who has attained years of discretion cannot advance or postpone the date of his full age by contract with his parent or guardian, and we do not hear of any one proposing to confer such a power. The test which Maine suggests as alone justifying the preservation of disabilities — that the persons con- cerned do not possess the faculty of forming a judgment on their own interests — will hardly be received as adequate for either of the cases just put. In fact, the interests which these rules of law regard are not those of the parties alone. Paramount considera- tions of the stability of society, or the general convenience of third persons, override the freedom usually left to parties in their own affairs. The law of persons may be and has been cut short ; but, so long as we recognise any differences at all among persons, we cannot allow their existence and nature to be treated merely as matter of bargain. Status may yield ground to Contract, but cannot itself be reduced to Contract. On the other hand Contract has made attacks on Property which have been repulsed. There was a time in the thirteenth century during which it seemed as if there was no rule of tenure that could not be modified by the agree- ment of parties. Our settled rules that only certain defined forms of interest in property can be created by private acts, our rule against perpetuities, are the answer of the Common Law to attempts to bring everything under private bargain and control. The import- ance of Contract in the feudal scheme of society is pointed out by Maine himself in this book, ch. ix ad fin. (cp. Pollock and Maitland, "H.E.L." ii. 230). One department of the law of Persons is increasing, not diminish- ing, in importance, namely the law of corporations or " moral persons." We are beginning to find that the law cannot afford to ignore col- lective personality — that of a trade union, for example — where fact and usage have conferred a substantially corporate character on a more or less permanent social group. Modern company law is largely, no doubt, a law of contract ; but of contract whose action is regulated and modified at every turn by the fact that one of the chief parts is bom by a corporate and not an individual person. Maine guarded his position, however, to a considerable extent in the final words of this chapter, for he seems not to include Marriage — at all events marriage among Western nations, which is preceded by and results from agreement of the parties — under the head of Status. And, if the term is thus restricted, the gravest apparent exception to Maine's dictum is removed. This, of course, involves a sensible narrowing of the term Status, a much discussed term which, according to the best modem expositions, includes the sum total of a man's personal rights and duties (Salmond, " Juris- Digitized by Microsoft® <=HAP- ^] NOTES 185 prudence," 1902, pp. 253-j'), or, to be verbally accurate, of his capacity for rights and duties (Holland, "Jurisprudence," 9th ed. p. 88). It is curious that the word " estate," which is nothing but the French form of " status," should have come to stand over against it in an almost opposite category. A man's estate is his measurable property ; what we call his status is his position as a lawful man, a voter, and so forth. The liability of every citizen to pay rates and taxes is a matter of status; what a given citizen has to pay depends on his estate, or portions of it assigned as the measures of particular imposts. We have, too, an " estate " in land, which so far preserves the original associations of " status " that, as we have just noted, contract may not alter its incidents or nature. Again, as Professor Maitland has pointed out (Introduction to Gierke's "Political Theories of the Middle Age," Camb. 1900, p. xxv), the Roman Status has also become the State of modern public law, and in that form has refused to be reduced to a species of contract by the ingenious efforts of individualist philosophers, notwithstanding the widespread acceptance of the Social Contract for a century or more. It is not clear how far Maine regarded the movement of which he spoke as a phase of the larger political individualism which pre- vailed in the eighteenth century and great part of the nineteenth, or what he would have thought of the reaction against this doctrine which we are now witnessing. At all events the questions at issue between publicists of various schools as to the proper limits of State interference with trade, or of State and municipal enterprise, do not seem to have much to do with simplifying the tenure and transfer of property, nor with removing obsolete personal disabilities. ProfessorDiceysaysindeed("Lawand Public Opinion in England," p. 283) that " the rights of workmen in regard to compensation for accidents have become a matter not of contract, but of status." But many other kinds -of contracts have long had incidents attached to them by law, and those incidents are not always subject to be varied at the will of the parties. A mortgagor cannot enter into an agreement with the mortgagee which has the effect of making the mortgage irredeemable, or even tends that way by " clogging the equity of redemption." It would be a strong thing to say that this peculiar doctrine of English courts of equity has created a status of mortgagors. The Trade Disputes Act, 1906, passed since this note was first published, may certainly be said to have conferred a new and unexampled status on combinations of both employers and workmen by exempting them in several respects from the operation of the general law ; but the obligation of contracts is not directly affected, and it remains to be seen whether the Act represents any general movement of legislative ideas, or anything else than the pressure of very powerfiil interests astutely applied at a critical moment. On one or two points it only confirms what was already the better supported opinion. Digitized by Microsoft® CHAPTER VI THE EARLY HISTORY OF TESTAMENTARY SUCCESSION If an attempt were made to demonstrate in England the superiority of the historical method of investigation to the modes of inquiry concerning Jurisprudence which are in fashion among us, no department of Law would better serve as an example than Testaments or Wills. Its capabili- ties it owes to its great length and great continuity. At the beginning of its history we find ourselves in the very infancy of the social state, surrounded by conceptions which it requires some effort of mind to realise in their ancient form ; while here, at the other extremity of its line of progress, we are in the midst of legal notions which are nothing more than those same conceptions disguised by the phraseology and by the habits of thought which belong to modern times, and exhibiting therefore a difficulty of another kind, the difficulty of believing that ideas which form part of our everyday mental stock can really stand in need of analysis and examination. The growth of the Law of WUls between these extreme points can be traced with remarkable distinctness. It was much less interrupted at the epoch of the birth of feudaUsm, than the history of most other branches of law. It is, indeed, true that as regards all i86 Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VI] INFLUENCE OF THE CHURCH 187 provinces of jurisprudence, the break caused by the division between ancient and modern history, or in other words by the dissolution of the Roman Eitipire, has been very greatly exaggerated. In- dolence has disinclined many writers to be at the pains of looking for threads of connection entangled and obscured by the confusions of six troubled centuries, while other inquirers, not naturally deficient in patience and industry, have been misled by idle pride in the legal system of their country, and by consequent unwillingness to confess its obligations to the jurisprudence of Rome. But these unfavourable influences have had compara- tively httle effect on the province of Testamentary Law. The barbarians were confessedly strangers to any such conception as that of a Will. The best authorities agree that there is no trace of it in those parts of their written codes which comprise the customs practised by them in. their original seats, and in their subsequent settlements on the edge of the Roman Empire. But soon after they became mixed with the population of the Roman provinces they appropriated from the Imperial jurisprudence the conception of a Will, at first in part, and afterwards in all its integrity. The influence of the Church had much to do with this rapid assimilation. The ecclesiastical power had very early succeeded to those privileges of custody and registration of Testaments which several of the heathen temples had enjoyed ; and even thus early it was almost exclusively to private bequests that the religious foundations owed their temporal possessions. Hence it is that the decrees of the earliest Provincial Councils perpetually contain Digitized by Microsoft® l88 HISTORY OF TESTAMENTARY SUCCESSION [chap- ^' anathemas against those who deny the sanctity of Wills. Here, in England, Church influence was certainly chief among the causes which by universal acknowledgment have prevented that discontinuity in the history of Testamentary Law which is sometimes beUeved to exist in the history of other provinces of Jurisprudence. The juris- diction over one class of WiU was delegated to the Ecclesiastical Courts, which applied to them, though not always intelligently, the principles of Roman jurisprudence ; and, though neither the Courts of Common Law nor the Court of Chan- cery owned any positive obligation to foUow the Ecclesiastical tribunals, they could not escape the potent influence of a system of settled rules in course of application by their side. The English law of testamentary succession to personality has become a modified form of the dispensation under which the inheritances of Roman citizens were administered. It is not difficult to point out the extreme difference of the conclusions forced on us by the historical treatment of the subject, from those to which we are conducted when, without the help of history, we merely strive to analyse our primd- facie impressions. I suppose there is nobody who, starting from the popular or even the legal conception of a Will, would not imagine that certain qualities are necessarily attached to it. He would say, for example, that a WiU necessarily takes effect at death only — that it is secret, not known as a matter of course to persons taking interests under its provisions — that it is revocable, i e. always capable of being superseded by a new Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VI] NATURAL EIGHT OF TESTATION 189 act of testation. Yet I shall be able to show that there was a time when none of these characteristics belonged to a Will. The Testaments from which our Wills are directly descended at first took effect immediately on their execution ; they were not secret ; they were not revocable. Few legal agencies are, in fact, the fruit of more complex historical agencies than that by which a man's written intentions control the posthumous dis- position of his goods. Testaments very slowly and gradually gathered round them the quaUties I have mentioned ; and they did this from causes and under pressure of events which may be called casual, or which at any rate have no interest for us at present, except so far as they have effected the history of law. At a time when legal theories were more abundant than at present — theories which, it is true, were for the most part gratuitous and premature enough, but which nevertheless rescued jurisprudence from that worse and more ignoble condition, not unknown to ourselves, in which nothing like a generalisation is aspired to, and law is regarded as a mere empirical pursuit — it was the fashion to explain the ready and apparently intuitive perception which we have of certain quaUties in a Will, by saying that they were natural to it, or, as the phrase would run in full, attached to it by the Law of Nature. Nobody, I imagine, would affect to maintain such a doctrine when once it was ascertained that all these characteristics had their origin within historical memory ; at the same time vestiges of the theory of which the doctrine is an offshoot, linger in forms of expression Digitized by Microsoft® igo HISTORY OF TESTAMENTARY SUCCESSION [chap, vi which we all of us use, and perhaps scarcely know how to dispense with. I may illustrate this by mentioning a position common in the legal Utera- ture of the seventeenth century. The jurists of that period very commonly assert that the power of Testation itself is of Natural Law, that it is a right conferred by the Law of Nature. Their teaching, though all persons may not at once see the connection, is in substance followed by those who affirm that the right of dictating or controlling the posthumous disposal of property is a necessary or natural consequence of the proprietary rights themselves. And every student of technical juris- prudence must have come across the same view, clothed in the language of a rather different school, which, in its rationale of this department of law, treats succession ex testamento as the mode of devolution which the property of deceaised persons ought primarily to foUow, and then pro- ceeds to account for succession ab inlestato as the incidental provision of the lawgiver for the discharge of a function which was only left un- performed through the neglect or misfortune of the deceased proprietor. These opinions are only expanded forms of the more compendious doctrine that Testamentary disposition is an institution of the Law of Nature. It is certainly never quite safe to pronounce dogmatically as to the range of association embraced by modern minds when they reflect on Nature and her Law ; but I beUeve that most persons, who affirm that the Testamentary Power is of Natural Law, may be taken to imply either that, as a matter of fact, it is universal, or that nations are prompted to sanction it by an Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VI] NATURE OF A WILL IQI original instinct and impulse. With respect to the first of these positions, I think that, when expUcitly set forth, it can never be seriously con- tended for in an age which has seen the severe restraints imposed on the Testamentary Power by the Code NapoUon, and has witnessed the steady multipUcation of systems for which the French codes have served as a model. To the second assertion we must object that it is contrary to the best-ascertained facts in the early history of law, and I venture to affirm generally that, in aU indigenous societies, a condition of jurisprudence in which Testamentary privileges are not allowed, or rather not contemplated, has preceded that later stage of legal development in which the mere wiU of the proprietor is permitted under more or less of restriction to override the claims of his kindred in blood. The conception of a Will or Testament cannot be considered by itself. It is a member, and not the first, of a series of conceptions. In itself a Will is simply the instrument by which the intention of the testator is declared. It must be clear, I think, that before such an instrument takes its turn for discussion, there are several prehminary points to be examined — as for example, what is it, what sort of right or interest, which passes from a dead man on his decease ? to whom and in what form does it pass ? and how came it that the dead were allowed to control the posthumous disposition of their property ? Thrown into technical language, the dependence of the various conceptions which contribute to the notion of a Will is thus expressed. A Will or 'Testament is an instniment by which Digitized by Microsoft® 192 HISTORY OF TESTAMENTARY SUCCESSION [chap, vi the devolution of an inheritance is prescribed. Inheritance is a form of universal succession. A universal succession is a succession to a universitas juris, or university of rights and duties. Inverting this order we have therefore to inquire what is a universitas juris ; what is a universal succession ; what is the form of universal succession which is called an inheritance ? And there are also two further questions, independent to some extent of the points I have mooted, but demanding solution before the subject of Wills can be exhausted. These are, how came an inheritance to be con- trolled in any case by the testator's volition, and what is the nature of the instrument by which it came to be controlled ? The first question relates to the universitas juris ; that is a university (or bundle) of rights and duties. A universitas juris is a collection of rights and duties united by the single circumstance of their having belonged at one time to some one person. It is, as it were, the legal clothing of some given individual. It is not formed by grouping together any rights and any duties. It can only be constituted by taking aU the rights and all the duties of a particular person. The tie which so connects a number of rights of property, rights of way, rights to legacies, duties of specific performance, debts, obligations, to compensate wrongs — which so connects all these legal privileges and duties together as to constitute them a univer- sitas juris, is the fact of their having attached to some individual capable of exercising them. Without this fact there is no university of rights and duties. The expression universitas juris is Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VI] UNIVERSAL SUCCESSION I93 not classical, but for the notion jurisprudence is exclusively indebted to Roman law ; nor is it at aU difficult to seize. We must endeavour to coUect under one conception the whole set of legal relations in which each one of us stands to the rest of the world. These, whatever be their character and composition, make up together a universitas juris ; and there is but little danger of mistake in forming the notion, if we are only careful to remember that duties enter into it quite as much as rights. Our duties may overbalance our rights. A man may owe more than he is worth, and therefore if a money value is set on his collective legal relations he may be what is called insolvent. But for all that the entire group of rights and duties which centres in him is not the less a " juris universitas." We come next to a " universal succession." A universal succession is a succession to a universitas juris. It occurs when one man is invested with the legal clothing of another, becoming at the same ' moment subject to all his liabihties and entitled to all his rights. In order that the universal suc- cession may be true and perfect, the devolution must take place uno ictu, as the jurists phrase it. It is of course possible to conceive one man acquiring the whole of the rights and duties of another at different periods, as for example by successive purchases ; or he might acquire them in different capacities, part as heir, part as pur- chaser, part as legatee. But though the group of rights and duties thus made up should in fact amount to the whole legal personality of a par- ticular individual, the acquisition would not be a Digitized by Microsoft® ja 194 HISTORY OF TESTAMENTARY SUCCESSION [chap, vi universal succession. In order that there may be a true universal succession, the transmission must be such as to pass the whole aggregate of rights and duties at the same moment and in virtue of the same legal capacity in the recipient. The notion of a universal succession, hke that of a " juris universitas," is permanent in jurisprudence, though in the English legal system it is obscured by the great variety of capacities in which rights are acquired, and, above all, by the distinction between the two great provinces of English property, " realty " and " personalty." The suc- cession of an assignee in bankruptcy to the entire property of the bankrupt is, however, a universal succession, though, as the assignee only pays debts to the extent of the assets, this is only a modified form of the primary notion. Were it common among us for persons to take assignments of all a man's property on condition of pa5nng all his debts, such transfers would exactly resemble the universal successions known to the oldest Roman Law. When a Roman citizen adrogated a son, i.e., took a man, not already under Patria Potestas, as his adoptive child, he succeeded universally to the adoptive child's estate, i.e., he took all the property and became liable for all the obligations. Several other forms of universal succession appear in the primitive Roman Law, but infinitely the most important and the most durable of all was that one with which we are more immediately concerned, Hsereditas or Inheritance. Inherit- ance was a universal succession, occurring at a death. The universal successor was Haeres or Heir. He stepped at once into all the rights and Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP, vil UNIVERSAL SUCCESSORS I95 all the duties of the dead man. He was instantly clothed with his entire legal person, and I need scarcely add that the special character of the Haeres remained the same, whether he was named by a Will or whether he took on an intestacy. The term Haeres is no more emphatically used of the Intestate than of the Testamentary Heir, for the manner in which a man became Haeres had nothing to do with the legal character he sus- tained. The dead man's universal successor, how- ever he became so, whether by Will or by In- testacy, was his Heir. But the Heir was not necessarily a single person. A group of persons, considered in law as a single unit, might succeed as co-heirs to the Inheritance. Let me now quote the usual Roman definition of an Inheritance. The reader will be in a position to appreciate the full force of the separate terms. Hcereditas est successio in universum jus quod de functus habuit ("an inheritance is a succession to the entire legal position of a deceased man "). The notion was that, though the physical person of the deceased had perished, his legal personality survived and descended unimpaired on his Heir or Co-heirs, in whom his identity (so far as the law was concerned) was continued. Our own law, in constituting the Executor or Administrator the representative of the deceased to the extent of his personal assets, may serve as an illustration of the theory from which it emanated, but, although it illustrates, it does not explain it. The view of even the later Roman Law required a closeness of correspondence between the position of the deceased and of his Heir which is no feature of Digitized by Microsoft® 196 HISTORY OF TESTAMENTARY SUCCESSION [chap, vi an English representation ; and, in the primitive jurisprudence everything turned on the continuity of succession. Unless provision was made in the will for the instant devolution of the testator's rights and duties on the Heir or Co-heirs, the testament lost all its effect. In modern Testamentary jurisprudence, as in the later Roman Law, the object of first importance is the execution of the testator's intentions. In the ancient law of Rome the subject of correspond- ing carefulness was the bestowal of the Universal Succession. One of these rules seems to our eyes a principle dictated by common sense, while the other looks very much like an idle crotchet. Yet that without the second of them the first would never have come into being, is as certain as any proposition of the kind can be. In order to solve this apparent paradox, and to bring into greater clearness the train of ideas which I have been endeavouring to indicate, I must borrow the results of the inquiry which was attempted in the earUer portion of the preceding chapter. We saw one pecuUarity invariably distinguishing the infancy of society. Men are regarded and treated, not as individuals, but always as members of a particular group. Every- body is first a citizen, and then, as a citizen, he is a member of his order — of an aristocracy or a democracy, of an order of patricians or plebeians ; or, in those societies which an unhappy fate has afflicted with a special perversion in their course of development, of a caste. Next, he is a member of a gens, house, or clan ; and lastly, he is a mem- ber of his family. This last was the narrowest Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VI] ARCHAIC SUCCESSION I97 and most personal relation in which he stood ; nor, paradoxical as it may seem, was he ever regarded as himself, as a distinct individual. His individuality was swallowed up in his family. I repeat the definition of a primitive society given before. It has for its units, not individuals, but groups of men united by the reality or the fiction of blood-relationship. It is in the peculiarities of an undeveloped society that we seize the first trace of a universal succession. Contrasted with the organisation of a modern state, the commonwealths of primitive times may be fairly described as consisting of a number of little despotic governments, each per- fectly distinct from the rest, each absolutely con- trolled by the prerogative of a single monarch. But though the Patriarch, for we must not yet call him the Pater-familias, had rights thus ex- tensive, it is impossible to doubt that he lay under an equal amplitude of obligations. If he governed the family, it was for its behoof. If he was lord of its possessions, he held them as trustee for his children and kindred. He had no privilege or position distinct from that conferred on him by his relation to the petty commonwealth which he governed. The Family, in fact, was a Corporation ; and he was its representative or, we might almost say, its Public officer. He enjoyed rights and stood under duties, but the rights and duties were, in the contemplation of his fellow-citizens and in the eye of the law, quite as much those of the collective body as his own. Let us consider for a moment, the effect which would be produced by the death of such a representative. In the eye Digitized by Microsoft® igS HISTORY OF TESTAMENTARY SUCCESSION [chap, vi of the law, in the view of the civil magistrate, the demise of the domestic authority would be a per- fectly immaterial event. The person representing the collective body of the family and primarily responsible to municipal jurisdiction would bear a different name ; and that would be all. The rights and obligations which attached to the deceased head of the house would attach, without breach of continuity, to his successor ; for, in point of fact, they would be the rights and ob- ligations of the family, and the family had the distinctive characteristic of a corporation — that it never died. Creditors would have the same remedies against the new chieftain as against the old, for the liabiUty being that of the stiU existing family would be absolutely unchanged. AU rights available to the family would be as available after the demise of the headship as before it — except that the corporation would be obliged — ^if indeed language so precise and technical can be properly used of these early times — would be obUged to sue under a slightly modified name. The history of jurisprudence must be followed in its whole course, if we are to understand how gradually and tardily society dissolved itself into the component atoms of which it is now constituted — by what insensible gradations the relation of man to man substituted itself for the relation of the individual to his family, and of famihes to each other. The point now to be attended to is that even when the revolution had apparently quite accomplished itself, even when the magistrate had in great measure assumed the place of the Pater-familias, and the civil tribunal substituted Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP, VI] THE FAMILY A CORPORATION I99 itself for the domestic fonim, nevertheless the whole scheme of rights and duties administered by the judicial authorities remained shaped by the influence of the obsolete privileges and coloured in every part by their reflection. There seems little question that the devolution of the Universitas Juris, so strenuously insisted upon by the Roman Law as the first condition of a testamentary or intestate succession, was a feature of the older form of society which men's minds have been unable to dissociate from the new, though with that newer phase it had no true or proper con- nection. It seems, in truth, that the prolongation of a man's legal existence in his heir, or in a group of co-heirs, is neither more nor less than a charac- teristic of the family transferred by a fiction to the individual. Succession in corporations is neces- sarily universal, and the family was a corporation. Corporations never die. The decease of individual members makes no difference to the collective existence of the aggregate body, and does not in any way affect its legal incidents, its faculties or liabilities. Now in the idea of a Roman universal succession all these qualities of a corporation seem to have been transferred to the individual citizen. His physical death is allowed to exercise no effect on the legal position which he filled, apparently on the principle that that position is to be adjusted as closely as possible to the analogies of a family, which, in its corporate character, was not of course liable to physical extinction. I observe that not a few Continental jurists have much difficulty in comprehending the nature of the connection between the conceptions blended Digitized by Microsoft® 200 HISTORY OF TESTAMENTARY SUCCESSION [chap, vi in a universal succession, and there is perhaps no topic in the philosophy of jurisprudence on which their speculations, as a general rule, possess so little value. But the student of Enghsh law ought to be in no danger of stumbUng at the analysis of the idea which we are examining. Much light is cast upon it by a fiction in our own system with which all lawyers are famiUar. EngUsh lawyers classify corporations as Corporations aggregate and Corporations sole. A Corporation aggregate is a true Corporation, but a Corporation sole is an in- dividual, being a member of a series of individuals, who is invested by a fiction with the quahties of a Corporation. I need hardly cite the King or the Parson of a Parish as instances of Corporations sole. The capacity or office is here considered apart from the particular person who from time to time may occupy it, and, this capacity being perpetual, the series of individuals who iill it are clothed with the leading attribute of Corporations — Perpetuity. Now in the older theory of Roman Law the individual bore to the family precisely the same relation which in the rationale of EngUsh jurisprudence a Corporation sole bears to a Cor- poration aggregate. The derivation and associa- tion of ideas are exactly the same. In fact, if we say to ourselves that for purposes of Roman Testa- mentary Jurisprudence each individual citizen was a Corporation sole, we shall not only realise the fuU conception of an inheritance, but have constantly at command the clue to the assumption in which it originated. It is an axiom with us that the King never dies, being a Corporation sole. His capacities are instantly filled by his successor, and Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VI] INTESTATE SUCCESSION 201 the continuity of dominion is not deemed to have been interrupted. With the Romans it seemed an equally simple and natural process, to eliminate the fact of death from the devolution of rights and obligations. The testator lived on in his heir or in the group of his co-heirs. He was in law the same person with them, and if any one in his testamentary dispositions had even constructively violated the principle which united his actual and his posthumous existence, the law rejected the defective instrument, and gave the inheritance to the kindred in blood, whose capacity to fulfil the conditions of heirship was conferred on them by the law itself, and not by any document which by possibility might be erroneously framed. When a Roman citizen died intestate or leaving no vaUd Will, his descendants or kindred became his heirs according to a scale which will be pre- sently described. The person or class of persons who succeeded did not simply represent the deceased, but, in conformity with the theory just delineated, they continued his civil life, his legal existence. The same results followed when the order of succession was determined by a Will, but the theory of the identity between the dead man and his heirs was certainly much older than any form of Testament or phase of Testamentary jurisprudence. This indeed is the proper moment for suggesting a doubt which wiU press on us with greater force the further we plumb the depths of this subject — whether wills would ever have come into being at all if it had not been for these re- markable ideas connected with universal succes- sion. Testamentary law is the apphcation of a Digitized by Microsoft® 202 HISTORY OF TESTAMENTARY SUCCESSION [chap, vi principle which may be explained on a variety of philosophical hypotheses as plausible as they are gratuitous ; it is interwoven with every part of modern society, and it is defensible on the broadest grounds of general expediency. But the warning can never be too often repeated, that the grand source of mistake in questions of jurisprudence is the impression that those reasons which actuate us at the present moment, in the maintenance of an existing institution, have necessarily anything in common with the sentiment in which the in- stitution originated. It is certain that, in the old Roman Law of Inheritance, the notion of a will or testament is inextricably mixed up, I might almost say confounded, with the theory of a man's posthumous existence in the person of his heir. The conception of a universal succession, firmly as it has taken root in jurisprudence, has not occurred spontaneously to the framers of every body of laws. Wherever it is now found, it may be shown to have descended from Roman law ; and with it have come down a host of legal rules on the subject of Testaments and Testamentary gifts, which modern practitioners apply without discerning their relation to the parent theory. But, in the pure Roman jurisprudence, the prin- ciple that a man lives on in his Heir — the elimina- tion, if we may so speak, of the fact of death — is too obviously for mistake the centre round which the whole Law of Testamentary and Intestate succession is circling. The unflinching sternness of the Roman law in enforcing compliance with the governing theory would in itself suggest that the theory grew out of something in the primitive Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VI] EARLY ROMAN WILLS 203 constitution of Roman society ; but we may push the proof a good way beyond the presumption. It happens that several technical expressions, dating from the earliest institution of wills at Rome, have been accidentally preserved to us. We have in Gains the formula of investiture by which the universal successor was created. We have the ancient name by which the person after- wards caUed Heir was at first designated. We have further the text of the celebrated clause in the Twelve Tables by which the Testamentary power was expressly recognised, and the clauses regulating Intestate Succession have also been preserved. AU these archaic phrases have one salient peculiarity. They indicate that what passed from the Testator to the Heir was the Family, that is, the aggregate of rights and duties contained in the Patria Potestas and growing out of it. The material property is in three instances not mentioned at all ; in two others, it is visibly named as an adjunct or appendage of the Family. The original Will or Testament was therefore an instrument, or (for it was probably not at first in writing) a proceeding, by which the devolution of the Family was regulated. It was a mode of declaring who was to have the chieftainship, in succession to the Testator. When Wills are understood to have this for their original object, we see at once how it is that they came to be connected with one of the most curious relics of ancient religion and law, the sacra, or Family Rites. These sacra were the Roman form of an institution which shows itself wherever society has not wholly shaken itself free from its primitive clothing. Digitized by Microsoft® 204 HISTORY OF TESTAMENTARY SUCCESSION [cha*. vi They are the sacrifices and ceremonies by which the brotherhood of the family is commemorated, the pledge and the witness of its perpetuity. Whatever be their nature — whether it be true or not that in all cases they are the worship of some mythical ancestor — they are everywhere employed to attest the sacredness of the family relation ; and therefore they acquire prominent significance and importance, whenever the continuous existence of the Family is endangered by a change in the person of its chief. Accordingly, we hear most about them in connection with demises of domestic sovereignty. Among the Hindoos, the right to inherit a dead man's property is exactly co-exten- sive with the duty of performing his obsequies. If the rites are not properly performed or not performed by the proper person, no relation is considered as established between the deceased and anybody surviving him ; the Law of Succes- sion does not apply, and nobody can inherit the property. Every great event in the Ufe of a Hindoo seems to be regarded as leading up to and bearing upon these solemnities. If he marries, it is to have children who may celebrate them after his death ; if he has no children, he lies under the strongest obligation to adopt them from another family, " with a view," writes the Hindoo doctor, " to the funeral cake, the water, and the solemn sacrifice." The sphere preserved to the Roman sacra in the time of Cicero, was not less in extent. It embraced Inheritances and Adoptions. No adoption was allowed to take place without due provision for the sacra of the family from which the adoptive son was transferred, and no Testa- Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VI] ROMAN AND HINDOO SACRA 205 ment was allowed to distribute an Inheritance without a strict apportionment of the expenses of these ceremonies among the different co-heirs. The differences between the Roman law at this epoch, when we obtain our last ghmpse of the sacra, and the existing Hindoo system, are most instructive. Among the Hindoos, the religious element in law has acquired a complete pre- dominance. Family sacrifices have become the keystone of all the Law of Persons and much of the Law of Things. They have even received a monstrous extension, for it is a plausible opinion that the self-immolation of the widow at her hus- band's funeral, a practice continued to historical times by the Hindoos, and commemorated in the traditions of several Indo-European races, was an addition grafted on the primitive sacra, under the influence of the impression, which always accom- panies the idea of sacrifice, that human blood is the most precious of all oblations. With the Romans, on the contrary, the legal obligation and the reUgious duty have ceased to be blended. The necessity of solemnising the sacra forms no part of the theory of civil law, but they are under the separate jurisdiction of the College of Pontiffs. The letters of Cicero to Atticus, which are full of allusions to them, leave no doubt that they con- stituted an intolerable burden on Inheritances ; but the point of development at which law breaks away from religion has been passed, and we are prepared for their entire disappearance from the later jurisprudence. In Hindoo law there is no such thing as a true Will. The place filled by Wills is occupied by Digitized by Microsoft® 206 HISTORY OF TESTAMENTARY SUCCESSION [chap, vi Adoptions. We can now see the relation of the Testamentary Power to the Faculty of Adoption, and the reason why the exercise of either of them could call up a peculiar solicitude for the perform- ance of the sacra. Both a Will and an Adoption threaten a distortion of the ordinary course of Family descent, but they are obviously contriv- ances for preventing the descent being wholly interrupted, when there is no succession of kindred to carry it on. Of the two expedients Adoption, the factitious creation of blood-relationship, is the only one which has suggested itself to the greater part of archaic societies. The Hindoos have indeed advanced one point on what was doubtless the antique practice, by allowing the widow to adopt when the father has neglected to do so, and there are in the local customs of Bengal some faint traces of the Testamentary powers. But to the Romans belongs pre-eminently the credit of in- venting the Willj the institution which, next to the Contract, has exercised the greatest influence in transforming human society. We must be careful not to attribute to it in its earliest shape the functions which have attended it in more recent times. It was at first, not a mode of distributing a dead man's goods, but one among several ways of transferring the representation of the household to a new chief. The goods descend no doubt to the Heir, but that is only because the government of the family carries with it in its devolution the power of disposing of the common stock. We are very far as yet from that stage in the history of Wills in which they become powerful instruments in modifying society through the Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. Til ROMAN IDEAS OF SUCCESSION 207 stimulus they give to the circulation of property and the plasticity they produce in proprietary rights. No such consequences as these appear in fact to have been associated with the Testamentary power even by the latest Roman lawyers. It will be found that Wills were never looked upon in the Roman community as a contrivance for parting Property and the Family, or for creating a variety of miscellaneous interests, but rather as a means of making a better provision for the members of a household than could be secured through the rules of Intestate succession. We may suspect indeed that the associations of a Roman with the practice of will-making were extremely different from those familiar to us nowadays. The habit of regarding Adoption and Testation as modes of continuing the Family cannot but have had something to do with the singular laxity of Roman notions as to the inheritance of sovereignty. It is impossible not to see that the succession of the early Roman Emperors to each other was con- sidered reasonably regular, and that, in spite of all that had occurred, no absurdity attached to the pretension of such Princes as Theodosius or Justinian to style themselves Caesar and Augustus. When the phenomena of primitive societies emerge into light, it seems impossible to dispute a proposition which the jurists of the seventeenth century considered doubtful, that Intestate In- heritance is a more ancient institution than Testamentary Succession. As soon as this is settled, a question of much interest suggests itself, how and under what conditions were the directions of a will first allowed to regulate the Digitized by Microsoft® 208 HISTORY OF TESTAMENTARY SUCCESSION [chap, vi devolution of authority over the household, and consequently the posthumous distribution of pro- perty. The difficulty of deciding the point arises from the rarity of Testamentary power in archaic communities. It is doubtful whether a true power of testation was known to any original society except the Roman. Rudimentary forms of it occur here and there, but most of them are not exempt from the suspicion of a Roman origin. The Athenian Will was, no doubt, indigenous, but then, as will appear presently, it was only an inchoate Testament. As to the Wills which are sanctioned by the bodies of law which have descended to us as the codes of the barbarian conquerors of imperial Rome, they are almost certainly Roman. The most penetrating German criticism has recently been directed to these leges Barbarorum, the great object of investigation being to detach those portions of each system which formed the customs of the tribe in its original home from the adventitious ingredients which were borrowed from the laws of the Romans. In the course of this process, one result has invariably disclosed itself, that the ancient nucleus of the code contains no trace of a Will. Whatever testamentary law exists, has been taken from Roman jurisprudence. Similarly, the rudimen- tary Testament which (as I am informed) the Rabbinical Jewish law provides for, has been attributed to contact with the Romans. The only form of Testament, not belonging to a Roman or Hellenic society, which can with any reason be supposed indigenous, is that recognised by the usages of the province of Bengal ; and the Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VI] PRIMITIVE OPERATION OF WILLS 209 Testament of Bengal, which some have even supposed to be an invention of Anglo-Indian lawyers, is at most only a rudimentary Will. The evidence, however, such as it is, seems to point to the conclusion that Testaments are at first only allowed to take effect on failure of the persons entitled to have the inheritance by right of blood genuine or fictitious. Thus, when Athenian citizens were empowered for the first time by the Laws of Solon to execute Testaments, they were forbidden to disinherit their direct male descendants. So, too, the Will of Bengal is only permitted to govern the succession so far as it is consistent with certain overriding claims of the family. Again, the original institutions of the Jews having provided nowhere for the privileges of Testatorship, the latter Rabbinical jurisprudence, which pretends to supply the casus omissi of the Mosaic law, allows the power of Testation to attach when all the kindred entitled under the Mosaic system to succeed have failed or are undiscoverable. The limitations by which the ancient German codes hedge in the testamen- tary jurisprudence which has been incorporated with them are also significant, and point in the same direction. It is the peculiarity of most of these German laws, in the only shape in which we know them, that, besides the allod or domain of each household, they recognise several sub- ordinate kinds or orders of property, each of which probably represents a separate transfusion of Roman principles into the primitive body of Teutonic usage. The primitive German or allodial property is strictly reserved to the kindred. Not 14 Digitized by Microsoft® 2IO HISTORY OF TESTAMENTARY SUCCESSION [chap, vi only is it incapable of being disposed of by testa- ment, but it is scarcely capable of being alienated by conveyance inter vivos. The ancient German law, like the Hindoo jurisprudence, makes the male children co-proprietors wdth their father, and the endowment of the family cannot be parted with except by the consent of all its members. But the other sorts of property, of more modern origin and lower dignity than the allodial possessions, are much more easily aUenated than they, and follow much more lenient rules of devolution. Women and the descendants of women succeed to them, obviously on the principle that they lie outside the sacred precinct of the Agnatic brotherhood. Now, it is on these last descriptions of property, and on these only, that the Testaments borrowed from Rome were at first allowed to operate. These few indications may serve to lend additional plausibility to that which in itself appears to be the most probable explanation of an ascertained fact in the early history of Roman Wills. We have it stated on abundant authority that Testaments, during the primitive period of the Roman State, were executed in the Comitia Calata, that is, in the Comitia Curiata, or Parlia- ment of the Patrician Burghers of Rome, when assembled for Private Business. This mode of execution has been the source of the assertion, handed down by one generation of civilians to another, that every Will at one era of Roman history was a solemn legislative enactment. But there is no necessity whatever for resorting to an explanation which has the defect of attributing Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VI] XHE PATRICIAN WILL 211 far too much precision to the proceedings of the ancient assembly. The proper key to the story concerning the execution of Wills in the Comitia Calata must no doubt be sought in the oldest Roman law of intestate succession. The canons of primitive Roman jurisprudence regulating the inheritance of relations from each other were, so long as they remained unmodified by the Edictal Law of the Praetor, to the following effect : — First, the sui or direct descendants who had never been emancipated succeeded. On the failure of the sui, the Nearest Agnate came into their place, that is, the nearest person or class of the kindred who was or might have been under the same Patria Potestas with the deceased. The third and last degree came next, in which the inheritance devolved on the Gentiles, that is, on the collective members of the dead man's gens or House. The House, I have explained already, was a fictitious extension of the family, consisting of all Roman Patrician citizens who bore the same name, and who on the ground of bearing the same name, were supposed to be descended from a common ancestor. Now the Patrician Assembly called the Comitia Curiata was a Legislature in which Gentes or Houses were exclusively repre- sented. It was a representative assembly of the Roman people, constituted on the assumption that the constituent unit of the state was the Gens. This being so, the inference seems inevitable, that the cognisance of Wills by the Comitia was connected with the rights of the Gentiles, and was intended to secure them in their privilege of ultimate inheritance. The whole apparent Digitized by Microsoft® 212 HISTORY OF TESTAMENTARY SUCCESSION [chap, vi anomaly is removed, if we suppose that a Testa- ment could only be made when the Testator had no gentiles discoverable, or when they waived their claims, and that every Testament was submitted to the General Assembly of the Roman Gentes, in order that those aggrieved by its dispositions might put their veto upon it if they pleased, or by allowing it to pass might be presumed to have renounced their reversion. It is possible that on the eve of the publication of the Twelve Tables this vetoing power may have been greatly curtailed or only occasionally and capriciously exercised. It is much easier, however, to indicate the meaning and origin of the jurisdiction confided to the Comitia Calata, than to trace its gradual development or progressive decay. The Testament to which the pedigree of all modern Wills may be traced is not, however, the Testament executed in the Calata Comitia, but another Testament designed to compete with it and destined to supersede it. The historical importance of this early Roman WiU, and the light it casts on much of ancient thought, wiU excuse me for describing it at some length. When the Testamentary power first discloses itself to us in legal history, there are signs that, like almost all the great Roman institutions, it was the subject of contention between the Patricians and the Plebeians. The effect of the political maxim, Plehs Gentem non habet, " a Plebeian cannot be a member of a house," was entirely to exclude the Plebeians from the Comitia Curiata. Some critics have accordingly supposed that a Plebeian could not have his Will read or Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VI] PLEBEIAN WILLS 2I3 recited to the Patrician Assembly, and was thus deprived of Testamentary privileges altogether. Others have been satisfied to point out the hard- ships of having to submit a proposed Will to the unfriendly jurisdiction of an assembly in which the Testator was not represented. Whatever be the true view, a form of Testament came into use, which has all the characteristics of a contrivance intended to evade some distasteful obligation. The Will in question was a conveyance inter vivos, a complete and irrevocable alienation of the Testator's family and substance to the person whom he meant to be his heir. The strict rules of Roman law must always have permitted such an alienation, but when the transaction was intended to have a posthumous effect, there may have been disputes whether it was valid for Testamentary purposes without the formal assent of the Patrician Parliament. If a difference of opinion existed on the point between the two classes of the Roman population, it was extin- guished, with many other sources of heartburning, by the great Decemviral compromise. The text of the Twelve Tables is still extant which says, " Pater familias uti de pecunid tuteldve rei sucb legdssit, ita jus esto " — a law which can hardly have had any other object than the legitimation of the Plebeian Will. It is well known to scholars that, centuries after the Patrician Assembly had ceased to be the legislature of the Roman State, it still continued to hold formal sittings for the convenience of private business. Consequently, at a period long subsequent to the publication of the Decemviral Digitized by Microsoft® 214 HISTORY OF TESTAMENTARY SUCCESSION [chap, vi Law, there is reason to believe that the Comitia Calata still assembled for the validation of Tes- taments. Its probable functions may be best indicated by saying that it was a Court of Regis- tration, with the understanding, however, that the Wills exhibited were not enrolled, but simply recited to the members, who were supposed to take note of their tenor and to commit them to memory. It is very likely that this form of Testament was never reduced to writing at all, but at all events if the Will had been originally written, the office of the Comitia was certainly confined to hearing it read aloud, the document being retained afterwards in the custody of the Testator, or deposited under the safeguard of some religious corporation. This publicity may have been one of the incidents of the Testament executed in the Comitia Calata which brought it into popular disfavour. In the early years of the Empire the Comitia still held its meetings, but they seem to have lapsed into the merest form, and few Wills, or none, were probably presented at the periodical sitting. It is the ancient Plebeian Will — the alternative of the Testament just described — which in its remote effects has deeply modified the civihsation of the modern world. It acquired at Rome all the popularity which the Testament submitted to the Calata Comitia appears to have lost. The key to all its characteristics lies in its descent from the mancipiutn, or ancient Roman convey- ance, a proceeding to which we may unhesitatingly assign the parentage of two great institutions without which modern society can scarcely be Digitized by Microsoft® '="*^- »•] MANCIPATION 215 supposed capable of holding together, the Contract and the Will. The Mancipium, or, as the word would exhibit itself in later Latinity, the Manci- pation, carries us back by its incidents to the infancy of civil society. As it sprang from times long anterior, if not to the invention, at all events to the popularisation, of the art of writing, gestures, symbolical acts, and solemn phrases take the place of docurnentary forms, and a lengthy and intricate ceremonial is intended to call the attention of the parties to the importance of the transaction, and to impress it on the memory of the witnesses. The imperfection, too, of oral, as compared with writteil testimony necessitates the multiplication of the witnesses and assistants beyond what in later times would be reasonable or intelligible limits. The Roman Mancipation required the presence first of all of the parties, the vendor and vendee, or we should perhaps rather say, if we are to use modern legal language, the grantor and grantee. There were also no less than five witnesses ; and an anomalous personage, the Libripens, who brought with him a pair of scales to weigh the uncoined copper money of ancient Rome. The Testament we are considering — the Testament per CBS et libram, " with the copper and the scales," as it long continued to be technically called — was an ordinary Mancipation with no change in the form and hardly any in words. The Testator was the grantor ; the five witnesses and the libripens were present ; and the place of grantee was taken by a person known technically as the familicB emptor, the Purchaser of the Family, Digitized by Microsoft® 2l6 HISTORY OF TESTAMENTARY SUCCESSION [chap, vi The ordinary ceremony of a Mancipation was then proceeded with. Certain formal gestures were made and sentences pronounced. The Emptor familicB simulated the payment of a price by striking the scales with a piece of money, and finally the Testator ratified what had been done in a set form of words called the " Nuncupatio " or publication of the transaction, a phrase which, I need scarcely remind the lawyer, has had a long history in Testamentary jurisprudence. It is necessary to attend particularly to the character of the person called familicB emptor. There is no doubt that at first he was the Heir himself. The Testator conveyed to him outright his whole " familia," that is, aU the rights he enjoyed over and through the family ; his property, his slaves, and aU his ancestral privileges, together, on the other hand, with all his duties and obligations. With these data before us, we are able to note several remarkable points in which the Manci- patory Testament, as it may be called, differed in its primitive form from a modern WiU. As it amounted to a conveyance out-and-out of the Testator's estate, it was not revocable. There could be no new exercise of a power which had been exhausted. Again, it was not secret. The Familiae Emptor, being himself the Heir, knew exactly what his rights were, and was aware that he was irreversibly entitled to the inheritance ; a knowledge which the violences inseparable from the best-ordered ancient society rendered extremely dangerous. But perhaps the most surprising consequences of this relation of Testaments to Conveyances Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VI] WILL AS CONVEYANCE ZT'J was the immediate vesting of the Inheritance in the Heir. This has seemed so incredible to not a few civiUans, that they have spoken of the Testator's estate as vesting conditionally on the Testator's death, or as granted to him from a time uncertain, i.e., the death of the grantor. But down to the latest period of Roman juris- prudence there was a certain class of transactions which never admitted of being directly modified by a condition, or of being limited to or from a point of time. In technical language they did not admit conditio or di&s. Mancipation was one of them, and therefore, strange as it may seem, we are forced to conclude that the primitive Roman Will took effect at once, even though the Testator survived his act of Testation. It is indeed likely that Roman citizens originally made their Wills only in the article of death, and that a provision for the continuance of the Family effected by a man in the flower of life would take the form rather of an Adoption than of a Will. Still we must believe that, if the Testator did recover, he could only continue to govern his household by the sufferance of his Heir. Two or three remarks should be made before I explain how these inconveniences were remedied, and how Testaments came to be invested with the characteristics now universally associated with them. The Testament was not necessarily written : at first, it seems to have been invariably oral, and, even in later times, the instrument declaratory of the bequests was only incidentally connected with the Will and formed no essential Digitized by Microsoft® 2l8 HISTORY OF TESTAMENTARY SUCCESSION [chap, vi part of it. It bore in fact exactly the same relation to the Testament which the deed leading the uses bore to the Fines and Recoveries of old English law, or which the charter of feoffment bore to the feoffment itself. Previously, indeed, to the Twelve Tables, no writing would have been of the slightest use, for the Testator had no power of giving legacies, and the only persons who could be advantaged by a will were the Heir or Co-heirs. But the extreme generaUty of the clause in the Twelve Tables soon produced the doctrine that the heir must take the inheritance burdened by any directions which the Testator might give him, or, in other words, take it subject to legacies. Written testamentary instruments assumed thereupon a new value, as a security against the fraudulent refusal of the heir to satisfy the legatees ; but to the last it was at the Testator's pleasure to rely exclusively on the testimony of the witnesses, and to declare by word of mouth the legacies which the familice emptor was com- missioned to pay. The terms of the expression Emptor familice demand notice. " Emptor " indicates that the WiU was Uterally a sale, and the word " familiae," when compared with the phraseology in the Testa- mentary clause in the Twelve Tables, leads us to some instructive conclusions. " Familia," in classical Latinity, means always a man's slaves. Here, however, and generally in the language of ancient Roman law, it includes all persons under his Potestas, and the Testator's material property or substance is understood to pass as an adjunct or appendage of his household. Turning to the Digitized by Microsoft® cHA!-. ri] PRETORIAN WILLS 2ig law of the Twelve Tables, it will be seen that it speaks of tutela rei suce, " the guardianship of his cubstance," a form of expression which is the exact reverse of the phrase just examined. There does not therefore appear to be any mode of escaping from the conclusion, that even at an era so comparatively recent as that of the Decemviral compromise, terms denoting " household " and " property " were blended in the current phrase- ology. If a man's household had been spoken of as his property we might have explained the expression as pointing to the extent of the Patria Potestas, but, as the interchange is reciprocal, we must allow that the form of speech carries us back to the primeval period in which property is owned by the family, and the family is governed by the citizen, so that the members of the community do not own their property and their family, but rather own their property through their family. At an epoch not easy to settle with precision, the Roman Praetors fell into the habit of acting upon Testaments solemnised in closer conformity with the spirit than the letter of the law. Casual dispensations became insensibly the established practice, till at length a wholly new form of Will was matured and regularly engrafted on the Edictal Jurisprudence. The new or Prcetorian Testament derived the whole of its impregnability from the Jus Honorarium or Equity of Rome. The Praetor of some particular year must have inserted a clause in his Inaugural Proclamation declaratory of his intention to sustain aU Testa- ments which should have been executed with such and such solemnities ; and, the reform having Digitized by Microsoft® 220 HISTORY OF TESTAMENTARY SUCCESSION [chap, vi been found advantageous, the article relating to it must have been again introduced by the Praetor's successor, and repeated by the next in office, till at length it formed a recognised portion of that body of jurisprudence which from these successive incorporations was styled the Per- petual or Continuous Edict. On examining the conditions of a vaUd Praetorian Will they will be plainly seen to have been determined by the requirements of the Mancipatory Testament, the innovating Praetor having obviously prescribed to himself the retention of the old formalities just so far as they were warrants of genuineness or securities against fraud. At the execution of the Mancipatory Testament seven persons had been present besides the Testator. Seven witnesses were accordingly essential to the Praetorian WiU ; two of them corresponding to the libripens and familicB emptor, who were now stripped of their symbolical character, and were merely present for the purpose of supplying their testimony. No emblematic ceremony was gone through ; the Will was merely recited ; but then it is probable (though not absolutely certain) that a written instrument was necessary to perpetuate the evi- dence of the Testator's dispositions. At aU events, whenever a writing was read or exhibited as a person's last Will, we know certainly that the Praetorian Court would not sustain it by special intervention, unless each of the seven witnesses had severally affixed his seal to the outside. This is the first appearance of sealing in the history of jurisprudence, considered as a mode of authen- tication. The use of seals, however, as mere Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VI] XHE BONORUM POSSESSIO 221 fastenings, is doubtless of much higher antiquity ; and it appears to have been known to the Hebrews. We may observe, that the seals of the Roman Wills, and other documents of importance, did not only serve as the index of the present or assent of the signatary, but were also literally fastenings which had to be broken before the writing could be inspected. The Edictal Law would therefore enforce the dispositions of a Testator, when, instead of being symbolised through the forms of mancipation, they were simply evidenced by the seals of seven witnesses. But it may be laid down as a general proposition, that the principal qualities of Roman property were incommunicable except through processes which were supposed to be coeval with the origin of the Civil Law. The Praetor therefore could not confer an Inheritance on anybody. He could not place the Heir or Co-heirs in that very relation in which the Testator had himself stood to his own rights and obligations. All he could do was to confer on the person designated as Heir the practical enjoyment of the property be- queathed, and to give the force of legal acquit- tances to his payments of the Testator's debts. When he exerted his powers to these ends, the Praetor was technically said to communicate the Bonorum Possessio. The Heir specially inducted under these circumstances, or Bonorum Possessor, had every proprietary privilege of the Heir by the Civil Law. He took the profits and he could alienate, but then, for all his remedies for redress against wrong, he must go, as we should phrase it, not to the Common Law, but to the Equity Digitized by Microsoft® 222 HISTORY OF TESTAMENTARY SUCCESSION [chap, vi side of the Praetorian Court. No great chance of error would be incurred by describing him as having an equitable estate in the inheritance ; but then, to secure ourselves against being deluded by the analogy, we must always recollect that in one year the Bonorum Possessio was operated upon by a principle of Roman Law known as Usucapion, and the Possessor became Quiritarian owner of all the property comprised in the inheritance. We know too httle of the older law of Civil Process to be able to strike the balance of advan- tage and disadvantage between the different classes of remedies supphed by the Praetorian Tribunal. It is certain, however, that, in spite of its many defects, the Mancipatory Testament by which the universitas juris devolved at once and unimpaired was never entirely superseded by the new WiU ; and at a period less bigoted to antiquarian forms, and perhaps not quite alive to their significance, all the ingenuity of the Jurisconsults seems to have been expended on the improvement of the more venerable instrument. At the era of Gains, which is that of the Antonine Caesars, the great blemishes of the Mancipatory Will had been removed. Originally, as we have seen, the essential character of the formalities had required that the Heir himself should be the Purchaser of the Family, and the consequence was that he not only in- stantly acquired a vested interest in the Testator's Property but was formally made aware of his rights. But the age of Gains permitted some un- concerned person to officiate as Purchaser of the Family. The Heir, therefore, was not necessarily informed of the succession to which he was Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VI] IMPROVEMENTS IN THE ROMAN WILL 223 destined ; and Wills thenceforward acquired the property of secrecy. The substitution of a stranger for the actual Heir in the functions of " Familiae Emptor " had other ulterior consequences. As soon as it was legalised, a Roman Testament came to consist of two parts or stages, — a Conveyance, which was a pure form, and a Nuncupatio, or Publication. In this latter passage of the pro- ceeding, the Testator either orally declared to the assistants the wishes which were to be executed after his death, or produced a written document in which his wishes were embodied. It was not probably till attention had been quite drawn off from the imaginary Conveyance, and concentrated on the Nuncupatio as the essential part of the transaction, that Wills were allowed to become revocable. I have thus carried the pedigree of Wills some way down in legal history. The root of it is the old Testament " with the copper and the scales," founded on a Mancipation or Conveyance. This ancient Will has, however, manifold defects, which are remedied, though only indirectly, by the Praetorian law. Meantime the ingenuity of the Jurisconsults effects, in the Common-Law Will or Mancipatory Testament, the very improvements which the Praetor may have concurrently carried out in Equity. These last ameliorations depend, however, on mere legal dexterity, and we see accordingly that the Testamentary Law of the day of Gains or Ulpian is only transitional. What changes next ensued we know not ; but at length just before the reconstruction of the jurisprudence by Justinian, we find the subjects of the Eastern Digitized by Microsoft® 224 NOTES [CHAP. VI Roman Empire employing a form of Will of which the pedigree is traceable to the Praetorian Testa- ment on one side, and to the Testament " with the copper and the scales," on the other. Like the Testament of the Praetor, it required no Mancipation, and was invalid unless sealed by seven witnesses. Like the Mancipatory Will, it passed the Inheritance and not merely a Bonorum Possessio. Several, however, of its most important features were annexed by positive enactments, and it is out of regard to this threefold derivation from the Praetorian Edict, from the Civil Law, and from the Imperial Constitutions, that Justinian speaks of the Law of Wills in his own day as Jus Triper- titum. The new Testament thus described is the one generally known as the Roman Will. But it was the Will of the Eastern Empire only ; and the researches of Savigny have shown that in Western Europe the old Mancipatory Testament, with all its apparatus of conveyance, copper, and scales, continued to be the form in use far down in the Middle Ages. NOTE M TESTAMENTARY SUCCESSION The burden of this chapter is that the Will or Testament of modern law, with its specific characters of being secret, revocable, and posthumous in operation, is unknown to archaic law, and is of comparatively recent introduction wherever we find it. Maine's position is amply confirmed by later historical research, and one or two seeming exceptions which he felt bound to notice have been removed. Jurists of the seventeenth century, we read in Maine's text, resorted to the law of nature to explain and justify testamentary power. This is almost enough of itself to show that no such power Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP, vil NOTES 225 was commonly found in customary law. For the doctrine of natural law was, as we have already seen, a progressive and rationalist doctrine. Its use was to override the commonplace objections founded on lack of authority or even on the existence of contrary custom ; and at the time of the Renaissance and even earlier it served speculative publicists in much the same way as the principle of utility (with which it has considerable affinities) has served modem reformers. In fact, the whole conception of individual succession to property, even without a will, is relatively modem. The archaic Indo-European family was, Maine tells us, a corporation, of which the patriarch for the time being was the representative or public officer — or at most, we may add, managing director. Evidently we are not meant to take this statement as if a definite legal doctrine of persons, much less artificial persons, was to be ascribed to the patriarchal stage of society. For in that stage, as Maine also says, a man was not yet regarded as an individual, but only as a member of his family and class ; and this is still true to a great extent in Hindu law. Now the modern doctrine of corporations assumes that the "natural person" or individual, considered as a subject of rights and duties, or "lawful man," as our English books say, is the normal unit of legal institutions, and that the collective personality of a group of men acting in a common interest or duty and behaving like an individual is something which needs to be explained. But for archaic society the collective body and not the individual is the natural person. We find the same conditions existing in full force among the German tribes in a much later period of time than that which Maine is directly considering in this chapter. A recent learned writer in France, dealing with precisely the same subject as it occurs in the medieval history of French law, has forcibly contrasted the Roman conception, as it was established in the classical law of the empire, with the German. " Le droit romain consacre le triomphe de I'individualisme ; la volont6 personnelle du chef de famille, voil4 le facteur juridique essentiel, I'agent de toutes les transactions, la force cr6atrice de tous les droits. Cette volont6 est si respect6e et si puissante, qu'elle continue d'agir apres la disparition de celui qui I'a exprim6e. Le pere regie le sort de sa fortune et de sa famille pour le temps oii il ne sera plus, et cela par un acte souverainement libre, qu'il est toujours k m^me de modifier. . . . L'individu sut juris est, dans le monde romain, I'unitfe juridique et social. "Chez les Germains, c'est bien plutdt la famille. II serait sans doute excessif, surtout pour le temps des Leges [the custumals collectively known as ' Leges Barbarorum '], de declarer en termes absolus que la famille est tout et que l'individu n'est rien; la v6rit6 sous cette forme serait exag6r6e et d6natur6e. Mais il est certain cependant que I'exaltation de l'individu est beaucoup moins Digitized by Microsoft® 226 NOTES [CHAP. VI complete qu'i Rome, et que d'autre part la famille forme une association, une sorte d'fitre coUectif arm6 de droits inconnus des jurisconsultes de I'Empire. L'6nergie individuelle est limit^e dans le temps, et les Germains ne peuvent pas concevoir qu'elle s'exerce au deli de la tombe ; sitdt I'homme mort, toutes ses volont^s s'6vanouissent. Au m6me moment ses prerogatives juridiques sont recouvertes et absorb^es par celles de ses parents, car de son vivant mfime sa famille jouissait de droits autonomes qu'il ne d6pendait pas de lui de supprimer : sa mort les d6veloppe, mais eUe ne les cr6e pas" (AufEroy, "Evolution du testament en France," Paris, 1899, pp. 1 73-4. Cf. Brunner, " Grundzuge der deutschen Rechtsgeschichte," § 56 ; " Das germanische Erbrecht war ein Familienrecht." For examples of analogous customs among various uncivilized tribes, see Lord Avebury, "Origin of Civilisation," 6th ed. pp. 489-91. The suggestion in Maine's text of regarding the Roman ancestor in his representative character as a kind of corporation sole may be helpful to English students, but we can hardly trust it to throw light on the actual formation of Roman legal ideas. For our English category of corporations sole is not only, as Maine calls it, a fiction, but modem, anomalous, and of no practical use. When a parson or other solely corporate office-holder dies, there is no one to act for the corporation until a successor is appointed, and, when appointed, that successor can do nothing which he could not do without being called a corporation sole. In the case of the parson even the continuity of the freehold is not saved, and it is said to be in abeyance in the interval. As for the king, or " the Crown," being a corporation sole, the language of our books appears to be nothing but a clumsy and, after all, ineffective device to avoid openly personifying the State. The problems of federal politics in Canada and Australia threaten to make the fiction complex. Is "the Crown" a trustee for Dominion and Province, for Common- wealth and State, with possibly conflicting interests ? or is there one indivisible Crown being or having several persons for different purposes? (F. W. Maitland, L.Q.R. xvi. 335, xvii. 131; W. Harrison Moore, L.Q.R. xx. 351 ; Markby, " Elements of Law," §145). The whole thing seems to have arisen from the technical difficulty of making grants to a parson and his successors after the practice of making them to God and the patron saint had been dis- continued, as tending to bring the saints into the unseemly position of litigants before secular courts. All this we may now think makes for historical curiosity rather than philosophical edification. But in any case the chief part of Maine's argument, his insistence on " the theory of a man's posthumous existence in the person of his heir," and the intimate connection of that theory with the ancestor's representative character as head of the family, goes to the root of the matter. Mr. Justice Holmes, now of the Supreme Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VI] NOTES 227 Court of the United States, writing twenty years after Maine, summed this up with concise elegance (" The Common Law," p. 343): " If the family was the owner of the property administered by a paterfamilias, its rights remained unaffected by the death of its temporary head. The family continued, although the head died. And when, probably by a gradual change, the paterfamilias came to be regarded as owner, instead of a simple manager of the family rights, the nature and continuity of those rights did not change with the title to them. The familia continued to the heirs as it was left by the ancestor. . . . " The aggregate of the ancestor's rights and duties, or, to use the technical phrase, the total persona sustained by him, was early separated from his natural personality. For this persona was but the aggregate of what had formerly been family rights and duties, and was originally sustained by any individual only as the family head. Hence it was said to be continued by the inheritance ; and when the heir assumed it, he had his action in respect of injuries previously committed." Maine proceeds to trace the development of the Roman testament from a distribution of property, taking effect at once, made in contemplation of impending death or great peril, and requiring, in its earliest form, something like legislative sanction (cp. Girard, " Manuel," pp. 792-5), through the intermediate stage of a conveyance reserving a life interest, which may be seen in the provincial customs of the Roman Empire, and much later in medieval and even modem systems. Muirhead (" Historical Introduction to the Pirvate Law of Rome," pp. 66, 168) pointed out a remedy for the difficulty suggested at p. 217, that a will by mancipation must have left the testator penniless. Usufruct might very well be reserved on a mancipation, Gai. ii. 2>i< " ^''^^ ^ reservation of a life interest in one's own familia would possibly be construed even more liberally than an ordinary usufruct." Still, usufruct is not among the earliest institutions, and it would be rash to say that the difficulty may not have been real at one time. But men have been driven all over the world, by an imperfect state of proparty law or by special reasons for avoiding publicity, to put very large trust in the honour of chosen friends and assistants ; and there is nothing about the Roman familiae emtor in his most archaic stage to surprise an English student who has made acquaint- ance with our medieval feoffee to uses. Indian practice will furnish a parallel in the bendmi (liteiaily, "anonymous") conveyances to a nominal purchaser, to hold on a secret trust for the real one, which appear to have survived the original reasons for them. Sohm, however, holds ("Institutes," § 112, pp. 543, 544, in Ledlie's trans- lation, 3rd ed.) that the testament per aes et libram was coupled with a mandate to the familiae em.tor, which was binding under the Digitized by Microsoft® 228 NOTES [CHAP, n well-known provision of the Twelve Tables, " nti lingua nuncupassit ita ius esto." This would of course simplify the matter. The same learned author's suggestion that the institution of an heir was a modified form of adoption — that is, an adoption deferred to the testator's death — does not seem to be generally accepted (Girard, "Manuel," p. 793). What is said in this chapter about Hindu law would no doubt have been fuller if a convenient and trustworthy text-book like Mr. Mayne's had existed at the time when it was written. I am not aware, however, that any modification is needed except on one point, namely that the strict determination of the order of successiou among an ancestor's next of kin according to the spiritual efficacy of their sacrifices is found only in the school of Bengal. This has been thought to be a deliberate Brahmanical innovation ; but lately two learned Indian scholars, Mr. Justice Mitra of the High Court of Calcutta and Mr. S. S. Setlur, have rejected that view ; the former of them asserts, but the latter denies, that the peculiar doctrines in question are of Buddhistic origin (see L.Q.R. xxi. 380, xxii. 50, xxiii. 202). As Maine himself said in 1883, " we now can discern something of the real relation which the sacerdotal Hindu law bears to the true ancient law of the race " (" Early Law and Custom," p. 194; see also the chapter on Ancestor Worship and Inheritance). The general importance of keeping up the family ritual both in Hindu and in other archaic law remains undoubted. Some addition has to be made as regards the Hindu will. Quite unknown to early Hindu law, will-making came into use in modem times, though not in imitation of European practice according to the best authorities, and was not recognised in any of the Presidency Courts before 1832, when it was allowed in Bengal. When "Ancient Law" was published the law was not yet quite settled in Madras and Bombay ; but the courts of those Presidencies followed the same course within a few years. Apparently the first form of the Bengal will was a gift mortis causa to religious uses. The reader will perceive the resemblance to the development of the testament of chattels, under ecclesiastical influence, in medieval English law. The English history, however, is for the most part too complex and peculiar to throw much light on the normal tjrpe of evolution. As for the Anglo-Saxon will, even if it can be assimilated to modem wills, which is doubtful, it was a special and anomalous kind of document, and disappeared after the Norman Conquest. Probably language is still to be found in popular books asserting or implying that before the Conquest there was general freedom of alienation ; but this is due to pure misunderstanding, the privileged class of transactions which are recorded in the Anglo-Saxon charters having been taken as typical and indigenous. Early English "post obit gifts" (Pollock and Maitland, " H.E.L." ii. 317. sqq., and see Note Q below) do present Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VI] NOTES 229 some analogy to the Roman will by mancipation ; and this appears m a strengthened form in the conveyance to feoffees to uses to be declared by the feoffee's will which was common in the later Middle Ages. In the thirteenth century divers learned clerks made an ingenious and, it seems, almost a successful attempt to create posthumous disposing power by grants inter vivos, containing in what we now call the "habendum" such words as " cuicunque dare vel etiam legare voluerit." A clause so framed is quite common in deeds of the third and even fourth quarters of that century, and inconsistent utterances in Bracton show that learned opinion fluctuated (i83, 412*, pro, 49a, fuller and seemingly more deliberate, contra, cp. Pollock and Maitland, ii. 37). We may believe' that for some time and to some extent the power such clauses purported to confer was exercised without objection. But this was a transitory experiment, and has nothing to do with any real testamentary distribution or succession. Local customs to devise land or, at any rate, purchased land existed, but their origin and early history are still obscure. In Scotland we find the most remarkable illustration of the prae-testamentary stage, as we may call it, of property law Properly there is no such term as Will in Scots law, and there was no true will of lands before 1868. "Heritage could only be transmitted by a deed containing words of de ^raesenti ^\%'^oAWon, and the use of the word 'dispone' was essential" (Green's "Encycl. of the Law of Scotland," s.v. Will.). The accustomed form was (and apparently still is, notwithstanding that it is no longer necessary) a "trust disposition and settlement," a present conveyance reserving a life interest to the grantor. Scotland, in fact, is the last home of the old Germanic Vergabung von Todes viegen (Goffin, " The Testamentary Executor," 1901, pp. 19, 99). It may survive many generations yet, for aught we know, as in the customs of Egypt and other parts of the Roman Empire essentially similar forms continued in use long after true wills had become familiar in the law of Rome. Original examples of the second century A.D. found at Naucratis might be seen in London some years ago. Notwithstanding the marks of Roman influence which the modem English will bears, its practical scope and effect remain as different as possible from those of the Roman testament. As a rule the wills of Englishmen having any considerable property to dispose of aim not at investing any one person with the whole of the testator's control over his estate, subject to payment of debts and legacies, but rather at postponing absolute control and preserving the estate under the sanction of a trust which w|ll ' Extant wills of the period which purport to devise parcels of land (Madox, Form. Anglic. DCCLXVIII., DCCLXIX., DCCLXXI.) are not conclusive as to the practice in the absence of a known previous grant with which they can be connected, as other explanations are possible. Digitized by Microsoft® 230 NOTES [CHAP. VI Eot be finally determined while any child of the testator is a minor or his widow living. The capital is to be intact as long as possible, while the income is enjoyed or applied according to the testator's directions. If any one is at all like a Roman heir, it is the executor, who does not necessarily take any beneficial interest, and whose origin is quite different (Goffin, oj). cit. p. 7,^ ; O. W. Holmes, L.Q. R. i. 165-6; Gierke, " Grundzuge des deutschen Privatrechts," § 126, in " Encykl. d. Rechtswiss." i. 555). The Roman horror of intestacy mentioned in the early part of the following chapter was equalled or surpassed among medieval Englishmen (Pollock and Maitland, ii. 356) ; but the reason was not one that would have occurred to any Roman from the time of Labeo to that of Justinian, being the danger to the intestate's soul if he died without having assigned a fitting part of his estate to pious uses (Du Cange s.v. intestatio). Digitized by Microsoft® CHAPTER VII ANCIENT AND MODERN IDEAS RESPECTING WILLS AND SUCCESSIONS Although there is much in the modem European Law of Wills which is intimately connected with the oldest rules of Testamentary disposition practised among men, there are nevertheless some important differences between ancient and modem ideas on the subject of WiUs and Succes- sions. Some of the points of difference I shall endeavour to illustrate in this chapter. At a period, removed several centuries from the era of the Twelve Tables, we find a variety of rules engrafted on the Roman Civil Law with the view of Umiting the disinherison of children ; we have the jurisdiction of the Praetor very actively exerted in the same interest ; and we are also presented with a new remedy, very anomalous in character and of uncertain origin, called the Querela Inofficiosi Testamenti, " the Plaint of an Unduteous Will," directed to the reinstatement of the issue in inheritances from which they had been unjustifiably excluded by a father's Testament. Comparing this condition of the law with the text of the Twelve Tables which concedes in terms the utmost liberty of Testation, several writers have been tempted to interweave a good deal of dramatic incident into 331 Digitized by Microsoft® 232 IDEAS AS TO WILLS AND SUCCESSIONS [chap, vii their history of the Law Testamentary. They tell us of the boundless license of disinherison in which the heads of families instantly began to indulge, of the scandal and injury to pubHc morals which the new practices engendered, and of the applause of all good men which hailed the courage of the Praetor in arresting the progress of paternal depravity. This story, which is not without some foundation for the principal fact it relates, is often so told as to disclose very serious mis- conceptions of the principles of legal history. The Law of the Twelve Tables is to be explained by the character of the age in which it was enacted. It does not license a tendency which a later era thought itself bound to counteract, but it proceeds on the assumption that no such tendency exists, or perhaps we should say, in ignorance of the possibihty of its existence. There is no hkehhood that Roman citizens began immediately to avail themselves freely of the power to disinherit. It is against aU reason and sound appreciation of history to suppose that the yoke of family bondage, still patiently submitted to, as we know, where its pressure gaUed most cruelly, would be cast off in the very particular in which its incidence in our own day is not otherwise than welcome. The Law of the Twelve Tables permitted the execution of Testaments in the only case in which it was thought possible that they could be exe- cuted, viz., on failure of children and proximate kindred. It did not forbid the disinherison of direct descendants, inasmuch as it did not legislate against a contingency which no Roman lawgiver of that era could have contemplated. No doubt, Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VII] FEELING RESPECTING INTESTACY 233 as the offices of family affection progressively lost the aspect of primary personal duties, the disinherison of children was occasionally at- tempted. But the interference of the Praetor, so far from being called for by the universaUty of the abuse, was doubtless first prompted by the fact that such instances of unnatural caprice were few and exceptional, and at conflict with the current morahty. The indications furnished by this part of Roman Testamentary Law are of a very different kind. It is remarkable that a Will never seems to have been regarded by the Romans as a means of disinheriting a Family, or of affecting the unequal distribution of a patrimony. The rules of law preventing its being turned to such a purpose, increase in number and stringency as the jurisprudence unfolds itself ; and these rules correspond doubtless with the abiding sentiment of Roman society, as distinguished from occasional variations of feeUng in individuals. It would rather seem as if the Testamentary Power were chiefly valued for the assistance it gave in making provision for a Family, and in dividing the in- heritance more evenly and fairly than the Law of Intestate Succession would have divided it. If this be the true reading of the general sentiment on the point, it explains to some extent the singular horror of Intestacy which always characterised the Roman. No evil seems to have been con- sidered a heavier visitation than the forfeiture of Testamentary privileges ; no curse appears to have been bitterer than that which imprecated on an enemy that he might die without a Will. Digitized by Microsoft® 234 IDEAS AS TO WILLS AND SUCCESSIONS [chap, vii The feeling has no counterpart, or none that is easily recognisable, in the forms of opinion which exist at the present day. All men at aU times will doubtless prefer chalking out the destination of their substance to having their office performed for them by the law ; but the Roman passion for Testacy is distinguished from the mere desire to indulge caprice by its intensity ; and it has, of course, nothing whatever in common with that pride of family, exclusively the creation of feudahsm, which accumulates one description of property in the hands of a single representative. It is probable, ct 'priori, that it was something in the rules of Intestate Succession which caused this vehement preference for the distribution of property under a Testament over its distribution by law. The difficulty, however, is, that on glancing at the Roman Law of Intestate Succession in the form which it wore for many centuries before Justinian shaped it into that scheme of inheritance which has been almost universally adopted by modem lawgivers, it by no means strikes one as remarkably unreasonable or in- equitable. On the contrary, the distribution it prescribes is so fair and rational, and differs so little from that with which modem society has been generally contented, that no reason suggests itself why it should have been regarded with extraordinary distaste, especially under a juris- prudence which pared down to a narrow compass the testamentary privileges of persons who had children to provide for. We should rather have expected that, as in France at this moment, the heads of famihes would generally save themselves Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP, viij ROMAN INTESTATE SUCCESSION 235 the trouble of executing a Will, and allow the Law to do as it pleased with their assets. I think, however, if we look a httle closely at the pre-Justinianean scale of Intestate Succession, we shaU discover the key to the mystery. The texture of the law consists of two distinct parts. One department of rules comes from the Jus Civile, the Common-Law of Rome ; the other from the Edict of the Praetor. The Civil Law, as I have already stated for another purpose, calls to the inheritance only three orders of successors in their turn ; the Unemancipated children, the nearest class of Agnatic kindred, and the Gentiles. Between these three orders, the Praetor interpolates various classes of rela- tives, of whom the Civil Law took no notice whatever. Ultimately, the combination of the Edict and of the Civil Law forms a table of succession not materially different from that which has descended to the generaUty of modem codes. The point for recollection is, that there must anciently have been a time at which the rules of the Civil Law determined the scheme of Intes- tate Succession exclusively, and at which the arrangements of the Edict were non-existent, or not consistently carried out. We cannot doubt that, in its infancy, the Praetorian juris- prudence had to contend with formidable obstruc- tions, and it is more than probable that, long after popular sentiment and legal opinion had acquiesced in it, the modifications which it periodically introduced were governed by no certain principles, and fluctuated with the varjdng Digitized by Microsoft® 236 IDEAS AS TO WILLS AND SUCCESSIONS [chap, vii bias of successive magistrates. The rules of Intestate Succession, which the Romans must at this period have practised, account, I think — and more than account — for that vehement distaste for an Intestacy to which Roman society during so many ages remained constant. The order of succession was this : on the death of a citizen, having no will or no vaUd wiU, his Unemancipated children became his Heirs. His emancipated sons had no share in the inheritance. If he left no direct descendants hving at his death, the nearest grade of the Agnatic kindred succeeded, but no part of the inheritance was given to any relative united (however closely) with the dead man through female descents. AU the other branches of the family were excluded, and the inheritance escheated to the Gentiles, or entire body of Roman citizens bearing the same name with the deceased. So that on failing to execute an operative Testa- ment, a Roman of the era under examination left his emancipated children absolutely without provision, while, on the assumption that he died childless, there was imminent risk that his posses- sions would escape from the family altogether, and devolve on a number of persons with whom he was merely connected by the sacerdotal fiction that assumed all members of the same gens to be descended from a common ancestor. The prospect of such an issue is in itself a nearly sufficient explanation of the popular sentiment ; but, in point of fact, we shall only half understand it, if we forget that the state of things I have been describing is likely to have existed at the very moment when Roman society was in the first Digitized by Microsoft® CHAi.. VII] TESTATION AND NATURAL AFFECTION 237 stage of its transition from its primitive organisa- tion in detached families. The empire of the father had indeed received one of the earhest blows directed at it through the recognition of Emancipation as a legitimate usage, but the law, still considering the Patria Potestas to be the root of family connection, persevered in looking on the emancipated children as strangers to the rights of kinship and ahens from the blood. We cannot, however, for a moment suppose that the limitations of the family imposed by legal pedantry had their counterpart in the natural affection of parents. Family attachments must still have retained that nearly inconceivable sanctity and intensity which belonged to them under the Patriarchal system ; and so httle are they likely to have been extinguished by the act of emanci- pation, that the probabiUties are altogether the other way. It may be unhesitatingly taken for granted that enfranchisement from the father's power was a demonstration, rather than a sever- ance, of affection — a mark of grace and favour accorded to the best-beloved and most esteemed of the children. If sons thus honoured above the rest were absolutely deprived of their heritage by an Intestacy, the reluctance to incur it requires no farther explanation. We might have assumed a priori that the passion for Testacy was generated by some moral injustice entailed by the rules, of Intestate succession ; and here we find them at variance with the very instinct by which early society was cemented together. It is possible to put ail that has been urged in a very succinct form. Every dominant sentiment of the primitive Digitized by Microsoft® 238 IDEAS AS TO WILLS AND SUCCESSIONS [chap, vii Romans was entwined with the relations of the family. But what was the Family ? The Law defined it one way — natural affection another. In the conflict between the two, the feeling we would analyse grew up, taking the form of an enthusiasm for the institution by which the dictates of affection were permitted to determine the fortunes of its object. I regard, therefore, the Roman horror of Intestacy as a monument of a very early conflict between ancient law and slowly changing ancient sentiment on the subject of the Family. Some passages in the Roman Statute-Law, and one statute in particular which hmited the capacity for inheritance possessed by women, must have contributed to keep alive the feehng ; and it is the general belief that the system of creating Fidei-Commissa, or bequests in trust, was devised to evade the disabiUties imposed by those statutes. But the feeling itself, in its remarkable intensity, seems to point back to some deeper antagonism between law and opinion ; nor is it at all wonderful that the improvements of jurisprudence by the Praetor should not have extinguished it. Every- body conversant with the philosophy of opinion is aware that a sentiment by no means dies out, of necessity, with the passing away of the circum- stances which produced it. It may long survive them ; nay, it may afterwards attain to a pitch and cUmax of intensity which it never attained during their actual continuance. The view of a WiU which regards it as con- ferring the power of diverting property from the Family, or of distributing it in such uneven Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. Tin MEDIEVAL WILLS 239 proportions as the fancy or good sense of the Testator may dictate, is not older than that later portion of the Middle Ages in which Feudalism had completely consolidated itself. When modern jurisprudence first shows itself in the rough, WiUs are rarely allowed to dispose with absolute freedom of a dead man's assets. Wherever at this period the descent of property was regulated by Will — and over the greater part of Europe movable or personal property was the subject of Testamentary disposition — the exercise of the Testamentary power was seldom allowed to interfere with the right of the widow to a definite share, and of the children to certain fixed propor- tions, of the devolving inheritance. The shares of the children, as their amount shows, were determined by the authority of Roman law. The provision for the widow was attributable to the exertions of the Church, which never relaxed its soUcitude for the interest of wives surviving their husbands — winning, perhaps, one of the most arduous of its triumphs when, after exacting for two or three centuries an express promise from the husband at marriage to endow his wife, it at length succeeded in engrafting the principle of Dower on the Customary Law of all Western Europe. Curiously enough, the dower of lands proved a more stable institution than the analo- gous and more ancient reservation of certain shares of the personal property to the widow and children. A few local customs in France main- tained the right down to the Revolution, and there are traces of similar usages in England ; but on the whole the doctrine prevailed that Digitized by Microsoft® 240 IDEAS AS TO WILLS AND SUCCESSIONS [chap, vii movables might be freely disposed of by Will, and, even when the claims of the widow continued to be respected, the privileges of the children were obliterated from jurisprudence. We need not hesitate to attribute the change to the in- fluence of Primogeniture. As the Feudal law of land practically disinherited all the children in favour of one, the equal distribution even of those sorts of property which might have been equally divided ceased to be viewed as a duty. Testaments were the principal instruments em- ployed in producing inequaUty, and in this condition of things originated the shade of differ- ence which shows itself between the ancient and the modern conception of a Will. But, though thehberty of bequest, enjoyed through Testaments, was thus an accidental fruit of Feudalism, there is no broader distinction than that which exists between a system of free Testamentary disposition and a system, Uke that of the Feudal land-law, under which property descends compulsorily in prescribed hues of devolution. This truth appears to have been lost sight of by the authors of the French Codes. In the social fabric which they determined to destroy, they saw Primogeniture resting chiefly on Family settlements, but they also perceived that Testaments were frequently employed to give the eldest son precisely the same preference which was reserved to him under the strictest of entails. In order, therefore, to make sure of their work, they not only rendered it impossible to prefer the eldest son to the rest in marriage-arrangements, but they almost expelled Testamentary successionfrom the law,lest it should Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP, viil PRIMOGENITURE 24I be used to defeat their fundamental principle of an equal distribution of property among children at the parent's death. The result is that they have established a system of small perpetual entails which is infinitely nearer akin to the system of feudal Europe than would be a perfect liberty of bequest. The land-law of England, " the Herculaneum of Feudahsm," is certainly much more closely allied to the land-law of the Middle Ages than that of any Continental country, and Wills with us are frequently used to aid or imitate that preference of the eldest son and his line which is a nearly universal feature in marriage settlements of real property. But nevertheless feehng and opinion in this country have been profoundly affected by the practice of Free Testamentary disposition ; and it appears to me that the state of sentiment in a great part of French society, on the subject of the conserva- tion of property in famihes, is much liker that which prevailed throughout Europe two or three centuries ago than are the current opinions of Enghshmen. The mention of Primogeniture introduces one of the most difficult problems of historical juris- prudence. Though I have not paused to explain my expressions, it may have been noticed that I have frequently spoken of a number of " co-heirs " as placed by the Roman Law of Succession on the same footing with a single Heir. In point of fact, we know of no period of Roman jurisprudence at which the place of the Heir, or Universal Successor, might not have been taken by a group of co-heirs. This group succeeded as a single unit, and the 16 Digitized by Microsoft® 242 IDEAS AS TO WILLS AND SUCCESSIONS [chap, vii assets were afterwards divided among them in a separate legal proceeding. When the Succession was ah intestato, and the group consisted of the children of the deceased, they each took an equal share of the property ; nor, though males had at one time some advantages over females, is there the faintest trace of Primogeniture. The mode of distribution is the same throughout archaic jurisprudence. It certainly seems that, when civil society begins and families cease to hold together through a series of generations, the idea which spontaneously suggests itself is to divide the domain equally among the members of each successive generation, and to reserve no privilege to the eldest son or stock. Some peculiarly significant hints as to the close relation of this phenomenon to primitive thought are furnished by systems yet more archaic than the Roman. Among the Hindoos, the instant a son is bom, he acquires a vested right in his father's property, which cannot be sold without recognition of his joint-ownership. On the son's attaining fuU age^ he can sometimes compel a partition of the estate, even against the consent of the parent ; and, should the parent acquiesce, one son can always have a partition even against the will of the others. On such partition taking place, the father has no advantage over his children, except that he has two of the shares instead of one. The ancient law of the German tribes was exceedingly similar. The allod or domain of the family was the joint property of the father and his sons. It does not, however, appear to have been habitually divided even at the death of the parent, and in the same Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VII] PRIMOGENITURE 243 way the possessions of a Hindoo, however divisible theoretically, are so rarely distributed in fact, that many generations constantly succeed each other without a partition taking place, and thus the Family in India has a perpetual tendency to expand into the Village Community, under conditions which I shall hereafter attempt to elucidate. All this points very clearly to the absolutely equal divi- sion of assets among the male children at death as the practice most usual with society at the period when family dependency is in the first stages of disintegration. Here then emerges the historical difl&culty of Primogeniture. The more clearly we perceive that, when the Feudal institutions were in process of formation, there was no source in the world whence they could derive their elements but the Roman Law of the provincials on the one hand and the archaic customs of the barbarians on the other, the more are we perplexed at first sight by our knowledge that neither Roman nor barbarian was accustomed to give any preference to the eldest son or his line in the succession to property. Primogeniture did not belong to the Customs which the barbarians practised on their first establishment within the Roman Empire. It is known to have had its origin in the benefices or beneficiary gifts of the invading chieftains. These benefices, which were occasionally conferred by the earlier immigrant kings, but were distributed on a great scale by Charlemagne, were grants of Roman provincial land to be holden by the beneficiary on condition of miUtary service. The allodial proprietors do not seem to have followed Digitized by Microsoft® 244 IDEAS AS TO WILLS AND SUCCESSIONS [chap, vii their sovereign on distant or difficult enterprises, and all the grander expeditions of the Prankish chiefs and of Charlemagne were accomplished with forces composed of soldiers either personally de- pendent on the royal house or compelled to serve it by the tenure of their land. The benefices, however, were not at first in any sense hereditary. They were held at the pleasure of the grantor, or at most for the fife of the grantee ; but still, from the very outset, no effort seems to have been spared by the beneficiaries to enlarge the tenure, and to continue their lands in their family after death. Through the feebleness of Charlemagne's successors, these attempts were universally suc- cessful, and the Benefice gradually transformed itself into the hereditary Fief. But, though the fiefs were hereditary, they did not necessarily descend to the eldest son. The rules of succession which they followed were entirely determined by the terms agreed upon between the grantor and the beneficiary, or imposed by one of them on the weakness of the other. The original tenures were therefore extremely various ; not indeed so capriciously various as is sometimes asserted, for all which have hitherto been described present some combination of the modes of succession familiar to Romans and to barbarians, but stiU exceedingly miscellaneous. In some of them the eldest son and his stock undoubtedly succeeded to the fief before the others, but such successions, so far from being universal, do not even appear to have been general. Precisely the same phenomena recur during that more recent transmutation of European society which entirely substituted the Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VII] ALLODS AND FIEFS 245 feudal form of property for the domainia (or Roman) and the allodial (or German). The allods were wholly absorbed by the fiefs. The greater allodial proprietors transformed themselves into feudal lords by conditional ahenations of portions of their land to dependants ; the smaller sought an escape from the oppressions of that terrible time by surrendering their property to some powerful chieftain, and receiving it back at his hands on condition of service in his wars. Mean- time, that vast mass of the population of Western Europe whose condition was servile or semi- servile — the Roman and German personal slaves, the Roman coloni and the German lidi — were concurrently absorbed by the feudal organisation, a few of them assuming a menial relation to the lords, but the greater part receiving lands on terms which in those centuries were considered degrading. The tenures created during this era of universal infeudation were as various as the conditions which the tenants made with their new chiefs or were forced to accept from them. As in the case of the benefices, the succession to some, but by no means all, of the estates followed the rule of Primogeniture. No sooner, however, has the feudal system prevailed throughout the West, than it becomes evident that Primogeniture has some great advantage over every other mode of succession. It spread over Europe with remark- able rapidity, the principal instrument of diffusion being Family Settlements, the Pactes de Famille of France and Haus-Gesetze of Germany, which universally stipulated that lands held by knightly service should descend to the eldest son. Ulti- Digitized by Microsoft® 246 IDEAS AS TO WILLS AND SUCCESSIONS [chap, tii mately the law resigned itself to follow inveterate practice, and we find that in all the bodies of Customary Law, which were gradually built up, the eldest son and stock are preferred in the suc- cession to estates of which the tenure is free and miUtary. As to lands held by servile tenures (and originally aU teniures were servile which bound the tenant to pay money or bestow manual labour), the system of succession prescribed by custom differed greatly in different countries and different provinces. The more general rule was that such lands were divided equally at death among all the children, but still in some instances the eldest son was preferred, in some the youngest. But Primogeniture usually governed the inherit- ance of that class of estates, in some respects the most important of aU, which were held by tenures that, Uke the English Socage, were of later origin than the rest, and were neither altogether free nor altogether servile. The diffusion of Primogeniture is usually ac- counted for by assigning what are called Feudal reasons for it. It is asserted that the feudal superior had a better security for the military service he required when the fief descended to a single person, instead of being distributed among a number on the decease of the last holder. With- out den5ring that this consideration may partially explain the favour gradually acquired by Primo- geniture, I must point out that Primogeniture became a custom of Europe much more through its popularity with the tenants than through any advantage it conferred on the lords. For its origin, moreover^ the reason given does not account Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP.viij POLITICAL PRIMOGENITURE 247 at all. Nothing in law springs entirely from a sense of convenience. There are always certain ideas existing antecedently on which the sense of convenience works, and of which it can do no more than form some new combination ; and to find these ideas in the present case is exactly the problem. A valuable hint is furnished to us from a quarter fruitful of such indications. Although in India the possessions of a parent are divisible at his death, and may be divisible during his life, ajnong all his male children in equal shares, and though this principle of the equal distribution of property extends to every part of the Hindoo in- stitutions, yet wherever public office or political power devolves at the decease of the last Incum- bent, the succession is nearly universally according to the rules of Primogeniture. Sovereignties descend therefore to the eldest son, and where the affairs of the Village Community, the corporate unit of Hindoo society, are confided to a single manager, it is generally the eldest son who takes up the administration at his parent's death. AH ofl&ces, indeed, in India, tend to become hereditary, and, when their nature permits it, to vest in the eldest member of the oldest stock. Comparing these Indian successions with some of the ruder social organisations which have survived in Europe almost to our own day, the conclusion suggests itself that, when Patriarchal power is not only domestic but political, it is not distributed among all the issue at the parent's death, but is the birthright of the eldest son. The chieftainship of a Highland clan, for example, followed the order Digitized by Microsoft® 248 IDEAS AS TO WILLS AND SUCCESSIONS [chap, vn of Primogeniture. There seems, p truth, to be a form of family dependency still more archaic than any of those which we know from the primitive records of organised civil societies. The Agnatic Union of the kindred in ancient Roman law, and a multitude of similar indications, point to a period at which all the ramifying branches of the family tree held together in one organic whole ; and it is no presumptuous conjecture, that, when the corporation thus formed by the kindred was in itself an independent society, it was governed by the eldest male of the oldest Une. It is true that we have no actual knowledge of any such society. Even in the most elementary communities, family- organisations, as we know them, are at most imferia in imperio. But the position of some of them, of the Celtic clans in particular, was suffi- ciently near independence within historical times to force on us the conviction that they were once separate imperia, and that Primogeniture regulated the succession to the chief taiinship. It is, however, necessary to be on our guard against modern associations with the term of law. We are speaking of a family-connection stiU closer and more stringent than any with which we are made acquainted by Hindoo society or ancient Roman law. If the Roman PaterfamiUas was visible steward of the family possessions, if the Hindoo father is only joint sharer with his sons, still more emphatically must the true patriarchal chieftain be merely the administrator of a common fund. The examples of succession by Primogeniture which were found among the Benefices may, there- fore, have been imitated from a system of family- Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VII] CARLOVINGIAN DECADENCE 249 government known to the invading races, though not in general use. Some ruder tribes may have still practised it, or, what is still more probable, society may have been so slightly removed from its more archaic condition that the minds of some men spontaneously recurred to it, when they were called upon to settle the rules of inheritance for a new form of property. But there is still the question. Why did Primogeniture gradually super- sede every other principle of succession ? The answer, I think, is, that European society de- cidedly retrogaded during the dissolution of the Carlovingian empire. It sank a point or two back even from the miserably low degree which it had marked during the earlier barbarian monarchies. The great characteristic of the period was the feebleness, or rather the abeyance, of kingly and therefore of civil authority ; and hence it seems as if, civil society no longer cohering, men univer- sally flung themselves back on a social organisa- tion older than the beginnings of civil communities. The lord with his vassals, during the ninth and tenth centuries, may be considered as a patriarchal household, recruited, not as in the primitive times by Adoption, but by Infeudation ; and to such a confederacy, succession by Primogeniture was a source of strength and durabihty. So long as the land was kept together on which the entire organisation rested, it was powerful for defence and attack ; to divide the land was to divide the little society, and voluntarily to invite aggression in an era of universal violence. We may be perfectly certain that into this preference for Primogeniture there entered no idea of disin- Digitized by Microsoft® 250 IDEAS AS TO WILLS AND SUCCESSIONS [chap, vii heriting the bulk of the children in favour of one. Everybody would have suffered by the division of the fief. Everybody was a gainer by its consolidation. The Family grew stronger by the concentration of power in the same hands ; nor is it hkely that the lord who was invested with the inheritance had any advantage over his brethren and kinsfolk in occupations, interests, or indul- gences. It would be a singular anachronism to estimate the privileges succeeded to by the heir of a fief, by the situation in which the eldest son is placed under an EngUsh strict settlement. I have said that I regard the early feudal con- federacies as descended from an archaic form of the Family, and as weeiring a strong resemblance to it. But then in the ancient world, and in the societies which have not passed through the cru- cible of feudalism, the Primogeniture which seems to have prevailed never transformed itself into the Primogeniture of the later feudal Europe. When the group of kinsmen ceased to be governed through a series of generations by a hereditary chief, the domain which had been managed for all appears to have been equally divided among all. Why did this not occur in the feudal world ? If during the confusions of the first feudal period the eldest son held the land for the behoof of the whole family, why was it that when feudal Europe had consoUdated itself, and regular communities were again estabUshed, the whole family did not resume that capacity for equal inheritance which had belonged to Roman and German alike ? The key which unlocks this difi&culty has rarely been seized by the writers who occupy themselves in Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP, viil PATRIARCH BECOMES OWNER 25I tracing the genealogy of Feudalism. They per- ceive the materials of the feudal institutions, but they miss the cement. The ideas and social forms which contributed to the formation of the system were unquestionably barbarian and archaic, but as soon as Courts and lawyers were called in to interpret and define it, the principles of interpre- tation which they applied to it were those of the latest Roman jurisprudence, and were therefore excessively refined and matured. In a patriarch- ally governed society, the eldest son may succeed to. the government of the Agnatic group, and to the absolute disposal of its property. But he is not therefore a true proprietor.. He has correla- tive duties not involved in the conception of proprietorship, but quite undefined and quite incapable of definition. The later Roman juris- prudence, however, like our own law, looked upon uncontrolled power over property as equivalent to ownership, and did not, and, in fact, could not, take notice of liabilities of such a kind, that the very conception of them belonged to a period anterior to regular law. The contact of the re- fined and the barbarous notion had inevitably for its effect the conversion of the eldest son into legal proprietor of the inheritance. The clerical and secular lawyers so defined his position from the first ; but it was only by insensible degrees that the younger brother, from participating on equal terms in all the dangers and enjo37ments of his kinsman, sank into the priest, the soldier of fortune, or the hanger-on of the mansion. The legal revolution was identical with that which occurred on a smaller scale, and in quite recent Digitized by Microsoft® 252 IDEAS AS TO WILLS AND SUCCESSIONS [chap, vii times, through the greater part of the Highlands of Scotland. When called in to determine the legal powers of the chieftain over the domains which gave sustenance to the clan, Scottish juris- prudence had long since passed the point at which it could take notice of the vague hmitations on completeness of dominion imposed by the claims of the clansmen, and it was inevitable therefore that it should convert the patrimony of many into the estate of one. For the sake of simplicity, I have called the mode of succession Primogeniture whenever a single son or descendant succeeds to the authority over a household or society. It is remarkable, however, that in the few very ancient examples which remain to us of this sort of succession, it is not always the eldest son, in the sense familiar to us, who takes up the representation. The form of Primogeniture which has spread over Western Europe has also been perpetuated among the Hindoos, and there is every reason to believe that it is the normal form. Under it, not only the eldest son, but the eldest Hne is always preferred. If the eldest son fails, his eldest son has precedence not only over brothers but over uncles ; and, if he too fails, the same rule is followed in the next generation. But when the succession is not merely to civil but to political power, a difficulty may present itself which wiU appear of greater magnitude according as the cohesion of society is less perfect. The chieftain who last exercised authority may have outlived his eldest son, and the grandson who is primarily entitled to succeed may be too young and imma- Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VII] FORMS OF PRIMOGENITURE 253 ture to undertake the actual guidance of the community, and the administration of its affairs. In such an event, the expedient which suggests itself to the more settled societies is to place the ififant heir under guardianship tiU he reaches the age of fitness for government. The guardian- ship is generally that of the male Agnates ; but it is remarkable that the contingency supposed is one of the rare cases in which ancient societies have consented to the exercise of power by women, doubtless out of respect to the overshadowing claims of the mother. In India, the widow of a Hindoo sovereign governs in the name of her infant son, and we cannot but remember that the custom regulating succession to the throne of France — which, whatever be its origin, is doubtless of the highest antiquity — preferred the queen- mother to aU other claimants for the Regency, at the same time that it rigorously excluded all females from the throne. There is, however, another mode of obviating the inconvenience attending the devolution of sovereignty on an infant heir, and it is one which would doubtless occur spontaneously to rudely organised com- munities. This is to set aside the infant heir altogether, and confer the chieftainship on the eldest surviving male of the first generation. The Celtic clan-associations, among the many pheno- mena which they preserved of an age in which civil and pohtical society were not yet even rudimentarily separated, have brought down this rule of succession to historical times. With them, it seems to have existed in the form of a positive canon, that, faiUng the eldest son, his next brother Digitized by Microsoft® 254 IDEAS AS TO WILLS AND SUCCESSIONS [chap, yii succeeds in priority to all grandsons, whatever be their age at the moment when the sovereignty devolves. Some writers have explained the prin- ciple by assuming that the Celtic customs took the last chieftain as a sort of root or stock, and then gave the succession to the descendant who should be least remote from him ; the uncle thus being preferred to the grandson as being nearer to the common root. No objection can be taken to this statement if it be merely intended as a description of the system of succession ; but it would be a serious error to conceive the men who first adopted the rule as applpng a course of reasoning which evidently dates from the time when feudal schemes of succession began to be debated among lawyers. The true origin of the preference of the uncle to the grandson is doubtless a simple calculation on the part of rude men in a rude society that it is better to be governed by a grown chieftain than by a child, and that the younger son is more hkely to have come to maturity than any of the eldest son's descen- dants. At the same time, we have some evidence that the form of Primogeniture with which we are best acquainted is the primary form, in the tradition that the assent of the clan was asked when an infant heir was passed over in favour of his uncle. There is a tolerably well authenti- cated instance of this ceremony in the annals of the Scottish Macdonalds ; and Irish Celtic antiquities, as interpreted by recent inquirers, are said to disclose many traces of similar prac- tices. The substitution by means of election, of a " worthier " Agnatic relative for an elder Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VII] MAHOMETAN RULE 255 is not unknown, too, in the system of the Indian Village Communities. Under Mahometan law, which has probably- preserved an ancient Arabian custom, inheritances of property are divided equally among sons, the daughters taking a half share ; but if any of the children die before the division of the inheritance, leaving issue behind, these grandchildren are entirely excluded by their uncles and aunts. Consistently with this principle, the succession, when poUtical authority devolves, is according to the form of Primogeniture which appears to have obtained among the Celtic societies. In the two great Mahometan famiUes of the West, the rule is believed to be, that the uncle succeeds to the throne in preference to the nephew, though the latter be the son of an elder brother ; but though this rule has been followed quite recently both in Egypt and in Turkey, I am informed that there has always been some doubt as to its governing the devolution of the Turkish sove- reignty. The policy of the Sultans has in fact generally prevented cases for its application from occurring, and it is possible that their wholesale massacres of their younger brothers may have been perpetrated quite as much in the interest of their children as for the sake of making away with dangerous competitors for the throne. It is evident, however, that in polygamous societies the form of Primogeniture will always tend to vary. Many considerations may constitute a claim on the succession, the rank of the mother, for example, or her degree in the affections of the father. Accordingly, some of the Indian Digitized by Microsoft® 256 NOTES [CHAP. VII Mahometan sovereigns, without pretending to any distinct testamentary power, claim the right of nominating the son who is to succeed. The blessing mentioned in the Scriptural history of Isaac and his sons has sometimes been spoken of as a wiU, but it seems rather to have been a mode of naming an eldest son. NOTE N PRIMOGENITURE Much has been written in recent years about the origins oi medieval jurisdiction and land tenure, and the peculiar complication of tenure with personal lordship and jurisdiction which we call feudalism ; we mention, almost at random, the names of Brunner, Waitz, Fustel de Coulanges, Flach, Luchaire ; but there is nothing to throw doubt on the general soundness of the luminous sketch given in this chapter. Maine returns to the subject in the latter part of ch. viii. At the end of that chapter an opinion is adopted, it seems from Kemble, that " some shade of servile debasement " attached to a Germanic king's or chieftain's personal companions. I have never been able to discover Kemble' s authority for this supposition, or to meet with any other acceptance of it. See, contra, Konrad Maurer in " Kritische tjberschau," ii. 391. Further observations on Primogeniture by Maine himself will be found in "The Early History of Institutions," pp. 124, 198-205. We may add to the brief mention of " parage " at p. 205 that the " paragium " of the Norman custumals has an important part in the Anglo-Norman nomenclature of Domesday Book. Groups of co-heirs holding " in paragio," and represented, for the purposes of the service due to their lord, by one of them who is sometimes called the senior, are common in several counties (Maitland, "Domesday Book and Beyond," p. 145; Pollock and Maitland, '■ H.E.L." ii. 263-4, 276 ; Pollock in Eng. Hist. Rev. 1896, xi. 228, note 65). This arrangement is a strong illustration of the practical convenience of primogeniture for the lord when feudal service was really military service. Maine's view that primogeniture originally had an official character seems to be thoroughly accepted; it would probably be found, if we had all the facts, that the occasional examples of primogeniture in servile or inferior tenures are to be explained by the tenement having been attached to some manorial or communal office. It would seem that, whether for reasons of Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VII] NOTES 257 convenience or because men liked to imitate the fashion of their lords, the general introduction of primogeniture in England was to some extent a popular movement. In 1255 the burgesses of Leicester alleged that they were being ruined by partible tenures, and procured a charter from their lord, Simon de Montfort, which Henry III. shortly afterwards confirmed, to change the course of descent to primogeniture (" Records of the Borough of Leicester," ed. Bateson, Nos. xxiii. xxiv., the latter indorsed "carta quod hereditas sit ad communem legem "). On the whole subject Mr. Evelyn Cecil's book " Primogeniture : A Short History of its Development in Various Countries, audits Practical EfEects," Lond. 1895, may be studied with advantage. 17 Digitized by Microsoft® CHAPTER VIII THE EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY The Roman Institutional Treatises, after giving their definition of the various forms and modifi- cations of ownership, proceed to discuss the Natural Modes of Acquiring Property. Those who are unfamiliar with the history of juris- prudence are not hkely to look upon these " natural modes " of acquisition as possessing, at first sight, either much speculative or much practical interest. The wild animal which is snared or kiUed by the hunter, the soil which is added to our field by the imperceptible deposits of a river, the tree which strikes its roots into our ground, are each said by the Roman lawyers to be acquired by us naturally. The older jurisconsults had doubtless observed that such acquisitions were universally sanctioned by the usages of the little societies around them, and thus the lawyers of a later age, finding them classed in the ancient Jus Gentium, and perceiving them to be of the simplest de- scription, allotted them a place among the ordi- nances of Nature. The dignity with which they were invested has gone on increasing in modern times till it is quite out of proportion to their original importance. Theory has made them its favourite food, and has enabled them to exercise the most serious influence on practice. Digitized by Microsoft® <=«*'■• »'"] OCCUPANCY 259 It will be necessary for us to attend to one only among these " natural modes of acquisition," Occupatio or Occupancy. Occupancy is the ad- visedly taking possession of that which at the moment is the property of no man^ with the view (adds the technical definition) of acquiring pro- perty in it for yourself. The objects which the Roman lawyers called res nullius — things which have not or have never had an owner — can only be ascertained by enumerating them. Among things which never had an owner are wild animals, fishes, wild fowl, jewels disinterred for the first time, and lands newly discovered or never before cultivated. Among things which have not an owner are movables which have been abandoned, lands which have been deserted, and (an anoma- lous but most formidable item) the property of an enemy. In all these objects the full rights of dominion were acquired by the Occupant, who first took possession of them with the intention of keeping them as his own — an intention which, in certain cases, had to be manifested by specific acts. It is not difficult, I think, to understand the universaHty which caused the practice of Occupancy to be placed by one generation of Roman lawyers in the Law common to all Nations, and the simpUcity which occasioned its being attributed by another to the Law of Nature. But for its fortunes in modern legal history we are less prepared by dt priori considerations. The Roman principle of Occupancy, and the rules into which the jurisconsults expanded it, are the source of all modem International Law on the subject of Capture in War and of the acquisition Digitized by Microsoft® 260 EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [chap, viii of sovereign rights in newly discovered countries. They have also supphed a theory of the Origin of Property, which is at once the popular theory, and the theory which, in one form or another, is acquiesced in by the great majority of specula- tive jurists. I have said that the Roman principle of Occupancy has determined the tenor of that chapter of International Law which is concerned with Capture in War. The Law of Warhke Capture derives its rules from the assumption that communities are remitted to a state of nature by the outbreak of hostiUties, and that, in the artificial natural condition thus produced, the institution of private property falls into abeyance so far as concerns the belligerents. As the later writers on the Law of Nature have always been anxious to maintain that private property was in some sense sanctioned by the system which they were expounding, the hypothesis that an enemy's property is res nullius has seemed to them perverse and shocking, and they are careful to stigmatise it as a mere fiction of jurisprudence. But, as soon as the Law of Nature is traced to its source in the Jus Gentium, we see at once how the goods of an enemy came to be looked upon as nobody's property, and therefore as capable of being acquired by the first occupant. The idea would occur spontaneously to persons prac- tising the ancient forms of Warfare, when victory dissolved the organisation of the conquering army and dismissed the soldiers to indiscriminate plunder. It is probable, however, that originally it was only movable property which was thus Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VIII] enemy's property 261 pennitted to be acquired by the Captor. We know on independent authority that a very different rule prevailed in ancient Italy as to the acquisition of ownership in the soil of a conquered country, and we may therefore suspect that the application of the principle of occupancy to land (always a matter of difficulty) dates from the period when the Jus Gentium was becoming the Code of Nature, and that it is the result of a generalisation effected by the jurisconsults of the golden age. Their dogmas on the point are preserved in the Pandects of Justinian, and amount to an unqualified assertion that enemy's property of every sort is res nullius to the other belligerent, and that Occupancy, by which the Captor makes it his own, is an institution of Natural Law. The rules which International jurisprudence derives from these positions have sometimes been stigmatised as needlessly indulgent to the ferocity and cupidity of combatants, but the charge has been made, I think, by persons who are unacquainted with the history of wars, and who are consequently ignorant how great an exploit it is to command obedience for a rule of any kind. The Roman principle of Occupancy, when it was admitted into the modern law of Capture in War, drew with it a number of sub- ordinate canons, limiting and giving precision to its operation, and if the contests which have been waged since the treatise of Grotius became an authority, are compared with those of an earlier date, it will be seen that, as soon as the Roman maxims were received. Warfare instantly assumed a more tolerable complexion. If the Digitized by Microsoft® 262 EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [chap, viii Roman law of Occupancy is to be taxed with having had pernicious influence on any part of the modern Law of Nations, there is another chapter in it which may be said, with some reason, to have been injuriously affected. In applying to the discovery of new countries the same prin- ciples which the Romans had applied to the finding of a jewel, the Pubhcists forced into their service a doctrine altogether unequal to the task expected from it. Elevated into extreme import- ance by the discoveries of the great navigators of the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries, it raised more disputes than it solved. The greatest uncertainty w£is very shortly found to exist on the very two points on which certainty was most required, the extent of the territory which was acquired for his sovereign by the discoverer, and the nature of the acts which were necessary to complete the adprehensio or assumption of sovereign pos- session. Moreover, the principle itself, conferring as it did such enormous advantages as the consequence of a piece of good luck, was instinc- tively mutinied against by some of the most adventurous nations in Europe, the Dutch, the Enghsh, and the Portuguese. Our own country- men, without expressly den5n.ng the rule of Inter- national Law, never did, in practice, admit the claim of the Spaniards to engross the whole of America south of the Gulf of Mexico, or that of the King of France to monopolise the valleys of the Ohio and the Mississippi. From the accession of Ehzabeth to the accession of Charles the Second, it cannot be said that there was at any time thorough peace in the American waters. Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP, vni] NATURAL OCCUPANCY 263 and the encroachments of the New England Colonists on the territory of the French King continued for almost a century longer. Bentham was so struck with the confusion attending the application of the legal principle, that he went out of his way to eulogise the famous Bull of Pope Alexander the Sixth, dividing the undis- covered countries of the world between the Spaniards and Portuguese by a line drawn one himdred leagues West of the Azores ; and, grotesque as his praises may appear at first sight, it may be doubted whether the arrangement of Pope Alexander is absurder in principle than the rule of PubUc Law which gave half a continent to the monarch whose servants had fulfilled the conditions required by Roman jurisprudence for the acquisition of property in a valuable object which could be covered by the hand. To all who pursue the inquiries which are the subject of this volume. Occupancy is pre-eminently interesting on the score of the service it has been made to perform for speculative jurisprudence, in furnishing a supposed explanation of the origin of private property. It was once universally believed that the proceeding implied in Occupancy was identical with the process by which the earth and its fruits, which were at first in common, became the allowed property of individuals. The course of thought which led to this assumption is not difficult to understand, if we seize the shade of difference which separates the ancient from the modern conception of Natural Law. The Roman lawyers had laid down that Occupancy was one of the Natural modes of acquiring pro- Digitized by Microsoft® 264 EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [chap, vwi perty, and they undoubtedly believed that, were mankind Uving under the institutions of Nature, Occupancy would be one of their practices. How far they persuaded themselves that such a con- dition of the race had ever existed, is a point, as I have already stated, which their language leaves in much uncertainty ; but they certainly do seem to have made the conjecture, which has at aU times possessed much plausibihty, that the institution of property was not so old as the existence of mankind. Modern jurisprudence, accepting all their dogmas without reservation, went far beyond them in the eager curiosity with which it dwelt on the supposed state of Nature. Since then it had received the position that the earth and its fruits were once res nullius, and since its pecuhar view of Nature led it to assume without hesitation that the human race had actually practised the Occupancy of res nullius long before the organisation of civil societies, the inference immediately suggested itself that Occupancy was the process by which the " no man's goods " of the primitive world became the private property of individuals in the world of history. It would be wearisome to enumerate the jurists who have subscribed to this theory in one shape or another, and it is the less necessary to attempt it because Blackstone, who is always a faithful index of the average opinions of his day, has summed them up in his 2nd book and 1st chapter. " The earth," he writes, " and all things therein were the general property of mankind from the immediate gift of the Creator. Not that the Digitized by Microsoft® cHAp.viH] blackstone's theory 265 communion of goods seems ever to have been applicable, even in the earliest ages, to aught but the substance of the thing ; nor could be extended to the use of it. For, by the law of nature and reason, he who first began to use it acquired therein a kind of transient property that lasted so long as he was using it, and no longer ; or to speak with greater precision, the right of possession continued for the same time only that the act of pos- session lasted. Thus the ground was in common, and no part was the permanent property of any man in particular ; yet whoever was in the occupation of any determined spot of it, for rest, for shade, or the like, acquired for the time a sort of ownership, from which it would have been unjust and contrary to the law of nature to have driven him by force, but the instant that he quitted the use or occupation of it, another might seize it without injustice." He then proceeds to argue that " when mankind increased in number, it became necessary to entertain conceptions of more permanent dominion, and to appropriate to in- dividuals not the immediate use only, but the very substance of the thing to be used." Some ambiguities of expression in this passage lead to the suspicion that Blackstone did not quite understand the meaning of the proposition which he found in his authorities, that property in the earth's surface was first acquired, under the law of Nature, by the occupant ; but the limitation which designedly or through misappre- hension he has imposed on the theory brings it into a form which it has not infrequently assumed. Many writers more famous than Blackstone for Digitized by Microsoft® 266 EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [chap, viii precision of language have laid down that, in the beginning of things, Occupancy hrst gave a right against the worid to an exclusive but temporary enjoyment, and that afterwards this right, while it remained exclusive, became perpetual. Their object in so stating their theory was to reconcile the doctrine that in the state of Nature res nullius became property through Occupancy, with the inference which they drew from the Scriptural history that the Patriarchs did not at first per- manently appropriate the soil which had been grazed over by their flocks and herds. The only criticism which could be directly applied to the theory of Blackstone would consist in inquiring whether the circumstances which make up his picture of a primitive society are more or less probable than other incidents which could be imagined with equal readiness. Pur- suing this method of examination, we might fairly ask whether the man who had occupied (Blackstone evidently uses this word with its ordinary Enghsh meaning) a particular spot of ground for rest or shade would be permitted to retain it without disturbance. The chances surely are that his right to possession would be exactly co-extensive with his power to keep it, and that he would be con- stantly liable to disturbance by the first comer who coveted the spot and thought himself strong enough to drive away the possessor. But the truth is that aU such cavil at these positions is perfectly idle from the very baselessness of the positions themselves. What mankind did in the primitive state may not be a hopeless subject of inquiry, but of their motives for doing it it is Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. Till] APHORISM OF SAVIGNY 267 impossible to know anything. These sketches of the phght of human beings in the first ages of the world are effected by first supposing mankind to be divested of a great part of the circumstances by which they are now surrounded, and by then assuming that, in the condition thus imagined, they would preserve the same sentiments and prejudices by which they are now actuated, — although, in fact, these sentiments may have been created and engendered by those very circum- stances of which, by the hypothesis, they are to be stripped. There is an aphorism of Savigny which has been sometimes thought to countenance a view of the origin of property somewhat similar to the theories epitomised by Blackstone. The great German jurist has laid down that all property is founded on Adverse Possession ripened by Pre- scription. It is only with respect to Roman law that Savigny makes this statement, and before it can fully be appreciated much labour must be expended in explaining and defining the expres- sions employed. His meaning wiU, however, be indicated with sufficient accuracy if we consider him to assert that, how far soever we carry our inquiry into the ideas of property received among the Romans, however closely we approach in tracing them to the infancy of law, we can get no farther than a conception of ownership involving the three elements in the canon — Possession, Ad- verseness of Possession, that is, a holding not permissive or subordinate, but exclusive against the world, and Prescription, or a period of time during which the Adverse Possession has unin- Digitized by Microsoft® 268 EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [chap, viii terruptedly continued. It is exceedingly probable that this maxim might be enunciated with more generality than was allowed to it by its author, and that no sound or safe conclusion can be looked for from investigations into any system of laws which are pushed farther back than the point at which these combined ideas constitute the notion of proprietary right. Meantime, so far from bearing out the popular theory of the origin of property, Savigny's canon is particularly valuable as directing our attention to its weakest point. In the view of Blackstone and those whom he follows, it was the mode of assuming the exclusive enjoyment which mysteriously affected the minds of the fathers of our race. But the mystery does not reside here. It is not wonderful that property began in adverse possession. It is not surprising that the first proprietor should have been the strong man armed who kept his goods in peace. But why it was that lapse of time created a senti- ment of respect for his possession — which is the exact source of the universal reverence of mankind for that which has for a long period de facto existed — are questions really deserving the profoundest examination, but lying far beyond the boundary of our present inquiries. Before pointing out the quarter in which we may hope to glean some information, scanty and uncertain at best, concerning the early history of proprietary right, I venture to state my opinion that the popular impression in reference to the part played by Occupancy in the first stages of civiUsation directly reverses the truth. Occupancy is the advised assumption of physical possession ; Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. Till] PRESUMPTION OF OWNERSHIP 269 and the notion that an act of this description confers a title to " res nuUius," so far from being characteristic of very early societies, is in all probability the growth of a refined jurisprudence and of a settled condition of the laws. It is only when the rights of property have gained a sanction from long practical inviolabiUty, and when the vast majority of the objects of enjoyment have been subjected to private ownership, that mere possession is allowed to invest the first possessor with dominion over commodities in which no prior proprietorship has been asserted. The sentiment in which this doctrine originated is absolutely irreconcilable with that infrequency and uncer- tainty of proprietary rights which distinguish the beginnings of civilisation. Its true basis seems to be, not an instinctive bias towards the institution of Property, but a presumption, arising out of the long continuance of that institution, that everything ought to have an owner. When possession is taken of a " res nullius," that is, of an object which is not, or has never been, reduced to dominion, the possessor is permitted to become proprietor from a feeling that aU valuable things are naturally the subjects of an exclusive enjoyment, and that in the given case there is no one to invest with the right of property except the Occupant. The Occupant, in short, becomes the owner, because aU things are presumed to be somebody's property and because no one can be pointed out as having a better right than he to the proprietorship of this particular thing. Even were there no other objection to the descriptions of mankind in their natural state Digitized by Microsoft® 270 EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [chap, viii which we have been discussing, there is one par- ticular in which they are fatally at variance with the authentic evidence possessed by us. It will be observed, that the acts and motives which these theories suppose are the acts and motives of Individuals. It is each Individual who for himself subscribes the Social Compact. It is some shifting sandbank in which the grains are Indi- vidual men, that according to the theory of Hobbes is hardened into the social rock by the wholesome discipline of force. It is an Individual who, in the picture drawn by Blackstone, " is in the occu- pation of a determined spot of ground for rest, for shade, or the Uke." The vice is one which necessarily afflicts all the theories descended from the Natural Law of the Romans, which differed principally from their Civil Law in the account which it took of Individuals, and which has ren- dered precisely its greatest service to civiUsation in enfranchising the individual from the authority of archaic society. But Ancient Law, it must again be repeated, knows next to nothing of Indi- viduals. It is concerned not with Individuals, but with FamiUes, not with single human beings, but groups. Even when the law of the State has suc- ceeded in penetrating the small circles of kindred into which it had originally no means of penetrat- ing, the view it takes of Individuals is curiously different from that taken by jurisprudence in its maturest stage. The life of each citizen is not regarded as limited by birth and death ; it is but a continuation of the existence of his forefathers, and it will be prolonged in the existence of his descendants. Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VIII] LAW OF PERSONS AND THINGS 27 1 The Roman distinction between the Law of Persons and the Law of Things, which though extremely convenient is entirely artificial, has evidently done much to divert inquiry on the subject before us from the true direction. The lessons learned in discussing the Jus Personarum have been forgotten where the Jus Rerum is reached, and Property, Contract, and DeUct, have been considered as if no hints concerning their original nature were to be gained from the facts ascertained respecting the original condition of Persons. The futiUty of this method would be manifest if a system of pure archaic law could be brought before us, and if the experiment could be tried of applying to it the Roman classifications. It would soon be seen that the separation of the Law of Persons from that of Things has no meaning in the infancy of the law, that the rules belonging to the two departments are inextricably mingled together, and that the distinctions of the later jurists are appropriate only to the later jurispru- dence. From what has been said in the earlier portions of this treatise, it will be gathered that there is a strong a priori improbability of our obtaining any clue to the early history of property, if we confine our notice to the proprietary rights of individuals. It is more than hkely that joint- ownership, and not separate ownership, is the really archaic institution, and that the forms of property which will afford us instruction wiU be those which are associated with the rights of families and of groups of kindred. The Roman jurisprudence will not here assist in enhghtening us, for it is exactly the Roman jurisprudence which. Digitized by Microsoft® 272 EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [chap, tiii transformed by the theory of Natural Law, has bequeathed to the moderns the impression that individual ownership is the normal state of pro- prietary right, and that ownership in common by groups of men is only the exception to a general rule. There is, however, one community which will always be carefully examined by the inquirer who is in quest of any lost institution of primeval society. How far soever any such institution may have undergone change among the branch of the Indo-European family which has been settled for ages in India, it will seldom be found to have entirely cast aside the sheU in which it was origin- ally reared. It happens that, among the Hindoos, we do find a form of ownership which ought at once to rivet our attention from its exactly fitting in with the ideas which our studies in the Law of Persons would lead us to entertain respecting the original condition of property. The Village Com- munity of India is at once an organised patriarchal society and an assemblage of co-proprietors. The personal relations to each other of the men who compose it are indistinguishably confounded with their proprietary rights, and to the attempts of English functionaries to separate the two may be assigned some of the most formidable miscarriages of Anglo-Indian administration. The Village Community is known to be of immense antiquity. In whatever direction research has been pushed into Indian history, general or local, it has always found the Community in existence at the farthest point of its progress. A great number of intelligent and observant writers, most of whom had no theory of any sort to support concerning its nature and Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP, vni] COMMUNITY AND PARTITION 273 origin, agree in considering it the least destructible institution of a society which never willingly sur- renders any one of its usages to innovation. Conquests and revolutions seem to have swept over it without disturbing or displacing it, and the most beneficent systems of government in India have always been those which have recog- nised it as the basis of administration. The mature Roman law, and modern jurispru- dence following in its wake, look upon co-ownership as an exceptional and momentary condition of the rights of property. This view is clearly indicated in the maxim which obtains universally in Western Europe, Nemo in communione potest invitus detineri (" No one can be kept in co-proprietorship against his wiU "). But in India this order of ideas is reversed, and it may be said that separate proprietorship is always on its way to become proprietorship in common. The process has been adverted to already. As soon as a son is born, he acquires a vested interest in his father's substance, and on attaining years of discretion he is even, in certain contingencies, permitted by the letter of the law to call for a partition of the family estate. As a fact, however, a division rarely takes place even at the death of the father, and the property constantly remains undivided for several genera- tions, though every member of every generation has a legal right to an undivided share in it. The domain thus held in common is sometimes administered by an elected manager, but more generally, and in some provinces always, it is managed by the eldest agnate, by the eldest re- presentative of the eldest line of the stock. Such 18 Digitized by Microsoft® 274 EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [cmap. viii an assemblage of joint proprietors, a body of kindred holding domain in common, is the simplest form of an Indian Village Community, but the Community is more than a brotherhood of relatives and more than an association of partners. It is an organised society, and besides providing for the management of the common fund, it seldom fails to provide, by a complete staff of function- aries, for internal government, for police, for the administration of justice, and for the apportion- ment of taxes and pubUc duties. The process which I have described as that under which a Village Community is formed, may be regarded as typical. Yet it is not to be sup- posed that every Village Community in India drew together in so simple a manner. Although, in the North of India, the archives, as I am informed, almost invariably show that the Community was founded by a single assemblage of blood-relations, they also supply information that men of alien extraction have always, from time to time, been engrafted on it, and a mere purchaser of a share may generally, under certain conditions, be ad- mitted to the brotherhood. In the South of the Peninsula there are often Communities which appear to have sprung not from one but from two or more families : and there are some whose com- position is known to be entirely artificial ; indeed, the occasional aggregation of men of different castes in the same society is fatal to the hypothesis of a common descent. Yet in aU these brother- hoods either the tradition is preserved, or the assumption made, of an original common parent- age. Mountstuart Elphinstone, who writes more Digitized by Microsoft® '=«*''• ^"3 INDIAN VILLAGES 275 particularly of the Southern Village Communities, observes of them (History of India,p.7i, 1905 edn.): "The popular notion is that the Village landholders are a;ll descended from one or more individuals who settled the Village ; and that the only exceptions are formed by persons who have derived their rights by purchase or otherwise from members of the original stock. The supposition is confirmed by the fact that, to this day, there are only single famihes of landholders in small villages and not many in large ones ; but each has branched out into so many members that it is not uncommon for the whole agricultural labour to be done by the landholders, without the aid either of tenants or of labourers. The rights of the landholders are theirs collectively, and, though they almost always have a more or less perfect partition of them, they never have an entire separation. A landholder, for instance, can sell or mortgage his rights ; but he must first have the consent of the Village, and the purchaser steps exactly into his place and takes up all his obligations. If a family becomes extinct, its share returns to the common stock." Some considerations which have been offered in the fifth chapter of this volume will assist the reader, I trust, in appreciating the significance of Elphinstone's language. No institution of the primitive world is likely to have been preserved to our day, unless it has acquired an elasticity foreign to its original nature through some vivify- ing legal fiction. The Village Community then is not necessarily an assemblage of blood-relations, but it is either such an assemblage or a body of co-proprietors formed on the model of an asso- Digitized by Microsoft® 276 EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [chap, vin elation of kinsmen. The type with which it should be compared is evidently not the Roman Family, but the Roman Gens or House. The Gens was also a group on the model of the family ; it was the family extended by a variety of fictions of which the exact nature was lost in antiquity. In historical times, its leading characteristics were the very two which Elphinstone remarks in the Village Community. There was always the assumption of a common origin, an assumption sometimes notoriously at variance with fact : and, to repeat the historian's words, " if a family became extinct, its share returned to the common stock." In old Roman law, unclaimed inherit- ances escheated to the Gentiles. It is further suspected by all who have examined their history that the Communities, hke the Gentes, have been very generally adulterated by the admission of strangers, but the exact mode of absorption cannot now be ascertained. At present, they are recruited, as Elphinstone tells us, by the admission of purchasers, with the consent of the brotherhood. The acquisition of the adopted member is, however, of the nature of a universal succession ; together with the share he has bought, he succeeds to the liabihties which the vendor had incurred towards the aggregate group. He is an Emptor Familias, and inherits the legal clothing of the person whose place he begins to fiU. The consent of the whole brotherhood re- quired for his admission may remind us of the consent which the Comitia Curiata, the Parliament of that larger brotherhood of self-styled kinsmen, the ancient Roman commonwealth, so strenuously Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP, viii] RUSSIAN VILLAGBS 277 insisted on as essential to the legalisation of an Adoption or the confirmation of a Will. The tokens of an extreme antiquity are dis- coverable in almost every single feature of the Indian Village Communities. We have so many independent reasons for suspecting that the in- fancy of law is distinguished by the prevalence of co-ownership, by the intermixture of personal with proprietary rights, and by the confusion of pubUc with private duties, that we should be justified in deducing many important conclusions from our observation of these proprietary brother- hoods, even if no similarly compounded societies could be detected in any other part of the world. It happens, however, that much earnest curiosity has been very recently attracted to a similar set of phenomena in those parts of Europe which have been most slightly affected by the feudal transformation of property, and which in many important particulars have as close an affinity with the Eastern as with the Western world. The researches of M. de Haxthausen, M. Tengo- borski, and others, have shown us that the Russian villages are not fortuitous assemblages of men, nor are they unions founded on contract ; they are naturally organised communities like those of India. It is true that these villages are always in theory the patrimony of some noble proprietor, and the peasants have within historical times been converted into the predial, and to a great extent into the personal, serfs of the seignior. But the pressure of this superior ownership has never crushed the ancient organisation of the village, and it is probable that the enactment Digitized by Microsoft® 278 EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [chap, viii of the Czar of Russia, who is supposed to have introduced serfdom, was really intended to prevent the peasants from abandoning that co-operation without which the old social order could not long be maintained. In the assumption of an agnatic connection between the villagers, in the blending of personal rights with privileges of ownership, and in a variety of spontaneous pro- visions for internal administration, the Russian village appears to be a nearly exact repetition of the Indian Community ; but there is one im- portant difference which we note with the greatest interest. The co-owners of an Indian village, though their property is blended, have their rights distinct, and this separation of rights is complete and continues indefinitely. The sever- ance of rights is also theoretically complete in a Russian village, but there it is only temporary. After the expiration of a given, but not in all cases of the same, period, separate ownerships are extinguished, the land of the village is thrown into a mass, and then it is redistributed among the families composing the community, according to their number. This repartition having been effected, the rights of families and of individuals are again allowed to branch out into various lines, which they continue to foUow till another period of division comes round. An even more curious variation from this type of ownership occurs in some of those countries which long formed a debatable land between the Turkish Empire and the possessions of the House of Austria. In Servia, in Croatia, and the Austrian Sclavonia, the villages are also brotherhoods of Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VIII] VARIETIES OF THE COMMUNITY 279 persons who are at once co-owners and kinsmen ; but there the internal arrangements of the com- munity differ from those adverted to in the last two examples. The substance of the common property is in this case neither divided in practice nor considered in theory as divisible, but the entire land is cultivated by the combined labour of all the villagers, and the produce is annually distributed among the households, sometimes according to their supposed wants, sometimes according to rules which give to particular persons a fixed share of the usufruct. All these practices are traced by the jurists of the East of Europe to a principle which is asserted to be found in the earhest Sclavonian laws, the principle that the property of famiUes cannot be divided for a perpetuity. The great interest of these phenomena in an inquiry like the present arises from the Ught they throw on the development of distinct proprietary rights inside the groups by which property seems to have been originally held. We have the strongest reason for thinking that property once belonged not to individuals nor even to isolated famihes, but to larger societies composed on the patriarchal model ; but the mode of transition from ancient to modern ownerships, obscure at best, would have been infinitely obscurer if several distinguishable forms of Village Com- munities had not been discovered and examined. It is worth while to attend to the varieties of internal arrangement within the patriarched groups which are, or were till recently, observable among races of Indo-European blood. The chiefs of the Digitized by Microsoft® 28o EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [chap, viii ruder Highland clans used, it is said, to dole out food to the heads of the households under their jurisdiction at the very shortest intervals, and sometimes day by day. A periodical distribution is also made to the Sclavonian villagers of the Austrian and Turkish provinces by the elders of their body, but then it is a distribution once for aU of the total produce of the year. In the Russian villages, however, the substance of the property ceases to be looked upon as indivisible, and separate proprietary claims are allowed freely to grow up, but then the progress of separation is peremptorily arrested after it has continued a certain time. In India, not only is there no indivisibility of the common fund, but separate proprietorship in parts of it may be indefinitely prolonged and may branch out into any number of derivative ownerships, the de facto partition of the stock being, however, checked by inveterate usage, and by the rule against the admission of strangers without the consent of the brotherhood. It is not of course intended to insist that these different forms of the Village Community repre- sent distinct stages in a process of transmutation which has been everywhere accomplished in the same manner. But, though the evidence does not warrant our going so far as this, it renders less presumptuous the conjecture that private pro- perty, in the shape in which we know it, was chiefly formed by the gradual disentanglement of the separate rights of individuals from the blended rights of a community. Our studies in the Law of Persons seemed to show us the Family expanding into the Agnatic group of kinsmen Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VIII] ANCIENT DIFFICULTIES OF ALIENATION 281 . then the Agnatic group dissolving into separate households ; lastly, the household supplanted by the individual ; and it is now suggested that each step in the change corresponds to an analogous alteration in the nature of Ownership. If there be any truth in the suggestion, it is to be observed that it materially affects the problem which theorists on the origin of Property have generally proposed to themselves. The question — perhaps an insoluble one — which they have mostly agitated is, what were the motives which first induced men to respect each other's possessions ? It may still be put, without much hope of finding an answer to it, in the form of an inquiry into the reasons which led one composite group to keep aloof from the domain of another. But, if it be true that far the most important passage in the history of Private Property is its gradual separa- tion from the co-ownership of kinsmen, then the great point of inquiry is identical with that which lies on the threshold of aU historical law — what were the motives which originally prompted men to hold together in the family union ? To such a question, Jurisprudence, unassisted by other sciences, is not competent to give a reply. The fact can only be noted. The undivided state of property in ancient societies is consistent with a pecuhar sharpness of division, which shows itself as soon as any single share is completely separated from the patrimony of the group. This phenomenon springs, doubtless, from the circumstance that the property is supposed to become the domain of a new group, so that any deaUng with it, in Digitized by Microsoft® 282 EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [chap, viii its divided state, is a transaction between two highly complex bodies. I have already compared Ancient Law to Modern International Law, in respect of the size and complexity of the corporate associations, whose rights and duties it settles. As the contracts and conveyances known to ancient law are contracts and conveyances to which not single individuals, but organised com- panies of men, are parties, they are in the highest degree ceremonious ; they require a variety of symbohcal acts and words intended to impress the business on the memory of aU who take part in it ; and they demand the presence of an inordinate number of witnesses. From these peculiarities, and others aUied to them, springs the universally unmalleable character of the ancient forms of property. Sometimes the patri- mony of the family is absolutely inalienable, as was the case with the Sclavonians, and still oftener, though alienations may not be entirely illegiti- mate, they are virtually impracticable, as among most of the Germanic tribes, from the necessity of having the consent of a large number of persons to the transfer. Where these impediments do not exist, or can be surmounted, the act of con- veyance itself is generally burdened with a perfect load of ceremony, in which not one iota can be safely neglected. Ancient law uniformly refuses to dispense with a single gesture, however grotesque ; with a single syllable, however its meaning may have been forgotten ; with a single witness, how- ever superfluous may be his testimony. The entire solemnities must be scrupulously completed by persons legally entitled to take part in it, Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VIII] CLASSIFICATIONS OF PROPERTY 283 or else the conveyance is null, and the seller is re-established in the rights of which he had vainly attempted to divest himself. These various obstacles to the free circulation of the objects of use and enjoyment, begin of course to make themselves felt as soon as society has acquired even a slight degree of activity, and the expedients by which advancing communities endeavour to overcome them form the staple of the history of Property. Of such expedients there is one which takes precedence of the rest from its antiquity and universaUty. The idea seems to have, spontaneously suggested itself to a great number of early societies, to classify property into kinds. One kind or sort of property is placed on a lower footing of dignity than the others, but at the same time is relieved from the fetters which antiquity has imposed on them. Subsequently, the superior convenience of the rules governing the transfer and descent of the lower order of property becomes generally recognised, and by a gradual course of innovation the plasticity of the less dignified class of valuable objects is communi- cated to the classes which stand conventionally higher. The history of Roman Property Law is the history of the assimilation of Res Mancipi to Res Nee Mancipi. The history of Property on the European continent is the history of the subver- sion of the feudalised law of land by the Romanised law of movables ; and though the history of ownership in England is not nearly completed, it is visibly the law of personalty which threatens to absorb and annihilate the law of realty. The only natural classification of the objects Digitized by Microsoft® 284 EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [chap, nii of enjoyment, the only classification which corre- sponds with an essential difference in the subject- matter, is that which divides them into Movables and Immovables. FamiUar as is this classifica- tion to jurisprudence, it was very slowly developed by Roman law, from which we inherit it, and was only finally adopted by it in its latest stage. The classifications of Ancient Law have sometimes a superficial resemblance to this. They occasionally divide property into categories, and place im- movables in one of them ; but then it is found that they either class along with immovables a number of objects which have no sort of relation with them, or else divorce them from various rights to which they have a close affinity. Thus, the Res Mancipi of Roman Law included not only land but slaves, horses, and oxen. Scottish law ranks with land a certain class of securities, and Hindoo law associates it with slaves. English law, on the other hand, parts leases of land for years from other interests in the soil, and joins them to personalty under the name of chattels real. Moreover, the classifications of Ancient Law are classifications implying superiority and inferiority ; while the distinction between movables and im- movables, so long at least as it was confined to Roman jurisprudence, carried with it no suggestion whatever of a difference in dignity. The Res Mancipi, however, did certainly at first enjoy a precedence over the Res Nee Mancipi, as did heritable property in Scotland, and realty in England, over the personalty to which they were opposed. The lawyers of all systems have spared no pains in striving to refer these classifications to Digitized by Microsoft® CHAR viii] SUPERIOR AND INFERIOR PROPERTY 285 some intelligible principle ; but the reasons of the severance must ever be vainly sought for in the philosophy of law : they belong not to its philo- sophy, but to its history. The explanation which appears to cover the greatest number of instances is, that the objects of enjoyment honoured above the rest were the forms of property known first and earliest to each particular community, and dignified therefore emphatically with the designa- tion of Property. On the other hand, the articles not enumerated among the favoured objects seem to have been placed on a lower standing, because the knowledge of their value was posterior to the epoch at which the catalogue of superior property was settled. They were at first unknown, rare, limited in their uses, or else regarded as mere appendages to the privileged objects. Thus, though the Roman Res Mancipi included a num- ber of movable articles of great value, still the most costly jewels were never allowed to take rank as Res Mancipi, because they were unknown to the early Romans. In the same way chattels real in England are said to have been degraded to the footing of personalty, from the infrequency and valuelessness of such estates under the feudal land-law. But the grand point of interest is the continued degradation of these commodities when their importance had increased and their number had multiplied. Why were they not successively included among the favoured objects of enjoy- ment ? One reason is found in the stubbornness with which Ancient Law adheres to its classifica- tions. It is a characteristic both of uneducated minds and of early societies, that they are little Digitized by Microsoft® 286 EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [chap, viii able to conceive a general rule apart from the particular applications of it with which they are practically familiar. They cannot dissociate a general term or maxim from the special examples which meet them in daily experience ; and in this way the designation covering the best-known forms of property is denied to articles which exactly resemble them in being objects of enjoyment and subjects of right. But to these influences, which exert peculiar force in a subject-matter so stable as that of law, are afterwards added others more consistent with progress in enlightenment and in the conceptions of general expediency. Courts and lawyers become at last ahve to the inconvenience of the embarrassing formalities required for the transfer, recovery, or devolution of the favoured commodities, and grow unwiUing to fetter the newer descriptions of property with the technical trammels which characterised the infancy of law. Hence arises a disposition to keep these last on a lower grade in the arrangements of Jurisprudence, and to permit their transfer by simpler processes than those which, in archaic conveyances, serve as stumbling-blocks to good faith and stepping- stones to fraud. We are perhaps in some danger of under-rating the inconveniences of the ancient modes of transfer. Our instruments of conveyance are written, so that their language, well pondered by the professional draftsman, is rarely defective in accuracy. But an ancient conveyance was not written, but acted. Gestures and words took the place of written technical phraseology, and any formula mispronounced, or symbolical act omitted, would have vitiated the proceeding as fatally as a Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP-V'"] RES MANCIPI 287 material mistake in stating the uses or setting out the remainders would, two hundred years ago, have vitiated an English deed. Indeed, the mis- chiefs of the archaic ceremonial are even thus only half stated. So long as elaborate conveyances, written or acted, are required for the alienation of land alone, the chances of mistake are not considerable in the transfer of a description of property which is seldom got rid of with much precipitation. But the higher class of property in the ancient world comprised not only land but several of the commonest and several of the most valuable movables. When once the wheels of society had begun to move quickly, there must have been immense inconvenience in demanding a highly intricate form of transfer for a horse or an ox, or for the most costly chattel of the old world — the Slave. Such commodities must have been constancy and even ordinarily conveyed with incomplete forms, and held, therefore, under imperfect titles. The Res Mancipi of old Roman law were, land, — ^in historical times, land on Italian soil, — slaves and beasts of burden, such as horses and oxen. It is impossible to doubt that the objects which make up the class are the instruments of agricultural labour, the commodities of first con- sequence to a primitive people. Such commodities were at first, I imagine, called emphatically Things or Property, and the mode of conveyance by which they were transferred was called a Mancipium or Mancipation ; but it was not probably till much later that they received the distinctive appellation of Res Mancipi, " Things which require a Mancioa- Digitized by Microsoft® 288 EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [chap, viii tion." By their side there may have existed or grown up a class of objects, for which it was not worth while to insist upon the full ceremony of Mancipation. If would be enough if, in trans- ferring these last from owner to owner, a part only of the ordinary formalities were proceeded with, namely, that actual deUvery, physical transfer, or tradition, which is the most obvious index of a change of proprietorship. Such commodities were the Res Nee Mancipi of the ancient jurisprudence, " things which did not require a Mancipation," little prized probably at first, and not often passed from one group of proprietors to another. While, however, the list of the Res Mancipi was irrevoc- ably closed, that of the Res Nee Mancipi admitted of indefinite expansion ; and hence every fresh conquest of man over material nature added an item to the Res Nee Mancipi, or effected an im- provement in those already recognised. Insen- sibly, therefore, they mounted to an equaUty with the Res Mancipi, and the impression of an intrinsic inferiority being thus dissipated, men began to observe the manifold advantages of the simple formality which accompanied their transfer over the more intricate and more venerable ceremonial. Two of the agents of legal amehoration, Fictions and Equity, were assiduously employed by the Roman lawyers to give the practical effects of a Mancipation to a Tradition ; and, though Roman legislators long shrank from enacting that the right of property in a Res Mancipi should be immediately transferred by bare dehvery of the article, yet even this step was at last ventured upon by Justinian, in whose jurisprudence the Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VIII] RES NEC MANCIPl 289 difference between Res Mancipi and Res Nee Mancipi disappears, and Tradition or Delivery becomes the one great conveyance known to the law. The marked preference which the Roman lawyers very early gave to Tradition caused them to assign it a place in their theory which has helped to blind their modern disciples to its true history. It was classed among the " natural " modes of acquisition, both because it was generally practised among the Itahan tribes, and because it was a process which attained its object by the simplest mechanism. If the expressions of the jurisconsults be pressed, they undoubtedly imply that Tradition, which belongs to the Law Natural, is more ancient than Mancipation, which is an institution of Civil Society ; and this, I need not say, is the exact reverse of the truth. The distinction between Res Mancipi and Res Nee Mancipi is the type of a class of distinctions to which civilisation is much indebted, distinctions which run through the whole mass of commodities, placing a few of them in a class by themselves, and relegating the others to a lower category. The inferior kinds of property are first, from dis- dain and disregard, released from the perplexed ceremonies in which primitive law deUghts, and then afterwards, in another state of intellectual progress, the simple methods of transfer and re- covery which have been allowed to come into use serve as a model which condemns by its con- venience and simplicity the cumbrous solemnities inherited from ancient days. But in some societies, the trammels in which Property is tied up are much too comphcated and stringent to be relaxed Digitized by Microsoft® -^9 ago EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [chap, viii in so easy a manner. Whenever male children have been born to a Hindoo, the law of India, as I have stated, gives them all an interest in his property, and makes their consent a necessary condition of its alienation. In the same spirit, the general usage of the old Germanic peoples — it is remarkable that the Anglo-Saxon customs seem to have been an exception — forbade alienations without the consent of the male children ; and the primitive law of the Sclavonians even pro- hibited them altogether. It is evident that such impediments as these cannot be overcome by a distinction between kinds of property, inasmuch as the difficulty extends to commodities of all sorts ; and accordingly. Ancient Law, when once launched on a course of improvement, encounters them with a distinction of another character, a distinction classifying property, not according to its nature but according to its origin. In India, where there are traces of both systems of classi- fication, the one which we are considering is exemplified in the difference which Hindoo law estabhshes between Inheritances and Acquisitions. The inherited property of the father is shared by the children as soon as they are born ; but accord- ing to the custom of most provinces, the acquisi- tions made by him during his hfetime are wholly his own, and can be transferred by him at pleasure. A similar distinction was not unknown to Roman Law, in which the earhest innovation on the Parental Powers took the form of a permission given to the son to keep for himself whatever he might have acquired in mihtary service. But the most extensive use ever made of this mode of Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VIII] INHERITANCES AND ACQUISITIONS ZQI classification appears to have been among the Germans. I have repeatedly stated that the allod, though not inalienable^ was commonly transferable with the greatest difficulty ; and moreover, it descended exclusively to the agnatic kindred. Hence an extraordinary variety of distinctions came to be recognised, all intended to diminish the inconveniences inseparable from allodial property. The wehrgeld, for example, or composition for the homicide of a relative, which occupies so large a space in German jurisprudence, formed no part of the family domain, and descended according to rules of succession altogether different. Similarly, the reipus, or fine leviable on the re-marriage of a widow, did not enter into the allod of the person to whom it was paid, and followed a Une of devo- lution in which the privileges of the agnates were neglected. The law, too, as among the Hindoos, distinguished the Acquisitions of the chief of the household from his Inherited property, and per- mitted him to deal with them under much more liberal conditions. Classifications of the other sort were also_ admitted, and the famiUar distinction drawn between land and movables ; but movable property was divided into several subordinate categories, to each of which different rules applied. This exuberance of classification, which may strike us as strange in so rude a people as the German conquerors of the Empire, is doubtless to be ex- plained by the presence in their systems of a considerable element of Roman Law, absorbed by them during their long sojourn on the confines of the Roman dominion. It is not difficult to trace a great number of the rules governing the transfer Digitized by Microsoft® 292 EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [chap, viii and devolution of the commodities which lay out- side the allod, to their source in Roman jurispru- dence, from which they were probably borrowed at widely distant epochs, and in fragmentary importations. How far the obstacles to the free circulation of property were surmounted by such contrivances, we have not the means even of conjecturing, for the distinctions adverted to have no modern history. As I before explained, the aUodial form of property was entirely lost in the feudal, and when the consolidation of feudahsm was once completed, there was practically but one distinction left standing of all those which had been known to the western world — the distinction between land and goods, immovables and mov- ables. Externally this distinction was the same with that which Roman law had finally accepted, but the law of the middle ages differed from that of Rome in distinctly considering immovable property to be more dignified than movable. Yet this one sample is enough to show the im- portance of the class of expedients to which it belongs. In all the countries governed by systems based on the French codes, that is, through much the greatest part of the Continent of Europe, the law of movables, which was always Roman law, has superseded and annulled the feudal law of land. England is the only country of importance in which this transmutation, though it has gone some way, is not nearly accomplished. Our own, too, it may be added, is the only considerable European country in which the separation of movables from immovables has been somewhat disturbed by the same influences which caused Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP, viii] PRESCRIPTION 293 the ancient classifications to depart from the only one which is countenanced by nature. In the main, the English distinction has been between land and goods ; but a certain class of goods have gone as heir-looms with the land, and a certain description of interests in land have from historical causes been ranked with personalty. This^is not the only instance in which English jurisprudence, standing apart from the main current of legal modification, has reproduced phenomena of archaic law. I proceed to notice one or two more con- trivances by which the ancient trammels of proprietary right were more or less successfully relaxed, premising that the scheme of this treatise only permits me to mention those which are of great antiquity. On one of them in particular it is necessary to dwell for a moment or two, because persons unacquainted with the early history of law will not be easily persuaded that a principle, of which modem jurisprudence has very slowly and with the greatest difficulty obtained the recognition, was really familiar to the very infancy of legal science. There is no principle in aU law which the moderns, in spite of its beneficial character, have been so loath to adopt and to carry to its legitimate consequences as that which was known to the Romans as Usucapion, and which has descended to modern jurisprudence under the name of Prescription. It was a positive rule of the oldest Roman law, a rule older than the Twelve Tables, that com- modities which had been uninterruptedly pos- sessed for a certain period became the property of Digitized by Microsoft® 294 EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [chap, viii the possessor. The period of possession was exceedingly short — one or two years, according to the nature of the commodities — and in historical times Usucapion was only allowed to operate when possession had commenced in a particular way ; but I think it likely that at a less advanced epoch possession was converted into ownership under conditions even less severe than we read of in our authorities. As I have said before, I am far from asserting that the respect of men for de facto possession is a phenomenon which jurisprudence can account for by itself, but it is very necessary to remark that primitive societies, in adopting the principle of Usucapion, were not beset with any of the speculative doubts and hesitations which have impeded its reception among the moderns. Prescriptions were viewed by the modern lawyers, first with repugnance, afterwards with reluctant approval. In several countries, including our own, legislation long declined to advance beyond the rude device of barring all actions based on a wrong whch had been suffered earlier than a fixed point of time in the past, generally the first year of some preceding reign ; nor was it till the middle ages had finally closed, and James the First had ascended the throne of England, that we obtained a true statute of limitation of a very imperfect kind. This tardiness in coppng one of the most famous chapters of Roman law, which was no doubt constantly read by the majority of European lawyers, the modern world owes to the influence of the Canon Law. The ecclesiastical customs out of which the Canon Law grew, concerneci as Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VIII] THEORIES OF PRESCRIPTION 295 they were with sacred or quasi-sacred interests, very naturally regarded the privileges which they conferred as incapable of being lost through disuse however prolonged ; and in accordance with this view, the spiritual jurisprudence, when afterwards consolidated, was distinguished by a marked leaning against Prescriptions. It was the fate of the Canon Law, when held up by the clerical lawyers as a pattern to secular legislation, to have a peculiar influence on first principles. It gave to the bodies of custom which were formed throughout Europe far fewer express rules than did the Roman law, but then it seems to have communicated a bias to professional opinion on a surprising number of fundamental points, and the tendencies thus produced progressively gained strength as each system was developed. One of the dispositions it produced was a disrelish for Prescriptions ; but I do not know that this pre- judice would have operated as powerfully as it has done, if it had not fallen in with the doctrine of the scholastic jurists of the realist sect, who taught that, whatever turn actual legislation might take, a right, how long soever neglected, was in point of fact indestructible. The remains of this state of feehng still exist. Wherever the philosophy of law is earnestly discussed, questions respecting the speculative basis of Prescription are always hotly disputed ; and it is still a point of the greatest interest in France and Germany, whether a person who has been out of possession for a series of years is deprived of his ownership as a penalty for his neglect, or loses it through the summary interposition of the law in its desire Digitized by Microsoft® 296 EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [chap, viii to have a finis litium. But no such scruples troubled the mind of early Roman society. Their ancient usages directly took away the ownership of everybody who had been out of possession, under certain circumstances, during one or two years. What was the exact tenor of the rule of Usucapion in its earliest shape, it is not easy to say ; but, taken with the hmitations which we find attending it in the books, it was a most useful security against the mischiefs of a too cumbrous system of conveyance. In order to have the benefit of Usucapion, it was necessary that the adverse possession should have begun in good faith, that is, with belief on the part of the possessor that he was lawfully acquiring the property, and it was further required that the commodity should have been transferred to him by some mode of aUenation which, however unequal to conferring a complete title in the particular case, was at least recognised by the law. In the case therefore of a Mancipation, however slovenly the performance might have been, yet if it had been carried so far as to involve a Tradition or DeUvery, the vice of the title would be cured by Usucapion in two years at most. I know nothing in the practice of the Romans which testifies so strongly to their legal genius as the use which they made of Usucapion. The difficulties which beset them were nearly the same with those which embarrassed and still embarrass the lawyers of England. Owing to the complexity of their system, which as yet they had neither the courage nor the power to reconstruct, actual right was constantly getting divorced from technical right, the equitable Digitized by Microsoft® cHAP.vin] JUDICIAL CONVEYANCES 297 ownership from the legal. But Usucapion, as manipulated by the jurisconsults, suppUed a self-acting machinery, by which the defects oi titles to property were always in course of being cured, and by which the ownerships that were temporarily separated were again rapidly cemented together with the briefest possible delay. Usu- capion did not lose its advantages tiU the reforms of Justinian. But as soon as law and equity had been completely fused, and when Mancipation ceased to be the Roman conveyance, there was no further necessity for the ancient contrivance, and Usucapion, with its periods of time consider- ably lengthened, became the Prescription which has at length been adopted by nearly all systems of modern law. I pass by with brief mention another expedient having the same object with the last, which, though it did not immediately make its appearance in English legal history, was of immemorial antiquity in Roman law ; such indeed is its apparent age that some German civilians, not sufficiently aware of the Kght thrown on the subject by the analogies of English law, have thought it even older than the Mancipation. I speak of the Cessio in Jure, a collusive recovery, in a Court of Law, of property sought to be conveyed. The plaintiff claimed the subject of this proceeding with the ordinary forms of a Utigation ; the defendant made default ; and the commodity was of course adjudged to the plaintiff. I need scarcely remind the English lawyer that this expedient suggested itself to our forefathers, and produced those famous Fines and Recoveries Digitized by Microsoft® 298 EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [chap, viii which did so much to undo the harshest trammels of the feudal land-law. The Roman and English contrivances have very much in common and illustrate each other most instructively, but there is this difference between them, that the object of the English lawyers was to remove compHcations already introduced into the title, while the Roman jurisconsults sought to prevent them by sub- stituting a mode of transfer necessarily unim- peachable for one which too often miscarried. The device is in fact one which suggests itself as soon as Courts of Law are in steady operation, but are nevertheless stiU under the empire of primitive notions. In an advanced state of legal opinion, tribunals regard collusive Utigation as an abuse of their procedure ; but there has always been a time when, if their forms were scrupulously complied with, they never dreamed of looking further. The influence of Courts of Law and of their procedure upon Property has been most extensive, but the subject is too large for the dimensions of this treatise, and would carry us further down the course of legal history than is consistent with its scheme. It is desirable, however, to mention, that to this influence we must attribute the im- portance of the distinction between Property and Possession — not, indeed, the distinction itself, which (in the language of an eminent English civilian) is the same thing as the distinction between the legal right to act upon a thing and the physical power to do so — ^but the extraordinary importance which the distinction has obtained in the philosophy of law. Few educated persons Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP, viii] PROPERTY AND POSSESSION 299 are so little versed in legal literature as not to have heard that the language of the Roman juris- consults on the subject of Possession long occa- sioned the greatest possible perplexity, and that the genius of Savigny is supposed to have chiefly proved itself by the solution which he discovered for the enigma. Possession, in fact, when em- ployed by the Roman lawyers, appears to have contracted a shade of meaning not easily accounted for. The word, as appears from its etymology, must have originally denoted physical contact or physical contact resumable at pleasure ; but as actually used, without any qualifying epithet, it signifies not simply physical detention, but physical detention coupled with the intention to hold the thing detained as one's own. Savigny, following Niebuhr, perceived that for this anomaly there could only be a historical origin. He pointed out that the Patrician burghers of Rome, who had become tenants of the greatest part of the public domain at nominal rents, were, in the view of the old Roman law, mere possessors, but then they were possessors intending to keep their land against all comers. They, in truth, put forward a claim almost identical with that which has recently been advanced in England by the lessees of Church lands. Admitting that in theory they were the tenants-at-will of the State, they contended that time and undisturbed enjoyment had ripened their holding into a species of ownership, and that it would be unjust to eject them for the purpose of redistributing the domain. The association of this claim with the Patrician tenancies, permanently influenced the sense of Digitized by Microsoft® 300 EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [chap, viii " possession." Meanwhile the only legal remedies of which the tenants could avail themselves, if ejected or threatened with disturbance, were the Possessory Interdicts, summary processes of Roman law which were either expressly devised by the Praetor for their protection, or else, ac- cording to another theory, had in olden times been employed for the provisional maintenance of possessions pending the settlement of questions of legal right. It came, therefore, to be understood that everybody who possessed property as his own had the power of demanding the Interdicts, and, by a system of highly artificial pleading, the Interdictal process was moulded into a shape fitted for the trial of conflicting claims to a dis- puted possession. Then cormnenced a movement which, as Mr. John Austin pointed out, exactly reproduced itself in Enghsh law. Proprietors, domini, began to prefer the simpler forms or speedier course of the Interdict to the lagging and intricate formalities of the Real Action, and for the purpose of avaihng themselves of the possessory remedy fell back upon the possession which was supposed to be involved in their proprietorship. The hberty conceded to persons who were not true Possessors, but Owners, to vindicate their rights by possessory remedies, though it may have been at first a boon, had ultimately the effect of seriously deteriorating both English and Roman jurisprudence. The Roman law owes to it those subtleties on the subject of Possession which have done so much to discredit it, while English law, after the actions which it appropriated to the recovery of real Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP, viii] EQUITABLE PROPERTY 3OI property had fallen into the most hopeless con- fusion, got rid at last of the whole tangled mass by a heroic remedy. No one can doubt that the virtual abolition of the English real actions which took place nearly thirty years since was a pubUc benefit, but stiU persons sensitive to the harmonies of jurisprudence will lament that, instead of cleansing, improving, and simplifying the true proprietary actions, we sacrificed them all to the possessory action of ejectment, thus basing our whole system of land recovery upon a legal fiction. Legal tribunals have also powerfully assisted to shape and modify conceptions of proprietary right by means of the distinction between Law and Equity, which always makes its first appear- ance as a distinction between jurisdictions. Equit- able property in England is simply property held under the jurisdiction of the Court of Chancery. At Rome, the Praetor's Edict introduced its novel principles in the guise of a promise that under certain circumstances a particular action or a particular plea would be granted ; and, accord- ingly, the property in bonis, or Equitable Pro- perty, of Roman Law was property exclusively protected by remedies which had their source in the Edict. The mechanism by which equitable rights were saved from being overridden by the claims of the legal owner was somewhat different in the two systems. With us their independence is secured by the Injunction of the Court of Chancery. Since, however. Law and Equity, while not as yet consoUdated, were administered under the Roman system by the same Court, Digitized by Microsoft® 302 EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [chap, vm nothing like the Injunction was required, and the Magistrate took the simpler course of refusing to grant to the Civil Law Owner those actions and pleas by which alone he could obtain the property that belonged in equity to another. But the practical operation of both systems was nearly the same. Both, by means of a distinction in procedure, were able to preserve new forms of property in a sort of provisional existence, until the time should come when they were recognised by the whole law. In this way, the Roman Praetor gave an immediate right of property to the person who had acquired a Res Mancipi by mere delivery, without waiting for the ripening of Usucapion. Similarly he in time recognised an ownership in the Mortgagee, who had at first been a mere " bailee " or depositary, and in the Emphyteuta, or tenant of land which was subject to a fixed perpetual rent. Following a parallel line of progress, the Enghsh Court of Chancery created a special proprietorship for the Mortgagor, for the Cestui que Trust, for the Married Woman who had the advantage of a particular kind of settlement, and for the Purchaser who had not yet acquired a complete legal ownership. All these are examples in which forms of proprietary right, distinctly new, were recognised and pre- served. But indirectly Property has been affected in a thousand ways by equity, both in England and at Rome. Into whatever comer of juris- prudence its authors pushed the powerful instru- ment in their command, they were sure to meet, and touch, and more or less matericuUy modify the law of property. When in the preceding pages Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. VHi] ROMAN AND FEUDAL LAW 303 I have spoken of certain ancient legal distinctions and expedients as having powerfully affected the history of ownership, I must be understood to mean that the greatest part of their influence has arisen from the hints and suggestions of improve- ment infused by them into the mental atmosphere which was breathed by the fabricators of equitable systems. But to describe the influence of Equity on Ownership would be to write its history down to our own days. I have alluded to it principally because several esteemed contemporary writers have thought that in the Roman severance of Equitable from Legal property we have the clue to that difference in the conception of Ownership, which apparently distinguishes the law of the middle ages from the law of the Roman Empire. The leading characteristic of the feudal conception is its recognition of a double proprietorship, the superior ownership of the lord of the fief co- existing with the inferior property or estate of the tenant. Now, this .duplication of proprietary right looks, it is urged, extremely hke a generalised form of the Roman distribution of rights over property into Quiritarian or legal, and (to use a word of late origin) Bonitarian or equitable. Gains himself observes upon the sphtting of dominion into two parts as a singularity of Roman law, and expressly contrasts it with the entire or allodial ownership to which other nations were accustomed. Jus- tinian, it is true, reconsoUdated dominion into one, but then it was the partially reformed system of the Western Empire, and not Justinian's jurisprudence, with which the barbarians were Digitized by Microsoft® 304 EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [chap, viii in contact during so many centuries. While they remained poised on the edge of the Empire, it may well be that they learned this distinction, which afterwards bore remarkable fruit. In favour of this theory, it must at aU events be admitted that the element of Roman law in the various bodies of barbarian custom has been very imperfectly examined. The erroneous or in- sufficient theories which have served to explain FeudaUsm resemble each other in their tendency to draw off attention from this particular ingre- dient in its texture. The older investigators, who have been mostly followed in this country, attached an exclusive importance to the circum- stances of the turbulent period during which the Feudal system grew to maturity ; and in later times a new source of error has been added to those already existing, in that pride of nationality which has led German writers to exaggerate the completeness of the social fabric which their forefathers had built up before their appearance in the Roman world. One or two English inquirers who looked in the right quarter for the foundations of the feudal system, failed nevertheless to conduct their investigations to any satisfactory result, either from searching too exclusively for analogies in the compilations of Justinian, or from confining their attention to the compendia of Roman law which are found appended to some of the extant barbarian codes. But, if Roman jurisprudence had any influence on the barbarous societies, it had probably produced the greatest part of its effects before the legislation of Justinian, and before the preparation of these compendia. It Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP, vm] LEGES BARBARORUM 305 was not the reformed and purified jurisprudence of Justinian, but the undigested system which prevailed in the Western Empire, and which the Eastern Corpus Juris never succeeded in dis- placing, that I conceive to have clothed with flesh and muscle the scanty skeleton of barbarous usage. The change must be supposed to have taken place before the Germanic tribes had dis- tinctly appropriated, as conquerors, any portion of the Roman dominions, and therefore long before Germanic monarchs had ordered breviaries of Roman law to be drawn up for the use of their Roman subjects. The necessity for some such h57pothesis will be felt by everybody who can appreciate the difference between archaic and developed law. Rude as are the Leges Barharorum which remain to us, they are not rude enough to satisfy the theory of their pxirely barbarous origin ; nor have we any reason for believing that we have received, in written records, more than a fraction of the fixed rules which were practised among themselves by the members of the conquering tribes. If we can once persuade ourselves that a considerable element of debased Roman . law already existed in the barbarian systems, we shall have done something to remove a grave difficulty. The German Law of the conquerors and the Roman law of their subjects would not have combined if they had not possessed more af&nity for each other than refined juris- prudence has usually for the customs of savages. It is extremely likely that the codes of the bar- barians, archaic as they seem, are only a compound of true primitive usage with half-understood Digitized by Microsoft® 20 306 EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [chap, vin Roman rules, and that it was the foreign ingre- dient which enabled them to coalesce with a Roman jurisprudence that had already receded somewhat from the comparative finish which it had acquired under the Western Emperors. But, though aU this must be allowed, there are several considerations which render it unlikely that the feudal form of ownership was directly suggested by the Roman duphcation of domainial rights. The distinction between legal and equit- able property strikes one cis a subtlety Uttle Ukely to be appreciated by barbarians ; and, moreover, it can scarcely be understood unless Courts of Law are contemplated in regulai operation. But the strongest reason against this theory is the existence in Roman law of a form of property — a creation of Equity, it is true — which suppUes a much simpler explanation of the transition from one set of ideas to the other. This is the Emphyteusis, upon which the Fief of the middle ages has often been fathered, though without much knowledge of the exact share which it had in bringing feudal ownership into the world. The truth is that the Emphyteusis, not probably as yet known by its Greek designation, marks one stage in a current of ideas which led ultimately to feudalism. The first mention in Roman history of estates larger than could be farmed by a Paterfamilias, with his household of sons and slaves, occurs when we come to the holdings of the Roman patricians. These great proprietors appear to have had no idea of any system of farming by free tenants. Their latifunuia seem to have been universally cultivated by slave-gangs, under baiUffs who were themselves Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. Till] XHE COLONI 307 slaves or freedmen ; and the only organisation attempted appears to have consisted in dividing the inferior slaves into small bodies, and making them the peculium of the better and trustier sort, who thus acquired a kind of interest in the effi- ciency of their labour. This system was, however, especially disadvantageous to one class of estated proprietors, the Municipalities. Functionaries in Italy were changed with the rapidity which often surprises us in the administration of Rome herself ; so that the superintendence of a large landed domain by an Italian corporation must have been excessively imperfect. Accordingly, we are told that with the municipalities began the practice of letting out agri vectigales, that is, of leasing land for a perpetuity to a free tenant, at a fixed rent, and under certain conditions. The plan was afterwards extensively imitated by individual proprietors, and the tenant, whose relation to the owner had originally been determined by his contract, was subsequently recognised by the Praetor as having himself a qualified proprietorship, which in time became known as an Emphyteusis. From this point the history of tenure parts into two branches. In the course of that long period during which our records of the Roman Empire are most incomplete, the slave-gangs of the great Roman families became transformed into the coloni, whose origin and situation constitute one of the obscurest questions in all history. We may suspect that they were formed partly by the elevation of the slaves, and partly by the degrada- tion of the free farmers ; and that they prove the richer classes of the Roman Empire to have Digitized by Microsoft® 308 EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [chap, viii become aware of the increased value which landed property obtains when the cultivator has an interest in the produce of the land. We know that their servitude was predial ; that it wanted many of the characteristics of absolute slavery, and that they acquitted their service to the landlord in rendering to him a fixed portion of the annual crop. We know further that they survived all the mutations of society in the ancient and modern worlds. Though included in the lower courses of the feudal structure, they con- tinued in many countries to render to the landlord precisely the same dues which they had paid to the Roman dominus, and from a particular class among them, the coloni medietarii, who reserved half the produce for the owner, are descended the metayer tenantry, who stiU conduct the cultivation of the soil in almost aU the South of Europe. On the other hand, the Emphyteusis, if we may so interpret the allusions to it in the Corpus Juris, became a favourite and beneficial modification of property ; and it may be conjec- tured that wherever free farmers existed, it was this tenure which regulated their interest in the land. The Praetor, as has been said, treated the Emphyteuta as a true proprietor. When ejected, he was allowed to reinstate himself by a Real Action, the distinctive badge of proprietary right, and he was protected from disturbance by the author of his lease so long as the canon, or quit-rent, was punctually paid. But at the same time it must not be supposed that the ownership of the author of the lease was either extinct or dormant. It was kept ahve by a power of re-entry on non- Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP.viii] FEUDAL SERVICES 309 payment of the rent, a right of pre-emption in case of sale, and a certain control over the mode of cultivation. We have, therefore, in the Emphy- teusis a striking example of the double ownership which characterised feudal property, and one, moreover, which is much simpler and much more easily imitated than the juxtaposition of legal and equitable rights. The history of the Roman tenure does not end, however, at this point. We have clear evidence that between the great fortresses which, disposed along the Une of the Rhine and Danube, long secured the frontier of the Empire against its barbarian neighbours, there extended a succession of strips of land, the agri limitrophi, which were occupied by veteran soldiers of the Roman army on the terms of an Emphyteusis. There was a double ownership. The Roman State was landlord of the soil, but the soldiers cultivated it without disturbance so long as they held themselves ready to be called out for military service whenever the state of the border should require it. In fact, a sort of garrison-duty, under a system closely resembling that of the mihtary colonies on the Austro-Turkish border, had taken the place of the quit-rent which was the service of the ordinary Emphyteuta. It seems impossible to doubt that this was the precedent copied by the barbarian monarchs who founded feudaUsm. It had been within their view for some hundred years, and many of the veterans who guarded the border were, it is to be remembered, themselves of barbarian extraction, who probably spoke the Germanic tongues. Not only does the proximity of so easily followed a Digitized by Microsoft® 310 EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY [chap, thi model explain whence the Prankish and Lombard Sovereigns got the idea of securing the miUtary service of their followers by granting away portions of their pubUc domain ; but it perhaps explains the tendency which immediately showed itself in the Benefices to become hereditary, for an Emphyteusis, though capable of being moulded to the terms of the original contract, nevertheless descended as a general rule to the heirs of the grantee. It is true that the holder of a benefice, and more recently the lord of one of those fiefs into which the benefices were transformed, appears to have owed certain services which were not likely to have been rendered by the miUtary colonist, and were certainly not rendered by the Emphyteuta. The duty of respect and gratitude to the feudal superior, the obligation to assist in endowing his daughter and equipping his son, the liability to his guardianship in minority, and many other similar incidents of tenure, must have been literally borrowed from the relations of Patron and Freedman under Roman law, that is, of quondam-master and quondam-slave. But then it is known that the earhest beneficiaries were the personal companions of the sovereign, and it is indisputable that this position, briUiant as it seems, was at first attended by some shade of servile debasement. The person who minis- tered to the Sovereign in his Court had given up something of that absolute personal freedom which was the proudest privilege of the allodia] proprietor. Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. Villi NOTES 311 NOTE O CAPTURE, OCCUPATION, POSSESSION The statements made in the early part of this chapter about the Roman doctrine of capture in war, its relation to the ordinary rules of occupatto, and the relation of both to the modem law of nations, are not easy to follow. Maine's general results do not depend on the accuracy of these statements, but it is necessary to indicate the points on which a reader unacquainted with Roman and international law might find the text misleading. First, there is really no authority for attributing to the Roman jurists the unqualified opinion that all spoil of war belonged to the individual captor, nor for deducing the rule of war firom the law of occupatio in time of peace. Next, it is by no means clear that the Roman law oioccu-patio was more than one of many elements which went to form the modern rules as to belligerent rights. It is necessary to examine the authorities in some detail. Maine seems to have relied on a passage of Gaius in the title of the Digest " de adquirendo rerum dominio " (41, i, 11. S, §7, 7, §1 ; 1. 6 is clumsily interpolated by the compilers from another writer, and is not to our purpose). Gaius has spoken of the " occupation " of res nullius, such as wild animals, and goes on to other classes of cases in which occupation or something like it confers owner- ship (and not merely possession) iure gentium. This last term would seem, in relation to hostile capture, to point to the actual usage of war rather than to the ideal law of nature, which at all events would not justify treating captives of free condition as slaves. "Item quae ex hostibus capiuntur iure gentium statim capientium finat . . ,. adeo quidem ut et liberi homines in servitutem deducantur." Then Paulus says, at the head of the next title, " de adquirenda vel amittenda pos^essione " : " Item bello capta et insula in raari enata et gemmae lapilli margaritae in litoribus inventae eius fiunt, qui primus eorum possessionem nanctus est." Obviously no proof or authority was needed to show that a public enemy in arras could have no civil rights. The point is not that spoil of war ceases to belong to the enemy, but that capture, when it occurs, makes the captor an owner and not merely a possessor as between himself and his fellow- citizens. This does not tell us what is lawful spoil of war according to any specially Roman usage, nor does it exclude the restrictions of military discipline. Under the Empire, in fact, the commanding oflBcer might distribute booty if he pleased, but plunder for the individual soldier's benefit or any kind of subsequent private appropriation was distinctly forbidden. " Is, qui praedam ab hostibus captam subripuit, lege peculatus tenetur et in quadruplum damnatur " : Modestinus in D. 48, 13, ad legem luliam peculatus. Digitized by Microsoft® 312 NOTES [CHAP, VIII 15 (ed. Mommsen, vulg 13). Indeed, it may well be that the dicta of Gaius and Paulus contemplate only the case of enemy property found on Roman ground at the outbreak of a war: "quae res hostiles apttd nos sunt non publicae sed occupantium fiunt": Celsus, D. 41, 1, 51, Grotius comments on this dictum of Celsus, understanding it in this sense, and holds the right of private capture to be confined to acts not in the course of service, "extra ministerium publicum" : De lure Belli ac Pacis, III. vi. xii. § I ; and so Girard, " Manuel,'' p. 314. There is no doubt that land seized in war was acquired and distributed by the State : Pomponius in D. 49, 15, de ca;ptivis, 20, §1. In considering these passages it is just as well to remember that problems arising out of a state of war between Rome and a civilized or wealthy enemy must have seemed a mere archaic curiosity to the jurists who flourished under the Antonines. Then as to Grotius's use of the Roman law, he certainly quotes the words of Gaius already set out ; but almost in the same breath he quotes the Old Testament, Plato, Xenophon, and Aristotle {of. cit. III. vi. ii. § 4). He denies (iv. § i) that enemy's land can be acquired by mere invasion short of permanent occupation in force. He seems to think private plundering admissible in strict right, but elsewhere, under the head of temperaments — a kind of counsels of perfection to mitigate the rigour of war, most of which have since been adopted as rules— he suggests that captured property should be restored on the conclusion of peace, so far as practicable (III. xiii., " temperamentum circa res captas"). Again, an early trait of Grotius, " De lure Praedae," published only in our own time (ed. Hamaker, Hag. Com. 1868), altogether repudiates the occupa- tion theory of the right to spoil of war. He likens it to the right of judicial execution, and explains away the dictum of Gaius by holding that the captor takes only as the servant and in the name of the State ; and he fortifies his doctrine, after the manner of the time, which he continued to follow in his own later work, with Hebrew, Homeric, and other Greek examples. It is difScult to find here much adoption of the Roman law of Occupancy. Perhaps other publicists of the seventeenth or eighteenth century may have been less discriminating than Grotius. If this is to be verified, it must be by some one more familiar with their writings than myself. No further light is thrown on the point in Maine's Cambridge lectures on international law, which he did not live to revise finally for publication. These questions, however, have long been antiquarian ; modem practice has abrogated the old harsh customs of war, and the seizure of movables or other personal property in its bare form has, except in a very few cases, become illegal (Hall, "Intern. Law," 5th ed. p. 427: the whole chapter should be consulted). Maine observes at p. 262 that the Roman law of Occupancy was Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. Villi NOTES 313 altogether unequal to the task of settling disputes of title between different nations claiming new territories in right of their respective subjects who had discovered and more or less taken possession of them. Undoubtedly this is true, and it could not be otherwise. The difficulties have arisen in almost every case, down to the recent boundary question between Venezuela and British Guiana, from attempts to treat isolated, slight, and partial acts of dominion as equivalent to effective possession. Roman law knows nothing of any " occupation'' which does not amount to full and actual control. Hence the learning of occupation had to be supplemented by that of possession. Roman law, like the Common Law, recognises the fact that a man cannot physically hold or control at the same time every square foot of a parcel of land, and therefore it allows legal possession to be acquired by entry on a part in the name of the whole and with intent to possess everything included in the boundaries. " Quod autem diximus et corpore et animo adquirere nos debere possessionem, non utique ita accipiendum est, ut qui fundum possidere velit omnes glebas circumambulet : sed sufficit quamlibet partem eius fundi introire, dum mente et cogitatione hac sit, uti totum fundum usque ad terminum velit possidere " (Paulas in D. 41, 2, deadq. velamitt. ^oss. 3, §1)- In order to apply this rule, however, we have to assume that the boundaries are known or ascertainable, and also that there is no effective opposition; and when the facts to which the application is to be made are those alleged to amount to a national occupation of unsettled territory, it is often far from easy to say whether these conditions are satisfied. In case of dispute whether possession has been established, we must resort to the rule of common sense, which is expressly adopted by the authorities of the Common Law, and does not contradict anything in the Roman Law, namely that regard must be had to the kind of use and control of which the subject-matter is capable (authorities collected in Pollock and Wright on Possession, pp. 31-5). On the question what is the "terminus" in the occupation of unsettled territory, certain conventional rules, which must be sought in the regular text-books of international law, have been more or less generally adopted by the custom of nations, and in some cases express agreements have been made (Hall, op. cit. p. 114). The doctrine that occupancy produces ownership is of course not of the highest antiquity. Besides the reasons given by Maine, the conception of individual ownership as a legal right, the dominium of Roman law, is itself relatively modern. How and why Roman law developed that conception as early as it did is a historical problem which, so far as I have learnt, we cannot solve with our materials. We only know that Roman property law, for whatever reason, was already quite individualist at the time of the Twelve Tables. I am not sure that I fully understand Maine's passing remark about the influence of Natural Law in this point (p. 270). Digitized by Microsoft® 314 NOTES [CHAP. VIII. At all events the transformation of the Hindu Joint Family to its modem type can hardly be set down to any such influence, and, so far as it has gone, the example appears fairly parallel. Blackstone's account of the origin of property is loose enough to deserve nearly all of Maine's criticism. He wholly fails to dis- tinguish beti/een physical control or " detention," possession in law, and ownerihip, and he talks as if our refined legal conceptions had come to primeval man ready made, and in exactly the form and language of eighteenth-century publicists. But perhaps it was needless cruelty to suggest that Blackstone either did not understand the technical meaning of Occupation or intended to impose on his readers by playing with a verbal ambiguity. The word occu^are is, after all, not purely technical in Latin ; it certainly has no technical meaning in the passage of Cicero which Blackstone quotes ("Comm.'' ii. 4; Cic. " de Fin." iii. 20, § 67). Cicero was neither an original philosopher nor a great jurist ; but no one would charge him with supposing that the right of a spectator in a theatre to the place he has taken (" eum locum quern quisque occuparit") had anything to do with the permanent acquisition of dominium. It would be more plausible to credit him with an inkling of the historical truth pointed out by Maine in these pages, that the notion of absolute legal ownership, and still more the presumption that everything ought to have an owner, or that, as our own books say, " the law must needs reduce the properties of all goods to some man," are rather modem than primitive. Blackstone's neglect to observe that the detached individual man whom he postulates is a kind of person altogether unknown to archaic institutions is the common and fatal fault, as Maine has in effect said, of all individualist theories of society: of Hobbes's, which Locke's was intended to refute, no less than of Blackstone's, which is a slight modification of Locke's. Incidentally, but with provoking brevity, Maine speaks of Savigny's aphorism that property is founded on adverse possession ripened by prescription. This aphorism is certainly true for English law. Property in goods is, in the terms and process of the Common Law, not distinguishable from a right, present or deferred, to possess them ; and it is only under statutory provisions of very recent introduction and partial application that we know any means of proving title to English land other than showing con- tinuous undisturbed possession, under a consistent claim of title, for a time long enough to exclude any reasonable fear of adverse claims. The conventional fixing of that time first by the usage of conveyancers and latterly by positive law makes no difference to the principle, nor do the elaborate rules which have been developed in various matters of detail. Title-deeds, as I have said elsewhere, are nothing but the written history of the possession and of the right in which it has been exercised. This is essentially Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. Till] NOTES 315 a Germanic institution, as any one who pursues the subject will find ; and when we consider the ideas of early Germanic law, we shall perhaps be less apt to find any problem in the fact of a possessor's rights being recognised by Roman law than to wonder how Roman law came so early by the full and clear conception of an owner's rights as distinct from possession. As to the historical origin of the Roman doctrine of Possession there are now several theories in the field, and none of them can be said to be generally accepted, certainly not Savigny's, which was dominant when Maine wrote. NOTE P THE INDIAN VILLAGE COMMUNITY After Maine had acquired oflacial knowledge of Indian affairs, he gave a hint in his lecture on "Village Communities" that the local customs of India are neither so simple nor so uniform in type as an ordinary European reader of "Ancient Law" might infer. " I shall have hereafter to explain," he said,' " that, though there are strong general resemblances between the Indian village communities wherever they are found in anything like completeness, they prove on close inspection to be not simple but composite bodies, including a number of classes with very various rights and claims." The publication in more than one form (most con- veniently in "The Indian Village Community," Lond. 1896) of B. H. Baden-Powell's authoritative researches on the Land Systems of British India has since made it common or at least easily accessible' knowledge that Indian villages are divisible into two principal and widely different types, of which the " assemblage of co-proprietors," formerly assumed to be the only normal one, is not the more ancient. Sir Alfred Lyall (L.Q.R. ix. 27) has approved Baden-Powell's '•' conclusion that the oldest form of village was not, as is usually supposed, a group of cultivators having joint or communistic interests, but a disconnected set of families who severally owned their separate holdings." There is a headman and there are village officers ; we may say there is administrative unity for many purposes ; but there is not communal ownership or tenure. There is no evidence that in villages of this kind, usually called ratyatwdri, and prevalent in Central and Southern India, the holdings were ever otherwise than separate and independent; "the so-called joint village followed, and did ' I cannot find any fulfilment of this intention in Maine's published work. See the Preface to the first edition of "Village Communities" for the probable explanation. ' Baden-Powell's work appears to haVe been wholly unknown to a learned gentleman resident at Madras, who published some notes on " Ancient Law " a few years ago. Digitized by Microsoft® 3l6 NOTES [CHAP, vin not precede, the village of separate holdings." In the joint or " landlord " villages of Oudh, the United (formerly North-West) Provinces, and the Panjab, we find a dominant family or clan, oligarchs and in fact landlords as regards the inferior majority of inhabitants, and more or less democratic (for the shares are not always equal) among themselves. This type of village, which is in some ways curiously like a smaller reproduction of a Greek city-state, may be due to several causes. Conquest may produce it, or a deliberate new settlement, or joint inheritance among descendants of a single founder. In the case of conquest it may be superimposed on a former ratyaiwdri vi\la.ge. Baden-Powell points out that all writers on the subject down to a time later than the publication not only of "Ancient Law" but of "Village Com- munities" had to generalise on incomplete materials. " It can hardly be doubted that the information available when Sir H. S. Maine wrote was very far from being what it has since become. None of the reports on the Panjab frontier tribal-villages were written — or at least were available in print ; and the greater part of the best Settlement Reports of the North-West Provinces, Oudh and the Panjab, are dated in years subsequent to the publication of 'Village Communities.' Further, the Settlement Reports of the Central Provinces, the District Manuals of Southern India, and the Survey Reports and Gazetteers of the Bombay districts were many of them not written, and the others were hardly known beyond the confines of their presidencies. In this fact I find the explanation of the total omission in Sir H. S. Maine's pages of any specific mention of the raiyatwdri form of village, and the little notice he takes of the tribal or clan constitution of Indian races in general, and of the frontier tribal villages in the Panjab" ("The Indian Village Community," p. 4). It will be quite a mistake, however, as we may learn at large from Baden-Powell, to assume that the family tenure or property which is the unit of the raiyatwdri village system is equivalent to individual ownership or any kind of ownership as understood in modem Western law. What is certain is that there is no such thing as the village community of Hindu times, any more than there is any such thing as the village community of the Middle Ages in Europe. But there remains much profit to be derived from comparing the effects of more or less similar causes in fixing the customs of land tenure in the East and the West, whether those effects are, as they sometimes are, closely similar, or varied by the presence of other and different conditions. We no longer expect to find complete and parallel survivals of a common prehistoric stock of institutions, but it is not less interesting to find how easily parallel types may be developed at very distant times and places ; and we are free to hold as a pious opinion that the Indian village council still known as the Five (^a«cA the State. On the other hand, the Church, in its anxiety to put a curb on sanguinary ferocity, sought about for authority to punish the graver misdeeds, and found it in those passages of Scripture which speak with approval of the powers of punishment committed to the civil magistrate. The New Testament was appealed to as proving that secular rulers exist for the terror of evil-doers ; the Old Testament, as laying down that " whoso sheddeth man's blood, by man shall his blood be shed." There can be no doubt, I imagine, that modern ideas on the subject of Digitized by Microsoft® 404 EARLY raSTORY OF DELICT AND CRIME [chap, x crime are based upon two assumptions contended for by the Church in the Dark Ages — first, that each feudal ruler, in his degree, might be assimi- lated to the Roman Magistrates spoken of by Saint Paul ; and next, that the offences which he was to chastise were those selected for pro- hibition in the Mosaic Commandments, or rather such of them as the Church did not reserve to her own cognisance. Heresy, supposed to be included in the First and Second Commandments, Adultery, and Perjury were ecclesiastical offences, and the Church only admitted the co-operation of the secular arm for the purpose of inflicting severer punishment in cases of extraordinary aggravation. At the same time, she taught that murder and robbery, with their various modi- fications, were under the jurisdiction of civil rulers, not as an accident of their position, but by the express ordinance of God. There is a passage in the writings of King Alfred (Kemble, ii. 209) which brings out into remarkable clearness the struggle of the various ideas that prevailed in his day as to the origin of criminal jurisdiction. It will be seen that Alfred attributes it partly to the authority of the Church and partly to that of the Witan, while he expressly claims for treason against the lord the . same immunity from ordinary rules which the Roman Law of Majestas had assigned to treason against the Caesar. " After this it hap- pened," he writes, " that many nations received the faith of Christ, and there were many synods assembled throughout the earth, and among the Enghsh race also after they had received the Digitized by Microsoft® '=*""■• ^] . NOTES 405 faith of Christ, both of holy bishops and of their exalted Witan. They then ordained that, out of that mercy which Christ had taught, secular lords, with their leave, might without sin take for every misdeed the bot in money which they ordained ; except in cases of treason against a lord, to which they dared not assign any mercy because Almighty God adjudged none to them that despised Him, nor did Christ adjudge any to them which sold Him to death ; and He commanded that a lord should be loved like Himself." NOTE S ARCHAIC PROCEDURE The account given by Maine of the symbolism involved in the Legis Actio Sacramenti may be taken as generally correct The Sacra- mentum itself, however, seems, according to the generally received modern opinion, to have had the definite and practical purpose of bringing the matter in dispute within the highest jurisdiction. Each party swears to the justice of his cause under a conventional forfeit, and thus the king, who is also chief priest, is brought in to decide which of them is perjured: " il faut au roi, chef de la religion et de la justice criminelle, chercher qui a raison." The separation of civil and spiritual jurisdiction under the Republic led to the abolition of the oath (Girard, " Manuel," pp. 13, 977). If this opinion is right, the Praetor does not represent a discreet passer-by, nor yet (as might also be conjectured) the village elders, but intervenes as the minister of the king's justice, conceived in the first instance (as it was in England in the early Middle Ages) as an extraordinary justice applicable only for special reasons. English readers hardly need to be reminded of the fictions by which the King's Bench and Exchequer extended their jurisdiction to ordinary pleas between subjects. Maine's reference to the trial scene described in the Iliad, 2. 497-508, as adorning the shield of Achilles, is very brief; but the whole scene is of such interest for early legal history that we may be allowed to dwell on it a little. The point specially made by Maine is that the two talents of gold are a fee for the Digitized by Microsoft® 4o6 NOTES [CHAP. member of the court who shall be thought to speak the law beat. On this he is confirmed by Dr. W. Leafs very careful inter- pretation of the passage in his notes ad loc, and his earlier paper in Joum. Hell. Stud. viii. 122. There is no difficulty about the magnitude of the sum, for the Homeric talent represents only the value of one ox (Ridgeway in Joum. Hell. Stud. viii. 133). We shall now give Dr. Leafs version. " The people were gathered in the place of assembly, and there had sprung up a strife ; two men were striving about the price of a man slain. The one averred that he had paid in full [namely by tender of the blood-fine then and there before the assembly ; but Dr. Leaf's alternative in his later notes to the Iliad, Appen- dix I., ' claimed to pay,' is as good or better for the grammar of ci^X^ro Train-' airoSoCvat, and makes better sense], and made de- claration thereof to the people, but the other refused to accept aught [this is the proper idiomatic meaning of dvaivero fu]bev fKetrOai : ' denied that he had received anything ' is, even apart from the context, barely admissible] ; and both were desirous to take an issue at the hand of a daysman [this person, lorup, summons the council and presides, but the judgment has to be theirs ; he is more like the sheriff in the old county court than a modem judge or referee]; and the people were shouting for both, taking part for either side [not unlike such glimpses as Bracton's Note Book and other sources afford us of the behaviour of medieval county courts]. And the heralds were restraining the people, and the elders sate on polished stones in the holy circle [such stones may be seen on Dartmoor to this day], and in their hands they held the clear- voiced herald's staves. With these they rose up and gave sentence in turn ; and in their midst lay two talents of gold to give to him among them that spake the justest doom." In addition to Dr. Leafs reasons for rejecting the view formerly current that the dispute is on the mere question of fact whether a blood-fine admitted to be due has been paid or not, we may observe that such a payment would surely be made in a notorious manner and with ample witness, to say nothing of the physical difficulty of handing over some score of cattle (for such would be the most likely form of payment) as privately as modem debtors hand over cash or post a cheque. The result is that we are confronted with an ancient Greek blood- feud in an interesting stage of transition, that in which the slain man's kindred are no longer free to accept or refuse compensation at their will, but are expected to abandon the feud, in a proper case, on receiving a sum fixed either by custom or by the judgment of the assembly. Homicide aggravated by treachery or the like would probably not fall within such a rule ; and the amount of the fine, if we may judge by the practice of Iceland as described in the Sagas, might give matter enough for discussion among Digitized by Microsoft® CHAP. X] NOTES 407 the wise men even if no preliminary question arose. Indications of a similar stage, though not clear enough to amount to proof if they stood alone, may be found in the Anglo-Saxon laws. There is no question in the Homeric text of a formally com- pulsory jurisdiction ; the parties have agreed to put themselves on the judgment of the assembly whether in all the circumstances, whatever they were, tender of the customary fine ought to be accepted. But when such voluntary references have become common practice we are near the point at which they cease to be voluntary, and the party who stands out for what formerly would have been his right incurs, at all events, public reprobation which will be an efficient sanction for most purposes. Maine's opinion that in the infancy of criminal jurisdiction the sum paid to the king, or the State, was not penal, but a fee for hearing and determining the cause at the request of the parties, "the fair price of its time and trouble," is borne out by later researches in the antiquities of Germanic law. Such was probably at one time the wite of the Anglo-Saxon laws, though it is treated as penal in the earliest documents we have. If one feature in early procedure may be fixed on more than another as marking the recognition of criminal and civil responsibility as distinct in character, though one and the same act may be and quite com- monly is both a wrong and an offence, perhaps it is the appearance of a special fine for breaking the peace. The development of the king's peace in England from a privilege attached to certain per- sons, places, and occasions, to the common right of every lawful man belongs to another and later stage. Digitized by Microsoft® INDEX ADOPTION Adoption, fiction of, 138 — influence of the sacra gentilicia on the law of, 5, 6, 31 — in Hindoo law, 205 Adprehensio ; or assumption of sovereign power in a newly dis- covered country, 262 ^quitas, the term, 60. See Equity £quus, the word, 61 Agnatic and Cognatic relationship, difference between, 61, 152 Agnation described, 152, 154 Agreement, Roman analysis of, 335 Agri vectigales, Roman practice of letting out, 307 — limitrophi of the Romans on the banks of the Rhine and Danube, 309 Alexander the Sixth, Pope, his Bull, 263 Alfred, King, his remarks on criminal jurisdiction, quoted, 404 Alienation of property, ancient difl&culties of, 281, 282 — archaic ceremonies of, 282 Allodial property, of the ancient Germans, 242, 291 America, United States of. De- claration of Independence of, 99 Anglo Saxons, character of their kingship, no — their law of succession, 290 — their penal law, 380, 383, 388 Archon of Athens, the office of the, 9 Aristocracies, origin of the rule of, 9 — those of Greece, Italy, and Asia Minor, 9 — difference between those of the East and West, 10 — aristocracies the depositaries and administrators of the law, 10, II — importance of judicial, before the invention of writing, 1 1 — foundation of aristocracies, 140 Aristotle, his Treatise on Rhe- toric, referred to, 81 Assignees in Bankruptcy, succes- sion of, 194 Athenian wills, 208 Athens, primitive penal law of, 390 Augustus, the Emperor, his altera- tions in the Roman law, 44, 45 Austin's " Province of Jurispru- dence Determined " referred to, 6 Bayle referred to, 92 Benefices of the invading chiefe of the Roman Empire, 243 — transformation of the Benefice into the hereditary Fief, 254 Bengalee Wills, 209 Bentham, his " Fragment on Government," referred to, 6 40S Digitized by Microsoft® INDEX 409 BENTHAM Bentham, causes of his influence in England, 84 — the Roman counterpart of Benthamism, 84 — the theory of Jurisprudence, 128 — his eulogy of the Bull of Pope Alexander the Sixth, 263 — Bentham and Austin's rules as to the essentials of a contract, 335 Blackstone, Sir William, his theory of the first principles of law, 123, 124 — his justification for the exclu- sion of the half-blood, 157 — his theory of the origin of property quoted, 264 — his theory criticised, 266 Bonorum Possessio of the Romans, 221 Bracton, his Plagiarisms, 87 Burgundians, the, referred to, 106 C^SAR, Julius, his contemplated additions to the Roman Statute Law, 45 Capet, Hugh, character of his sovereignty, 1:0 Capture in War, sources of the modem International Law of, 2S9 — ancient Law of, 260 Caracalla, efiect of his constitution in enlarging the Patria Potestas, 151 Casuists, the, 360 — comparison of their system with that of Grotius and his school, 360 — origin of Casuistry, 361 — blow struck at Casuistry by Pascal, 362 Cessio in Jure of Property, in Roman and in English Law, 297 Cestui que Trust, special pro- prietorship created for the, 302 Chancellor, the Lord, compared with a Roman Praetor, 66, 67 Chancery, Court of, in England remarks on the, 48 — origin of its system, 48, 49 Charlemagne, his claim to univer- sal dominion, 108 — his distribution of Benefices, 243 Children, disinherison of, under the Romans, 231 China, cause of the arrest oi progress in, 28 Churches, Eastern and Western, conclusion of the East on theo- logical subjects accepted by the West without dispute or review, 365 — problems of the Western Church, 366 Cicero referred to, 63 — his allusions to the ancient Roman Sacra, 205 Code Napoleon, restraints imposed by it on the Testamentary Power, 191 Codes, Ancient, I — sources of knowledge afforded by the Greek Homeric poems, 2 — Themistes, 3, 4 — Hindoo Laws of Manu, 5 — difference between Ccise-law and Code-law, 12 — era of Codes, 12 — the Twelve Tables, i, 12 — the Codes of Solon and Draco, H — importance of Codes to ancient societies, 14-17 Coemption, or higher form of civil marriage of the ancient Ro- mans, 159 Cognatic relationship described, 152. IS3 Co-heirs, rights and duties of, 195 — rights of, under the Roman Law, 241 , Digitized by Microsoft® 410 INDEX Coloni of the Romans, 245 — origin and situation of the, 307 Comitia Calata, ancient Roman execution of Wills in the, 210 — end of the, 214 Comitia Centuriata, power of the, 395 — Curiata, powers of the, 395 — Tributa, powers of the, 395 Commentaries of the Roman law- yers, 39 Common law of England, formerly an unwritten law, 1 1 — difference between Case-law and Code-law, 12 — Case-law and its anomalies, 35 — similarity between English Case-law and the Responsa Prudentium of the Romans, 37 Confarreation, or religious mar- riage of the ancient Romans, 159 Constantino, the Emperor, his improvements in the Law, 45 — his modification of the Patria Potestas, 149 Contract, movement of societies from Status to, 174 — early history of, 319 — Contract and Political Eco- nomy, 320 — Rousseau's doctrine of an original Social Contract, 323 — Montesquieu's apologue of the Troglodytes, 325 — early notions of Contract, 326 — Roman Contracts, 328 — specialising process in ancient law, 329 — historical alliance between Con- tracts and Conveyances, 331 — changes in the Nexum, 331 — Executory Contracts of Sale, 334 — primitive association of Con- veyances and Contracts, 334 — ancient and modem doctrine of Contracts. 335 CUSTOMARY Contract, the Roman Obligation, 336 — Roman classification of Con- tracts, 337 — the Verbal Contract, 338 — the Literal or Written Con- tract, 342 — the Real Contract, 343 — Consensual Contracts, 343 — changes in Contract law, 348 — history of the progress of Con tract law, 349 — Quasi-Con tracts, 353 — Contract law and Fiefs, 372 Conveyances, relation of Wills to, under the Roman Law, 214 — consequence of this relation, 216 — remedies, 217 — historical alliance between Con- tracts and Conveyances, 331 C 0-0 wnership of property, amongst the Hindoos, 272, 273 — regarded by the Roman Law as exceptional and momentary, 273 Corporations aggregate, 200 — sole, leading attribute of, 200 " Corpus Juris Civilis " of Jus- tinian, 69 — resorted to by English Chan- cery judges, 48 Creation, Greek philosophical ex- planation of the fabric of, 56 Creditors, cause of the extrava- gant powers given to, by ancient laws, 334 Crimes and Wrongs. Ste Delict and Crime Croatia, co-ownership of the villa- gers of, 278 Curatores of male Orphans under the Roman law, 166 Curse, inherited, Greek notion of an, 135 Customary Law, 6 — Homeric terms for customs, 5 — origin of customary law, 8 — epoch of customary law and its Digitized by Microsoft® INDEX 411 CYCLOPS custody by a privileged order, II Cyclops, Homer's account of, quoted, 133 Dkath, disappearance of, from the penal system of republican Rome, 395 — causes for this, 395 — death punishment a necessity in certain stages of society, 396 Debtors, cause of the severity of ancient laws against, 334 Decretals, forged, motives of the author of the, 87 Delict and Crime, early history of, 377 — Penal law in ancient codes, 378 — Crimes and Wrongs, crimina and delicta, 379 — Furtum or Theft of the Roman Law, 380, 387 — Wrongs and Sins both known to primitive jurisprudence, 381 — difference between the ancient and modern conception of Crime, 382 — the Roman Legis Actio Sacra- menti, 384 — Homer's description of an ancient law-suit, 386 — primitive penal law of Athens, 390 — old Rtiman criminal jurispru- dence, 390 — the Quaestiones, 391 — Quaestores Paxricidii, 391 — Duumviri Perduellionis, 391 — the first true Roman Criminal Law, 392 — the primitive history of crimi- nal law, 392 — extreme multiplicity of Roman criminal tribunals, 397 — capricious classification of crimes, 399 EQUALITY Delict and Crime, statutes of Sylla and Augustus, 400 — later law of crimes, 402 — crimina extraordinaria, 401 — mode of administering criminal justice under the Roman Empire, 401 — modern history of crimes, 403 — King Alfred on Criminal juris- diction quoted, 404 Discovery, considered as a mode of acquiring dominion, 262 Dominion, its nature, limitation, and mode of securing it, 104 — of the Romans, 330 Dower, the principle of, engrafted on the Customary Law of Western Europe, 239 Draco, rudeness of the Code of, 14 — penal laws of, 377 Dumoulin referred to, 90 Dumont's " Sophismes Anar- chiques," remarks, 96 Duumviri Perduellionis, the, 391 Edict of the Roman Praetor, 44, 59. 65-7, 219, 301 Egypt, Modern, rule of succession to the throne of, 255 Eldon, Lord, his Chancellorship, 70 Elphinstone's " History of India " quoted, 275 Emphyteusis, system of, 306 et seq. — rights of the Emphyteuta, 308 Emptor FamiUae. See Familiae Emptor England, the Land-law of, at the present time, 24 1 English Common Law, formerly an unwritten law, 11 — law, hesitation of our Courts in declaring principles of, 43 EquaJity of men, doctrine of the, 96 — as understood by the Roman jurisconsults, 97 Digitized by Microsoft® 412 INDEX EQUALITY Equality of men, its meaning in its modern dress, 97 — ordinance of Louis Hutin quoted, 97 — declaration of American Inde- pendence, 99 — assumption of the Grotian school, 103 Equity, early history of, 29 — equity considered as an agent by which the adaptation of law to social wants is carried on, 32 — meaning of the term equity, 32 — difference between equity and legal fictions, 32 between equity and legisla- tion, 33, 34 — remarks on the law of nature and equity, 48 et seq. — the English Court of Chancery, 48 — origin of its system, 48, 49 — tlie equity of Rome, 49 — origin and history of the term "Equity," 60 — the terms £quitas and 'lebrrii, 60 — picture presented to the Roman mind by the word " Equity," 62 — the English Chancellor com- pared with the Roman Praetor, 67 — exhaustion of the power of growth in Roman Equity, 69 — features common to English and Roman Equity, 69 et seq. — distinction between Law and Equity in their conceptions of proprietary right, 301 Ethics, obligations of, to the Roman Law, 357 — the Casuists', 359 — Grotius and his school, 359 Familia. meaning of, in the lan- FIDEI-COMMISSA guage of the ancient Roman Law, 218 Familise Emptor, oflSce of the. 215 — rights and duties of the, 216 — remarks on the expression Familiae Emptor, 218 Family the, of Archaic society, 140 — disintegration of the Family, 172 — regarded as a corporation, 197 — organisations of elementary communities, 248 — Highland chieftainship, 241 — Families, not Individuals, known to ancient law, 270 — Indian, Russian, Croatian, and Sclavonian laws respecting the property of Families, 279, 280 Feudal view of the ownership of property, 304 Feudal services, 310 Feudalism, its connection with territorial sovereignty, 109 — feudal organisation, 109, no — the modern Will an accidental fruit of, 239, 240 — Feudalism and Contract law, 373 Fictions, legal, 26, 28 — early history of, 28 — meanirg of fictio in old Roman Law, 30 — object of the fictiones, 30 — instances cited from the Eng- lish and Roman Law, 3 1 — their former importance and modem uselessness, 31, 32 — difference between legal fictions and equity, 32, 33 — and between legal fictions and legislation, 33 — instances of legal fictions, 34 — Case-law and its auiomalies, 35 Fidei-Commissa, or Bequests in Trust, of the Roman Law, 338 Digitized by Microsoft® INDEX 413 Fiefs, hereditary, gradual trans- formation of Benefices into, 344 — original tenures, 244, 245 — laws of fiefs, 374 Foreigners, causes of immigration of, into ancient Rome, 50, 5 1 — exclusion of, under the early Roman republic, 51 France, lawyers and juridical science of, S$ et seq. — effects of the alliance between the lawyers and the kings, on the fortunes of, 85, 86 — difference between the Pays de Droit Coutumier and the Pays de Droit £crit, 88, 89 — pre-eminence given in France to Natural Law, 90 — Rousseau, 92 — the Revolution, 95 Franks, the, referred to, io6 — Roman institution of the Patria Potestas not known to the, 150 Free-will and Necessity, question of, unknown to the Greeks, 363 Furtum, or Theft, of the Roman Law, 380 Gaiwj referred to, 55 — bis description of the institution of the Patria Potestas, 142 — his information respecting the Perpetual Tutelage of women, 159 — on the duplication of proprie- tary right, referred to, 303 Galatae, the Patria Potestas of the, 143 Gens, or House, of the Romans compared with the Village Community of India, 276 Gentiles, Roman, their rights in cases of Intestate Succession, 236 German law of Succession, 290 Germans, Wills of the ancient, 208, 209 RiERBDITAS Germans, penal laws of the ancient, 377 — Patria Potestas of the, 149 — primitive property of, 209 — the ancient law of allodial property, 242 " Germany " of Tacitus, its value, 129 — suspicions as to its fidelity, 130 — allodial property of, 290 Greece, aristocracies of, 9 Greek theory of a Law of Nature, 55. 56 Greeks, equality of laws on which they prided themselves, 60 — their tendency to confound law and fact, 81 — their notion of an inherited curse, 135 — assistance afforded by, in the formation of the Roman codes, 13, 14 — Umited Patria Potestas of the, 143. 144 — metaphysics of the, 351 — their want of capacity for pro- ducing a philosophy of law, 363 Grote, Mr., his " History of Greece," referred to, 4, 8 Grotius, Hugo, and his successors, on International law, 100 — his doctrines, 103 — success of his treatise " De Jure Belli et Pacis," 112 — his theory of a. natural state and of a system of principles congenial to it, 123 — his moral philosophy and that of his school, 360 — comparison of his system with that of the Casuists, 360, 361 Guardianship, Perpetual, of Wo- men under the Roman Law, 158 — amongst the Hindoos, 158 — amongst the Scandinavians, 158 H.ffi;REDiTAS, or Inheritance, de- finition, 195 Digitized by Microsoft® 414 INDEX Hseres or Heir, his rights and duties, 194, 204, 241 Half-blood relationship, 157 — the rule according to the customs of Normandy, 157 Haus-Gesetze of Germany, 245 Heirs, rights of, under the Roman Law, 194, 202, 241 Highland chieftainship hereditary, 247 — form of Primogeniture, 252 Hindoo laws of Manu, 5, 15, i6 — Customary Law, 6 — law of Succession, 290 — differences between Inheri- tances and Acquisitions, 290 — Perpetual Tutelage of Women amongst the Hindoos, 158 — right amongst the Hindoos, to inherit a dead man's property, 204 — the Hindoo sacra, 205. — the Suttee, 205 — the place of Wills amongst the Hindoos occupied by Adop- tions, 205 — rights of the first-born son amongst the Hindoos, 242 — primogeniture of the Hindoos in public office or political power, but not in property, 247 Hindoos, form of Ownership of Property amongst the, — the Village Community, 272 — Co-ownership, 273 — simplest form of the Village Community, 274, 275 — Acquisitions of Property and Inheritances, Hindoo distinc- tion between, 290 Hobbes, his theory of the origin of law, 124 Homer, his account of the Cyclops, quoted, 133 — his description of an ancient law-suit, 385 Homeric poems, rudimentary idesis afforded by the, jural 2 Homeric poems, Themis and The- mistes, 3, 4 — Homeric words for Custom, 5 India, heroic and aristocratic eras of the races of, 9 — laws of Manu, 5, 15, 16 — Customary law of, 6 — stage beyond which India has not passed, 28 Inheritance a form of universal succession, 192 — Roman definition of an In- heritance, 195 — old Roman Law of, 202 — and Acquisition, Hindoo differ ences between, 290 Injunction of the Court of Chan- cery, 301 Institutes of the Roman lawyers, 39 International Law, modem con- fusion between it and Jus Gentium, 56 — function of the Law of Nature in giving birth to modem International Law, 99 — postulates forming the founda- tion of International Law, 99 — Grotius and his successors, 100 — dominion, 104 — territorial sovereignty, 105 — the ante-Grotian system of the Law of Nations, 1 1 1 — preparation of the public mind for the reception of the Grotian system, in, 112 — success of the treatise " De Jure Belli et Pacis," 112 — points of junction between modern public law and terri- torial sovereignty, 1 1 3 — sources of the mode in case of Capture in War, 260 Intestacy. See Succession, In- testate 'Iffonitithe Greek principle of, 60,63 Digitized by Microsoft® INDEX 415 ITAIY Italy, aristocracies of, 9 — codes of, 12 — instability of society in ancient, 50 — territorial sovereigntyof princes of, no Jews, Wills of the, 208 Julianus, Salvius, the Praetor, his Edict, 65 — effect of his measures on the Praetorian Edicts, 67 Jurisconsults, early Roman, 40-2 — later, 44 — Natural Laiw of the, 82 Jurisprudence, golden age of Roman, 58 Jurists, Roman, period of, 68, 69 Jus Feciale, or International Law of the Romans, 56 Jus Gentium, origin of, 52 c< seq. — circumstances of the origin of, 53 — how regarded by a Roman, 53 — and by a modern lawyer, 54 — difference between the Jus Gentium and the Jus Natu- rale, 55, 56 — point of contact between the old Jus Gentium and the Jus Naturale, 60 — difference between the Jus Gentium and the Quiritarian Law, 61 — influence of the, on modem civilisation, 105 Jns Naturaile, or Law of Nature, SS — difference between the Jus Naturale and the Jus Gen- tium, 55, 36 — Greek conceptions of Nature and her law, 56 — point of contact between the old Jus Gentium and the Law of Nature, 60 — modern history of the Law of Nature. 79 Jus Naturale, Natural law of the Roman Jurisconsults, 82 — ancient counterpart of Ben- thamism, 84 — vastness of the influence of the Law of Nature on modern society, 85 — history of the Law of Nature, 85 et seq. — pre-eminence given to Natural law in France, 90 — its condition at the middle of the eighteenth century, 91 — Rousseau, 92 — the French Revolution, 95 — equality of men, 96 — function of the Law of Nature in giving birth to modern International Law, 99 — sources of the Modern Inter- national Law of Capture in War, 259 Justinian's " Institutes " quoted, 49 — referred to, 60 — " Pandects " of, 68 — " Corpus Juris Civilis " of, 69 — his modifications of the Patria Potestas, 149 — his scale of Intestate Succes- sion, 234 Kings, origin of the doctrine of the divine right of, 356 Kingship, heroic, origin of, 8 Lacedemonian kings, authority of the, 9 Land-law of England at the present day, 241 Land and goods, English distinc- tion between, 293 Latifundia, Roman mode of culti- vating the, 306 Law, socialnecessities and opinions always in advance of, 29 — agencies by which law is brought into harmony with society, 29 Digitized by Microsoft® 4i6 INDEX Law, ancient, 123 — theories of a natural state and of a system congenial to it, 123 — Grotius, Blackstone, Locke, and Hobbes, 123, 124 — theory of Montesquieu, 125 — Bentham, 127 — dissatisfaction with existing theories, 128 — proper mode of inquiry, 1 28 — the Patriarchal theory, 131 — fiction of Adoption, 138 — the archaic Family, 140 — the Patria Potestas of the Romans, 142 — agnatic and cognatic relation- ships, 152 — Guardianship of Women, 158 — ancient Roman Marriage, 159 — Master and Slave, 166 Leges Barbarorum, 305 Leges Corneliae of Sylla, 44, 45 Leges Julias of Augustus, 45 Legis Actio Sacramenti of the Romans described, 384 Legislation, era of, 29, 30 — considered as an agent by which the adaptation of law to the social wants is carried on, 33 — difference between it and legal fictions, 34 Lex Calpurnia de Repetundis, the first true Roman Criminal Law, 392 Lex Plaetoria, purport of the, 166 Lidi of the Germans, 24; Local Contiguity as the condi- tion of community in political functions, 140 Locke, John, referred to, 92 — his theory of the origin of law, 124 Lombards, referred to, 106 Louis Hutin, King of France, his ordinance quoted, 97 Mahometan Law of Succession, 2SS Majority and Minority, meaning of the terms in Roman Law, 166 Mancipation, Roman, 53, 215, 288 331 — mode of giving the effect of Mancipation to a Tradition, 288 Manus of the Romans, 330 Marriage, ancient Roman, 159 — later Roman, 161 Master and Slave, 166 — under the Romans, 167 — in the United States, 167 Manu, Hindoo Laws of, 5, 15, 16 Merovingian kings of the Franks, 107 Metayers, the, of the south of Europe, 308 " Moniteur," the, during the period of the French Revolu- tion, 96 Montesquieu's " Esprit des Lois," remarks on, 91 — his Theory of Jurisprudence, 125 — Apologue of Montesquieu con- cerning the Troglodytes, in the " Lettres Persanes," 325 Moral doctrines, early, 135 Mortgagor, special proprietorship created by the Court of Chan- cery for the, 302 Moses, testamentary power not provided for by the Laws of, 209 Naples, territorial sovereignty of the monarchs of, no Nations, Law of, 100 et seq. See International Law and Jus Gentium Nature and her Law, Greek con- ceptions of, 56 Nexum of the ancient Romans, 51.328 — changes in the, 331 Digitized by Microsoft® INDEX 417 NORMANDY Normandy, customs of, referred to, IS7 N4/J0I, the word not known to the Homeric poems, 5 Nuncupatio, of the Romans, 216 Obligations of the Roman Law, 336 — rights and duties of, 337 Occupatio, or Occupancy, of the Roman Law, a " natural mode of acquiring property," 259, 263 — things which never had an owner, 259 — things which have not an owner, 259 — Capture in war, 259 — Discovery, 262 — objections to the popular theory of Occupancy, 269 Ordinance of Louis Hutin, quoted, 97 Orphans, Guardianship of male, under the Roman Law, 165 Pactes de FamUle of France, 245 Pascal, his " Lettres Provin- ciales," 362 Paterfamilias in elementary com- munities, 248 Patria Potestas, the, of the Romans, 142 — of the Galatae, 143 — of the Greeks, 144 — causes which helped to mitigate the stringency of the father's power over the persons of his children, 147 — liabilities of the Paterfamilias, 151 — unity of person between the Paterfamilias and the Filius- familias, 151 — rights and duties of the Pater- familias, 151, 152, 248, 249 — the Patria Potestas not a dur- able institution. 153 PR/ETOMAN Patriarchal theory of primeval jurisprudence, 131 — chief points from Scriptural accounts, 132 — Homer's account of the Cy- clops, 133 Pays de Droit ^crit and'Pa3rs de Droit Coutumier, difference be- tween the, 88, 89 PecuUum, the, of the Romans, 149 — Castrense Peculium, 149 — Quasi-castrense Peculium, 149 Penal law in ancient codes, 377 Perjury, how punished by the ancient Romans, 400 Persian monarchy, heroic and aristocratic eras of the races composing the, 9 Persians, the ancient, their veracity, 333 Uns of the Greeks, meaning of the, 56 Plebeian Wills of the Romans, 212 — legalised by, at the Twelve Tables, 213 — their influence on the civilisa- tion of the modern world, 314 Political ideas, early, 137 — foundation of aristocracies, 140 Political Economy and Contract, 320 Polygamy, its influence on Primo- geniture, 255 Possessory interdicts of the Ro- man Law, 300 Prsetor, origin of the office of, 64 — Edict of the, 44, 59, 65, 67 — the Roman, compared with an English Chancellor, 66, 67 — restraints on the Praetor, 67 — the Praetor the chief equity judge as well as the great common law magistrate, 68 Praetor Peregrinus, office of the, 64 Praetorian Edict of the Romans, 44, 59. 66, 67 — the Edictum Perpetuum, 65 — that of Salvius Julianus, 65, 67 27 Digitized by Microsoft® 4i8 INDEX PE^TORIAN Praetorian Edict, remedies given by the, 301 Praetorian Will, the, 219 — described, 220 Prescription of Property, history of, 293 et seg. Primogeniture, changes in the Law of Succession, caused by, 340 — almost destroyed by the authors of the French code, 240, 241 — results of the French system, 241 — rights of the first-bom son amongst the Hindoos, 242 — early history of Primogeniture, 243 — Benefices, 243 — gradual transformation of Benefices into hereditary Fiefs, 244 — the Pactes de Famille of France and the Haus-Gesetze of Ger- many, 245 — causes of the diffusion of Primo- geniture, 246 — in public offices or political power amongst the Hindoos, but not in property, 247 — ancient forms of Primogeniture 248 — why did Pn mogeniture gradu- ally supersede every other principle of Succession ? 249 — earlier and later Primogeniture, 250 — Hindoo rule of the eldest son and of the eldest line also, 252 — Celtic form of Primogeniture, 253 — Mahometan form, 255 — influence of polygamy on Pri- mogeniture, 255 Progress, causes of the arrest of, of the greater part of mankind, 83 Property, early history of, 258 PROPERTY Property, " natural modes " of acquisition, 258 — Occupancy, 259 — Capture in War, 259 — rule of Discovery, 262 — history of the origin of pro- perty, 263 — Blackstone on the theory of Occupancy as the origin of property, 264 — aphorism of Savigny on the origin of property, 267 — objections to the popular theory of Occupancy, 268 — Co-ownership amongst the Hindoos, 272 — the Gens, or House, of the Romans compared with the Village Community of India, 276 — Russian village co-ownership, 277 — Croatian and Sclavonian Laws respecting the property of Families, 278, 279 — ancient difficulties of Aliena- tion, 282 — natural classification of pro perty, 283 — ancient modes of transfer of property, 286 — definition of the Res Mancipi, 287 — tradition of property, 288 — distinction between Res Man- cipi and Res Nee Mancipi, 289 — Hindoo Law of Inheritances and Acquisitions, 290, 291 — law of movables and law of land, according to the French codes, 292 — and in England, 392 — Usucapion, or Prescription, 293 — Cessio in Jure, or recovery, in a Court of Law, of property sought to be conveyed, 297 — influence of Courts of Law and Digitized by Microsoft® INDEX 419 moPERTY of their procedure upon Pro- perty, 298 Property, distinction between Pro- perty and Possession, 298 — - and between Law and Equity in their conceptions of pro- prietary right, under the Roman and English Law, 301 — feudal view of Ownership, 303 — Roman and barbarian law of Ownership, 304 — Roman system of Tenancy, 306 — the Coloni of the Romans and the Metayers of the South of Europe, 307, 308 — rights of the Emphyteuta, 308 — the Agri Limitrophi of the Rhine and the Danube, 309 Proscriptions, Roman, origin of the, 397 Pupilage or Wardship in modem jurisprudence, 166 — compared with the Guardian- ship of Orphans under the Roman Law, 165 Quasi-contract, 353 — meaning of, in Roman Law, 354 Quasi, meaning of the word, in Roman Law, 354 Quaestiones Perpetuae of the Ro- mans, 392 — theory of the Quaestiones, 393, 394 — results traceable to the Quaes- tiones, 398 Quaestores Parricidii of the an- cient Romans, 391 Querela Inofficiosi Testamenti of the old Roman Law, 231 Quiritarian Law, the, 5 1 — principles of the, 61 difference between it and the Jus Gentium, 61 Recoveries, collusive, of pro- perty in the Roman and English Law, 297 Regency, form of, according to the French custom regulating the succession to the throne, 253 Reipus, the, of Germany, 291 Res Mancipi and Res Nee Mancipi, 284, 289 — definition of the Res Mancipi, 287 Res nnllius of the Roman Law 261 Responsa Prudentium of the Ro- mans described, 37 — similarity between them and English Case-law, 37 — decline and extinction of the Responses, 43, 44 Revolution, French, effects of the theory of the state of Nature on the, 95 Rex Sacrorum, or Rex Sacriftculus office of the, 9, 64 Roman Law, i — the Twelve Tables, i, 12. 37 — influence of the sacra on the Law of Adoption and of Wills, 6 — class of codes to which the Roman code belongs, 13 — probable assistance afforded by the Greeks, 1 3 — meaning of fictio, 30 — instances of fictiones cited, 30 — the Responsa Prudentium de- scribed, 37 — judicial functions of the Magis- trates of RepubUcan Rome, 39 — reasons why the Roman Law was not popularised, 40 — sources of the characteristic excellence of the Roman Law, 41 decline and extinction of the Responses, 43, 44 — the Praetorian Edict, 44, S9. 65. 67 — the Leges Comeliee, 44, 45 — later jurisconsults, 44 Digitized by Microsoft® 420 INDEX Roman Law, remarks on the Sta- tute Law of the Romans, 44, 45 — and on the Equity of the Romans, 48, 49 — golden age of Roman jurispru- dence, 58 — Roman Equity, 61, 68 — features common to both Eng- lish and Roman Equity, 69 et seq. — International Law largely in- debted to Roman Law,99, 100 — the Patria Potestas of the Roman Law, 144 et seq. — Agnatic and Cognatic Relation- ship, 152 — Perpetual Tutelage of Women, 158 — Roman Marriage, 159, 160 — Guardianship of male Orphans, 164 — Law of Persons — Master and Slave. 166 — Testamentary Law, lij et seq. — Wills anciently executed in the Comitia Calata, 210, 212 — ancient Roman Law of Intes- tate Succession, 211 — Roman Wills described, 212 — the Mancipation, 215 — the Nuncupatio, 216 — the Praetorian Will, 219 — first appearance of Sealing in the history of jurisprudence as a mode of authentication, 220 — Querela Inofficiosi Testament!, 231 — Disinherison of Children under, 231 — Intestate Succession under, 233 — Fidei-Commissa, or bequests in trusts, 238 — rights of Co-heirs, 241 — Occupancy, 259 — Roman distinction between the Law of Persons and the Law ef Things, 271 Roman Law, influence of Roman classifications, 271 — Co-ownership of property re- garded by the mature Roman Law as exceptional and mo- mentary, 273 — the Gens of the Romans com- pared with an Indian Village Community, 276 — Res Mancipi and Res Nee Mancipi, 284, 287 — Mancipation, 288 — Usucapion, or Prescription, 293 — the Cessio in Jure, 297 — distinction between Property and Possession, 298 — Roman and Barbarian Law, 304 — Roman Contracts, 327 et seq. — the Four Contracts, 337 — connection between Theology and Roman Law, 363, 364 — causes of improvement in Ro- man Law, 369 — Roman Law in the Eastern Empire, 371 — Civil Wrongs of the Roman Law, 379 — the Legis Actio Sacramenti, 384 — old Roman Criminal Juris- prudence, 390 — extreme multiplicity of Roman criminal tribunals, 397 — results traceable to the Quaes- tiones, 398 Romans, causes of the rapid pro- gress of the Stoical philosophy amongst the, 58 — their progress in legal im- provement, 59 Rome, immigration of foreigners into, 50, 51 — exclusion of foreigners, under the early Republic, 5 1 — See of, origin of the tendency to attribute secular superio- rity to the, 109 Digitized by Microsoft® INDEX 421 ROME Rome, decline of ecclesiastical in- fluence in international ques- tions, III — early political ideas of, 137 Rousseau, J. J., influence of his writings, 92 — his doctrine of an original Social Compact, 323, 324 Russian villages. Co-ownership of the occupiers of, 278 Sacra, or Family Rites, of the Romans, 6, 31, 203, 204 — of the Hindoos, 205 Sacramental Action of the Ancient Romans, 51 Salic Law, origin of the, 1 56 Savigny, on Possession and Pro- perty, 299, 300 — his aphorism on the Origin of Property, 267 Scxvola, Q. Mucins, his manual of the Civil Law, 43, 44 Scandinavian nations, their laws respecting the Perpetual Tute- lage of Women, 158, 163 Sclavonian laws respecting the property of families, 279 Sealing, first appearance of, in jurisprudence, as a mode of authentication, 220 Sin, mortal and venial, casuistical distinction between, 361 Sins known to primitive jurispru- dence, 381 Slavery, ancient, 167 — under the Romans, 167 — in the United States of America, 167 Socage, English law of, 246 Social Compact, Rousseau's doc- trine of an original, 323, 324 — Dr. Whewell quoted, 356 Societies, stationary and pro- gressive, 27 — difference between stationary and progressive societies, 28 agencies by which Law is SOVEREIGNTY brought into harmony with Progressive Societies, 29 Societies, perils of early, 80 — primitive, 1 34 — early moral doctrines, 135 — early political ideas, 137 — fiction of Adoption, 138 — foundation of aristocracies, 140 — principle of Local Contiguity, 140 — the ancient Family, 140 — the Patria Potestas, I42 — agnatic and cognatic relation- ships, 152 — Guardianship of Women, 158 — ancient Roman Marriage, 159 — Master and Slave, 166 — uniformity of movement of the progressive societies, 172 — disintegration of the Family, 172 — movement of societies from status to contract, 174 — Universal Succession, 193, 194, I9S — primitive society and universal succession, 197 — the ancient family a corpora- tion, 197 Society in primitive times not a collection of individuals, but an aggregation of families, 134 Solon, Attic code of, 14 " Sophismes Anarchiques " of Dn- mont, remarks on, 96 Sovereign, origin of the doctrine that the monarch is the fountain of justice, 402 Sovereignty, territorial, proposi- tion of International Law on, 105, 106 — Tribe-sovereignty, 106 — Charlemagne and universal do- minion, 108 — Territorial sovereignty ao off- shoot of feudalism, 108 — the See of Rome, 109 — • Hugh Capet, r 10 Digitized by Microsoft® 422 INDEX SOVEREIGNTY Sovweignty, the Anglo-Saxon princes, no — Naples, Spain, and Italy, i lO — Venice, i lo — points of junction between territorial sovereignty and modern public law, 113 Spain, territorial sovereignty of the monarchs of, no Status, movement of societies from, to contract, 1 74 Statute Law of the Romans, 44, 49 Stoic philosophy, principles of the, 57 — its rapid progress in Roman society, 57 — alliance of the Roman lawyers with the Stoics, 58 Succession, rules of, according to the Hindoo Customary law, 6 — Testamentary, 1 86 — early history, 186 — influence of the Church in en- forcing the sanctity of Wills, 187 — English law of, 188 — qualities necessarily attached to Wills, 188 — natural rights of testation, 189 — restraints imposed by the Code Napolfeon, 191 — nature of a Will, 191 — rights and duties of universal successor, 192 — usual Roman definition of an Inheritance, 195 — difference between modern Tes- tamentary jurisprudence and the ancient law of Rome, 196 — the Family regarded as a Cor- poration, 197 — old Roman Law of Inheritance and its notion of a Will, 202 — ancient objects of Wills, 203 — Saera, or Family Rites, of the Romans, 203 — and of the Hindoos, 204, 205 SUCCESSION Succession, the invention of Wills due to the Romans, 206 — Roman ideas of Succession, 207 — Testamentary Succession less ancient than Intestate Suc- cession, 207 — primitive operation of Wills. 209 — Wills of the ancient Germans, 209 — Jewish and Bengalee Wills, 208, 209 — mode of execution of ancient Roman Wills, 211 — description of ancient Roman Wills, 212 — influence of ancient Plebeian Wills on the civilisation of the modem world, 214 — the Mancipation, 215 — relation of Wills to convey- ances, 214 — the Testament per as et Hbram, 215, 223, 224 — consequence of this relation of Testaments to Conveyances, 216 — remedies, 217 — ancient Wills not written, 217 — remarks on the expression Emptor Familiae, 218 — the Praetorian 'Will, 219 — the Bonorum Possessio, and the Bonorum Possessor, 221 — improvements in the old Will, 222, 223 — ancient and modem ideas re- specting Wills and Succes sions, 231 — Disinherison of Children, 231 — the age of Wills coeval with that of Feudalism, 239 — introduction of the principle of Dower, 239 — rights of Heirs and Co-heirs under th* Roman Law, 241 — intestate, 207 — ancient Roman law of, 211, 234 Digitized by Microsoft® INDEX 42't SCCCE9SION Sucession, the Justinian scale of Intestate Succession, 235 — order of Intestate Succession among the Romans, 236 — horror of intestacy felt by the Romans, 237, 238 — rights of all the children of the deceased under the Roman Law, 242 — Universal, 192, 201 — in what it consists, 193 — the universal successor, 194 — formula of old Roman investi- ture referred to, 203 Suttee of the Hindoos, 205 Sylla, L. Cornelias, his improve- ments in the Roman Law, 44, 45 Tables, the Twelve Decemviral, I. 12. 37 — collections of opinions interpre- tative of the, 37 — their legalisation of Plebeian Wills, 213 — Law of the Twelve Tables re- specting Testamentary Dis- positions, 231, 232 Tablets, laws engraven on, 13 Tacitus, value of his " Germany " as a record of primitive history, 129 — suspicions as to its fidelity, 130 Tarquins, change in the adminis- tration of the law after the expulsion of the, 63, 64 Tenancy, Roman system of, 243 Testaments. See Succession, Tes- tamentary Theft, ancient Roman Law of, 322, 387, 388 — modern breaches of trust, 322 Themis and Themistes of the Greek Homeric poems, 3, 5, 134 Theology, connection between it and Roman Law, 364 Thirty Years' War, influence of the horrors of the, on the suc- WILLS cess of the treatise " De Jure Belli et Pacis " of Grotius, 112 Torts, law of, 379 Tradition of property amongst the Romans, 388 — practical effect of a Mancipa- tion given to a Tradition, 388 Transfer of property, ancient modes of, 287 Troglodytes, the, 325 Turkey, rule of succession to the throne of, 255 Ulpian, his attempt to distin- guish between the Jus Naturale and the Jus Gentium, 55 Universitas juris, in what it con sists, 192 Usucapion, principle of Roman Law known as, 222 — history of, 293 Usus, or lower form of civil mar- riage of the ancient Romans, IS9 Vandals, the, referred to, 106 Venetians, their lapse from tribe sovereignty to territorial sove- reignty, no Village Communities of India, 372, 275 et seq. Visigoths, the, referred to, 106 Voltaire, referred to, 92 Wakfake, ancient forms of, 260 Wehrgeld, the, of Germany, 291 Whewell, Dr., on original Social Compact, quoted, 356 — his view of "Moral Philosophy, 357 Widow's share of her husband's estate, 239 — the reipus, or fine leviable on the re-marriage of a widow in Germany, 291 Wills, influence of the Sacra Gentilicia on the law of, 6 — See Succession, Testamentary Digitized by Microsoft® 4*4 INDEX Women, la^rs respecting the status of, 157 — Roman law of the Perpetual Tutelage of, 158 — amongst the Hindoos, 158 — and amongst the Scandina- vians, 158 — Guardianship of Women under the Roman Law, 158 — tutelage of, amongst the Hin- doos, 153 Women, tutelage of, amongst the Scandinavians, 158 — ancient Roman Marriage, 159 — later Roman Marriage, 160 — special Proprietorship created by the Court of Chancery for, 302 ZEtJS, not judge. 4 a lawmaker, but a Digitized by Microsoft® INDEX TO INTRODUCTION AND NOTES Achilles, trial scene on Homeric shield of, 405 Aequitas, 76 American Revolution, 119 Ancestor-worship, 177, 228 Anglo-Saxon land tenure, 317 — penal law, 407 — wills, 228 Aquinas, St. Thomas, 73, 114 Aristotle, 73, 116 AuflEroy, Henri, 225 Avebury, Lord, 176, 226 Azo of Bologna, 116 Baden-Powell, B. H., 315 Bentham, Jeremy, 175 Blackstone, Sir William, 117, 314 Blood-feud in archaic Greek law, 406 Bracton or Bratton, Henry of, 116, 229 Bryce, James, 73, 76, 114 Capture, marriage by, 178 — in war, 311 Case-law, 46 Chancery, Court of, 78 Contract, early history of, 374 — Status and, 183 — the Social, 376 Corporations, 225, 226 Custom, codification of, 24 — in Homer, 20, 21 Debt in early English law, 375 Dicey, A. V., 185 Dooms and legislation, 22 Du Molin or Dumoulin, Charles 118 EguiTY, 77 Family, early history of, 176 — in Hindu law, 182 — the Cyclopean, 180, 183 Fictions, 46, 405 Figgis, J. Neville, 376 French Revolution, 119 Gentili, Albbrico, 120 Gierke, Otto, 73 Girard, Paul Fr6d6ric, 19, 227, 312, 317, 405 Grotius or Groot, Hugo, 73, 312 Hindu law, wills in, 228 Holmes, O. W. (Justice), 227 Homer, archaic custom in, 20 — blood-feud in, 406 Hooker, Richard, 115, 120 Iceland, early courts and juris- diction in, 20, 23 Ihering, Rudolf von, xviii, 178 Ilbert, Sir Courtenay, 22, 174 Indian Village Community, 315 International law, 120 Intestacy, 230 Jones, Sir William, xxii Jus gentium and jus naturale, 73, 75 Kbmble, John Mitchell, zx, xxi, 256 4*5 28 Digitized by Microsoft® 426 INDEX TO rNTRODUCTION AND NOTES King, Homeric, his dooms, ai — residuary jurisdiction of, 77 — Roman, civil jurisdiction of, 405 Kings, divine right of, 376 Kohler, JoSef, 22, 176, 181 Kovalevsky, Maxime, 176, 178 Lang, Andrew, 182 Law, natural, 73-77, 114-120, 225 — of nations, 120, 31* — of persons, 184 — Roman, in England, 117 — written and unwritten, 23 Law Merchant, 75 Leaf, Walter, 406 Lyall, Sir Alfred, 182, 315 McLennan, J. F., 176, 179, 183 Magic, 182 Maitland, F. W., 118, 178, 181, 185. 317 Mancipi, res, 3 17 Marriage, 178, 180, 183, 184 Matriarchal family, 177 Montesquieu, Charles de Secondat, Baron, 115, 174 Morgan, L. H., 176, 179, 181, 183 Muirhead, James, 227, 3x7, 374 Nature, law of. See Law — state of, 115, 119 Nexum, 374 Occupation, in Roman and in- ternational law, 311 Orestes, 177 Palgravb, Sir Francis, xxi Paragium, tenure in, 256 Patria Potestas, 181 Patriarchal theory, 176 Persons, law of, 184 Philip the Fair of France, 118 Possession, 313, 314 Primogeniture, 256 Quasi-contract, 375 Religion and magic, 182 Roman law in England, 117 Rousseau, Jean- Jacques, 119 Savigny, F. C. von, xviii, 314, 374 Scotland, testamentary disposi- tions in, 229 Selden, John, 117 Slavery, 75, 76, 118 Sovereignty, distinguished from feudal superiority, 121 Spencer, Herbert, 177 Status, 183 Stipulation in Roman law, origin of. 374 Testament, early Roman, 227 Themistes, 21 Twelve Tables, the, 18, 228, 317 Tylor, E. B., 176 178, 180 Ulpian, on law of nature, 75 ViLLAGB Communities, Indian, 315 Wales, Statute of, 122 War, capture of property in, 311 Wills and testaments, 224, 228 Printtd in Great Britain by Hatell, Watam & Viney, Li., Latuion and AyUshtiry. Digitized by Microsoft® Digitized by Microsoft® Digitized by Microsoft® Digitized by Microsoft® Digitized by Microsoft® Digitized by Microsoft® { tSffi